The Genealogy of Morals (Translated by Horace B. Samuel with an Introduction by Willard Huntington Wright)
3.5/5
()
About this ebook
Friedrich Nietzsche
Friedrich Nietzsche was a German philosopher and author. Born into a line of Protestant churchman, Nietzsche studied Classical literature and language before becoming a professor at the University of Basel in Switzerland. He became a philosopher after reading Schopenhauer, who suggested that God does not exist, and that life is filled with pain and suffering. Nietzsche’s first work of prominence was The Birth of Tragedy in 1872, which contained new theories regarding the origins of classical Greek culture. From 1883 to 1885 Nietzsche composed his most famous work, Thus Spake Zarathustra, in which he famously proclaimed that “God is dead.” He went on to release several more notable works including Beyond Good and Evil and The Genealogy of Morals, both of which dealt with the origins of moral values. Nietzsche suffered a nervous breakdown in 1889 and passed away in 1900, but not before giving us his most famous quote, “From life's school of war: what does not kill me makes me stronger.”
Read more from Friedrich Nietzsche
33 Masterpieces of Philosophy and Science to Read Before You Die (Illustrated): Utopia, The Meditations, The Art of War, The Kama Sutra, Candide Rating: 4 out of 5 stars4/5The Will to Power Rating: 4 out of 5 stars4/5The Geneology of Morals: With linked Table of Contents Rating: 4 out of 5 stars4/5The Gay Science: With a Prelude in Rhymes and an Appendix of Songs Rating: 4 out of 5 stars4/5Ecce Homo: How One Becomes What Rating: 4 out of 5 stars4/5Philosophy in the Tragic Age of the Greeks Rating: 4 out of 5 stars4/5The Portable Nietzsche (Portable Library) Rating: 3 out of 5 stars3/5THUS SPOKE ZARATHUSTRA - A Book for All and None (World Classics Series): Philosophical Novel Rating: 4 out of 5 stars4/5The Quotable Nietzsche Rating: 4 out of 5 stars4/550 Masterpieces you have to read before you die vol: 2 (2024 Edition) Rating: 0 out of 5 stars0 ratingsBasic Writings of Nietzsche (Modern Library Classics) Rating: 0 out of 5 stars0 ratingsUnpublished Letters Rating: 5 out of 5 stars5/5The Collected Works of Arthur Schopenhauer: PergamonMedia Rating: 0 out of 5 stars0 ratingsThe Will to Power (Volumes I and II) Rating: 4 out of 5 stars4/5
Related to The Genealogy of Morals (Translated by Horace B. Samuel with an Introduction by Willard Huntington Wright)
Related ebooks
Human, All Too Human Rating: 0 out of 5 stars0 ratingsThe Essays of Arthur Schopenhauer; Studies in Pessimism Rating: 0 out of 5 stars0 ratingsThe Dialogues of Seneca Rating: 0 out of 5 stars0 ratingsGerman Philosophy And Politics Rating: 0 out of 5 stars0 ratingsThe Genealogy of Morals Rating: 0 out of 5 stars0 ratingsThe Ethics Rating: 4 out of 5 stars4/5On the Fourfold Root of the Principle of Sufficient Reason, and on the Will in Nature - Two Essays Rating: 4 out of 5 stars4/5The Burning Bush: Collected Speeches of Elias Simojoki Rating: 5 out of 5 stars5/5The Natural History of Religion Rating: 3 out of 5 stars3/5The Joyful Wisdom Rating: 0 out of 5 stars0 ratingsDream Psychology Rating: 0 out of 5 stars0 ratingsPlato: The Complete Works (31 Books) Rating: 0 out of 5 stars0 ratingsThe Laws Rating: 4 out of 5 stars4/5Kant's Prolegomena: To Any Future Metaphysics Rating: 0 out of 5 stars0 ratingsA General View of Positivism Rating: 0 out of 5 stars0 ratingsThe Anti-Christ Rating: 0 out of 5 stars0 ratingsPolitics Rating: 4 out of 5 stars4/5Geneaology of Morals Rating: 4 out of 5 stars4/5Timaeus Rating: 4 out of 5 stars4/5Prolegomena to a Philosophy of Religion Rating: 3 out of 5 stars3/5Friedrich Nietzsche Rating: 4 out of 5 stars4/5Philosophy of the Sixteenth and Seventeenth Centuries Rating: 4 out of 5 stars4/5Mysticism and Logic Rating: 0 out of 5 stars0 ratingsLeviathan Rating: 0 out of 5 stars0 ratingsNietzsche's Final Teaching Rating: 0 out of 5 stars0 ratingsCategories Rating: 4 out of 5 stars4/5Semiosis of Power in Early Medieval Culture: Myths, Monsters, Intertexts Rating: 0 out of 5 stars0 ratingsThe Philosophy of Marx Rating: 0 out of 5 stars0 ratings
Philosophy For You
The Dictionary of Obscure Sorrows Rating: 4 out of 5 stars4/5Meditations: Complete and Unabridged Rating: 4 out of 5 stars4/5The Meditations of Marcus Aurelius Rating: 4 out of 5 stars4/5How to Think Like a Roman Emperor: The Stoic Philosophy of Marcus Aurelius Rating: 4 out of 5 stars4/5The Lessons of History Rating: 4 out of 5 stars4/5The Art of Loving Rating: 4 out of 5 stars4/5Why Buddhism is True: The Science and Philosophy of Meditation and Enlightenment Rating: 4 out of 5 stars4/5THE EMERALD TABLETS OF THOTH THE ATLANTEAN Rating: 4 out of 5 stars4/5The Subtle Art of Being Alone: Why Embracing Solitude Beats Embracing Loneliness Rating: 5 out of 5 stars5/5A Mindful Year: Daily Meditations: Reduce Stress, Manage Anxiety, and Find Happiness in Everyday Life Rating: 5 out of 5 stars5/5The Republic by Plato Rating: 4 out of 5 stars4/5Daily Stoic: A Daily Journal On Meditation, Stoicism, Wisdom and Philosophy to Improve Your Life Rating: 5 out of 5 stars5/5Focus on What Matters: A Collection of Stoic Letters on Living Well Rating: 4 out of 5 stars4/5The Little Book of Stoicism: Timeless Wisdom to Gain Resilience, Confidence, and Calmness Rating: 4 out of 5 stars4/5The Kama Sutra of Vatsyayana (Illustrated) Rating: 3 out of 5 stars3/5The Bhagavad Gita Rating: 5 out of 5 stars5/5The Art of War Rating: 4 out of 5 stars4/5The Socratic Method: A Practitioner's Handbook Rating: 4 out of 5 stars4/5Sun Tzu's The Art of War: Bilingual Edition Complete Chinese and English Text Rating: 4 out of 5 stars4/5How to Hold a Cockroach: A book for those who are free and don't know it Rating: 5 out of 5 stars5/5
Reviews for The Genealogy of Morals (Translated by Horace B. Samuel with an Introduction by Willard Huntington Wright)
6 ratings8 reviews
- Rating: 5 out of 5 stars5/5
Feb 9, 2018
Hey you know what them Christians really piss me of walking about the place claiming all these absolutes of whats good and bad. Morality wasn't set in stone it evolved, there were different views before them and there sure as hell can be different views after them. - Rating: 3 out of 5 stars3/5
Feb 9, 2018
Verzameling geniale en minder geniale inzichten, van wie er vele intussen gemeengoed zijn geworden - Rating: 4 out of 5 stars4/5
Feb 9, 2018
Of all the books by or about Nietzsche, I think this particular edition of the Genealogy would be the best place for the novice to start. The introduction by Clark (a very well regraded Nietzsche scholar) is excellent and provides a workable framework for interpreting a text (and an author) that can often be difficult to decipher. The scholarly apparatus is exhaustive; the editors provide end notes that cover nearly every page in the original text and help the reader to make sense of Nietzsche's sometimes unclear allusions and provide voluminous biographic and bibliographic detail covering both Nietzsche and the interlocutors he mentions in the text (as well as a few he merely alludes to). As for the text itself, I think it is notable primarily for the genealogical analysis of the concepts of good/right-bad/wrong and for a glimpse of Nietzsche's "perspectivalist" epistemology in the third section. These views have been highly influential (although not among philosophers as such) over the past century and anyone that wishes to understand the course and trajectory of 20th century thought should be aware of them. Nietzsche is a master stylist, so the reading is fun as well as thought provoking.Of course, the central question, considering Nietzsche qua philosopher, is this: Does Nietzsche get thing right?I think it's pretty clear that the answer is "no". Although his castigation of scientific atheism as an extension (perhaps the highest extension) of religious asceticism shows depth and brilliance, he doesn't ever give us any solid arguments for thinking that truth itself hinges on particular standards of evaluation. Nietzsche seems to me to be skeptical of the idea of truth as correspondence (the standard view) because it situates truth outside of life. It makes truth something that transcends individual human beings. Perhaps this is true, and given Nietzsche's rejection of any and all transcendent things it makes sense that he'd want to reject truth conceived of in this way. What isn't clear is that he CAN do this, that is, that his view is warranted. The fact that the correspondence of theory of truth has implications that Nietzsche finds repulsive is no reason for thinking that it's false.Furthermore, without some notion of truth as correspondence, it's not clear that his earlier critique of moral concepts has any real bite. - Rating: 2 out of 5 stars2/5
Feb 9, 2018
A book of 3 essays. Almost stopped reading after introduction. Then again half way through first essay. Found a few statements interesting in first 2 essays.Found third essay a bit more interesting.Neitzsche mentions becoming more Chinese. Also shutting down animal aspects of humans and hibernating, internalizing instincts. I wonder how Nietzsche exercised. - Rating: 3 out of 5 stars3/5
Feb 9, 2018
Being three essays in which the great prophet of atheism discusses the origins of morality, particularly Christian morality, in human psychology, contrasting an asceticism which attempts to appeal to a mass mind to older, pagan mentalities which the author considers superior. As always with Nietzsche, the book is full of insights which are expressed in colorful and dramatic language. The book is jumpy, though, and extremely esoteric. It often seems that no two paragraphs have the least connection with each other, which is somewhat typical of Nietzsche's rambling later books. . - Rating: 4 out of 5 stars4/5
Feb 9, 2018
If you liked what he did to God, you'll love Nietzsche's take on morality. The rich invented "good" and "bad" because they never suffered, and the poor and downtrodden invented "good" and "evil" because they needed a concept for the really horrible things that happened to them. Nietzche tries to unscientifically trace the evolution of morality. Reall fun. - Rating: 4 out of 5 stars4/5
Feb 9, 2018
If you liked what he did to God, you'll love Nietzsche's take on morality. The rich invented "good" and "bad" because they never suffered, and the poor and downtrodden invented "good" and "evil" because they needed a concept for the really horrible things that happened to them. Nietzche tries to unscientifically trace the evolution of morality. Reall fun. - Rating: 3 out of 5 stars3/5
Feb 9, 2018
The word ought has its origins in the word owe. Whether or not this relationship survives translation I don't know, but why let semantics get in the way of a good idea. Reading Beyond Good and Evil before attempting this follow-up work would be the more logical option. But I doubt one can simply dip one's toe in to Nietzsche anyway - it is a case of diving in head first and trying to make sense of the turmoil. Nietzsche's racism reflects the tone of the times, and there is plenty of conflicting views to support the argument that his sister re-construed his work to fit comfortably with the Nazis. But in the end I felt Nietzsche's racism was as relevant to Nazism as Jack London's. It is interesting that he seems to support women's rights (remembering that J.S. Mill's On the Subjection of Women was published 18 years before), planes the edges off his Orientalism with Buddhism and Brahmanism, and doesn't appear so overjoyed at the "death of God" as Atheist's gleefully point out. Indeed, Nietzsche makes a point of saying that science is a more advanced form of the "ascetic ideal". The back cover of the work sums up Nietzsche's thesis as "culture and morality, rather than being eternal verities, are human-made". This is an oversimplification that reduces the depth of his work. Far be it for me to be an apologist for Nietzsche - the "intellectual" gatekeepers would never let such work be published today - but the brilliance is in its originality. To comprehend the thesis adequately, prior reading of Buddhism, Luther, Brahmanism, Kant, Spinoza, Goethe, Feuerbach, and Schopenhauer would be helpful but is not essential. However, a knowledge of the classics (at least Plato) is important. Nietzsche final words are that "man will wish Nothingness rather than not wish at all". I immediately thought of the maxim "if you fail to plan, you plan to fail". Probably the most useful idea from this work is that one needs to go back to first principles in establishing a philosophy - does or can truth exist? - (and even if we don't care to consciously develop a philosophy, the shepherds of the "herd mentality" will provide one for us without our knowledge or consent), and Nietzsche does so by regularly referring back to "Heracleitus" and Hesiod. I have already picked up the scent of the pre-Socratics and their importance in understanding the human-created chasm between philosophy and religion (and more recently, but less convincingly, between science and religion), and Nietzsche confirms this clue. Rather than the ?ber-power of pre-Enlightenment Christian church and its priesthood driving the herd, Nietzsche foresaw ("forsooth"?) the pluralism of modern asceticism (which annoys me on Facebook, Twitter, and the news media any time I look). Admittedly, he was optimistic about this future, but then he didn't know what "the Internet" would say about him (how I loathe that saying!). So why don't I see the ascetic for what it is and just get off Facebook once again? Well. it's the guilt, you see. But you can't blame me - I didn't create it (Facebook or the guilt).
Book preview
The Genealogy of Morals (Translated by Horace B. Samuel with an Introduction by Willard Huntington Wright) - Friedrich Nietzsche
THE GENEALOGY OF MORALS
By FRIEDRICH NIETZSCHE
Translated By HORACE B. SAMUEL
Introduction by
WILLARD HUNTINGTON WRIGHT
The Genealogy of Morals
By Friedrich Nietzsche
Translated By Horace B. Samuel
Introduction by Willard Huntington Wright
Print ISBN 13: 978-1-4209-5629-0
eBook ISBN 13: 978-1-4209-5630-6
This edition copyright © 2017. Digireads.com Publishing.
All rights reserved. No part of this publication may be reproduced, distributed, or transmitted in any form or by any means, including photocopying, recording, or other electronic or mechanical methods, without the prior written permission of the publisher, except in the case of brief quotations embodied in critical reviews and certain other noncommercial uses permitted by copyright law.
Cover Image: a detail of Romans of the Decadence
by Thomas Couture, c. 1847.
Please visit www.digireads.com
CONTENTS
INTRODUCTION
EDITOR’S NOTE
PREFACE
FIRST ESSAY. GOOD AND EVIL,
GOOD AND BAD
SECOND ESSAY. GUILT,
BAD CONSCIENCE,
AND THE LIKE
THIRD ESSAY. WHAT IS THE MEANING OF ASCETIC IDEALS?
BIOGRAPHICAL AFTERWORD
Introduction
The Genealogy of Morals
("Zur Genealogie der Moral) was written by Nietzsche primarily as an elaboration and elucidation of the philosophic points which were merely sketched in
Beyond Good and Evil. This former work had met with small success, and the critics, failing to understand its doctrines, read converse meanings in it. One critic hailed Nietzsche at once as an anarchist, and this review went far in actuating him in drawing up the three essays which comprise the present book. As will be remembered, several of Nietzsche’s most important principles were stated and outlined in
Beyond Good and Evil, especially his doctrine of slave-morality and master-morality. Now he undertakes to develop this proposition, as well as many others which he set forth provisionally in his earlier work. This new polemic may be looked upon both as a completing of former works and as a further preparation for
The Will to Power." The book, a comparatively brief one (it contains barely 40,000 words), was written in a period of about two weeks during the early part of 1887. In July the manuscript was sent to the publisher, but was recalled for revisions and addenda; and most of Nietzsche’s summer was devoted to correcting it. Later that same year the book appeared; and thereby its author acquired another friendly reader, Georg Brandes, to whom, more than to any other critic, Nietzsche owes his early recognition.
The style of The Genealogy of Morals
is less aphoristic than any of the books which immediately preceded or followed it. Few new doctrines are propounded in it; and since it was for the most part an analytic commentary on what had gone before, its expositional needs were best met by Nietzsche’s earlier style of writing. I have spoken before of the desultory and sporadic manner in which Nietzsche was necessitated to present his philosophy. Nowhere is his method of work better exemplified than in this new work. Nearly every one of his books overlaps another. Propositions are sketchily stated in one essay, which receive elucidation only in future volumes. Beyond Good and Evil
was a commentary on Thus Spake Zarathustra
; The Genealogy of Morals
is a commentary on the newly propounded theses in Beyond Good and Evil
and is in addition an elaboration of many of the ideas which took birth as far back as Human, All-Too-Human.
Out of The Genealogy of Morals
in turn grew The Antichrist
which dealt specifically with the theological phase of the former’s discussion of general morals. And all of these books were but preparations for The Will to Power.
For this reason it is difficult to acquire a complete understanding of Nietzsche’s philosophy unless one follows it consecutively and chronologically. The book at present under discussion is a most valuable one from an academic standpoint, for, while it may not set forth any new and important doctrines, it goes deep into the origins and history of moral concepts, and explains many of the important conclusions in Nietzsche’s moral code. It brings more and more into prominence the main pillars of his ethical system and explains at length the steps in the syllogism which led to his doctrine of master-morality. It ascertains the origin of the concept of sin, and describes the racial deterioration which has followed in the train of Christian ideals.
In many ways this book is the profoundest of all the writings Nietzsche left us. For the first time he separates theological and moral prejudices and traces them to different origins. This is one of the most important steps taken by him. By so doing he became an explorer of entirely new fields. The moral historians and psychologists who preceded him had considered moral precepts and Christian injunctions as stemming from the same source: their genealogies had led them to the same common spring. Nietzsche entered the search with new methods. He applied the philologic test to all moral values. He brought to his task, in addition to a historical sense, what he calls "an innate faculty of psychological discrimination par excellence He posed the following questions, and endeavoured to answer them by inquiring into the minutest aspects of historical conditions:
Under what conditions did Man invent for himself those judgments of value, ‘good’ and ‘evil’? And what intrinsic value do they possess in themselves? Have they up to the present hindered or advanced human well-being? Are they a symptom of the distress, impoverishment, and degeneration of Human Life? Or, conversely, is it in them that is manifested the fulness, the strength, and the will of Life, its courage, its self-confidence, its future? In his research, Nietzsche first questioned the value of pity. He found it to be a symptom of modern civilisation—a quality held in contempt by the older philosophers, even by such widely dissimilar minds as Plato, Spinoza, La Rochefoucauld and Kant—but a quality given high place by the more modern thinkers. Despite the seemingly apparent isolation of the problem of pity-morality, Nietzsche saw that in truth it was a question which underlay all other moral propositions; and, using it as a ground-work for his research, he began to question the utility of all those values held as good,
to apply the qualities of the good man
to the needs of civilisation, and to inquire into the results left upon the race by the bad man.
So great was the misunderstanding which attached to his phrase, beyond good and evil,
and so persistently was this phrase interpreted in its narrow sense of beyond good and bad,
that he felt the necessity of drawing the line of distinction between these two diametrically opposed conceptions and of explaining the origin of each. His first essay in The Genealogy of Morals
is devoted to this task. At the outset he devotes considerable space criticising the methods and conclusions of former genealogists of morals, especially of the English psychologists who attribute an intrinsic merit to altruism because at one time altruism possessed a utilitarian value. Herbert Spencer’s theory that good
is the same as purposive
brings from Nietzsche a protest founded on the contention that because a thing was at one time useful, and therefore good,
it does not follow that the thing is good in itself. By the etymology of the descriptive words of morality, Nietzsche traces the history of modern moral attributes through class distinctions to their origin in the instincts of the nobles
and the vulgarians.
He shows the relationship between the Latin bonus and the warrior,
by deriving bonus from duonus. Bellum, he shows, equals duellum which equals duen-lum, in which word duonus is contained. Likewise, he points out the aristocratic origin of happiness
—a quality arising from an abundance of energy and the consciousness of power.
Good and evil,
according to Nietzsche, is a sign of slave-morality; while good and bad
represents the qualities in the master-morality. The one stands for the adopted qualities of the subservient races; the other embodies the natural functioning of dominating races. The origin of the good
in these two instances is by no means the same. In the strong man good
represented an entirely different condition than the good
in the resentful and weak man; and these two goods
arose out of different causes. The one was spontaneous and natural—inherent in the individual of strength: the other was a manufactured condition, an optional selection of qualities to soften and ameliorate the conditions of existence. Evil
and bad,
by the same token, became attributes originating in widely separated sources. The evil
of the weak man was any condition which worked against the manufactured ideals of goodness, which brought about unhappiness—it was the beginning of the conception of a slave-morality, a term applied to all enemies. The bad
of the strong man was the concept which grew directly out of his feeling for good,
and which had no application to another individual. Thus the ideas of good
and bad
are directly inherited from the nobles of the race, and these ideas included within themselves the tendency toward establishing social distinctions.
The second section of The Genealogy of Morals,
called ‘Guilt,’ ‘Bad Conscience,’ and the Like,
is another important document, the reading of which is almost imperative for the student who would understand the processes of thought which led to Nietzsche’s philosophic conclusions. In this essay Nietzsche traces the origin of sin to debt, thereby disagreeing with all the genealogists of morals who preceded him. He starts with the birth of memory in man and with the corresponding will to forgetfulness, showing that out of these two mental qualities was bom responsibility. Out of responsibility in turn grew the function of promising and the accepting of promises, which at once made possible between individuals the relationship of debtor
and creditor.
As soon as this relationship was established, one man had rights over another. The creditor could exact payment from the debtor, either in the form of material equivalent or by inflicting an injury in which was contained the sensation of satisfaction. Thus the creditor had the right to punish in cases where actual repayment was impossible. And in this idea of punishment began not only class distinction but primitive law. Later, when the power to punish was transferred into the hands of the community, the law of contract came into existence. Here, says Nietzsche, we find the cradle of the whole moral world of the ideas of guilt,
conscience,
and duty
; and adds, Their commencement, like the commencement of all great things in the world, is thoroughly and continuously saturated in blood.
Carrying out the principle underlying the relationship of debtor and creditor we arrive at the formation of the community. In return for protection and for communal advantages the individual pledged his good behaviour. When he violated this contract with the community, the community, in the guise of the defrauded creditor, took its revenge, or exacted its payment, from the debtor, the criminal. And, as was the case in early history, the community deprived the violator of future advantages and protection. The debtor was divested of all rights, even of mercy, for then there were no degrees in law-breaking. Primitive law was martial law. Says Nietzsche, This shows why war itself (counting the sacrificial cult of war) has produced all the forms under which punishment has manifested itself in history.
Later, as the community gathered strength, the offences of the individual debtors were looked upon as less serious. Out of its security grew leniency toward the offender: the penal code became mitigated, and, as in all powerful nations to-day, the criminal was protected. Only when there was a consciousness of weakness in a community did the acts of individual offenders take on an exaggerated seriousness, and under such conditions the law was consequently harshest. Thus, justice and the infliction of legal penalties are direct outgrowths of the primitive relation of debt between individuals. Herein we have the origin of guilt.
Nietzsche attempts an elaborate analysis of the history of punishment, in an effort to ascertain its true meaning, its relation to guilt and to the community, and its final effects on both the individual and society. It has been impossible to present the sequence of this analysis by direct excerpts from his own words, due to the close, synthetic manner in which he has made his research. Therefore I offer the following brief exposition of the section in which he examines the causes and effects of punishment. To begin with, Nietzsche disassociates the origin
and the end
of punishment, and regards them as two separate and distinct problems. He argues that the final utility of a thing, in the sense that revenge and deterrence are the final utilities of punishment, is in all cases opposed to the origin of that thing; that every force or principle is constantly being put to new purposes by forces greater than itself, thus making it impossible to determine its inception by the end for which it is used. Therefore the function
of punishing was not conceived with a view to punishing, but may have been employed for any number of ends, according as a will to power has overcome that function and made use of it for its own purpose: in short; punishment, like any organ or custom or thing,
has passed through a series of new interpretations and adjustments and meanings—and is not a direct and logical progressus to an end.
Having established this point, Nietzsche endeavours to determine the utilisation to which the custom of punishment has been put—to ascertain the meaning which has been interpreted into it. He finds that even in modern times not one but many uses have been made of punishment, and that in ancient times so diverse have been the utilisations of punishment that it is impossible to define them all. In fact, one cannot determine the precise reason for punishment. To emphasise this point, Nietzsche gives a long list of possible meanings. Taking up the more popular supposed utilities of punishment at the present time—such as creating in the wrong-doer the consciousness of guilt, which is supposed to evolve into conscience and remorse—he shows wherein punishment fails in its object. Against this theory of the creation of remorse, he advances psychology and shows that, to the contrary, punishment numbs and hardens. He argues also that punishment for the purpose of making the wrong-doer conscious of the intrinsic reprehensibility of his crime, fails because the very act for which he is chastened is practised in the service of justice and is called good.
Eliminating thus the supposed effects of punishment, Nietzsche arrives at the conclusion that punishment makes only for caution and secrecy, and is therefore detrimental.
In his analysis of the origin of the bad conscience,
Nietzsche lends himself to quotation. Therefore I have been able to present in his own words a fair resume of the course pursued by him in his examination of the history of conscience. This particular branch of his research is carried into the formation of the State
which, according to him, grew out of a herd of blonde beasts.
The older theory of the state, namely: that it originated in the adoption of a contract, is set aside as untenable when dealing with a peoples who possessed conquerors or masters. These masters, argues Nietzsche, had no need of contracts. By using the bad conscience
as a ground for inquiry, the causes for the existence of altruism are shown to be included in the self-cruelty which followed in the wake of the instinct "for freedom. (This last point is developed fully in the discussion of ascetic ideals which is found at the end of the book now under consideration.) Nietzsche traces the birth of deities back along the lines of credit and debt. First came the fear of ancestors. Then followed the obligation to ancestors. At length the sacrifice to ancestors marked the beginning of a conception of duty (debt) to the supernatural. The ancestors of powerful nations in time became heroes, and finally evolved into gods. Later monotheism came as a natural consequence, and God became the creditor. In the expiation of sin, as symbolised in the crucifixion of Christianity, we have this same relationship of debtor and creditor carried out into a more complex form through the avenues of self-torture.
The most important essay in The Genealogy of Morals
is the last, called What is the Meaning of Ascetic Ideals?
Nietzsche examines this question in relation to the artist, to the philosopher, to the priest, and to the race generally. In his examination of the problem in regard to artists he uses Wagner as a basis of inquiry, comparing the two phases of Wagner’s art—the Parsifalian and the ante-Parsifalian. Artists, asserts Nietzsche, need a support of constituted authority; they are unable to stand alone—standing alone is opposed to their deepest instincts
—and so they make use of asceticism as a rampart, as building material, to give their work authority. In his application of the ascetic ideal to philosophers, Nietzsche presents the cases of Schopenhauer and Kant, and concludes that asceticism in such instances is used as an escape from torture—a means to recreation and happiness. With the philosopher the ideal of asceticism is not a denial of existence. Rather is it an affirmation of existence. It permits him