About this ebook
Author W. W. Sawyer begins with a very basic viewpoint of abstract algebra, using simple arithmetic and elementary algebra. He then proceeds to arithmetic and polynomials, slowly progressing to more complex matters: finite arithmetic, an analogy between integers and polynomials, an application of the analogy, extending fields, and linear dependence and vector spaces. Additional topics include algebraic calculations with vectors, vectors over a field, and fields regarded as vector spaces. The final chapter proves that angles cannot be trisected by Euclidean means, using a proof that shows how modern algebraic concepts can be used to solve an ancient problem. Exercises appear throughout the book, with complete solutions at the end.
Related to A Concrete Approach to Abstract Algebra
Titles in the series (100)
First-Order Partial Differential Equations, Vol. 2 Rating: 0 out of 5 stars0 ratingsFirst-Order Partial Differential Equations, Vol. 1 Rating: 5 out of 5 stars5/5Differential Forms Rating: 5 out of 5 stars5/5Analytic Inequalities Rating: 5 out of 5 stars5/5A Catalog of Special Plane Curves Rating: 2 out of 5 stars2/5Differential Forms with Applications to the Physical Sciences Rating: 5 out of 5 stars5/5Advanced Calculus: Second Edition Rating: 5 out of 5 stars5/5Topology for Analysis Rating: 4 out of 5 stars4/5Laplace Transforms and Their Applications to Differential Equations Rating: 5 out of 5 stars5/5Methods of Applied Mathematics Rating: 3 out of 5 stars3/5Optimization Theory for Large Systems Rating: 5 out of 5 stars5/5How to Gamble If You Must: Inequalities for Stochastic Processes Rating: 0 out of 5 stars0 ratingsInfinite Series Rating: 4 out of 5 stars4/5Vision in Elementary Mathematics Rating: 3 out of 5 stars3/5History of the Theory of Numbers, Volume II: Diophantine Analysis Rating: 0 out of 5 stars0 ratingsAn Introduction to Lebesgue Integration and Fourier Series Rating: 0 out of 5 stars0 ratingsGeometry: A Comprehensive Course Rating: 4 out of 5 stars4/5Chebyshev and Fourier Spectral Methods: Second Revised Edition Rating: 4 out of 5 stars4/5Numerical Methods Rating: 5 out of 5 stars5/5An Adventurer's Guide to Number Theory Rating: 3 out of 5 stars3/5Dynamic Probabilistic Systems, Volume II: Semi-Markov and Decision Processes Rating: 0 out of 5 stars0 ratingsMathematics for the Nonmathematician Rating: 4 out of 5 stars4/5Calculus: An Intuitive and Physical Approach (Second Edition) Rating: 4 out of 5 stars4/5Statistical Inference Rating: 4 out of 5 stars4/5Fourier Series and Orthogonal Polynomials Rating: 0 out of 5 stars0 ratingsA History of Mathematical Notations Rating: 4 out of 5 stars4/5Counterexamples in Topology Rating: 4 out of 5 stars4/5Applied Functional Analysis Rating: 0 out of 5 stars0 ratingsA Treatise on Probability Rating: 0 out of 5 stars0 ratingsDifferential Geometry Rating: 5 out of 5 stars5/5
Related ebooks
Prelude to Mathematics Rating: 4 out of 5 stars4/5Foundations and Fundamental Concepts of Mathematics Rating: 4 out of 5 stars4/5Naive Set Theory Rating: 4 out of 5 stars4/5Concepts of Modern Mathematics Rating: 4 out of 5 stars4/5The Red Book of Mathematical Problems Rating: 0 out of 5 stars0 ratingsIntegral Equations Rating: 0 out of 5 stars0 ratingsAlgebraic Number Theory Rating: 0 out of 5 stars0 ratingsElementary Number Theory: An Algebraic Approach Rating: 0 out of 5 stars0 ratingsFundamentals of Modern Mathematics: A Practical Review Rating: 0 out of 5 stars0 ratingsAn Adventurer's Guide to Number Theory Rating: 3 out of 5 stars3/5Elementary Theory of Numbers Rating: 4 out of 5 stars4/5Vector Spaces and Matrices Rating: 0 out of 5 stars0 ratingsElements of Abstract Algebra Rating: 4 out of 5 stars4/5Probability Theory: A Concise Course Rating: 4 out of 5 stars4/5Algebraic Methods in Statistical Mechanics and Quantum Field Theory Rating: 0 out of 5 stars0 ratingsThe Theory of Algebraic Numbers Rating: 4 out of 5 stars4/5Linear Algebra Rating: 3 out of 5 stars3/5Rudiments of Algebraic Geometry Rating: 0 out of 5 stars0 ratingsIntroduction to Differential Geometry for Engineers Rating: 0 out of 5 stars0 ratingsMatrices and Linear Algebra Rating: 4 out of 5 stars4/5What Is Mathematical Logic? Rating: 3 out of 5 stars3/5Introduction to Matrices and Vectors Rating: 0 out of 5 stars0 ratingsGeometric Algebra Rating: 5 out of 5 stars5/5Vector Geometry Rating: 0 out of 5 stars0 ratingsComputability and Unsolvability Rating: 4 out of 5 stars4/5Feynman Lectures Simplified 4A: Math for Physicists Rating: 5 out of 5 stars5/5Introduction to the Theory of Sets Rating: 3 out of 5 stars3/5Boolean Algebra Rating: 3 out of 5 stars3/5
Mathematics For You
Calculus For Dummies Rating: 4 out of 5 stars4/5Math Magic: How To Master Everyday Math Problems Rating: 3 out of 5 stars3/5Pre-Calculus For Dummies Rating: 5 out of 5 stars5/5My Best Mathematical and Logic Puzzles Rating: 4 out of 5 stars4/5Mental Math Secrets - How To Be a Human Calculator Rating: 5 out of 5 stars5/5Calculus Made Easy Rating: 4 out of 5 stars4/5The Everything Everyday Math Book: From Tipping to Taxes, All the Real-World, Everyday Math Skills You Need Rating: 5 out of 5 stars5/5Quantum Physics for Beginners Rating: 4 out of 5 stars4/5Basic Math & Pre-Algebra For Dummies Rating: 4 out of 5 stars4/5Statistics: a QuickStudy Laminated Reference Guide Rating: 0 out of 5 stars0 ratingsAlgebra - The Very Basics Rating: 5 out of 5 stars5/5Introducing Game Theory: A Graphic Guide Rating: 4 out of 5 stars4/5Algebra I For Dummies Rating: 4 out of 5 stars4/5The Art of Statistical Thinking Rating: 5 out of 5 stars5/5The Little Book of Mathematical Principles, Theories & Things Rating: 3 out of 5 stars3/5Game Theory: A Simple Introduction Rating: 4 out of 5 stars4/5Geometry For Dummies Rating: 4 out of 5 stars4/5Calculus Made Easy Rating: 5 out of 5 stars5/5Mental Math: Tricks To Become A Human Calculator Rating: 2 out of 5 stars2/5Trigonometry For Dummies Rating: 5 out of 5 stars5/5Precalculus: A Self-Teaching Guide Rating: 4 out of 5 stars4/5The Cartoon Introduction to Calculus Rating: 5 out of 5 stars5/5Feynman Lectures Simplified 4A: Math for Physicists Rating: 5 out of 5 stars5/5Introductory Discrete Mathematics Rating: 4 out of 5 stars4/5Calculus: An Intuitive and Physical Approach (Second Edition) Rating: 4 out of 5 stars4/5Calculus Essentials For Dummies Rating: 5 out of 5 stars5/5
Reviews for A Concrete Approach to Abstract Algebra
3 ratings1 review
- Rating: 5 out of 5 stars5/5
Nov 25, 2014
See my review of Mathematician's Delight. Basically, anything written by W. W. Sawyer is pure gold, and worth reading. This book shows that Sawyer is just as adept with advanced as with elementary material.
Book preview
A Concrete Approach to Abstract Algebra - W. W. Sawyer
Introduction
The Aim of This Book and How to Read It
AT THE PRESENT time there is a widespread desire, particularly among high school teachers and engineers, to know more about modern mathematics.
Institutes are provided to meet this desire, and this book was originally written for, and used by, such an institute. The chapters of this book were handed out as mimeographed notes to the students. There were no lectures
; I did not in the classroom try to expound the same material again. These chapters were the lectures.
In the classroom we simply argued about this material. Questions were asked, obscure points were clarified.
In planning such a course, a professor must make a choice. His aim may be to produce a perfect mathematical work of art, having every axiom stated, every conclusion drawn with flawless logic, the whole syllabus covered. This sounds excellent, but in practice the result is often that the class does not have the faintest idea of what is going on. Certain axioms are stated. How are these axioms chosen? Why do we consider these axioms rather than others? What is the subject about? What is its purpose? If these questions are left unanswered, students feel frustrated. Even though they follow every individual deduction, they cannot think effectively about the subject. The framework is lacking; students do not know where the subject fits in, and this has a paralyzing effect on the mind.
On the other hand, the professor may choose familiar topics as a starting point. The students collect material, work problems, observe regularities, frame hypotheses, discover and prove theorems for themselves. The work may not proceed so quickly; all topics may not be covered; the final outline may be jagged. But the student knows what he is doing and where he is going; he is secure in his mastery of the subject, strengthened in confidence of himself. He has had the experience of discovering mathematics. He no longer thinks of mathematics as static dogma learned by rote. He sees mathematics as something growing and developing, mathematical concepts as something continually revised and enriched in the light of new knowledge. The course may have covered a very limited region, but it should leave the student ready to explore further on his own.
This second approach, proceeding from the familiar to the unfamiliar, is the method used in this book. Wherever possible, I have tried to show how modern higher algebra grows out of traditional elementary algebra. Even so, you may for a time experience some feeling of strangeness. This sense of strangeness will pass; there is nothing you can do about it; we all experience such feelings whenever we begin a new branch of mathematics. Nor is it surprising that such strangeness should be felt. The traditional high school syllabus—algebra, geometry, trigonometry—contains little or nothing discovered since the year 1650 A.D. Even if we bring in calculus and differential equations, the date 1750 A.D. covers most of that. Modern higher algebra was developed round about the years 1900 to 1930 A.D. Anyone who tries to learn modern algebra on the basis of traditional algebra faces some of the difficulties that Rip Van Winkle would have experienced, had his awakening been delayed until the twentieth century. Rip would only overcome that sense of strangeness by riding around in airplanes until he was quite blasé about the whole business.
Some comments on the plan of the book may be helpful. Chapter 1 is introductory and will not, I hope, prove difficult reading. Chapter 2 is rather a long one. In a book for professional mathematicians, the whole content of this chapter would fill only a few lines. I tried to spell out in detail just what those few lines would convey to a mathematician. Chapter 2 was the result. The chapter contains a solid block of rather formal calculations (pages 50–56). Psychologically, it seemed a pity to have such a block early in the book, but logically I did not see where else I could put it. I would advise you not to take these calculations too seriously at a first reading. The ideas are explained before the calculations-begin. The calculations are there simply to show that the program can be carried through. At a first reading, you may like to take my word for this and skip pages 50–56. Later, when you have seen the trend of the whole book, you may return to these formal proofs. I would particularly emphasize that the later chapters do not in any way depend on the details of these calculations—only on the results.
The middle of the book is fairly plain sailing. You should be able to read these chapters fairly easily.
I am indebted to Professor Joseph Landin of the University of Illinois for the suggestion that the book should culminate with the proof that angles cannot be trisected by Euclidean means. This proof, in chapter 11, shows how modern algebraic concepts can be used to solve an ancient problem. This proof is a goal toward which the earlier chapters work.
I assume, if you are a reader of this book, that you are reasonably familiar with elementary algebra. One important result of elementary algebra seems not to be widely known. This is the remainder theorem. It states that when a polynomial f(x) is divided by x – a, the remainder is f(a). If you are not familiar with this theorem and its simple proof, it would be wise to review these, with the help of a text in traditional algebra.
Chapter 1
The Viewpoint of Abstract Algebra
THERE ARE two ways in which children do arithmetic—by understanding and by rote. A good teacher, certainly in the earlier stages, aims at getting children to understand what 5 – 2 and 6 × 8 mean. Later, he may drill them so that they will answer 48
to the question Eight sixes?
without having to draw eight sets of six dots and count them.
Suppose a foreign child enters the class. This child knows no arithmetic, and no English, but has a most retentive memory. He listens to what goes on. He notices that some questions are different from others. For instance, when the teacher makes the noise What day is it today?
the children may make the noise Monday
or Tuesday
or Wednesday
or Thursday
or Friday.
This question, he notices, has five different answers. There are also questions with two possible answers, Yes
and No.
For example, to the question Have you finished this sum?
sometimes one, sometimes the other answer is given.
However, there are questions that always receive the same answer. Hi
receives the answer Hi.
Twelve twelves?
receives the answer A hundred and forty-four
—or, at least, the teacher seems more satisfied when this response is given. Soon the foreign child might learn to make these responses, without realizing that Hi
and 144
are in rather different categories.
Suppose that the foreign child comes to school after the children in his class have finished working with blocks and beads. He sees 1 2 × 1 2 = 144 written and hears it spoken, but is never present when 12 is related to the counting of twelve objects.
One cannot say that he understands arithmetic, but he may be top of the class when it comes to reciting the multiplication table. With an excellent memory, he may have complete mastery of formal, mechanical arithmetic.
We may thus separate two elements in arithmetic. (i) The formal element—this covers everything the foreign child can observe and learn. Formal arithmetic is arithmetic seen from the outside. (ii) The intuitive element—the understanding of arithmetic, its meaning, its connection with the actual world. This understanding we derive by being part of the actual universe, by experiencing life and seeing it from the inside.
For teaching, both elements of arithmetic are necessary. But there are certain activities for which the formal approach is helpful. In the formalist philosophy of mathematics, a kind of behaviorist view is taken. Instead of asking How do mathematicians think?
the formalist philosophers ask What do mathematicians do?
They look at mathematics from the outside: they see mathematicians writing on paper, and they seek rules or laws to describe how the mathematicians behave.
Formalist philosophy is hardly likely to provide a full picture of mathematics, but it does illuminate certain aspects of mathematics.
A practical application of formalism is the design of all kinds of calculating machines and automatic appliances. A calculating machine is not expected to understand what 71 × 493 means, but it is expected to give the right answer. A fire alarm is not expected to understand the danger to life and the damage to property involved in a fire. It is expected to ring bells, to turn on sprinklers, and so forth. There may even be some connection between the way these mechanisms operate and the behavior of certain parts of the brain.
One might say that the abstract approach studies what a machine is, without bothering about what it is for.
Naturally, you may feel it is a waste of time to study a mechanism that has no purpose. But the abstract approach does not imply that a system has no meaning and no use; it merely implies that, for the moment, we are studying the structure of the system, rather than its purpose.
Structure and purpose are in fact two ways of classifying things. In comparing a car and an airplane, you would say that the propeller of an airplane corresponds to the driving wheels of a car if you are thinking in terms of purpose; you would however say that the propeller corresponds to the cooling fan if you are thinking in terms of structure.
Needless to say, a person familiar with all kinds of mechanical structures—wheels, levers, pulleys, and so on—can make use of that knowledge in inventing a mechanism. In a really original invention, a structure might be put to a purpose it had never served before.
Arithmetic Regarded as a Structure
Accordingly, we are going to look at arithmetic from the viewpoint of the foreign student. We shall forget that 12 is a number used for counting, and that + and × have definite meanings. We shall see these things purely as signs written on the keys of a machine.
Stimulus: 12 × 12.
Response: 144.
Our calculating machine would have the following visible parts:
(i) A space where the first number is recorded.
(ii) A space for the operations +, ×, –, ÷.
(iii) A space for the second number.
These constitute the input.
The output is the answer, a single number.
Playing around with our machine, we would soon observe certain things. Order is important with ÷ and –. Thus 6 ÷ 2 gives the answer 3, while 2 ÷ 6 gives the answer 1/3. But order is not important with + and ×. Thus 3 + 4 and 4 + 3 both give 7; 3 X 4 and 4 X 3 both give 12.
We have the commutative laws: a + b = b + a, a × b = b × a. (Or ab = ba, with the usual convention of leaving out the multiplication sign.)
Commutativity is not something that could have been predicted in advance. Since 6 ÷ 2 is not the same as 2 ÷ 6, we could not say, for any sign S, that
a S b = b S a.
Some comment may be made here on the symbol S. In school algebra, letters usually stand for numbers. In what we are doing, letters stand for things written on the keys of machines. The form a S b covers, for example,
a times
b,
a plus
b,
a minus
b,
a over
b,
a to the power
b,
a -th root of
b,
a -'s log to base
b,
as well as many more complicated ways of combining a and b that one could devise.
Commutativity, then, is something we may notice about a machine. It is one example of the kind of remark that can be made about a machine.
Ordinary arithmetic has one property that is inconvenient for machine purposes: it is infinite. If we make a calculating machine that goes up to 999,999 we are unable to work out, say, 999,999 + 999,999 or 999,999 × 999,999 by following the ordinary rules for operating the machine.
We can consider a particular calculating machine that is very much simpler, and that avoids the trouble of infinity. This machine will answer any question appropriate to its system. It deals with a particular part or aspect of arithmetic.
If two even numbers are added together, the result is an even number. If an even number is added to an odd number, the result is odd. We may, in fact, write
Even + Even = Even
Even + Odd = Odd
Odd + Odd = Even.
Similarly, there are multiplication facts,
Even × Even = Even
Even × Odd = Even
Odd × Odd = Odd.
Here we have a miniature arithmetic. There are only two elements in it, Even and Odd. Let us abbreviate, writing A for Even, B for Odd. Then
A + A = A
A + B = B
B + A = B
B + B = A
A × A = A
A × B = A
B × A = A
B × B = B
which may be written more compactly as
Our foreign student would have no reason for regarding A and B in the tables above as any different from 0, 1, 2, 3, · · · , in the ordinary addition and multiplication tables. He might think of it as another arithmetic.
He does not know anything about its meaning. What can he observe about its structure? Does it behave at all like ordinary arithmetic? In actual fact, the similarities are very great. I shall only mention a few of them at this stage.
Both addition and multiplication are commutative in the A, B arithmetic. For instance, A + B = B + A and A × B = B × A.
In ordinary arithmetic the number zero occurs. We know the meaning of zero. But how could zero be identified by someone who only saw the structure of arithmetic? Quite easily, for there are two properties of zero that single it out. First, when zero is added to a number, it makes no difference. Second, whatever number zero is multiplied by, the result is always zero.
Thus
Is there a symbol in the A, B arithmetic that plays the role of zero? It makes a difference when B is added: A + B is not A, nor is B + B the same as B. A is the only possible candidate, and in fact A passes all the tests. When you add A, it makes no difference; when anything is multiplied by A, you get A.
Is there anything that corresponds to 1? The only distinguishing property I can think of for 1 is that multiplication by 1 has no visible effect:
In the A, B arithmetic, multiplication by B leaves any symbol unchanged. So B plays the part of 1.
This suggests that we might have done better to choose O (capital o) as a symbol instead of A and I as a symbol instead of B, because O looks like zero, and I looks rather like 1.
Our tables would then read
Now this looks very much like ordinary arithmetic. In fact, the only question that would be raised by somebody who thought I stood for 1 and O for zero would be, Haven't you made a mistake in writing I + I = O?
All the other statements are exactly what you would expect from ordinary arithmetic.
The tables of this arithmetic
are
We arrived at the tables above by considering even and odd numbers. But we could arrive at the same pattern without any mention of numbers.
Imagine the following situation. There is a narrow bridge with automatic signals. If a car approaches from either end, a signal All clear—Proceed
is flashed on. But if cars approach from both ends, a warning signal is flashed, and the car at, say, the north end is instructed to withdraw.
In effect, the mechanism asks two questions: Is a car approaching from the south? Is one approaching from the north?
The answers to these questions are the input, the stimulus. The output, the response of the mechanism, is to switch on an appropriate signal.
For the all-clear signal the scheme is as follows.
Should all-clear signal be flashed?
For the warning signal the scheme is as follows.
Should warning signal be flashed?
If you compare these tables with the earlier ones, you will see that they are exactly the same in structure. No
replaces O,
Yes
replaces I
; all clear
is related to +, warning signal
to ×.
One could also realize this pattern by simple electrical circuits.
If you had this machine in front of you, you would not know whether it was intended for calculations with even and odd numbers, or for traffic control, or for some other purpose.
When the same pattern is embodied in two different systems, the systems are called isomorphic. In our example above, the traffic control system is isomorphic with the arithmetic of Even and Odd. The same machine does for both.
Isomorphism does not simply mean that there is some general resemblance between the two systems. It means that they have exactly the same pattern. Our example above shows this exact correspondence. Wherever O
occurs in one system, No
occurs in the other; wherever I
occurs in one system, Yes
occurs in the other.
The statements, these two systems are isomorphic
and there is an isomorphism between them,
are two different ways of saying the same thing. To prove two systems isomorphic, you must demonstrate a correspondence between them, like the one in our example.
The study of structures has two things to offer us. First, the same structure may have many different realizations. By studying the single structure, we are simultaneously learning several different subjects.
Second, even though we have only one realization of our structure in mind, we may be able to simplify our proofs and clarify our understanding of the subject by treating it abstractly—that is to say, by leaving out details that merely complicate the picture and are not relevant to