Gardner, Martin - The Colossal Book of Mathematics
Gardner, Martin - The Colossal Book of Mathematics
It
- I "\I ST F \\ ART. M n nl:'nit} l.lf War"i(il
"' Martin . ardnf!r s pu f much with the
t wor of urreali t rt: surprising, and
innurntial ror Rt'nt'l1uion, to (omt' In colle<tion
lakes his timef'xplainina both
tht' iOf,pirational outxro", uf math("mati( all
richest pu les resuhinK in a book that is fun and
insightful.
pu
SIIASIIA . \;f'_ VOf'k
l.Inhr"f'nit \, ;au I hot' u' Ib.. Po. a- Ad .... nlu"'
column for \rlrwri 1
is cola I ('ollt'clion of Martin Garon ,'s f
and columns rem:ukable- retrospective- of
hi" a."toll i hin I, inn... tial r
traonUn
1011"-11 ."LtF'-J PAll.OS.pruJruurolm.lht'm,lUl
't-.. l nlvrnh : ulhor 011.".,. ( . a d
I \I",I.,..uli, i R J. ,,...
,.yarn'" : Martin ha turnf"d do ens of inno-
I )oun sle into milt h professors lind thou nds of
milth 0 i nlu inn nt luun ,t r . lit
I Boo' 01 "'a,,.
tion:'
- PERSI 1>1 ACOl'I S ,. n'prd l n h r n 6t ,
BN 0- 393- 02023-1
I I
9 7803
\'It \\ \\ \\ \\ ((
ISBN 0-393-02023-1 USA $35.00
CAN. $51.00
"Newton said that his many mathematical 3l:l:omplish.
ments came because he stood on the shoulders of giants.
For those of us who have tried to make mathematics acces-
sible to a wider audienl:e, there is one giant who towers
well above anyone else: Martin Gardner."
-K E I T H DE V LIN, Stanrord University, unler ror Ih .. Study of Languag ..
and Inrormat ion; aut hor or Til,. Mal" Gmr, wi nner or t he 2000
CommuniClltions Award or the Joint Polic::y Board ror Mathematics
W
hether discussing hexaflexagon!' or nllmher
Klein bottles or the c:"sSf'ncf' of "nothing," Martin
Gardner has single-handedly creat d tht: fit: Id of '"recreational
mathematics." The Colossal R()()k ()f MntheHunics collects
togethtr Gardner's most popular pieces frorn hi. legendary
"Mathematical Games" olumn, which rdn in Scientific
American for twenty-five vt:'ars. Gardner's array ofahsorhing PU7-
zles and mind-twisting paradoxes openL IllLlthernatks up to the
world at large, inspiring people to see past numbers and funnulJs
and experience." the application of mathematical principles to the
mvstf'riolls world arounu thf'm. vVith articles on topi cs
from simple algebrd to the twisting surfaces of Mobius strip.
fTom an endless game of Bulgarian to the unre<.Kh .. lhle
dream of time travel, this volumt L' omprisc, a suhstantial and
definitive monument to Gardner's influenu' on m.ltht matles,
science, and culture.
In its twelve sections, "lhe C()/(lS5{l/ &ok of Mllthemlltics
explores a wide range of Jreas, eclch startlingly illuminated hv
Gardner's incisive expertise. Beginning with seemingly simple'
topiL"s, Gardner expertlY guides us through (omplic.lted .mel
wondrous worlds: by WdY of basic we \..ontempl"te the
mesmeri7ing, often hilarious, Iingui "ti( and numerical possihili-
ties of palindromes; using simple geomt'try. hc dissc(tstht, pnncj
pies of symmetry upon which the renowned mathematical Jrtist
M C. F,cher constructs his unique, dizzvin univen;t' . Gdrdner,
like lew thinkers today. mdds J ngorous scientific skepticism
with a prot()und artisti( and imaginative impulse. I lis stunning
t'xplorati<.m nf"The <.. 'hurch of the Fourth l )imensinn," for exam-
ple, bridges the dispJr Jte worlds of religinn .md sl' ience hy hril -
liantly imJgining the spatial possihility ofGtxl\ presem:e in the
world dS a fOurth dimension, at once "t:'vervwhere and nowhere."
With hnundle s wi .. dom dnd his tradem<lrk wit, Gardner
Ie mHHlIlld (m lUI( k II(/p)
I. (''''''Illt'(( I,.t"" "(lHI 'elr)
the to nlrthf'r Fngaxt' ch(lllFnging topi\. s like proha-
hilitv and gJme theory which helve plagu d clever gclmhlers,
FJmOLS mathematicians, for centuri es. Whether dehunking
Paslal's wa Jer with hasic prohability. mc!kin \ isual music with
fra -tals. or uncoiling a "knotted doughnut" with introdu "tory
topology. Gardner continuollsi displays his fierce intelligence
and gentle humor I lis articles (onn-ont both the comrortinljl}
mum..lane-"Generalil.ed TIcktacktoe
if
and "Spn. uts and Rrussel
Sprouts" -and the quakingly ahstract-'Ilexaflt"xagons," "Nothing,"
and "Evervthing: He navigates the, e taggeringly oh clire topics
with a deft intelligenL"e and. with addendums dnd suggested read
in lists, he mforms tht"se classIc articles With new insight
Admired by s ientists and mathemati ians, writers and
readers, Gardner's vast knowledge and burning curiosity reveal
themselves on every page. The culmination of a lifelong devotion
to the wonders ofmathemati s, The ColOS5flI &ok of Mathematics
is the largest and moc;t comprehensive rnath hook ever
hIed hv Gardner and remams an mdispensahle volume for ama-
teurs and experts alike,
MARTIN GARDNER iC\ the authofofmore than seventy
ona vast rangeoftoplCs.mdudingfluisand Fallacies in the Nflm
of Science The Annotated Alice and Did Adnm and hJe Hnve
Nnvels? He wrote the "Mdthemati 'al Games" oJumn for
Scientific American for more than twentv-f1ve years and is a regular
oiumnist fi)r The Skepricnl Enquirer He lives in Hendersonvill
North ..arolina.
M C KET Of ' /C; N BY OI;:BRA MORTON HO't'T
JAC KET ART C REZA ESTAKHRIANISTON E
A THOR PHUTO(;RAPIi BY OLAN MILLS
PRINTED IN THE UJ'.o1T ED STATES ot- "MERI A 8-01
The
Colossal
Book of
Mathematics
}llso by Martin Gardner
Fads and Fallacies in the Name of Science
Mathematics, Magic, and Mystery
Great Essays in Science (ed.)
Logic Machines and Diagrams
The Scientific American Book of Mathematical
Puzzles and Diversions
The Annotated Alice
The Second Scientific American Book of
Mathematical Puzzles and Diversions
Relativity for the Million
The Annotated Snark
The Ambidextrous Universe
The Annotated Ancient Mariner
New Mathematical Diversions from Scientific
American
The Annotated Casey at the Bat
Perplexing Puzzles and Tantalizing Teasers
The Unexpected Hanging and Other
Mathematical Diversions
Never Make Fun of a Thrtle, My Son (verse)
The Sixth Book of Mathematical Games from
Scientific American
Codes, Ciphers, and Secret Writing
Space Puzzles
The Snark Puzzle Book
The Flight of Peter Fromm (novel)
Mathematical Magic Show
More Perplexing Puzzles and Tantalizing Teasers
The Encyclopedia of Impromptu Magic
Aha! Insight
Mathematical Carnival
Science: Good, Bad, and Bogus
Science Fiction Puzzle Tales
Aha! Gotcha
Wheels, Life, and Other Mathematical
Amusements
Order and Surprise
Also by Martin Gardner
The Whys of a Philosophical Scrivener
Puzzles from Other Worlds
The Magic Numbers of Dr. Matrix
Knotted Doughnuts and Other Mathematical
Entertainments
The Wreck of the Titanic Foretold?
Riddles of the Sphinx
The Annotated Innocence of Father Brown
The No-Sided Professor (short stories)
Time Travel and Other Mathematical
Bewilderments
The New Age: Notes of a Fringe Watcher
Gardner's Whys and Wherefores
Penrose Tiles to Trapdoor Ciphers
How Not to Test a Psychic
The New Ambidextrous Universe
More Annotated Alice
The Annotated Night Before Christmas
Best Remembered Poems (ed.)
Fractal Music, Hypercards, and More
The Healing Revelations of Mary Baker Eddy
Martin Gardner Presents
My Best Mathematical and Logic Puzzles
Classic Brainteasers
Famous Poems of Bygone Days (ed.)
Urantia: The Great Cult Mystery
The Universe Inside a Handkerchief
On the Wild Side
Weird Water and Fuzzy Logic
The Night Is Large
Mental Magic
The Annotated Thursday
Visitors from Oz (novel)
The Annotated Alice: The Definitive Edition
Did Adam and Eve Have Navels?
Martin Gardner
The
COLOSSAL
Classic Puzzles, Paradoxes, and Problems
w. W. Norton &- Company
New York London
Number Theory
Algebra
Geometry
Probability
Topology
Game Theory
Infinity
and other Topics
of Recreational
Mathematics
Copyright 2001 by Martin Gardner
All rights reserved
Printed in the United States of America
First Edition
The text of this book is composed in Melior, with the display set in Goudy
Sans Italic with Augustea Open.
Composition by Allentown Digital Services
Manufacturing by The Maple-Vail Book Manufacturing Group
Book design by Charlotte Staub
Production manager: Andrew Marasia
Library of Congress Cataloging-in-Publication Data
Gardner, Martin, 1914-
The colossal book of mathematics: classic puzzles, paradoxes, and
problems: number theory, algebra, geometry, probability, topology, game
theory, infinity, and other topics of recreational mathematics I Martin
Gardner.
p.cm.
Includes bibliographical references and index.
ISBN 0-39302023-1
1. Mathematical recreations. 1. Title.
QA95.G245 2001
793.7'4-dc21 2001030341
W. W. Norton & Company, Inc., 500 Fifth Avenue, New York, N.Y. 10110
www.wwnorton.com
W. W. Norton & Company Ltd., Castle House, 75/76 Wells Street, London
W1T3QT
1234567890
For Qerard Piel
Who made all this possible
Contents
Preface xi
I Arithmetic and Algebra
I. The Monkey and the Coconuts 3
2. The Calculus of Finite Differences 10
3. Palindromes: Words and Numbers 23
II Plane Geometry
4. Curves of Constant Width 35
5. Rep-Tiles 46
6. Piet Hein's Superellipse 59
1. Penrose Tiles 73
8. The Wonders of a Planiverse 94
III Solid Geometry and Higher Dimensions
9. The Helix 117
10. Packing Spheres 128
II. Spheres and Hyperspheres 137
12. The Church of the Fourth Dimension 150
13. Hypercubes 162
14. Non-Euclidean Geometry 175
IV Symmetry
15. Rotations and Reflections 189
16. The Amazing Creations of Scott Kim 198
11. The Art of M. C. Escher 212
V Topology
18. Klein Bottles and Other Surfaces 227
19. Knots 239
20. Doughnuts: Linked and Knotted 254
VI Probability
21. Probability and Ambiguity 273
22. Nontransitive Dice and Other Paradoxes 286
23. More Nontransitive Paradoxes 297
VII Infinity
24. Infinite Regress 315
25. Aleph-Null and Aleph-One 327
26. Supertasks 340
21. Fractal Music 350
28. Surreal Numbers 369
VIII Combinatorics
29. Hexaflexagons 385
30. The Soma Cube 398
31. The Game of Life 409
32. Paper Folding 423
33. Ramsey Theory 437
34. Bulgarian Solitaire and Other
Seemingly Endless Tasks 455
IX qames and Decision Theory
35. A Matchbox Game-Learning Machine 471
36. Sprouts and Brussels Sprouts 485
37. Harary's Generalized Ticktacktoe 493
38. The New Eleusis 504
X Physics
39. Time Travel 517
40. Does Time Ever Stop? 531
41. Induction and Probability 541
42. Simplicity 553
XI Logic and Philosophy
43. The Unexpected Hanging 567
44. Newcomb's Paradox 580
45. Nothing 592
46. Everything 610
XII Miscellaneous
47. Melody-Making Machines 627
48. Mathematical Zoo 640
49. Godel, Escher, Bach 660
50. Six Sensational Discoveries 674
Selected Titles by the Author on
Mathematics 695
Index 697
Preface
My long and happy relationship with Scientific American, back
in the days when Gerard Piel was publisher and Dennis Flanagan was
the editor, began in 1952 when I sold the magazine an article on the his-
tory of logic machines. These were curious devices, invented in pre-
computer centuries, for solving problems in formal logic. The article
included a heavy paper insert from which one could cut a set of win-
dow cards I had devised for solving syllogisms. I later expanded the ar-
ticle to Logic Machines and Diagrams, a book published in 1959.
My second sale to Scientific American was an article on hexa-
flexagons, reprinted here as Chapter 29. As I explain in that chapter's
addendum, it prompted Piel to suggest a regular department devoted to
recreational mathematics. Titled "Mathematical Games" (that M. G. are
also my initials was a coincidence), the column ran for a quarter of a
century. As these years went by I learned more and more math. There
is no better way to teach oneself a topic than to write about it.
Fifteen anthologies of my Scientific American columns have been
published, starting with the Scientific American Book of Mathematical
Puzzles and Diversions (1959) and ending with Last Recreations (1997).
To my surprise and delight, Robert Weil, my editor at W. W. Norton,
suggested that I select 50 of what I consider my "best" columns, mainly
in the sense of arousing the greatest reader response, to make this hefty,
and, in terms of my career, definitive book you now hold. I have not in-
cluded any of my whimsical interviews with the famous numerologist
Dr. Irving Joshua Matrix because all those columns have been gathered
in The Magic Numbers of Dr. Matrix (1985).
To each chapter I have added an addendum, often lengthy, to update
the material. I also have provided selected bibliographies for further
reading.
Martin Gardner
Hendersonville, NC
xi
I
Arithmetic
and Algebra
Chapter I The Monkey
and the Coconuts
In the October 9,1926, issue of The Saturday Evening Post ap-
peared a short story by Ben Ames Williams entitled "Coconuts." The
story concerned a building contractor who was anxious to prevent a
competitor from getting an important contract. A shrewd employee of
the contractor, knowing the competitor's passion for recreational math-
ematics, presented him with a problem so exasperating that while he
was preoccupied with solving it he forgot to enter his bid before the
deadline.
Here is the problem exactly as the clerk in Williams's story phrased it:
Five men and a monkey were shipwrecked on a desert island, and they
spent the first day gathering coconuts for food. Piled them all up to-
gether and then went to sleep for the night.
But when they were all asleep one man woke up, and he thought there
might be a row about dividing the coconuts in the morning, so he de-
cided to take his share. So he divided the coconuts into five piles. He
had one coconut left over, and he gave that to the monkey, and he hid his
pile and put the rest all back together.
By and by the next man woke up and did the same thing. And he had
one left over, and he gave it to the monkey. And all five of the men did
the same thing, one after the other; each one taking a fifth of the co-
conuts in the pile when he woke up, and each one having one left over
for the monkey. And in the morning they divided what coconuts were
left, and they came out in five equal shares. Of course each one must
have known there were coconuts missing; but each one was guilty as the
others, so they didn't say anything. How many coconuts were there in
the beginning?
Williams neglected to include the answer in his story. It is said that
the offices of The Saturday Evening Post were showered with some
3
2,000 letters during the first week after the issue appeared. George Ho-
race Lorimer, then editor-in-chief, sent Williams the following historic
wire:
FOR THE LOVE OF MIKE, HOW MANY COCONUTS? HELL POPPING AROUND HERE.
For 20 years Williams continued to receive letters requesting the an-
swer or proposing new solutions. Today the problem of the coconuts is
probably the most worked on and least often solved of all the Dio-
phantine brainteasers. (The term Diophantine is descended from Dio-
phantus of Alexandria, a Greek algebraist who was the first to analyze
extensively equations calling for solutions in rational numbers.)
Williams did not invent the coconut problem. He merely altered a
much older problem to make it more confusing. The older version is the
same except that in the morning, when the final division is made, there
is again an extra coconut for the monkey; in Williams's version the final
division comes out even. Some Diophantine equations have only one
answer (e.g., x
2
+ 2 = r); some have a finite number of answers; some
(e.g., r + r = Z3) have no answer. Both Williams's version of the co-
conut problem and its predecessor have an infinite number of answers
in whole numbers. Our task is to find the smallest positive number.
The older version can be expressed by the following six indetermi-
nate equations which represent the six successive divisions of the co-
conuts into fifths. N is the original number; F, the number each sailor
received on the final division. The 1's on the right are the coconuts
tossed to the monkey. Each letter stands for an unknown positive inte-
ger:
N=5A+ 1,
4A = 5B+ 1,
4B 5C+ 1,
4C= 5D+ 1,
4D= 5E+ 1,
4E= 5F+ 1.
It is not difficult to reduce these equations by familiar algebraic
methods to the following single Diophantine equation with two un-
knowns:
1,024N= 15,625F+ 11,529.
This equation is much too difficult to solve by trial and error, and al-
though there is a standard procedure for solving it by an ingenious use
4 ARITHMETIC AND ALGEBRA
of continued fractions, the method is long and tedious. Here we shall
be concerned only with an uncanny but beautifully simple solution
involving the concept of negative coconuts. This solution is sometimes
attributed to the University of Cambridge physicist P.A.M. Dirac
(1902-1984), but in reply to my query Professor Dirac wrote that he ob-
tained the solution from J.H.C. Whitehead, professor of mathematics
(and nephew of the famous philosopher). Professor Whitehead, an-
swering a similar query, said that he got it from someone else, and I
have not pursued the matter further.
Whoever first thought of negative coconuts may have reasoned some-
thing like this. Since N is divided six times into five piles, it is clear
that 56 (or 15,625) can be added to any answer to give the next highest
answer. In fact any multiple of 56 can be added, and similarly any mul-
tiple can be subtracted. Subtracting multiples of 56 will of course even-
tually give us an infinite number of answers in negative numbers.
These will satisfy the original equation, though not the original prob-
lem, which calls for a solution that is a positive integer.
Obviously there is no small positive value for N which meets the
conditions, but possibly there is a simple answer in negative terms. It
takes only a bit of trial and error to discover the astonishing fact that
there is indeed such a solution: -4. Let us see how neatly this works
out.
The first sailor approaches the pile of -4 coconuts, tosses a positive
coconut to the monkey (it does not matter whether the monkey is given
his coconut before or after the division into fifths), thus leaving five
negative coconuts. These he divides into five piles, a negative coconut
in each. After he has hidden one pile, four negative coconuts remain-
exactly the same number that was there at the start! The other sailors
go through the same ghostly ritual, the entire procedure ending with
each sailor in possession of two negative coconuts, and the monkey,
who fares best in this inverted operation, scurrying off happily with six
positive coconuts. To find the answer that is the lowest positive inte-
ger, we now have only to add 15,625 to -4 to obtain 15,621, the solu-
tion we are seeking.
This approach to the problem provides us immediately with a gen-
eral solution for n sailors, each of whom takes one nth of the coconuts
at each division into nths. If there are four sailors, we begin with three
negative coconuts and add 4
5
. If there are six sailors, we begin with five
negative coconuts and add 6
7
, and so on for other values of n. More for-
The Monkey and the Coconuts 5
mally, the original number of coconuts is equal to k(nn+l) - m(n - 1),
where n is the number of men, m is the number of coconuts given to the
monkey at each division, and k is an arbitrary integer called the para-
meter. When n is 5 and m is 1, we obtain the lowest positive solution
by using a parameter of 1.
Unfortunately, this diverting procedure will not apply to Williams's
modification, in which the monkey is deprived of a coconut on the
last division. I leave it to the interested reader to work out the solution
to the Williams version. It can of course be found by standard Dio-
phantine techniques, but there is a quick shortcut if you take advantage
of information gained from the version just explained. For those who
find this too difficult, here is a very simple coconut problem free of all
Diophantine difficulties.
Three sailors come upon a pile of coconuts. The first sailor takes half
of them plus half a coconut. The second sailor takes half of what is left
plus half a coconut. The third sailor also takes half of what remains
plus half a coconut. Left over is exactly one coconut which they toss to
the monkey. How many coconuts were there in the original pile? If you
will arm yourself with 20 matches, you will have ample material for a
trial and error solution.
Addendum
If the use of negative coconuts for solving the earlier version of
Ben Ames Williams's problem seems not quite legitimate, essentially
the same trick can be carried out by painting four coconuts blue. Nor-
man Anning, now retired from the mathematics department of the Uni-
versity of Michigan, hit on this colorful device as early as 1912 when
he published a solution (School Science and Mathematics, June 1912,
p. 520) to a problem about three men and a supply of apples. Anning's
application of this device to the coconut problem is as follows.
We start with 56 coconuts. This is the smallest number that can be di-
vided evenly into fifths, have one-fifth removed, and the process re-
peated six times, with no coconuts going to the monkey. Four of the 56
coconuts are now painted blue and placed aside. When the remaining
supply of coconuts is divided into fifths, there will of course be one left
over to give the monkey.
After the first sailor has taken his share, and the monkey has his co-
conut, we put the four blue coconuts back with the others to make a
6 ARITHMETIC AND ALGEBRA
pile of 55 coconuts. This clearly can be evenly divided by 5. Before
making this next division, however, we again put the four blue co-
conuts aside so that the division will leave an extra coconut for the
monkey.
This procedure-borrowing the blue coconuts only long enough to
see that an even division into fifths can be made, then putting them
aside again-is repeated at each division. After the sixth and last divi-
sion, the blue coconuts remain on the side, the property of no one.
They play no essential role in the operation, serving only to make
things clearer to us as we go along.
A good recent reference on Diophantine equations and how to solve
them is Diophantus and Diophantine Equations by Isabella Bash-
makova (The Mathematical Association of America, 1997).
There are all sorts of other ways to tackle the coconut problem. John
M. Danskin, then at the Institute for Advanced Study, Princeton, NJ, as
well as several other readers, sent ingenious methods of cracking the
problem by using a number system based on 5. Scores of readers wrote
to explain other unusual approaches, but all are a bit too involved to ex-
plain here.
Answers
The number of coconuts in Ben Ames Williams's version of the
problem is 3,121. We know from the analysis of the older version that
55 4, or 3,121, is the smallest number that will permit five even divi-
sions of the coconuts with one going to the monkey at each division.
After these five divisions have been made, there will be 1,020 coconuts
left. This number happens to be evenly divisible by 5, which permits
the sixth division in which no coconut goes to the monkey.
In this version of the problem a more general solution takes the form
of two Diophantine equations. When n, the number of men, is odd, the
equation is
Number of coconuts = (1 + nk)nn - (n - 1).
When n is even,
Number of coconuts = (n - 1 + nk)nn - (n - 1).
In both equations k is the parameter that can be any integer. In
Williams's problem the number of men is 5, an odd number, so 5 is sub-
The Monkey and the Coconuts 7
stituted for n in the first equation, and k is taken as 0 to obtain the low-
est positive answer.
A letter from Dr. J. Walter Wilson, a Los Angeles dermatologist, re-
ported an amusing coincidence involving this answer:
Sirs:
I read Ben Ames Williams's story about the coconut problem in 1926,
spent a sleepless night working on the puzzle without success, then
learned from a professor of mathematics how to use the Diophantine
equation to obtain the smallest answer, 3,121.
In 1939 I suddenly realized that the home on West 80th Street, Ingle-
wood, California, in which my family and I had been living for several
months, bore the street number 3121. Accordingly, we entertained all of
our most erudite friends one evening by a circuit of games and puzzles,
each arranged in a different room, and visited by groups of four in rota-
tion.
The coconut puzzle was presented on the front porch, with the table
placed directly under the lighted house number blazingly giving the se-
cret away, but no one caught on!
The simpler problem of the three sailors, at the end of the chapter,
has the answer: 15 coconuts. If you tried to solve this by breaking
matches in half to represent halves of coconuts, you may have con-
cluded that the problem was unanswerable. Of course no coconuts
need be split at all in order to perform the required operations.
Ben Ames Williams's story was reprinted in Clifton Fadiman's an-
thology, The Mathematical Magpie (1962), reissued in paperback by
Copernicus in 1997. David Singmaster, in his unpublished history of
famous mathematical puzzles, traces similar problems back to the Mid-
dle Ages. Versions appear in numerous puzzle books, as well as in text-
books that discuss Diophantine problems. My bibliography is limited
to periodicals in English.
Bibliography
N. Anning, "Solution to a Problem," School Science and Mathematics, June 1912,
p.520.
N. Anning, "Monkeys and Coconuts," The Mathematics Teacher, Vol. 54, Decem-
ber 1951, pp. 560-62.
J. Bowden, "The Problem ofthe Dishonest Men, the Monkeys, and the Coconuts,"
Special Topics in Theoretical Arithmetic, pp. 203-12. Privately printed for the
author by Lancaster Press, Inc., Lancaster, PA, 1936.
8 ARITHMETIC AND ALGEBRA
P. W. Brashear, "Five Sailors and a Monkey," The Mathematics Teacher, October
1967, pp. 597-99.
S. King, "More Coconuts," The College Mathematics Journal, September 1998, pp.
312-13.
R. B. Kirchner, "The Generalized Coconut Problem," The American Mathematical
Monthly, Vol. 67, June-July 1960, pp. 516-19.
R. E. Moritz, "Solution to Problem 3,242," The American Mathematical Monthly,
Vol. 35, January 1928, pp. 47-48.
T. Shin and G. Salvatore, "On Coconuts and Integrity," Crux Mathematicorum,
Vol. 4, August/September 1978, pp. 182-85.
S. Singh and D. Bhattacharya, "On Dividing Coconuts: A Linear Diophantine Prob-
lem," The College Mathematics Journal, May 1997, pp. 203-4.
The Monkey and the Coconuts 9
Chapter 2 The Calculus of
Finite Differences
The calculus of finite differences, a branch of mathematics that
is not too well known but is at times highly useful, occupies a halfway
house on the road from algebra to calculus. W. W. Sawyer, a mathe-
matician at Wesleyan University, likes to introduce it to students by
performing the following mathematical mind-reading trick.
Instead of asking someone to "think of a number" you ask him to
"think of a formula." To make the trick easy, it should be a quadratic
formula (a formula containing no powers of x greater than x
2
). Suppose
he thinks of 5x
2
+ 3x - 7. While your back is turned so that you cannot
see his calculations, ask him to substitute 0,1, and 2 for x, then tell you
the three values that result for the entire expression. The values he
gives you are -7, 1, 19. After a bit of scribbling (with practice you can
do it in your head) you tell him the original formula!
The method is simple. Jot down in a row the values given to you. In
a row beneath write the differences between adjacent pairs of num-
bers, always subtracting the number on the left from its neighbor on the
right. In a third row put the difference between the numbers above it.
The chart will look like this
-7 1 19
8 18
10
The coefficient of x
2
, in the thought-of formula, is always half the bot-
tom number of the chart. The coefficient of x is obtained by taking half
the bottom number from the first number of the middle row. And the
constant in the formula is simply the first number of the top row.
What you have done is something analogous to integration in calcu-
lus. If y is the value of the formula, then the formula expresses a func-
10
tion of y with respect to x. When x is given values in a simple arith-
metic progression (0, 1, 2, ... ), thenyassumes a series of values (-7, 1,
19, ... ). The calculus of finite differences is the study of such series.
In this case, by applying a simple technique to three terms of a series,
you were able to deduce the quadratic function that generated the three
terms.
The calculus of finite differences had its origin in Methodus Incre-
mentorum, a treatise published by the English mathematician Brook
Taylor (who discovered the "Taylor theorem" of calculus) between
1715 and 1717. The first important work in English on the subject (after
it had been developed by Leonhard Euler and others) was published in
1860 by George Boole, of symbolic-logic fame. Nineteenth-century al-
gebra textbooks often included a smattering of the calculus, then it
dropped out of favor except for its continued use by actuaries in check-
ing annuity tables and its occasional use by scientists for finding for-
mulas and interpolating values. Today, as a valuable tool in statistics
and the social sciences, it is back in fashion once more.
For the student of recreational mathematics there are elementary pro-
cedures in the calculus of finite differences that can be enormously
useful. Let us see how such a procedure can be applied to the old prob-
lem of slicing a pancake. What is the maximum number of pieces into
which a pancake can be cut by n straight cuts, each of which crosses
each of the others? The number is clearly a function of n. If the func-
tion is not too complex, the method of differences may help us to find
it by empirical techniques.
No cut at all leaves one piece, one cut produces two pieces, two cuts
yield four pieces, and so on. It is not difficult to find by trial and error
that the series begins: 1, 2, 4,7,11, ... (see Figure 2.1). Make a chart as
before, forming rows, each representing the differences of adjacent
terms in the row above:
NUMBER OF CUTS
Number of pieces
First differences
Second differences
o 1 2 3 4
1 2 4 7 11
1 2 3 4
1 1 1
If the original series is generated by a linear function, the numbers in
the row of first differences will be all alike. If the function is a qua-
dratic, identical numbers appear in the row of second differences. A
The Calculus of Finite Differences 11
2 CUTS
4 PIECES
Figure 2.1. The pancake problem
o CUTS
1 PIECE
3 CUTS
7 PIECES
1 CUT
2 PIECES
4 CUTS
11 PIECES
cubic formula (no powers higher than Xl) will have identical numbers
in the row of third differences, and so on. In other words, the number
of rows of differences is the order of the formula. If the chart required
10 rows of differences before the numbers in a row became the same,
you would know that the generating function contained powers as high
as x
10
.
Here there are only two rows, so the function must be a quadratic. Be-
cause it is a quadratic, we can obtain it quickly by the simple method
used in the mind-reading trick.
The pancake-cutting problem has a double interpretation. We can
view it as an abstract problem in pure geometry (an ideal circle cut by
ideal straight lines) or as a problem in applied geometry (a real pancake
cut by a real knife). Physics is riddled with situations of this sort that
can be viewed in both ways and that involve formulas obtainable from
empirical results by the calculus of finite differences. A famous exam-
ple of a quadratic formula is the formula for the maximum number of
electrons that can occupy each "shell" of an atom. Going outward from
the nucleus, the series runs 0, 2, 8, 18, 32, 50 .... The first row of dif-
ferences is 2, 6, 10, 14, 18 .... The second row is 4, 4, 4, 4 .... Apply-
12 ARITHMETIC AND ALGEBRA
ing the key to the mind-reading trick, we obtain the simple formula 2n2
for the maximum number of electrons in the nth shell.
What do we do if the function is of a higher order? We can make use
of a remarkable formula discovered by Isaac Newton. It applies in all
cases, regardless of the number of tiers in the chart.
Newton's formula assumes that the series begins with the value of the
function when n is O. We call this number a. The first number of the
first row of differences is b, the first number of the next row is c, and
so on. The formula for the nth number of the series is
b
cn(n - 1) dn(n - 1)(n - 2)
a + n + + --=-------'---'-----=-
2 2-3
en(n - l)(n - 2)(n - 3) ...
+--'-----'-'-------'-""""'-------'-
2-3-4
The formula is used only up to the point at which all further addi-
tions would be zero. For example, if applied to the pancake-cutting
chart, the values of 1, 1, 1 are substituted for a, b, c in the formula. (The
rest of the formula is ignored because all lower rows of the chart con-
sist of zeros; d, e, f, ... therefore have values of zero, consequently the
entire portion of the formula containing these terms adds up to zero.)
In this way we obtain the quadratic function ~ n 2 + n + 1.
Does this mean that we have now found the formula for the maxi-
mum number of pieces produced by n slices of a pancake? Unfortu-
nately the most that can be said at this point is "Probably." Why the
uncertainty? Because for any finite series of numbers there is an infin-
ity of functions that will generate them. (This is the same as saying
that for any finite number of points on a graph, an infinity of curves can
be drawn through those points.) Consider the series 0,1,2,3 .... What
is the next term? A good guess is 4. In fact, if we apply the technique
just explained, the row of first differences will be l's, and Newton's for-
mula will tell us that the nth term of the series is simply n. But the
formula
1
n + 24n(n l)(n - 2)(n - 3)
also generates a series that begins 0, 1, 2, 3 .... In this case the series
continues, not 4, 5, 6, ... but 5, 10, 21 ....
There is a striking analogy here with the way laws are discovered in
science. In fact, the method of differences can often be applied to phys-
The Calculus of Finite Differences 13
ical phenomena for the purpose of guessing a natural law. Suppose, for
example, that a physicist is investigating for the first time the way in
which bodies fall. He observes that after one second a stone drops 16
feet, after two seconds 64 feet, and so on. He charts his observations
like this:
o 16
16 48
32
64
80
32
144
112
32
256
Actual measurements would not, of course, be exact, but the num-
bers in the last row would not vary much from 32, so the physicist as-
sumes that the next row of differences consists of zeros. Applying
Newton's formula, he concludes that the total distance a stone falls in
n seconds is 16n
2
But there is nothing certain about this law. It repre-
sents no more than the simplest function that accounts for a finite se-
ries of observations: the lowest order of curve that can be drawn
through a finite series of points on a graph. True, the law is confirmed
to a greater degree as more observations are made, but there is never
certainty that more observations will not require modification of the
law.
With respect to pancake cutting, even though a pure mathematical
structure is being investigated rather than the behavior of nature, the
situation is surprisingly similar. For all we now know, a fifth slice may
not produce the sixteen pieces predicted by the formula. A single fail-
ure of this sort will explode the formula, whereas no finite number of
successes, however large, can positively establish it. "Nature," as
George P6lya has put it, "may answer Yes or No, but it whispers one an-
swer and thunders the other. Its Yes is provisional, its No is defini-
tive." P6lya is speaking of the world, not abstract mathematical
structure, but it is curious that his point applies equally well to the
guessing of functions by the method of differences. Mathematicians do
a great deal of guessing, along lines that are often similar to methods of
induction in science, and P6lya has written a fascinating work, Math-
ematics and Plausible Reasoning, about how they do it.
Some trial and error testing, with pencil and paper, shows that five
cuts of a pancake do in fact produce a maximum of sixteen pieces. This
successful prediction by the formula adds to the probability that the
formula is correct. But until it is rigorously proved (in this case it is not
hard to do) it stands only as a good bet. Why the simplest formula is so
14 ARITHMETIC AND ALGEBRA
often the best bet, both in mathematical and scientific guessing, is one
of the lively controversial questions in contemporary philosophy of
science. For one thing, no one is sure just what is meant by "simplest
formula."
Here are a few problems that are closely related to pancake cutting
and that are all approachable by way of the calculus of finite differ-
ences. First you find the best guess for a formula, then you try to prove
the formula by deductive methods. What is the maximum number of
pieces that can be produced by n simultaneous straight cuts of a flat fig-
ure shaped like a crescent moon? How many pieces of cheesecake can
be produced by n simultaneous plane cuts of a cylindrical cake? Into
how many parts can the plane be divided by intersecting circles of the
same size? Into how many regions can space be divided by intersecting
spheres?
Recreational problems involving permutations and combinations
often contain low-order formulas that can be correctly guessed by the
method of finite differences and later (one hopes) proved. With an un-
limited supply of toothpicks of n different colors, how many different
triangles can be formed on a flat surface, using three toothpicks for the
three sides of each triangle? (Reflections are considered different, but
not rotations.) How many different squares? How many different tetra-
hedrons can be produced by coloring each face a solid color and using
n different colors? (Two tetrahedrons are the same if they can be turned
and placed side by side so that corresponding sides match in color.)
How many cubes with n colors?
Of course, if a series is generated by a function other than a polyno-
mial involving powers of the variable, then other techniques in the
method of differences are called for. For example, the exponential func-
tion 2
n
produces the series 1, 2,4,8, 16 .... The row of first differences
is also 1, 2,4,8, 16, ... , so the procedure explained earlier will get us
nowhere. Sometimes a seemingly simple situation will involve a series
that evades all efforts to find a general formula. An annoying example
is the necklace problem posed in one of Henry Ernest Dudeney's puz-
zle books. A circular necklace contains n beads. Each bead is black or
white. How many different necklaces can be made with n beads? Start-
ing with no beads, the series is 0, 2, 3, 4, 6, 8, 13, 18, 30 .... (Figure 2.2
shows the 18 different varieties of necklace when n = 7.) I suspect that
two formulas are interlocked here, one for odd n, one for even, but
whether the method of differences will produce the formulas, I do not
The Calculus of Finite Differences 15
two
16 AND
Figure 2.3. Five lines make ten triangles.
n
3
+ 3n
2
+ an
6
that can be obtained by applying Newton's formula to results obtained
empirically, but it does not seem to apply to the zero case. When a
doughnut is not cut at all, clearly there is one piece, whereas the for-
mula says there should be no pieces. To make the formula applicable,
we must define "piece" as part of a doughnut produced by cutting.
Where there is ambiguity about the zero case, one must extrapolate
backward in the chart of differences and assume for the zero case a
value that produces the desired first number in the last row of differ-
ences.
To prove that the formula given for the maximum number of regions
into which a pancake (circle) can be divided by n straight cuts, consider
first the fact that each nth line crosses n - 1 lines. The n - 1 lines di-
vide the plane into n regions. When the nth line crosses these n regions,
it cuts each region into two parts, therefore every nth line adds n re-
gions to the total. At the beginning there is one piece. The first cut
adds one more piece, the second cut adds two more pieces, the third
cut adds three more, and so on up to the nth cut which adds n pieces.
Therefore the total number of regions is 1 + 1 + 2 + 3 + ... + n. The sum
of 1 + 2 + 3 + ... + n is %n(n - 1). To this we must add 1 to obtain the
final formula.
The bead problem was given by Dudeney as problem 275 in his Puz-
The Calculus of Finite Differences 17
zles and Curious Problems. John Riordan mentions the problem on
page 162, problem 37, of his Introduction to Combinatorial Analysis
(Wiley, 1958; now out of print), indicating the solution without giving
actual formulas. (He had earlier discussed the problem in "The Com-
binatorial Significance of a Theorem of P6Iya," Journal of the Society
for Industrial and Applied Mathematics, Vol. 5, No.4, December 1957,
pp. 232-34.) The problem was later treated in considerable detail, with
some surprising applications to music theory and switching theory, by
Edgar N. Gilbert and John Riordan, in "Symmetry Types of Periodic Se-
quences," Illinois Journal of Mathematics, Vol. 5, No.4, December
1961, pages 657-65. The authors give the following table for the num-
ber of different types of necklaces, with beads of two colors, for neck-
laces of 1 through 20 beads:
NUMBER OF NUMBER OF
BEADS NECKLACES
1 2
2 3
3 4
4 6
5 8
6 13
7 18
8 30
9 46
10 78
11 126
12 224
13 380
14 687
15 1,224
16 2,250
17 4,112
18 7,685
19 14,310
20 27,012
The formulas for the necklace problem do not mean, by the way, that
Dudeney was necessarily wrong in saying that a solution was not pos-
sible, since he may have meant only that it was not possible to find a
polynomial expression for the number of necklaces as a function of n
so that the number could be calculated directly from the formula with-
18 ARITHMETIC AND ALGEBRA
out requiring a tabulation of prime factors. Because the formulas in-
clude Euler's phi function, the number of necklaces has to be calculated
recursively. Dudeney's language is not precise, but it is possible that he
would not have considered recursive formulas a "solution." At any
rate, the calculus of finite differences is not in any way applicable to the
problem, and only the recursive formulas are known.
Several dozen readers (too many for a listing of names) sent correct
solutions to the problem before Golomb's formulas were printed, some
of them deriving it from Riordan, others working it out entirely for
themselves. Many pointed out that when the number of beads is a
prime (other than 2), the formula for the number of different necklaces
becomes very simple:
2
n
-
1
- 1 n-l
---- + 2-2 + 1.
n
The following letter from John F. Gummere, headmaster of William
Penn Charter School, Philadelphia, appeared in the letters department
of Scientific American in October 1961:
Sirs:
I read with great interest your article on the calculus of finite differ-
ences. It occurs to me that one of the most interesting applications of
Newton's formula is one I discovered for myself long before I had reached
the calculus. This is simply applying the method of finite differences to
series of powers. In experimenting with figures, I noticed that if you
wrote a series of squares such as 4,9,16,25,36,49 and subtracted them
from each other as you went along, you got a series that you could sim-
ilarly subtract once again and come up with a finite difference.
So then I tried cubes and fourth powers and evolved a formula to the
effect that if n is the power, you must subtract n times, and your constant
difference will be factorial n. I asked my father about this (he was for
many years director of the Strawbridge Memorial Observatory at Haver-
ford College and teacher of mathematics). In good Quaker language he
said: "Why, John, thee has discovered the calculus of finite differences."
Donald Knuth called my attention to the earliest known solution of
Dudeney's bead problem. Percy A. MacMahon solved the problem as
early as 1892. This and the problem are discussed in Section 4.9 of
Concrete Mathematics (1994), by Ronald Graham, Donald Knuth, and
Oren Patashnik.
The Calculus of Finite Differences 19
Answers
How many different triangles can be formed with n straight
lines? It takes at least three lines to make one triangle, four lines will
make four triangles, and five lines will make 10 triangles. Applying the
calculus of finite differences, one draws up the table in Figure 2.4.
NUMBER OF LINES 0 1 2 3 4 5 Figure 2.4. The answer
to the triangle problem
NUMBER OF TRIANGLES 0 0 0 1 4 10
FIRST DIFFERENCES 0 0 1 3 6
SECOND DIFFERENCES 0 1 2 3
THIRD DIFFERENCES 1 1 1
The three rows of differences indicate a cubic function. Using New-
ton's formula, the function is found to be: %n(n - l)(n - 2). This will
generate the series 0, 0, 0, 1, 4, 10, ... and therefore has a good
chance of being the formula for the maxinlum number of triangles
that can be made with n lines. But it is still just a guess, based on a
small number of pencil and paper tests. It can be verified by the fol-
lowing reasoning.
The lines must be drawn so that no two are parallel and no more than
two intersect at the same point. Each line is then sure to intersect every
other line, and every set of three lines must form one triangle. It is not
possible for the same three lines to form more than one triangle, so the
number of triangles formed in this way is the maximum. The problem
is equivalent, therefore, to the question: In how many different ways
can n lines be taken three at a time? Elementary combinatorial theory
supplies the answer: the same as the formula obtained empirically.
Solomon W. Golomb, was kind enough to send me his solution to the
necklace problem. The problem was to find a formula for the number
of different necklaces that can be formed with n beads, assuming tha!
each bead can be one of two colors and not counting rotations and re-
flections of a necklace as being different. The formula proves to be far
beyond the power of the simple method of differences.
Let the divisors of n (including 1 and n) be represented by dl' d
2
,
d
3
For each divisor we find what is called Euler's phi function for
that divisor, symbolized <I>(d). This function is the number of positive
integers, not greater than d, that have no common divisor with d. It is
assumed that 1 is such an integer, but not d. Thus <1>(8) is 4, because 8
20 ARITHMETIC AND ALGEBRA
has the following four integers that are prime to it: 1, 3, 5, 7. By con-
vention, <P(1) is taken to be 1. Euler's phi functions for 2, 3,4,5,6, 7 are
1,2,2,4,2,6, in the same order. Let a stand for the number of differ-
ent colors each bead can be. For necklaces with an odd number of
beads the formula for the number of different necklaces with n beads
is the one given at the top of Figure 2.5. When n is even, the formula is
the one at the bottom of the illustration.
1 [ .ll. n n 11]
- q,(d
1
) ad, + q,(d
2
) ali; ... + - (1 + a) a"2
2n 2
Figure 2.S. Equations for the solution of the necklace problem
The single dots are symbols for multiplication. Golomb expressed
these formulas in a more compressed, technical form, but I think the
above forms will be clearer to most readers. They are more general than
the formulas asked for because they apply to beads that may have any
specified number of colors.
The formulas answering the other questions in the chapter are:
1. Regions of a crescent moon produced by n straight cuts:
n
2
+ 3n
---+1.
2
2. Pieces of cheesecake produced by n plane cuts:
n
3
+ 5n
---+1.
6
3. Regions of the plane produced by n intersecting circles:
n
2
- n + 2.
4. Regions of the plane produced by n intersecting ellipses:
2n2 2n + 2.
5. Regions of space produced by n intersecting spheres:
- 3n + 8)
3
The Calculus of Finite Differences 21
6. Triangles formed by toothpicks of n colors:
n
3
+ 2n
3
7. Squares formed with toothpicks of n colors:
n
4
+ n
2
+ 2n
4
8. Tetrahedrons formed with sides of n colors:
n
4
+ 11n2
12
9. Cubes formed with sides of n colors:
n
6
+ 3n
4
+ 12n
3
+ 8n
2
24
Bibliography
E. L. Baker, "The Method of Differences in the Determination of Formulas," School
Science and Mathematics, April 1967, pp. 309-15.
C. Jordan, The Calculus of Finite Differences, Chelsea, 1965.
K. S. Miller, An Introduction to the Calculus of Finite Differences and Difference
Equations, Henry Holt, 1960.
W. E. Milne, Numerical Calculus, Princeton University Press, 1949.
L. M. Milne-Thomson, The Calculus of Finite Differences, Macmillan, 1951.
R. C. Read, "P6Iya's Theorem and its Progeny," in Mathematics Magazine, VoL 60,
December 1987, pp. 275-82. Eighteen references are listed.
22 ARITHMETIC AND ALGEBRA
A man} a a canal-Suez!
-Ethel Merperso:n,
in Son of Giant Sea Tortoise,
Ann AY.lQ'UUW;;',I..l
usually defined as a or
.;J'\J..L.l.I..'\J.LJ.'-" .... LJl that spell the same backward as forward. The term is also ap-
are types
long
play, perhaps because of a
aesthetic pleasure in the kind of symmetry palindromes possess. Palin-
dromes that are
'-' ..... , ........ , ................ some
3.1. seagull: a visual palindrome
An old palindrome conjecture origin (there are
enees it
integer. it and add the
is repeated with the sum to obtain a second sum, and the process COD-
a
a
68 generates a palindrome in three steps:
23
68
+ 86
154
+451
605
+506
1,111
For all two-digit numbers it is obvious that if the sum of their digits
is less than 10, the first step gives a two-digit palindrome. If their dig-
its add to 10, 11, 12, 13, 14, 15, 16, or 18, a palindrome results after 2,
1, 2, 2, 3, 4, 6, 6 steps, respectively. As Angela Dunn points out in
Mathematical Bafflers (McGraw-Hill, 1964; Dover, 1980), the excep-
tions are numbers whose two digits add to 17. Only 89 (or its reversal,
98) meets this proviso. Starting with either number does not produce
a palindrome until the 24th operation results in 8,813,200,023,188.
The conjecture was widely regarded as being true until 1967, al-
though no one had succeeded in proving it. Charles W. Trigg, a Cali-
fornia mathematician well known for his work on recreational
problems, examined the conjecture more carefully in his 1967 article
"Palindromes by Addition." He found 249 integers smaller than
10,000 that failed to generate a palindrome after 100 steps. The small-
est such number, 196, was carried to 237,310 steps in 1975 by Harry
J. Saal, at the Israel Scientific Center. No palindromic sum appeared.
Trigg believed the conjecture to be false. (The number 196 is the
square of 14, but this is probably an irrelevant fact.) Aside from the
249 exceptions, all integers less than 10,000, except 89 and its rever-
sal, produce a palindrome in fewer than 24 steps. The largest palin-
drome, 16,668,488,486,661, is generated by 6,999 (or its reversal) and
7,998 (or its reversal) in 20 steps.
The conjecture has not been established for any number system and
has been proved false only in number notations with bases that are
powers of 2. (See the paper by Heiko Harborth listed in the bibliogra-
phy.) The smallest binary counterexample is 10110 (or 22 in the deci-
mal system). After four steps the sum is 10110100, after eight steps it
is 1011101000, after 12 steps it is 101111010000. Every fourth step in-
creases by one digit each of the two sequences of underlined digits.
Brother Alfred Brousseau, in "Palindromes by Addition in Base Two,"
proved that this asymmetric pattern repeats indefinitely. He also found
other repeating asymmetric patterns for larger binary numbers.
24 ARITHMETIC AND ALGEBRA
There is a small but growing literature on the properties of palin-
dromic prime numbers and conjectures about them. Apparently there
are infinitely many such primes, although so far as I know this has not
been proved. It is not hard to show, however, that a palindromic prime,
with the exception of 11, must have an odd number of digits. Can the
reader do this before reading the simple proof in the answer section?
Norman T. Gridgeman conjectured that there is an infinity of prime
pairs of the form 30,103-30,203 and 9,931,399-9,932,399 in which all
digits are alike except the middle digits, which differ by one. But
Gridgeman's guess is far from proved.
Gustavus J. Simmons wrote two papers on palindromic powers. After
showing that the probability of a randomly selected integer being palin-
dromic approaches zero as the number of digits in the integer increases,
Simmons examined square numbers and found them much richer than
randomly chosen integers in palindromes. There are infinitely many
palindromic squares, most of which, it seems, have square roots that
also are palindromes. (The smallest nonpalindromic root is 26). Cubes
too are unusually rich in palindromes. A computer check on all cubes
less than 2.8 x 10
14
turned up a truly astonishing fact. The only palin-
dromic cube with a nonpalindromic cube root, among the cubes ex-
amined by Simmons, is 10,662,526,601. Its cube root, 2,201, had been
noticed earlier by Thigg, who reported in 1961 that it was the only non-
palindrome with a palindromic cube less than 1,953,125,000,000. It is
not yet known if 2,201 is the only integer with this property.
Simmons' computer search of palindromic fourth powers, to the
same limit as his search of cubes, failed to uncover a single palindromic
fourth power whose fourth root was not a palindrome of the general
form 10 ... 01. For powers 5 through 10 the computer found no palin-
dromes at all except the trivial case of 1. Simmons conjectured that
there are no palindromes of the form Xk where k is greater than 4.
"Repunits," numbers consisting entirely of l's, produce palindromic
squares when the number of units is one through nine, but 10 or more
units give squares that are not palindromic. It has been erroneously
stated that only primes have palindromic cubes, but this is disproved
by an infinity of integers, the smallest of which is rep unit 111. It is di-
visible by 3, yet its cube, 1,367,631, is a palindrome. The number 836
is also of special interest. It is the largest three-digit integer whose
square, 698,896, is palindromic, and 698,896 is the smallest palin-
dromic square with an even number of digits. (Note also that the num-
Palindromes: Words and Numbers 25
ber remains palindromic when turned upside down.) Such palin-
dromic squares are extremely rare. The next-larger one with an even
number of digits is 637,832,238,736, the square of 798,644.
Turning to language palindromes, we first note that no common Eng-
lish words of more than seven letters are palindromic. Examples of
seven-letter palindromes are reviver, repaper, deified, and rotator. The
word "radar" (for radio detecting and ranging) is notable because it
was coined to symbolize the reflection of radio waves. Dmitri
Borgmann, whose files contain thousands of sentence palindromes in
all major languages, asserts in his book Language on Vacation that the
largest nonhyphenated word palindrome is saippuakauppias, a
Finnish word for a soap dealer.
Among proper names in English, according to Borgmann, none is
longer than Wassamassaw, a swamp north of Charleston, sc. Legend
has it, he writes, that it is an Indian word meaning "the worst place ever
seen." Yreka Bakery has long been in business on West Miner Street in
Yreka, CA. Lon Nol, the former Cambodian premier, has a palindromic
name, as does U Nu, once premier of Burma. Revilo P. Oliver, a classics
professor at the University of Illinois, has the same first name as his fa-
ther and grandfather. It was originally devised to make the name
palindromic. If there is anyone with a longer palindromic name I do
not know of it, although Borgmann suggests such possibilities as
Norah Sara Sharon, Edna Lala Lalande, Duane Rollo Renaud, and
many others.
There are thousands of excellent sentence palindromes in English, a
few of which were discussed in a chapter on word play in my Sixth
Book of Mathematical Games from Scientific American. The interested
reader will find good collections in the Borgmann book cited above
and in the book by Howard Bergerson. Composing palindromes at night
is one way for an insomniac to pass the dark hours, as Roger Angell so
amusingly details in his article" Ainmosni" (HInsomnia" backward) in
The New Yorker. I limit myself to one palindrome that is not well
known, yet is remarkable for both its length and naturalness: "Doc note,
I dissent. A fast never prevents a fatness. I diet on cod." It won a prize
for James Michie in a palindrome contest sponsored by the New States-
man in England; results were published in the issue for May 5,1967.
Many of the winning palindromes are much longer than Michie's, but,
as is usually the case, the longer palindromes are invariably difficult to
understand.
26 ARITHMETIC AND ALGEBRA
Palindromists have employed various devices to make the unintelli-
gibility of long palindromes more plausible: presenting them as
telegrams, as one side only of a telephone conversation, and so on.
Leigh Mercer, a leading British palindromist (he is the inventor of the
famous "A man, a plan, a canal-Panama!"), has suggested a way of
writing a palindrome as long as one wishes. The sentence has the form,
" , sides reversed, is ' .' " The first blank can be any se-
quence of letters, however long, which is repeated in reverse order in
the second blank.
Good palindromes involving the names of U.S. presidents are ex-
ceptionally rare. Borgmann cites the crisp "Taft: fat!" as one of the
shortest and best. Richard Nixon's name lends itself to "No 'x' in 'Mr.
R. M. Nixon'?" although the sentence is a bit too contrived. A shorter,
capitalized version of this palindrome, NO X IN NIXON, is also in-
vertible.
The fact that "God" is "dog" backward has played a role in many sen-
tence palindromes, as well as in orthodox psychoanalysis. In Freud's
Contribution to Psychiatry A. A. Brill cites a rather farfetched analysis
by Carl Jung and others of a patient suffering from a ticlike upward
movement of his arms. The analysts decided that the tic had its origin
in an unpleasant early visual experience involving dogs. Because of the
"dog-god" reversal, and the man's religious convictions, his uncon-
scious had developed the gesture to symbolize a warding off of the evil
"dog-god." Edgar Allan Poe's frequent use of the reversal words "dim"
and "mid" is pointed out by Humbert Humbert, the narrator of
Vladimir Nabokov's novel Lolita. In the second canto of Pale Fire, in
Nabokov's novel of the same title, the poet John Shade speaks of his
dead daughter's propensity for word reversals:
... She twisted words: pot, top,
Spider, redips. And upowder" was ured wop. "
Such word reversals, as well as sentences that are different sentences
when they are spelled backward, are obviously close cousins of palin-
dromes, but the topic is too large to go into here.
Palindrome sentences in which words, not letters, are the units have
been a specialty of another British expert on word play, J. A. Lindon.
Two splendid examples, from scores that he has composed, are
"You can cage a swallow, can't you, but you can't swallow a cage, can
you?"
Palindromes: Words and Numbers 27
"Girl, bathing on Bikini, eyeing boy, finds boy eyeing bikini on
bathing girl."
Many attempts have been made to write letter-unit palindrome
poems, some quite long, but without exception they are obscure,
rhymeless, and lacking in other poetic values. Somewhat better poems
can be achieved by making each line a separate palindrome rather than
the entire poem or by using the word as the unit. Lindon has written
many poems of both types. A third type of palindrome poem, invented
by Lindon, employs lines as units. The poem is unchanged when its
lines are read forward but taken in reverse order. One is allowed, of
course, to punctuate duplicate lines differently. The following example
is one of Lindon's best:
As I was passing near the jail
I met a man, but hurried by.
His face was ghastly, grimly pale.
He had a gun. I wondered why
He had. A gun? I wondered . .. why,
His face was ghastly! Grimly pale,
I met a man, but hurried by,
As I was passing near the jail.
This longer one is also by Lindon. Both poems appear in Howard W.
Bergerson's Palindromes and Anagrams (Dover, 1973).
28
DOPPELGANGER
Entering the lonely house with my wife,
I saw him for the first time
Peering furtively from behind a bush-
Blackness that moved,
A shape amid the shadows,
A momentary glimpse of gleaming eyes
Revealed in the ragged moon.
A closer look (he seemed to turn) might have
Put him to flight forever-
I dared not
(For reasons that I failed to understand),
Though I knew I should act at once.
I puzzled over it, hiding alone,
Watching the woman as she neared the gate.
He came, and I saw him crouching
ARITHMETIC AND ALGEBRA
Night after night.
Night after night
He came, and I saw him crouching,
Watching the woman as she neared the gate.
I puzzled over it, hiding alone-
Though I knew I should act at once,
For reasons that I failed to understand
I dared not
Put him to flight forever.
A closer look (he seemed to turn) might have
Revealed in the ragged moon
A momentary glimpse of gleaming eyes,
A shape amid the shadows,
Blackness that moved.
Peering furtively from behind a bush,
I saw him, for the first time,
Entering the lonely house with my wife.
Lindon holds the record for the longest word ever worked into a
letter-unit palindrome. To understand the palindrome you must know
that Beryl has a husband who enjoys running around his yard without
any clothes on. Ned has asked him if he does this to annoy his wife. He
answers: "Named un denominationally rebel, I rile Beryl? La, no! I tan.
I'm, 0 Ned, nude, man!"
Addendum
A. Ross Eckler, editor and publisher of Word Ways, a quarterly
journal on word play that has featured dozens of articles on palin-
dromes of all types, wrote to say that the "palindromic gap" between
English and other languages is perhaps not as wide as I suggested. The
word "semitime" can be pluralized to make a 9-letter palindrome and
"kinnikinnik" is an ii-letter palindrome. Dmitri Borgmann pointed
out in Word Ways, said Eckler, that an examination of foreign dictio-
naries failed to substantiate such long palindromic words as the
Finnish soap dealer, suggesting that they are artificially created words.
Among palindromic towns and cities in the United States, Borgmann
found the 7-letter Okonoko (in West Virginia). If a state (in full or ab-
breviated form) is part of the palindrome, Borgmann offers Apollo, PA,
Palindromes: Words and Numbers 29
and Adaven, Nevada. Some U.S. towns, Eckler continued, are inten-
tional reversal pairs, such as Orestod and Dotsero, in Eagle County,
Colorado, and Colver and Revloc, in Cambria County, Pennsylvania.
Nova and Avon, he added, are Ohio towns that are an unintentional re-
versal pair.
George L. Hart III sent the following letter, which was published in
Scientific American, November 1970:
Sirs:
Apropos of your discussion of palindromes, I would like to offer an ex-
ample of what I believe to be the most complex and exquisite type of
palindrome ever invented. It was devised by the Sanskrit aestheticians,
who termed it sarvatobhadra, that is, "perfect in every direction." The
most famous example of it is found in the epic poem entitled
Sisupiilavadha.
sa - ka - ra - na - na - ra - ka - sa -
ka - ya - sa - da - da- sa - ya - ka
ra - sa - ha - va va - ha - sa - ra -
na - da - va - da - da - va - da - na.
(na da va da da va da na
ra sa ha va va ha sa ra
ka ya sa da da sa ya ka
sa ka ra na na ra ka sa)
Here hyphens indicate that the next syllable belongs to the same word.
The last four lines, which are an inversion of the first four, are not part
of the verse but are supplied so that its properties can be seen more eas-
ily. The verse is a description of an army and may be translated as fol-
lows: "[That army], which relished battle [rasahava], contained allies
who brought low the bodes and gaits of their various striving enemies
[sakarananarakasakayasadadasayaka], and in it the cries of the best of
mounts contended with musical instruments [vahasaranadavada-
davadana]."
Two readers, D. M. Gunn and Rosina Wilson, conveyed the sad news
that the Yreka Bakery no longer existed. However, in 1970 its premises
were occupied by the Yrella Gallery, and Ms. Wilson sent a Polaroid
picture of the gallery'S sign to prove it. Whether the gallery is still there,
I do not know.
Lee Sallows repaired the "near miss" palindrome in this chapter's
epigraph by adding a word: "Zeus! A man, a plan, a canal-Suez!"
30 ARITHMETIC AND ALGEBRA
Answers
Readers were asked to prove that no prime except 11 can be a
palindrome if it has an even number of digits. The proof exploits a well-
known test of divisibility by 11 (which will not be proved here): If the
difference between the sum of all digits in even positions and the sum
of all digits in odd positions is zero or a multiple of 11, the number is a
multiple of 11. When a palindrome has an even number of digits, the
digits in odd positions necessarily duplicate the digits in even posi-
tions; therefore the difference between the sums of the two sets must be
zero. The palindrome, because it has 11 as a factor, cannot be prime.
The same divisibility test applies in all number systems when the fac-
tor to be tested is the system's base plus one. This proves that no palin-
drome with an even number of digits, in any number system, can be
prime, with the possible exception of11. The number 11 is prime if the
system's base is one less than a prime, as it is in the decimal system.
Bibliography
The palindrome number conjecture
D. Ahl, "Follow-up on Palindromes," Creative Computing, May 1975, p. 18.
A. Brousseau, "Palindromes by Addition in Base Two," Mathematics Magazine,
Vol. 42, November 1969, pp. 254-56.
F. Gruenberger, "How to Handle Numbers With Thousands of Digits, and Why One
Might Not Want To," Scientific American, Vol. 205, April 1984, pp. 19-26.
H. Harborth, "On Palindromes," Mathematics Magazine, Vol. 46, March 1973,
pages 96-99.
G. Johns and J. Wiegold, "The Palindromic Problem in Base 2," Mathematical
Gazette, Vol. 78, November 1994, p. 312.
W. Koetke, "Palindromes: For Those Who Like to Start at the Beginning." Creative
Computing, January 1975, pp. 10-12.
G. Kr5ber, "On Non-Palindromic Patterns in Palindromic Processes," Mathemati-
cal Gazette, Vol. 80, November 1996, pp. 577-79.
D. J. Lanska, "The 196 Problem," Journal of Recreational Mathematics, Vol. 18, No.
2,1985-86,pp.152-53.
D. J. Lanska, "More on the 196 Problem," Journal of Recreational Mathematics, Vol.
18, No.4, 1985-86, pp. 305-6.
R. Sprague, Recreation in Mathematics, Dover, 1963, Problem 5.
C. W. Trigg, "Palindromes by Addition," Mathematics Magazine, Vol. 40, January
1967, pp. 26-28.
C. W. Trigg, "More on Palindromes by Reversal-Addition," Mathematics Magazine,
Vol. 45, September 1972, pp. 184-86.
Palindromes: Words and Numbers 31
C. W. Trigg, "Versum Sequences in the Binary System." Pacific Journal of Mathe-
matics, Vol. 47, 1973, pp. 263-75.
"The 196 Problem," Popular Computing, Vol. 3, September 1975, pp. 6-9.
Palindromic primes
1. Card, "Patterns in Primes," Journal of Recreational Mathematics, Vol. 1, April
1968, pp. 93-99.
H. Gabai and D. Coogan, "On Palindromes and Palindromic Primes," Mathematics
Magazine, Vol. 42, November 1969, pp. 252-54.
C. W. Thigg, "Special Palindromic Primes," Journal of Recreational Mathematics,
Vol. 4, July 1971, pages 169-70.
Palindromic Powers
G. J. Simmons, "Palindromic Powers," Journal of Recreational Mathematics, Vol.
3, April 1970, pp. 93-98.
G. J. Simmons, "On Palindromic Squares of Non-Palindromic Numbers," Journal
of Recreational Mathematics, Vol. 5, January 1972, pp. 11-19.
C. W. Thigg, "Palindromic Cubes," Mathematics Magazine, Vol. 34, March 1961, p.
214.
Word Palindromes
R. Angell, "Ainmosni," The New Yorker, May 31,1969, pp. 32-34.
H. W. Bergerson, Palindromes and Anagrams, Dover, 1973.
C. C. Bombaugh, Oddities and Curiosities of Words and Literature, M. Gardner
(ed.), Dover, 1961.
D. Borgmann, Language on Vacation, Scribner's, 1965.
D. Borgmann, Beyond Language, Scribner's, 1967.
S. J. Chism, From A to Zotamorf: The Dictionary of Palindromes, Word Ways, 1992.
M. Donner, I Love Me, Vol. I: S. Wordrow's Palindrome Encyclopedia, Algonquin
Books, 1996.
M. Gardner, "The Oulipo," Penrose Tiles To Trapdoor Ciphers, Chapters 6 and 7,
W. H. Freeman, 1989.
S. W. Golomb, "I Call on Professor Osseforp," Harvard Bulletin, March 1972, p. 45.
W. Irvine, "Madam, I'm Adam and Other Palindromes," Scribner's, 1987.
]. Kuhn and M. Kuhn, Rats Live on No Evil Star, Everett House, 1981.
R. Lederer, "Palindromes: The Art of Reverse English," Verbatim, Vol. 11, Winter
1985, pp. 14-15.
L. Levine. Dr. Award and Olson in Oslo: A Palindromic Novel, By author, 1980.
J. Pool, Lid Off a Daffodil: A Book of Palindromes, Holt, Rinehart, and Winston,
1985.
R. Stuart, Too Hot To Hoot, McKay, 1977.
Word Ways: The Journal of Recreational Linguistics. Vol. 1, February 1968.
"Weekend Competition," New Statesman, April 14, 1967, p. 521; May 5, 1967, p.
630; December 22,1972, p. 955; March 9, 1973, p. 355.
"Results of Competition," New York Magazine, December 22, 1969, p. 82.
"The Contest," Maclean's Magazine, December 1969, pp. 68-69.
32 ARITHMETIC AND ALGEBRA
II
Plane Geometry
Chapter 4 Curves of
Constant Width
If an enormously heavy object has to be moved from one spot
to another, it may not be practical to move it on wheels. Axles might
buckle or snap under the load. Instead the object is placed on a fiat plat-
form that in turn rests on cylindrical rollers. As the platform is pushed
forward, the rollers left behind are picked up and put down again in
front.
An object moved in this manner over a fiat, horizontal surface obvi-
0usly does not bob up and down as it rolls along. The reason is simply
that the cylindrical rollers have a circular cross section, and a circle is
a closed curve possessing what mathematicians call "constant width."
If a closed convex curve is placed between two parallel lines and the
lines are moved together until they touch the curve, the distance be-
tween the parallel lines is the curve's "width" in one direction. An el-
lipse clearly does not have the same width in all directions. A platform
riding on elliptical rollers would wobble up and down as it rolled over
them. Because a circle has the same width in all directions, it can be ro-
tated between two parallel lines without altering the distance between
the lines.
Is the circle the only closed curve of constant width? Most people
would say yes, thus providing a sterling example of how far one's math-
ematical intuition can go astray. Actually there is an infinity of such
curves. Anyone of them can be the cross section of a roller that will roll
a platform as smoothly as a circular cylinder! The failure to recognize
such curves can have and has had disastrous consequences in indus-
try. To give one example, it might be thought that the cylindrical hull
of a half-built submarine could be tested for circularity by just mea-
suring maximum widths in all directions. As will soon be made clear,
such a hull can be monstrously lopsided and still pass such a test. It is
35
B
A ~ - - - - - - - - . . . . . . . . ; J C
4.1
Reuleaux L.I. ........... "",L\J rc)tating in SQllare.
36
Cross section of drill in hole
Watts chuck and drill
4.2.
37
the compass and draw arc FG. Do the same at the other corners. The re-
sulting curve has a width, in all directions, that is the sum of the same
two radii. This of course makes it a curve of constant width. Other
symmetrical curves of constant width result if you start with a regular
pentagon (or any regular polygon with an odd number of sides) and fol-
low similar procedures.
~ ~ ~ ~ - - - - - G
,
H
Figure 4.3. Symmetrical rounded-corner curve of constant width
There are ways to draw unsymmetrical curves of constant width.
One method is to start with an irregular star polygon (it will necessar-
ily have an odd number of points) such as the seven-point star shown
in black in Figure 4.4. All of these line segments must be the same
length. Place the compass point at each corner of the star and connect
the two opposite corners with an arc. Because these arcs all have the
same radius, the resulting curve (shown in gray) will have constant
width. Its corners can be rounded off by the method used before. Ex-
tend the sides of the star a uniform distance at all points (shown with
broken lines) and then join the ends of the extended sides by arcs
drawn with the compass point at each corner of the star. The rounded-
corner curve, which is shown in black, will be another curve of con-
stant width.
Figure 4.5 demonstrates another method. Draw as many straight lines
as you please, all mutually intersecting. Each arc is drawn with the
compass point at the intersection of the two lines that bound the arc.
Start with any arc, then proceed around the curve, connecting each arc
to the preceding one. If you do it carefully, the curve will close and will
have constant width. (Proving that the curve must close and have con-
38 PLANE GEOMETRY
Figure 4.4. Star-polygon method of drawing a curve of constant width
stant width is an interesting and not difficult exercise.) The preceding
curves were made up of arcs of no more than two different circles, but
curves drawn in this way may have arcs of as many different circles as
you wish.
B
Figure4.S. Crossed-lines method Random CUIve and tangents
A curve of constant width need not consist of circular arcs. In fact,
you can draw a highly arbitrary convex curve from the top to the bot-
tom of a square and touching its left side (arc ABC in Figure 4.5), and
this curve will be the left side of a uniquely determined curve of con-
stant width. To find the missing part, rule a large number of lines, each
parallel to a tangent of arc ABC and separated from the tangent by a dis-
tance equal to the side of the square. This can be done quickly by using
both sides of a ruler. The original square must have a side equal to the
ruler's width. Place one edge of the ruler so that it is tangent to arc
Curves of Constant Width 39
ABC at one of its points, then use the ruler's opposite edge to draw a
parallel line. Do this at many points, from one end of arc ABC to the
other. The missing part of the curve is the envelope of these lines. In
this way you can obtain rough outlines of an endless variety of lopsided
curves of constant width.
It should be mentioned that the arc ABC cannot be completely arbi-
trary. Roughly speaking, its curvature must not at any point be less
than the curvature of a circle with a radius equal to the side of the
square. It cannot, for example, include straight-line segments. For a
more precise statement on this, as well as detailed proofs of many ele-
mentary theorems involving curves of constant width, the reader is re-
ferred to the excellent chapter on such curves in The Enjoyment of
Mathematics, by Hans Rademacher and Otto Toeplitz.
If you have the tools and skills for woodworking, you might enjoy
making a number of wooden rollers with cross sections that are various
curves of the same constant width. Most people are nonplused by the
sight of a large book rolling horizontally across such lopsided rollers
without bobbing up and down. A simpler way to demonstrate such
curves is to cut from cardboard two curves of constant width and nail
them to opposite ends of a wooden rod about six inches long. The
curves need not be of the same shape, and it does not matter exactly
where you put each nail as long as it is fairly close to what you guess
to be the curve's "center." Hold a large, light-weight empty box by its
ends, rest it horizontally on the attached curves and roll the box back
and forth. The rod wobbles up and down at both ends, but the box
rides as smoothly as it would on circular rollers!
The properties of curves of constant width have been extensively in-
vestigated. One startling property, not easy to prove, is that the perime-
ters of all curves with constant width n have the same length. Since a
circle is such a curve, the perimeter of any curve of constant width n
must of course be 1tn, the same as the circumference of a circle with di-
ameter n.
The three-dimensional analogue of a curve of constant width is the
solid of constant width. A sphere is not the only such solid that will ro-
tate within a cube, at all times touching all six sides of the cube; this
property is shared by all solids of constant width. The Simplest exam-
ple of a nonspherical solid of this type is generated by rotating the
Reuleaux triangle around one of its axes of symmetry (see Figure 4.6,
left). There is an infinite number of others. The solids of constant width
40 PLANE GEOMETRY
4.6. Two constant
41
pentagons, hexagons, and even octagons. In three-space, Goldberg has
shown, there are nonspherical rotors for the regular tetrahedron and oc-
tahedron, as well as the cube, but none for the regular dodecahedron
and icosahedron. Almost no work has been done on rotors in dimen-
sions higher than three.
Figure 4.1.
Least-area rotor in equilateral triangle Line rotated in deltoid curve
Closely related to the theory of rotors is a famous problem named the
Kakeya needle problem after the Japanese mathematician Soichi
Kakeya, who first posed it in 1917. The problem is as follows: What is
the plane figure of least area in which a line segment of length 1 can be
rotated 360 degrees? The rotation obviously can be made inside a cir-
cle of unit diameter, but that is far from the smallest area.
For many years mathematicians believed the answer was the deltoid
curve shown at the right of Figure 4.7, which has an area exactly half
that of a unit circle. (The deltoid is the curve traced by a point on the
circumference of a circle as it rolls around the inside of a larger circle,
when the diameter of the small circle is either one third or two thirds
that of the larger one.) If you break a toothpick to the size of the line seg-
ment shown, you will find by experiment that it can be rotated inside
the deltoid as a kind of one-dimensional rotor. Note how its end points
remain at all times on the deltoid's perimeter.
In 1927, ten years after Kakeya popped his question, the Russian
mathematician Abram Samoilovitch Besicovitch (then living in Copen-
hagen) dropped a bombshell. He proved that the problem had no an-
swer. More accurately, he showed that the answer to Kakeya's question
is that there is no minimum area. The area can be made as small as one
wants. Imagine a line segment that stretches from the earth to the moon.
We can rotate it 360 degrees within an area as small as the area of a
postage stamp. If that is too large, we can reduce it to the area of Lin-
coln's nose on a postage stamp.
42 PLANE GEOMETRY
Besicovitch's proof is too complicated to give here (see references in
bibliography), and besides, his domain of rotation is not what topolo-
gists call simply connected. For readers who would like to work on a
much easier problenl: What is the smallest convex area in which a line
segment of length 1 can be rotated 360 degrees? (A convex figure is one
in which a straight line, joining any two of its points, lies entirely on
the figure. Squares and circles are convex; Greek crosses and crescent
moons are not.)
Addendum
Although Watts was the first to acquire patents on the process
of drilling square holes with Reuleaux-triangle drills, the procedure
was apparently known earlier. Derek Beck, in London, wrote that he
had met a man who recalled having used such a drill for boring square
holes when he was an apprentice machinist in 1902 and that the prac-
tice then seemed to be standard. I have not, however, been able to learn
anything about the history of the technique prior to Watts's 1917
patents.
In 1969 England introduced a 50-pence coin with seven slightly
curved sides that form a circle of constant width, surely the first seven-
sided coin ever minted. The invariant width allows the coin to roll
smoothly down coin-operated machines.
Answers
What is the smallest convex area in which a line segment of
length 1 can be rotated 360 degrees? The answer: An equilateral trian-
gle with an altitude of 1. (The area is one third the square root of 3.)
Any figure in which the line segment can be rotated obviously must
have a width at least equal to 1. Of all convex figures with a width of
1, the equilateral triangle of altitude 1 has the smallest area. (For a
proof of this the reader is referred to Convex Figures, by I. M. Yaglom
and V. G. Boltyanskii, pp. 221-22.) It is easy to see that a line segment
of length 1 can in fact be rotated in such a triangle (see Figure 4.8).
The deltoid curve was believed to be the smallest simply connected
area solving the problem until 1963 when a smaller area was discov-
ered independently by Melvin Bloom and I. J. Schoenberg.
Curves of Constant Width 43
1 2 3
4 5 6
Figure 4.8. Answer to the needle-turning problem
Bibliography
W. Blaschke, Kreis und Kugel, Leipzig, 1916; Berlin: W. de Gruyter, 1956.
J. H. Cadwell, Topics in Recreational Mathematics, Cambridge, England: Cam-
bridge University Press, 1966, Chapter 15.
J. Casey, "Perfect and Not-So-Perfect Rollers," The Mathematics Teacher, Vol. 91,
January 1998, pp. 12-20.
G. D. Chakerian and H. Groemer, "Convex Bodies of Constant Width," Convexity
and Its Applications, P. M. Gruber and J. M. Wills (eds.), Boston: Birkhauser,
1983.
J. A. Dossey, "What?-A Roller with Corners?," Mathematics Teacher, December
1972, pp. 720-24.
J. C. Fisher, "Curves of Constant Width from a Linear Viewpoint," Mathematics
Magazine, Vol. 60, June 1987, pp. 131-40.
J. A. Flaten, "Curves of Constant Width," The Physics Teacher, Vol. 37, October
1999, pp. 418-19.
M. Goldberg, "Trammel Rotors in Regular Polygons," American Mathematical
Monthly, Vol. 64, February 1957, pp. 71-78.
M. Goldberg, "Rotors in Polygons and Polyhedra," Mathematical Tables and Other
Aids to Computation, Vol. 14, July 1960, pp. 229-39.
M. Goldberg, "N-Gon Rotors Making N + 1 Contacts with Fixed Simple Curves,"
American Mathematical Monthly, Vol. 69, June/July 1962, pp. 486-91.
M. Goldberg, "Two-lobed Rotors with Three-Lobed Stators," Journal of Mecha-
nisms, Vol. 3, 1968, pp. 55-60.
C. G. Gray, "Solids of Constant Breadth," Mathematical Gazette, December 1972,
pp.289-92.
R. Honsberger, Mathematical Gems, Washington, D.C., 1973, Chapter 5.
H. Rademacher and O. Toeplitz, The Enjoyment of Mathematics, Princeton, NJ:
Princeton University Press, 1957; Dover, 1990. See pp. 163-77, 203.
44 PLANE GEOMETRY
F. Reuleaux, The Kinematics of Machinery, New York: Macmillan, 1876; Dover
Publications, 1964, pp. 129-46.
S. G. Smith, "Drilling Square Holes," The Mathematics Teacher, Vol. 86, October
1993, pp. 579-83.
I. M. Yaglom and V. G. Boltyanskii, Convex Figures, New York: Holt, Rinehart &
Winston, 1961, Chapters 7 and 8.
On I<.akeya's needle problem:
A. S. Besicovitch, "The Kakeya Problem," American Mathematical Monthly, Vol.
70, August/September 1963, pp. 697-706.
A. A. Blank, "A Remark on the Kakeya Problem," American Mathematical Monthly,
Vol. 70, August/September 1963, pp. 706-11.
J. H. Cadwell, Topics in Recreational Mathematics, Cambridge, England: Cam-
bridge University Press, 1966. See pp. 96-99.
F. Cunningham, Jr., "The Kakeya Problem for Simply Connected and Star-shaped
Sets," American Mathematical Monthly, Vol. 78, February 1971, pp. 114-29.
I. M. Yaglom and V. G. Boltyanskii, Convex Figures, New York: Holt. Rinehart &
Winston, 1961, pp. 61-62, 226-27.
Curves of Constant Width 45
Chapter 5 Rep-Tiles
Only three regular polygons-the equilateral triangle, the
square, and the regular hexagon-can be used for tiling a floor in such
a way that identical shapes are endlessly repeated to cover the plane.
But there is an infinite number of irregular polygons that can provide
this kind of tiling. For example, a triangle of any shape whatever will
do the trick. So will any four-sided figure. The reader can try the fol-
lowing test. Draw an irregular quadrilateral (it need not even be con-
vex, which is to say that it need not have interior angles that are all less
than 180 degrees) and cut 20 or so copies from cardboard. It is a pleas-
ant task to fit them all together snugly, like a jigsaw puzzle, to cover a
plane.
There is an unusual and less familiar way to tile a plane. Note that
each trapezoid at the top of Figure 5.1 has been divided into four
smaller trapezoids that are exact replicas of the original. The four repli-
cas can, of course, be divided in the same way into four still smaller
replicas, and this can be continued to infinity. To use such a figure for
tiling we have only to proceed to infinity in the opposite direction: we
put together four figures to form a larger model, four of which will in
turn fit together to make a still larger one. The British mathematician
Augustus De Morgan summed up this sort of situation admirably in the
following jingle, the first four lines of which paraphrase an earlier jin-
gle by Jonathan Swift:
46
Great fleas have little fleas
Upon their backs to bite 'em,
And little fleas have lesser fleas,
And so ad infinitum.
The great fleas themselves, in turn,
Have greater fleas to go on;
While these again have greater still,
And greater still, and so on.
Until 1962 not much was known about polygons that have this curi-
ous property of making larger and smaller copies of themselves. In
1962 Solomon W. Golomb, who was then on the staff of the Jet Propul-
sion Laboratory of the California Institute of Technology and is now a
professor at the University of Southern California, turned his attention
to these "replicating figures"-or "rep-tiles," as he calls them. The re-
sult was three privately issued papers that lay the groundwork for a
general theory of polygon "replication." These papers, from which al-
most all that follows is extracted, contain a wealth of material of great
interest to the recreational mathematician.
In Golomb's terminology a replicating polygon of order k is one that
can be divided into k replicas congruent to one another and similar to
the original. Each of the three trapezoids in Figure 5.1, for example, has
a replicating order of 4, abbreviated as rep-4. Polygons of rep-k exist for
any k, but they seem to be scarcest when k is a prime and to be most
abundant when k is a square number.
Three trapezoids that have a replicating order of 4
Figure 5.1. The only known rep-2 polygons
Only two rep-2 polygons are known: the isosceles right triangle and
the parallelogram with sides in the ratio of 1 to the square root of 2 (see
bottom of Figure 5.1). Golomb found simple proofs that these are the
only possible rep-2 triangles and quadrilaterals, and there are no other
convex rep-2 polygons. The existence of concave rep-2 polygons ap-
pears unlikely, but so far their nonexistence has not been proved.
Rep-Tiles 47
The interior angles of the parallelogram can vary without affecting its
rep-2 property. In its rectangular form the rep-2 parallelogram is al-
most as famous in the history of art as the "golden rectangle," discussed
in the Second Scientific American Book of Mathematical Puzzles and
Diversions. Many medieval and Renaissance artists (Albrecht Diirer,
for instance) consciously used it for outlining rectangular pictures. A
trick playing card that is sometimes sold by street-corner pitchmen ex-
ploits this rectangle to make the ace of diamonds seem to diminish in
size three times (see Figure 5.2). Under cover of a hand movement the
card is secretly folded in half and turned over to show a card exactly
half the size of the preceding one. If each of the three smaller aces is a
rectangle similar to the original, it is easy to show that only a 1-by-v2
rectangle can be used for the card. The rep-2 rectangle also has less friv-
olous uses. Printers who wish to standardize the shape of the pages in
books of various sizes find that in folio, quarto, or octavo form it pro-
duces pages that are all similar rectangles. European writing paper also
has a similar shape.
A
+
y
Figure S.2. A trick diminishing card based on the rep-2 rectangle
The rep-2 rectangle belongs to the family of parallelograms shown in
the top illustration of Figure 5.3. The fact that a parallelogram with
sides of 1 and Vk is always rep-k proves that a rep-k polygon exists for
any k. It is the only known example, Golomb asserts, of a family of fig-
ures that exhibit all the replicating orders. When k is 7 (or any prime
greater than 3 that has the form 4n - 1), a parallelogram of this family
is the only known example. Rep-3 and rep-5 triangles exist. Can the
reader construct them?
A great number of rep-4 figures are known. Every triangle is rep-4
and can be divided as shown in the second illustration from the top of
48 PLANE GEOMETRY
V2 VS" 2
I l; Ill; 0Zll
V5 V6
IIlTll !lATII
The I-by-vk parallelogram is a rep-k polygon
Every triangle and parallelogram is rep-4
The Sphinx, the only known rep-4 pentagon
I
I I
U f--
The three known varieties of rep-4 hexagons
Figure S.3.
Rep-Tiles 49
Figure 5.3. Among the quadrilaterals, any parallelogram is rep-4, as
shown in the same illustration. The three trapezoids in the top illus-
tration of Figure 5.1 are the only other examples of rep-4 quadrilater-
als so far discovered.
Only one rep-4 pentagon is known: the sphinx-shaped figure in the
third illustration from the top of Figure 5.3. Golomb was the first to dis-
cover its rep-4 property. Only the outline of the sphinx is given so that
the reader can have the pleasure of seeing how quickly he can dissect
it into four smaller sphinxes. (The name "sphinx" was given to this fig-
ure by T. H. O'Beirne of Glasgow.)
There are three known varieties of rep-4 hexagons. If any rectangle is
divided into four quadrants and one quadrant is thrown away, the re-
maining figure is a rep-4 hexagon. The hexagon at the right at the bot-
tom of Figure 5.3 shows the dissection (familiar to puzzlists) when the
rectangle is a square. The other two examples of rep-4 hexagons (each
of which can be dissected in more than one way) are shown at the mid-
dle and left in the same illustration.
No other example of a standard polygon with a rep-4 property is
known. There are, however, "stellated" rep-4 polygons (a stellated poly-
gon consists of two or more polygons joined at single points), two exam-
ples of which, provided by Golomb, are shown at the top of Figure 5.4.
In the first example a pair ofidentical rectangles can be substituted for the
squares. In addition, Golomb has found three nonpolygonal figures that
are rep-4, although none is constructible in a finite number of steps. Each
of these figures, shown at the left in the bottom illustration of Figure 5.4,
is formed by adding to an equilateral triangle an endless series of smaller
triangles, each one-fourth the size of its predecessor. In each case four of
these figures will fit together to make a larger replica, as shown at the
right in the same illustration. (There is a gap in each replica because the
original cannot be drawn with an infinitely long series of triangles.)
It is a curious fact that every known rep-4 polygon of a standard type
is also rep-9. The rep-4 Nevada-shaped trapezoid of Figure 5.5 can be
dissected into nine replicas in many ways, only one of which is shown.
(Can the reader dissect each of the other rep-4 polygons, not counting
the stellated and infinite forms, into nine replicas?) The converse is
also true: All known standard rep-9 polygons are also rep-4.
Three interesting examples of stellated rep-9 polygons, discovered
and named by Golomb, are shown in Figure 5.B. None of these poly-
gons is rep-4.
50 PLANE GEOMETRY
1\vo stellated
5.4. Three eXSllDJ:ues
5.5. is
51
(A),
(B).
52
S.1. A
5.8.
53
144. It is conjectured that none of the three has a lower replicating
order.
Figure 5.9. Three rep-144 polygons
Golomb has noted that every known polygon of rep-4, including the
stellated polygons, will divide a parallelogram with a multiplicity of 2.
In other words, if any known rep-4 polygon is replicated, the pair can
be fitted together to form a parallelogram! It is conjectured, but not yet
proved, that this is true of all rep-4 polygons.
An obvious extension of Golomb's pioneer work on replication the-
ory (of which only the most elementary aspects have been detailed
here) is into three or even higher dimensions. A trivial example of a
replicating solid figure is the cube: it obviously is rep-B, rep-27, and so
on for any order that is a cubical number. Other trivial examples result
from giving plane replicating figures a finite thickness, then forming
layers of larger replicas to make a model of the original solid. Less triv-
ial examples certainly exist; a study of them might lead to significant
results.
In addition to the problems already posed, here are two unusual dis-
section puzzles closely related to what we have been considering (see
Figure 5.10). First the easier one: Can the reader divide the hexagon
(left) into two congruent stellated polygons? More difficult: Divide the
pentagon (right) into four congruent stellated polygons. In neither case
are the polygons similar to the original figure.
Addendum
I gave the conjecture that none of the three polygons shown in
Figure 5.9 has a replicating order lower than 144. Wrong for all three!
MarkA. Mandel, then 14, wrote to show how the middle polygon could
be cut into 36 replicas (see Figure 5.11). Robert Reid, writing from Peru,
found a way for 121 copies of the first hexomino to replicate and 64
54 PLANE GEOMETRY
Figure S.ID. Two dissection problems
Figure 5.11. Hexomino: rep-tile of order 36
Figure 5.12. A Rep-at polygon
copies of the third polygon to do the same. Reid also proved that the
hexomino shown in Figure 5.12 is a rep-tile of order 81.
Rep-Tiles 55
Ralph H. Hinrichs, Phoenixville, PA, discovered that if the middle
hexagon at the bottom of Figure 5.3 is dissected in a slightly different
way (the pattern within each rectangle is mirror-reflected), the entire
figure can undergo an infinite number of affine transformations (the 90-
degree exterior angle taking any acute or obtuse value) to provide an in-
finity of rep-4 hexagons. Only when the angle is 90 degrees is the figure
also rep-9, thus disproving an early guess that all rep-4 standard poly-
gons are rep-9 and vice versa.
The three nonpolygon rep-tiles shown in Figure 5.4 are now called
"self-similar fractals." Such fractals are being extensively studied. I
have not listed recent references in my bibliography, but interested
readers can consult Christoph Bandt's "Self-Similar Sets 5," in the Pro-
ceedings of the American Mathematical Society, Vol. 112, June 1991,
pages 349-62, and his list of references.
The rep-tile triangle second from the top in Figure 5.12-incidently
it is not accurately drawn-is mentioned in Plato's Timaeus. Timaeus
points out that it is half of an equilateral triangle and that he considers
it the "most beautiful" of all scalene triangles. (See the Random House
edition of Plato, edited by Benjamin Jowett, Vol. 2, p. 34.)
Sol Golomb is best known for his work on polyominoes-shapes
formed by joining n unit squares along their edges. Golomb's classic
study, Polyominoes, was reissued by Princeton University Press in
1994.
The most spectacular constructions of what Golomb calls "infin-tiles
(rep-tiles with infinitely many sides) are in the papers by Jack Giles, Jr.,
cited in the bibliography. Giles calls them "superfigures." Many of
Golomb's infin-tiles, and those of Giles, are early examples of fractals.
Golomb tells me that Giles was a parking lot attendant in Florida when
he sent his papers to Golomb, who in turn submitted them to the Jour-
nal of Combinatorial Theory.
Answers
The problem of dissecting the sphinx is shown in Figure 5.13,
top. The next two illustrations show how to construct rep-3 and rep-5
triangles. The bottom illustration gives the solution to the two dissec-
tion problems involving stellated polygons. The first of these can be
varied in an infinite number of ways; the solution shown here is one of
the simplest.
56 PLANE GEOMETRY
S.I l. Solutions to dissection problems
second solution is an old-timer. Loyd, in his column
Woman's Home Companion (October 1905) out that the fig-
a
that he a year trying to cut the mitre shape into four congruent
Rep-Tiles 57
parts, each simply connected, but was unable to do better than the so-
lution reproduced here. It can be found in many old puzzle books a n ~
tedating Loyd's time.
Bibliography
R. O. Davies, "Replicating Boots," Mathematical Gazette, Vol. 50, May 1966, p.
157.
F. M. Dekking. "Replicating Superfigures and Endomorphisms of Free Groups,"
Journal of Combinatorial Theory, Vol. 32A, 1982, pp. 315-20.
J. Doyen and M. Lenduyt, "Dissection of Polygons," Annals of Discrete Mathemat-
ics, Vol. 18, 1983, pp. 315-18.
J. Giles, Jr., "Infinite-level Replication Dissections of Plane Figures," "Construction
of Replicating Superfigures, " and "Superfigures Replicating with Polar Symme-
try," Journal of Combinatorial Theory, 26A, 1979, pp. 319-27,328-34,335-37.
J. Giles, Jr., "The Gypsy Method of Superfigure Construction," Journal of Recre-
ational Mathematics, Vol. 13, 1980/81, pp. 97-101.
M. Goldberg and B. M. Stewart, "A Dissection Problem for Sets of Polygons," Amer-
ican Mathematical Monthly, Vol. 71, December 1964, pp. 1077-95.
S. W. Golomb, "Replicating Figures in the Plane," Mathematical Gazette, Vol. 48,
December 1964, pp. 403-12.
H. D. Grossman, "Fun with Lattice Points," Scripta Mathematica, Vol. 14, June
1948, pp. 157-59.
C. D. Langford, "Uses of a Geometrical Puzzle," Mathematical Gazette, Vol. 24,
July 1940, pp. 209-11.
R. Sibson, "Comments on Note 1464," Mathematical Gazette, Vol. 24, December
1940, p. 343.
G. Valette and T. Zamfirescu, "Les Partages d'un Polygone Convexe en 4 Polygones
Semblables au Premier," Journal of Combinatorial Theory, Ser. B, Vol. 16, 1974,
pp.1-16.
58 PLANE GEOMETRY
Chapter 6
There is one art, no more, no less: to do all
things with artlessness. -Piet Hein
Piet Hein's
Superellipse
Civilized man is surrounded on all sides, indoors and out, by
a subtle, seldom-noticed conflict between two ancient ways of shaping
things: the orthogonal and the round. Cars on circular wheels, guided
by hands on circular steering wheels, move along streets that intersect
like the lines of a rectangular lattice. Buildings and houses are made up
mostly of right angles, relieved occasionally by circular domes and
windows. At rectangular or circular tables, with rectangular napkins on
our laps, we eat from circular plates and drink from glasses with cir-
cular cross sections. We light cylindrical cigarettes with matches from
rectangular packs, and we pay the rectangular bill with rectangular
credit cards, checks, or dollar bills and circular coins.
Even our games combine the orthogonal and the round. Most outdoor
sports are played with spherical balls on rectangular fields. Indoor
games, from pool to checkers, are similar combinations of the round
and the rectangular. Rectangular playing cards are held in a fanlike cir-
cular array. The very letters on this rectangular page are patchworks of
right angles and circular arcs. Wherever one looks the scene swarms
with squares and circles and their affinely stretched forms: rectangles
and ellipses. (In a sense the ellipse is more common than the circle, be-
cause every circle appears elliptical when seen from an angle.) In op
paintings and textile designs, squares, circles, rectangles, and ellipses
jangle against one another as violently as they do in daily life.
The Danish writer and inventor Piet Hein asked himself a fascinat-
ing question: What is the simplest and most pleasing closed curve that
mediates fairly between these two clashing tendencies? Originally a
scientist, Piet Hein (he is always spoken of by both names) was well
known throughout Scandinavia and English-speaking countries for his
enormously popular volumes of gracefully aphoristic poems (which
59
critics have likened to the epigrams of Martial) and for his writings on
scientific and humanistic topics. To recreational mathematicians he is
best known as the inventor of the game Hex, of the Soma cube, and of
other remarkable games and puzzles. He was a friend of Norbert
Wiener, whose last book, God and Golem, Inc., is dedicated to him.
The question Piet Hein asked himself had been suggested by a knotty
city-planning problem that first arose in 1959 in Sweden. Many years
earlier Stockholm had decided to raze and rebuild a congested section
of old houses and narrow streets in the heart of the city, and after World
War IT this enormous and costly program got under way. Two broad
new traffic arteries running north-south and east-west were cut through
the center of the city. At the intersection of these avenues a large rec-
tangular space (now called SergeI's Square) was laid out. At its center is
an oval basin with a fountain surrounded by an oval pool containing
several hundred smaller fountains. Daylight filters through the pool's
translucent bottom into an oval self-service restaurant, below street
level, surrounded by oval rings of pillars and shops. Below that there are
two more oval floors for dining and dancing, cloakrooms, and kitchen.
In planning the exact shape of this center the Swedish architects ran
into unexpected snags. The ellipse had to be rejected because its
pointed ends would interfere with smooth traffic flow around it; more-
over, it did not fit harmoniously into the rectangular space. The city
planners next tried a curve made up of eight circular arcs, but it had a
patched-together look with ugly "jumps" of curvature in eight places.
In addition, plans called for nesting different sizes of the oval shape,
and the eight-arc curve refused to nest in a pleasing way.
At this stage the architectural team in charge of the project consulted
Piet Hein. It was just the kind of problem that appealed to his combined
mathematical and artistic imagination, his sense of humor, and his
knack of thinking creatively in unexpected directions. What kind of
curve, less pointed than the ellipse, could he discover that would nest
pleasingly and fit harmoniously into the rectangular open space at the
heart of Stockholm?
To understand Piet Hein's novel answer we must first consider the el-
lipse, as he did, as a special case of a more general family of curves with
the following formula in Cartesian coordinates:
60 PLANE GEOMETRY
where a and b are unequal parameters (arbitrary constants) that repre-
sent the two semiaxes of the curve and n is any positive real number.
The vertical brackets indicate that each fraction is to be taken with re-
spect to its absolute value; that is, its value without regard to sign.
When n =2, the real values of x and ythat satisfy the equation (its "so-
lution set") determine the points on the graph that lie on an ellipse with
its center at the origin of the two coordinates. As n decreases from 2 to
1, the oval becomes more pointed at its ends ("subellipses," Piet Rein
called them). When n = 1, the figure is a parallelogram. When n is less
than 1, the four sides are concave curves that become increasingly con-
cave as n approaches O. At n = 0 they degenerate into two crossed
straight lines.
If n is allowed to increase above 2, the oval develops flatter and flat-
ter sides, becoming more and more like a rectangle; indeed, the rec-
tangle is its limit as n approaches infinity. At what point is such a
curve most pleasing to the eye? Piet Rein settled on n = 2%. With the
help of a computer, 400 coordinate pairs were calculated to 15 decimal
places and larger, precise curves were drawn in many different sizes,
all with the same height-width ratios (to conform with the proportions
of the open space at the center of Stockholm), The curves proved to be
strangely satisfying, neither too rounded nor too orthogonal, a happy
blend of elliptical and rectangular beauty. Moreover, such curves could
be nested, as shown in Figures 6.1 and 6.2, to give a strong feeling of
harmony and parallelism between the concentric ovals. Piet Rein
called all such curves with exponents above 2 "superellipses." Stock-
holm immediately accepted the 2 1/2-exponent superellipse as the
basic motif of its new center. Already the large superelliptical pool has
conferred upon Stockholm an unusual mathematical flavor, like the
big catenary curve of St. Louis's Gateway Arch, which dominates the
local skyline.
Meanwhile Piet Rein's superellipse has been enthusiastically
adopted by Bruno Mathsson, a well-known Swedish furniture designer.
Re first produced a variety of superelliptical desks, now in the offices
of many Swedish executives, and has since followed with superellip-
tical tables, chairs, and beds. (Who needs the corners?) Industries in
Denmark, Sweden, Norway, and Finland turned to Piet Rein for solu-
tions to various orthogonal-versus-circular problems, and he worked on
superelliptical furniture, dishes, coasters, lamps, silverware, textile
patterns, and so on. The tables, chairs, and beds embodied another Piet
Piet Rein's Superellipse 61
Figure 6.1. Concentric superellipses
Figure 6.2. Plan of Stockholm's underground restaurants and the pools above them
62 PLANE GEOMETRY
IS
6.3.
on
63
In the same way, one can raise the exponent in the corresponding
Cartesian formulas for spheres and ellipsoids to obtain what Piet Hein
called "superspheres" and "superellipsoids." If the exponent is 2%,
such solids can be regarded as spheres and ellipsoids that are halfway
along the road to being cubes and bricks.
The true ellipsoid, with three unequal axes, has the formula
x
2
Z2
2" + b
2
+ 2 = 1,
a c
where a, b, and c are unequal parameters representing half the length
of each axis. When the three parameters are equal, the figure is a
sphere. When only two are equal, the surface is called an "ellipsoid of
rotation" or a spheroid. It is produced by rotating an ellipse on either
of its axes. If the rotation is on the longer axis, the result is a prolate
spheroid-a kind of egg shape with circular cross sections perpendic-
ular to the axis.
It turns out that a solid model of a prolate spheroid, with homoge-
neous density, will no more balance upright on either end than a
chicken egg will, unless one applies to the egg a stratagem usually cred-
ited to Columbus. Columbus returned to Spain in 1493 after having
discovered America, thinking that the new land was India and that he
had proved the earth to be round. At Barcelona a banquet was given in
his honor. This is how Girolamo Benzoni, in his History of the New
World (Venice, 1565), tells the story (I quote from an early English trans-
lation):
Columbus, being at a party with many noble Spaniards ... one of them
undertook to say: "Mr. Christopher, even if you had not found the Indies,
we should not have been devoid of a man who would have attempted
the same thing that you did, here in our own country of Spain, as it is
full of great men clever in cosmography and literature." Columbus said
nothing in answer to these words, but having desired an egg to be
brought to him, he placed it on the table saying: "Gentlemen, I will lay
a wager with any of you, that you will not make this egg stand up as I
will, naked and without anything at all." They all tried, and no one suc-
ceeded in making it stand up. When the egg came round to the hands of
Columbus, by beating it down on the table he fixed it, having thus
crushed a little of one end; wherefore all remained confused, under-
standing what he would have said: That after the deed is done, every-
body knows how to do it.
64 PLANE GEOMETRY
The story may be true, but a suspiciously similar story had been told
15 years earlier by Giorgio Vasari in his celebrated Lives of the Most Em-
inent Painters, Sculptors and Architects (Florence, 1550). Young Fil-
ippo Brunelleschi, the Italian architect, had designed an unusually
large and heavy dome for Santa Maria del Fiore, the cathedral of Flo-
rence. City officials had asked to see his model, but he refused,
"proposing instead ... that whosoever could make an egg stand upright
on a flat piece of marble should build the cupola, since thus each man's
intellect would be discerned. Taking an egg, therefore, all those Masters
sought to make it stand upright, but not one could find a way. Where-
upon Filippo, being told to make it stand, took it graciously, and, giv-
ing one end of it a blow on the flat piece of marble, made it stand
upright. The craftsmen protested that they could have done the same;
but Filippo answered, laughing, that they could also have raised the
cupola, if they had seen the model or the design. And so it was re-
solved that he should be commissioned to carry out this work."
The story has a topper. When the great dome was finally completed
(many years later, but decades before Columbus's first voyage), it had
the shape of half an egg, flattened at the end.
What does all this have to do with supereggs? Well, Piet Hein (my
source, by the way, for the references on Columbus and Brunelleschi)
discovered that a solid model of a 2Vz-exponent superegg-indeed, a
superegg of any exponent-if not too tall for its width, balances im-
mediately on either end without any sort of skulduggery! Indeed,
dozens of chubby wooden and silver supereggs are now standing po-
litely and permanently on their ends all over Scandinavia.
Consider the silver superegg shown in Figure 6.3, which has an ex-
ponent of 2Vz and a height-width ratio of 4 : 3. It looks as if it should
topple over, but it does not. This spooky stability of the superegg (on
both ends) can be taken as symbolic of the superelliptical balance be-
tween the orthogonal and the round, which is in turn a pleasant sym-
bol for the balanced mind of individuals such as Piet Hein who
mediated so successfully between C. P. Snow's "two cultures."
Addendum I
The family of plane curves expressed by the formula I xl a In +
I yl bin = 1 was first recognized and studied by Gabriel Lame, a 19th-
century French physicist, who wrote about them in 1818. In France they
Piet Rein's Supere1Jipse 65
are called courbes de Lame; in Germany, Lamesche kurven. The curves
are algebraic when n is rational, transcendent when n is irrational.
When n = 2/3 and a = b (see Figure 6.4) the curve is an astroid. This
is the curve generated by a point on a circle that is one-fourth or three-
fourths the radius of a larger circle, when the smaller circle is rolled
around the inside of the larger one. Solomon W. Golomb called atten-
tion to the fact that if n is odd, and the absolute value signs are dropped
in the formula for Lame curves, you get a family of curves of which the
famous Witch of Agnesi (The curve studied by Maria Gaetana Agnesi)
is a member. (The witch results when n = 3.) William Hogan wrote to
say that parkway arches, designed by himself and other engineers, often
are Lame curves of exponent 2.2. In the thirties, he said, they were
called "2.2 ellipses."
Figure 6.4. Supercircle and related curves
When a superellipse (a Lame curve with exponent greater than 2) is
applied to a physical object, its exponent and parameters a and b can,
of course, be varied to suit circumstances and taste. For the Stockholm
center, Piet Hein used the parameters n = 2% and alb = 6/5. A few years
66 PLANE GEOMETRY
later Gerald Robinson, a Toronto architect, applied the superellipse to
a parking garage in a shopping center in Peterborough, a Toronto sub-
urb. The length and width were required to be in the ratio alb = 9/7.
Given this ratio, a survey indicated that an exponent slightly greater
than 2.7 produced a superellipse that seemed the most pleasing to those
polled. This suggested e as an exponent (since e = 2.718 ... ).
Readers suggested other parameters. J. D. Turner proposed mediating
between the extremes of circle and square (or rectangle and ellipse) by
picking the exponent that would give an area exactly halfway between
the two extreme areas. D. C. Mandeville found that the exponent me-
diating the areas of a circle and square is so close to pi that he won-
dered if it actually is pi. Unfortunately it is not. Norton Black, using a
computer, determined that the value is a trifle greater than 3.17. Thrner
also proposed mediating between ellipse and rectangle by choosing an
exponent that sends the curve through the midpoint of a line joining
the rectangle's corner to the corresponding point on the ellipse.
Turner and Black each suggested that the superellipse be combined
with the aesthetically pleasing "golden rectangle" by making alb the
golden ratio. Turner's vote for the most pleasing superellipse went to
the oval with parameters alb = golden ratio and n = e. Michel L. Balin-
ski and Philetus H. Holt III, in a letter published in The New York
Times in December 1968 (I failed to record the day of the month) rec-
ommended a golden superellipse with n = 21fz as the best shape for the
negotiating table in Paris. At that time the diplomats preparing to ne-
gotiate a Vietnam peace were quarreling over the shape of their table.
If no table can be agreed upon, Balinski and Holt wrote, the diplomats
should be put inside a hollow superegg and shaken until they are in
"su perelli ptic agreement."
The superegg is a special case of the more general solid shape which
one can call a superellipsoid. The superellipsoid's formula is
I
Xl
n
IYln IZl
n
- + - + - = 1.
abc
When a = b = c, the solid is a supersphere, its shape varying from
sphere to cube as the exponent varies. When a = b, the solid is super-
circular in cross section, with the formula
Piet Rein's Superellipse 67
Supereggs, with circular cross-sections, have the formula
When I wrote my column on the superellipse, I believed that any
solid superegg based on an exponent greater than 2 and less than in-
finity would balance on its end provided its height did not exceed its
width by too great a ratio. A solid superegg with an exponent of infin-
ity would, of course, be a right circular cylinder that would, in princi-
ple, stand on its flat end regardless of how much higher it was than
wide. But short of infinity it seemed intuitively clear that for each ex-
ponent there was a critical ratio beyond which the egg would be un-
stable. Indeed, I even published the following proof that this is the case:
If the center of gravity, CG, of an egg is below the center of curvature, CC,
of the egg's base at the central point of the base, the egg will balance. It
balances because any tipping of the egg will raise the CG. If the CG is
above the CC, the egg is unstable because the slightest tipping lowers the
CG. To make this clear, consider first the sphere shown at the left in Fig-
ure 6.5. Inside the sphere the CG and CC are the same point: the center
of the sphere. For any supersphere with an exponent greater than 2, as
shown second from left in the illustration, the CC is above the CG be-
cause the base is less convex. The higher the exponent, the less convex
the base and the higher the CC.
Now suppose the supersphere is stretched uniformly upward along its
vertical coordinates, transforming it into a superellipsoid of rotation, or
what Piet Hein calls a superegg. As it stretches, the CC falls and the CG
rises. Clearly there must be a point X where the CC and the CG coincide.
Before this crucial point is reached the superegg is stable, as shown third
from left in Figure 6.5. Beyond that point the superegg is unstable (right).
C. E. Gremer, a retired U.S. Navy commander, was the first of many
readers to inform me that the proof is faulty. Contrary to intuition, at the
base point of all supereggs, the center of curvature is infinitely high! If
we increase the height of a superegg while its width remains constant,
the curvature at the base point remains "flat." German mathematicians
call it a flachpunkt. The superellipse has a similar flachpunkt at its
ends. In other words, all supereggs, regardless of their height-width
ratio, are theoretically stable! As a superegg becomes taller and thinner,
there is of course a critical ratio at which the degree of tilt needed to
68 PLANE GEOMETRY
Figure 6.5. Diagrams for a false proof of superegg instability
topple it comes so close to zero that such factors as inhomogeneity of
the material, surface irregularity, vibrations, air currents, and so on
make it practically unstable. But in a mathematically ideal sense there
is no critical height-width ratio. As Piet Hein put it, in theory one can
balance any number of supereggs, each an inch wide and as tall as the
Empire State Building, on top of one another, end to end, and they will
not fall. Calculating precise "topple angles" at which a given superegg
will not regain balance is a tricky problem in calculus. Many readers
tackled it and sent their results.
Speaking of egg balancing, the reader may not know that almost any
chicken egg can be balanced on its broad end, on a smooth surface, if
one is patient and steady-handed. Nothing is gained by shaking the
egg first in an attempt to break the yolk. Even more puzzling as a par-
lor trick is the following method of balancing an egg on its pointed
end. Secretly put a tiny amount of salt on the table, balance the egg on
it, then gently blow away the excess grains before you call in viewers.
The few remaining grains which hold the egg are invisible, especially
on a white surface. For some curious reason, balancing chicken eggs le-
gitimately on their broad ends became a craze in China in 1945-at
least, so said Life in its picture story of April 9, 1945.
The world's largest superegg, made of steel and aluminum and
weighing almost a ton, was set up outside Kelvin Hall in Glasgow, Oc-
tober 1971, to honor Piet Hein's appearance there as a speaker during
an exhibition of modern homes. The superellipse has twice appeared
on Danish postage stamps: In 1970 on a blue two-kroner honoring
Bertel Thorvaldsen and in 1972 on a Christmas seal bearing portraits of
the queen and the prince consort.
Piet Hein's Superellipse 69
6.6. .... ..... .. '-' ... J . I . . . I . . I . l l J g ~ on two .J.JCI...U..I..:J'.u. stamps
70
1. Nimbi. This is a 12-counter version of Piet Hein's nim-type game.
The counters are locked-in, sliding pegs on a reversible circular
board so that after a game is played by pushing the pegs down and
turning the board over it is set for another game.
2. Anagog. Here we have a spherical cousin ofPiet Hein's Soma cube. Six
pieces of joined unit spheres are to be formed into a 20-sphere tetra-
hedron or two 10-sphere tetrahedrons or other solid and flat figures.
3. Crux. A solid cross of six projecting arms is so designed that each arm
rotates separately. One of several problems is to bring three spots of
different colors together at each intersection.
4. Twitchit. A dodecahedron has rotating faces and the problem is to
turn them until three different symbols are together at each corner.
5. Bloxbox. W. W. Rouse Ball, discussing the standard 14-15 sliding-
block puzzle in his Mathematical Recreations and Essays, wrote in
1892: "We can conceive also of a similar cubical puzzle, but we could
not work it practically except by sections." Eighty-one years later,
Piet Hein found an ingenious practical solution. Seven identical unit
cubes are inside a transparent plastic order-2 cube. When the cube is
tilted properly, gravity slides a cube (with a pleasant click) into the
hole. Each cube has three black and three white sides. Problems in-
clude forming an order-2 cube (minus one corner) with all sides one
color, or all sides checkered, or all striped, and so on.
Does the parity principle involved in flat versions apply to the
three-dimensional version? And what are the minimum required
moves to get from one pattern to another? Bloxbox opens a Pandora's
box of questions.
Scantion International, a Danish management and consulting com-
pany, adopted the superegg as its logo. In 1982 it moved its world head-
quarters to Princeton, NJ, where Scantion-Princeton, as it is called, built
a luxurious hotel and conference center hidden within the 25 acres of
Princeton's Forrestal Center. An enormous stone superegg stands on the
plaza in front of the hotel. The Schweppes Building, in Stamford, CT, just
south of Exit 25 on the Merritt Parkway, has the shape of a superellipse.
Hermann Zapf designed a typeface whose "bowls" are based on the
superellipse. He called it "Melior" because the curve meliorates be-
tween an ellipse and a rectangle. You'll find a picture of the upper- and
lower-case letters on page 284 of Douglas Hofstadter's Metamagical
Themas (Basic Books, 1985), with comments on page 291.
Piet Rein's SuperelJipse 71
6.1. "'-7J. .... u.J:\.L>J cut a u ....... 'v ................ t"' .. "'J.
J.
31-37.
55-66.
72
Chapter 7 Penrose Tiles
At the end of a 1975 Scientific American column on tiling the
plane periodically with congruent convex polygons (reprinted in my
Time Travel and Other Mathematical Bewilderments) I promised a later
column on nonperiodic tiling. This chapter reprints my fulfillment of
that promise-a 1977 column that reported for the first time a remark-
able nonperiodic tiling discovered by Roger Penrose, the noted British
mathematical physicist and cosmologist. First, let me give some defin-
itions and background.
A periodic tiling is one on which you can outline a region that tiles
the plane by translation, that is, by shifting the position of the region
without rotating or reflecting it. M. C. Escher, the Dutch artist, was fa-
mous for his many pictures of periodic tilings with shapes that resem-
ble living things. Figure 7.1 is typical. An adjacent black and white
bird constitute a fundamental region that tiles by translation. Think of
the plane as being covered with transparent paper on which each tile
is outlined. Only if the tiling is periodic can you shift the paper, with-
out rotation, to a new position where all outlines again exactly fit.
An infinity of shapes-for instance the regular hexagon-tile only pe-
riodically. An infinity of other shapes tile both periodically and non-
periodically. A checkerboard is easily converted to a nonperiodic tiling
by identical isosceles right triangles or by quadrilaterals. Simply bisect
each square as shown in Figure 7.2A, left, altering the orientations to
prevent periodicity. It is also easy to tile nonperiodically with domi-
noes.
Isoceles triangles also tile in the radial fashion shown in the center
of Figure 7.2(A). Although the tiling is highly ordered, it is obviously
not periodic. As Michael Goldberg pointed out in a 1955 paper titled
"Central Tessellations," such a tiling can be sliced in half, and then the
73
7.1. A pelLlOlalC .. "''''''"''' .... QUlV.U.
A
--
-- "- "-
- ./ -
- ...,....
/
/
B
at
74
tiles spirally. Figure 7.3 shows a striking pattern obtained in this way
from a nine-sided polygon. It was first found by Heinz Voderberg in a
complicated procedure. Goldberg's method of obtaining it makes it al-
most trivial.
Figure 1.3. A spiral tiling by Heinz Voderberg
In all known cases of nonperiodic tiling by congruent figures the fig-
ure also tiles periodically. Figure 7.2(B}, right, shows how two of the
Voderberg enneagons go together to make an octagon that tiles period-
ically in an obvious way.
Another kind of nonperiodic tiling is obtained by tiles that group to-
gether to form larger replicas of themselves. Solomon W. Golomb calls
them "reptiles." Figure 7.4 shows how a shape called the H sphinx"
tiles nonperiodically by giving rise to ever larger sphinxes. Again, two
sphinxes (with one sphinx rotated 180 degrees) tile periodically in an
obvious way.
Are there sets of tiles that tile only nonperiodically? By "only" we
mean that neither a single shape or subset nor the entire set tiles peri-
odically but that by using all of them a nonperiodic tiling is possible.
Rotating and reflecting tiles are allowed.
For many decades experts believed no such set exists, but the sup-
Penrose Tiles 75
are
six a nOllpe:nodic
77
A
Ace
78
H
Kite
Short bow tie
C
T
T
T
Dart
B
tie
and dart
should make at least 100 kites and 60 darts. The pieces need be colored
on one side only. The number of pieces of the two shapes are (like their
areas) in the golden ratio. You might suppose you need more of the
smaller darts, but it is the other way around. You need 1.618 ... as
many kites as darts. In an infinite tiling this proportion is exact. The ir-
rationality of the ratio underlies a proof by Penrose that the tiling is
nonperiodic because if it were periodic, the ratio clearly would have to
be rational.
A good plan is to draw as many darts and kites as you can on one
sheet, with a ratio of about five kites to three darts, using a thin line for
the curves. The sheet can be photocopied many times. The curves can
then be colored, say, red and green. Conway has found that it speeds
constructions and keeps patterns stabler if you make many copies of the
three larger shapes as is shown in Figure 7.6(C). As you expand a pat-
tern, you can continually replace darts and kites with aces and bow
ties. Actually an infinity of arbitrarily large pairs of shapes, made up of
darts and kites, will serve for tiling any infinite pattern.
A Penrose pattern is made by starting with darts and kites around one
vertex and then expanding radially. Each time you add a piece to an
edge, you must choose between a dart and a kite. Sometimes the choice
is forced, sometimes it is not. Sometimes either piece fits, but later you
may encounter a contradiction (a spot where no piece can be legally
added) and be forced to go back and make the other choice. It is a good
plan to go around a boundary, placing all the forced pieces first. They
cannot lead to a contradiction. You can then experiment with unforced
pieces. It is always possible to continue forever. The more you play
with the pieces, the more you will become aware of "forcing rules"
that increase efficiency. For example, a dart forces two kites in its con-
cavity, creating the ubiquitous ace.
There are many ways to prove that the number of Penrose tilings is
uncountable, just as the number of points on a line is. These proofs rest
on a surprising phenomenon discovered by Penrose. Conway calls it
"inflation" and "deflation." Figure 7.7 shows the beginning of inflation.
Imagine that every dart is cut in half and then all short edges of the orig-
inal pieces are glued together. The result: a new tiling (shown in heavy
black lines) by larger darts and kites.
Inflation can be continued to infinity, with each new "generation" of
pieces larger than the last. Note that the second-generation kite, al-
though it is the same size and shape as a first-generation ace, is formed
Penrose Tiles 79
1.1.
80
Not all possible sequences of the four symbols can be produced this
way, but those that label different patterns can be shown to correspond
in number with the number of points on a line.
We have omitted the colored curves on our pictures of tilings be-
cause they make it difficult to see the tiles. If you work with colored
tiles, however, you will be struck by the beautiful designs created by
these curves. Penrose and Conway independently proved that when-
ever a curve closes, it has a pentagonal symmetry, and the entire region
within the curve has a fivefold symmetry. At the most a pattern can
have two curves of each color that do not close. In most patterns all
curves close.
Although it is possible to construct Penrose patterns with a high de-
gree of symmetry (an infinity of patterns have bilateral symmetry), most
patterns, like the universe, are a mystifying mixture of order and un-
expected deviations from order. As the patterns expand, they seem to
be always striving to repeat themselves but never quite managing it. G.
K. Chesterton once suggested that an extraterrestrial being, observing
how many features of a human body are duplicated on the left and the
right, would reasonably deduce that we have a heart on each side. The
world, he said, "looks just a little more mathematical and regular than
it is; its exactitude is obvious, but its inexactitude is hidden; its wild-
ness lies in wait." Everywhere there is a "silent swerving from accuracy
by an inch that is the uncanny element in everything . . . a sort of se-
cret treason in the universe." The passage is a nice description of Pen-
rose's planar worlds.
There is something even more surprising about Penrose universes. In
a curious finite sense, given by the "local isomorphism theorem," all
Penrose patterns are alike. Penrose was able to show that every finite
region in any pattern is contained somewhere inside every other pat-
tern. Moreover, it appears infinitely many times in every pattern.
To understand how crazy this situation is, imagine you are living on
an infinite plane tessellated by one tiling of the uncountable infinity of
Penrose tilings. You can examine your pattern, piece by piece, in ever
expanding areas. No matter how much of it you explore you can never
determine which tiling you are on. It is no help to travel far out and ex-
amine disconnected regions, because all the regions belong to one large
finite region that is exactly duplicated infinitely many times on all pat-
terns. Of course, this is trivially true of any periodic tessellation, but
Penrose Tiles 81
Penrose universes are not periodic. They differ from one another in in-
finitely many ways, and yet it is only at the unobtainable limit that one
can be distinguished from another.
Suppose you have explored a circular region of diameter d. Call it the
"town" where you live. Suddenly you are transported to a randomly
chosen parallel Penrose world. How far are you from a circular region
that exactly matches the streets of your home town? Conway answers
with a truly remarkable theorem. The distance from the perimeter of the
home town to the perimeter of the duplicate town is never more than
d times half of the cube of the golden ratio, or 2.11 + times d. (This is
an upper bound, not an average.) If you walk in the right direction,
you need not go more than that distance to find yourself inside an exact
copy of your home town. The theorem also applies to the universe in
which you live. Every large circular pattern (there is an infinity of dif-
ferent ones) can be reached by walking a distance in some direction
that is certainly less than about twice the diameter of the pattern and
more likely about the same distance as the diameter.
The theorem is quite unexpected. Consider an analogous isomor-
phism exhibited by a sequence of unpatterned digits such as pi. If you
pick a finite sequence of 10 digits and then start from a random spot in
pi, you are pretty sure to encounter the same sequence if you move far
enough along pi, but the distance you must go has no known upper
bound, and the expected distance is enormously longer than 10 digits.
The longer the finite sequence is, the farther you can expect to walk to
find it again. On a Penrose pattern you are always very close to a du-
plicate of home.
There are just seven ways that darts and kites will fit around a ver-
tex. Let us consider first, using Conway's nomenclature, the two ways
with pentagonal symmetry.
The sun (shown in white in Figure 7.8) does not force the placing of
any other piece around it. If you add pieces so that pentagonal sym-
metry is always preserved, however, you will be forced to construct the
beautiful pattern shown. It is uniquely determined to infinity.
The star, shown in white in Figure 7.9, forces the 10 light gray kites
around it. Enlarge this pattern, always preserving the fivefold symmetry,
and you will create another flowery design that is infinite and unique.
The star and sun patterns are the only Penrose universes with perfect
pentagonal symmetry, and there is a lovely sense in which they are
equivalent. Inflate or deflate either of the patterns and you get the other.
82 PLANE GEOMETRY
1.8.
1.9.
It no more
ure
83
Deuce Jack Queen
1.10. queen
84
7.11.
85
...... , ... , ................ '"' ...... to
Buzzsaw Starfish Asterlx
1.12.
86
87
areas.
1.14. A n011pe:flOCllc
88
about kites and darts can be translated into a theorem about the Penrose
rhombuses or any other pair of Penrose tiles and vice versa. Conway
prefers to work with darts and kites, but other mathematicians prefer
working with the simpler rhombuses. Robert Ammann has found a be-
wildering variety of other sets of nonperiodic tiles. One set, consisting
of two convex pentagons and a convex hexagon, forces non periodicity
without any edge markings. He found several pairs, each a hexagon
with five interior angles of 90 degrees and one of 270 degrees.
Figure 1.1 s. The Pythagorean E
pentagram
A ~ - - - - - - ~ ~ - - - - ~ - - - - - - - - ~
Are there pairs of tiles not related to the golden ratio that force non-
periodicity? Is there a pair of similar tiles that force non periodicity? Is
there a pair of convex tiles that will force nonperiodicity without edge
markings?
Of course, the major unsolved problem is whether there is a single
shape that will tile the plane only nonperiodically. Most experts think
not, but no one is anywhere near proving it. It has not even been shown
that if such a tile exists, it must be nonconvex.
Addendum
For much more on Penrose tiles, see Chapter 2 in my Penrose
Tiles to Trapdoor Ciphers (Mathematical Association of America 1989;
paperback, 1997) in which I discuss solid forms of the tiles and their as-
tonishing application to what are called quasicrystals. Until Penrose's
discovery, crystals based on fivefold symmetry were believed to be im-
Penrose Tiles 89
possible to construct. My bibliography gives only a small sampling of
books and papers about quasicrystals that have been published in re-
cent years.
In 1993 John Horton Conway made a significant breakthrough when
he discovered a convex solid called a biprism that tiles space only ape-
riodically. (Aperiodic has replaced nonperiodic as a term for a tile that
tiles only in a nonperiodic way.) A few years earlier Peter Schmitt, at
the University of Vienna, found a nonconvex solid that fills space ape-
riodically, though in a trivial fashion. Conway's subtler solid is de-
scribed and pictured in Keith Devlin's The Language of Mathematics
(W. H. Freeman, 1998, pp. 219-20; paperback, 2000). Doris Schatt-
schneider kindly supplied me with the pattern shown in Figure 7.16 for
constructing the Conway solid.
To assemble, score on all interior
lines, then cut around the outline of
the pattern. Tabs labeled u are to be
folded up, those with d are to be
folded down. Two prisms are then
assembled, one on each side of the
common rhombus face.
Figure 1.16. Conway's biprism. The central rhombus (which is inside the model when as-
sembled) has sides of length 2 and short diagonal length Yz. The small angle of the
rhombus is arcos(3/4) "" 41.4 degrees. Two triangular prisms are built on this common
rhombus face. The diagonal of the prism parallelogram face has length Y(33/4) = 2.87.
When assembled, the vertices of the rhombus that is a common face of the two prisms
are the poles of 2 twofold rotation raxes.
As Devlin explains, Conway's biprism fills space in layers. Every
layer is periodic, but each adjacent layer must be rotated by an irra-
tional angle that forces aperiodicity. Unfortunately neither of the two
aperiodic solids leads to the construction of a flat tile that covers the
plane aperiodically. Finding such a tile or proving it nonexistent is the
top unsolved problem in tiling theory.
In 1997 Penrose sued England's Kimberly-Clark Company for putting
his tiling pattern on their quilted toilet paper without his permission.
90 PLANE GEOMETRY
See Time, May 5, 1997, page 26, for the story and a picture of the
paper's pattern. I don't know the outcome of the lawsuit.
For a long time Penrose tiles were unavailable for purchase. Happily
they are now on the market in a variety of forms that can be obtained
from Kadon Enterprises, 1227 Lorrene Drive, Pasadena, MD 21122.
Bibliography
Nonperiodic tiling
E.P.M. Beenker, "Algebraic Theory of Nonperiodic Tilings of the Plane by Two
Simple Building Blocks: A Square and a Rhombus," Eindhoven University of
Technology, the Netherlands, Department of Mathematics and Computer Sci-
ence, T. H. Report 82-WSK-04, September 1982.
R Berger "The Undecidability of the Domino Problem," Memoirs of the American
Mathematical Society, No. 66, 1966.
N. G. de Bruijn. "Algebraic Theory of Penrose's Nonperiodic THings of the Plane,"
Koninklijke Nederlandse Akademie van Wetenschappen Proceedings Ser. A,
Vol. 84,1981,pp. 39-66.
M. Goldberg, "Central Tessellations," Scripta Mathematica, Vol. 21, 1955, pp.
253-60.
B. Griinbaum and G. C. Shephard, "Some Problems on Plane THings," The Mathe-
matical Gardner, D. A Klamer (ed.), Prindle, Weber & Schmidt, 1981.
B. Griinbaum and G. C. Shephard, Tilings and Patterns, W. H. Freeman, 1986.
R K. Guy, "The Penrose Pieces," Bulletin of the London Mathematical Society,
Vol. 8, 1976, pp. 9-10.
I. Hargittai, "Quasicrystal Structure in Bad Ragaz," The Mathematical Intelligencer,
44,1992,pp.58-59.
M. Naylor, "Nonperiodic Tiling," The Mathematics Teacher, 92, 1999, pp. 34-39.
K. Miyazaki, On Some Periodical and Non-Periodical Honeycombs, A Kobe Uni-
versity monograph, 1977.
R Penrose, "The Role of Aesthetics in Pure and Applied Mathematical Research,"
Bulletin of the Institute of Mathematics and Its Applications, Vol. 10, 1974, pp.
266-71.
R Penrose, "Pentaplexity: A Class of Nonperiodic THings of the Plane," Eureka, 39,
1978, pp. 16-22. Reprinted in The Mathematical Intelligencer, Vol. 2, 1979, pp.
32-37 and in Geometrical Combinatorics, F. C. Holroyd and R J. Wilson, (eds.),
Pitman, 1984.
R Penrose, "Remarks on Tiling," The Mathematics of Long-Range Aperiodic Order,
RV. Moody (ed.), Kluwer, 1997, pp. 467-97.
I. Peterson, "From Here to Infinity," Islands of Truth, W. H. Freeman, 1990, pp.
86-95.
I. Peterson, "Clusters and Decagons," Science News, 150, 1996, pp. 232-33.
Penrose Tiles 91
C. Radin, Miles of Tiles, American Mathematical Society, 1999.
R. M. Robinson, "Undecidability and Nonperiodicity for THings of the Plane," In-
ventiones Mathematicae, Vol. 12, 1971, pp. 177-209.
T. Sibley and S. Wagon, "Rhombic Penrose Tiling Can Be 3-Colored," American
Mathematical Monthly, vol. 107, March 2000, pp. 251-53.
S. Wagon, "Penrose Tiles," Mathematica in Action, W. H. Freeman, 1993, pp.
108-17.
H. Wang, "Games, Logic and Computers," Scientific American, November 1965, pp.
98-106.
,Quasierystals
M. W. Browne, "Puzzling Crystals Plunge Scientists into Uncertainty," The New
York Times, July 30, 1985, p. Cl ff.
M. W. Browne, "Potential Seen in New Quasicrystals," The New York Times, Sep-
tember 5, 1989.
M. W. Browne, " 'Impossible' Form of Matter Takes Spotlight in Study of Solids,"
The New York Times, September 5, 1989.
M. W. Browne, "New Data Help Explain Crystals That Defy Nature," The New York
Times, November 24, 1998.
L. Danzer, "Three-Dimensional Analogs of the Planar Penrose Tiling and Qua-
sicrystals," Discrete Mathematics, 76,1989, pp. 1-7.
N. G. de Bruijn, "A Riffle Shuffle Card Trick and Its Relation to Quasicrystal The-
ory," Nieuw Archiefvoor Wiskunde, Vol. 5, November 1987.
A. Goldman et al., "Quasicrystalline Materials," American Scientist, 8, 1996, pp.
230-41.
I. Hargittai (ed.), Fivefold Symmetry, World Scientific, 1991.
J. Horgan, "Quasicrystals: Rules of the Game," Science, 247, 1990, pp. 1020-22.
C. Jano, Quasicrystals: A Primer, Oxford Science, 1994.
M. V. Jaric (ed.), Introduction to Quasicrystals, Vol. 1, Aperiodicityand Order, Aca-
demic Press, 1988 and Vol. 2, Introduction to the Mathematics of Quasicrystals,
Academic Press, 1989; M. V. Jaric and D. Gratias (eds.), Vol. 3, Extended Icosa-
hedral Structures, Academic Press, 1990.
M. La Brecque, "Opening the Door to Forbidden Symmetries," Mosaic, Vol. 18,
1987-1988,pp.2-23.
D. Levine, "Quasicrystals: A New Class of Ordered Structure," Ph.D. thesis, Uni-
versity of Pennsylvania, 1986.
R. Mosseri and J. F. Sadoc, "Pauling's Model Not Universally Accepted," Nature,
Vol. 319,1986, p. 104. Reply to Pauling's 1985 paper.
D. R. Nelson, "Quasicrystals," SCientifiC American, August 1986, pp. 42-51.
D. R. Nelson and B. L Halperin, "Pentagonal and Icosahedral Order in Rapidly
Cooled Metals," Science, Vol. 229,1985, pp. 235-38.
J. Patera, Quasicrystals and Discrete Geometry, American Mathematical Society,
1998.
L. Pauling, "Apparent Icosahedral Symmetry is Due to Directed Multiple Twinning
of Cubic Crystals," Nature, VoL 317. 1985. p. 512.
92 PLANE GEOMETRY
L. Pauling, "Icosahedral Symmetry," Science, Vol. 239, 1988, pp. 963-64. This let-
ter from Linus Pauling continues his attack on quasicrystals, with a reply by Paul
Steinhardt.
1. Peterson, "The Fivefold Way for Crystals," Science News, Vol. 127, 1985, pp.
188-89. Reprinted in Peterson's collection The Mathematical Tourist, W. H.
Freeman, 1988, pp. 200-212.
1. Peterson, "Tiling to Infinity," Science News, Vol. 134, July 16, 1988, p. 42.
I. Peterson, "Shadows and Symmetries," Science News, 140, 1991, pp. 408-19.
M. Senechal, Quasicrystals and Geometry, Cambridge University Press, 1995.
M. Senechal and J. Taylor, "Quasicrystal: The View From Les Houches," Mathe-
maticallntelligencer, 12, 1990, pp. 54-63.
P. J. Steinhardt, "Quasicrystals," American Scientist, November/December 1986,
pp. 586-597. Its bibliography lists more than 40 technical papers.
P. Steinhardt, "Crazy Crystals," New Scientist, January 25,1997, pp. 32-35.
P. Steinhardt and S. Ostlund (eds.), The Physics of Quasicrystals, World Scientific,
1987.
P. W. Stepheus and A. I. Goldman, "The Structure of Quasicrystals," Scientific
American, April 1991, pp. 44ff.
D. P. Vincenzo and P. J. Steinhardt (eds.), Quasicrystals: The State of the Art, World
Scientific, 1991.
H. C. Von Baeyer, "Impossible Crystals," Discover, February 1990, pp. 69-78.
D. Voss, "Smash the System," New Scientist, 27, 1999, pp. 42-46.
Penrose Tiles 93
Chapter 8
Planiversal scientists are not a very
common breed.
-Alexander Keewatin Dewdney
The Wonders
of a Planiverse
Jls far as anyone knows the only existing universe is the one
we live in, with its three dimensions of space and one of time. It is not
hard to imagine, as many science-fiction writers have, that intelligent
organisms could live in a four-dimensional space, but two dimensions
offer such limited degrees of freedom that it has long been assumed in-
telligent 2-space life forms could not exist. Two notable attempts have
nonetheless been made to describe such organisms.
In 1884 Edwin Abbott Abbott, a London clergyman, published his
satirical novel Flatland. Unfortunately the book leaves the reader al-
most entirely in the dark about Flatland's physical laws and the tech-
nology developed by its inhabitants, but the situation was greatly
improved in 1907 when Charles Howard Hinton published An Episode
of Flatland. Although written in a flat style and with cardboard char-
acters, Hinton's story provided the first glimpses of the possible science
and technology of the two-dimensional world. His eccentric book is,
alas, long out of print, but you can read about it in the chapter "Flat-
lands" in my book The Unexpected Hanging and Other Mathematical
Diversions (Simon & Schuster, 1969).
In "Flatlands" I wrote: "It is amusing to speculate on two-
dimensional physics and the kinds of simple mechanical devices that
would be feasible in a flat world." This remark caught the attention of
Alexander Keewatin Dewdney, a computer scientist at the University
of Western Ontario. Some of his early speculations on the subject were
set down in 1978 in a university report and in 1979 in "Exploring the
Planiverse," an article in Journal of Recreational Mathematics (Vol. 12,
No.1, pp. 16-20; September). Later in 1979 Dewdney also privately
published "Two-dimensional Science and Technology," a 97-page tour
de force. It is hard to believe, but Dewdney actually lays the ground-
94
work for what he calls a planiverse: a possible two-dimensional world.
Complete with its own laws of chemistry, physics, astronomy, and bi-
ology, the planiverse is closely analogous to our own universe (which
he calls the steriverse) and is apparently free of contradictions. I should
add that this remarkable achievement is an amusing hobby for a math-
ematician whose serious contributions have appeared in some 30 pa-
pers in technical journals.
Dewdney's planiverse resembles Hinton's in having an earth that he
calls (as Hinton did) Astria. Astria is a dislike planet that rotates in pla-
nar space. The Astrians, walking upright on the rim of the planet, can
distinguish east and west and up and down. Naturally there is no north
or south. The "axis" of Astria is a point at the center of the circular
planet. You can think of such a flat planet as being truly two-
dimensional or you can give it a very slight thickness and imagine it as
moving between two frictionless planes.
As in our world, gravity in a planiverse is a force between objects that
varies directly with the product of their masses, but it varies inversely
with the linear distance between them, not with the square of that dis-
tance. On the assumption that forces such as light and gravity in a
planiverse move in straight lines, it is easy to see that the intensity of
such forces must vary inversely with linear distance. The familiar text-
book figure demonstrating that in our world the intensity of light varies
inversely with the square of distance is shown at the top of Figure 8.1.
The obvious planar analogue is shown at the bottom of the illustra-
tion.
To keep his whimsical project from" degenerating into idle specula-
tion" Dewdney adopts two basic principles. The "principle of similarity"
states that the planiverse must be as much like the steriverse as possi-
ble: a motion not influenced by outside forces follows a straight line,
the flat analogue of a sphere is a circle, and so on. The "principle of
modification" states that in those cases where one is forced to choose
between conflicting hypotheses, each one equally similar to a steriver-
sal theory, the more fundamental one must be chosen and the other
must be modified. To determine which hypothesis is more fundamen-
tal Dewdney relies on the hierarchy in which physics is more funda-
mental than chemistry, chemistry is more fundamental than biology,
and so on.
To illustrate the interplay between levels of theory Dewdney con-
siders the evolution of the planiversal hoist in Figure 8.2. The engineer
The Wonders of a Planiverse 95
FigureS.I.
ARC
LIGHT
NINE
SQUARE
INCHES
I ').
I I ..... "
I I '
I
1,.1 I I
I 1'",,,, l
I I I "''I
I.. : 1 I
I '-I.. I I
I 1"'..1. 1
I I r"' ....
I I I
.... '" I I
"' .... I
tEt=--------THREE FEET---------:.t
THREE
INCHES
who designed it first gave it arms thinner than those in the illustration,
but when a metallurgist pointed out that planar materials fracture more
easily than their 3-space counterparts, the engineer made the arms
thicker. Later a theoretical chemist, invoking the principles of similar-
ity and modification at a deeper level, calculated that the planiversal
molecular forces are much stronger than had been suspected, and so
the engineer went back to thinner arms.
The principle of similarity leads Dewdney to posit that the planiverse
Figure 8.2.
96 PLANE GEOMETRY
is a three-dimensional continuum of space-time containing matter
composed of molecules, atoms, and fundamental particles. Energy is
propagated by waves, and it is quantized. Light exists in all its wave-
lengths and is refracted by planar lenses, making possible planiversal
eyes, planiversal telescopes, and planiversal microscopes. The plani-
verse shares with the steriverse such basic precepts as causality; the
first and second laws of thermodynamics; and laws concerning inertia,
work, friction, magnetism, and elasticity.
Dewdney assumes that his planiverse began with a big bang and is
currently expanding. An elementary calculation based on the inverse-
linear gravity law-shows that regardless of the amount of mass in the
planiverse the expansion must eventually halt, so that a contracting
phase will begin. The Astrian night sky will of course be a semicircle
along which are scattered twinkling points of light. If the stars have
proper motions, they will continually be occulting one another. If As-
tria has a sister planet, it will over a period of time occult every star in
the sky.
We can assume that Astria revolves around a sun and rotates, thereby
creating day and night. In a planiverse, Dewdney discovered, the only
stable orbit that continually retraces the same path is a perfect circle.
Other stable orbits roughly elliptical in shape are possible, but the axis
of the ellipse rotates in such a way that the orbit never exactly closes.
Whether planiversal gravity would allow a moon to have a stable orbit
around Astria remains to be determined. The difficulty is due to the
sun's gravity, and resolving the question calls for work on the planar
analogue of what our astronomers know as the three-body problem.
Dewdney analyzes in detail the nature of Astrian weather, using
analogies to our seasons, winds, clouds, and rain. An Astrian river
would be indistinguishable from a lake except that it might have faster
currents. One peculiar feature of Astrian geology is that water cannot
flow around a rock as it does on the earth. As a result rainwater steadily
accumulates behind any rock on a slope, tending to push the rock
downhill: the gentler the slope is, the more water accumulates and the
stronger the push is. Dewdney concludes that given periodic rainfall
the Astrian surface would be unusually flat and uniform. Another con-
sequence of the inability of water to move sideways on Astria is that it
would become trapped in pockets within the soil, tending to create
large areas of treacherous quicksand in the hollows of the planet. One
hopes, Dewdney writes, that rainfall is infrequent on Astria. Wind too
The Wonders of a Planiverse 97
would have much severer effects on Astria than on the earth because
like rain it cannot "go around" objects.
Dewdney devotes many pages to constructing a plausible chemistry
for his planiverse, modeling it as much as possible on three-
dimensional matter and the laws of quantum mechanics. Figure 8.3
shows Dewdney's periodic table for the first 16 planiversal elements.
Because the first two are so much like their counterparts in our world,
they are called hydrogen and helium. The next 10 have composite
names to suggest the steriversal elements they most resemble; for ex-
ample, lithrogen combines the properties of lithium and nitrogen. The
next four are named after Hinton, Abbott, and the young lovers in Hin-
ton's novel, Harold Wall and Laura Cartwright.
ATOMIC NAME SYMBOL SHELL STRUCTURE VALENCE
NUMBER ls 2s 2p 3s 3p 3d 4s 4p ...
1 HYDROGEN H 1 1
2 HELIUM He 2 2
3 LITROGEN Lt 2 1 1
4 BEROXYGEN Bx 2 2 2
5 FLUORON FI 2 2 1 3
6 NEOCARBON Nc 2 2 2 4
7 SODAUNUM Sa 2 2 2 1 1
8 MAGNILICON Me 2 2 2 2 2
9 ALUPHORUS Ap 2 2 2 2 1 3
10 SULFICON Sp 2 2 2 2 2 4
11 CHLOPHORUS Cp 2 2 2 2 2 1 5
12
ARGOFUR At 2 2 2 2 2 2 B
13 HINTONIUM Hn 2 2 2 2 2 2 1 1
14
ABBOOEN Ab 2 2 2 2 2 2 2 2
15 HAROLDIUM Wa 2 2 2 2 2 2 2 1 3
16 LAURANIUM La 2 2 2 2 2 2 2 2 4
FigureS.3.
In the flat world atoms combine naturally to form molecules, but of
course only bonding that can be diagrammed by a planar graph is al-
lowed. (This result follows by analogy from the fact that intersecting
bonds do not exist in steriversal chemistry.) As in our world, two
asymmetric molecules can be mirror images of each other, so that nei-
ther one can be "turned over" to become identical with the other. There
are striking parallels between planiversal chemistry and the behavior
of steriversal monolayers on crystal surfaces (see J. G. Dash, "Two-
dimensional Matter," Scientific American, May 1973). In our world
molecules can form 230 distinct crystallographic groups, but in the
98 PLANE GEOMETRY
pI ani verse they can form only 17. I am obliged to pass over Dewdney's
speculations about the diffusion of molecules, electrical and magnetic
laws, analogues of Maxwell's equations, and other subjects too techni-
cal to summarize here.
Dewdney assumes that animals on Astria are composed of cells that
cluster to form bones, muscles, and connective tissues similar to those
found in steriversal biology. He has little difficulty showing how these
bones and muscles can be structured to move appendages in such a
way that the animals can crawl, walk, fly, and swim. Indeed, some of
these movements are easier in a planiverse than in our world. For ex-
ample, a steriversal animal with two legs has considerable difficulty
balancing while walking, whereas in the planiverse if an animal has
both legs on the ground, there is no way it can fall over. Moreover, a fly-
ing planiversal animal cannot have wings and does not need them to
fly; if the body of the animal is aerodynamically shaped, it can act as a
wing (since air can go around it only in the plane). The flying animal
could be propelled by a flapping tail.
Calculations also show that Astrian animals probably have much
lower metabolic rates than terrestrial animals because relatively little
heat is lost through the perimeter of their body. Furthermore, animal
bones can be thinner on Astria than they are on the earth, because they
have less weight to support. Of course, no Astrian animal can have an
open tube extending from its mouth to its anus, because if it did, it
would be cut in two.
In the appendix to his book The Structure and Evolution of the Uni-
verse (Harper, 1959) G. J. Whitrow argues that intelligence could not
evolve in 2-space because of the severe restrictions two dimensions
impose on nerve connections. "In three or more dimensions," he
writes, "any number of [nerve] cells can be connected with [one an-
other] in pairs without intersection of the joins, but in two dimensions
the maximum number of cells for which this is possible is only four."
Dewdney easily demolishes this argument, pointing out that if nerve
cells are allowed to fire nerve impulses through "crossover points,"
they can form flat networks as complex as any in the steriverse.
Planiversal minds would operate more slowly than steriversal ones,
however, because in the two-dimensional networks the pulses would
encounter more interruptions. (There are comparable results in the the-
ory of two-dimensional automatons.)
Dewdney sketches in detail the anatomy of an Astrian female fish
The Wonders of a Planiverse 99
100
life-giving plants and animals, it is clear that very little of the Astrian
surface can be disturbed without inviting the biological destruction of
the planet. For example, here on earth we may build a modest highway
through the middle of several acres of rich farmland and destroy no
more than a small percentage of it. A corresponding highway on Astria
will destroy all the 'acreage' it passes over .... Similarly, extensive
cities would quickly use up the Astrian countryside. It would seem
that the only alternative for the Astrian technological society is to go
underground." A typical subterranean house with a living room, two
bedrooms, and a storage room is shown in Figure 8.5. Collapsible chairs
and tables are stored in recesses in the floors to make the rooms easier
to walk through.
BEDROOMS
Figure B.S.
The many simple three-dimensional mechanical elements that have
obvious analogues on Astria include rods, levers, inclined planes,
springs, hinges, ropes, and cables (see Figure 8.6, top). Wheels can be
rolled along the ground, but there is no way to turn them on a fixed
axle. Screws are impossible. Ropes cannot be knotted; but by the same
token, they never tangle. Tubes and pipes must have partitions, to keep
their sides in place, and the partitions have to be opened (but never all
of them at once) to allow anything to pass through. It is remarkable that
in spite of these severe constraints many flat mechanical devices can be
built that will work. A faucet designed by Dewdney is shown in Figure
8.6, bottom. To operate it the handle is lifted. This action pulls the
valve away from the wall of the spout, allowing the water to flow out.
When the handle is released, the spring pushes the valve back.
The device shown in Figure 8.7 serves to open and close a door (or
a wall). Pulling down the lever at the right forces the wedge at the bot-
tom to the left, thereby allowing the door to swing upward (carrying the
wedge and the levers with it) on a hinge at the top. The door is opened
The Wonders of a Planiverse 101
HINGE 2 J ~ ~ - - ,
SPRING
-'VVVVVv-
ROD
PLANE
I ~
~
Figure 6 (top)
f'cgure 8.6.
from the left by pushing up on the other lever. The door can be lowered
from either side and the wedge can be moved back to stabilize the wall
by moving a lever in the appropriate direction. This device and the
faucet are both mechanisms with permanent planiversal hinges: circu-
lar knobs that rotate inside hollows but cannot be removed from them.
Figure B.B depicts a planiversal steam engine whose operation par-
allels that of a steriversal engine. Steam under pressure is admitted
into the cylinder of the engine through a sliding valve that forms one
of its walls (top). The steam pressure causes a piston to move to the
right until steam can escape into a reservoir chamber above it. The sub-
sequent loss of pressure allows the compound leaf spring at the right
of the cylinder to drive the piston back to the left (bottom). The sliding
valve is closed as the steam escapes into the reservoir, but as the pis-
ton moves back it reopens, pulled to the right by a spring-loaded arm.
Figure B.9 depicts Dewdney's ingenious mechanism for unlocking a
door with a key. This planiversallock consists of three slotted tumblers
(a) that line up when a key is inserted (b) so that their lower halves
move as a unit when the key is pushed (e). The pushing of the key is
transmitted through a lever arm to the master latch, which pushes
down on a slave latch until the door is free to swing to the right (d). The
bar on the lever arm and the lip on the slave latch make the lock diffi-
cult to pick. Simple and compound leaf springs serve to return all the
102 PLANE GEOMETRY
Figure B.7.
parts of the lock except the lever arm to their original positions when
the door is opened and the key is removed. When the door closes, it
strikes the bar on the lever arm, thereby returning that piece to its orig-
inal position as well. This flat lock could actually be employed in the
steriverse; one simply inserts a key without twisting it.
"It is amusing to think," writes Dewdney, "that the rather exotic de-
sign pressures created by the planiversal environment could cause us
to think about mechanisms in such a different way that entirely novel
solutions to old problems arise. The resulting designs, if steriversally
practical, are invariably space-saving."
Thousands of challenging planiversal problems remain unsolved. Is
there a way, Dewdney wonders, to design a two-dimensional windup
motor with flat springs or rubber bands that would store energy? What
The Wonders of a Planiverse 103
8.8.
a
8.9.
104
d
SPRING-
LOADED
ARM
PLANE
1
ments) about what might be observed. "The experimentalist's loss,"
observes Dewdney, "is the theoretician's gain."
A marvelous exhibit could be put on of working models of planiver-
sal machines, cut out of cardboard or sheet metal, and displayed on a
surface that slopes to simulate planiversal gravity. One can also imag-
ine beautiful cardboard exhibits of planiversallandscapes, cities, and
houses. Dewdney has opened up a new game that demands knowledge
of both science and mathematics: the exploration of a vast fantasy
world about which at present almost nothing is known.
It occurs to me that Astrians would be able to play two-dimensional
board games but that such games would be as awkward for them as
three-dimensional board games are for us. I imagine them, then, play-
ing a variety of linear games on the analogue of our 8 x 8 chessboard.
Several games of this type are shown in Figure 8.10. Part (a) shows the
start of a checkers game. Pieces move forward only, one cell at a time,
and jumps are compulsory. The linear game is equivalent to a game of
regular checkers with play confined to the main diagonal of a standard
board. It is easy to see how the second player wins in rational play and
how in misere, or "giveaway," checkers the first player wins just as
easily. Linear checkers games become progressively harder to analyze
as longer boards are introduced. For example, which player wins stan-
dard linear checkers on the ll-cell board when each player starts with
checkers on the first four cells at his end of the board?
2 3 4 5 6 7 8
a
I r=J1r=J 1r=J I
b
a
c
E
d
e
Figure 8. I O.
106 PLANE GEOMETRY
Part (b) in the illustration shows an amusing Astrian analogue of
chess. On a linear board a bishop is meaningless and a queen is the
same as a rook, so the pieces are limited to kings, knights, and rooks.
The only rule modification needed is that a knight moves two cells in
either direction and can jump an intervening piece of either color. If the
game is played rationally, will either White or Black win or will the
game end in a draw? The question is surprisingly tricky to answer.
Linear go, played on the same board, is by no means trivial. The ver-
sion I shall describe, called pinch, was invented in 1970 by James
Marston Henle, a mathematician at Smith College.
In the game of pinch players take turns placing black and white
stones on the cells of the linear board, and whenever the stones of one
player surround the stones of the other, the surrounded stones are re-
moved. For example, both sets of white stones shown in part (c) of Fig-
ure 8.10 are surrounded. Pinch is played according to the following two
rules.
Rule 1: No stone can be placed on a cell where it is surrounded un-
less that move serves to surround a set of enemy stones. Hence in the
situation shown in part (d) of the illustration, White cannot play on
cells 1, 3, or 8, but he can play on cell 6 because this move serves to sur-
round cell 5.
Rule 2: A stone cannot be placed on a cell from which a stone was re-
moved on the last play if the purpose of the move is to surround some-
thing. A player must wait at least one turn before making such a move.
For example, in part (e) of the illustration assume that Black plays on
cell 3 and removes the white stones on cells 4 and 5. White cannot play
on cell 4 (to surround cell 3) for his next move, but he may do so for any
later move. He can play on cell 5, however, because even though a
stone was just removed from that cell, the move does not serve to sur-
round anything. This rule is designed to decrease the number of stale-
mates, as is the similar rule in go.
Two-cell pinch is a trivial win for the second player. The three- and
four-cell games are easy wins for the first player if he takes the center
in the three-cell game and one of the two central cells in the four-cell
one. The five-cell game is won by the second player and the six- and
seven-cell games are won by the first player. The eight-cell game jumps
to such a high level of complexity that it becomes very exciting to play.
Fortunes often change rapidly, and in most situations the winning
player has only one winning move.
The Wonders of a P]aniverse 107
Addendum
My column on the planiverse generated enormous interest.
Dewdney received some thousand letters offering suggestions about
flatland science and technology. In 1979 he privately printed Two-
Dimensional Science and Technology, a monograph discussing these
new results. Two years later he edited another monograph, A Sympo-
sium of Two-Dimensional Science and Technology. It contained papers
by noted scientists, mathematicians, and laymen, grouped under the
categories of physics, chemistry, astronomy, biology, and technology.
Newsweek covered these monographs in a two-page article, "Life in
Two Dimensions" (January 18, 1980), and a similar article, "Scientific
Dreamers' Worldwide Cult," ran in Canada's Maclean's magazine (Jan-
uary 11,1982). Omni (March 1983), in an article on "Flatland Redux,"
included a photograph of Dewdney shaking hands with an Astrian.
In 1984 Dewdney pulled it all together in a marvelous work, half
nonfiction and half fantasy, titled The Planiverse and published by Po-
seidon Press, an imprint of Simon & Schuster. That same year he took
over the mathematics column in Scientific American, shifting its em-
phasis to computer recreations. Several collections of his columns have
been published by W. H. Freeman: The Armchair Universe (1987), The
Turing Omnibus (1989), and The Magic Machine (1990).
An active branch of physics is now devoted to planar phenomena. It
involves research on the properties of surfaces covered by a film one
molecule thick, and a variety of two-dimensional electrostatic and elec-
tronic effects. Exploring possible flatlands also relates to a philosoph-
ical fad called "possible worlds." Extreme proponents of this
movement actually argue that if a universe is logically possible-that
is, free of logical contradictions-it is just as "real" as the universe in
which we flourish.
In Childhood's End Arthur Clarke describes a giant planet where in-
tense gravity has forced life to evolve almost flat forms with a vertical
thickness of one centimeter.
The following letter from J. Richard Gott III, an astrophysicist at
Princeton University, was published in Scientific American (October
1980):
I was interested in Martin Gardner's article on the physics of Flatland,
because for some years I have given the students in my general relativ-
108 PLANE GEOMETRY
ity class the problem of deriving the theory of general relativity for Flat-
land. The results are surprising. One does not obtain the Flatland ana-
logue of Newtonian theory (masses with gravitational fields falling off
like llr) as the weak-field limit. General relativity in Flatland predicts no
gravitational waves and no action at a distance. A planet in Flatland
would produce no gravitational effects beyond its own radius. In our
four-dimensional space-time the energy momentum tensor has 10 in-
dependent components, whereas the Riemann curvature tensor has 20
independent components. Thus it is possible to find solutions to the
vacuum field equations GJ,LV == 0 (where all components of the energy
momentum tensor are zero) that have a nonzero curvature. Black-hole
solutions and the gravitational-field solution external to a planet are ex-
amples. This allows gravitational waves and action at a distance. Flat-
land has a three-dimensional space-time where the energy momentum
tensor has six independent components and the Riemann curvature ten-
sor also has only six independent components. In the vacuum where all
components of the energy momentum tensor are zero all the compo-
nents of the Riemann curvature tensor must also be zero. No action at a
distance or gravity waves are allowed.
Electromagnetism in Flatland, on the other hand, behaves just as one
would expect. The electromagnetic field tensor in four-dimensional
space-time has six independent components that can be expressed as
vector E and B fields with three components each. The electromagnetic
field tensor in a three-dimensional space-time (Flatland) has three in-
dependent components: a vector E field with two components and a
scalar B field. Electromagnetic radiation exists, and charges have electric
fields that fall off like llr.
Two more letters, published in the same issue, follow. John S. Harris,
of Brigham Young University's English Department, wrote:
As I examined Alexander Keewatin Dewdney's planiversal devices in
Martin Gardner's article on science and technology in a two-dimensional
universe, I was struck with the similarity of the mechanisms to the lock-
work of the Mauser military pistol of 1895. This remarkable automatic
pistol (which had many later variants) had no pivot pins or screws in its
functional parts. Its entire operation was through sliding cam surfaces
and two-dimensional sockets (called hinges by Dewdney). Indeed, the
lockwork of a great many firearms, particularly those of the 19th century,
follows essentially planiversal principles. For examples see the cutaway
drawings in Book of Pistols and Revolvers by W.H.B. Smith.
Gardner suggests an exhibit of machines cut from cardboard, and that
The Wonders of a Planiverse 109
is exactly how the firearms genius John Browning worked. He would
sketch the parts of a gun on paper or cardboard, cut out the individual
parts with scissors (he often carried a small pair in his vest pocket), and
then would say to his brother Ed, "Make me a part like this." Ed would
ask, "How thick, John?" John would show a dimension with his thumb
and forefinger, and Ed would measure the distance with calipers and
make the part. The result is that virtually every part of the 100 or so
Browning designs is essentially a two-dimensional shape with an added
thickness.
This planiversality of Browning designs is the reason for the obsoles-
cence of most of them. Dewdney says in his enthusiasm for the plani-
verse that "such devices are invariably space-saving." They are also
expensive to manufacture. The Browning designs had to be manufac-
tured by profiling machines: cam-following vertical milling machines. In
cost of manufacture such designs cannot compete with designs that can
be produced by automatic screw-cutting lathes, by broaching machines,
by stamping, or by investment casting. Thus although the Browning de-
signs have a marvelous aesthetic appeal, and although they function
with delightful smoothness, they have nearly all gone out of produc-
tion. They simply got too expensive to make.
Stefan Drobot, a mathematician at Ohio State University, had this to
say:
In Martin Gardner's article he and the authors he quotes seem to have
overlooked the following aspect of a "planiverse": any communication
by means of a wave process, acoustic or electromagnetic, would in such
a universe be impossible. This is a consequence of the Huygens princi-
ple, which expresses a mathematical property of the (fundamental) so-
lutions of the wave equation. More specifically, a sharp impulse-type
signal (represented by a "delta function") originating from some point is
propagated in a space of three spatial dimensions in a manner essentially
different from that in which it is propagated in a space of two spatial di-
mensions. In three-dimensional space the signal is propagated as a
sharp-edged spherical wave without any trail. This property makes it
possible to communicate by a wave process because two signals follow-
ing each other in a short time can be distinguished.
In a space with two spatial dimensions, on the other hand, the funda-
mental solution of the wave equation represents a wave that, although it
too has a sharp edge, has a trail of theoretically infinite length. An ob-
server at a fixed distance from the source of the signal would perceive the
oncoming front (sound, light, etc.) and then would keep perceiving it, al-
110 PLANE GEOMETRY
though the intensity would decrease in time. This fact would make com-
munication by any wave process impossible because it would not allow
two signals following each other to be distinguished. More practically
such communication would take much more time. This letter could not
be read in the planiverse, although it is (almost) two-dimensional.
My linear checkers and chess prompted many interesting letters. Abe
Schwartz assured me that on the ll-cell checker field Black also wins if
the game is give-away. I. Richard Lapidus suggested modifying linear
chess by interchanging knight and rook (the game is a draw), by adding
more cells, by adding pawns that capture by moving forward one space,
or by combinations of the three modifications. If the board is long
enough, he suggested duplicating the pieces-two knights, two rooks-
and adding several pawns, allowing a pawn a two-cell start option as in
standard chess. Peter Stampolis proposed sustituting for the knight two
pieces called "kops" because they combine features of knight and bishop
moves. One kop moves only on white cells, the other moves on black.
Of course many other board games lend themselves to linear forms,
for example, Reversi (also called Othello), or John Conway's Phutball,
described in the two-volume Winning Ways written by Elwyn
Berlekamp, Richard Guy, and John Conway.
Burr puzzles are wooden take-apart puzzles often referred to as Chi-
nese puzzles. Dewdney's Scientific American column (October 1985)
describes a clever planar version of a burr puzzle designed by Jeffrey
Carter. It comes apart only after a proper sequence of pushes and pulls.
A graduate student in physics, whose name I failed to record, had a
letter in Science News, December 8,1984, protesting the notion that re-
search in planar physics was important because it led to better under-
standing of three-dimensional physics. On the contrary, he wrote,
planar research is of great interest for its own sake. He cited the quan-
tum Hall effect and the whole field of microelectronics which is based
on two-dimensional research and has many technological applications.
Answers
In ll-celllinear checkers (beginning with Black on cells 1,2,3,
and 4 and White on cells 8, 9, 10, and 11) the first two moves are forced:
Black to 5 and White to 7. To avoid losing, Black then goes to 4, and
White must respond by moving to 8. Black is then forced to 3 and
The Wonders of a Planiverse 111
White to 9. At this point Black loses with a move to 2 but wins with a
move to 6. In the latter case White jumps to 5, and then Black jumps to
6 for an easy end -game victory.
On the eight-cell linear chessboard White can win in at most six
moves. Of White's four opening moves, RxR is an instant stalemate and
the shortest possible game. R-5 is a quick loss for White if Black plays
RxR. Here White must respond with N-4, and then Black mates on his
second move with RxN. This game is one of the two "fool's mates," or
shortest possible wins. The R-4 opening allows Black to mate on his
second or third move if he responds with N-5.
White's only winning opening is N-4. Here Black has three possible
replies:
1. RxN. In this case White wins in two moves with RxR.
2. R-5. White wins with K-2. If Black plays R-6, White mates with NxR.
If Black takes the knight, White takes the rook, Black moves N-5, and
White mates by taking Black's knight.
3. N-5. This move delays Black's defeat the longest. In order to win
White must check with NxR, forcing Black's king to 7. White moves
his rook to 4. If Black plays KxN, White's king goes to 2, Black's K-7
is forced, and White's RxN wins. If Black plays N-3 (check), White
moves the king to 2. Black can move only the knight. If he plays N-
1, White mates with N-8. If Black plays N-5, White's N-8 forces
Black's KxN, and then White mates with RxN.
The first player also has the win in eight-cell pinch (linear go) by
opening on the second cell from an end, a move that also wins the six-
and seven-cell games. Assume that the first player plays on cell 2. His
unique winning responses to his opponent's plays on 3,4,5,6,7, and
8 are respectively 5,7,7,7,5, and 6. I leave the rest of the game to the
reader. It is not known whether there are other winning opening moves.
James Henle, the inventor of pinch, assures me that the second player
wins the nine-cell game. He has not tried to analyze boards with more
than nine cells.
Bibliography
D. Burger, Sphereland: A Fantasy about Curved Spaces and an Expanding Uni-
verse, T. Y. Crowell, 1965.
112 PLANE GEOMETRY
A. K. Dewdney, The Planiverse, Poseidon, 1984; Copernicus, 2000.
A. K. Dewdney, 200 Percent of Nothing: An Eye Opening Tour Through the Twists
and Turns of Math Abuse and Innumeracy, Wiley, 1994.
A. K. Dewdney, Introductory Computer Science: Bits of Theory, Bytes of Practice,
W. H. Freeman, 1996.
A. K. Dewdney, "The Planiverse Project: Then and Now," Mathematical Intelli-
gencer, Vol. 22, No.1, 2000, pp. 46-48.
C. H. Hinton, An Episode of Flatland, Swan Sonnenschein & Co., 1907.
R. Jackiw, "Lower Dimensional Gravity," Nuclear Physics, Vol. B252, 1985, pp.
343-56.
I. Peterson, "Shadows From a Higher Dimension," Science News, Vol. 126, No-
vember 3,1984, pp. 284-85.
A. Square and E. A. Abbott, Flatland: A Romance of Many Dimensions, Dover Pub-
lications, Inc., 1952. Several other paperback editions are currently in print.
I. Stewart, Flatterland, Perseus Publishing, 2001.
P. J. Stewart, "Allegory Through the Computer Class: Sufism in Dewdney's Plani-
verse," Sufi, Issue 9, Spring 1991, pp. 26-30.
The Wonders of a Planiverse 113
lilili
Solid Qeometry
and Higher
Dimensions
Chapter 9
Rosy's instant acceptance of our model at
first amazed me. I had feared that her sharp,
stubborn mind, caught in her self-made an-
tihelical trap, might dig up irrelevant results
that would foster uncertainty about the cor-
rectness of the double helix. Nonetheless,
like almost everyone else, she saw the ap-
peal of the base pairs and accepted the fact
that the structure was too pretty not to be
true. -James D. Watson, The Double Helix
The Helix
A straight sword will fit snugly into a straight scabbard. The
same is true of a sword that curves in the arc of a circle: it can be
plunged smoothly into a scabbard of the same curvature. Mathemati-
cians sometimes describe this property of straight lines and circles by
calling them "self-congruent" curves; any segment of such a curve can
be slid along the curve, from one end to the other, and it will always
"fit. "
Is it possible to design a sword and its scabbard that are not either
straight or curved in a circular arc? Most people, after giving this care-
ful consideration, will answer no, but they are wrong. There is a third
curve that is self-congruent: the circular helix. This is a curve that coils
around a circular cylinder in such a way that it crosses the "elements"
of the cylinder at a constant angle. Figure 9.1 makes this clear. The el-
ements are the vertical lines that parallel the cylinder's axis; A is the
constant angle with which the helix crosses every element. Because of
the constant curvature of the helix a helical sword would screw its
way easily in and out of a helical scabbard.
Actually the straight line and the circle can be regarded as limiting
cases of the circular helix. Compress the curve until the coils are very
close together and you get a tightly wound helix resembling a Slinky
toy; if angle A increases to 90 degrees, the helix collapses into a circle.
On the other hand, if you stretch the helix until angle A becomes zero,
the helix is transformed into a straight line. If parallel rays of light
shine perpendicularly on a wall, a circular helix held before the wall
with its axis parallel to the rays will cast on the wall a shadow that is
117
9.1. .... ...... ''-'''''''''L.LL on
118 AND
ral around cones), including bedsprings and spiral ramps such as the
inverted conical ramp in Frank Lloyd Wright's Guggenheim Museum in
New York City.
Not so in nature! Helical structures abound in living forms, from the
simplest virus to parts of the human body, and in almost every case the
genetic code carries information that tells each helix precisely "which
way to go." The genetic code itself is carried by a double-stranded he-
lical molecule of DNA, its two right-handed helices twining around
each other like the two snakes on the staff of Hermes. Moreover, since
Linus Pauling's pioneer work on the helical structure of protein mole-
cules, there has been increasing evidence that every giant protein mol-
ecule found in nature has a "backbone" that coils in a right-handed
helix. In both nucleic acid and protein, the molecule's backbone is a
chain made up of units each one of which is an asymmetric structure
of the same handedness. Each unit, so to speak, gives an additional
twist to the chain, in the same direction, like the steps of a helical stair-
case.
Larger helical structures in animals that have bilateral symmetry usu-
ally come in mirror-image pairs, one on each side of the body. The
horns of rams, goats, antelopes, and other mammals are spectacular
examples (see Figure 9.2). The cochlea of the human ear is a conical
helix that is left-handed in the left ear and right-handed in the right. A
curious exception is the tooth of the narwhal, a small whale that flour-
ishes in arctic waters. This whimsical creature is born with two teeth
in its upper jaw. Both teeth remain permanently buried in the jaw of the
female narwhal, and so does the right tooth of the male. But the male's
left tooth grows straight forward, like a javelin, to the ridiculous length
of eight or nine feet-more than half the animal's length from snout to
tail! Around this giant tooth are helical grooves that spiral forward in
a counterclockwise direction (see Figure 9.3). On the rare occasions
when both teeth grow into tusks, one would expect the right tooth to
spiral clockwise. But no, it too is always left-handed. Zoologists dis-
agree on how this could come about. Sir D' Arcy Thompson, in his book
On Growth and Form, defends his own theory that the whale swims
with a slight screw motion to the right. The inertia of its huge tusk
would produce a torque at the base of the tooth that might cause it to
rotate counterclockwise as it grows (see J. T. Bonner, "The Horn of the
Unicorn," Scientific American, March 1951).
Whenever a single helix is prominent in the structure of any living
The Helix 119
Figure 9.2. Helical horns of the Pamir sheep have opposite handedness.
Figure 9.3. Helical grooves of the narwhal tooth are always left-handed.
plant or animal, the species usually confines itself to a helix of a spe-
cific handedness. This is true of countless forms of helical bacteria as
well as of the spermatozoa of all higher animals. The human umbilical
cord is a triple helix of one vein and two arteries that invariably coil to
the left. The most striking instances are provided by the conical helices
of the shells of snails and other mollusks. Not all spiral shells have a
handedness. The chambered nautilus, for instance, coils on one plane;
like a spiral nebula, it can be sliced into identical left and right halves.
But there are thousands of beautiful molluscan shells that are either
left- or right-handed (see Figure 9.4). Some species are always left-
handed and some are always right-handed. Some go one way in one lo-
cality and the other way in another. Occasional "sports" that twist the
wrong way are prized by shell collectors.
A puzzling type of helical fossil known as the devil's corkscrew (Dae-
monelix) is found in Nebraska and Wyoming. These huge spirals, six
feet or more in length, are sometimes right-handed and sometimes left-
handed. Geologists argued for decades over whether they are fossils of
extinct plants or helical burrows made by ancestors of the beaver. The
beaver theory finally prevailed after remains of small prehistoric
beavers were found inside some of the corkscrews.
In the plant world helices are common in the structure of stalks,
stems, tendrils, seeds, flowers, cones, leaves-even in the spiral
arrangement of leaves and branches around a stalk. The number of
120 SOLID GEOMETRY AND HIGHER DIMENSIONS
Figure 9.4. Three molluscan shells that are right-handed conical helices
turns made along a helical path, as you move from one leaf to the leaf
directly above it, tends to be a number in the familiar Fibonacci series:
1, 2, 3, 5, 8, 13, ... (Each number is the sum of the preceding two num-
bers.) A large literature in the field known as "phyllotaxy" (leaf arrange-
ment) deals with the surprising appearance of the Fibonacci numbers
in botanical phenomena of this sort.
The helical stalks of climbing plants are usually right-handed, but
thousands of species of twining plants go the other way. The honey-
suckle, for instance, is always left-handed; the bindweed (a family that
includes the morning glory) is always right-handed. When the two
plants tangle with each other, the result is a passionate, violent embrace
that has long fascinated English poets. "The blue bindweed," wrote
Ben Jonson in 1617, "doth itself enfold with honeysuckle." And Shake-
speare, in A Midsummer Night's Dream, has Queen Titania speak of her
intention to embrace Bottom the Weaver (who has been transformed
into a donkey) by saying: "Sleep thou, and I will wind thee in my
arms'! ... So doth the woodbine the sweet honeysuckle/Gently en-
twist." In Shakespeare's day "woodbine" was a common term for
bindweed. Because it later carne to be applied exclusively to honey-
suckle many commentators reduced the passage to absurdity by su p-
posing that Titania was speaking of honeysuckle twined with
honeysuckle. Awareness of the opposite handedness of bindweed and
honeysuckle heightens, of course, the meaning of Titania's metaphor.
The Helix 121
More recently, a charming sQng called "Misalliance," celebrating the
love of the honeysuckle for the bindweed, has been written by the
British poet and entertainer Michael Flanders and set to music by his
friend Donald Swann. With Flanders' kind permission the entire song
is reproduced on the opposite page. (Readers who would like to learn
the tune can hear it sung by Flanders and Swann on the Angel record-
ing of At the Drop of a Hat, their hilarious two-man revue that made
such a hit in London and New York.) Note that Flanders' honeysuckle
is right-handed and his bindweed, left-handed. It is a matter of con-
vention whether a given helix is called left- or right-handed. If you
look at the point of a right-handed wood screw, you will see the helix
moving toward you counterclockwise, so that it can just as legitimately
be called left-handed. Flanders simply adopts the convention oppo-
site to the one taken here.
The entwining of two circular helices of opposite handedness is also
involved in a remarkable optical-illusion toy that was sold in this coun-
try in the 1930s. It is easily made by twisting together a portion of two
wire coils of opposite handedness (see Figure 9.6). The wires must be
soldered to each other at several points to make a rigid structure. The
illusion is produced by pinching the wire between thumb and forefin-
ger of each hand at the left and right edges of the central overlap. When
the hands are moved apart, the fingers and thumbs slide along the wire,
causing it to rotate and create a barber's-pole illusion of opposite hand-
edness on each side. This is continuously repeated. The wire seems to
be coming miraculously out of the inexhaustible meshed portion. Since
the neutrino and antineutrino are now known to travel with screw mo-
tions of opposite handedness, I like to think of this toy as demonstrat-
ing. the endless production of neutrinos and their mirror-image
particles.
On the science toy market at the time I write (2000) is a device called
"Spinfinity." It consists of two aluminum wire helices that are inter-
twined. When rotated you see the two helices moving in opposite di-
rections.
The helical character of the neutrino's path results from the fusion of
its forward motion (at the speed of light) with its "spin." Helical paths
of a similar sort are traced by many inanimate objects and living things:
a point on the propeller of a moving ship or plane, a squirrel running
up or down a tree, Mexican free-tailed bats gyrating counterclockwise
when they emerge from caves at Carlsbad, NM. Conically helical paths
122 SOLID GEOMETRY AND HIGHER DIMENSIONS
Figure 9.S.
MISALLIANCE
The fragrant Honeysuckle spirals clockwise to the sun
And many other creepers do the same.
But some climb counterclockwise, the Bindweed does, for one,
Or Convolvulus, to give her proper name.
Rooted on either side a door, one of each species grew,
And raced toward the window ledge above.
Each corkscrewed to the lintel in the only way it knew,
Where they stopped, touched tendrils, smiled and fell in love.
Said the right-handed Honeysuckle
To the left-handed Bindweed:
"Oh, let us get married,
If our parents don't mind. We'd
Be loving and inseparable.
Inextricably entwined, we'd
Live happily ever after, JJ
Said the Honeysuckle to the Bindweed.
To the Honeysuckle's parents it came as a shock.
"The Bindweeds," they cried, "are inferior stock.
They're uncultivated, of breeding bereft.
We twine to the right and they twine to the left!"
Said the countercockwise Bindweed
To the clockwise Honeysuckle:
"We'd better start saving-
Many a mickle maks a muckle-
Then run away for a honeymoon
And hope that our luck'll
Take a turn for the better, JJ
Said the Bindweed to the Honeysuckle.
A bee who was passing remarked to them then:
"I've said it before, and I'll say it again:
Consider your offshoots, if offshoots there be.
They'll never receive any blessing from me."
Poor little sucker, how will it learn
When it is climbing, which way to turn?
Right-left-what a disgrace!
Or it may go straight up and fall flat on its face!
Said the right-hand-thread Honeysuckle
To the left-hand-thread Bindweed:
"It seems that against us all fate has combined.
Oh my darling, oh my darling,
Oh my darling Columbine
Thou art lost and gone forever,
We shall never intertwine. JJ
Together they found them the very next day
They had pulled up their roots and just shriveled away,
Deprived of that freedom for which we must fight,
To veer to the left or to veer to the right!
MICHAEL FLANDERS
Figure 9.6. Helical toy that suggests the production of neutrinos
are taken by whirlpools, water going down a drain, tornadoes, and
thousands of other natural phenomena.
Writers have found helical motions useful on the metaphorical level.
The progress of science is often likened to an inverted conical spiral:
the circles growing larger and larger as science probes further into the
unknown, always building upward on the circles of the past. The same
spiral, a dark, bottomless whirlpool into which an individual or hu-
manity is sliding, has also been used as a symbol of pessimism and de-
spair. This is the metaphor that closes Norman Mailer's book
Advertisements for Myself. "Am I already on the way out?" he asks.
Time for Mailer is a conical helix of water flushing down a cosmic
drain, spinning him off "into the spiral of star-lit empty waters."
And now for a simple helix puzzle. A rotating barber's pole consists
of a cylinder on which red, white, and blue helices are painted. The
cylinder is four feet high. The red stripe cuts the cylinder's elements
(vertical lines) with a constant angle of 60 degrees. How long is the red
stripe?
The problem may seem to lack sufficient information for determin-
ing the stripe's length; actually it is absurdly easy when approached
properly.
Addendum
In my Second Scientific American Book of Mathematical Puz-
zles and Diversions (1961) I introduced the following brainteaser in-
volving two helices of the same handedness:
THE TWIDDLED BOLTS
Two icl,entical bolts are placed together so that their helical grooves in-
termesh (Figure 9.7). If you move the bolts around each other as you
would twiddle your thumbs, holding each bolt firmly by the head so that
it does not rotate and twiddling them in the direction shown, will the
heads (a) move inward, (b) move outward, or (c) remain the same dis-
tance from each other? The problem should be solved without resorting
to actual test.
124 SOLID GEOMETRY AND HIGHER DIMENSIONS
Figure 9.7. Twiddled bolts
Two similar helices are also involved in a curious patent by someone
named Socrates Scholfield of Providence, RI. I cannot now recall how
I came across it. A picture of the device, from the patent's first page, is
shown in Figure 9.B. It is to be used in classrooms for demonstrating the
nature of God. One helix represents good; the other, evil. As you can
see, they are holessly intertwined. The use of the device is given in de-
tail in five pages of the patent.
I know nothing about Mr. Scholfield except that in 1907 he pub-
lished a 59-page booklet titled The Doctrine of Mechanicalism. I tried
to check it in the New York Public Library many years ago, but the li-
brary has lost its copy. I once showed Scholfield's patent to the philoso-
pher Charles Hartshorne, one of my teachers at the University of
Chicago. I expected him to find the device amusing. To my surprise,
Hartshorne solemnly read the patent's pages and pronounced them ad-
mirable.
The Slinky toy furnishes an interesting problem in physics. If you
stand on a chair, holding one end of Slinky so that the helix hangs
straight down, then drop the toy, what happens? Believe it or not, the
lower end of Slinky doesn't move until the helix has come together,
then it falls with the expected rate. Throughout the experiment the
toy's center of gravity descends with the usual acceleration.
Jlnswers
If a right triangle is wrapped around any type of cylinder, the
base of the triangle going around the base of the cylinder, the triangle's
hypotenuse will trace a helix on the cylinder. Think of the red stripe of
the barber's pole as the hypotenuse of a right triangle, then "unwrap"
the triangle froIfL the cylinder. The triangle will have angles of 30 and
60 degrees. The hypotenuse of such a triangle must be twice the alti-
The Helix 125
1,087,186.
Ffs.2.
WITNESSES.
Figure 9.S.
126
S. SOHOLFIELD.
ILLUSTRATIVE EDUOATIONAL DEVIOE.
!l'I'LIOATIOH rlUD JUl. II, nOB.
Patented Feb. 17,1914.
fiG .1.
FiG.4.
FiG.5.
INVENTOR.
SOLID GEOMETRY AND HIGHER DIMENSIONS
tude. (This is easily seen if you place two such triangles together to
form an equilateral triangle.) In this case the altitude is four feet, so that
the hypotenuse (red stripe) is eight feet.
The interesting part of this problem is that the length of the stripe is
independent not only of the diameter of the cylinder but also of the
shape of its cross section. The cross section can be an irregular closed
curve of any shape whatever; the answer to the problem remains the
same.
The twiddled bolts move neither inward nor outward. They behave
like someone walking up a down escalator, always staying in the same
place.
Bibliography
T. A. Cook, The Curves of Life, New York: Henry Holt, 1914; Dover, 1979.
H.S.M. Coxeter, Introduction to Geometry, New York: John Wiley and Sons, 1961;
Second edition, 1989.
F. E. Graves, "Nuts and Bolts," Scientific American, June 1984, pp. 136-44.
J. B. Pettigrew, Design in Nature, Vol. II, London: Longmans, Green, and Co., 1908.
J. D. Watson, The Double Helix, New York: Atheneum, 1968; Norton, 1980.
The Helix 127
Chapter 10 Packing Spheres
Spheres of identical size can be piled and packed together in
many different ways, some of which have fascinating recreational fea-
tures. These features can be understood without models, but if the
reader can obtain a supply of 30 or more spheres, he will find them an
excellent aid to understanding. Ping-pong balls are perhaps the best for
this purpose. They can be coated with rubber cement, allowed to dry,
then stuck together to make rigid models.
First let us make a brief two-dimensional foray. If we arrange spheres
in square formation (see Figure 10.1, right), the number of balls in-
volved will of course be a square number. If we form a triangle (see Fig-
ure 10.1, left), the number of balls is a triangular number. These are the
simplest examples of what the ancients called "figurate numbers."
They were intensively studied by early mathematicians (a famous trea-
tise on them was written by Blaise Pascal), and although little attention
is paid them today, they still provide intuitive insights into many as-
pects of elementary number theory.
2
3
4
5
15
25
Figure 10.1. The basis of triangular numbers (left) and of square numbers (right)
128
For example, it takes only a glance at Figure 10.1, left, to see that the
sum of any number of consecutive positive integers, beginning with 1,
is a triangular number. A glance at Figure 10.1, right, shows that square
numbers are formed by the addition of consecutive odd integers, be-
ginning with 1. Figure 10.2 makes immediately evident an interesting
theorem known to the ancient pythagoreans: Every square number is
the sum of two consecutive triangular numbers. The algebraic proof is
simple. A triangular number with n units to a side is the sum of 1 + 2
+ 3 + ... n, and can be expressed by the formula ~ n ( n + 1). The pre-
ceding triangular number has the formula n (n - 1). If we add the two
formulas and simplify, the result is n
2
Are there numbers that are si-
multaneously square and triangular? Yes, there are infinitely many of
them. The smallest (not counting 1, which belongs to any figurate se-
ries) is 36; then the series continues: 1225,41616, 1413721,48024900,
.... It is not so easy to devise a formula for the nth term of this series.
~ 2 1
~ 2 8
49
F'lgUre 10.2. Square and triangular numbers are related.
Three-dimensional analogies of the plane-figurate numbers are ob-
tained by piling spheres in pyramids. Three-sided pyramids, the base
and sides of which are equilateral triangles, are models of what are
called the tetrahedral numbers. They form the series 1,4, 10, 20, 35, 56,
84, ... and can be represented by the formula !n(n + l)(n + 2), where n
is the number of balls along an edge. Four-sided pyramids, with square
bases and equilateral triangles for sides (Le., half of a regular octahe-
dron), represent the (square) pyramidal numbers 1, 5, 14, 30, 55, 91,
140, .... They have the formula !n(n + 1)(2n + 1). Just as a square can
be divided by a straight line into two consecutive triangles, so can a
Packing Spheres 129
PYTamids. (If you
has to be kept
or
Many
into two consecutive tetrahedral
a of a PYTamidal numberp the bottom
rolling apart. This can by ..., ...................... L"""
wood u..J.u .... .A.JOi.
t-'Tn,O' of pyra-
answer are ................. ,..., ...
................. " ~ , ............ now that we have a very large box
t
say a crate for a piano,
we wish to with as many golf as we can.
we a OJ" ................... "-''--'- as
circumferences Figure 10.3. The
10.3. In ne:x:agolnal ClOS8-1::lacking,
lows labeled B.
130
go in .. U..l .......... ", in in
AND
1. We place each ball on a hollow A that is directly above a ball in the
first layer. If we continue in this way, placing the balls of each layer
directly over those in the next layer but one, we produce a structure
called hexagonal close-packing.
2. We place each ball in a hollow B, directly above a hollow in the first
layer. If we follow this procedure for each layer (each ball will be di-
rectly above a ball in the third layer beneath it), the result is known
as cubic close-packing. Both the square and the tetrahedral pyramids
have a packing structure of this type, though on a square pyramid the
layers run parallel to the sides rather than to the base.
In forming the layers of a close-packing we can switch back and forth
whenever we please from hexagonal to cubic packing to produce vari-
ous hybrid forms of close-packing. In all these forms-cubic, hexago-
nal, and hybrid-each ball touches 12 other balls that surround it, and
the density of the packing (the ratio of the volume of the spheres to the
total space) is 1t/\118 = .74048 +, or almost 75 percent.
Is this the largest density obtainable? No denser packing is known,
but in an article published in 1958 (on the relation of close-packing to
froth) H.S.M. Coxeter of the University of Toronto made the startling
suggestion that perhaps the densest packing has not yet been found. It
is true that no more than 12 balls can be placed so that all of them
touch a central sphere, but a thirteenth ball can almost be added. The
large leeway here in the spacing ofthe 12 balls, in contrast to the com-
plete absence of leeway in the close-packing of circles on a plane, sug-
gests that there might be some form of irregular packing that would be
denser than .74. No one has yet proved that no denser packing is pos-
sible, or even that 12 point-contacts for each sphere are necessary for
densest packing. As a result of Coxeter's conjecture, George D. Scott of
the University of Toronto made some experiments in random packing
by pouring large numbers of steel balls into spherical flasks, then
weighing them to obtain the density. He found that stable random-
packings had a density that varied from about .59 to .63. So if there is
a packing denser than. 74, it will have to be carefully constructed on a
pattern that no one has yet thought of.
Assuming that close-packing is the closest packing, readers may like
to test their packing prowess on this exceedingly tricky little problem.
The interior of a rectangular box is 10 inches on each side and 5 inches
Packing Spheres 131
deep. What is the largest number of steel spheres 1 inch in diameter
that can be packed in this space?
If close-packed circles on a plane expand uniformly until they fill the
interstices between them, the result is the familiar hexagonal tiling of
bathroom floors. (This explains why the pattern is so common in na-
ture: the honeycomb of bees, a froth of bubbles between two flat sur-
faces almost in contact, pigments in the retina, the surface of certain
diatoms and so on.) What happens when closely packed spheres ex-
pand uniformly in a closed vessel or are subjected to uniform pressure
from without? Each sphere becomes a polyhedron, its faces corre-
sponding to planes that were tangent to its points of contact with other
spheres. Cubic close-packing transforms each sphere into a rhombic do-
decahedron (see Figure 10.4, top), the 12 sides of which are congruent
rhombi. Hexagonal close-packing turns each ball into a trapezo-
rhombic dodecahedron (see Figure 10.4, bottom), six faces of which are
rhombic and six, trapezoidal. If this figure is sliced in half along the
gray plane and one half is rotated 60 degrees, it becomes a rhombic do-
decahedron.
In 1727 the English physiologist Stephen Hales wrote in his book
Vegetable Staticks that he had poured some fresh peas into a pot, com-
pressed them, and had obtained "pretty regular dodecahedrons." The
experiment became known as the "peas of Buff on" (because the Comte
de Buffon later wrote about a similar experiment), and most biologists
accepted it without question until Edwin B. Matzke, a botanist at Co-
lumbia University, repeated the experiment. Because of the irregular
sizes and shapes of peas, their nonuniform consistency and the random
packing that results when peas are poured into a container, the shapes
of the peas after compression are too random to be identifiable. In ex-
periments reported in 1939 Matzke compressed lead shot and found
that if the spheres had been cubic close-packed, rhombic dodecahe-
drons were formed; but if they had been randomly packed, irregular 14-
faced bodies predominated. These results have important bearing,
Matzke has pointed out, on the study of such structures as foam and liv-
ing cells in undifferentiated tissues.
The problem of closest packing suggests the opposite question: What
is the loosest packing; that is, what rigid structure will have the lowest
possible density? For the structure to be rigid, each sphere must touch
at least four others, and the contact points must not be all in one hemi-
sphere or all on one equator of the sphere. In his Geometry and the
132 SOLID GEOMETRY AND HIGHER DIMENSIONS
133
- 2
AND
10.6 (top) is a "look-see"
four circles packed centers on a square lattice equal
area of area a Figure 10.6 (bottom) is a
between on a .................... ,...
tice is equal the area of the triangle minus half the
10.6. Two look-see proofs
................................ a 150-page '4proor' of Kepler's conjecture. It was widely hailed
as valid, but soon were finding
them, consensus
false and beyond
In 1998 Thomas Hales, at the University of Michigan and one of
Hsiang's harshest proof
cause it
on lengthy computer calculations, the verdict is still
whether Kepler's conjecture been verified.
Incidently,
more
pacldng of any identical convex solids.
The smallest number of oranges that will form two tetrahedral
pyramids of one ~ ..... ~
1
680. This is a tetrahedral number that can be split into two smaller
tetrahedral numbers: 120 and 560. The edges of the three pyramids are
8, 14, and 15.
A box 10 inches square and 5 inches deep can be close-packed with
1 inch-diameter steel balls in a surprising variety of ways, each ac-
commodating a different number of balls. The maximum number, 594,
is obtained as follows: Turn the box on its side and form the first layer
by making a row of five, then a row of four, then of five, and so on. It
is possible to make 11 rows (6 rows of five each, 5 rows of four each),
accommodating 50 balls and leaving a space of more than .3 inch to
spare. The second layer also will take 11 rows, alternating four and
five balls to a row, but this time the layer begins and ends with four-ball
rows, so that the number of balls in the layer is only 49. (The last row
of four balls will project .28+ inch beyond the edge of the first layer, but
because this is less than .3 inch, there is space for it.) Twelve layers
(with a total height of 9.98+ inches) can be placed in the box, alternat-
ing layers of 50 balls with layers of 49, to make a grand total of 594
balls.
Bibliography
Kepler's Conjecture
B. Cipra, "Gaps in a Sphere Packing Proof," Science, Vol. 259, 1993, p. 895.
T. C. Hales, "The Status of the Kepler Conjecture," Mathematical Intelligencer, Vol.
16, No. 3, 1994,pp.47-58.
T. C. Hales, "Cannonballs and Honeycombs," Notices of the American Mathemat-
ical Society, Vol. 47, April 2000, pp. 440-49.
J. Horgan, "Mathematicians Collide Over a Claim About Packing Spheres," Scien-
tific American, December 1994, pp. 32-34.
D. Mackenzie, "The Proof is in the Packing," American Scientist, VoL 86, Novem-
ber/December, 1998, pp. 524-25.
S. Singh, "Mathematics 'Proves' What the Grocer Always Knew," The New York
Times, August 25, 1998, p. F3.
1. Stewart, "Has the Sphere Packing Problem Been Solved?" New Scientist, Vol. 134,
May 2,1992, p. 16.
H. Wu, "On the Sphere Packing Problem and the Proof of Kepler's Conjecture," In-
ternational Journal of Mathematics, Vol. 4, No.5, 1998, pp. 739-831.
H. Wu, "A Rejoinder to Hales's Article," Mathematical Intelligencer, Vol. 17, No.1,
1995, pp. 35-42.
136 SOLID GEOMETRY AND HIGHER DIMENSIONS
Chapter II Spheres and
Hyperspheres
A circle is the locus of all points on the plane at a given dis-
tance from a fixed point on the plane. Let's extend this to Euclidean
spaces of all dimensions and call the general n-sphere the locus of all
points in n-space at a given distance from a fixed point in n-space. In
a space of one dimension (a line) the i-sphere consists of two points at
a given distance on each side of a center point. The 2-sphere is the cir-
cle, the 3-sphere is what is commonly called a sphere. Beyond that are
the hyperspheres of 4, 5, 6, ... dimensions.
Imagine a rod of unit length with one end attached to a fixed point.
If the rod is allowed to rotate only on a plane, its free end will trace a
unit circle. If the rod is allowed to rotate in 3-space, the free end traces
a unit sphere. Assume now that space has a fourth coordinate, at right
angles to the other three, and that the rod is allowed to rotate in 4-
space. The free end then generates a unit 4-sphere. Hyperspheres are
impossible to visualize; nevertheless, their properties can be studied by
a simple extension of analytic geometry to more than three coordinates.
A circle's Cartesian formula is a
2
+ b
2
= r, where r is the radius. The
sphere's formula is a
2
+ b
2
+ c
2
= r. The 4-sphere's formula is a
2
+ b
2
+
c
2
+ cP = r, and so on up the ladder of Euclidean hyperspaces.
The "surface" of an n-sphere has a dimensionality of n -1. A circle's
"surface" is a line of one dimension, a sphere's surface is two-
dimensional, and a 4-sphere's surface is three-dimensional. Is it possi-
ble that 3-space is actually the hypersurface of a vast 4-sphere? Could
such forces as gravity and electromagnetism be transmitted by the vi-
brations of such a hypersurface? Many late-19th-century mathemati-
cians and physicists, both eccentric and orthodox, took such
suggestions seriously. Einstein himself proposed the surface of a 4-
sphere as a model of the cosmos, unbounded and yet finite. Just as
137
Flatlanders on a sphere could travel the straightest possible line in any
direction and eventually return to their starting point, so (Einstein sug-
gested) if a spaceship left the earth and traveled far enough in anyone
direction, it would eventually return to the earth. If a Flatlander started
to paint the surface of the sphere on which he lived, extending the
paint outward in ever widening circles, he would reach a halfway point
at which the circles would begin to diminish, with himself on the in-
side, and eventually he would paint himself into a spot. Similarly, in
Einstein's cosmos, if terrestrial astronauts began to map the universe in
ever-expanding spheres, they would eventually map themselves into a
small globular space on the opposite side of the hypersphere.
Many other properties of hyperspheres are just what one would ex-
pect by analogy with lower-order spheres. A circle rotates around a
central point, a sphere rotates around a central line, a 4-sphere rotates
around a central plane. In general the axis of a rotating n-sphere is a
space of n - 2. (The 4-sphere is capable, however, of a peculiar double
rotation that has no analogue in 2- or 3-space: it can spin simultane-
ously around two fixed planes that are perpendicular to each other.)
The projection of a circle on a line is a line segment, but every point on
the segment, with the exception of its end points, corresponds to two
points on the circle. Project a sphere on a plane and you get a disk, with
every point inside the circumference corresponding to two points on
the sphere's surface. Project a 4-sphere on our 3-space and you get a
solid ball with every internal point corresponding to two points on the
4-sphere's hypersurface. This too generalizes up the ladder of spaces.
The same is true of cross sections. Cut a circle with a line and the
cross section is a l-sphere, or a pair of points. Slice a sphere with a
plane and the cross section is a circle. Slice a 4-sphere with a 3-space
hyperplane and the cross section is a 3-sphere. (You can't divide a 4-
sphere into two pieces with a 2-plane. A hyperapple, sliced down the
middle by a 2-plane, remains in one piece.) Imagine a 4-sphere moving
slowly through our space. We see it first as a point and then as a tiny
sphere that slowly grows in size to its maximum cross section, then
slowly diminishes and disappears.
A sphere of any dimension, made of sufficiently flexible material,
can be turned inside out through the next-highest space. Just as we can
twist a thin rubber ring until the outside rim becomes the inside, so a
hypercreature could seize one of our tennis balls and turn it inside out
through his space. He could do this all at once or he could start at one
138 SOLID GEOMETRY AND HIGHER DIMENSIONS
spot on the ball, turn a tiny portion first, then gradually enlarge it until
the entire ball had its inside outside.
One of the most elegant of the formulas that generalize easily to
spheres of all dimensions is the formula for the radii of the maximum
number of mutually touching n-spheres. On the plane, no more than
four circles can be placed so that each circle touches all the others,
with every pair touching at a different point. There are two possible sit-
uations (aside from degenerate cases in which one circle has an infinite
radius and so becomes a straight line): either three circles surround a
smaller one (Figure 11.1, left) or three circles are inside a larger one
(Figure 11.1, right). Frederick Soddy, the British chemist who received
a Nobel prize in 1921 for his discovery of isotopes, put it this way in
the first stanza of The Kiss Precise, a poem that appeared in Nature
(Vol. 137, June 20, 1936, p. 1021):
4
Figure 11.1. Find the radius of the fourth circle.
For pairs of lips to kiss maybe
Involves no trigonometry.
'Tis not so when four circles kiss
Each one the other three.
To bring this off the four must be
As three in one or one in three.
If one in three, beyond a doubt
Each gets three kisses from without.
If three in one, then is that one
Thrice kissed internally.
Spheres and Hyperspheres 139
Soddy's next stanza gives the simple formula. His term "bend" is
what is usually called the circle's curvature, the reciprocal of the ra-
dius. (Thus a circle of radius 4 has a curvature or "bend" of 1/4.) If a cir-
cle is touched on the inside, as it is in the case of the large circle
enclosing the other three, it is said to have a concave bend, the value
of which is preceded by a minus sign. As Soddy phrased all this:
Four circles to the kissing come.
The smaller are the benter.
The bend is just the inverse of
The distance from the center.
Though their intrigue left Euclid dumb
There's now no need for rule of thumb.
Since zero bend's a dead straight line
And concave bends have minus sign,
The sum of the squares of all four bends
Is half the square of their sum.
Letting a, b, c, d stand for the four reciprocals, Soddy's formula is
2(a
2
+ b
2
+ c
2
+ d
2
) = (a + b + c + dJ2. The reader should have little dif-
ficulty computing the radii of the fourth kissing circle in each illustra-
tion. In the poem's third and last stanza this formula is extended to five
mutually kissing spheres:
To spy out spherical affairs
An oscular surveyor
Might find the task laborious,
The sphere is much the gayer,
And now besides the pair of pairs
A fifth sphere in the kissing shares.
Yet, signs and zero as before,
For each to kiss the other four
The square of the sum of all five bends
Is thrice the sum of their squares.
The editors of Nature reported in the issue for January 9, 1937 (Vol.
139, p. 62), that they had received several fourth stanzas generalizing
Soddy's formula to n-space, but they published only the following, by
Thorold Gosset, an English barrister and amateur mathematician:
140
And let us not confine our cares
To simple circles, planes and spheres,
But rise to hyper flats and bends
SOLID GEOMETRY AND HIGHER DIMENSIONS
Where kissing multiple appears.
In n-ic space the kissing pairs
Are hyperspheres, and Truth declares-
As n + 2 such osculate
Each with an n + 1-fold mate.
The square of the sum of all the bends
Is n times the sum of their squares.
In simple prose, for n-space the maximum number of mutually
touching spheres is n + 2, and n times the sum of the squares of all
bends is equal to the square of the sum of all bends. It later developed
that the formula for four kissing circles had been known to Rene
Descartes, but Soddy rediscovered it and seems to have been the first
to extend it to spheres.
Note that the general formula even applies to the three mutually
touching two-point "spheres" of i-space: two touching line segments
"inside" a third segment that is simply the sum of the other two. The
formula is a great boon to recreational mathematicians. Puzzles about
mutually kissing circles or spheres yield readily to it. Here is a pretty
problem. Three mutually kissing spherical grapefruits, each with a ra-
dius of three inches, rest on a flat counter. A spherical orange is also on
the counter under the three grapefruits and touching each of them.
What is the radius of the orange?
Problems about the packing of unit spheres do not generalize easily
as one goes up the dimensional ladder; indeed, they become increas-
ingly difficult. Consider, for instance, the problem of determining the
largest number of unit spheres that can touch a unit sphere. For circles
the number is six (see Figure 11.2). For spheres it is 12, but this was not
proved until 1874. The difficulty lies in the fact that when 12 spheres
are arranged around a thirteenth, with their centers at the corners of an
imaginary icosahedron (see Figure 11.3), there is space between every
pair. The waste space is slightly more than needed to accommodate a
thirteenth sphere if only the 12 could be shifted around and properly
packed. If the reader will coat 14 ping-pong balls with rubber cement,
he will find it easy to stick 12 around one of them, and it will not be at
all clear whether or not the thirteenth can be added without undue
distortions. An equivalent question (can the reader see why?) is: Can 13
paper circles, each covering a 60-degree arc of a great circle on a sphere,
be pasted on that sphere without overlapping?
H.S.M. Coxeter, writing on "The Problem of Packing a Number of
Spheres and Hyperspheres 141
, 1.2.
a
a
142 AND
Equal Nonoverlapping Circles on a Sphere" (in Transactions of the
New York Academy of Sciences, Vol. 24, January 1962, pp. 320-31),
tells the story of what may be the first recorded discussion of the prob-
lem of the 13 spheres. David Gregory, an Oxford astronomer and friend
of Isaac Newton, recorded in his notebook in 1694 that he and Newton
had argued about just this question. They had been discussing how
stars of various magnitudes are distributed in the sky and this had led
to the question of whether or not one unit sphere could touch 13 oth-
ers. Gregory believed they could. Newton disagreed. As Coxeter writes,
"180 years were to elapse before R. Hoppe proved that Newton was
right." Simpler proofs have since been published, the latest in 1956 by
John Leech, a British mathematician.
How many unit hyperspheres in 4-space can touch a unit hyper-
sphere? It is not yet known if the answer is 24 or 25. Nor is it known
for any higher space. For spaces 4 through 8 the densest possible pack-
ings are known only if the centers of the spheres form a regular lattice.
These packings give 24, 40, 72, 126, and 240 for the "kissing number"
of spheres that touch another.
Why the difficulty with 9-space? A consideration of some paradoxes
involving hypercubes and hyperspheres may cast a bit of dim light on
the curious turns that take place in 9-space. Into a unit square one can
pack, from corner to diagonally opposite corner, a line with a length of
Vz. Into a unit cube one can similarly pack a line of vi The distance
between opposite corners of an n-cube is vIi, and since square roots in-
crease without limit, it follows that a rod of any size will pack into a
unit n-cube if n is large enough. A fishing pole 10 feet long will fit di-
agonally in the one-foot 100-cube. This also applies to objects of higher
dimension. A cube will accommodate a square larger than its square
face. A 4-cube will take a 3-cube larger than its cubical hyperface. A 5-
cube will take larger squares and cubes than any cube of lower dimen-
sion with an edge of the same length. An elephant or the entire Empire
State Building will pack easily into an n-cube with edges the same
length as those of a sugar cube if n is sufficiently large.
The situation with respect to an n-sphere is quite different. No mat-
ter how large n becomes, an n-sphere can never contain a rod longer
than twice its radius. And something very queer happens to its n-vol-
ume as n increases. The area of the unit circle is, of course, n. The vol-
ume of the unit sphere is 4.1+. The unit 4-sphere's hypervolume is
4.9+. In 5-space the volume is still larger, 5.2+, then in 6-space it de-
Spheres and Hyperspheres 143
creases to 5.1+, and thereafter steadily declines. Indeed, as n ap-
proaches infinity the hypervolume of a unit n-sphere approaches zero!
This leads to many unearthly results. David Singmaster, writing "On
Round Pegs in Square Holes and Square Pegs in Round Holes" (Math-
ematics Magazine, Vol. 37, November 1964, pp. 335-37), decided that
a round peg fits better in a square hole than vice versa because the ratio
of the area of a circle to a circumscribing square (re/4) is larger than the
ratio of a square inscribed in a circle (2/re). Similarly, one can show that
a ball fits better in a cube than a cube fits in a ball, although the differ-
ence between ratios is a bit smaller. Singmaster found that the differ-
ence continues to decrease through 8-space and then reverses: in
9-space the ratio of n-ball to n-cube is smaller than the ratio of n-cube
to n-ball. In other words, an n-ball fits better in an n-cube than an n-
cube fits in an n-ball if and only if n is 8 or less.
The same 9-space turn occurs in an unpublished paradox discov-
ered by Leo Moser. Four unit circles will pack into a square of side 4
(see Figure 11.4). In the center we can fit a smaller circle of radius Vz
- 1. Similarly, eight unit spheres will pack into the corners of a cube of
side 4 (see Figure 11.5). The largest sphere that will fit into the center
has a radius of v'3 - 1. This generalizes in the obvious way: In a 4-cube
of side 4 we can pack 16 unit 4-spheres and a central4-sphere of radius
V4 -1, which equals 1, so that the central sphere now is the same size
as the others. In general, in the corners of an n-cube of side 4 we can
pack 2
n
unit n-spheres and presumably another sphere of radius vIi -
1 will fit at the center. But see what happens when we come to 9-space:
the central hypersphere has a radius of y'g - 1 = 2, which is equal to
half the hypercube's edge. The central sphere cannot be larger than
this in any higher n-cube because it now fills the hypercube. No longer
is the central hypersphere inside the spheres that surround the center
of every hyperface, yet there is space at 2
9
= 512 corners to take 512 unit
9-spheres!
A related unpublished paradox, also discovered by Moser, concerns
n-dimensional chessboards. All the black squares of a chessboard are
enclosed with circumscribed circles (see Figure 11.6). Assume that
each cell is of side 2 and area 4. Each circle has a radius of Vz and an
area of 2re. The area in each white cell that is left white (is not enclosed
by a circle) is 8 - 2re = 1.71+. In the analogous situation for a cubical
chessboard, the black cubical cells of edge 2 are surrounded by spheres.
The volume of each black cell is 8 and the volume of each sphere,
144 SOLID GEOMETRY AND HIGHER DIMENSIONS
11.4. Four "" ..... " .... ..,.,. ........................ """ one of radius -1
".S.
one with a 1.
Spheres 145
11.6. Leo Moser's hVlper'chlessbo,ard problem
146 AND
such packing lattices are closely related to the construction of error-
correcting codes-efficient ways of transmitting information with a
minimum number of errors. The definitive treatise on the topic, by
John Horton Conway and N.J.A. Sloane (1988), runs 663 pages and has
a bibliography of 1,500 entries!
The densest packing of unit spheres, either lattice-based or irregu-
lar, is known only for the circle, regarded as a two-dimensional
"sphere." Densest lattice packings are known only for n-dimensional
spheres when n = 2 through 8. Beyond n 8 there are only conjectures
about such packings. In some cases irregular packings have been dis-
covered that are denser than lattice packings. The most famous of
higher space packings is a very dense lattice in 24 dimensions, known
as the Leech lattice after the British Mathematician John Leech who
discovered it. Each sphere in this remarkable structure touches
196,560 others!
Answers
The first problem was to determine the sizes of two circles,
each of which touches three mutually tangent circles with radii of one,
two, and three units. Using the formula given in the chapter,
2 1 + ~ + ~ + -
(
1 1 1 )
4 9 x
2 (
1 1 1)2
1+-+ + ~
2 3 x'
where x is the radius of the fourth circle, one obtains a value of 6/23 for
the radius of the smaller circle, 6 for the larger one.
The second problem concerned three grapefruits with three-inch
radii and an orange, all resting on a counter and mutually touching.
What size is the orange? The plane on which they rest is considered a
fifth sphere of infinite radius that touches the other four. Since it has
zero curvature it drops out of the formula relating the reciprocals of the
radii of five mutually touching spheres. Letting x be the radius of the
orange, we write the equation,
which gives x a value of one inch.
The problem can, of course, be solved in other ways. When it ap-
peared as problem 43 in the Pi Mu Epsilon Journal, November 1952,
Spheres and Hyperspheres 147
Leon Bankoff solved it this way, with R the radius of each large sphere
and r the radius of the small sphere:
"The small sphere, radius r, touches the table at a point equidistant
from the contacts of each of the large spheres with the table. Hence it
lies on the circumcenter of an equilateral triangle, the side of which is
2R. Then (R + r) is the hypotenuse of a right triangle, the altitude of
which is (R - r) and the base of which is 2Rv3/3. So
(R + r)2 = (R - r)2 + 4R2/3, or r = R/3."
The answer to Leo Moser's paradox of the hypercubic chessboard in
four-dimensional space is that no portion of a white cell remains un-
enclosed by the hyperspheres surrounding each black cell. The radius
of each hypersphere is \14, or 2. Since the hypercubic cells have edges
of length 2, we see at once that each of the eight hyperspheres around
a white cell will extend all the way to the center of that cell. The eight
hyperspheres intersect one another, leaving no portion of the white
cell unenclosed.
Bibliography
The Kiss Precise
W. S. Brown, "The Kiss Precise," American Mathematical Monthly, Vol. 76, June
1969, pp. 661-63.
D. Pedoe, "On a Theorem in Geometry," American Mathematical Monthly, Vol. 76,
June/July 1967, pp. 627----40.
Maximum Spheres that Touch a Sphere
H.S.M. Coxeter, "An Upper Bound for the Number of Equal Nonoverlapping
Spheres That Can Touch Another of the Same Size," Proceedings of Symposia
in Pure Mathematics, Vol. 7, 1963, pp. 53-71.
J. Leech, "The Problem of the Thirteen Spheres," The Mathematical Gazette, VoL
240, February 1956, pp. 22-23.
A. M. Odlyzko and N.J.A. Sloane, "New Bounds on the Number of Unit Spheres
That Can Touch a Unit Sphere in n Dimensions," Journal of Combinatorial The-
DIY, Ser. A, Vol. 26, March 1979, pp. 210-14.
J. C. Prepp, "Kepler's Spheres and Rubik's Cube," Mathematics Magazine, Vol. 61,
October 1988, pp. 231-39.
I. Stewart, "The Kissing Number," Scientific American, February 1992, pp. 112-15.
A. J. Wasserman, "The Thirteen Spheres Problem," Eureka, Spring 1978, pp. 4649.
148 SOLID GEOMETRY AND HIGHER DIMENSIONS
N-space Packing
J. H. Conway and N.J.A. Sloane, Leech Lattice, Sphere Packings, and Related Top-
ics, Springer-Verlag, 1984.
J. H. Conway and N.J.A. Sloane, Sphere Packings, Lattices, and Groups, Springer-
Verlag, 1988.
I. Peterson, "Curves For a Tighter Fit," Science News, Vol. 137, May 19, 1990, pp.
316-17.
N.J.A. Sloane, "The Packing of Spheres," Scientific American, January 1984, pp.
116-25.
Spheres and Hyperspheres 149
Chapter 12 The Church of
the Fourth Dimension
"Could 1 but rotate my arm out of the limits
set to it," one of the Utopians had said to
him, "1 could thrust it into a thousand
dimensions." -H. G. Wells. Men Like Gods
Alexander Pope once described London as a "dear, droll, dis-
tracting town." Who would disagree? Even with respect to recreational
mathematics, I have yet to make an imaginary visit to London without
coming on something quite extra-ordinary. Once, for instance, I was
reading the London Times in my hotel room a few blocks from Pic-
cadilly Circus when a small advertisement caught my eye:
Weary of the world of three dimensions? Come worship with us Sunday
at the Church of the Fourth Dimension. Services promptly at 11 A.M., in
Plato's grotto. Reverend Arthur Slade, Minister.
An address was given. I tore out the advertisement, and on the follow-
ing Sunday morning rode the Underground to a station within walking
distance of the church. There was a damp chill in the air and a light
mist was drifting in from the sea. I turned the last corner, completely
unprepared for the strange edifice that loomed ahead of me. Four enor-
mous cubes were stacked in one column, with four cantilevered cubes
jutting in four directions from the exposed faces of the third cube from
the ground. I recognized the structure at once as an unfolded hyper-
cube. Just as the six square faces of a cube can be cut along seven lines
and unfolded to make a two-dimensional Latin cross (a popular floor
plan for medieval churches), so the eight cubical hyperfaces of a four-
dimensional cube can be cut along seventeen squares and "unfolded"
to form a three-dimensional Latin cross.
A smiling young woman standing inside the portal directed me to a
stairway. It spiraled down into a basement auditorium that I can only
describe as a motion-picture theater combined with a limestone cavern.
The front wall was a solid expanse of white. Formations of translucent
pink stalactites glowed brightly on the ceiling, flooding the grotto with
150
a rosy light. Huge stalagmites surrounded the room at the sides and
back. Electronic organ music, like the score of a science-fiction film,
surged into the room from all directions. I touched one of the stalag-
mites. It vibrated beneath my fingers like the cold key of a stone xylo-
phone.
The strange music continued for 10 minutes or more after I had taken
a seat, then slowly softened as the overhead light began to dim. At the
same time I became aware of a source of bluish light at the rear of the
grotto. It grew more intense, casting sharp shadows of the heads of
the congregation on the lower part of the white wall ahead. I turned
around and saw an almost blinding point oflight that appeared to come
from an enormous distance.
The music faded into silence as the grotto became completely dark
except for the brilliantly illuminated front wall. The shadow of the
minister rose before us. After announcing the text as Ephesians, Chap-
ter 3, verses 17 and 18, he began to read in low, resonant tones that
seemed to come directly from the shadow's head: " ... that ye, being
rooted and grounded in love, may be able to comprehend with all saints
what is the breadth, and length, and depth, and height. ... "
It was too dark for note-taking, but the following paragraphs sum-
marize accurately, I think, the burden of Slade's remarkable sermon.
Our cosmos-the world we see, hear, feel-is the three-dimensional
"surface" of a vast, four-dimensional sea. The ability to visualize, to
comprehend intuitively, this "wholly other" world of higher space is
given in each century only to a few chosen seers. For the rest of us, we
must approach hyperspace indirectly, by way of analogy. Imagine a
Flatland, a shadow world of two dimensions like the shadows on the
wall of Plato's famous cave (Republic, Chapter 7). But shadows do not
have material substance, so it is best to think of Flatland as possessing
an infinitesimal thickness equal to the diameter of one of its funda-
mental particles. Imagine these particles floating on the smooth surface
of a liquid. They dance in obedience to two-dimensional laws. The in-
habitants of Flatland, who are made up of these particles, cannot con-
ceive of a third direction perpendicular to the two they know.
We, however, who live in 3-space can see every particle of Flatland.
We see inside its houses, inside the bodies of every Flatlander. We can
touch every particle of their world without passing our finger through
their space. If we lift a Flatlander out of a locked room, it seems to him
a miracle.
The Church of the Fourth Dimension 151
In an analogous way, Slade continued, our world of 3-space floats on
the quiet surface of a gigantic hyperocean; perhaps, as Einstein once
suggested, on an immense hypersphere. The four-dimensional thick-
ness of our world is approximately the diameter of a fundamental par-
ticle. The laws of our world are the "surface tensions" of the hypersea.
The surface of this sea is uniform, otherwise our laws would not be uni-
form. A slight curvature of the sea's surface accounts for the slight,
constant curvature of our space-time. Time exists also in hyperspace.
If time is regarded as our fourth coordinate, then the hyperworld is a
world of five dimensions. Electromagnetic waves are vibrations on the
surface of the hypersea. Only in this way, Slade emphasized, can sci-
ence escape the paradox of an empty space capable of transmitting en-
ergy.
What lies outside the sea's surface? The wholly other world of God!
No longer is theology embarrassed by the contradiction between God's
immanence and transcendence. Hyperspace touches every point of 3-
space. God is closer to us than our breathing. He can see every portion
of our world, touch every particle without moving a finger through our
space. Yet the Kingdom of God is completely "outside" 3-space, in a di-
rection in which we cannot even point.
The cosmos was created billions of years ago when God poured
(Slade paused to say that he spoke metaphorically) on the surface of the
hypersea an enormous quantity of hyperparticles with asymmetric
three-dimensional cross sections. Some of these particles fell into 3-
space in right-handed form to become neutrons, the others in left-
handed form to become antineutrons. Pairs of opposite parity
annihilated each other in a great primeval explosion, but a slight pre-
ponderance of hyperparticles happened to fall as neutrons and this ex-
cess remained. Most of these neutrons split into protons and electrons
to form hydrogen. So began the evolution of our "one-sided" material
world. The explosion caused a spreading of particles. To maintain this
expanding universe in a reasonably steady state, God renews its mat-
ter at intervals by dipping his fingers into his supply of hyperparticles
and flicking them toward the sea. Those which fall as antineutrons are
annihilated, those which fall as neutrons remain. Whenever an an-
tiparticle is created in the laboratory, we witness an actual "turning
over" of an asymmetric particle in the same way that one can reverse
in 3-space an asymmetric two-dimensional pattern of cardboard. Thus
152 SOLID GEOMETRY AND HIGHER DIMENSIONS
the production of antiparticles provides an empirical proof of the real-
ity of 4-space.
Slade brought his sermon to a close by reading from the recently dis-
covered Gnostic Gospel of Thomas: "If those who lead you say to you:
Behold the kingdom is in heaven, then the birds will precede you. If
they say to you that it is in the sea, then the fish will precede you. But
the kingdom is within you and it is outside of you."
Again the unearthly organ music. The blue light vanished, plunging
the cavern into total blackness. Slowly the pink stalactites overhead
began to glow, and I blinked my eyes, dazzled to find myself back in 3-
space.
Slade, a tall man with iron-gray hair and a small dark mustache, was
standing at the grotto's entrance to greet the members of his congrega-
tion. As we shook hands I introduced myself and mentioned my Sci-
entific American column. "Of course!" he exclaimed. "I have some of
your books. Are you in a hurry? If you wait a bit, we'll have a chance
to chat."
After the last handshake Slade led me to a second spiral stairway of
opposite handedness from the one on which I had descended earlier.
It carried us to the pastor's study in the top cube of the church. Elabo-
rate models, 3-space projections of various types of hyperstructures,
were on display around the room. On one wall hung a large reproduc-
tion of Salvador Dali's painting "Corpus Hypercubus." In the picture,
above a flat surface of checkered squares, floats a three-dimensional
cross of eight cubes; an unfolded hypercube identical in structure with
the church in which I was standing.
"Tell me, Slade," I said, after we were seated, "is this doctrine of
yours new or are you continuing a long tradition?"
"It's by no means new," he replied, "though I can claim to have es-
tablished the first church in which hyperfaith serves as the corner-
stone. Plato, of course, had no conception of a geometrical fourth
dimension, though his cave analogy clearly implies it. In fact, every
form of Platonic dualism that divides existence into the natural and su-
pernatural is clearly a nonmathematical way of speaking about higher
space. Henry More, the 17th-century Cambridge Platonist, was the first
to regard the spiritual world as having four spatial dimensions. Then
along came Immanuel Kant, with his recognition of our space and time
as subjective lenses, so to speak, through which we view only a thin
The Church of the Fourth Dimension 153
slice of transcendent reality. After that it is easy to see how the concept
of higher space provided a much needed link between modern science
and traditional religions."
"You say 'religions,' " I put in. "Does that mean your church is not
Christian? "
"Only in the sense that we find essential truth in all the great world
faiths. I should add that in recent decades the Continental Protestant
theologians have finally discovered 4-space. When Karl Barth talks
about the 'vertical' or 'perpendicular' dimension, he clearly means it in
a four-dimensional sense. And of course in the theology of Karl Heim
there is a full, explicit recognition of the role of higher space."
"Yes," I said. "I recently read an interesting book called Physicist
and Christian, by William G. Pollard (executive director of the Oak
Ridge Institute of Nuclear Studies and an Episcopal clergyman). He
draws heavily on Heim's concept of hyperspace."
Slade scribbled the book's title on a note pad. "I must look it up. I
wonder if Pollard realizes that a number of late-19th-century Protes-
tants wrote books about the fourth dimension. A. T. Schofield's Another
World, for example (it appeared in 1888) and Arthur Willink's The
World of the Unseen (subtitled "An Essay on the Relation of Higher
Space to Things Eternal"; published in 1893). Of course modern oc-
cultists and spiritualists have had a field day with the notion. Peter D.
Ouspensky, for instance, has a lot to say about it in his books, although
most of his opinions derive from the speculations of Charles Howard
Hinton, an American mathematician. Whately Carington, the English
parapsychologist, wrote an unusual book in 1920-he published it
under the byline of W. Whately Smith-on A Theory of the Mecha-
nism of Surviva1. "
"Survival after death?"
Slade nodded. "I can't go along with Carington's belief in such things
as table tipping being accomplished by an invisible four-dimensional
lever, or clairvoyance as perception from a point in higher space, but I
regard his basic hypothesis as sound. Our bodies are simply three-
dimensional cross sections of our higher four-dimensional selves. Ob-
viously a man is subject to all the laws of this world, but at the same
time his experiences are permanently recorded-stored as information,
so to speak-in the 4-space portion of his higher self. When his 3-space
body ceases to function, the permanent record remains until it can be
154 SOLID GEOMETRY AND HIGHER DIMENSIONS
attached to a new body for a new cycle of life in some other 3-space
continuum. "
"I like that," I said. HIt explains the complete dependence of mind on
body in this world, at the same time permitting an unbroken continu-
ity between this life and the next. Isn't this close to what William James
struggled to say in his little book on immortality?"
"Precisely. James, unfortunately, was no mathematician, so he had to
express his meaning in nongeometrical metaphors."
"What about the so-called demonstrations of the fourth dimension by
certain mediums," I asked. "Wasn't there a professor of astrophysics in
Leipzig who wrote a book about them?"
I thought I detected an embarrassed note in Slade's laugh. "Yes, that
was poor Johann Karl Friedrich Zollner. His book Transcendental
Physics was translated into English in 1881, but even the English copies
are now quite rare. Zollner did some good work in spectrum analysis,
but he was supremely ignorant of conjuring methods. As a consequence
he was badly taken in, I'm afraid, by Henry Slade, the American
medium."
"Slade?" I said with surprise.
"Yes, I'm ashamed to say we're related. He was my great-uncle. When
he died, he left a dozen fat notebooks in which he had recorded his
methods. Those notebooks were acquired by the English side of my
family and handed down to me."
"This excites me greatly," I said. "Can you demonstrate any of the
tricks?"
The request seemed to please him. Conjuring, he explained, was one
of his hobbies, and he thought that the mathematical angles of several
of Henry's tricks would be of interest to my readers.
From a drawer in his desk Slade took a strip of leather, cut as shown
at the left in Figure 12.1, to make three parallel strips. He handed me a
ballpoint pen with the request that I mark the leather in some way to
prevent later substitution. I initialed a corner as shown. We sat on op-
posite sides of a small table. Slade held the leather under the table for
a few moments, then brought it into view again. It was braided exactly
as shown at the right in the illustration! Such braiding would be easy
to accomplish if one could move the strips through hyperspace. In 3-
space it seemed impossible.
Slade's second trick was even more astonishing. He had me examine
The Church of the Fourth Dimension 155
Figure 12.1. Slade's leather strip
-braided in hyperspace?
a rubber band of the wide, flat type shown at the left in Figure 12.2.
This was placed in a matchbox, and the box was securely sealed at
both ends with cellophane tape. Slade started to place it under the
table, then remembered he had forgotten to have me mark the box for
later identification. I drew a heavy X on the upper surface.
Figure 12.2. Slade's rubber band -knotted in hyperspace?
"If you like," he said, "you yourself may hold the box under the
table."
I did as directed. Slade reached down, taking the box by its other end.
There was a sound of movement and I could feel that the box seemed
to be vibrating slightly.
Slade released his grip. "Please open the box."
First I inspected the box carefully. The tape was still in place. My
mark was on the cover. I slit the tape with my thumbnail and pushed
open the drawer. The elastic band-mira bile dictu-was tied in a sim-
ple knot as shown at the right in Figure 12.2.
"Even if you managed somehow to open the box and switch bands,"
I said, "how the devil could you get a rubber band like this?"
Slade chuckled. "My great-uncle was a clever rascal."
156 SOLID GEOMETRY AND HIGHER DIMENSIONS
I was unable to persuade Slade to tell me how either trick was done.
The reader is invited to think about them before he reads this chapter's
answer section.
We talked of many other things. When I finally left the Church of the
Fourth Dimension, a heavy fog was swirling through the wet streets of
London. I was back in Plato's cave. The shadowy forms of moving cars,
their headlights forming flat elliptical blobs of light, made me think of
some familiar lines from the Rubaiyat of a great Persian mathemati-
cian:
We are no other than a moving row
Of magic shadow-shapes that come and go
Round with the sun-illumined lantern held
In midnight by the Master of the Show.
Addendum
Although I spoke in the first paragraph of this chapter of an
"imaginary visit" to London, when the chapter first appeared in Sci-
entific American several readers wrote to ask for the address of Slade's
church. The Reverend Slade is purely fictional, but Henry Slade the
medium was one of the most colorful and successful mountebanks in
the history of American spiritualism. See my article on Slade in The
Encyclopedia of the Paranormal, edited by Gordon Stein, Prometheus
Books, 1996, and my remarks about Slade's fourth-dimensional trick-
ery in The New Ambidextrous Universe (W. H. Freeman, 1990).
At the time I wrote about the Church of the Fourth Dimension no em-
inent physicist had ever contended that there might actually be spaces
"out there," higher than our familiar 3-space. (The use of a fourth di-
mension in relativity theory was no more than a way of handling time
in the theory's equations.) Now, however, particle physicists are in a eu-
phoric state over a theory of superstrings in which fundamental parti-
cles are not modeled as geometrical points, but as extremely tiny closed
loops, of great tensile strength, that vibrate in higher spaces. These
higher spaces are "compacted"-curled up into tight little structures
too small to be visible or even to be detected by today's atom smashers.
Some physicists regard these higher spaces as mere artifices of the
mathematics, but others believe they are just as real as the three spaces
we know and love. (On superstrings, see my New Ambidextrous Uni-
The Church of the Fourth Dimension 157
verse.) It is the first time physicists have seriously entertained the no-
tion of higher spaces that are physically real. This may have stimu-
lated the publication of recent books on the fourth and higher
dimensions. I particularly recommend Thomas F. Banchoff's Beyond
the Third Dimension, if for no other reason than for its wondrous com-
puter graphics.
In recent years the theory of superstrings has been extended to mem-
brane or brane theory in which the strings are attached to vibrating
surfaces that live in higher space dimensions. Some theorists are spec-
ulating that our universe is an enormous brane floating in hyperspace
along with countless other "island universes," each with its own set of
laws. A possibility looms that these other universes could be detected
by their gravity seeping into our universe and generating the elusive in-
visible dark matter which physicists suspect furnishes 90 percent of the
matter in our universe. For these wild speculations see George John-
son's mind-boggling article, "Physicists Finally Find a Way to Test Su-
perstring Theory," in The New York Times, April 4, 2000.
Membrane theory is also called M-theory, the M standing for mem-
brane, mystery, magic, marvel, and matrix. See "Magic, Mystery, and
Matrix," a lecture by Edward Witten, the world's top expert on super-
strings, published in Notices of the AMS (American Mathematical So-
ciety), Vol. 45, November 1998, and his 1998 videotape M-Theory,
available from the AMS.
Answers
Slade's method of braiding the leather strip is familiar to Boy
Scouts in England and to all those who make a hobby of leathercraft.
Many readers wrote to tell me of books in which this type of braiding
is described: George Russell Shaw, Knots, Useful and Ornamental (p.
86); Constantine A. Belash, Braiding and Knotting (p. 94); Clifford Pyle,
Leather Craft as a Hobby (p. 82); Clifford W. Ashley, The Ashley Book
of Knots (p. 486); and others. For a full mathematical analysis, see
J.A.H. Shepperd, "Braids Which Can Be Plaited with Their Threads
Tied Together at Each End," Proceedings of the Royal Society, A, Vol.
265,1962, pages 229-44.
There are several ways to go about making the braid. Figure 12.3 was
drawn by reader George T. Rab of Dayton, OH. By repeating this pro-
cedure one can extend the braid to any multiple of six crossings. An-
158 SOLID GEOMETRY AND HIGHER DIMENSIONS
"
159
this when he started to put the box under the table, then "remembered"
that I had not yet initialed it. The prepared box could have been stuck
to the underside of the table with magician's wax. It would require
only a moment to press the unprepared box against another dab of wax,
then take the prepared one. In this way the switch occurred before I
marked the box. The vibrations I felt when Slade and I held the box
under the table were probably produced by one of Slade's fingers press-
ing firmly against the box and sliding across it.
Fitch Cheney, mathematician and magician, wrote to tell about a sec-
ond and simpler way to create a knotted elastic band. Obtain a hollow
rubber torus-they are often sold as teething rings for babies-and cut
as shown by the dotted line in Figure 12.5. The result is a wide endless
band tied in a single knot. The band can be trimmed, of course, to nar-
rower width.
Figure 12.S. A second way
to produce a knotted
rubber band
It was Stover, by the way, who first suggested to me the problem of
tying a knot in an elastic band. He had been shown such a knotted
band by magician Winston Freer. Freer said he knew three ways of
doing it.
Bibliography
T. F. Banchoff, Beyond the Third Dimension, New York: W. H. Freeman, 1990.
M. Gardner, "Group Theory and Braids," New Mathematical Diversions from Sci-
entific American, Chapter 2, New York: Simon and Schuster, 1966. Reissued by
the University of Chicago Press, 1983.
K. Heim, Christian Faith and Natural Science, New York: Harper, 1953; paper-
back,1957.
C. H. Hinton, The Fourth Dimension, London: Swan Sonnenschein, 1904; Allen &
Unwin, 1951.
160 SOLID GEOMETRY AND HIGHER DIMENSIONS
H. P. Manning, Geometry of Four Dimensions, New York: Macmillan, 1914; Dover
Publications (paperback), 1956.
H. P. Manning, The Fourth Dimension Simply Explained, New York: Munn, 1910;
New York: Dover Publications (paperback), 1960.
E. H. Neville, The Fourth Dimension, Cambridge, England: Cambridge University
Press, 1921.
C. Pickover, Surfing Through Hyperspace, England: Oxford University Press, 1999.
R. Rucker (ed.), Speculations on the Fourth Dimension, New York: Dover, 1980.
R. Rucker, The Fourth Dimension: Toward a Geometry of Higher Reality, Boston:
Houghton-Mifflin, 1984.
J.A.H. Shepperd, "Braids Which Can Be Plaited with Their Threads Tied Together
at Each End," Proceedings of the Royal Society, A, Vol. 265, 1962, pp. 229-44.
D.M.Y. Sommerville, An Introduction to the Geometry of N Dimensions, London:
Methuen, 1929; New York: Dover Publications (paperback), 1958.
The Church of the Fourth Dimension 161
Chapter 13
The children were vanishing.
They went in fragments, like thick smoke in a
wind, or like movement in a distorting mirror.
Hand in hand they went, in a direction Para-
dine could not understand . ...
-LEwIs PADGETI, from "Mimsy Were the Borogoves"
Hypercubes
The direction that Paradine, a professor of philosophy, could
not understand is a direction perpendicular to each of the three coor-
dinates of space. It extends into 4-space in the same way a chess piece
extends upward into 3-space with its axis at right angles to the x and y
coordinates of the chessboard. In Padgett's great science fiction story,
Paradine's children find a wire model of a tesseract (a hypercube of four
dimensions) with colored beads that slide along the wires in curious
ways. It is a toy abacus that had been dropped into our world by a 4-
space scientist tinkering with a time machine. The abacus teaches the
children how to think four-dimensionally. With the aid of some cryp-
tic advice in Lewis Carroll's Jabberwocky they finally walk out of 3-
space altogether.
Is it possible for the human brain to visualize four-dimensional struc-
tures? The 19th-century German physicist Hermann von Helmholtz ar-
gued that it is, provided the brain is given proper input data.
Unfortunately our experience is confined to 3-space and there is not the
slightest scientific evidence that 4-space actually exists. (Euclidean 4-
space must not be confused with the non-Euclidean four-dimensional
space-time of relativity theory, in which time is handled as a fourth co-
ordinate.) Nevertheless, it is conceivable that with the right kind of
mathematical training a person might develop the ability to visualize
a tesseract. "A man who devoted his life to it," wrote Henri Poincare,
"could perhaps succeed in picturing to himself a fourth dimension."
Charles Howard Hinton, an eccentric American mathematician who
once taught at Princeton University and who wrote a popular book
called The Fourth Dimension, devised a system of using colored blocks
for making 3-space models of sections of a tesseract. Hinton believed
that by playing many years with this "toy" (it may have suggested the
162
toy in Padgett's story), he had acquired a dim intuitive grasp of 4-space.
"I do not like to speak positively," he wrote, "for I might occasion a loss
of time on the part of others, if, as may very well be, I am mistaken. But
for my own part, I think there are indications of such an intuition .... "
Hinton's colored blocks are too complicated to explain here (the
fullest account of them is in his 1910 book, A New Era a/Thought). Per-
haps, however, by examining some of the simpler properties of the
tesseract we can take a few wobbly first steps toward the power of vi-
sualization Hinton believed he had begun to achieve.
Let us begin with a point and move it a distance of one unit in a
straight line, as shown in Figure 13.1(a). All the points on this unit line
can be identified by numbering them from 0 at one end to 1 at the
other. Now move the unit line a distance of one unit in a direction per-
pendicular to the line (b). This generates a unit square. Label one cor-
ner 0, then number the points from 0 to 1 along each of the two lines
that meet at the zero corner. With these x and y coordinates we can now
label every point on the square with an ordered pair of numbers. It is
just as easy to visualize the next step. Shift the square a unit distance
in a direction at right angles to both the x and the yaxes (e). The result
is a unit cube. With x, y, z coordinates along three edges that meet at a
corner, we can label every point in the cube with an ordered triplet of
numbers.
Although our visual powers boggle at the next step, there is no logi-
cal reason why we cannot assume that the cube is shifted a unit dis-
tance in a direction perpendicular to all three of its axes (d). The space
generated by such a shift is a 4-space unit hypercube-a tesseract-
with four mutually perpendicular edges meeting at every corner. By
choosing a set of such edges as w, x, y, z axes, one might label every
point in the hypercube with an ordered quadruplet of numbers. Ana-
lytic geometers can work with these ordered quadruplets in the same
way they work with ordered pairs and triplets to solve problems in
plane and solid geometry. In this fashion Euclidean geometry can be ex-
tended to higher spaces with dimensions represented by any positive
integer. Each space is Euclidean but each is topologically distinct: a
square cannot be continuously deformed to a straight line, a cube de-
formed to a square, a hypercube to a cube, and so on.
Accurate studies of figures in 4-space can be made only on the basis
of an axiomatic system for 4-space, or by working analytically with the
w, x, y, z equations of the four-coordinate system. But the tesseract is
Hypercubes 163
a
....... _----...
o
C
~ 1
;;
o
""",;
;"
.,;
"
1 ;;
.,'
;'"
... ;
b
0 1
, ,
I I
1 I I 1
I I
I I
I I
1-
-
d
Figure 13.1. Steps toward generating a hypercube
such a simple 4-space structure that we can guess many of its proper-
ties by intuitive, analogical reasoning. A unit line has two end points.
When it is moved to generate a square, its ends have starting and stop-
ping positions and therefore the number of corners on the square is
twice the number of points on the line, or four. The two moving points
generate two lines, but the unit line has a start and a stop position and
so we must add two more lines to obtain four as the number of lines
bounding the square.
In similar fashion, when the square is moved to generate a cube, its
four corners have start and stop positions and therefore we multiply
four by two to arrive at eight corners on the cube. In moving, each of the
four points generates a line, but to those four lines we must add the
square's four lines at its start and the four lines at its stop, making 4 +
4 + 4 = 12 edges on the cube. The four lines of the moving square gen-
erate four new faces, to which the start and stop faces are added, mak-
ing 4 + 1 + 1 = 6 faces on the cube's surface.
Now suppose the cube is pushed a unit distance in the direction of
a fourth axis at right angles to the other three, a direction in which we
cannot point because we are trapped in 3-space. Again each corner of
the cube has start and stop positions, so that the resulting tesseract has
164 SOLID GEOMETRY AND HIGHER DIMENSIONS
2 x 8 = 16 corners. Each point generates a line, but to these eight lines
we must add the start and stop positions of the cube's 12 edges to make
8 + 12 + 12 = 32 unit lines on the hypercube. Each of the cube's 12 edges
generates a square, but to those 12 squares we must add the cube's six
squares before the push and the six after the push, making 12 + 6 + 6 =
24 squares on the tesseract's hypersurface.
It is a mistake to suppose the tesseract is bounded by its 24 squares.
They form only a skeleton of the hypercube, just as the edges of a cube
form its skeleton. A cube is bounded by square faces and a hypercube
is bounded by cubical faces. When the cube is pushed, each of its
squares moves a unit distance in an unimaginable direction at right
angles to its face, thereby generating another cube. To the six cubes
generated by the six moving squares we must add the cube before it is
pushed and the same cube after it is pushed, making eight in all. These
eight cubes form the hypercube's hypersurface.
The chart in Figure 13.2 gives the number of elements in "cubes" of
spaces one through four. There is a simple, surprising trick by which
this chart can be extended downward to higher n-cubes. Think of the
nth line as an expansion of the binomial (2x + l)n. For example, the line
segment of 1-space has two points and one line. Write this as 2x+ 1 and
multiply it by itself:
2x + 1
2x + 1
4r + 2x
2x + 1
4x
2
+ 4x + 1
n-SPACE POINTS
0 1
1 2
2 4
3 8
4 16
LINES
0
1
4
12
32
SQUARES CUBES TESSERACTS
0 0 0
0 0 0
1 0 0
6 1 0
24 8 1
Figure 13.2. Elements of structures analogous to the cube in various dimensions
Hypercubes 165
Note that the answer correspond the chart's
Indeed, each line of the chart, written as a polynomial
+ 1, gives the next are of a
space as a fourth-power
and multiply by 2x+ 1:
16x4 + + +
+1
2x + 1
+ 16x
2
+
+ 24x2 + Bx + 1
+ 80.0 + 4ox2 + + 1
one
............... LI"' .... on the chart equals twice the number
it number diagonally
If you ............ '-, ....................... ofa on
a plane, you can the
comes from a I'J\J.L.L.L'- close to the cube and the cube is held a cer-
the projection 1
example, a fly cannot along all edges of a cube in a
_..., ......... _ over an edge twice J nor can it do this on
the
166
GEOMETRY AND
Figure 13.4 is the analogous projection in 3-space of the edges of a
tesseract; more accurately, it is a plane projection of a three-
dimensional model that is in turn a projection of the hypercube. All the
elements of the tesseract given by the chart are easily identified in the
model, although six of the eight cubes suffer perspective distortions just
as four of the cube's square faces are distorted in its projection on the
plane. The eight cubes are the large cube, the small interior cube, and
the six hexahedrons surrounding the small cube. (Readers should also
try to find the eight cubes in Figure 13.1(d)-a projection of the tesser-
act, from a different angle, into another 3-space model.) Here again the
topological properties of both models are the same'as those of the edges
of the tesseract. In this case a fly can walk along all the edges without
traversing any edge twice. (In general the fly can do this only on hy-
percubes in even spaces, because only in even spaces do an even num-
ber of edges meet at each vertex.)
Figure 13.4. Projection of the
tesseract in 3-space
Many properties of unit hypercubes can be expressed in simple for-
mulas that apply to hypercubes of all dimensions. For example, the di-
agonal of a unit square has a length of Vz. The longest diagonals on the
unit cube have a length of vi In general a diagonal from corner to op-
posite corner on a unit cube in n-space is Vn.
A square of side x has an area of x
2
and a perimeter of 4x. What size
square has an area equal to its perimeter? The equation x
2
= 4x gives x
a value of 4. The unique answer is therefore a square of side 4. What
size cube has a volume equal to its surface area? After the reader has
answered this easy question he should have no difficulty answering
two more: (1) What size hypercube has a hypervolume (measured by
unit hypercubes) equal to the volume (measured by unit cubes) of its
hypersurface? (2) What is the formula for the edge of an n-cube whose
n-volume is equal to the (n - l)-volume of its "surface"?
Hypercubes 167
Puzzle books often ask questions about cubes that are easily asked
about the tesseract but not so easily answered. Consider the longest
line that will fit inside a unit square. It is obviously the diagonal, with
a length of Yz. What is the largest square that will fit inside a unit
cube? If the reader succeeds in answering this rather tricky question,
and if he learns his way around in 4-space, he might try the more dif-
ficult problem of finding the largest cube that can be fitted into a unit
tesseract.
An interesting combinatorial problem involving the tesseract is best
approached, as usual, by first considering the analogous problems for
the square and cube. Cut open one corner of a square (see top drawing
in Figure 13.5) and its four lines can be unfolded as shown to form a
one-dimensional figure. Each line rotates around a point until all are in
the same i-space. To unfold a cube, think of it as formed of squares
joined at their edges; cut seven edges and the squares can be unfolded
(bottom drawing) until they all lie in 2-space to form a hexomino (six
unit squares joined at their edges). In this case each square rotates
around an edge. By cutting different edges one can unfold the cube to
make different hexomino shapes. Assuming that an asymmetric hex-
omino and its mirror image are the same, how many different hexomi-
noes can be formed by unfolding a cube?
The eight cubes that form the exterior surface of the tesseract can be
cut and unfolded in similar fashion. It is impossible to visualize how
a 4-space person might "see" (with three-dimensional retinas?) the hol-
low tesseract. Nevertheless, the eight cubes that bound it are true sur-
faces in the sense that the hyperperson can touch any point inside any
cube with the point of a hyperpin without the pin's passing through
any other point in the cube, just as we, with a pin, can touch any point
inside any square face of a cube without the pin's going through any
other point on that face. Points are "inside" a cube only to us. To a hy-
perperson every point in each cubical "face" of a tesseract is directly
exposed to his vision as he turns the tesseract in his hyperfingers.
Even harder to imagine is the fact that a cube in 4-space will rotate
around any of its faces. The eight cubes that bound the tesseract are
joined at their faces. Indeed, each of the 24 squares in the tesseract is a
joining spot for two cubes, as can easily be verified by studying the 3-
space models. If 17 of these 24 squares are cut, separating the pair of
cubes attached at that spot, and if these cuts are made at the right
places, the eight cubes will be free to rotate around the seven uncut
168 SOLID GEOMETRY AND HIGHER DIMENSIONS
o
A
B C 0
E
F
13.5. Unfolding a square (top) and a cube (bottom)
their faces),
(Figure 13 owned
to
;Ch.:>LJO ... JLUUW ....... polycube analogous
Observe how Dali has the contrast between 2-space and 3-
by a ..................... L"\.'u.L
cross an un-
" O T " ~ " " ' T Dali symbolizes the belief that the
death of Christ was a metahistorical event, taking place in a region
our limited use
of the "wholly other" world has long been a favorite
as P. as well as of ........ "I'J' .............
a more mundane level the unfolded
story "-And
Hypercubes 169
MS'trol)Olltan Museum of Chester 1955
11.6. 1954
170 AND
to Flatlanders as a square. There are some remarkable adventures inside
the tesseract and some unearthly views through its windows before
the house, jarred by. another earthquake, falls out of our space alto-
gether.
The notion that part of our universe might fall out of 3-space is not
so crazy as it sounds. The eminent American physicist J. A. Wheeler
has a perfectly respectable" dropout" theory to explain the enormous
energies that emanate from quasi-stellar radio sources, or quasars.
When a giant star undergoes gravitational collapse, perhaps a central
mass is formed of such incredible density that it puckers space-time
into a blister. If the curvature is great enough, the blister could pinch
together at its neck and the mass could fall out of space-time, releas-
ing energy as it vanishes.
But back to hypercubes and one final question. How many different
order-8 polycubes can be produced by unfolding a hollow hypercube
into 3-space?
Addendum
Hiram Barton, a consulting engineer of Etchingham, Sussex,
England, had the following grim comments to make about Hinton's col-
ored cubes:
Dear Mr. Gardner:
A shudder ran down my spine when I read your reference to Hinton's
cubes. I nearly got hooked on them myself in the nineteen-twenties.
Please believe me when I say that they are completely mind-destroying.
The only person I ever met who had worked with them seriously was
Francis Sedlak, a Czech neo-Hegelian philosopher (he wrote a book
called The Creation of Heaven and Earth) who lived in an Oneida-like
community near Stroud, in Gloucestershire.
As you must know, the technique consists essentially in the sequen-
tial visualizing of the adjoint internal faces of the poly-colored unit
cubes making up the large cube. It is not difficult to acquire considerable
facility in this, but the process is one of autohypnosis and, after a while,
the sequences begin to parade themselves through one's mind of their
own accord. This is pleasurable, in a way, and it was not until I went to
see Sedlak in 1929 that I realized the dangers of setting up an au-
tonomous process in one's own brain. For the record, the way out is to
establish consciously a countersystem differing from the first in that the
Hypercubes 171
core cube shows different colored faces, but withdrawal is slow and I
wouldn't recommend anyone to play around with the cubes at all.
The problem of pushing a larger cube through a hole in a smaller
cube is known as Prince Rupert's problem. The question seems to have
first been asked by Prince Rupert (1619-1682), a nephew of England's
King Charles. If you hold a cube so one corner points directly toward
you, you will see a regular hexagon. The largest square that will go
into a cube has a face that can be inscribed within this hexagon. Note
that two of the interior square's sides can be drawn on the outside of the
cube. The other two edges are within the cube.
Apparently I was the first to pose the analogous problem of deter-
mining the largest cube that would go inside a hypercube. Over the
years I received many letters from readers who claimed to have an-
swered this question. Most of the letters were too technical for me to
understand, and wildy different results were claimed.
Richard Guy and Richard Nowakowski, in their feature on unsolved
problems (American Mathematical Monthly, Vol. 104, December 1997,
pp. 967-69) report on a lengthy proof by Kay R. Pechenick DeVicci of
Moorestown, NJ, that the desired cube's edge is 1.007434775 .... It is
the square root of 1.014924 ... , the smaller root of 4.0 - 28r - 7x
2
+
16x + 16. Her paper, which includes a generalization to the largest m-
cube in an n-cube, has not been published. Guy and his two collabora-
tors on Unsolved Problems in Geometry (1991), Section B4, refer to
DeVicci's work as having solved the problem for the 3-cube in a 4-cube,
but they refer to the more general problem of n dimensions as unsolved.
When I began editing columns for this anthology I searched my files
for all the letters I had received on this problem. One writer believed
the answer was simply the unit cube of side 1, which turned out to be
quite close to the truth.
In going more carefully through my correspondence on this prob-
lem I was astonished to find that no less than four readers had obtained
the same answer as Da Vicci-a cube with an edge of 1.00743 .... I here
list them alphabetically along with the year of their letter: Hermann
Baer, Post Gilboa, Israel (1974); Eugen I. Bosch, Washington, D.C.
(1966); G. de Josselin de Jong, Delft, The Netherlands (1971); and Kay
R. Pechenick, Lafayette Hill, PA (1983).
The problem of finding all the ways a hypercube can be "unfolded"
to make distinct polycubes (unit cubes joined at their faces) was solved
172 SOLID GEOMETRY AND HIGHER DIMENSIONS
by Peter Turney in his 1984 paper (see bibliography). Using graph the-
ory, Turney found 261 unfoldings. His method extends easily to hy-
percubes of any number of dimensions.
In the Journal of Recreational Mathematics (Vol. 15, No.2. 1982-83,
p. 146) Harry Nelson showed how the 11 polyominoes that fold into a
cube would fit inside a 9 x 9 square and also inside a 7 x 11 rectangle.
It is not known if they will fit inside a smaller rectangle.
Answers
A tesseract of side x has a hypervolume of .0. The volume of its
hypersurface is 8x3. If the two magnitudes are equal, the equation gives
x a value of 8. In general an n-space "cube" with an n-volume equal to
the (n - l)-volume of its "surface" is an n-cube of side 2n.
The largest square that can be fitted inside a unit cube is the square
shown in Figure 13.7. Each corner of the square is a distance of % from
a corner of the cube. The square has an area of exactly 9/8 and a side
that is three-fourths of the square root of 2. Readers familiar with the
old problem of pushing the largest possible cube through a square hole
in a smaller cube will recognize this square as the cross section of the
limiting size of the square hole. In other words, a cube of side not quite
three-fourths of the square root of 2 can be pushed through a square
hole in a unit cube.
Figure 13.7. Packing a square in a cube
Figure 13.8 shows the 11 different hexominoes that fold into a cube.
They form a frustrating set, because they will not fit together to make
any of the rectangles that contain 66 unit squares, but perhaps there are
some interesting patterns they will form.
Hypercubes 173
,
F;.pre 13.8. The 11 hexominoes that fold into cubes
Bibliography
H.S.M. Coxeter, Regular Polytopes, Dover, 3e, 1973.
M. Gardner, "And He Built Another Crooked House," Puzzles From Other Worlds,
Vintage, 1984.
K. Heim, Christian Faith and Natural Science, Harper Torchbook, 1957.
C. H. Hinton, A New Era of Thought, Swan Sonnenschein, 1888.
C. H. Hinton, The Fourth Dimension, Allen & Unwin, 1904.
R. A. Jacobson, "Paths of Minimal Length Within Hypercubes," The American
Mathematical Monthly, Vol. 73, October 1966, pp. 868-72.
H. P. Manning, Geometry of Four Dimensions, Dover, 1956.
H. P. Manning, The Fourth Dimension Simply Explained, Dover, 1960.
E. H. Neville, The Fourth Dimension, Cambridge University Press, 1921.
R. Rucker (ed), Speculations on the Fourth Dimension: Selected Writings of C. H.
Hinton, Dover, 1980.
R. Rucker, Infinity and the Mind, Birkiiuser, 1982.
R. Rucker, The Fourth Dimension, Houghton Mifflin, 1984.
D.M.Y. Sommerville, An Introduction to the Geometry of N Dimensions, Dover,
1958.
W. S. Tevis, Jr., "The Ifth of Oofth," Galaxy Science Fiction, April, 1957, pp. 59-69.
A wild and funny tale about a cube that distorts space and
time.
P. Thmey, "Unfolding the Tesseract," Journal of Recreational Mathematics, Vol. 17,
No.1, 1984-85, pp. 1-16.
174 SOLID GEOMETRY AND HIGHER DIMENSIONS
Chapter 14
"Lines that are parallel
meet at Infinity!"
Euclid repeatedly,
heatedly,
urged.
Until he died,
and so reached that vicinity:
in it he
found that the damned things
diverged.
-Piet Hein, Grooks VI
Non-Euclidean
Qeometry
Euclid's Elements is dull, long-winded, and does not make ex-
plicit the fact that two circles can intersect, that a circle has an outside
and an inside, that triangles can be turned over, and other assumptions
essential to his system. By modern standards Bertrand Russell could
call Euclid's fourth proposition a "tissue of nonsense" and declare it a
scandal that the Elements was still used as a textbook.
On the other hand, Euclid's geometry was the first major effort to or-
ganize the subject as an axiomatic system, and it seems hardly fair to
find fault with him for not anticipating all the repairs made when
David Hilbert and others formalized the system. There is no more strik-
ing evidence of Euclid's genius than his realization that his notorious
fifth postulate was not a theorem but an axiom that had to be accepted
without proof.
Euclid's way of stating the postulate was rather cumbersome, and it
was recognized early that it could be given the following simpler form:
Through a point on a plane, not on a given straight line, only one line
is parallel to the given line. Because this is not quite as intuitively ob-
vious as Euclid's other axioms mathematicians tried for 2,000 years to
remove the postulate by making it a theorem that could be established
on the basis of Euclid's other axioms. Hundreds of proofs were at-
tempted. Some eminent mathematicians thought they had succeeded,
but it always turned out that somewhere in their proof an assumption
had been made that either was equivalent to the parallel postulate or re-
quired the postulate.
175
For example, it is easy to prove the parallel postulate if you assume
that the sum of the angles of every triangle equals two right angles. Un-
fortunately you cannot prove this assumption without using the paral-
lel postulate. An early false proof, attributed to Thales of Miletus, rests
on the existence of a rectangle, that is, a quadrilateral with four right an-
gles. You cannot prove, however, that rectangles exist without using the
parallel postulate! In the 17th century John Wallis, a renowned English
mathematician, believed he had proved the postulate. Alas, he failed to
realize that his assumption that two triangles can be similar but not
congruent cannot be proved without the parallel postulate. Long lists
can be made of other assumptions, all so intuitively obvious that they
hardly seem worth asserting, and all equivalent to the parallel postu-
late in the sense that they do not hold unless the postulate holds.
In the early 19th century trying to prove the postulate became some-
thing of a mania. In Hungary, Farkas Bolyai spent much of his life at the
task, and in his youth he discussed it often with his German friend
Karl Friedrich Gauss. Farkas' son Janos became so obsessed by the
problem that his father was moved to write in a letter: "For God's sake,
I beseech you, give it up. Fear it no less than sensual passions because
it too may take all your time and deprive you of your health, peace of
mind and happiness in life."
Janos did not give it up, and soon he became persuaded not only
that the postulate was independent of the other axioms but also that a
consistent geometry could be created by assuming that through the
point an infinity of lines were parallel to the given line. "Out of noth-
ing I have created a new universe," he proudly wrote to his father in
1823.
Farkas at once urged his son to let him publish these sensational
claims in an appendix to a book he was then completing. "If you have
really succeeded, it is right that no time be lost in making it public, for
two reasons: first, because ideas pass easily from one to another who
can anticipate its publication; and secondly, there is some truth in this,
that many things have an epoch in which they are found at the same
time in several places, just as the violets appear on every side in spring.
Also every scientific struggle is just a serious war, in which I cannot say
when peace will arrive. Thus we ought to conquer when we are able,
since the advantage is always to the first comer."
Janos' brief masterpiece did appear in his father's book, but as it hap-
pened the publication of the book was delayed until 1832. The Russ-
176 SOLID GEOMETRY AND HIGHER DIMENSIONS
ian mathematician Nikolai Ivanovitch Lobachevski had beat him to it
by disclosing details of the same strange geometry (later called by Felix
Klein hyperbolic geometry) in a paper of 1829. What is worse, when
Farkas sent the appendix to his old friend Gauss, the Prince of Mathe-
maticians replied that if he praised the work, he would only be prais-
ing himself, inasmuch as he had worked it all out many years earlier
but had published nothing. In other letters he gave his reason. He did
not want to arouse an Houtcry" among the "Boeotians," by which he
meant his conservative colleagues. (In ancient Athens the Boeotians
were considered unusually stupid.)
Crushed by Gauss's response, Janos even suspected that his father
might have leaked his marvelous discovery to Gauss. When he later
learned of Lobachevski's earlier paper, he lost interest in the topic and
published nothing more. "The nature of real truth of course cannot but
be one and the same in Marcos-Vasarhely as in Kamchatka and on the
moon," he wrote, resigned to having published too late to win the
honor for which he had so passionately hoped.
In some ways the story of the Italian Jesuit Giralamo Saccheri is even
sadder than that of Bolyai. As early as 1733, in a Latin book called Eu-
clid Cleared of All Blemish, Saccheri actually constructed both types of
non-Euclidean geometry (we shall come to the second type below)
without knowing it! Or so it seems. At any rate Saccheri refused to be-
lieve either geometry was consistent, but he came so close to accepting
them that some historians think he pretended to disbelieve them just
to get his book published. "To have claimed that a non-Euclidean sys-
tem was as 'true' as Euclid's," writes Eric Temple Bell (in a chapter on
Saccheri in The Magic of Numbers), "would have been a foolhardy in-
vitation to repression and discipline. The Copernicus of Geometry
therefore resorted to subterfuge. Taking a long chance, Saccheri de-
nounced his own work, hoping by this pious betrayal to slip his heresy
past the censors."
I cannot resist adding two anecdotes about the Bolyais. Janos was a
cavalry officer (mathematics had always been strictly a recreation)
known for his swordsmanship, his skill on the violin, and his hot tem-
per. He is said to have once challenged 13 officers to duels, provided
that after each victory he would be allowed to play to the loser a piece
on his violin. The elder Bolyai is reported to have been buried at his
own request under an apple tree, with no monument, to commemorate
history's three most famous apples: the apple of Eve, the golden apple
Non-Euclidean Geometry 177
Paris gave Venus as a beauty-contest prize, and the falling apple that in-
spired Isaac Newton.
Before the 19th century had ended it became clear that the parallel
postulate not only was independent of the others but also that it could
be altered in two opposite ways. If it was replaced (as Gauss, Bolyai,
and Lobachevski had proposed) by assuming an infinite number of "ul-
traparallel" lines through the point, the result would be a new geome-
try just as elegant and as "true" as Euclid's. All Euclid's other postulates
remain valid; a "straight" line is still a geodesic, or shortest line. In this
hyperbolic space all triangles have an angle sum less than 180 degrees,
and the sum decreases as triangles get larger. All similar polygons are
congruent. The circumference of any circle is greater than pi times the
diameter. The measure of curvature of the hyperbolic plane is negative
(in contrast to the zero curvature of the Euclidean plane) and every-
where the same. Like Euclidean geometry, hyperbolic geometry gener-
alizes to 3-space and all higher dimensions.
The second type of non-Euclidean geometry, which Klein names "el-
liptic," was later developed simultaneously by the German mathe-
matician Georg Friedrich Bernhard Riemann and the Swiss
mathematician Ludwig SchHifli. It replaces the parallel postulate with
the assumption that through the point no line can be drawn parallel to
the given line. In this geometry the angle sum of a triangle is always
more than 180 degrees, and the circumference of a circle is always less
than pi times the diameter. Every geodesic is finite and closed. The
lines in every pair of geodesics cross.
To prove consistency for the two new geometries various Euclidean
models of each geometry were found showing that if Euclidean geom-
etry is consistent, so are the other two. Moreover, Euclidean geometry
has been "arithmetized," proving that if arithmetic is consistent, so too
is Euclid's geometry. We now know, thanks to Kurt G6del, that the con-
sistency of arithmetic is not provable in arithmetic, and although there
are consistency proofs for arithmetic (such as the famous proof by Ger-
hard Gentzen in 1936), no such proof has yet been found that can be
considered entirely constructive by an intuitionist (see A. Calder, "Con-
structive Mathematics," Scientific American, October 1979). God ex-
ists, someone once said, because mathematics is consistent, and the
Devil exists because we are not able to prove it.
The various metaproofs of arithmetic's consistency, as Paul C. Rosen-
bloom has put it, may not have eliminated the Devil, but they have re-
178 SOLID GEOMETRY AND HIGHER DIMENSIONS
179
though they are unaware of any change because all their measuring in-
struments Similarly get smaller. At the boundary their size would be-
come zero, but they can never reach the boundary. If they proceed
toward it with uniform velocity, their speed (to us) steadily decreases,
although to them it seems constant. Thus their universe, which we see
as being finite, is to them infinite. Hyperbolic light follows geodesics,
but because its velocity is proportional to its distance from the bound-
ary it takes paths that we see as circular arcs meeting the boundary at
right angles.
In this hyperbolic world a triangle has a maximum finite area, as is
shown in Figure 14.2, although its three "straight" sides go to infinity
in hyperbolic length and its three angles are zero. You must not think
of Escher's mosaic as being laid out on a sphere. It is a circle enclosing
an infinity of fish-Coxeter calls it a "miraculous draught"-that get
progressively smaller as they near the circumference. In the hyperbolic
plane, of which the picture is only a model, the fish are all identical in
size and shape. It is important to remember that the creatures of a hy-
perbolic world would not change in shape as they moved about, light
would not change in speed, and the universe would be infinite in all
directions.
figure 14.2.
The curved white lines in Escher's woodcut do not, as many people
have supposed, model hyperbolic geodesics. The lines are called
equidistant curves or hypercycles. Each line has a constant perpendic-
ular distance (measured hyperbolically) from the hyperbolic straight
line that joins the arc's ends. Note that along each white curve fish of
the same color swim head to tail. If you consider all the points where
180 SOLID GEOMETRY AND HIGHER DIMENSIONS
four fins meet, these points are the vertexes of a regular tiling of the hy-
perbolic plane by equilateral triangles with angles of 45 degrees. The
centers of the triangles are the points where three left fins meet and
three mouths touch three tails. The 45-degree angles make it possible
for eight triangles to surround each vertex, where in a Euclidean tiling
by equilateral triangles only six triangles can surround each vertex.
Escher and Coxeter had corresponded from the time they met in
1954, and Escher's interest in tilings of the hyperbolic plane had been
aroused by the illustrations in a 1957 paper on crystal symmetry that
Coxeter had written and sent to him. In a lovely article titled "The
Non-Euclidean Symmetry of Escher's Picture 'Circle Limit III' " (in the
journal Leonardo, Vol. 12, 1979, pp. 19-25) Coxeter shows that each
white arc meets the boundary at an angle of almost 80 degrees. (The
precise value is 27/4 + 25/4 arc secants.) Coxeter considers Circle Limit
III the most mathematically sophisticated of all Escher's pictures. It
even anticipated a discovery Coxeter did not make until five years after
the woodcut was finished!
Elliptic geometry is roughly modeled by the surface of a sphere. Here
Euclidean straight lines become great circles. Clearly no two can be
parallel, and it is easy to see that triangles formed by arcs of great cir-
cles must have angles that add up to more than two right angles. The
hyperbolic plane is similarly modeled by the saddle-shaped surface of
a pseudosphere, generated by rotating a tractrix about its asymptote.
It is a misuse of the word "crank" to apply it to mathematicians who
erred in thinking, before the independence of the parallel postulate
was established, that they had proved the postulate. The same cannot
be said of those amateurs of later decades who could not understand
the proofs of the postulate's independence or who were too egotistical
to try. Augustus De Morgan, in his classic compendium of eccentric
mathematics, A Budget of Paradoxes, introduces us to Britain's most in-
defatigable 19th-century parallel-postulate prover, General Perronet
Thompson. Thompson kept issuing revisions of his many proofs (one
was based on the equiangular spiral), and although De Morgan did his
best to dissuade him from his futile efforts, he was unsuccessful.
Thompson also wanted to replace the tempered scale of the piano with
an octave of 40 notes.
The funniest of the American parallel-postulate provers was the Very
Reverend Jeremiah Joseph Callahan, then president of Duquesne Uni-
versity in Pittsburgh. In 1931, when Father Callahan announced he
Non-Euclidean Geometry 181
had trisected the angle, Time gave the story sober treatment and ran his
photograph. The following year Callahan published his major work,
Euclid or Einstein: A Proof of the Parallel Theory and a Critique of
MetageometIY(Devon-Adair, 1932), a 31D-page treatise in which he as-
cended to heights of argumentem ad hominem. Einstein is "fuddled,"
he "has not a logical mind," he is in a "mental fog," he is a "careless
thinker." "His thought staggers, and reels, and stumbles, and falls, like
a blind man rushing into unknown territory." "Sometimes one feels
like laughing," Callahan wrote, "and sometimes one feels a little irri-
tated .... But there is no use expecting Einstein to reason."
What Callahan found so irritating was Einstein's adoption of a gen-
eralized non-Euclidean geometry, formulated by Riemann, in which
the curvature of physical space varies from point to point depending on
the influence of matter. One of the great revolutions brought about by
relativity theory was the discovery that an enormous overall simplifi-
cation of physics is obtained by assuming physical space to have this
kind of non-Euclidean structure.
It is now commonplace (how astonished, and I think delighted, Kant
would have been by the notion!) to recognize that all geometric systems
are equally "true" in the abstract but that the structure of physical space
must be determined empirically. Gauss himself thought of triangulat-
ing three mountain peaks to see if their angles added up to two right an-
gles. It is said he actually made such a test, with inconclusive results.
Although experiments can prove physical space is non-Euclidean, it is
a curious fact that there is no way to prove it is Euclidean! Zero curva-
ture is a limiting case, midway between elliptic and hyperbolic curva-
tures. Since all measurement is subject to error, the deviation from zero
could always be too slight for detection.
Poincare held the opinion that if optical experiments seemed to show
physical space was non-Euclidean, it would be best to preserve the
simpler Euclidean geometry of space and assume that light rays do not
follow geodesics. Many mathematicians and physicists, including Rus-
sell, agreed with Poincare until relativity theory changed their mind.
Alfred North Whitehead was among the few whose mind was never
changed. He even wrote a book on relativity, now forgotten, in which
he argued for preserving a Euclidean universe (or at least one of con-
stant curvature) and modifying the physical laws as necessary. (For a
discussion of Whitehead's controversy with Einstein, see Robert M.
182 SOLID GEOMETRY AND HIGHER DIMENSIONS
Palter's Whitehead's Philosophy of Science, University of Chicago
Press, 1960.)
Physicists are no longer disturbed by the notion that physical space
has a generalized non-Euclidean structure. Callahan was not merely
disturbed; he was also convinced that all non-Euclidean geometries
are self-contradictory. Einstein, poor fellow, did not know how easy it
is to prove the parallel postulate. If you are curious about how Callahan
did it, and about his elementary error, see D. R. Ward's paper in The
Mathematical Gazette (Vol. 17, May 1933, pp. 101-4).
Like their cousins who trisect the angle, square the circle, and find
simple proofs of Fermat's last theorem, the parallel-postulate provers
are a determined breed. A more recent example is William 1. Fischer
of Munich, who in 1959 published a 100-page Critique of Non-
Euclidean Geometry. Ian Stewart exposed its errors in the British jour-
nal Manifold (No. 12, Summer 1972, pp. 14-21). Stewart quotes from
a letter in which Fischer accuses establishment mathematicians of sup-
pressing his great work and orthodox journals of refusing to review it:
"The university library at Cambridge refused even to put my booklet on
file .... I had to write to the vice-chancellor to overcome this boycott."
There are, of course, no sharp criteria for distinguishing crank math-
ematics from good mathematics, but then neither are there sharp crite-
ria for distinguishing day from night, life from non-life, and where the
ocean ends and the shore begins. Without words for parts of continu-
ums we could not think or talk at all. If you, dear reader, have a way to
prove the parallel postulate, don't tell me about it!
Addendum
Imagine a small circle around the north pole of the earth. If it
keeps expanding, it reaches a maximum size at the equator, after which
it starts to contract until it finally becomes a point at the south pole. In
similar fashion, an expanding sphere in four-dimensional elliptical
space reaches a maximum size, then contracts to a point.
In addition to the three geometries described in this chapter, there is
what Bolyai called "absolute geometry" in which theorems are true in
all three. It is astonishing that the first 28 theorems of Euclid's Ele-
ments are in this category, along with other novel theorems that Bolyai
showed to be independent of the parallel postulate.
Non-Euclidean Geometry 183
I was surprised to see in a 1984 issue of Speculations in Science and
Technology (VoL 7, pp. 207-16), a defense of Father Callahan's proof of
the parallel postulate! The authors are Richard Hazelett, vice president
of the Hazelett Strip-Casting Corporation, Colchester, VT, and Dean E.
Thrner, who teaches at the University of North Colorado, in Greeley.
Hazelett is a mechanical engineer with master's degrees from the Uni-
versity of Texas and Boston University. Taylor, an ordained minister in
the Disciples of Christ Church, has a doctorate from the University of
Texas.
It is easy to understand why both men do not accept Einstein's gen-
eral theory of relativity. Indeed, they have edited a book of papers at-
tacking Einstein. Titled The Einstein Myth and the Ives Papers, it was
published in 1979 by Devin-Adair.
In an earlier column on geometrical fallacies, reprinted in Wheels,
Life, and Other Mathematical Amusements (1983), I discussed in detail
Father Callihan's false "proof" of the parallel postulate. For other false
proofs, see Underwood Dudley's book cited in the bibliography.
In the Encyclopaedia Britannica's tenth edition Bertrand Russell con-
tributed an article on "Geometry, Non-Euclidean." It was revised for the
eleventh edition (1910) with Whitehead's name added as coauthor.
They argued that at present, on grounds of simplicity, if an experiment
ever contradicted Euclidean geometry it would be preferable to ques-
tion the experiment rather than give up Euclidean geometry. Of course
they wrote this before relativity theory proved otherwise. Poincare's ob-
jection to non-Euclidean geometry was unqualified. Russell changed
his mind in the light of relativity theory, but if Whitehead ever changed
his mind I've been unable to find evidence for it.
Bibliography
R. BonoIa, Non-Euclidean Geometry, Open Court, 1912; Dover, 1955.
E. Breitenberger, "Gauss's Geodesy and the Axiom of Parallels," Archive for History
of Exact Sciences, Vol. 31, 1984, pp. 273-89.
H.S.M. Coxeter, Regular Compound Tessellations of the Hyperbolic Plane, Pro-
ceedings of the Royal Society, A, VoL 278, 1964, pp. 147-67.
H.S.M. Coxeter, Non-Euclidean Geometry, 5e, University of Toronto Press, 1965.
H. S.M. Coxeter, The Non-Euclidean Symmetry of Escher's Picture 'Circle Limit III. '
Leonardo, Vol. 12, 1979, pp. 19-25.
U. Dudley, Euclid's Fifth Postulate, Mathematical Cranks, Mathematical Associa-
tion of America, 1992, pp. 137-58.
184 SOLID GEOMETRY AND HIGHER DIMENSIONS
S. Gindikin, The Wonderland of Poincaria, Quantum, November/December 1992,
pp.21-28.
S. H. Gould, The Origin of Euclid's Axioms, Mathematical Gazette, Vol. 46, De-
cember, 1962, pp. 269-90.
M. J. Greenberg, Euclidean and Non-Euclidean Geometries: Development and His-
tory, 3e, W. H. Freeman, 1994.
S. Kulczycki, Non-Euclidean Geometry, Macmillan, 1961.
W. W. Maiers, Introduction to Non-Euclidean Geometry, Mathematics Teacher, No-
vember 1964, pp. 457-61.
R. M. Palter, Whitehead's Philosophy of Science, University of Chicago Press, 1960.
Reviewed by Adolf Griinbaum in The Philosophy Review, Vol. 71, April 1962.
D. Pedoe, Non-Euclidean Geometry, New Scientist, No. 219, January 26,1981, pp.
206-7.
J. F. Rigby, Some Geometrical Aspects of a Maximal Three-Coloured Triangle-Free
Graph, Journal of Combinatorial Theory, Series B, Vol. 34, June 1983, pp.
313-22.
D.M.Y. Sommerville, The Elements of Non-Euclidean Geometry, Dover, 1958.
J. W. Withers, Euclid's Parallel Postulate: Its Nature, Validity, and Place in Geo-
metrical Systems, Open Court, 1905.
H. E. Wolfe, Non-Euclidean Geometry, Henry Holt, 1945.
Non-Euclidean Geometry 185
N
Symmetry
Chapter 15 Rotations
and Reflections
A geometric figure is said to be symmetrical if it remains un-
changed after a "symmetry operation" has been performed on it. The
larger the number of such operations, the richer the symmetry. For ex-
ample, the capital letter A is unchanged when reflected in a mirror
placed vertically beside it. It is said to have vertical symmetry. The
capital B lacks this symmetry but has horizontal symmetry: it is un-
changed in a mirror held horizontally above or below it. S is neither
horizontally nor vertically symmetrical but remains the same if rotated
180 degrees (twofold symmetry). All three of these symmetries are pos-
sessed by H, I, 0, and X. X is richer in symmetry than H or I because,
if its arms cross at right angles, it is also unchanged by quarter-turns
(fourfold symmetry). 0, in circular form, is the richest letter of all. It is
unchanged by any type of rotation or reflection.
Because the earth is a sphere toward the center of which all objects
are drawn by gravity, living forms have found it efficient to evolve
shapes that possess strong vertical symmetry combined with an obvi-
ous lack of horizontal or rotational symmetry. In making objects for his
use man has followed a similar pattern. Look around and you will be
struck by the number of things you see that are essentially unchanged
in a vertical mirror: chairs, tables, lamps, dishes, automobiles, air-
planes, office buildings-the list is endless. It is this prevalence of ver-
tical symmetry that makes it so difficult to tell when a photograph has
been reversed, unless the scene is familiar or contains such obvious
clues as reversed printing or cars driving on the wrong side of the road.
On the other hand, an upside-down photograph of almost anything is
instantly recognizable as inverted.
The same is true of works of graphic art. They lose little, if anything,
by reflection, but unless they are completely nonrepresentational no
189
careless museum director is likely to hang one upside down. Of course,
abstract paintings are often inverted by accident. The New York Times
Magazine (October 5, 1958) inadvertently both reversed and inverted a
picture of an abstraction by Piet Mondrian, but only readers who knew
the painting could possibly have noticed it. In 1961, at the New York
Museum of Modern Art, Matisse's painting, Le Bateau, hung upside
down for 47 days before anyone noticed the error.
So accustomed are we to vertical symmetry, so unaccustomed to see-
ing things upside down, that it is extremely difficult to imagine what
most scenes, pictures, or objects would look like inverted. Landscape
artists have been known to check the colors of a scene by the undigni-
fied technique of bending over and viewing the landscape through their
legs. Its upside-down contours are so unfamiliar that colors can be seen
uncontaminated, so to speak, by association with familiar shapes.
Thoreau liked to view scenes this way and refers to such a view of a
pond in Chapter 9 of Walden. Many philosophers and writers have
found symbolic meaning in this vision of a topsy-turvy landscape; it
was one of the favorite themes of G. K. Chesterton. His best mystery sto-
ries (in my opinion) concern the poet-artist Gabriel Gale (in The Poet
and the Lunatics), who periodically stands on his hands so that he can
"see the landscape as it really is: with the stars like flowers, and the
clouds like hills, and all men hanging on the mercy of God. "
The mind's inability to imagine things upside down is essential to
the surprise produced by those ingenious pictures that turn into some-
thing entirely different when rotated 180 degrees. Nineteenth-century
political cartoonists were fond of this device. When a reader inverted
a drawing of a famous public figure, he would see a pig or jackass or
something equally insulting. The device is less popular today, although
Life for September 18, 1950, reproduced a remarkable Italian poster on
which the face of Garibaldi became the face of Stalin when viewed up-
side down. Children's magazines sometimes reproduce such upside-
down pictures, and now and then they are used as advertising
gimmicks. The back cover of Life for November 23,1953, depicted an
Indian brave inspecting a stalk of corn. Thousands of readers probably
failed to notice that when this picture was inverted it became the face
of a man, his mouth watering at the sight of an open can of corn.
I know of only four books that are collections of upside-down draw-
ings. Peter Newell, a popular illustrator of children's books who died
in 1924, published two books of color plates of scenes that undergo
190 SYMMETRY
amusing transformations when inverted:
Topsys and Turvys Number 2 (1894). In 1946 a London publisher is-
a faces drawn by Rex
an ............... " ...... 0..;, ......... in 1
richly symmetrical title
15.1.}
(Its title page reproduced in
on page
invertible book
The technique upside-down drawing was carried to unbelievable
heights a
he a six-panel color cornie for the Sunday of
One took the panels in order, reading the cap-
one the page upside down and
reverse to
achieve continuity by means of two chief characters called Little Lady
Old Man
o ; ; ; . . , - , ~ ........... mad surpasses all understanding. A collection of 25 of
his comics was published by G. W. Dillingham in 1905 under the
of
cause it
a Au..uL '-AU 'U U. "."..1
and Reflections 191
Figure 1S.2. A typical upside-down cartoon by Gustave Verbeek
century Swiss painter Matthaus Merian that becomes a man's profile
when the picture is given a quarter-turn counterclockwise. The rab-
bit-duck in Figure 15.3 is the best-known example of a quarter-turn
picture. Psychologists have long used it for various sorts of testing.
Harvard philosopher Morton White once reproduced a rabbit-duck
drawing in a magazine article to symbolize the fact that two historians
can survey the same set of historical facts but see them in two essen-
tially different ways.
Our lifelong conditioning in the way we see things is responsible for
a variety of startling upside-down optical illusions. All astronomers
know the necessity of viewing photographs of the moon's surface so
that sunlight appears to illuminate the craters from above rather than
below. We are so unaccustomed to seeing things illuminated from
below that when such a photograph of the moon is inverted, the craters
instantly appear to be circular mesas rising above the surface. One of
the most amusing illusions of this same general type is shown in Fig-
ure 15.4. The missing slice of pie is found by turning the picture upside
down. Here again the explanation surely lies in the fact that we almost
always see plates and pies from above and almost never from below.
Upside-down faces could not be designed, of course, if it were not for
192 SYMMETRY
Figure 15.3. A quarter-turn clockwise
makes the duck into a rabbit.
Figure 15.4. Where is the missing slice?
the fact that our eyes are not too far from midway between the top of
the head and the chin. School children often amuse themselves by
turning a history book upside down and penciling a nose and mouth on
the forehead of some famous person.
When this is done on an actual face, using eyebrow pencil and lip-
stick, the effect becomes even more grotesque. It was a popular party
pastime of the late 19th century. The following account is from an old
book entitled What Shall We Do Tonight?
The severed head always causes a sensation and should not be suddenly
exposed to the nervous .... A large table, covered with a cloth suffi-
ciently long to reach to the floor all around and completely hide all be-
neath, is placed in the center of the room .... A boy with soft silky hair,
rather long, being selected to represent the head, must lie upon his back
under the table entirely concealed, excepting that portion of his face
above the bridge of his nose. The rest is under the tablecloth.
His hair must now be carefully combed down, to represent whiskers,
and a face must be painted ... upon the cheeks and forehead; the false
eyebrows, nose and mouth, with mustache, must be strongly marked
with black water color, or India ink, and the real eyebrows covered with
a little powder or flour. The face should also be powdered to a deathlike
pallor ....
The horror of this illusion may be intensified by having a subdued
light in the room in which the exhibition has been arranged. This
conceals in a great degree any slight defects in the "making-up" of the
head ....
Needless to add, the horror is heightened when the "head" suddenly
opens its eyes, blinks, stares from side to side, wrinkles its cheeks (fore-
head).
The physicist Robert W. Wood (author of How to Tell the Birds from
the Flowers) invented a funny variation of the severed head. The face
is viewed upside down as before, but now it is the forehead, eyes, and
Rotations and Reflections 193
nose that are covered, leaving only the mouth and chin exposed. Eyes
and nose are drawn on the chin to produce a weird little pinheaded
creature with a huge, flexible mouth. The stunt was a favorite of Paul
Winchell, the television ventriloquist. He wore a small dummy's body
on his head to make a figure that he called Ozwald, while television
camera techniques inverted the screen to bring Ozwald right side up.
In 1961 an Ozwald kit was marketed for children, complete with the
dummy's body and a special mirror with which to view one's own face
upside down.
It is possible to print or even write in longhand certain words in
such a way that they possess twofold symmetry. The Zoological Soci-
ety of San Diego, for instance, publishes a magazine called ZOONOOZ,
the name of which is the same upside down. The longest sentence of
this type that I have come across is said to be a sign by a swimming pool
designed to read the same when viewed by athletes practicing hand-
stands: NOW NO SWIMS ON MON. (See Figure 15.5.)
----
. " . ~ . " .. -
I' f ~
, I'/., ...r-
1 \ ~ __
I.... -
sketch reproduced by courtesy of the artist, John McClellan
Figure 15.5. An invertible sign
It is easy to form numbers that are the same upside down. As many
have noticed, 1961 is such a number. It was the first year with twofold
symmetry since 1881, the last until 6009, and the twenty-third since the
year 1. Altogether there are 38 such years between A.D. 1 and A.D. 10000
(according to a calculation made by John Pomeroy), with the longest in-
terval between 1961 and 6009. J. F. Bowers, writing in the Mathemati-
194
SYMMETRY
cal Gazette for December 1961, explains his clever method of calculat-
ing that by A.D. 1000000 exactly 198 invertible years will have passed.
The January 1961 issue of Mad featured an upside-down cover with the
year's numerals in the center and a line predicting that the year would
be a mad one.
Some numbers, for example 7734 (when the 4 is written so that it is
open at the top), become words when inverted; others can be written
to become words when reflected. With these quaint possibilities in
mind, the reader may enjoy tackling the following easy problems:
1. Oliver Lee, age 44, who lives at 312 Main Street, asked the city to
give his car a license plate bearing the number 337-31770. Why?
2. Prove the sum in Figure 15.6 to be correct.
3 4 I 4 Figure 15.6. Is the sum correct?
340
74813
43374813
3. Circle six digits in the group below that will add up to exactly 21.
1
3
5
9
1
3
5
9
1
3
5
9
4. A basket contains more than half a dozen eggs. Each egg is either
white or brown. Let x be the number of white eggs, and y be the num-
ber of brown. The sum of x and y, turned upside down, is the product
of x and y. How many eggs are in the basket?
Addendum
George Carlson, art editor of John Martin's Book, a monthly
magazine for children that flourished in the 1920s, contributed some
dozen upside-down pictures to the magazine. Many other examples
can be found in several books on optical illusions and related pictures
by England's Keith Kay. In 1980 Lothrop published The Turn About,
Think About, Look About Book, by Beau Gardner. It features pictures
to be viewed both upside down and after quarter-turns.
Rotations and Reflections 195
90 to lanlosca}:)e 90
to
196
three swans on a lake. Their reflections in the water are three elephants.
The landscape is reproduced in color in Richard Gregory's book on
mirrors, Mirrors in Mind (1997).
Landscapes that turn into faces when rotated 90 degrees were popu-
lar among German painters of the Renaissance. Two examples are re-
produced in Figure 15.7.
Answers
1. The number 337-31770 upside down spells "Ollie Lee."
2. Hold the sum to a mirror.
3. Turn the picture upside down, circle three 6's and three 1 's to
make a total of 21.
4. The basket has nine white eggs and nine brown eggs. When the
sum, 18, is inverted, it becomes 81, the product. Had it not been spec-
ified that the basket contained more than six eggs, three white and
three brown would have been another answer.
Rotations and Reflections 197
Chapter 16 The Amazing
Creations of Scott Kim
Scott Kim's Inversions, published in 1981 by Byte Publications,
is one of the most astonishing and delightful books ever printed. Over
the years Kim has developed the magical ability to take just about any
word or short phrase and letter it in such a way that it exhibits some
kind of striking geometrical symmetry. Consider Kim's lettering of my
name in Figure 16.1. Turn it upside down and presto! It remains exactly
the same!
Students of curious wordplay have long recognized that short words
can be formed to display various types of geometrical symmetry. On the
Rue Mozart in Paris a clothing shop called "New Man" has a large sign
lettered "NeW MaN" with the e and the a identical except for their ori-
entation. As a result the entire sign has upside-down symmetry. The
names VISTA (the magazine of the United Nations Association).
ZOONOOZ (the magazine of the San Diego zoo) and NISSIN (a Japan-
ese manufacturer of camera flash equipment) are all cleverly designed
so that they have upside-down symmetry.
BOO HOO, DIOXIDE, EXCEEDED, and DICK COHEN DIED 10 DEC
1883 all have mirror symmetry about a horizontal axis. If you hold
them upside down in front of a mirror, they appear unchanged. One
day in a supermarket my sister was puzzled by the name on a box of
crackers, "spep oop," until she realized that a box of "doo dads" was on
the shelf upside down. Wallace Lee, a magician in North Carolina, liked
198
to amuse friends by asking if they had ever eaten any "ittaybeds," a
word he printed on a piece of paper like this:
1 ...... aLlbeds
After everyone said no, he would add:
"Of course, they taste much better upside down."
Many short words in conventional typefaces turn into other words
when they are inverted. MOM turns into WOW and "up" becomes the
abbreviation "dn." SWIMS remains the same. Other words have mirror
symmetry about a vertical axis, such as "bid" (and "pig" if the g is
drawn as a mirror image of the p). Here is an amusing way to write
"minimum" so that it is the same when it is rotated 180 degrees:
o 0
o 0
It is Kim who has carried this curious art of symmetrical calligraphy
to heights not previously known to be possible. By ingeniously dis-
torting letters, yet never so violently that one cannot recognize a word
or phrase, Kim has produced incredibly fantastic patterns. His book is
a collection of such wonders, interspersed with provocative observa-
tions on the nature of symmetry, its philosophical aspects, and its em-
bodiment in art and music as well as in wordplay.
Kim is no stranger to my Scientific American columns. He is of Ko-
rean descent, born in the U.S., who in 1981 was doing graduate work
in computer science at Stanford University. He was in his teens when
he began to create highly original problems in recreational mathemat-
ics. Some that have been published in Scientific American include his
"lost-king tours" (April 1977), the problem of placing chess knights on
the corners of a hypercube (February 1978), his solution to "boxing a
box" (February 1979), and his beautifully symmetrical "m-pire map"
given in Chapter 6 of my Last Recreations. In addition to a remarkable
ability to think geometrically (not only in two and three dimensions but
also in 4-space and higher spaces) Kim is a classical pianist who for
years could not decide between pursuing studies in mathematics or in
music. In the early 1980s he was intensely interested in the use of com-
The Amazing Creations of Scott Kim 199
puters for designing typefaces, a field pioneered by his friend and men-
tor at Stanford, the computer scientist Donald E. Knuth.
For several years Kim's talent for lettering words to give them unex-
pected symmetries was confined to amusing friends and designing fam-
ily Christmas cards. He would meet a stranger at a party, learn his or her
name, then vanish for a little while and return with the name neatly
drawn so that it would be the same upside down. His 1977 Christmas
card, with upside-down symmetry, is shown in Figure 16.2. (Lester
and Pearl are his father and mother; Grant and Gail are his brother and
sister.) The following year he found a way to make "Merry Christmas,
1978," mirror-symmetrical about a horizontal axis, and in 1979 he
made the mirror axis vertical. (See Figures 16.3 and 16.4.)
Figure '6.2.
For a wedding anniversary of his parents Kim designed a cake with
chocolate and vanilla frosting in the pattern shown in Figure 16.5.
("Lester" is in black, "Pearl" is upside down in white.) This is Kim's
"figure and ground" technique. You will find another example of it in
Godel, Escher, Bach: An Eternal Golden Braid, the Pulitzer-prize-
winning book by Kim's good friend Douglas R. Hofstadter. Speaking of
200 SYMMETRY
Figure 16.3.
Figure 16.S
Figure 16.6.
o o
Kurt Gade!, J. S. Bach, and M. C. Escher, Figure 16.6 shows how Kim
has given each name a lovely mirror symmetry. In Figure 16.7 Kim has
lettered the entire alphabet in such a way that the total pattern has
left-right symmetry.
Kim's magic calligraphy came to the attention of Scot Morris, an ed-
itor at Omni. Morris devoted a page of his popular column on games to
Kim's work in Omni's September 1979 issue, and he announced a
reader's contest for similar patterns. Kim was hired to judge the thou-
sands of entries that came in. You will find the beautiful prizewinners
in Omni's April 1980 issue and close runners-up in Morris' columns for
May and November of the same year.
All the patterns in Kim's book are his own. A small selection of a few
The Amazing Creations of Scott Kim 201
}l3CDEf\
GltB
1 M r
pq
mr
1JJW
r_e'6.7. ~
Figure 16.8.
lIfJlQi
202
m!<bE _Dltdll
(ommu N+N
nimtia) V16IY1ON
infinityinfinUy
infinityinfinUy
infinityinfinUy
SYMMETRY
more is given in Figure 16.8 to convey some notion of the amazing va-
riety of visual tricks Kim has up his sleeve.
I turn now to two unusual mathematical problems originated by Kim,
both of which are still only partly solved. In 1975, when Kim was in
high school, he thought of the following generalization of the old prob-
lem of placing eight queens on a chessboard so that no queen attacks
another. Let us ask, said Kim, for the maximum number of queens that
can be put on the board so that each queen attacks exactly n other
queens. As in chess, we assume that a queen cannot attack through an-
other queen.
When n is 0, we have the classic problem. Kim was able to prove that
when n is 1, 10 queens is the maximum number. (A proof is in Journal
a/Recreational Mathematics, Vol. 13, No.1, 1980-81, p. 61.) A pleasing
solution is shown in Figure 16.9 top. The middle illustration shows a
maximal solution of 14 queens when n is 2, a pattern Kim described in
a letter as being "so horribly asymmetric that it has no right to exist."
There are only conjectures for the maximum when n is 3 or 4. Kim's best
result of 16 queens for n = 3 has the ridiculously simple solution shown
in Figure 16.9, bottom, but there is no known proof that 16 is maxi-
mum. For n = 4 Kim's best result is 20 queens. Can you place 20 queens
on a chessboard so each queen attacks exactly four other queens?
The problem can of course be generalized to finite boards of any size,
but Kim has a simple proof based on graph theory that on no finite
board, however large, can n have a value greater than 4. For n = 1 Kim
has shown that the maximum number of queens cannot exceed the
largest integer less than or equal to 4k13, where k is the number of
squares along an edge of the board. For n = 2 he has a more difficult
proof that the maximum number of queens cannot exceed 2k - 2, and
that this maximum is obtainable on all even-order boards.
Kim's problem concerning polycube snakes has not previously been
published, and he and I would welcome any light that readers can
throw on it. First we must define a snake. It is a single connected chain
of identical unit cubes joined at their faces in such a way that each cube
(except for a cube at the end of a chain) is attached face to face to ex-
actly two other cubes. The snake may twist in any possible direction,
provided no internal cube abuts the face of any cube other than its two
immediate neighbors. The snake may, however, twist so that any num-
ber of its cubes touch along edges or at corners. A polycube snake may
be finite in length, having two end cubes that are each fastened to only
The Amazing Creations of Scott Kim 203
figure 16.9.
:00
II
n - 1
n=2
f--
OJ r--
I
n-3
one cube, or it may be finite and closed so that it has no ends. A snake
may also have just one end and be infinite in length, or it may be infi-
nite and endless in both directions.
We now ask a deceptively simple question. What is the smallest
number of snakes needed to fill all space? We can put it another way.
Imagine space to be completely packed with an infinite number of unit
cubes. What is the smallest number of snakes into which it can be dis-
sected by cutting along the planes that define the cubes?
If we consider the two-dimensional analogue of the problem (snakes
made of unit squares), it is easy to see that the answer is two. We sim-
ply intertwine two spirals of infinite one-ended flat snakes, one gray,
one white, as in Figure 16.10.
204
SYMMETRY
16.10.
how fill
O.L.J..C:LI. ..... 'C:)O is not so easily answered. a
four infinitely long one-ended snakes (it is convenient of
as a interlocked
helical shapes that fill all space.
plain in a limited space; you will have to take my
with two! "A solution with only two snakes," he wrote a letter,
a yin-yang symbol:
space left one snake
beauty of such an entwining, and the possibility a .............. , ..............
large enough me searching for a solution."
can course
cubes any number of dimensions. Kim has a
space of n dimensions the minimum number of snakes that completely
fill it
I once
John Horton Conway, the Cambridge mathematician now
When I Kim had not yet shown that
Conway
stared into three-space for a minute or two, then exclainled,
vious!"
notob-
I no idea through I can only
that if the impossibility of filling three-space with two snakes is not
obvious to Conway or to Kim, it probably is not obvious to anyone
The ...,. ............ ..., ..... ..> of Kim 205
16.1 I.
see a
David Morice published this two-stanza "poem" in Wordways (No-
vember 1987, p. 235).
DICK HID
CODEBOOK+
DOBIE KICKED
HOBQ-OH HECK-I DECIDED
I EXCEEDED ID-I BOXED
HICK-ODD DODO-EH KID
DEBBIE CHIDED-HOCK CHECKBOOK
ED-BOB BEDDED CHOICE CHICK
HO HQ-HE ECHOED-OH OH
DOBIE ICED HOODED IBEX
I COOKED OXHIDE COD
EDIE HEEDED COOKBOOK +
ED
DECKED
BOB
To read the second stanza, hold the poem upside down in front of a
mirror.
Donald Knuth, Ronald Graham, and Oren Patashnik, in their mar-
velous book Concrete Mathematics (the word is a blend of Continuous
and Discrete mathematics), published by Addison-Wesley in 1989, in-
troduce their readers to the "umop-apisdn" function. Rotate the word
180 degrees to see what it means in English.
One conjecture about the origin of the expression "Mind your ps and
qs" is that printers often confused the two letters when they were in
lower case. A more plausible theory is that British tavern owners had
to mind their pints and quarts.
In his autobiography Arrow in the Blue, Arthur Koestler recalls meet-
ing many science cranks when he was a science editor in Berlin. One
was a man who had invented a new alphabet. Each letter had fourfold
rotational symmetry. This, he proclaimed, made it possible for four
people, seated on the four sides of a table, to simultaneously read a
book or newspaper at the table's center.
Have you heard about the dyslexic atheist who didn't believe in dog?
Or D.A.M.N., an organization of National Mothers Against Dyslexia?
I could easily write another chapter about the amazing Scott Kim. He
received his Ph.D. in Computers and Graphic Design, at Stanford Uni-
The Amazing Creations of Scott Kim 207
versity, working under Donald Knuth. At a curious gathering of mathe-
maticians, puzzle buffs, and magicians in Atlanta in 1995, Kim demon-
strated how your fingers can model the skeleton of a tetrahedron and a
cube, and how they can form a trefoil knot of either handedness. He also
played an endless octave on a piano, each chord rising up the scale yet
never going out of hearing range, and proved he could whistle one tune
and hum another at the same time. During the Atlanta gathering, he
and his friends Karl Schaffer and Erik Stern of the Dr. Schaffer & Mr.
Stern Dance Ensemble presented a dance performance titled "Dances for
the Mind's Eye." Choreographed by the three performers, the perfor-
mance was based throughout on mathematical symmetries.
Among books illustrated by Kim are my Aha! Gotcha (W. H. Free-
man, 1982) and Han Vardi's Illustrated Computational Recreations in
Mathematica (Addison-Wesley, 1991). Together with Ms. Robin Samel-
son, Kim produced Letterform and illusion, a computer disk with an ac-
companying 48-page book of programs designed for use with Claris's
MacPaint. In 1994 Random House published Kim's Puzzle Workout, a
collection of 42 brilliant puzzles reprinted from his puzzle column in
New Media Magazine. It is the only book of puzzles known to me in
which every single puzzle is totally original with the author.
Scott Kim's queens problem brought many letters from readers who
sent variant solutions for n = 2,3, and 4 on the standard chessboard, as
well as proofs for maximum results and unusual ways to vary the prob-
lem. The most surprising letters came from Jeffrey Spencer, Kjell
Rosquist, and William Rex Marshall. Spencer and Rosquist, writing in
1981, each independently bettered by one Kim's 20-queen solution for
n = 4 on the chessboard. Figure 16.12 shows how each placed 21
queens. It is not unique. Writing in 1989 from Dunedin, New Zealand,
Marshall sent 36 other solutions!
Marshall also went two better than Kim's chessboard pattern for n =
3. He sent nine ways that 18 queens can each attack three others on the
chessboard. The solution shown in Figure 16.13 is of special interest be-
cause only three queens are not on the perimeter. Marshall found a sim-
ple pigeonhole proof that for the order-8 board, n = 4, 21 queens is
indeed maximum. His similar proof shows 18 maximum for n = 3. More
generally, he showed that for n = 4, with k the order of the board, the
maximum is 3k- 3 for k greater than 5. When n = 3, Marshall proved that
the maximum number of queens is the largest even number less than or
208
SYMMETRY
66.12.
41
I t
I
i
i
........
... L_ .... _ 16.13
- 4)/5. n = 2, found
p lies to all boards than 2, not just to boards of even
Perhaps it is worth noting that when n = 4, no queen can occupy a
corner
.................................. sent a n ..... L.LL .............
sider the topmost queen in the leftmost occupied row. At the most it
can
a
independently obtained the same results, as
obtained by William They were published in a paper ti-
Math-
264-71.
In 1996 I received a second letter from William Marshall. He sent me
the provided complete
=1
K N=l N=2 N=3 N=4
3 0 4 2 0
4 5 2 4 0
5 0 1 31 0
6 2 1 304 (307) 1
7 138 (149) 5 2 3
8 47 (49) 2 9 40
9 1 15 755 655
3
Figun 16.14.
of Scott 209
16.15.
n 2, k= 5 n= 2, k=6 n=4. k=6
n=1,k=9
n 2, k= 8
n=3. k=9
210
16.18.
of 211
Chapter 17
What I give form to in daylight is only one
percent of what I've seen in darkness.
-M. C. ESCHER
The Art of
M. C. Escher
There is an obvious but superficial sense in which certain
kinds of art can be called mathematical art. Op art, for instance, is
"mathematical," but in a way that is certainly not new. Hard-edged,
rhythmic, decorative patterns are as ancient as art itself, and even the
modern movement toward abstraction in painting began with the geo-
metric forms of the cubists. When the French Dadaist painter Hans Arp
tossed colored paper squares in the air and glued them where they fell,
he linked the rectangles of cubism to the globs of paint slung by the
later "action" painters. In a broad sense even abstract expressionist art
is mathematical, since randomness is a mathematical concept.
This, however, expands the term "mathematical art" until it becomes
meaningless. There is another and more useful sense of the term that
refers not to techniques and patterns but to a picture's subject matter.
A representational artist who knows something about mathematics can
build a composition around a mathematical theme in the same way
that Renaissance painters did with religious themes or Russian painters
do with political themes. No living artist has been more successful
with this type of "mathematical art" than Maurits C. Escher of the
Netherlands.
"I often feel closer to mathematicians than to my fellow artists," Es-
cher has written, and he has been quoted as saying, "All my works are
games. Serious games." His lithographs, woodcuts, wood engravings,
and mezzotints can be found hanging on the walls of mathematicians
and scientists in all parts of the world. There is an eerie, surrealist as-
pect to some of his work, but his pictures are less the dreamlike fan-
tasies of a Salvador Dali or a Rene Magritte than they are subtle
philosophical and mathematical observations intended to evoke what
the poet Howard Nemerov, writing about Escher, called the "mystery,
212
absurdity, and sometimes terror" of the world. Many of his pictures
concern mathematical structures that have been discussed in books on
recreational mathematics, but before we examine some of them, a word
about Escher himself.
He was born in Leeuwarden in Holland in 1898, and as a young man
he studied at the School of Architecture and Ornamental Design in
Haarlem. For 10 years he lived in Rome. After leaving Italy in 1934 he
spent two years in Switzerland and five in Brussels, then settled in the
Dutch town of Baarn where he and his wife lived until his death in
1972. Although he had a successful exhibit in 1954 at the Whyte
Gallery in Washington, he was much better known in Europe than here.
A large collection of his work is now owned by the National Gallery of
Art in Washington, D.C.
Among crystallographers Escher is best known for his scores of in-
genious tessellations of the plane. Designs in the Alhambra reveal how
expert the Spanish Moors were in carving the plane into periodic rep-
etitions of congruent shapes, but the Mohammedan religion forbade
them to use the shapes of living things. By slicing the plane into jigsaw
patterns of birds, fish, reptiles, mammals, and human figures, Escher
has been able to incorporate many of his tessellations into a variety of
startling pictures.
In Reptiles, the lithograph shown in Figure 17.1, a little monster
crawls out of the hexagonal tiling to begin a brief cycle of 3-space life
that reaches its summit on the dodecahedron; then the reptile crawls
back again into the lifeless plane. In Day and Night, the woodcut in Fig-
ure 17.2, the scenes at the left and the right are not only mirror images
but also almost "negatives" of each other. As the eye moves up the cen-
ter, rectangular fields flow into interlocking shapes of birds, the black
birds flying into daylight, the white birds flying into night. In the cir-
cular wood-cut Heaven and Hell (Figure 17.3) angels and devils fit to-
gether, the similar shapes becoming smaller farther from the center and
finally fading into an infinity of figures, too tiny to be seen, on the rim.
Good, Escher may be telling us, is a necessary background for evil, and
vice versa. This remarkable tessellation is based on a well-known Eu-
clidean model, devised by Henri Poincare, of the non-Euclidean hy-
perbolic plane; the interested reader will find it explained in H.S.M.
Coxeter's Introduction to Geometry (Wiley, 1961), pages 282-90.
If the reader thinks that patterns of this kind are easy to invent, let
him try it! "While drawing I sometimes feel as if I were a spiritualist
The Art of M. C. Escher 213
Ill.
11.2.
214
2000 Cordon Art B.V.-Baam-Holland. All
lGVllit:l:i. 1l.th()griapJl. 1943
Mickelson
and wooaC:llt. 1938
reserved.
' ~ J . Heaven
2000 Cordon Art B.V.-Baarn-Holland. All
\ ..1> ...1\ ....."" ....., .... 1960
reserved.
215
the International Union of Crystallography, reproduces 41 of Escher's
tessellations, many in full color.
Figures 17.4 and 17.5 illustrate another category of Escher's work, a
play with the laws of perspective to produce what have been called
"impossible figures." In the lithograph Belvedere, observe the sketch of
the cube on a sheet lying on the checked floor. The small circles mark
two spots where one edge crosses another. In the skeletal model held
by the seated boy, however, the crossings occur in a way that is not re-
alizable in 3-space. The belvedere itself is made up of impossible struc-
tures. The youth near the top of the ladder is outside the belvedere but
the base of the ladder is inside. Perhaps the man in the dungeon has
lost his mind trying to make sense of the contradictory structures in his
world.
The lithograph Ascending and Descending derives from a perplexing
impossible figure that first appeared in an article, "Impossible Objects:
A Special Type of Visual Illusion," by L. S. Penrose, a British geneticist,
and his son, the mathematician Roger Penrose (British Journal of Psy-
chology, February 1958). The monks of an unknown sect are engaged
in a daily ritual of perpetually marching around the impossible stair-
way on the roof of their monastery, the outside monks climbing, the in-
side monks descending. "Both directions," comments Escher, "though
not without meaning, are equally useless. Two refractory individuals
refuse to take part in this 'spiritual exercise.' They think they know bet-
ter than their comrades, but sooner or later they will admit the error of
their nonconformity."
Many Escher pictures reflect an emotional response of wonder to the
forms of regular and semiregular solids. "In the midst of our often
chaotic society," Escher has written, "they symbolize in an unrivaled
manner man's longing for harmony and order, but at the same time
their perfection awes us with a sense of our own helplessness. Regular
polyhedrons have an absolutely nonhuman character. They are not in-
ventions of the human mind, for they existed as crystals in the earth's
crust long before mankind appeared on the scene. And in regard to the
spherical shape--is the universe not made up of spheres?"
The lithograph Order and Chaos (Figure 17.6) features the "small
stellated dodecahedron," one of the four "Kepler-Poinsot polyhedrons"
that, together with the five Platonic solids, make up the nine possible
"regular polyhedrons." It was first discovered by Johannes Kepler, who
called it "urchin" and drew a picture of it in his Harmonices mundi
216 SYMMETRY
11.4.
The
2000 Cordon Art D.V.-Baam-Holland. All
reserved.
217
11.5.
218
2000 Gordon Art B.V.-Ba.a.rn-Holland. All
.. .. .......,,'-'JOi.i .......... ,LA..1960
reserved.
2000 Cordon Art B.V.-Baam-Holland. All
L .. 1950
reserved.
219
220
III Hand with
1935
All any person can possibly know about the world is derived from
what enters his skull through various sense organs; there is a sense in
which one never experiences anything except what lies within the cir-
cle of his own sensations and ideas. Out of this "phenomenology" he
constructs what he believes to be the external world, including those
other people who appear to have minds in egocentric predicaments
like his own. Strictly speaking, however, there is no way he can prove
that anything exists except himself and his shifting sensations and
thoughts. Escher is seen staring at his own reflection in the sphere.
The glass mirrors his surroundings, compressing them inside one per-
fect circle. No matter how he moves or twists his head, the point mid-
way between his eyes remains exactly at the center of the circle. "He
cannot get away from that central point," says Escher. "The ego re-
mains immovably the focus of his world."
Escher's fascination with the playthings of topology is expressed in
a number of his pictures. At the top of the woodcut Knots (Figure 17.8)
we see the two mirror-image forms of the trefoil knot. The knot at top
left is made with two long flat strips that intersect at right angles. This
double strip was given a t w ~ s t before being joined to itself. Is it a sin-
gle one-sided band that runs twice around the knot, intersecting itself,
or does it consist of two distinct but intersecting Mobius bands? The
large knot below the smaller two has the structure of a four-sided tube
that has been given a quarter-twist so that an ant walking inside, on one
of the central paths, would make four complete circuits through the
knot before it returned to its starting point.
The wood engraving Three Spheres (Figure 17.9), a copy of which is
owned by New York's Museum of Modern Art, appears at first to be a
sphere undergoing progressive topological squashing. Look more care-
fully, however, and you will see that it is something quite different. Can
the reader guess what Escher, with great verisimilitude, is depicting here?
Addendum
When Escher died in 1972, at the age of 73, he was just begin-
ning to become world-famous; not only among mathematicians and
scientists (who were the first to appreciate him), but also with the pub-
lic at large, especially with the young counterculture. The Escher cult
is still growing. You see his pictures everywhere: on the covers of math-
ematical textbooks, on albums of rock music, on psychedelic posters
The Art of M. C. Escher 221
2000 Cordon Art B.V.-Baam-HoHand. All rights reserved.
11.8. Knots, woodcut, 1965
glow under black light, even on T-shirts. When I
an my
can ran one on cover) J I purchased from Es-
only one print, a woodcut. For a mere I
pictures that now
fame?
222 SYMMETRY
223
Bibliography
This highly selective list of references is limited to books and
articles in English. For an extensive bibliography, including foreign
references and motion pictures, see Visions of Symmetry, the definitive
work on Escher by Doris Schattschneider.
H.S.M. Coxeter, "Angels and Devils," The Mathematical Gardner, D. Klarner (ed.),
Wadsworth,1981.
H.S.M. Coxeter et al. (eds.), M. C. Escher: Art and Science, Elsevier, 1986.
H.S.M. Coxeter, "The Trigonometry of Escher's Woodcut 'Circle Limit 1lI,' " The
Mathematical Intelligencer, Vol. 18, No.4, 1996, pp. 42-46.
B. Ernst. The Magic Mirror ofM. C. Escher, Random House, 1976; Ballantine, 1976.
M. C. Escher, Escher on Escher, Abrams, 1989. (Translated by Karin Ford.)
L. Glasser, "Teaching Symmetry," The Journal of Chemical Education, Vol. 44, Sep-
tember 1967, pp. 502-11.
J. L. Locher (ed.), The World of M. C. Escher, Abrams, 1971.
J. L. Locher (ed.), M. C. Escher: His Life and Complete Graphic Work, Abrams,
1982. Reviewed by H.S.M. Coxeter in The Mathematical Intelligencer, Vol. 7, No.
1,1985,pp.59-69.
C. H. MacGillavry, Symmetry Aspects of M. C. Escher's Periodic Drawings, A. Oost-
hoek's Uitgeversmaatschappij NV, 1965. Reprinted as Fantasy and Symmetry-
The Periodic Drawings of M. C. Escher, Abrams, 1976
H. Nemerov, "The Miraculous Transformations of Maurits Cornelis Escher,"
Artists's Proof, Vol. 3, Fall/Winter 1963-64, pp. 32-39.
E. R. Ranucci, "Master of Tesselations: M. C. Escher, 1898-1972," Mathematics
Teacher, Vol. 67, April 1974, pp. 299-306.
J. C. Rush, "On the Appeal ofM. C. Escher's Pictures," Leonardo, Vol. 12, 1979, pp.
48-50.
D. Schattschneider, "The P61ya Escher Connection," Mathematics Magazine, VoL
60, December 1987, pp. 293-98.
D. Schattschneider, Visions of Symmetry, W. H. Freeman, 1990.
D. Schattschneider, "Escher's Metaphors," Scientific American, November 1994,
pp.66-71.
D. Schattschneider and W. Walker, M. C. Escher: Kaleidocyc1es, Ballantine, 1977;
revised edition, Pomegranate Artbooks, 1987.
M. Severin, "The Dimensional Experiments of M. C. Escher," Studio, February
1951, pp. 50-53.
J. L. Teeters, "How to Draw Tesselations of the Escher Type," Mathematics Teacher,
VoL 67, April 1974, pp. 307-10.
M. L. Teuber, "Sources of Ambiguity in the Prints of Maurits C. Escher," Scientific
American, Vol. 231, July 1974, pp. 90-104. See also the correspondence on this
article in Vol. 232, January 1975, pp. 8-9.
K. Wilkie, "Escher: The Journey to Infinity," Holland Herald, Vol. 9, No.1, 1974,
pp.20-43.
224 SYMMETRY
V
Topology
Chapter 18 Klein Bottles
and Other Surfaces
Three jolly sailors from Blaydon-on-Tyne
They went to sea in a bottle by Klein.
Since the sea was entirely inside the hull
The scenery seen was exceedingly dull.
-Frederick Winsor,
The Space Child's Mother Goose
To a topologist a square sheet of paper is a model of a two-
sided surface with a single edge. Crumple it into a ball and it is still
two-sided and one-edged. Imagine that the sheet is made of rubber.
You can stretch it into a triangle or circle, into any shape you please,
but you cannot change its two-sidedness and one-edgedness. They are
topological properties of the surface, properties that remain the same
regardless of how you bend, twist, stretch, or compress the sheet.
Two other important topological invariants of a surface are its chro-
matic number and Betti number. The chromatic number is the maxi-
mum number of regions that can be drawn on the surface in such a way
that each region has a border in common with every other region. If
each region is given a different color, each color will border on every
other color. The chromatic number of the square sheet is 4. In other
words, it is impossible to place more than four differently colored re-
gions on the square so that any pair has a boundary in common. The
term "chromatic number" also designates the minimum number of col-
ors sufficient to color any finite map on a given surface. It is now
known that 4 is the chromatic number, in this map-coloring sense, for
the square, tube, and sphere, and for all other surfaces considered in
this chapter, the chromatic number is the same under both definitions.
The Betti number, named after Enrico Betti, a 19th-century Italian
physicist, is the maximum number of cuts that can be made without di-
viding the surface into two separate pieces. If the surface has edges,
each cut must be a "crosscut": one that goes from a point on an edge to
another point on an edge. If the surface is closed (has no edges), each
cut must be a "loop cut": a cut in the form of a simple closed curve.
Clearly the Betti number of the square sheet is O. A crosscut is certain
to produce two disconnected pieces.
227
le.l. a
IB.2. Torus sUIltace .......... " ............... a SQlllare
229
230
shows how the bottle is traditionally depicted. Imagine the lower end of
a tube stretched out, bent up, and plunged through the tube's side, then
joined to the tube's upper mouth. In an actual model made, say, of glass
there would be a hole where the tube intersects the side. You must dis-
regard this defect and think of the hole as being covered by a continua-
tion of the bottle's surface. There is no hole, only an intersection of
surfaces. This self-intersection is necessary because the model is in 3-
space. If we conceive of the surface as being embedded in 4-space, the
self-intersection can be eliminated entirely. The Klein bottle is one-sided,
no-edged, and has a Betti number of 2 and a chromatic number of 6.
Daniel Pedoe, a mathematician at the University of Minnesota, is the
author of The Gentle Art of Mathematics. It is a delightful book, but on
page 84 Professor Pedoe slips into a careless bit of dogmatism. He de-
scribes the Klein bottle as a surface that is a challenge to the glass
blower, but one "which cannot be made with paper." Now, it is true that
at the time he wrote this apparently no one had tried to make a paper
Klein bottle, but that was before Stephen Barr, a science-fiction writer
and an amateur mathematician of Woodstock, NY, turned his attention
to the problem. Barr quickly discovered dozens of ways to make paper
Klein bottles. Here I will describe a variation of my own that is made
from a paper tube. The tube can be a sealed envelope with its left and
right edges cut open.
The steps are given in Figure 18.4. First, make a tube by folding the
square in half and joining the right edges with a strip of tape as shown
(Step 1). Cut a slot about a quarter of the distance from the top of the
tube (Step 2), cutting only through the thickness of paper nearest you.
This corresponds to the "hole" in the glass model. Fold the model in
half along the broken line A. Push the lower end of the tube up through
the slot (Step 3) and join the edges all the way around the top of the
model (Step 4) as indicated by the arrows. It is not difficult to see that
this flat, square model is topologically identical with the glass bottle
shown in Figure 18.3. In one way it is superior: there is no actual hole.
True, you have a slot where the surface self-intersects, but it is easy to
imagine that the edges of the slot are joined so that the surface is every-
where edgeless and continuous.
Moreover, it is easy to cut this paper model and demonstrate many
of the bottle's astonishing properties. Its Betti number of 2 is demon-
strated by cutting the two loops formed by the two pairs of taped edges.
If you cut the bottle in half vertically, you get two Mobius bands, one
Klein Bottles and Other Surfaces 231
232
F
a
233
along the solid black lines shown in Step 1. Fold the square along the
diagonal A-A /, inserting slot C into slot B (Steps 2 and 3). You must
think of the line where the slots interlock as an abstract line of self-
intersection. Fold up the two bottom triangular flaps E and F, one on
each side (Step 4), and tape the edges as indicated.
The model is now what topologists call a cross-cap, a self-
intersecting Mobius strip with an edge that can be stretched into a cir-
cle without further self-intersection. This edge is provided by the edges
of cut D, originally made along the square's diagonal. Note that unlike
the usual model of a Mobius strip, this one is symmetrical: neither
right- nor left-handed. When the edge of the cross-cap is closed by tap-
ing it (Step 5), the model becomes a projective plane. You might expect
it to have a Betti number of 2, like the Klein bottle, but it does not. It
has a Betti number of 1. No matter how you loop-cut it, the cut pro-
duces either two pieces or a piece topologically equivalent to a square
sheet that cannot be cut again without making two pieces. If you re-
move a disk from anywhere on the surface of the projective plane, the
model reverts to a cross-cap.
Figure lB.7 summarizes all that has been said. The square diagrams
in the first column show how the edges join in each model. Sides ofthe
same color join each to each, with the direction of their arrows coin-
ciding. Corners labeled with the same letter are comers that come to-
gether. Broken lines are sides that remain edges in the finished model.
Next to the chromatic number of each model is shown one way the sur-
face can be mapped to accommodate the maximum number of colors.
It is instructive to color each sheet as shown, coloring the regions on
both sides of the paper (as though the paper were cloth through which
the colors soaked), because you must think of the sheet as having zero
thickness. An inspection of the final model will show that each region
does indeed border on every other one.
Addendum
Although I was not the first to model Klein bottles with paper
(credit for this goes to Stephen Barr-see bibliography), my contribu-
tion was to show how easily a model can be made from an envelope
and cut in half to make two Mobius strips of opposite handedness.
A simple way to demonstrate the one-sided property of a Klein bot-
tle is to punch a hole in a model and insert a piece of string. No matter
234 TOPOLOGY
BETTI
SURFACE CHROMATIC NUMBER SIDES EDGES NUMBER
A B
r-----....
~
I I
SQUARE
I I
(OR DISK)
I I
4 2 1 0
I I
I I
.... _____ ...l
C 0
A A
TUBE
[ I _ ~ ~ ]
4
~
2 2 1
B B
A B
SPHERE
D
4
B C
~
2 0 0
A B
[ ~ ~ ! ]
~
MOBIUS
6 3 4 5 3
STRIP
1 1 1
-
6 1
B A
A A
0 ~
7
1
TORUS 7 56 2 0 2
3
4
A A
A A
D ~
KLEIN
6 2 3
BOTTLE
1 0 2
4 6
A A
A B
PROJECTIVE [I ~ ) t[
1
5
6 21
3 t-- 1 0 1
PLANE
-E--
4
6
B A
Figure IB.7. Topological invariants of seven basic surfaces
Klein Bottles and Other Surfaces
235
where you make the hole, you can always tie the ends of the string to-
gether.
The Klein bottle continues to intrigue limerick writers. Here are three
I have encountered:
Topologists try hard to floor us
With a nonorientable torus.
The bottle of Klein
They say is divine
But it is so exceedingly porous.
-Anonymous
A geometrician named Klein
Thought the Mobius band asinine.
"Though its outside is in,
Still it's ugly as sin;
It ain't round like that bottle o'minef"
-M. M. H. Coffee and J. J. Zeltmacher, Jr.
An anti-strong-drinker named Klein
Invented a bottle for wine.
"There's no stopper," he cried,
"And it has no inside,
So the grapes have to stay on the vine!"
-James Albert Lindon
I confess that I have made use of a Klein bottle in two works of fic-
tion. Professor Slapenarski falls into a Klein bottle and disappears at
the end of my mathematically flawed story "The Island of Five Colors"
(you'll find it in Clifton Fadiman's anthology Fantasia Mathematica),
and again in my novel Visitors from Oz (1999) where it is used as a de-
vice for transporting Dorothy, Scarecrow, and Tin Woodman from Oz
(now in a parallel world) to Central Park in Manhattan.
If you would like to own a glass Klein bottle, a firm called Acme,
6270 Colby Street, Oakland, CA 94618, has five handsome glass Klein
bottles for sale, of various sizes, shapes, and prices. The firm can also
be reached on the Internet at www.kleinbottle.com.
Answers
The torus-cutting problem is solved by first ruling three paral-
leI lines on the unfolded square (see Figure 18.8), When the square is
236 TOPOLOGY
Figure 18.8. Solution to the torus-
cutting problem
folded into a torus, as explained, the lines make two closed loops. Cut-
ting these loops produces two interlocked bands, each two-sided with
two half-twists.
How does one find a loop cut on the Klein bottle that will change the
surface to a single Mobius strip? On both left and right sides of the nar-
row rectangular model described you will note that the paper is creased
along a fold that forms a figure-eight loop. Cutting only the left loop
transforms the model into a Mobius band; cutting only the right loop
produces an identical band of opposite handedness.
What happens if both loops are cut? The result is a two-sided, two-
edged band with four half-twists. Because of the slot the band is cut
apart at one point, so that you must imagine the slot is not there. This
self-intersecting band is mirror-symmetrical, neither right- nor left-
handed. You can free the band of self-intersection by sliding it carefully
out of the slot and taping the slot together. The handedness of the re-
sulting band (that is, the direction of the helices formed by its edges)
depends on whether you slide it out to the right or the left. This and the
previous cutting problems are based on paper models that were in-
vented by Stephen Barr and are described in his Experiments in Topol-
ogy (Crowell, 1964).
Bibliography
M. A. Armstrong, Basic Topology, Springer-Verlag, 1983.
B. H. Arnold, Intuitive Concepts in Elementary Topology, Prentice-Hall, 1962.
S. Barr, Experiments in Topology, Crowell, 1964.
W. G. Chinn and N. E. Steenrod, First Concepts o/Topology. Mathematical Associ-
ation of America, 1966.
Klein Bottles and Other Surfaces 237
F. H. Crowe, Introduction to Topology, Saunders, 1989.
G. K. Francis, A Topological Picture Book, Springer-Verlag, 1987.
D. W. Hall and G. L. Spencer, Elementary Topology, Wiley, 1955.
W. Lietzmann, Visual Topology, Chatto and Windus, 1965.
M. J. Mansfield, Introduction to Topology, Van Nostrand, 1963; Krieger, 1972.
W. S. Massey, Algebraic Topology: An Introduction, Harcourt, Brace, 1967.
B. Mendelsohn, Introduction to Topology, Blackie, 1963.
E. M. Patterson, Topology, Oliver and Boyd, 1956.
V. V. Prasolov, Intuitive Topology, Providence, Rl: American Mathematical Society,
1995.
I. Stewart, "The Topological Dressmaker," Scientific American, July 1993, pp.
110-12.
L Stewart, "Glass Klein Bottles," Scientific American, March 1998, pp. 100-1. See
also the note at the end of Stewart's December 1998 column.
I. Stewart, "Tangling With Topology," Scientific American, April 1999, pp. 123-24.
A. W. Tucker and H. S. Bailey, "Topology," Scientific American, January 1950, pp.
18-24.
R. L. Wilder, "Topology: Its Nature and Significance," Mathematics Teacher, Octo-
ber 1962, pp. 462-75.
238 TOPOLOGY
Chapter 19
"A knot!" said Alice, always ready to make
herself useful, and looking anxiously about
her. "Oh, do let me help to undo itl"
-Alice in Wonderland, Chapter 3
Knots
To a topologist knots are closed curves embedded in three-
dimensional space. It is useful to model them with rope or cord and to
diagram them as projections on a plane. If it is possible to manipulate
a closed curve-of course, it must not be allowed to pass through it-
self-so that it can be projected on a plane as a curve with no crossing
points then the knot is called trivial. In ordinary discourse one would
say the curve is not knotted. "Links" are two or more closed curves that
cannot be separated without passing one through another.
The study of knots and links is now a flourishing branch of topology
that interlocks with algebra, geometry, group theory, matrix theory,
number theory, and other branches of mathematics. Some idea of its
depth and richness can be had from reading Lee Neuwirth's excellent
article "The Theory of Knots" in Scientific American (June 1979). Here
we shall be concerned only with some recreational aspects of knat the-
ory: puzzles and curiosities that to be understood require no more than
the most elementary knowledge of the topic.
Let's begin with a question that is trivial but that can catch even
mathematicians off guard. Tie an overhand knot in a piece of rope as is
shown in Figure 19.1. If you think of the ends of the rope as being
joined, you have tied what knot theorists call a trefoil knot. It is the sim-
plest of all knots in the sense that it can be diagrammed with a mini-
mum of three crossings. (No knot can have fewer crossings except the
trivial knot that has none.) Imagine that end A of the rope is passed
through the loop from behind and the ends are pulled. Obviously the
knot will dissolve. Now suppose the end is passed twice through the
loop as is indicated by the broken line. Will the knot dissolve when the
ends of the rope are pulled?
Most people guess that it will form another knot. Actually the knot
239
Figure 19.1.
dissolves as before. The end must go three times through the loop to
produce another knot. If you try it, you will see that the new trefoil cre-
ated in this way is not the same as the original. It is a mirror image. The
trefoil is the simplest knot that cannot be changed to its mirror image
by manipulating the rope.
The next simplest knot, the only one with a minimum of four cross-
ings, is the figure eight at the right in Figure 19.1. In this form it is eas-
ily changed to its mirror image. Just turn it over. A knot that can be
manipulated to make its mirror image is called amphicheiral because
like a rubber glove it can be made to display either handedness. After
the figure eight the next highest amphicheiral knot has six crossings,
and it is the only 6-knot of that type. Amphicheiral knots become pro-
gressively scarcer as crossing numbers increase.
A second important way to divide knots into two classes is to dis-
tinguish between alternating and nonalternating knots. An alternating
knot is one that can be diagrammed so that if you follow its curve in ei-
ther direction, you alternately go over and under at the crossings. Al-
ternating knots have many remarkable properties not possessed by
nonalternating knots.
Still another important division is into prime and composite knots.
A prime knot is one that cannot be manipulated to make two or more
separated knots. For example, the square knot and the granny knot are
not prime because each can be changed to two side-by-side trefoils.
The square knot is the "product" of two trefoils of opposite handed-
240 TOPOLOGY
ness. The granny is the product of two trefoils of the same handed-
ness, and therefore (unlike the square knot) it is not amphicheiral. Both
knots are alternating. As an easy exercise, see if you can sketch a square
knot with six (the minimum) alternating crossings.
All prime knots of seven or fewer crossings are alternating. Among
the 8-knots only the three in Figure 19.2 are nonalternating. No matter
how long you manipulate a rope model of one of these knots, you will
never get it to lie flat in the form of an alternating diagram. The knot at
top right is a bowline. The bottom knot is a torus knot as explained
below.
Figure 19.2.
A fourth basic binary division of knots is into the invertible and non-
invertible. Imagine an arrow painted on a knotted rope to give a direc-
tion to the curve. If it is possible to manipulate the rope so that the
structure remains the same but the arrow points the other way, the knot
is invertible. Until the mid-1960s one of the most vexing unsolved
problems in knot theory was whether noninvertible knots exist. All
knots of seven or fewer crossings, and all but one 8-knot and four 9-
knots had earlier been found invertible by manipulating rope models.
It was in 1963 that Hale F. Trotter, now at Princeton University, an-
nounced in the title of a surprising paper "Non-invertible Knots Exist"
(Topology, Vol. 2, No.4, December 1963, pp. 275-80).
Trotter described an infinite family of pretzel knots that will not in-
vert. A pretzel knot is one that can be drawn, without any crossings, on
the surface of a pretzel (a two-hole torus). It can be drawn as shown in
Knots 241
Figure 19.3 as a two-strand braid that goes around two "holes," or it can
be modeled by the edge of a sheet of paper with three twisted strips. If
the braid surrounds just one hole, it is called a torus knot because it can
be drawn without crossings on the surface of a doughnut.
Figure 19.3.
Trotter found an elegant proof that all pretzel knots are noninvertible
if the crossing numbers for the three twisted strips are distinct odd in-
tegers with absolute values greater than 1. Positive integers indicate
braids that twist one way and negative integers indicate an opposite
twist. Later Trotter's student Richard L. Parris showed in his unpub-
lished Ph.D. thesis that the absolute values can be ignored provided the
signed values are distinct and that these conditions are necessary as
well as sufficient for noninvertible pretzels. Thus the simplest nonin-
vertible pretzel is the one shown. Its crossing numbers of 3, -3, and 5
make it an ll-knot.
It is now known that the simplest noninvertible knot is the am-
phicheiral 8-knot in Figure 19.4. It was first proved noninvertible by
Aldo Kawauchi in Proceedings o/the Japan Academy (Vol. 55, Series
A, No. 10, December 1979, pp. 399-402). According to Richard Hartley,
in "Identifying Non-invertible Knots" (Topology, Vol. 22, No.2, 1983,
pp. 137-45), this is the only noninvertible knot of eight crossings, and
there are only two such knots of nine crossings and 33 of 10. All 36 of
these knots had earlier been declared noninvertible by John Horton
Conway, but only on the empirical grounds that he had not been able
to invert them. The noninvertible knots among the more than 550 knots
with 11 crossings had not yet been identified.
In 1967 Conway published the first classification of all prime knots
with 11 or fewer crossings. (A few minor errors were corrected in a later
printing.) You will find clear diagrams for all prime knots through 10
crossings, and all links through nine crossings, in Dale Rolfsen's valu-
242 TOPOLOGY
Figure 19.4.
able 1990 book Knots and Links. There are no knots with 1 or 2 cross-
ings, one with 3, one with 4, two with 5, three with 6, seven with 7, 21
with 8 crossings, 49 with 9, 165 with 10, and 552 with 11, for a total of
801 prime knots with 11 or fewer crossings. At the time I write, the clas-
sification has been extended through 16 crossings.
There are many strange ways to label the crossings of a knot, then de-
rive an algebraic expression that is an invariant for all possible dia-
grams of that knot. One of the earliest of such techniques produces
what is called a knot's Alexander polynomial, named after the Ameri-
can mathematician James W. Alexander who discovered it in 1928.
Conway later found a beautiful new way to compute a "Conway poly-
nomial" that is equivalent to the Alexander one.
For the unknotted knot with no crossings the Alexander polynomial
is 1. The expression for the trefoil knot of three crossings is x
2
- X + 1,
regardless of its handedness. The figure-eight knot of four crossings
has the polynomial x
2
- 3x + 1. The square knot, a product of two tre-
foils, has an Alexander polynomial of (x
2
- x+ 1)2, the square of the tre-
foil's expression. Unfortunately, a granny knot has the same
polynomial. If two knot diagrams give different polynomials, they are
sure to be different knots, but the converse is not true. Two knots may
Knots 243
have the same polynomial yet not be the same. Finding a way to give
any knot an expression that applies to all diagrams of that knot, and
only that knot, is the major unsolved problem in knot theory.
Although there are tests for deciding whether any given knot is triv-
ial, the methods are complex and tedious. For this reason many prob-
lems that are easy to state are not easy to resolve except by working
empirically with rope models. For instance, is it possible to twist an
elastic band around a cube so that each face of the cube has an
under-over crossing as shown in Figure 19.5. To put it another way, can
you tie a cord around a cube in this manner so that if you slip the cord
off the cube, the cord will be unknotted?
Figure 19.5.
Note that on each face the crossing must take one of the four forms
depicted in the illustration. This makes 4
6
= 4,096 ways to wrap the
cord. The wrapping can be diagrammed as a 12-knot, with six pairs of
crossings, each pair of which can have one of four patterns. The prob-
lem was first posed by Horace W. Hinkle in Journal of Recreational
Mathematics in 1978. In a later issue (Vol. 12, No.1, 1979-80, pp.
60-62) Karl Scherer showed how symmetry considerations reduce the
number of essentially different wrappings to 128. Scherer tested each
wrapping empirically and found that in every case the cord is knotted.
This has yet to be confirmed by others, and no one has so far found a
simpler way to attack the problem. The impossibility of getting the de-
sired wrapping with an unknotted cord seems odd, because it is easy
to twist a rubber band around a cube to put the under-over crossings on
just two or four faces (all other faces being straight crossings), and
seemingly impossible to do it on just one face, three faces, or five faces.
One would therefore expect six to be possible, but apparently it is not.
It may also be impossible to get the pattern even if two, three, or four
rubber bands are used.
244 TOPOLOGY
Figure 19.6 depicts a delightful knot-and-link puzzle that was sent to
me by its inventor, Majunath M. Regde, then a mathematics student in
India. The rope's ends are tied to a piece of furniture, say a chair. Note
that the two trefoil knots form a granny. The task is to manipulate the
rope and ring so that the ring is moved to the upper knot as is indicated
by the broken line. All else must remain identical.
Figure 19.6.
It is easy to do if you have the right insight. Of course, the rope must
not be untied from the chair, nor are you allowed to open a knot and
pass the chair through it. It will help if you think of the ends of the rope
as being permanently fastened to a wall.
The trick of dissolving or creating knots by passing a person through
a loop was actually used by fake mediums in the days when it was
fashionable to relate psychic phenomena to the fourth dimension.
Knots in closed curves are possible only in 3-space. In 4-space all knots
dissolve. If you could toss an unknotted loop of rope to a creature in 4-
space, it could tie any knot in the loop and toss it back to you with the
knot permanently formed. There was a popular theory among physi-
cists who believed in spiritualism that mediums had the power to move
objects in and out of higher spaces. Some mediums, such as the Amer-
ican mountebank Renry Slade, exploited this theory by pretending to
put knots into closed loops of cord. Johann Karl F. Zollner, an Austrian
physicist, devoted an entire book to Slade and hyperspace. Its English
translation, Transcendental Physics (Arno Press, 1976), is worth read-
ing as striking testimony to the ease with which an intelligent physicist
can be gulled by a clever conjurer.
Knots 245
In another instance, psychic investigators William Cox and John
Richards exhibited a stop-action film that purported to show two
leather rings becoming linked and unlinked inside a fish tank. "Later
examination showed no evidence that the rings were severed in any
way," wrote National Enquirer when it reported this "miracle" on Oc-
tober 27,1981. I was then reminded of an old conjuring stage joke. The
performer announces that he has magically transported a rabbit from
one opaque box to another. Then before opening either box he says
that he will magically transport the rabbit back again.
It is easy, by the way, to fabricate two linked "rubber bands." Just
draw them linked on the surface of a baby's hollow rubber teething
ring and carefully cut them out. Two linked wood rings, each of a dif-
ferent wood, can be carved if you insert one ring into a notch cut into
a tree, then wait many years until the tree grows around and through
it. Because the trefoil is a torus knot, it too is easily cut from a teething
ring.
The trick I am about to describe was too crude for Slade, but less
clever mediums occasionally resorted to it. You will find it explained,
along with other knot-tying swindles, in Chapter 2 of Hereward Car-
rington's The Physical Phenomena of Spiritualism, Fraudulent and
Genuine (H. B. Turner & Co., Boston, 1907). One end of a very long
piece of rope is tied to the wrist of one guest and the other end is tied
to the wrist of another guest. After the seance, when the lights are
turned on, several knots are in the rope. How do they get there?
The two guests stand side by side when the lights go out. In the dark
the medium (or an accomplice) makes a few large coils of rope, then
passes them carefully over the head and body of one of the guests. The
coils lie flat on the floor until later, when the medium casually asks that
guest to step a few feet to one side. This frees the coils from the person,
allowing the medium to pull them into a sequence of tight knots at the
center of the rope. Stepping to one side seems so irrelevant to the phe-
nomenon that no one remembers it. Ask the guest himself a few weeks
later whether he changed his position, and he will vigorously and hon-
estly deny it.
Roger Penrose, the British mathematician and physicist, once
showed me an unusual trick involving the mysterious appearance of a
knot. Penrose invented it when he was in grade school. It is based on
what in crocheting, sewing, and embroidery is called a chain stitch.
Begin the chain by trying a trefoil knot at one end of a long piece of
246 TOPOLOGY
heavy cord or thin rope and hold it with your left hand as in step 1 in
Figure 19.7. With your right thumb and finger take the cord at A and
pull down a loop as in step 2. Reach through the loop, take the cord at
B, and pull down another loop (step 3). Again reach forward through
the lowest loop, take the cord at D, and pull down another loop (step
4). Continue in this way until you have formed as long a chain as pos-
sible.
Figure 19.7.
With your right hand holding the lower end of the chain, pull the
chain taut. Ask someone to select any link he likes and then pinch the
link between his thumb and forefinger. Pull on both ends of the cord.
All links dissolve, as expected, but when he separates his finger and
thumb, there is a tight knot at precisely the spot he pinched!
Joel Langer, a mathematician at Case Western Reserve University,
made a remarkable discovery. He found a way of constructing what he
calls "jump knots" out of stainless-steel wire. The wire is knotted and
then its ends are bonded. When it is manipulated properly, it can be
pressed flat to form a braided ring. Release pressure on the ring; tension
in the wire causes it to spring suddenly into a symmetrical three-
dimensional shape. It is now a frustrating puzzle to collapse the wire
back to its ring form.
In 1981 Langer and his associate Sharon O'Neil formed a company
they called Why Knots. It made and sold three handsome jump knots:
the Figure Eight, the Chinese Button Knot, and the Mathematician's
Loop. When you slide one of these wire knots out of its square enve-
lope, it pops into an elegant hanging ornament. The figure eight is the
easiest to put back into its envelope. The Chinese button knot (so called
because it is a form widely used in China for buttons on nightclothes)
is more difficult. The mathematician's loop is the most difficult.
Knots 247
These shapes make it easier to understand how the 18th-century
physicists could have developed a theory, respectable in its day, that
molecules are different kinds of knots into which vortex rings of ether
(today read "space-time") get themselves tied. Indeed, it was just such
speculation that led the Scottish physicist Peter Guthrie Tait to study
topology and conduct the world's first systematic investigation of knot
theory.
Addendum
Enormous advances in knot theory have been made since this
chapter was written in 1983, and knot theory is now one of the most ex-
citing and active branches of mathematics. Dozens of new polynomials
for classifying knots have been discovered. One is called the Homfly
after the last initials of its six independent discoverers. The most sig-
nificant new expression is the Jones polynomial found in 1984 by the
New Zealand mathematician Vaughan F. R. Jones, now at the Univer-
sity of California, Berkeley. It has since been improved and generalized
by Louis Kauffman and others. Although these new polynomials are
surprisingly simple and powerful, no one has yet come up with an al-
gebraic technique for distinguishing all knots. Knots with different
polynomials are different, but it is still possible that two distinct knots
will have the same expression.
The Alexander polynomial does not decide between mirror-image
knots, and as we have seen, it does not distinguish the square knot
from the granny. The Jones polynomial provides both distinctions. So
far, it is not clear just why the Jones and the other new polynomials
work. "They're magic" is how Joan Birman, a knot expert at Barnard
College, put it.
The most amazing development in recent knot theory was the dis-
covery that the best way to understand the Jones polynomial was in
terms of statistical mechanics and quantum theory! Sir Michael Atiyah
now retired from the University of Edinburgh, was the first to see these
connections, then Edward Witten, at the Institute for Advanced Study
in Princeton, did the pioneer work in developing the connections. Knot
theory now has surprising applications to superstrings, a theory that ex-
plains basic particles by treating them as tiny loops, and to quantum
field theory. There is intense interaction between today's physicists
248 TOPOLOGY
and topologists. Discoveries in physics are leading to new discoveries
in topology, and vice versa. No one can predict where it will all lead.
Another unexpected application of knot theory is in broadening our
understanding of the structure and properties of large molecules such
as polymers, and especially the behavior of DNA molecules. DNA
strands can become horribly knotted and linked, unable to replicate
until they are untied or unlinked by enzymes called topoisom-erases.
To straighten out a DNA strand, enzymes have to slice them so they can
pass through themselves or another strand, then splice the ends to-
gether again. The number of times this must occur to undo a knot or
linkage of DNA determines the speed with which the DNA unknots or
unlinks.
There is a delightful three-color test for deciding if a knot diagram
represents a knot. Draw the diagram, then see if you can color its "arcs"
(portions of the line between two crossings) with three colors so that ei-
ther all three colors meet at each crossing or there is only one color at
each crossing, and provided at least one crossing shows all three col-
ors. If you can do this, the line is knotted. If you can't, the line mayor
may not be knotted. The three-coloring can also be used to prove that
two knots are different.
In 1908 the German mathematician Heinrich Tietze conjectured that
two knots are identical if and only if their complements-the topolog-
ical structure of the space in which they are embedded-are identical.
His conjecture was proved in 1988 by two American mathematicians,
Cameron M. Gordon and John E. Luecke. A knot's complement is a
structure in 3-space, in contrast to the knot which is one-dimensional.
Its topological structure is more complicated than the knot's, but of
course it contains complete information about the knot. The theorem
fails for links. Two links that are not the same can have identical com-
plements.
Associated with each knot's complement is a group. Like the poly-
nomials, which can be extracted from the group, two knots can have the
same group yet not be the same knots. An anonymous poet summed up
the situation this way in the British periodical Manifold (Summer
1972):
Knots
A knot and
another
249
knot may
not be the
same knot, though
the knot group of
the knot and the
other knot's
knot group
differ not; BUT
if the knot group
ofa knot
is the knot group
of the not
knotted
knot,
the knot is
not
knotted.
The American philosopher Charles Peirce, in a section on knots in
his New Elements of Mathematics (Volume 2, Chapter 4), shows how
the Borromean rings (three rings linked in such a way that although
they can't be separated, no two rings are linked) can be cut from a
three-hole torus. Peirce also shows how to cut the figure-eight knot
and the bowline knot from a two-hole torus.
Richard Parris called attention to the fact that not all of the 4,096
ways to wrap string around the cube, in the problem I posed, are knots.
Most of them are links of two, three, or four separate loops.
Conway has proved that if you draw a complete graph for seven
points located anywhere in space-that is, draw a line connecting each
pair of points-the lines will form at least one knot.
For the most recent results in knot theory there is now a Journal of
Knot Theory and Its Ramifications.
Answers
Figure 19.8 shows how a square knot can be changed to an al-
ternating knot of six crossings. Simply flip dotted arc a over to make
arc b.
Figure 19.9 shows one way to solve the ring-and-granny-knot puzzle.
First make the lower knot small, then slide it (carrying the ring with it)
250 TOPOLOGY
FigUI'e 19.8.
a
FigUI'e 19.9.
-,
'\
,
It,
I
I
/
--""
b c
up and through the higher knot (a). Open it. Two trefoil knots are now
side by side (b). Make the ringless knot small, then slide it through and
down the other knot. Open it up and you have finished (e).
Bibliography
Books
C. C. Adams, The Knot Book. W. H. Freeman, 1994.
M. Atiyah. The Geometry and Physics of Knots, Cambridge University Press, 1990.
R. H. Crowell and R. H. Fox, Introduction to Knot Theory, Blaisdell, 1963; Springer-
Verlag, 1977.
D. W. Fanner and T. B. Stanford, Knots and Surfaces, American Mathematical So-
ciety, 1998.
L. Kauffman, On Knots, Princeton University Press, 1987.
L. Kauffman, Knots and Physics, World Scientific, 1991.
T. Kohno, New Developments in the Theory of Knots, World Scientific, 1990.
C. Livingston, Knot Theory, Washington, DC: Mathematical Association of Amer-
ica, 1993.
K. Murasugi, Knot Theory and Its Applications, Birkhauser, 1999.
V. V. Pracolov, Knots, Links, Braids, and 3-Manifolds, Providence, RI: American
Mathematical Society, 1997.
D. Rolfsen, Knots and Links, Publish or Perish, 1976, Second edition, 1990.
J. c. Thrner and P. van de Griend, The History and Science of Knots, World Scien-
tific, 1996.
Knots 251
D.J.A. Walsh, Complexity Knots, Colourings and Counting, Cambridge University
Press, 1993.
Papers
Out of hundreds of papers on knot theory published since 1980,
I have selected only a few that have appeared since 1990.
C. C. Adams, "THings of Space by Knotted Tiles," Mathematical Intelligencer, Vol.
17, No.2, 1995, pp. 41-51.
P. Andersson "The Color Invariant for Knots and Links," American Mathematical
Monthly, Vol. 102, May 1995, pp. 442-48.
M. Atiyah, "Geometry and Physics," The Mathematical Gazette, March 1996, pp.
78-82.
J. S. Birman "Recent Developments in Braid and Link Theory," The Mathematical
Intelligencer, Vol. 13 1991, pp. 57-60.
B. Cipra, "Knotty Problems-and Real-World Solutions," Science, Vol. 255, Janu-
ary 24,1992, pp. 403-4.
B. Cipra, "From Knot to Unknot," What's Happening in the Mathematical Sci-
ences, Vol 2, 1994, pp. 8-13.
O. T. Dasbach and S. Hougardy, "Does the Jones Polynomial Detect Unknotted-
ness?" Experimental Mathematics, Vol. 6, 1997, pp. 51-56.
S. Harris and G. Quenell, "Knot Labelings and Knots Without Labelings." Mathe-
matical Intelligencer, Vol. 21, No.2, 1999, pp. 51-56.
B. Hayes, "Square Knots," American Scientist, November/December, 1997, pp.
506-10.
J. Haste, M. Thistlewaite, and J. Weeks, "The First 1,701,936 Knots," Mathemati-
cal Intelligencer, Vol. 20, No.4, 1998, pp. 33-48.
V. F. R. Jones, "Knot Theory and Statistical Mechanics," Scientific American, No-
vember 1990, pp. 98-103.
R. Matthews, "Knots Landing," New Scientist, February 1, 1997, pp. 42-43.
W. Menasco and 1. Rudolph, "How Hard is it to Untie a Knot?" American Scien-
tist, Vol. 83, January/February 1995, pp. 38-50.
I. Peterson, "Knotty Views," Science News, Vol. 141, March 21,1992, pp. 186-7.
A. Sosinsky, "Braids and Knots," Quantum, January/February 1995, pp. 11-15.
A. Sosinsky, "Knots, Links, and Their Polynomials," Quantum, July/August 1995,
pp.9-14.
I. Stewart, "Knots, Links and Videotape," Scientific American, January 1994, pp.
152-54.
D. W. Sumners, "Untangling DNA," The MathematicalIntelligencer, Vol. 12, 1990,
pp.71-80.
D. W. Sumners, "Lifting the Curtain: Using Topology to Probe the Hidden Action
of Enzymes," Notices of the American Mathematical Society, Vol. 42, May 1995,
pp.528-31.
O. Viro, "Tied Into Knot Theory," Quantum, May/June 1998, pp. 18-20.
252 TOPOLOGY
Knot Theory and Quantum Mechanics
M. Atiyah, The Geometry and Physics of Knots, Cambridge University Press, 1990.
M. L. Ge and C. N. Yang (eds), Braid Groups, Knot Theory and Statistical Mechan-
ics, World Scientific, 1989.
V. F. R. Jones, "Knot Theory and Statical Mechanics," Scientific American, No-
vember 1990, pp. 98-103.
E. Witten, "Quantum Field Theory and the Jones Polynomial," Communications in
Mathematical Physics, Vol. 1 2 ~ , No.3, 1989, pp. 351-99.
Knots 253
-ANON.
20.1. torus
254
with one handle, a cube with one hole through it, and so on. Think of
these surfaces as a thin membrane that can be stretched or compressed
as much as one wishes. Each can be deformed until it becomes a per-
fect toroidal surface. In what follows, "torus" will mean any surface
topologically equivalent to a torus.
A common misunderstanding about topology is the belief that a rub-
ber model of a surface can always be deformed in three-dimensional
space to make any topologically equivalent model. This often is not the
case. A Mobius strip, for example, has a handedness in 3-space that
cannot be altered by twisting and stretching. Handedness is an extrin-
sic property it acquires only when embedded in 3-space. Intrinsically
it has no handedness. A 4-space creature could pick up a left-handed
strip, turn it over in 4-space and drop it back in our space as a right-
handed modeL
A similar dichotomy applies to knots in closed curves. Tie a single
overhand (or trefoil) knot in a piece of rope and join the ends. The sur-
face of the rope is equivalent to a knotted torus. It has a handedness,
and no amount of fiddling with the rope can change the parity. Intrin-
sically the rope is not even knotted. A 4-space creature could take from
us an unknotted closed piece of rope and, without cutting it, return it
to us as knotted in either left or right form. All the properties of knots
are extrinsic properties of toruses (or, if you prefer, one-dimensional
curves that may be thought of as toruses whose meridians have shrunk
to points) that are embedded in 3-space.
It is not always easy to decide intuitively if a given surface in 3-space
can be elastically deformed to a different but topologically equivalent
surface. A striking instance, discussed nearly 50 years ago (see Albert
W. Tucker and Herbert S. Bailey, Jr., "Topology," Scientific American,
January 1950), concerns a rubber torus with a hole in its surface. Can
it be turned inside out to make a torus of identical shape? The answer
is yes. It is hard to do with a rubber model (such as an inner tube), but
a model made of wool reverses readily. Stephen Barr, in his Second
Miscellany of Puzzles (Macmillan, 1969), recommends making it from
a square piece of cloth. Fold the cloth in half and sew together oppo-
site edges to make a tube. Now sew the ends of the tube together to
make a torus that is square shaped when flattened. For ease in revers-
ing, the surface hole is a slot cut in the outer layer of cloth (shown by
the broken line in Figure 20.2).
After the cloth torus is turned inside out, it is exactly the same shape
Doughnuts: Linked and Knotted 255
2
3
)
J
I
\.)
20.2. torus
256
b
20.3. Torus and
257
Figure 20.4. Three varieties of a two-hole torus
Figure 20.5. R. H. Bing's proof
is moved over the cube's surface, as indicated by the arrows, dragging
the tube along with it. It goes left to the base of the other tube, climbs
that tube's side, moves to the right across the top of the cube, circles its
top hole counterclockwise, continues left around the other hole, over
the cube's front edge, down the front face, around the lower edge to the
cube's bottom face, and then across that face to the position it formerly
occupied. It is easy to see that the tube attached to this hole has been
untied. Naturally the procedure is reversible. If you had a sufficiently
pliable doughnut surface with two holes, you could manipulate it until
one hole became a knot tied around the other.
Topologists worried for decades about whether two separate knots
side by side on a closed rope could cancel each other; that is, could the
rope be manipulated until both knots dissolved? No pair of canceling
258 TOPOLOGY
knots had been found, but proving the impossibility of such a pair was
another matter. It was not even possible to show that two trefoil knots
of opposite handedness could not cancel. Proofs of the general case
were not found until the early 1950s. One way of proving it is ex-
plained by Ralph H. Fox in "A Quick Trip through Knot Theory," in
Topology of 3-Manifolds and Related Topics, edited by M. K. Fort, Jr.
(Prentice-Hall, 1963). It is a reductio ad absurdum proof that unfortu-
nately involves the sophisticated concept of an infinity of knots on a
closed curve and certain assumptions about infinite sets that must be
carefully specified to make the proof rigorous.
When John Horton Conway, a former University of Cambridge math-
ematician now at Princeton University, was in high school, he hit on a
simpler proof that completely avoids infinite sets of knots. Later he
learned that essentially the same proof had been formulated earlier,
but I have not been able to determine by whom. Here is Conway's ver-
sion as he explained it years ago in a letter. It is a marvelous example
of how a knotted torus can play an unexpected role in proving a fun-
damental theorem of modern knot theory.
Conway's proof, like the one for the infinite knots, is a reductio ad ab-
surdum. We begin by imagining that a closed string passes through the
opposite walls of a room (see Figure 20.6). Since we shall be concerned
only with what happens inside the room, we can forget about the string
outside and regard it as being attached to the side walls. On the string
are knots A and B. Each is assumed to be genuine in the sense that it
cannot be removed by manipulating the string if it is the only knot on
the string. It also is assumed that the two knots will cancel each other
when both are on the same closed curve. The proof applies to pairs of
knots of any kind whatever, but here we show the knots as simple tre-
foils of opposite parity. If the knots can cancel, it means that the string
can be manipulated until it stretches straight from wall to wall. Think
of the string as being elastic to provide all the needed slack for such an
operation. In the center figure we introduce an elastic torus around the
string. Note that the tube "swallows" knot A but "circumnavigates"
knot B (Conway's terminology). Any parallel drawn on this tube, on the
section between the walls, obviously must be knotted in the same way
as knot B. Indeed, it can be shown that any line on the tube's surface,
stretching from wall to wall and never crossing itself at any spot on the
tube's surface, will be knotted like knot B.
"Now," writes Conway, "comes the crunch." Perform on the string
Doughnuts: Linked and Knotted 259
A B
Figure 20.6. John Horton Conway's proof
the operation that we assumed would dissolve both knots. This can be
done without breaking the tube. Because the string is never allowed to
pass through itself during the deformation, we can always push the
tube's wall aside if it gets in the way. The third drawing in Figure 20.6
shows the final result. The string is unknotted. The tube may have
reached a horribly complicated shape impossible to draw. Consider a
vertical plane passing through the straight string and cutting the
twisted tube. We can suppose that the tube's cross section will look
something like what is shown with the possibility of various "islands,"
but there will necessarily be two lines, XYand MN, from wall to wall
that do not cross themselves at any point on the vertical plane. Each
line will be unknotted. Moreover, each line also is a curve that does not
cross itself on the tube's surface. As we have seen, all such lines were
(before the deformation) knotted like knot B. The deformation has
therefore removed a knot equivalent to knot B from each of these two
260 TOPOLOGY
20.1. "" LJ--J.'-LJ.J.O toruses
261
There are doughnuts and doughnuts
with knots and with no knots
and many a doughnut
so nuts that we know not.
Here are three more toroidally knotty questions.
1. How many closed curves can be drawn on a torus, each a trefoil knot
of the same handedness, so that no two curves cross each other at any
point?
2. If two closed curves are drawn on a torus so that each forms a trefoil
knot but the knots are of opposite parity, what is the minimum num-
ber of points at which the two curves will intersect each other?
3. Show how to cut a solid two-hole doughnut with one slice of a knife
so that the result is a solid outside-knotted torus. The "slice" is not,
of course, planar. More technically, show how to remove from a two-
hole doughnut a section topologically equivalent to a disk so that
what remains is a solid knotted torus. (This amusing result was dis-
covered by John Stallings in 1957 and communicated to me by James
Stasheff.)
Addendum
In studying the properties of topological surfaces, one must al-
ways keep in mind the distinction between intrinsic properties, inde-
pendent of the space in which the surface is embedded, and properties
that arise from the embedding. The "complement" of a surface con-
sists of all the points in the embedding space that are not in the surface.
For example, a torus with no knot, one with an outside knot, and one
with an inside knot all have identical intrinsic properties. No two have
topologically identical complements; hence, no two are equivalent in
their extrinsic topological properties.
John Stillwell, a mathematician at Monash University, Australia, sent
several fascinating letters in which he showed how an unknotted torus
with any number of holes-such toruses are equivalent to the surfaces
<;>f spheres with handles-could be turned inside out through a surface
hole. He was not sure whether a knotted torus, even with only one
hole, could be turned inside out through a hole in its surface.
Many beautiful, counterintuitive problems involving links and knots
in toruses have been published. See Rolfsen's book, cited in the bibli-
262 TOPOLOGY
20.8. can
ence
torus A?
on
are
two
263
2. Two topologists were discussing at lunch the two linked surfaces
shown at the left in Figure 20.10, which one of them had drawn on
a paper napkin. You must not think of these objects as solids, like
ropes or solid rubber rings. They are the surfaces of toruses, one sur-
face of genus 1 (one hole), the other of genus 2 (two holes).
Figure 20.10.
Thinking in the mode of "rubber-sheet geometry," assume that the
surfaces in the illustration can be stretched or shrunk in any desired
way provided there is no tearing or sticking together of separate parts.
Can the two-hole torus be deformed so that one hole becomes un-
linked as is shown at the right in the illustration?
Topologist X offers the following impossibility proof. Paint a ring
on each torus as is shown by the black lines. At the left the rings are
linked. At the right they are unlinked.
"You will agree," says X, "that it is impossible by continuous de-
formation to unlink two linked rings embedded in three-dimensional
space. It therefore follows that the transformation is impossible."
"But it doesn't follow at all," says Y.
Who is right? I am indebted to Herbert Taylor for discovering and
sending this mystifying problem.
3. Figure 20.11 depicts a familiar linkage known as the Borromean
rings. No two rings are linked, yet all three are linked. It is impossi-
ble to separate them without cutting at least one torus. Show how it
is possible for any number of toruses to form a linked structure even
though no two of them are linked.
4. Are the two structures shown in Figure 20.12 topologically the same?
That is, can one be transformed to the other by a continuous defor-
mation?
264 TOPOLOGY
figure 20.1 J.
an ... JLJ. ............ .LJl ................ can re-
versed through a hole to produce an externally knotted (see Fig-
13). to cover almost
to
its original size.
2D.13. to
in reversing the unknotted through a hole, the deformation
appears the same
......... A7'l"!."'V ........... that initially it is a parallel circling the torus's elongated hole,
whereas after the
no
Doughnuts: Linked Knotted 265
is now closed at both ends. As indicated by the arrow, the hole is now
surrounded by the knotted tube.
Piet Hein's two-hole torus, with an internal knot passing through an
external one, is easily shown to be the same as a two-haler with only
an external knot. Simply slide one end of the inside knot around the
outside knot (in the manner explained earlier) and back to its starting
point. This unties the internal knot. Piet Hein's two-haler, with the ex-
ternal knot going through a hole, can be unknotted by the deformation
shown in Figure 20.14.
5 6 7
Figure 20.14. Unknotting a two-hole torus
Answers to the first three toroidal questions are as follows:
1. An infinity of noncrossing closed curves, each knotted with the same
handedness, can be drawn on a torus (see Figure 20.15, top). If a
torus surface is cut along any of these curves, the result is a two-
sided, knotted band.
2. Two closed curves on a torus, knotted with opposite handedness,
will intersect each other at least 12 times.
3. A rotating slice through a solid two-hole doughnut is used to produce
a solid that is topologically equivalent to a solid, knotted torus (see
Figure 20.15, bottom). Think of a short blade as moving downward
and rotating one and a half turns as it descends. If the blade does not
turn at all, two solid toruses result. A half-turn produces one solid,
266 TOPOLOGY
8
b
J,,, ...u,u .... <:> ...... curves on a torus .. s..J..I., ......... ,;::O.1J. a
1.
267
The torus with the mouth can, however, swallow the other one so
that the eaten torus is inside in the first sense explained above. Fig-
ure 20.16 shows how it is done. In the process it is necessary for the
cannibal torus to turn inside out.
A good way to understand what happens is to imagine that torus
A is shrunk until it becomes a stripe of paint that circles B. Tum A
inside out through its mouth. The painted stripe goes inside, but in
Figure 20.16. How one torus eats another
268
1. Mouth starts
to open.
2. It lengthens to
an enonnous grin.
3. Grin widens until
torus becomes
two attached bands.
4. Horizontal band
enlarges, vertical
band shrinks.
5. Vertical band
widens and creeps
around victim.
6. Mouth closes.
TOPOLOGY
doing so it ends up circling B's hole. Expand the stripe back to a
torus and you have the final picture of the sequence.
2. Figure 20.17 shows how a continuous deformation of the two-hole
torus will unlink one of its holes from the single-hole torus. The ar-
gument for the impossibility of this task fails because if a ring is
painted around one hole (as is shown by the black line), the ring be-
comes distorted in such a way that after the hole is unlinked the
painted ring remains linked through the one-hole torus.
A B c
D E F
Figure 20.11.
For a mind-boggling selection of similar problems involving linked
toruses, see Herbert Taylor's article "Bicycle Tubes Inside Out," in
The Mathematical Gardner (Wadsworth, 1981), edited by David
Klarner.
3. Figure 20.18 shows a circular chain that obviously can be enlarged
to include any number of links. No two toruses are linked. If one
link is cut and removed, all the others are free of one another.
4. The two forms are topologically identical. To prove this, imagine the
linked form deformed to a sphere with two "handles" as shown in
Figure 20.19.
Now imagine the base of one handle being moved over the surface,
by shrinking the surface in front and stretching it in back, along the
path shown by the dotted line. This links the two handles. The struc-
ture is now easily altered to correspond with the linked form of the
toroids.
Doughnuts: Linked and Knotted 269
20.18.
20.19.
VI
Probability
Chapter 21 Probability
and Ambiguity
Charles Sanders Peirce once observed that in no other branch
of mathematics is it so easy for experts to blunder as in probability the-
ory. History bears this out. Leibniz thought it just as easy to throw 12
with a pair of dice as to throw 11. Jean Ie Rond d' Alembert, the great
18th-century French mathematician, could not see that the results of
tossing a coin three times are the same as tossing three coins at once,
and he believed (as many amateur gamblers persist in believing) that
after a long run of heads, a tail is more likely.
Today, probability theory provides clear, unequivocal answers to
simple questions of this sort, but only when the experimental proce-
dure involved is precisely defined. A failure to do this is a common
source of confusion in many recreational problems dealing with
chance. A classic example is the problem of the broken stick. If a stick
is broken at random into three pieces, what is the probability that the
pieces can be put together in a triangle? This cannot be answered with-
out additional information about the exact method of breaking to be
used.
One method is to select, independently and at random, two points
from the points that range uniformly along the stick, then break the
stick at these two points. If this is the procedure to be followed, the an-
swer is 1/4, and there is a neat way of demonstrating it with a geomet-
rical diagram. We draw an equilateral triangle, then connect the
midpoints of the sides to form a smaller shaded equilateral triangle in
the center (see Figure 21.1). If we take any point in the large triangle
and draw perpendiculars to the three sides, the sum of these three lines
will be constant and equal to the altitude of the large triangle. When
this point, like point A, is inside the shaded triangle, no one of the
three perpendiculars will be longer than the sum of the other two.
273
prC)baltJillty is 1/4
274
represent the smaller piece. In order for this line to be smaller than the
sum of the other two perpendiculars, the point where the lines meet
cannot be inside the small triangle at the top of the diagram. It must
range uniformly over the lower three triangles. The shaded triangle
continues to represent favorable points, but now it is only one-third the
area under consideration. The chances, therefore, are 1/3 that when
we break the larger piece, the three pieces will form a triangle. Since
our chance of picking the larger piece is 1/2, the answer to the original
question is the product of 1/2 and 1/3, or 1/6.
Geometrical diagrams of this sort must be used with caution because
they too can be fraught with ambiguity. For example, consider this
problem discussed by Joseph Bertrand, a famous French mathemati-
cian. What is the probability that a chord drawn at random inside a cir-
cle will be longer than the side of an equilateral triangle inscribed in the
circle?
We can answer as follows. The chord must start at some point on the
circumference. We call this point A, then draw a tangent to the circle
at A, as shown in the top illustration of Figure 21.2. The other end of
the chord will range uniformly over the circumference, generating an
infinite series of equally probable chords, samples of which are shown
on the illustration as broken lines. It is clear that only those chords that
cut across the triangle are longer than the side of the triangle. Since the
angle of the triangle at A is 60 degrees, and since all possible chords lie
within a 180-degree range, the chances of drawing a chord larger than
the side of the triangle must be 60/180, or 113.
Now let us approach the same problem a bit differently. The chord
we draw must be perpendicular to one of the circle's diameters. We
draw the diameter, then add the triangle as shown in the illustration at
bottom left of Figure 21.2. All chords perpendicular to this diameter
will pass through a point that ranges uniformly a] ong the diameter.
Samples of these chords are again shown as broken lines. It is not hard
to prove that the distance from the center of the circle to A is half the
radius. Let B mark the midpoint on the other side of the diameter. It is
now easy to see that only those chords crossing the diameter between
A and B will be longer than the side of the triangle. Since AB is half the
diameter, we obtain an answer to our problem of 1/2.
Here is a third approach. The midpoint of the chord will range uni-
formly over the entire space within the circle. A study of the illustra-
tion at bottom right of Figure 21.2 will convince you that only chords
Probability and Ambiguity 275
on it,
we draw the chord on which the fly is the midpoint. The probability
that this chord is longer than the side of the triangle is 1/4.
Each of these procedures is a legitimate method of obtaining a "ran-
dom chord." The problem as originally stated, therefore, is ambiguous.
It has no answer until the meaning of "draw a chord at random" is
made precise by a description of the procedure to be followed. Appar-
ently nothing resembling any of the three procedures is actually
adopted by most people when they are asked to draw a random chord.
In an interesting unpublished paper entitled "The Human Organism as
a Random Mechanism" Oliver L. Lacey, professor of psychology at the
University of Alabama, reports on a test which showed the probability
to be much better than 1/2 that a subject would draw a chord longer
than the side of the inscribed triangle.
Another example of ambiguity arises from a failure to specify the
randomizing procedure. Readers were told that Mr. Smith had two chil-
dren, at least one of whom was a boy, and were asked to calculate the
probability that both were boys. Many readers correctly pointed out
that the answer depends on the procedure by which the information "at
least one is a boy" is obtained. If from all families with two children,
at least one of whom is a boy, a family is chosen at random, then the an-
swer is 1/3. But there is another procedure that leads to exactly the
same statement of the problem. From families with two children, one
family is selected at random. If both children are boys, the informant
says "at least one is a boy. If both are girls, he says "at least one is a girl."
And if both sexes are represented, he picks a child at random and says
"at least one is a ... ," naming the child picked. When this procedure
is followed, the probability that both children are of the same sex is
clearly 1/2. (This is easy to see because the informant makes a state-
ment in each of the four cases-BB, BG, GB, GG-and in half of these
cases both children are of the same sex.)
The following wonderfully confusing little problem involving three
prisoners and a warden is even more difficult to state unambiguously.
Three men-A, B, and C-were in separate cells under sentence of
death when the governor decided to pardon one of them. He wrote
their names on three slips of paper, shook the slips in a hat, drew out
one of them, and telephoned the warden, requesting that the name of
the lucky man be kept secret for several days. Rumor of this reached
Probability and Ambiguity 277
prisoner A. When the warden made his morning rounds, A tried to
persuade the warden to tell him who had been pardoned. The warden
refused.
"Then tell me," said A, "the name of one of the others who will be
executed. If B is to be pardoned, give me C's name. If C is to be par-
doned, give me B's name. And if I'm to be pardoned, flip a coin to de-
cide whether to name B or C."
"But if you see me flip the coin," replied the wary warden, "you'll
know that you're the one pardoned. And if you see that I don't flip a
coin, you'll know it's either you or the person I don't name."
"Then don't tell me now," said A. "Tell me tomorrow morning."
The warden, who knew nothing about probability theory, thought it
over that night and decided that if he followed the procedure suggested
by A, it would give A no help whatever in estimating his survival
chances. So next morning he told A that B was going to be executed.
After the warden left, A smiled to himself at the warden's stupidity.
There were now only two equally probable elements in what mathe-
maticians like to call the "sample space" of the problem. Either C
would be pardoned or himself, so by all the laws of conditional prob-
ability, his chances of survival had gone up from 1/3 to 1/2.
The warden did not know that A could communicate with C, in an
adjacent cell, by tapping in code on a water pipe. This A proceeded to
do, explaining to C exactly what he had said to the warden and what
the warden had said to him. C was equally overjoyed with the news be-
cause he figured, by the same reasoning used by A, that his own sur-
vival chances had also risen to 1/2.
Did the two men reason correctly? If not, how should each have cal-
culated his chances of being pardoned?
Addendum
In giving the second version of the broken stick problem I could
hardly have picked a better illustration of the ease with which experts
can blunder on probability computations, and the dangers of relying on
a geometrical diagram. My solution was taken from William A. Whit-
worth's DCC Exercises in Choice and Chance, Problem 677; the same
answer will be found in many other older textbooks on probability. It
is entirely wrong!
278 PROBABILITY
In the first version of the problem, in which the two breaking points
are simultaneously chosen, the representative point on the diagram
ranges uniformly over the large triangle, permitting a comparison of
areas to obtain a correct answer. In the second version, in which the
stick is broken, then the larger piece is broken, Whitworth assumed that
the point on the diagram ranged uniformly over the three lower trian-
gles. It doesn't. There are more points within the central triangle than
in the other two.
Let the length of the stick be 1 and x be the length of the smallest
piece after the first break. To obtain pieces that will form a triangle,
the larger segment must be broken within a length equal to 1 - x.
Therefore the probability of obtaining a triangle is xll - x. We now
have to average all values of x, from 0 to 1/2, to obtain a value for this
expression. It proves to be - 1 + 2 log 2, or .386. Since the probability
is 1/2 that the larger piece will be picked for breaking, we multiply
.386 by 1/2 to obtain .193, the answer to the problem. This is a trifle
larger than 1/6, the answer obtained by following Whitworth's rea-
soning.
A large number of readers sent very clear analyses of the problem. In
the above summary, I followed a solution sent by Mitchell P. Marcus of
Binghamton, NY. Similar solutions were received from Edward Adams,
Howard Grossman, Robert C. James, Gerald R. Lynch, G. Bach and R.
Sharp, David Knaff, Norman Geschwind, and Raymond M. Redheffer.
Professor Redheffer, at the University of California, is coauthor (with
Ivan S. Sokolnikoff1 of Mathematics of Physics and Modern Engineer-
ing (McGraw-Hill, 1958), in which will be found (p. 636) a full discus-
sion of the problem. See also Ingenious Mathematical Problems and
Methods by L. A. Graham (Dover, 1959, Problem 32) for other methods
of solving the problem's first version.
Frederick R. Kling, John Ross, and Norman Cliff, all with the Educa-
tional Testing Service, Princeton, NJ, also sent a correct solution of the
problem's second version. At the close of their letter they asked which
of the following three hypotheses was most probable:
1. Mr. Gardner honestly blundered.
2. Mr. Gardner deliberately blundered in order to test his readers.
3. Mr. Gardner is guilty of what is known in the mathematical world
as keeping up with the d' Alemberts.
The answer: number three.
Probability and Ambiguity 279
Answers
The answer to the problem of the three prisoners is that A's
chances of being pardoned are 1/3, and that Cs chances are 2/3.
Regardless of who is pardoned, the warden can give A the name of a
man, other than A, who will die. The warden's statement therefore has
no influence on A's survival chances; they continue to be 1/3.
The situation is analogous to the following card game. Two black
cards (representing death) and a red card (the pardon) are shuffled and
dealt to three men: A, B, C (the prisoners). If a fourth person (the war-
den) peeks at all three cards, then turns over a black card belonging to
either B or C, what is the probability that A's card is red? There is a
temptation to suppose it is 1/2 because only two cards remain face-
down, one of which is red. But since a black card can always be shown
for B or C, turning it over provides no information of value in betting
on the color of A's card.
This is easy to understand if we exaggerate the situation by letting
death be represented by the ace of spades in a full deck. The deck is
spread, and A draws a card. His chance of avoiding death is 51/52.
Suppose now that someone peeks at the cards, then turns face up 50
cards that do not include the ace of spades. Only two face-down cards
are left, one of which must be the ace of spades, but this obviously
does not lower A's chances to 112. It doesn't because it is always pos-
sible, if one looks at the faces of the 51 cards, to find 50 that do not in-
clude the ace of spades. Finding them and turning them face up,
therefore, has no effect on A's chances. Of course if 50 cards are turned
over at random, and none prove to be the ace of spades, then the chance
that A drew the death card does rise to 1/2.
What about prisoner C? Since either A or C must die, their respective
probabilities for survival must add up to 1. A's chances to live are 1/3;
therefore Cs chances must be 2/3. This can be confirmed by consider-
ing the four possible elements in our sample space, and their respective
initial probabilities:
1. C is pardoned, warden names B (probability 1/3).
2. B is pardoned, warden names C (probability 1/3).
3. A is pardoned, warden names B (probability 1/6).
4. A is pardoned, warden names C (probability 1/6).
280 PROBABILITY
Only cases 1 and 3 apply when it becomes known that B will die. The
chances that it is case 1 are 1/3, or twice the chances (1/6) that it is case
3, so Cs survival chances are two to one, or 213. In the card-game model
this means that there is a probability of 2/3 that Cs card is red.
This problem of the three prisoners brought a flood of mail, pro and
con; happily, all objections proved groundless. Sheila Bishop of East
Haven, CT, sent the following well-thought-out analysis:
SIRS:
I was first led to the conclusion that A's reasoning was incorrect by the
following paradoxical situation. Suppose the original conversation be-
tween A and the warden had taken place in the same way, but now sup-
pose that just as the warden was approaching A's cell to tell him that B
would be executed, the warden fell down a manhole or was in some
other way prevented from delivering the message.
A could then reason as follows: "Suppose he was about to tell me that
B would be executed. Then my chance of survival would be 1/2. If, on
the other hand, he was going to tell me that C would be executed, then
my chances would still be 1/2. Now I know as a certain fact that he
would have told me one of those two things; therefore, either way, my
survival chances are bound to be 1/2." Following this line of thought
shows that A could have figured his chances to be 1/2 without ever ask-
ing the warden anything!
After a couple of hours I finally arrived at this conclusion: Consider a
large number of trios of prisoners all in this same situation, and in each
group let A be the one who talks to the warden. If there are 3n trios al-
together, then in n of them A will be pardoned, in n B will be pardoned,
and in n C will be pardoned. There will be 3nl2 cases in which the war-
den will say, "B will be executed." In n of these cases C will go free and
in nl2 cases A will go free; Cs chances are twice as good as A's. Hence
A's and C's chances of survival and 1/3 and 2/3 respectively ....
Lester R. Ford, Jr., and David N. Walker, both with the Arizona office
of General Analysis Corporation, felt that the warden has been unjustly
maligned:
SIRS:
We are writing to you on behalf of the warden, who is a political ap-
pointee and therefore unwilling to enter into controversial matters in his
own behalf.
You characterize him in a slurring manner as "The warden, who knew
Probability and Ambiguity 281
nothing about probability theory, ... " and I feel that a grave injustice is
being done. Not only are you incorrect (and possibly libelous), but I can
personally assure you that his hobby for many years has been mathe-
matics, and in particular, probability theory. His decision to answer A's
question, while based on a humanitarian attempt to brighten the last
hours of a condemned man (for, as we all now know, it was C who re-
ceived the pardon), was a decision completely compatible with his in-
structions from the governor.
The only point on which he is open to criticism (and on this he has
already been reprimanded by the governor) is that he was unable to pre-
vent A from communicating with C, thereby permitting Cto more accu-
rately estimate his chances of survival. Here too, no great damage was
done, since C failed to make proper use of the information.
If you do not publish both a retraction and an apology, we shall feel
impelled to terminate our subscription.
Addendum
The problem of the two boys, as I said, must be very carefully
stated to avoid ambiguity that prevents a precise answer. In my Aha,
Gotcha I avoided ambiguity by imagining a lady who owned two par-
rots--one white, one black. A visitor asks the owner, "Is one bird a
male?" The owner answers yes. The probability both parrots are male
is 1/3. Had the visitor asked, "Is the dark bird a male?'" a yes answer
would have raised the probability that both birds are male to 1/2.
Richard E. Bedient, a mathematician at Hamilton College, described
the prisoner's paradox in a poem that appeared in The American Math-
ematical Monthly, Vol. 101, March 1994, page 249:
282
THE PRISONER'S PARADOX REVISITED
Awaiting the dawn sat three prisoners wary,
A trio of brigands named Tom, Dick and Mary.
Sunrise would signal the death knoll of two,
Just one would survive, the question was who.
Young Mary sat thinking and finally spoke.
To the jailer she said, "You may think this a joke"
But it seems that my odds of surviving 'til tea,
Are clearly enough just one out of three.
But one of my cohorts must certainly go,
Without question, that's something I already know.
PROBABILITY
Telling the name of one who is lost,
Can't possibly help me. What could it cost?"
The shriveled old jailer himself was no dummy,
He thought, But why not?" and pointed to Tommy.
"Now it's just Dick and [" Mary chortled with glee,
((One in two are my chances, and not one in three!"
Imagine the jailer's chagrin, that old elf,
She'd tricked him, or had she? Decide for yourself.
When I introduced the three prisoners paradox in my October 1959
column, I received a raft of letters from mathematicians who believed
my solution was invalid. The number of such letters, however, was
small compared to the thousands of letters Marilyn vos Savant received
when she gave a version of the problem in her popular Parade column
for September 9,1990.
Ms. Savant's version of the paradox was based on a then-popular
television show called Let's Make a Deal, hosted by Monty Hall. Imag-
ine three doors, Marilyn wrote, to three rooms. Behind one door is a
prize car. Behind each of the other two doors is a goat. A guest on the
show is given a chance to win the prize by selecting the door with the
car. If she chooses at random, clearly the probability she will select the
prize door is 1/3. Now suppose, that after the guest's selection is voiced,
Monty Hall, who knows what is behind each door, opens one door to
disclose a goat. Two closed doors remain. One might reason that be-
cause the car is now behind one of just two doors, the probability the
guest had chosen the correct door has risen to 1/2. Not so! As Marilyn
correctly stated, it remains 1/3. Because Monty can always open a door
with a goat, his opening such a door conveys no new information that
alters the 1/3 probability.
Now comes an even more counterintuitive result. If the guest
switches her choice from her initial selection to the other closed door,
her chances of winning rise to 2/3. This should be obvious if one grants
that the probability remains 1/3 for the first selection. The car must be
behind one of the two doors, therefore the probabilities for each door
must add to 1, or certainty. If one door has a probability of 1/3 being
correct, the other door must have a 2/3 probability.
Marilyn was flooded with letters from irate readers, many accusing
her of being ignorant of elementary probability theory and many from
professional mathematicians. So awesome was the mail, and so con-
Probability and Ambiguity 283
troversial, that The New York Times, on July 21, 1991, ran a front page,
lengthy feature about the flap. The story, written by John Tierney, was
titled "Behind Monty Hall's Doors: Puzzle, Debate and Answer?" (See
also letters about the feature in The Times, August 11,1991.)
The red-faced mathematicians, who were later forced to confess they
were wrong, were in good company. Paul Erdos, one of the world's
greatest mathematicians, was among those unable to believe that
switching doors doubled the probability of success. Two recent bi-
ographies of the late Erdos reveal that he could not accept Marilyn's
analysis until his friend Ron Graham, of Bell Labs, patiently explained
it to him.
The Monty Hall problem, as it came to be known, generated many ar-
ticles in mathematical journals. I list some of them in this chapter's bib-
liography.
Bibliography
The Three Prisoners Paradox
D. H. Brown, "The Problem of the Three Prisoners," Mathematics Teacher, Febru-
ary 1966, pp. 181-82.
R. Falk, "A Closer Look at the Probabilities ofthe Notorious Three Prisoners." Cog-
nition, Vol. 43,1992, pp. 197-223.
S. Ichikawa and H. Takeichi, "Erroneous Beliefs in Estimating Posterior Probabil-
ity," Bahaviormetrika, No. 27,1990, pp. 59-73.
S. Shimojo and S. Ichikano, "Intuitive Reasoning About Probability: Theoretical
and Experiential Analysis of Three Prisoners," Cognition, Vol. 32, 1989, pp.
1-24.
N. Starr, "A Paradox in Probability Theory," Mathematics Teacher, February 1973,
pp.166-68.
The Monty Hall Problem
E. Barbeau, "Fallicies, Flaws, and Flimflams," The College Mathematics Journal,
Vol. 26, May 1995, pp. 132-84.
A. H. Bohl, M. J. Liberatore, and R. L. Nydick, "A Tale of Two Goats ... and a Car,"
Journal of Recreational Mathematics, Vol. 27, 1995, pp. 1-9.
J. P. Georges and T. V. Craine, "Generalizing Monty's Dilemma," Quantum,
March/April1995, pp. 17-21.
L. Gillman, "The Car and the Goats." American Mathematical Monthly, Vol. 99,
1992, pp. 3-7.
A. Lo Bello, "Ask Marilyn: The Mathematical Controversy in Parade Magazine,"
Mathematical Gazette, Vol, 75, October 1991, pp. 271-72.
284 PROBABILITY
J. Paradis, P. Viader, and L. Bibiloni, "A Mathematical Excursion: From the Three-
door Problem to a Cantortype Set." American Mathematical Monthly, VoL 106,
March 1999, pp. 241-51.
J. M. Shaughnessy and T. Dick, "Monte's Dilemma: Should You Stick or Switch?"
Mathematics Teacher, April 1991, pp. 252-56.
M. vos Savant, "Ask Marilyn," Parade, Septembr 9,1990; December 2,1990; Feb-
ruary 17, 1991; July 7, 1991; September 8, 1991; October 13 1991; January 5,
1992; January 26,1992.
Probability and Ambiguity 285
Chapter 22 Nontransitive Dice
and Other Paradoxes
Probability theory abounds in paradoxes that wrench common
sense and trap the unwary. In this chapter we consider a startling new
paradox involving the relation called transitivity and a group of para-
doxes stemming from the careless application of what is called the
principle of indifference.
Transitivity is a binary relation such that if it holds between A and B
and between Band C; it must also hold between A and C. A common
example is the relation "heavier than." If A is heavier than Band B is
heavier than C; then A is heavier than C. The three sets of four dice
shown "unfolded" in Figure 22.1 were designed by Bradley Efron, a sta-
tistician at Stanford University, to dramatize some discoveries about a
general class of probability paradoxes that violate transitivity. With any
of these sets of dice you can operate a betting game so contrary to in-
tuition that experienced gamblers will find it almost impossible to com-
prehend even after they have completely analyzed it.
The four dice at the top of the illustration are numbered in the sim-
plest way that provides the winner with the maximum advantage.
Allow someone to pick any die from this set. You then select a die
from the remaining three. Both dice are tossed and the person who gets
the highest number wins. Surely, it seems, if your opponent is allowed
the first choice of a die before each contest, the game must either be fair
or favor your opponent. If at least two dice have equal and maximum
probabilities of winning, the game is fair because if he picks one such
die, you can pick the other; if one die is better than the other three, your
opponent can always choose that die and win more than half of the
contests. This reasoning is completely wrong. The incredible truth is
that regardless of which die he picks you can always pick a die that has
a 2/3 probability of winning, or two-to-one odds in your favor!
286
10 4
__________________
Figure 22.1. Nontransitive dice
The paradox (insofar as it violates common sense) arises from the
mistaken assumption that the relation "more likely to win" must be
transitive between pairs of dice. This is not the case with any of the
three sets of dice. In each set the relation "more likely to win" is indi-
cated by an arrow that points to the losing die. Die A beats B, B beats
C, Cbeats D-and D beats A! In the first set the probability of winning
with the indicated die of each pair is 2/3. This is easily verified by list-
ing the 36 possible throws of each pair, then checking the 24 cases in
which one die bears the highest number.
The other two sets of four dice, also designed by Efron, have the
same nontransitive property but fewer numbers are repeated in order
to make an analysis of the dice more difficult. In the second set the
probability of winning with the indicated die is also 2/3. Because ties
are possible with the third set it must be agreed that ties will be broken
by rolling again. With this procedure the winning probability for each
of the four pairings in the third set is 11/17, or .647.
It has been proved, Efron writes, that 2/3 is the greatest possible ad-
vantage that can be achieved with four dice. For three sets of numbers
the maximum advantage is .618, but this cannot be obtained with dice
because the sets must have more than six numbers. If more than four
sets are used (numbers to be randomly selected within each set), the
possible advantage approaches a limit of 3/4 as the number of sets in-
creases.
A fundamental principle in calculating probabilities such as dice
Nontransitive Dice and Other Paradoxes 287
throws is one that goes back to the beginnings of classical probability
theory in the 18th century. It was formerly called "the principle of in-
sufficient reason" but is now known as "the principle of indifference/'
a crisper phrase coined by John Maynard Keynes in A Treatise on Prob-
ability. (Keynes is best known as an economist, but his book on proba-
bility has become a classic. It had a major influence on the inductive
logic of Rudolf Carnap.) The principle is usually stated as follows: If
you have no grounds whatever for believing that anyone of n mutually
exclusive events is more likely to occur than any other, a probability of
1/ n is assigned to each.
For example, you examine a die carefully and find nothing that fa-
vors one side over another, such as concealed loads, noncubical shape,
beveling of certain edges, stickiness of certain sides, and so on. You as-
sume that there are six equally probable ways the cube can fall; there-
fore you assign a probability of 1/6 to each. If you toss a penny, or play
the Mexican game of betting on which of two sugar cubes a fly will
alight on first, your ignorance of any possible bias prompts you to as-
sign a probability of 1/2 to each of the two outcomes. In none of these
samples do you feel obligated to make statistical, empirical tests. The
probabilities are assigned a priori. They are based on symmetrical fea-
tures in the structures and forces involved. The die is a regular solid,
the probability of the penny's balancing on its edge is virtually zero,
there is no reason for a fly to prefer one sugar cube to another, and so
on. Ultimately, of course, your analysis rests on empirical grounds,
since only experience tells you, say, that a weighted die face would af-
fect the odds, whereas a face colored red (with the others blue) would
not.
Some form of the principle of indifference is indispensable in prob-
ability theory, but it must be carefully qualified and applied with ex-
treme caution to avoid pitfalls. In many cases the traps spring from a
difficulty in deciding which are the equally probable cases. Suppose,
for instance, you shuffle a packet of four cards-two red, two black-
and deal them face down in a row. Two cards are picked at random, say
by placing a penny on each. What is the probability that those two
cards are the same color?
One person reasons: "There are three equally probable cases. Either
both cards are black, both are red, or they are different colors. In two
cases the cards match, therefore the matching probability is 2/3."
"No," another person counters, "there are four equally probable
288 PROBABILITY
cases. Either both cards are black, both are red, card x is black and y is
red, or x is red and y is black. More simply, the cards either match or
they do not. In each way of putting it the matching probability clearly
is 1/2."
The fact is that both people are wrong. (The correct probability will
be given in the Answer Section. Can the reader calculate it?) Here the
errors arise from a failure to identify correctly the equally probable
cases. There are, however, more confusing paradoxes-actually fallac-
ies-in which the principle of indifference seems intuitively to be ap-
plicable, whereas it actually leads straight to a logical contradiction.
Cases such as these result when there are no positive reasons for be-
lieving n events to be equally probable and the assumption of equiprob-
ability is therefore based entirely, or almost entirely, on ignorance.
For example, someone tells you: "There is a cube in the next room
whose size has been selected by a randomizing device. The cube's edge
is not less than one foot or more than three feet." How would you esti-
mate the probability that the cube's edge is between one and two feet
as compared with the probability that it is between two and three feet?
In your total ignorance of additional information, is it not reasonable to
invoke the principle of indifference and regard each probability as 1/2?
It is not. If the cube's edge ranges between one and two feet, its vol-
ume ranges between 1
3
, or one, cubic foot and 2
3
, or eight, cubic feet.
But in the range of edges from two to three feet, the volume ranges be-
tween 2
3
(eight) and 3
3
(27) cubic feet-a range almost three times the
other range. If the principle of indifference applies to the two ranges of
edges, it is violated by the equivalent ranges of volume. You were not
told how the cube's "size" was randomized, and since "size" is am-
biguous (it could mean either the cube's edge or its volume) you have
no clues to guide your guessing. If the cube's edge was picked at ran-
dom, the principle of indifference does indeed apply. It is also applic-
able if you are told that the cube's volume was picked at random, but
of course you then have to assign a probability of 1/2 to each of the two
ranges from one to 14 and from 14 to 27 cubic feet, and to the corre-
sponding ranges for the cube's edge. If the principle applies to the edge,
it cannot apply to the volume without contradiction, and vice versa.
Since you do not know how the size was selected, any application of
the principle is meaningless.
Carnap, in attacking an uncritical use of the principle in Harold Jef-
freys' Theory of Probability, gives the following example of its misuse.
Nontransitive Dice and Other Paradoxes 289
You know that every ball in an urn is blue, red, or yellow, but you
know nothing about how many balls of each color are in the urn. What
is the probability that the first ball taken from the urn will be blue? Ap-
plying the principle of indifference, you say it is 1/2. The probability
that it is not blue must also be 1/2. If it is not blue, it must be red or yel-
low, and because you know nothing about the number of red or yellow
balls, those colors are equally probable. Therefore you assign to red a
probability of 1/4. On the other hand, if you begin by asking for the
probability that the first ball will be red, you must give red a
ity of 1/2 and blue a probability of 1/4, which contradicts your previ-
ous estimates.
It is easy to prove along similar lines that there is life on Mars. What
is the probability that there is simple plant life on Mars? Since argu-
ments on both sides are about equally cogent, we answer 1/2. What is
the probability that there is simple animal life on Mars? Again, 1/2.
Now we seem forced to assert that the probability of there being "either
plant or animal life" on Mars is 1/2 + 1/2 = 1, or certainty, which is ab-
surd. The philosopher Charles Sanders Peirce gave a similar argument
that seems to show that the hair of inhabitants on Saturn had to be
ther of two different colors. It is easy to invent others.
In the history of metaphysics the most notorious misuse of the prin-
ciple surely was by Blaise Pascal, who did pioneer work on probabil-
ity theory, in a famous argument that became known as "Pascal's
wager." A few passages from the original and somewhat lengthy argu-
ment (in Pascal's Pensees, Thought 233) are worth quoting:
"God is, or he is not." To which side shall we incline? Reason can de-
termine nothing about it. There is an infinite gulf fixed between us. A
game is playing at the extremity of this infinite distance in which heads
or tails may turn up. What will you wager? There is no reason for back-
ing either one or the other, you cannot reasonably argue in favor of ei-
ther ....
Yes, but you must wager .... Which will you choose? ... Let us weigh
the gain and the loss in choosing "heads" that God is .... If you gain, you
gain all. If you lose, you lose nothing. Wager, then, unhesitatingly that
he is.
Lord Byron, in a letter, rephrased Pascal's argument effectively: "In-
disputably, the firm believers in the Gospel have a great advantage over
all others, for this simple reason-that, if true, they will have their re-
290 PROBABILITY
ward hereafter; and if there be no hereafter, they can be but with the in-
fidel in his eternal sleep, having had the assistance of an exalted hope
through life, without subsequent disappointment, since (at the worst
for them) out of nothing nothing can arise, not even sorrow." Similar
passages can be found in many contemporary books of religious apolo-
getics.
Pascal was not the first to insist in this fashion that faith in Christian
orthodoxy was the best bet. The argument was clearly stated by the
4th-century African priest Arnobius the Elder, and non-Christian forms
of it go back to Plato. This is not the place, however, to go into the cu-
rious history of defenses and criticisms of the wager. I content myself
with mentioning Denis Diderot's observation that the wager applies
with equal force to other major faiths such as Islam. The mathemati-
cally interesting aspect of all of this is that Pascal likens the outcome
of his bet to the toss of a coin. In other words, he explicitly invokes the
principle of indifference to a situation in which its application is math-
ematically senseless.
The most subtle modern reformulation of Pascal's wager is by
William James, in his famous essay The Will to Believe, in which he ar-
gues that philosophical theism is a better gamble than atheism. In a still
more watered-down form it is even used occasionally by humanists to
defend optimism against pessimism at a time when the extinction of
the human race seems as likely in the near future as its survival.
"While there is a chance of the world getting through its troubles,"
says the narrator of H. G. Wells's little read novel Apropos of Dolores,
"I hold that a reasonable man has to behave as though he was sure of
it. If at the end your cheerfulness is not justified, at any rate you will
have been cheerful."
Addendum
The following letter, from S. D. Turner, contains some surpris-
ing information:
Your bit about the two black and two red cards reminds me of an exer-
cise I did years ago, which might be called N-Card Monte. A few cards,
half red, half black, or nearly so, are shown face up by the pitchman,
then shuffled and dealt face down. The sucker is induced to bet he can
pick two of the same color.
The odds will always be against him. But because the sucker will
Nontransitive Dice and Other Paradoxes 291
make erroneous calculations (like the 2/3 and 1/2 in your 2:2 example),
or for other reasons, he will bet. The pitchman can make a plausible
spiel to aid this: "Now, folks, you don't need to pick two blacks, and you
don't need to pick two reds. If you draw either pair you win!"
The probability of getting two of the same color, where there are R reds
and B blacks, is:
R2 + B2 - (R + B)
P=
(R + B) (R + B-1)
This yields the figures in the table [see Figure 22.2], one in lowest-
terms fractions, the other in decimaL Only below and to the left of the
stairstep line does the sucker get an even break or better. But no pitch-
man would bother with odds more favorable to the sucker than the 1/3
probability for 2:2, or possibly the 2/5 for 3:3.
Surprisingly, the two top diagonal lines are identicaL That is, if you
are using equal reds and blacks, odds are not changed if a card is re-
moved before the two are selected! In your example of 2:2, the proba-
Red Cards
1 2 3 4 5 6 7 8 13 26
- - -
---
-"'-
2
1 1
3 3
3
1 2
~ 2 5
4
~
7
3
~ 5 15 7
5
2
it S ~ a 3
6
~ 4 1
i5
-f, -f,
7 7 ~
7
3 11
i
2Z
fi
6
..2..
4 18 35 -rn 13
8
Z
~
a1 11
19
fi
7
L
9 55 33 39 1!' 15
13
12
Ui
25
'E 26
g
1II
51
0
~
2 .333 .333
m
3 .500 .400 .400
4 .600 .466 .429 .429
5 .667 .524 .465 .444 .444
6 .714 .572 .500 .467 .455 .455
7 .750 .611 .533 .491 .470 .462 .462
8 .778 .645 .564 .515 .488 .472 .466 .466
13
.460
26 .490
Figure 22.2. Probability of drawing two cards of the same color
292 PROBABILITY
bility is 1/3 and it is also 1/3 when starting with 2:1 (as is evident be-
cause the one card not selected can be anyone of the three). The gener-
ality of this can be shown thus: If B = Rand B R 1 are substituted into
the above equation, the result in each case is R - 1/ 2R 1.
Some readers sent detailed explanations of why the arguments be-
hind the fallacies that I described were wrong, apparently not realizing
that these fallacies were intended to be howlers based on the misuse of
the principle of indifference. Several readers correctly pointed out that
although Pascal did invoke the principle of indifference by referring to
a coin flip in his famous wager, the principle is not essential to his ar-
gument. Pascal posits an infinite gain for winning a bet in which the
loss (granting his assumptions) would always be finite regardless of
the odds.
Efron's nontransitive dice aroused almost as much interest among
magicians as among mathematicians. It was quickly perceived that the
basic idea generalized to k sets of n-sided dice, such as dice in the
shapes of regular octahedrons, dodecahedrons, icosahedrons, or cylin-
ders with n flat sides. The game also can be modeled by k sets of n-
sided tops, spinners with n numbers on each dial, and packets of n
playing cards.
Karl Fulves, in his magic magazine The Pallbearers Review (January
1971) proposed using playing cards to model Efron's dice. He suggested
the following four packets: 2,3,4, 10,], Q; 1,2,8,9,9, 10; 6, 6, 7, 7,8,
8; and 4,5, 5, 6, Q, K. Suits are irrelevant. First player selects a packet,
shuffles it, and draws a card. Second player does the same with another
packet. If the chosen cards have the same value, they are replaced and
two more cards drawn. Ace is low, and high card wins. This is based
on Efron's third set of dice where the winning probability, if the second
player chooses properly, is 11/17. To avoid giving away the cyclic se-
quence of packets, each could be placed in a container (box, cup, tray,
etc.) with the containers secretly marked. Before each play, the con-
tainers would be randomly mixed by the first player while the second
player turned his back. Containers with numbered balls or counters
could of course be substituted for cards.
In the same issue of The Pallbearers Review cited above, Columbia
University physicist Shirley Quimby proposed a set of four dice with
the following faces:
Nontransitive Dice and Other Paradoxes 293
3,4,5,20,21,22
1,2,16,17,18,19
10,11,12,13,14,15
6,7,8,9,23,24
Note that numbers 1 through 24 are used just once each in this ele-
gant arrangement. The dice give the second player a winning proba-
bility of 2/3. If modeled with 24 numbered cards, the first player would
select one of the four packets, shuffle, then draw a card. The second
player would do likewise, and high card wins.
R.C.H. Cheng, writing from Bath University, England, proposed a
novel variation using a single die. On each face are numbers 1 through
6, each numeral a different color. Assume that the colors are the rain-
bow colors red, orange, yellow, green, blue, and purple. The chart
below shows how the numerals are colored on each face.
FACE RED ORANGE YELLOW GREEN BLUE PURPLE
A 1 2 3 4 5 6
B 6 1 2 3 4 5
C 5 6 1 2 3 4
D 4 5 6 1 2 3
E 3 4 5 6 1 2
F 2 3 4 5 6 1
The game is played as follows: The first player selects a color, then
the second player selects another color. The die is rolled and the per-
son whose color has the highest value wins. It is easy to see from the
chart that if the second player picks the adjacent color on the right-the
sequence is cyclic, with red to the "right" of purple-the second player
wins five out of six times. In other words, the odds are 5 to 1 in his
favor!
To avoid giving away the sequence of colors, the second player
should occasionally choose the second color to the right, where his
winning odds are 4 to 2, or the color third to the right where the odds
are even. Perhaps he should even, on rare occasions, take the fourth or
fifth color to the right where odds against him are 4 to 2 and 5 to 1 re-
spectively. Mel Stover has suggested putting the numbers and colors on
a six-sided log instead of a cube.
294 PROBABILITY
This, too, models nicely with 36 cards, formed in six piles, each
bearing a colored numeral. The chart's pattern is obvious, and easily ap-
plied to n
2
cards, each with numbers 1 through n, and using n differ-
ent colors. In presenting it as a betting game you should freely display
the faces of each packet to show that all six numbers and all six colors
are represented. Each packet is shuffled and placed face down. The
first player is "generously" allowed first choice of a color and to select
any packet. The color with the highest value in that packet is the win-
ner. In the general case, as Cheng pointed out in his 1971 letter, the sec-
ond player can always choose a pile that gives him a probability of
winning equal to (n -l)/n.
A simpler version of this game uses 16 playing cards. The four pack-
ets are
AS, JH, QC, KD
KS, AH, JC, QD
QS, KH, AC, JD
JS, QH, KC, AD
Ace here is high, and the cyclic sequence of suits is spades, hearts,
clubs, diamonds. The second player wins with 3 to 1 odds by choos-
ing the next adjacent suit, and even odds if he goes to the next suit but
one.
These betting games are all variants of nontransitive voting para-
doxes, about which there is extensive literature.
Answers
The probability that two randomly selected cards, from a set of
two red and two black cards, are the same color is 1/3. If you list the 24
equally probable permutations ofthe four cards, then pick any two po-
sitions (for example, second and fourth cards), you will find eight cases
in which the two cards match in color. One way to see that this proba-
bility of 8/24 or 1/3 is correct is to consider one of the two chosen
cards. Assume that it is red. Of the remaining three cards only one is
red, and so the probability that the second chosen card will be red is
1/3. Of course, the same argument applies if the first card is black.
Most people guess that the odds are even, when actually they are 2:1 in
favor of the cards' having different colors.
Nontransitive Dice and Other Paradoxes 295
Bibliography
R. Carnap, "Statistical and Inductive Probability," The Structure of Scientific
Thought, E. H. Madden (ed.), Houghton Mifflin, 1960.
J. M. Keynes, A Treatise on Probability, Macmillan, 1921; Harper & Row (paper-
back),1962.
On Pascal's Wager:
J. Cargile. "Pascal's Wager," Philosophy: The Journal of the Royal Institute of Phi-
losophy, Vol. 41, July 1966, pp. 250-57.
I. Hacking, The Emergence of Probability: A Philosophical Study of Early Ideas
About Probability, Induction, and Statistical Inference, Cambridge University
Press, 1976.
M.B. Turner, "Deciding for God-the Bayesian Support of Pascal's Wager," Philos-
ophy and Phenomenological Research, Vol. 29, September 1968, pp. 84-90.
On Nontransitive Dice
G. Finnell, "A Dice Paradox," Epilogue, July 1971, pp. 2-3. This is another magic
magazine published by Karl Fulves.
R. P. Savage, "The Paradox of Nontransitive Dice," American Mathematical
Monthly, VoL 101, May 1994, pp. 429-36.
296 PROBABILITY
Chapter 23 More
Nontransitive Paradoxes
I have just so much logic, as to be able to see . ..
that for me to be too good for you, and for you to
be too good for me, cannot be true at once, both
ways.
-ELIZABETH BARRETT, in a letter to Robert Browning.
When a relation R that is true with respect to xRy and yRz also
holds for xRz, the relation is said to be transitive. For example, "less
than" is transitive among all real numbers. If 2 is less than n, and the
square root of 3 is less than 2, we can be certain that the square root of
3 is less than n. Equality also is transitive: if a = band b = c, then a = c.
In everyday life such relations as "earlier than," "heavier than," "taller
than," "inside," and hundreds of others are transitive.
It is easy to think of relations that are not transitive. If A is the father
of Band B is the father of C, it is never true that A is the father of C. If
A loves Band B loves C, it does not follow that A loves C. Familiar
games abound in transitive rules (if poker hand A beats B and B beats
C, then A beats C), but some games have nontransitive (or intransitive)
rules. Consider the children's game in which, on the count of three, one
either makes a fist to symbolize "rock," extends two fingers for "scis-
sors," or all fingers for "paper." Rock breaks scissors, scissors cut paper,
and paper covers rock. In this game the winning relation is not transi-
tive.
Occasionally in mathematics, particularly in probability theory and
decision theory, one comes on a relation that one expects to be transi-
tive but that actually is not. If the nontransitivity is so counterintuitive
as to boggle the mind, we have what is called a nontransitive paradox.
The oldest and best-known paradox of this type is a voting paradox
sometimes called the Arrow paradox after Kenneth J. Arrow because of
its crucial role in Arrow's "impossibility theorem," for which he shared
a Nobel prize in economics in 1972. In Social Choice and Individual
Values, Arrow specified five conditions that almost everyone agrees are
essential for any democracy in which social decisions are based on in-
dividual preferences expressed by voting. Arrow proved that the five
297
conditions are logically inconsistent. It is not possible to devise a vot-
ing system that will not, in certain instances, violate at least one of the
five essential conditions. In short, a perfect democratic voting system
is in principle impossible.
As Paul A. Samuelson has put it: "The search of the great minds of
recorded history for the perfect democracy, it turns out, is the search for
a chimera, for a logical self-contradiction .... Now scholars allover the
world-in mathematics, politics, philosophy, and economics-are try-
ing to salvage what can be salvaged from Arrow's devastating discov-
ery that is to mathematical politics what Kurt Godel's 1931
impossibility-of-proving-consistency theorem is to mathematical
logic."
Let us approach the voting paradox by first considering a funda-
mental defect of our present system for electing officials. It frequently
puts in office a man who is cordially disliked by a majority of voters but
who has an enthusiastic minority following. Suppose 40 percent of the
voters are enthusiastic supporters of candidate A. The opposition is
split between 30 percent for Band 30 percent for C. A is elected even
though 60 percent of the voters dislike him.
One popular suggestion for avoiding such consequences of the split
vote is to allow voters to rank all candidates in their order of preference.
Unfortunately, this too can produce irrational decisions. The matrix in
Figure 23.1 (left) displays the notorious voting paradox in its simplest
form. The top row shows that a third of the voters prefer candidates A,
B, and C in the order ABC. The middle row shows that another third
A
31
B
C
RANK ORDER
2
B
c
A
3
c
A
B
D E F
A 8 1 6
3 5 7
c 4 9 2
-
Figure 23.1. The voting paradox (left) and the tournament paradox based on the magic
square (right)
298 PROBABILITY
rank them BCA, and the bottom row shows that the remaining third
rank them CAB. Examine the matrix carefully and you will find that
when candidates are ranked in pairs, non transitivity rears its head.
Two-thirds of the voters prefer A to B, two-thirds prefer B to C, and two-
thirds prefer Cto A. If A ran against B, A would win. If B ran against C,
B would win. If C ran against A, C would win. Substitute proposals for
candidates and you see how easily a party in power can rig a decision
simply by its choice of which paired proposals to put up first for a
vote.
The paradox was recognized by the Marquis de Condorcet and oth-
ers in the late 18th century and is known in France as the Condorcet ef-
fect. Lewis Carroll, who wrote several pamphlets on voting,
rediscovered it. Most of the early advocates of proportional represen-
tation were totally unaware of this Achilles' heel; indeed, the paradox
was not fully recognized by political theorists until the mid-1940s,
when Duncan Black, a Welsh economist, rediscovered it in connection
with his monumental work on committee decision making. The ex-
perts are nowhere near agreement on which of Arrow's five conditions
should be abandoned in the search for the best voting system. One sur-
prising way out, recommended by many decision theorists, is that
when a deadlock arises, a "dictator" is chosen by lot to break it. Some-
thing close to this solution actually obtains in certain democracies,
England for instance, where a constitutional monarch (selected by
chance in the sense that lineage guarantees no special biases) has a
carefully limited power to break deadlocks under certain extreme con-
ditions.
The voting paradox can arise in any situation in which a decision
must be made between two alternatives from a set of three or more.
Suppose that A, B, and C are three men who have simultaneously pro-
posed marriage to a girl. The rows of the matrix for the voting paradox
can be used to show how she ranks them with respect to whatever
three traits she considers most important, say intelligence, physical at-
tractiveness, and income. Taken by pairs, the poor girl finds that she
prefers A to B, B to C, and C to A. It is easy to see how similar conflicts
can arise with respect to one's choice of a job, where to spend a vaca-
tion, and so on.
Paul R. Halmos once suggested a delightful interpretation of the ma-
trix. Let A, B, and C stand for apple pie, blueberry pie, and cherry pie.
A certain restaurant offers only two of them at any given meal. The
More Nontransitive Paradoxes 299
rows show how a customer ranks the pies with respect to three prop-
erties, say taste, freshness, and size of slice. It is perfectly rational, says
Halmos, for the customer to prefer apple pie to blueberry, blueberry to
cherry, and cherry to apple. In his Adventures of a Mathematician
(Scribner, 1976), Stanislaw Ulam speaks of having discovered the non-
transitivity of such preferences when he was eight or nine and of later
realizing that it prevented one from ranking great mathematicians in a
linear order of relative merit.
Experts differ on how often nontransitive orderings such as this one
arise in daily life, but some recent studies in psychology and economics
indicate that they are commoner than one might suppose. There are even
reports of experiments with rats showing that under certain conditions
the pairwise choices of individual rats are nontransitive. (See Warren S.
McCulloch, "A Heterarchy of Values Determined by the Topology of Ner-
vous Nets," Bulletin of Mathematical Biophysics 7,1945, pp. 89-93.)
Similar paradoxes arise in round-robin tournaments between teams.
Assume that nine tennis players are ranked in ability by the numbers
1 through 9, with the best player given the number 9 and the worst
given the number 1. The matrix in Figure 23.1 (right) is the familiar
order-3 magic square. Let rows A, B, and C indicate how the nine play-
ers are divided into three teams with each row comprising a team. In
round-robin tournaments between teams, where each member of one
team plays once against each member of the others, assume that the
stronger player always wins. It turns out that team A defeats B, B de-
feats C, and C defeats A, in each case by five games to four. It is im-
possible to say which team is the strongest. The same non transitivity
holds if columns D, E, and F of the matrix are the teams.
Many paradoxes of this type were jointly investigated by Leo Moser
and J. W. Moon. Some of the Moser-Moon paradoxes underlie striking
and little-known sucker bets. For example, let each row (or each col-
umn) of an order-3 magic-square matrix be a set of playing cards, say
the ace, 6, and 8 of hearts for set A, the 3, 5, and 7 of spades for set B,
and the 2, 4, and 9 of clubs for C (see Figure 23.2). Each set is random-
ized and placed face down on a table. The sucker is allowed to draw a
card from any set, then you draw a card from a different set. The high
card wins. It is easy to prove that no matter what set the sucker draws
from, you can pick a set that gives you winning odds of five to four. Set
A beats B, Bbeats C, and Cbeats A. The victim may even be allowed to
decide each time whether the high or the low card wins. If you play low
300 PROBABILITY
A
c
Figure 23.2. Nontransitive sucker bet based on magic square: A ~ B ~ C ~ A
card wins, simply pick the winning pile with respect to a nontransitive
circle that goes the other way. A good way to play the game is to use
sets of cards from three decks with backs of different colors. The packet
of nine cards is shuffled each time, then separated by the backs into the
three sets. The swindle is, of course, isomorphic with the tennis-
tournament paradox.
Nontransitivity prevails in many other simple gambling games. In
some cases, such as the top designed by Andrew Lenard (see Figure
23.3), the nontransitivity is easy to understand. The lower part of the
top is fixed but the upper disk rotates. Each of two players chooses a
different arrow, the top is spun (in either direction), and the person
whose arrow points to the section with the highest number wins. A
beats B, B beats C, and C beats A, in each case with odds of two to one.
More Nontransitive Paradoxes 301
23.3. Nontransitive
A B
2 2 4
3 4 5 6
C D
3 5
4 5 2 6
A-B-C-D-A
23.4. Nontransitive
covered (appropriately) by a mathematician named Walter Penney, was
given as a problem in the Journal of Recreational Mathematics (October
1969, p. 241). It is not well known, and most mathematicians simply
cannot believe it when they first hear of it. It is certainly one of the finest
of all sucker bets. It can be played with a penny, or as a side bet on the
reds and blacks of a roulette wheel, or in any situation in which two al-
ternatives are randomized with equal odds. We shall assume that a
penny is used. If it is flipped three times, there are eight equally proba-
ble outcomes: HHH, HHT, HTH, HTT, THH, THT, TTH, and TTT. One
player selects one of these triplets, and the other player selects a differ-
ent one. The penny is then flipped repeatedly until one of the chosen
triplets appears as a run and wins the game. For example, if the chosen
triplets are HHT and THT and the flips are THHHT, the last three flips
show that HHThas won. In brief, the first triplet to appear as a run wins.
One is inclined to assume that one triplet is as likely to appear first
as any other, but it takes only a moment to realize that this is not the
case even with doublets. Consider the doublets HH, HT, TH, and TT.
HH and HT are equally likely to appear first because, after the first H
appears, it is just as likely to be followed by an H as by a T. The same
reasoning shows that TT and TH are equal. Because of symmetry, HH
= TT and HT = TH. TH beats HH with odds of three to one, however,
and HTbeats TTwith the same probability. Consider HT and TT. TTis
always preceded by HT except when TT appears on the first two flips.
This happens in the long run only once in four times. and so the prob-
ability that HT beats TT is 3/4. Figure 23.5 shows the probability that
B, the second player, will win for all pairs of doublets.
HT TH TT
114 112
HT
112 3/4
TH 3/4 112
TT 112 114 112
figure 23.S. Probabilities of B winning
More Nontransitive Paradoxes 303
When we turn to triplets, the situation becomes much more surpris-
ing. Since it does not matter which side of a coin is designated heads,
we know that HHH = TTT, TTH HHT, HTH = THT, and so on. When
we examine the probabilities for unequal pairs, however, we discover
that the game is not transitive. No matter what triplet the first player
takes, the second player can select a better one. Figure 23.6 gives the
probability that B, the second player, defeats A for all possible pairings.
To find B's best response to a triplet chosen by A, find A's triplet at the
top, go down the column until you reach a probability (shown in gray),
then move left along the row to B's triplet on the left.
A
B
HHT HTH HTT THH THT TTH TTT
HHH
112 2/5 215 118 5/12 3/10 112
HHT
112 213 2/3 1/4 5/8 112 7110
HTH 3/5 113 112 112 112 3/8 7/12
HTT
3/5 1/3 112 112 112 3/4 7/8
THH 7/8 3/4 112 112 l/2 1/3 3/5
THT 7/12 3/8 112 112 l/2 l/3 3/5
TTH 7/10 112 5/8 1/4 213 213 112
TTT
112 3/10 5112 1/8 2/5 2/5 112
Figure 23.6. Probabilities of B winning in a triplet game
Note that B's probability of winning is, at the worst, 2/3 (or odds of
two to one) and can go as high as 7/8 (or odds of seven to one). The
seven-to-one odds are easy to comprehend. Consider THH and HHH. If
HHH first appears anywhere except at the start, it must be preceded by
304
PROBABILITY
a T, which means that THHhas appeared earlier. HHHwins, therefore,
only when it appears on the first three flips. Clearly this happens only
once in eight flips.
Barry Wolk of the University of Manitoba has discovered a curious
rule for determining the best triplet. Let X be the first triplet chosen.
Convert it to a binary number by changing each H to zero and each T
to 1. Divide the number by 2, round down the quotient to the nearest
integer, multiply by 5, and add 4. Express the result in binary, then con-
vert the last three digits back to Hand T.
Nontransitivity holds for all higher n-tuplets. A chart supplied by
Wolk gives the winning probabilities for B in all possible pairings of
quadruplets (see Figure 23.7). Like the preceding two charts and charts
for all higher n-tuplets, the matrix is symmetric about the center. The
upper right quadrant is the lower left quadrant upside down, and the
same holds for the upper left and lower right quadrants. The probabil-
ities for B's best responses to A are shown in gray.
In studying these figures, Wolk discovered another kind of anomaly
as surprising as nontransitivity. It has to do with what are called wait-
ing times. The waiting time for an n-tuplet is the average number of
tosses, in the long run, until the specified n-tuplet appears. The longer
you wait for a bus, the shorter becomes the expected waiting time. Pen-
nies, however, have no memory, so that the waiting time for an n-tuplet
is independent of all previous flips. The waiting time for Hand Tis 2.
For doublets the waiting time is 4 for HT and TH, and 6 for HH and TT.
For triplets the waiting times are 8 for HHT, HHT, THH, and TTH; 10
for HTH and THT; and 14 for HHH and TTT. None of this contradicts
what we know about which triplet of a pair is likely to show first. With
quadruplets, however, contradictions arise with six pairs. For example,
THTHhas a waiting time of 20 and HTHHhas a waiting time of 18. Yet,
THTH is more likely to turn up before HTHH with a probability of
9/14, or well over one-half. In other words, an event that is less frequent
in the long run is likely to happen before a more frequent event. There
is no logical contradiction involved here, but it does show that "aver-
age waiting time" has peculiar properties.
There are many ways to calculate the probability that one n-tuplet
will precede another. You can do it by summing infinite series, by
drawing tree diagrams, by recursive techniques that produce sets of
linear equations, and so on. One of the strangest and most efficient
techniques was devised by John Horton Conway of Princeton Univer-
More Nontransitive Paradoxes 305
HHHT HHTH HHIT HTHH HTHT HITH HITT THHH THHT THTH THIT ITHH ITHT ITTH TTTT
2/5 3/8 3/8 3/8 1/4 3/8 7122 112
112
517 112 5112 9/16 9116 5/14 112 7/16 5/8
213 3/4
112 5/8
HTHT 7112 3/8 217 112 9/14 7/16 7/16 7/16 5/8
HITH 7/11 317 112 1/3 112 9116 5112 7112 7112 7/16 5/8
HITT 7/11 317 112 113 112 9/16 5/12 7/12 7/1
7112 7/12 5112 9/16 112 112 1/3
7116 7/12 7112 5/12 9116 112 112 112 113
7/16 7/16 7116 9114 112 7116 7/16
/16 7116 7/16 112 5/14 7112 7112
112 9116 5112 9/16 9/16 9/16 1/8
1TTT 112 7122 3/8 114 3/8 3/8 3/8
Figure 23.7. Probabilities of B winning in a quadruplet game
sity. I have no idea why it works. It just cranks out the answer as if by
magic, like so many of Conway's other algorithms.
The key to Conway's procedure is the calculation of four binary num-
bers that Conway calls leading numbers. Let A stand for the 7-tuplet
HHTHHHT and B for THHTHHH. We want to determine the probabil-
ity of B beating A. To do this, write A above A, B above B, A above B,
and B above A (see Figure 23.8). Above the top tuplet of each pair a bi-
nary number is constructed as follows. Consider the first pair, AA. Look
at the first letter of the top tuplet and ask yourself if the seven letters,
beginning with this first one, correspond exactly to the first seven let-
ters of the tuplet below it. Obviously they do, and so we put a 1 above
the first letter. Next, look at the second letter of the top tuplet and ask
306
PROBABILITY
if the six letters, starting with this one, correspond to the first six let-
ters of the tuplet below. Clearly they do not, and so we put zero above
the second letter. Do the five letters starting with the third letter of the
top tuplet correspond to the first five letters of the lower tuplet? No, and
so this letter also gets zero. The fourth letter gets another zero. When we
check the fifth letter of the top A, we see that HHT does correspond to
the first three letters of the lower A, and so the fifth letter gets a 1. Let-
ters six and seven each get zero. The "A leading A number," or AA, is
1000100, in which each 1 corresponds to a yes answer; each zero, to a
no. Translating 1000100 from binary to decimal gives us 68 as the lead-
ing number for AA.
Figure 23.8 shows the results of this procedure in calculating lead-
ing numbers AA, BB, AB, and BA. Whenever an n-tuplet is compared
with itself, the first digit of the leading number must, of course, be 1.
When compared with a different tuplet, the first digit mayor may not
be 1.
1000100 = 68
A=HHTHHHT
A=HHTHHHT
1000000 =64
B= THHTHHH
B= THHTHHH
0000001 = 1
A=HHTHHHT
B=THHTHHH
0100011=35
B= THHTHHH
A=HHTHHHT
AA -AB:BB-BA
68 - 1 :64 - 35
67:29
Figure 23.8. John Horton Conway's algorithm for calculating odds of B's n-tuplet beating
A's n-tuplet
The odds in favor of B beating A are given by the ratio AA-AB:BB-
BA. In this case 68-1:64-35 = 67:29. As an exercise, the reader can try
calculating the odds in favor of THH beating HHH. The four leading
numbers will be AA = 7, BB = 4, AB = 0, and BA = 3. Plugging these into
the formula, AA-AB:BB-BA gives odds of 7-0:4-3, or seven to one,
as expected. The algorithm works just as well on tuplets of unequal
lengths, provided the smaller tuplet is not contained within the larger
one. If, for example, A = HH and B = HHT, A obviously wins with a
probability of 1.
More Nontransitive Paradoxes 307
I conclude with a problem by David 1. Silverman, who was the first
to introduce the Penney paradox in the problems department that he
then edited for the Journal of Recreational Mathematics (Vol. 2, Octo-
ber 1969, p. 241). The reader should have little difficulty solving it by
Conway's algorithm. TTHH has a waiting time of 16 and HHH has a
waiting time of 14. Which of these tuplets is most likely to appear first
and with what probability?
Addendum
Numerous readers discovered that Barry Wolk's rule for picking
the best triplet B to beat triplet A is equivalent to putting in front of A
the complement of its next-to-last symbol, then discarding the last sym-
bol. More than half these correspondents found that the method also
works for quadruplets except for the two in which Hand T alternate
throughout. In such cases the symbol put in front of A is the same as its
next to last one.
Since October 1974, when this chapter first appeared in Scientific
American, many papers have been published that prove Conway's al-
gorithm and give procedures for picking the best n-tuplet for all values
of n. Two important early articles are cited in the bibliography. The
paper by Guibas and Odlyzko gives 26 references.
Readers David Sachs and Bryce Hurst each noted that Conway's
"leading number," when an n-tuplet is compared with itself, automat-
ically gives that tuplet's waiting time. Simply double the leading num-
ber.
Ancient Chinese philosophers (I am told) divided matter into five
categories that form a nontransitive cycle: wood gives birth to fire, fire
to earth, earth to metal, metal to water, and water to wood. Rudy
Rucker's science-fiction story "Spacetime Donuts" (Unearth, Summer
1978) is based on a much more bizarre nontransitive theory. If you
move down the scale of size, to several steps below electrons, you get
back to the galaxies of the same universe we now occupy. Go up the
scale several stages beyond our galactic clusters, and you are back to the
elementary particles-not larger ones, but the very same particles that
make our stars. The word "matter" loses all meaning.
The following letter was published in Scientific American Uanuary
1975):
308 PROBABILITY
Sirs:
Martin Gardner's article on the paradoxical situations that arise from
non transitive relations may have helped me win a bet in Rome on the
outcome of the Ali v. Foreman world heavyweight boxing title match in
ZaIre on October 30.
Ali, though slower than in former years, and a 4-1 betting underdog,
may have had a psychological and motivational advantage for that par-
ticular fight. But in addition, Gardner's mathematics might be relevant.
Even though Foreman beat Frazier, who beat Ali, Ali could still beat
Foreman because there may be a nontransitive relation between the
three.
I ranked the three fighters against the criteria of speed, power, and
technique (including psychological technique) as reported in the press,
and spotted a nontransitive relation worth betting on:
Speed
Power
Technique
ALI
2
3
1
FRAZIER
1
2
3
FOREMAN
3
1
2
Foreman's power and technique beat Frazier, but Ali's technique and
speed beat Foreman. It was worth the bet. The future implications are,
however, that Frazier can still beat Ali!
ANTHONY PIEL
Vaud, Switzerland
David Silverman (Journal of Recreational Mathematics 2, October
1969, p. 241) proposed a two-person game that he called "blind
Penney-ante." It is based on the nontransitive triplets in a run of fair
coin tosses. Each player simultaneously chooses a triplet without
knowing his opponent's choice. The triplet that shows up first wins.
What is a player's best strategy? This is not an easy problem. A full so-
lution, based on an 8 x 8 game matrix, is given in The College Mathe-
matics Journal as the answer to Problem 299 (January 1987, pp. 74-76).
Answers
Which pattern of heads and tails, TTHH or HHH, is more likely
to appear first as a run when a penny is repeatedly flipped? Applying
More Nontransitive Paradoxes 309
John Horton Conway's algorithm, we find that TTHH is more likely to
precede HHHwith a probability of 7/12, or odds of seven to five. Some
quadruplets beat some triplets with even greater odds. For example,
THHH precedes HHH with a probability of 7/8, or odds of seven to
one. This is easy to see. HHH must be preceded by a T unless it is the
first triplet of the series. Of course, the probability of that is 1/8.
The waiting time for TTHH and for THHH is 16, compared with a
waiting time of 14 for HHH. Both cases of the quadruplet versus the
triplet, therefore, exhibit the paradox of a less likely event occurring be-
fore a more likely event with a probability exceeding 1/2.
Bibliography
Nontransitiue Voting and Tournament Paradoxes
K. J. Arrow, Social Choice and Individual Values, Wiley, 1951; second edition,
1970.
D. Black, The Theory of Committees and Elections, Cambridge University Press,
1958; Kluwer Academic, 1986.
S. J. Brams, Paradoxes in Politics, Free Press, 1976.
R Farquharson, Theory of Voting, Yale University Press, 1969.
P. C. Fishburn, "Paradoxes of Voting," The American Political Science Review, Vol.
68, June 1974, pp. 539-46.
D. Khahr, "A Computer Simulation of the Paradox of Voting," American Political
Science Review, Vol. 50, June 1966, pp. 384-96.
RD. Luce and H. Raiffa, Games and Decision, Wiley, 1957.
A. F. MacKay, Arrow's Theorem: The Paradox of Social Choice, Yale University
Press, 1980.
J. W. Moon, Topics on Tournaments, Holt, Rinehart, and Winston, 1968.
W. H. Riker, "Voting and the Summation of Preferences: An Interpretive Biblio-
graphical Review of Selected Developments During the Last Decade." The Amer-
ican Political Science Review 55, December 1961, pp. 900-11.
W. H. Riker, "Arrow's Theorem and Some Examples of the Paradox of Voting,"
Mathematical Applications in Political Science, Q.M. Claunch (ed.), Southern
Methodist University, 1965.
Z. Usiskin, "Max-Min Probabilities in the Voting Paradox," The Annals of Mathe-
matical Statistics, Vol. 35. June 1964, pp. 857-62.
Nontransitiue Betting qames
M. Gardner, "Lucifer at Las Vegas," Science Fiction Puzzle Tales, Clarkson Potter,
1981, Problem 27.
R Honsberger, "Sheep Fleecing with Walter Funkenbusch," Mathematical Gems
III, Washington, DC: Mathematical Association of America, 1985.
310 PROBABILITY
J. C. Frauenthal and A. B. Miller, "A Coin Tossing Game," Mathematics Magazine
53, September 1980, pp. 239-43.
R. L. Tenney and C. C. Foster, "Nontransitive Dominance," Mathematics Magazine
49, May 1976, pp. 115-20.
Conway's Algorithm
S. Collings, "Coin Sequence Probabilities and Paradoxes," Bulletin of the Institute
of Mathematics and its Applications 18, November/December 1982, pp. 227-32.
R. L. Graham, D. E. Knuth, and O. Patashnik, Concrete Mathematics, 2e, Addison-
Wesley, 1994, pp. 403-10.
L. J. Guibas and A. M. Odlyzko, "String Overlaps, Pattern Matching, and Nontran-
sitive Games," Journal of Combinatorial Theory 30, March 1981, pp. 183-208.
More Nontransitive Paradoxes 311
VJ[I
Infinity
Chapter 24 Infinite Regress
Chairman of a meeting of the Society of Lo-
gicians: "Before we put the motion: 'That the
motion be now put,' should we not first put
the motion: That the motion: "That the mo-
tion be now put" be now put'?"
From an old issue of Punch
The infinite regress, along which thought is compelled to march
backward in a never ending chain of identical steps, has always aroused
mixed emotions. Witness the varied reactions of critics to the central
symbol of Broadway's most talked-about 1964 play, Edward Albee's Tiny
Alice. The principal stage setting-the library of an enormous castle
owned by Alice, the world's richest woman-was dominated by a scale
model of the castle. Inside it lived Tiny Alice. When lights went on and
off in the large castle, corresponding lights went on and off in the small
one. A fire erupted simultaneously in castle and model. Within the
model there was a smaller model in which a tinier Alice perhaps lived,
and so on down, like a set of nested Chinese boxes. ("Hell to clean,"
commented the butler, whose name was Butler.) Was the castle itself,
into which the play's audience peered, a model in a still larger model,
and that in turn ... ? A similar infinite nesting is the basis ofE. Nesbit's
short story, "The Town in the Library in the Town in the Library" (in her
Nine Unlikely Tales); perhaps this was the source of Albee's idea.
For many of the play's spectators the endless regress of castles stirred
up feelings of anxiety and despair: Existence is a mysterious, impene-
trable, ultimately meaningless labyrinth; the regress is an endless cor-
ridor that leads nowhere. For theological students, who were said to
flock to the play, the regress deepens an awareness of what Rudolf Otto,
the German theologican, called the mysterium tremendum: the ulti-
mate mystery, which one must approach with awe, fascination, hu-
mility, and a sense of "creaturehood." For the mathematician and the
logician the regress has lost most of its terrors; indeed, as we shall soon
see, it is a powerful, practical tool even in recreational mathematics.
First, however, let us glance at some of the roles it has played in West-
ern thought and letters.
315
Aristotle, taking a cue from Plato's Parmenides, used the regress in
his famous "third man" criticism of Plato's doctrine of ideas. If all men
are alike because they have something in common with Man, the ideal
and eternal archetype, how (asked Aristotle) can we explain the fact
that one man and Man are alike without assuming another archetype?
And will not the same reasoning demand a third, fourth, and fifth ar-
chetype, and so on into the regress of more and more ideal worlds?
A similar aversion to the infinite regress underlies Aristotle's argu-
ment, elaborated by hundreds of later philosophers, that the cosmos
must have a first cause. William Paley, an 18th-century English the-
ologian, put it this way: "A chain composed of an infinite number of
links can no more support itself than a chain composed of a finite num-
ber of links." A finite chain does indeed require support, mathemati-
cians were quick to point out, but in an infinite chain eve.lY link hangs
securely on the one above. The question of what supports the entire se-
ries no more arises than the question of what kind of number precedes
the infinite regress of negative integers.
Agrippa, an ancient Greek skeptic, argued that nothing can be
proved, even in mathematics, because every proof must be proved valid
and its proof must in turn be proved, and so on. The argument is re-
peated by Lewis Carroll in his paper "What the Tortoise Said to
Achilles" (Mind, April 1895). After finishing their famous race, which
involved an infinite regress of smaller and smaller distances, the Tor-
toise traps his fellow athlete in a more disturbing regress. He refuses to
accept a simple deduction involving a triangle until Achilles has writ-
ten down an infinite series of hypothetical assumptions, each necessary
to make the preceding argument valid.
F. H. Bradley, the English idealist, argued (not very convincingly)
that our mind cannot grasp any type of logical relation. We cannot say,
for example, that castle A is smaller than castle B and leave it at that,
because "smaller than" is a relation to which both castles are related.
Call these new relations c and d. Now we have to relate c and d to the
two castles and to "smaller than." This demands four more relations,
they in turn call for eight more, and so on, until the shaken reader col-
lapses into the arms of Bradley's Absolute.
In recent philosophy the two most revolutionary uses of the regress
have been made by the mathematicians Alfred Tarski and Kurt Gade!.
Tarski avoids certain troublesome paradoxes in semantics by defining
truth in terms of an endless regress of "metalanguages," each capable
316 INFINITY
of discussing the truth and falsity of statements on the next lower level
but not on its own level. As Bertrand Russell once explained it: "The
man who says 'I am telling a lie of order n' is telling a lie, but a lie of
order n + 1." In a closely related argument Godel was able to show that
there is no single, all-inclusive mathematics but only an infinite regress
of richer and richer systems.
The endless hierarchy of gods implied by so many mythologies and
by the child's inevitable question "Who made God?" has appealed to
many thinkers. William James closed his Varieties of Religious Experi-
ence by suggesting that existence includes a collection of many gods,
of different degrees of inclusiveness, "with no absolute unity realized
in it at all. Thus would a sort of polytheism return upon us .... " The
notion turns up in unlikely places. Benjamin Franklin, in a quaint lit-
tle work called Articles of Belief and Acts of Religion, wrote: "For I be-
lieve that man is not the most perfect being but one, but rather that
there are many degrees of beings superior to him." Our prayers, said
Franklin, should be directed only to the god of our solar system, the
deity closest to us. Many writers have viewed life as a board game in
which we are the pieces moved by higher intelligences who in turn are
the pieces in a vaster game. The prophet in Lord Dunsany's story "The
South Wind" observes the gods striding through the stars, but as he
worships them he sees the outstretched hand of a player "enormous
over Their heads."
Graphic artists have long enjoyed the infinite regress. The striking
cover of the April 1965, issue of Scientific American showed the mag-
azine cover reflected in the pupil of an eye. The cover of the Novem-
ber 1964, Punch showed a magician pulling a rabbit out of a hat. The
rabbit in turn is pulling a smaller rabbit out of a smaller hat, and this
endless series of rabbits and hats moves up and off the edge of the
page. It is not a bad picture of contemporary particle physics. It is now
known that protons and neutrons are made of smaller units called
quarks, and if superstring theory is correct, all particles are made of ex-
tremely tiny loops that vibrate at different frequencies. Does the uni-
verse have, as some physicists believe, infinite levels of structure?
The play within the play, the puppet show within the puppet show,
the story within the story have amused countless writers. Luigi Piran-
delIo's Six Characters in Search of an Author is perhaps the best-
known stage example. The protagonist in Miguel de Unamuno's novel
Mist, anticipating his death later in the plot, visits Unamuno to protest
Infinite Regress 317
and troubles the author with the thought that he too is only the figment
of a higher imagination. Philip Quarles, in Aldous Huxley's Point
Counter Point, is writing a novel suspiciously like Point Counter Point.
Edouard, in Andre Gide's The Counterfeiters, is writing The Counter-
feiters. Norman Mailer's story "The Notebook" tells of an argument be-
tween the writer and his girl friend. As they argue he jots in his
notebook an idea for a story that has just come to him. It is, of course,
a story about a writer who is arguing with his girl friend when he gets
an idea ....
J. E. Littlewood, in A Mathematician's Miscellany, recalls the fol-
lowing entry, which won a newspaper prize in Britain for the best piece
on the topic: "What would you most like to read on opening the morn-
ing paper?"
OUR SECOND COMPETITION
The First Prize in the second of this year's competitions goes to Mr.
Arthur Robinson, whose witty entry was easily the best of those we re-
ceived. His choice of what he would like to read on opening his paper
was headed "Our Second Competition" and was as follows: "The First
Prize in the second ofthis year's competitions goes to Mr. Arthur Robin-
son, whose witty entry was easily the best of those we received. His
choice of what he would like to read on opening his paper was headed
'Our Second Competition,' but owing to paper restrictions we cannot
print all of it."
One way to escape the torturing implications of the endless regress
is by the topological trick of joining the two ends to make a circle, not
necessarily vicious, like the circle of weary soldiers who rest them-
selves in a bog by each sitting on the lap of the man behind. Albert Ein-
stein did exactly this when he tried to abolish the endless regress of
distance by bending three-dimensional space around to form the hy-
persurface of a four-dimensional sphere. One can do the same thing
with time. There are Eastern religions that view history as an endless
recurrence of the same events. In the purest sense one does not even
think of cycles following one another, because there is no outside time
by which the cycles can be counted; the same cycle, the same time go
around and around. In a similar vein, there is a sketch by the Dutch
artist Maurits C. Escher of two hands, each holding a pencil and sketch-
ing the other (see Figure 24.1). In Through the Looking Glass Alice
dreams of the Red King, but the King is himself asleep and, as Twee-
318 INFINITY
24.1. Maurits C ......... "" .............
IrrniAnrln Hands
319
of old-Asgool, Trodath, Skun, and Rhoog-he sees the shadowy forms
of three larger gods farther up the slope. He leads his disciples up the
mountain only to observe, years later, two larger gods seated at the
summit, from which they point and mock at the gods below. Shaun
takes his followers still higher. Then one night he perceives across the
plain an enormous, solitary god looking angrily toward the mountain.
Down the mountain and across the plain goes Shaun. While he is carv-
ing on rock the story of how his search has ended at last with the dis-
covery of the ultimate god, he sees in the far distance the dim forms of
four higher deities. As the reader can guess, they are Asgool, Trodath,
Skun, and Rhoog.
No branch of mathematics is immune to the infinite regress. Numbers
on both sides of zero gallop off to infinity. In modular arithmetics they
go around and around. Every infinite series is an infinite regress. The
regress underlies the technique of mathematical induction. Georg Can-
tor's transfinite numbers form an endless hierarchy of richer infinities.
A beautiful modern example of how the regress enters into a mathe-
matical proof is related to the difficult problem of dividing a square into
other squares no two of which are alike. The question arises: Is it pos-
sible similarly to cut a cube into a finite number of smaller cubes no
two of which are alike? Were it not for the deductive power of the
regress, mathematicians might still be searching in vain for ways to do
this. The proof of impossibility follows.
Assume that it is possible to "cube the cube." The bottom face of
such a dissected cube, as it rests on a table, will necessarily be a
"squared square." Consider the smallest square in this pattern. It can-
not be a corner square, because a larger square on one side keeps any
larger square from bordering the other side (see Figure 24.2{a)). Simi-
larly, the smallest square cannot be elsewhere on the border, between
corners, because larger squares on two sides prevent a third larger
square from touching the third side (Figure 24.2{b)). The smallest
square must therefore be somewhere in the pattern's interior. This in
turn requires that the smallest cube touching the table be surrounded
by cubes larger than itself. This is possible (Figure 24.2{ c)), but it means
that four walls must rise above all four sides of the small cube-pre-
venting a larger cube from resting on top of it. Therefore on this small-
est cube there must rest a set of smaller cubes, the bottoms of which
will form another pattern of squares.
The same argument is now repeated. In the new pattern of squares
320 INFINITY
b
cannot
the smallest cube) on
will form another pattern of squares. Clearly the argument leads an
endless regress of smaller like the endless hierarchy of fleas in
solvable.
constructions one, involving an infinite
curve a area one
inch?
equilateral
pathological curves are infinite in number. Start
24.3{a)) on the central third of
a
321
cwve
322
24.4.
curve
323
friend once said. the universe seems to be made of nothing, yet some-
how it manages to exist.
Some top mathematical physicists, Stanislaw Ulam and David Bohm
for example, defended and defend the notion that matter has infinite
layers of structure in both directions. One of H. G. Wells's fantasies
portrayed our universe as a molecule in a ring worn by a gigantic hand.
I described the snowflake curve before it became known as the old-
est and simplest of Benoit Mandelbrofs famous fractals. For more on
fractals, see this volume's Chapter 27 and Chapter 8 of my Penrose
Tiles to Trapdoor Ciphers.
Answers
The cross-stitch curve has, like its analogue the snowflake, an
infinite length. It bounds an area twice that of the original square. The
drawing at the left in Figure 24.5 shows its appearance after the third
construction. After many more steps it resembles (when viewed at a
distance) the drawing at the right. Although the stitches seem to run di-
agonally' actually every line segment in the figure is vertical or hori-
zontal. Similar constructions of pathological curves can be based on
any regular polygon, but beyond the square the figure is muddied by
overlapping, so that certain conventions must be adopted in defining
what is meant by the enclosed area.
Samuel P. King, Jr., of Honolulu, supplied a good analysis of curves
of this type, including a variant of the cross-stitch discovered by his fa-
ther. Instead of erecting four squares outwardly each time, they are
Figure 24.S. Solution to cross-stitch curve problem
324 INFINITY
erected inwardly from sides of each
infinite but encloses zero area.
J. L. Borges, "Avatars of the Tortoise," Labyrinths: Selected Stories
ings, New York: New Directions, 1964.
curve an
J. L. Borges. "Partial Magic in the Quixote," Labyrinths: Selected and Other
Writings, New New Directions, 1964.
W. King, "Snowflake Curves," The Mathematics Teacher, 57. April,
1964, pp. 219-22.
A Dutch
Infinite Regress 325
H. P. Owen, "Infinity in Theology and Metaphysics," The Encyclopedia of Philos-
ophy. Vol. 4, New York: Crowell Collier, 1967, pp. 190-93.
J. Passmore, "The Infinite Regress," Philosophical Reasoning, New York: Charles
Scribner's Sons, 1961.
J. E. Schneider, "A Generalization ofthe Von Koch Curve," Mathematics Magazine,
Vol. 38, No.3, May, 1965, pp. 144-47.
J. Thomson, "Infinity in Mathematics and Logic," The Encyclopedia of Philosophy,
Vol. 4, New York: Crowell Collier, 1967, pp. 183-90.
326
INFINITY
Chapter 25
A graduate student at Trinity
Computed the square of infinity.
But it gave him the fidgets
To put down the digits,
Aleph-Null
and Aleph-One
So he dropped math and took up divinity
-ANONYMOUS
In 1963 Paul J. Cohen, then a 29-year-old mathematician at
Stanford University, found a surprising answer to one of the great prob-
lems of modern set theory: Is there an order of infinity higher than the
number of integers but lower than the number of points on a line? To
make clear exactly what Cohen proved, something must first be said
about those two lowest known levels of infinity.
It was Georg Ferdinand Ludwig Philipp Cantor who first discovered
that beyond the infinity of the integers-an infinity to which he gave
the name aleph-null-there are not only higher infinities but also an in-
finite number of them. Leading mathematicians were sharply divided
in their reactions. Henri Poincare called Cantorism a disease from
which mathematics would have to recover, and Hermann Weyl spoke
of Cantor's hierarchy of alephs as "fog on fog."
On the other hand, David Hilbert said, "From the paradise created for
us by Cantor, no one will drive us out," and Bertrand Russell once
praised Cantor's achievement as "probably the greatest of which the age
can boast." Today only mathematicians of the intuitionist school and a
few philosophers are still uneasy about the alephs. Most mathemati-
cians long ago lost their fear of them, and the proofs by which Cantor
established his "terrible dynasties" (as they have been called by the
world-renowned Argentine writer Jorge Luis Borges) are now univer-
sally honored as being among the most brilliant and beautiful in the
history of mathematics.
Any infinite set of things that can be counted 1, 2, 3, ... has the car-
dinalnumber alepho (aleph-null), the bottom rung of Cantor's aleph
ladder. Of course, it is not possible actually to count such a set; one
merely shows how it can be put into one-to-one correspondence with
the counting numbers. Consider, for example, the infinite set of primes.
327
It is easily put in one-to-one correspondence with the positive inte-
gers:
1
L
2
2
L
3
3
L
5
4
L
7
5 6 ...
J- J-
11 13 ...
The set of primes is therefore an aleph-null set. It is said to be "count-
able" or "denumerable." Here we encounter a basic paradox of all infi-
nite sets. Unlike finite sets, they can be put in one-to-one
correspondence with a part of themselves or, more technically, with
one of their "proper subsets." Although the primes are only a small por-
tion of the positive integers, as a completed set they have the same
aleph number. Similarly, the integers are only a small portion of the ra-
tional numbers (the integers plus all integral fractions), but the rationals
form an aleph-null set too.
There are all kinds of ways in which this can be proved by arranging
the rationals in a countable order. The most familiar way is to attach
them, as fractions, to an infinite square array of lattice points and then
count the points by following a zigzag path, or a spiral path if the lat-
tice includes the negative rationals. Here is another method of ordering
and counting the positive rationals that was proposed by the American
logician Charles Sanders Peirce.
Start with the fractions 0/1 and 1/0. (The second fraction is mean-
ingless, but that can be ignored.) Sum the two numerators and then the
two denominators to get the new fraction 1/1, and place it between the
previous pair: 0/1, 1/1, 1/0. Repeat this procedure with each pair of ad-
jacent fractions to obtain two new fractions that go between them:
0 1 1 2 1
1 2 1 1 0
The five fractions grow, by the same procedure, to nine:
0 1 1 2 1 3 2 3 1
-
-
- -
1 3 2 3 1 2 1 1 0
In this continued series every rational number will appear once and
only once, and always in its simplest fractional form. There is no need,
as there is in other methods of ordering the rationals, to eliminate frac-
tions, such as 10/20, that are equivalent to simpler fractions also on the
list, because no reducible fraction ever appears. If at each step you fill
328 INFINITY
the cracks, so to speak, from left to right, you can count the fractions
simply by taking them in their order of appearance.
This series, as Peirce said, has many curious properties. At each new
step the digits above the lines, taken from left to right, begin by re-
peating the top digits of the previous step: 01, 011, 0112, and so on.
And at each step the digits below the lines are the same as those above
the lines but in reverse order. As a consequence, any two fractions
equally distant from the central 111 are reciprocals of each other. Note
also that for any adjacent pair, alb, eld, we can write such equalities as
be - ad = 1, and eld - alb = llbd. The series is closely related to what
are called Farey numbers (after the English geologist John Farey. who
first analyzed them), about which there is now a considerable litera-
ture.
It is easy to show that there is a set with a higher infinite number of
elements than aleph-null. To explain one of the best of such proofs, a
deck of cards is useful. First consider a finite set of three objects, say a
key, a watch, and a ring. Each subset of this set is symbolized by a row
of three cards (see Figure 25.1.), a face-up card (white) indicates that the
object above it is in the subset, a face-down card (black) indicates that
it is not. The first subset consists of the original set itself. The next
three rows indicate subsets that contain only two of the objects. They
are followed by the three subsets of single objects and finally by the
empty (or null) subset that contains none of the objects. For any set of
n elements the number of subsets is 2n. (It is easy to see why. Each el-
ement can be either included or not, so for one element there are two
subsets, for two elements there are 2 x 2 = 4 subsets, for three elements
there are 2 x 2 x 2 = 8 subsets, and so on.) Note that this formula applies
even to the empty set, since 2 = 1 and the empty set has the empty set
as its sole subset.
This procedure is applied to an infinite but countable (aleph-null) set
of elements at the left in Figure 25.2. Can the subsets of this infinite set
be put into one-to-one correspondence with the counting integers? As-
sume that they can. Symbolize each subset with a row of cards, as be-
fore, only now each row continues endlessly to the right. Imagine these
infinite rows listed in any order whatever and numbered 1., 2, 3, ...
from the top down.
If we continue forming such rows, will the list eventually catch all
the subsets? No-because there is an infinite number of ways to pro-
duce a subset that cannot be on the list. The simplest way is to consider
Aleph-Null and Aleph-One 329
2
3
4
5
6
7
8
25.1. bUI)seiLS a set
330
CD
@ @
CD
@ @
0110
0 0
2
D II
2 1
3
II 10
3 .0
4
I
4 .0
5
0111
5 1
Figure 2S.2. A countable infinity has an uncountable infinity of subsets (left) that corre-
spond to the real numbers (right).
nal number 2 raised to the power of aleph-nulL This proof shows that
such a set cannot be matched one-to-one with the counting integers. It
is a higher aleph, an "uncountable" infinity.
Cantor's famous diagonal proof, in the form just given. conceals a
startling bonus. It proves that the set of real numbers (the rationals plus
the irrationals) is also uncountable. Consider a line segment, its ends
numbered 0 and 1. Every rational fraction from 0 to 1 corresponds to a
point on this line. Between any two rational points there is an infinity
of other rational points; nevertheless, even after all rational points are
identified, there remains an infinity of unidentified points-points that
correspond to the unrepeating decimal fractions attached to such alge-
braic irrationals as the square root of 2 and to such transcendental ir-
rationals as pi and e. Every point on the line segment, rational or
irrational, can be represented by an endless decimal fraction. But these
fractions need not be decimal; they can also be written in binary nota-
tion. Thus every point on the line segment can be represented by an
endless pattern of l's and O's, and every possible endless pattern of l's
and O's corresponds to exactly one point on the line segment. See Ad-
dendum.
Now, suppose each face-up card at the left in Figure 25.2 is replaced
by 1 and each face-down card is replaced by 0, as shown at the right in
the illustration. Put a binary point in front of each row and we have an
Aleph-Null and Aleph-One 331
infinite list of binary fractions between 0 and 1. But the diagonal set of
symbols, after each 1 is changed to 0 and each 0 to 1, is not on the list,
and the real numbers and points on the line are uncountable. By care-
ful dealing with the duplications Cantor showed that the three sets-
the subsets of aleph-null, the real numbers, and the totality of points on
a line segment-have the same number of elements. Cantor called this
cardinal number C, the "power of the continuum." He believed it was
also Xl (aleph-one), the first infinity greater than aleph-null.
By a variety of simple, elegant proofs Cantor showed that C was the
number of such infinite sets as the transcendental irrationals (the alge-
braic irrationals, he proved, form a countable set), the number of points
on a line of infinite length, the number of points on any plane figure or
on the infinite plane, and the number of points in any solid figure or in
all of 3-space. Going into higher dimensions does not increase the num-
ber of points. The points on a line segment one inch long can be
matched one-to-one with the points in any higher-dimensional solid, or
with the points in the entire space of any higher dimension.
The distinction between aleph-null and aleph-one (we accept, for
the moment, Cantor's identification of aleph-one with C) is important
in geometry whenever infinite sets of figures are encountered. Imagine
an infinite plane tessellated with hexagons. Is the total number of ver-
tices aleph-one or aleph-null? The answer is aleph-null; they are eas-
ily counted along a spiral path (see Figure 25.3). On the other hand, the
number of different circles of one-inch radius that can be placed on a
sheet of typewriter paper is aleph-one because inside any small square
near the center of the sheet there are aleph-one points, each the center
of a different circle with a one-inch radius.
Consider in turn each of the five symbols J. B. Rhine uses on his
"ESP" test cards (see Figure 25.4). Can it be drawn an aleph-one num-
ber of times on a sheet of paper, assuming that the symbol is drawn
with ideal lines of no thickness and that there is no overlap or inter-
section of any lines? (The drawn symbols need not be the same size, but
all must be similar in shape.) It turns out that all except one can be
drawn an aleph-one number of times. Can the reader show which sym-
bol is the exception?
Richard Schlegel, a physicist, attempted to relate the two alephs to
cosmology by calling attention to a seeming contradiction in the steady-
state theory. According to that theory, the number of atoms in the cos-
mos at the present time is aleph-null. (The cosmos is regarded as
332 INFINITY
25.3. counts
25.4. Five "ESp
li
blings, they would have grown to an aleph-one set. But the cosmos
cannot contain an aleph-one set of atoms. Any collection of distinct
physical entities (as opposed to the ideal entities of mathematics) is
countable and therefore, at the most, aleph-nulL
In his paper, "The Problem of Infinite Matter in Steady-State Cos-
mology," Schlegel found the way out. Instead of regarding the past as
a completed aleph-null set of finite time intervals (to be sure, ideal in-
stants in time form an aleph-one continuum, but Schlegel is concerned
with those finite time intervals during which doublings of atoms
occur), we can view both the past and the future as infinite in the in-
ferior sense of "becoming" rather than completed. Whatever date is
suggested for the origin of the universe (remember, we are dealing with
the steady-state model, not with a Big Bang or oscillating theory), we
can always set an earlier date. In a sense there is a "beginning," but we
can push it as far back as we please. There is also an "end," but we can
push it as far forward as we please. As we go back in time, continually
halving the number of atoms, we never halve them more than a finite
number of times, with the result that their number never shrinks to
less than aleph-nulL As we go forward in time, doubling the number of
atoms, we never double more than a finite number of times: therefore
the set of atoms never grows larger than aleph-nulL In either direction
the leap is never made to a completed aleph-null set of time intervals.
As a result the set of atoms never leaps to aleph-one and the disturbing
contradiction does not arise.
Cantor was convinced that his endless hierarchy of alephs, each ob-
tained by raising 2 to the power of the preceding aleph, represented all
the alephs there are. There are none in between. Nor is there an Ulti-
mate Aleph, such as certain Hegelian philosophers of the time identi-
fied with the Absolute. The endless hierarchy of infinities itself, Cantor
argued, is a better symbol of the Absolute.
All his life Cantor tried to prove that there is no aleph between aleph-
null and C, the power of the continuum, but he never found a proof. In
1938 Kurt Godel showed that Cantor's conjecture, which became
known as the Continuum Hypothesis, could be assumed to be true,
and that this could not conflict with the axioms of set theory.
What Cohen proved in 1963 was that the opposite could also be as-
sumed. One can posit that C is not aleph-one; that there is at least one
aleph between aleph-null and C, even though no one has the slightest
notion of how to specify a set (for example, a certain subset of the tran-
334 INFINITY
scendental numbers) that would have such a cardinal number. This
too is consistent with set theory. Cantor's hypothesis is undecidable.
Like the parallel postulate of Euclidean geometry, it is an independent
axiom that can be affirmed or denied. Just as the two assumptions about
Euclid's parallel axiom divided geometry into Euclidean and non-
Euclidean, so the two assumptions about Cantor's hypothesis now di-
vide the theory of infinite sets into Cantorian and non-Cantorian. It is
even worse than that. The non-Cantorian side opens up the possibility
of an infinity of systems of set theory, all as consistent as standard the-
ory now is and all differing with respect to assumptions about the
power of the continuum.
Of course Cohen did no more than show that the continuum hy-
pothesis was undecidable within standard set theory, even when the
theory is strengthened by the axiom of choice. Many mathematicians
hope and believe that some day a "self-evident" axiom, not equivalent
to an affirmation or denial of the continuum hypothesis, will be found,
and that when this axiom is added to set theory, the continuum hy-
pothesis will be decided. (By "self-evident" they mean an axiom which
all mathematicians will agree is "true.") Indeed, G6del expected and
Cohen expects this to happen and are convinced that the continuum
hypothesis is in fact false, in contrast to Cantor, who believed and
hoped it was true. So far, however, these remain only pious Platonic
hopes. What is undeniable is that set theory has been struck a gigantic
cleaver blow, and exactly what will come of the pieces no one can say.
Addendum
In giving a binary version of Cantor's famous diagonal proof
that the real numbers are uncountable, I deliberately avoided compli-
cating it by considering the fact that every integral fraction between 0
and 1 can be represented as an infinite binary fraction in two ways. For
example, % is .01 followed by aleph-null zeroes and also .001 followed
by aleph-null ones. This raises the possibility that the list of real binary
fractions might be ordered in such a way that complementing the di-
agonal would produce a number on the list. The constructed number
would, of course, have a pattern not on the list, but could not this be a
pattern which expressed, in a different way, an integral fraction on the
list?
The answer is no. The proof assumes that all possible infinite binary
Aleph-Null and Aleph-One 335
patterns are listed, therefore every integral fraction appears twice on the
list, once in each of its two binary forms. It follows that the constructed
diagonal number cannot match either form of any integral fraction on
the list.
In every base notation there are two ways to express an integral frac-
tion by an aleph-null string of digits. Thus in decimal notation V4 =
.2500000 ... = .2499999 .... Although it is not necessary for the validity
of the diagonal proof in decimal notation, it is customary to avoid am-
biguity by specifying that each integral fraction be listed only in the
form that terminates with an endless sequence of nines, then the diag-
onal number is constructed by changing each digit on the diagonal to
a different digit other than nine or zero.
Until I discussed Cantor's diagonal proof in Scientific American, I
had not realized how strongly the opposition to this proof has per-
sisted; not so much among mathematicians as among engineers and
scientists. I received many letters attacking the proof. William Dil-
worth, an electrical engineer, sent me a clipping from the LaGrange
Citizen, LaGrange, IL, January 20,1966, in which he is interviewed at
some length about his rejection of Can tori an "numerology." Dilworth
first delivered his attack on the diagonal proof at the International Con-
ference on General Semantics, New York, 1963.
One of the most distinguished of modern scientists to reject Canto-
rian set theory was the physicist P. W. Bridgman. He published a paper
about it in 1934, and in his Reflections of a Physicist (Philosophical Li-
brary, 1955) he devotes pages 99-104 to an uncompromising attack on
transfinite numbers and the diagonal proof. "I personally cannot see an
iota of appeal in this proof," he writes, "but it appears to me to be a per-
fect nonsequitur-my mind will not do the things that it is obviously
expected to do if it is indeed a proof."
The heart of Bridgman's attack is a point of view widely held by
philosophers of the pragmatic and operationalist schools. Infinite num-
bers, it is argued, do not "exist" apart from human behavior. Indeed, all
numbers are merely names for something that a person does, rather
than names of "things." Because one can count 25 apples but cannot
count an infinity of apples, "it does not make sense to speak of infinite
numbers as 'existing' in the Platonic sense, and still less does it make
sense to speak of infinite numbers of different orders of infinity, as
does Cantor."
"An infinite number," declares Bridgman, "is a certain aspect of what
336 INFINITY
one does when he embarks on carrying out a process . . . an infinite
number is an aspect of a program of action."
The answer to this is that Cantor did specify precisely what one must
"do" to define a transfinite number. The fact that one cannot carry out an
infinite procedure no more diminishes the reality or usefulness of Can-
tor's alephs than the fact that one cannot fully compute the value of pi di-
minishes the reality or usefulness of pi. It is not, as Bridgman maintained,
a question of whether one accepts or rejects the Platonic notion of num-
bers as "things." For an enlightened pragmatist, who wishes to ground all
abstractions in human behavior, Cantorian set theory should be no less
meaningful or potentially useful than any other precisely defined ab-
stract system such as, say, group theory or a non-Euclidean geometry.
Several readers attacked Schlegel's claim that Cantor's alephs expose
a contradiction in a steady-state theory of the universe. They focused
on his argument that after a countable infinity of atom doublings the
cosmos would contain an uncountable infinity of atoms. For details on
this objection see Rudy Rucker's Infinity and the Mind (The Mathe-
matical Association of America, 1982), pages 241-42.
For an account of crank objections to Cantor's alephs, see "Cantor's
Diagonal Process," in Underwood Dudley's Mathematical Cranks (The
Mathematical Association of America, 1992).
Answers
Which of the five ESP symbols cannot be drawn an aleph-one
number of times on a sheet of paper, assuming ideal lines that do not
overlap or intersect, and replicas that may vary in size but must be
similar in the strict geometric sense?
Only the plus symbol cannot be aleph-one replicated. Figure 25.5
shows how each of the other four can be drawn an aleph-one number
of times. In each case points on line segment AB form an aleph-one
continuum. Clearly a set of nested or side-by-side figures can be drawn
so that a different replica passes through each of these points, thus
putting the continuum of points into one-to-one correspondence with
a set of nonintersecting replicas. There is no comparable way to place
replicas of the plus symbol so that they fit snugly against each other.
The centers of any pair of crosses must be a finite distance apart (al-
though this distance can be made as small as one pleases), forming a
countable (aleph-null) set of points. The reader may enjoy devising a
Aleph-Null and Aleph-One 337
H++H++ts
A S
Figure 25.5. Proof for "ESP" -symbol problem
formal proof that aleph-one plus symbols cannot be drawn on a page.
The problem is similar to one involving alphabet letters that can be
found in Leo Zippin 's Uses of Infinity (Random House, 1962), page 57.
So far as I know, no one has yet specified precisely what conditions
must be met for a linear figure to be aleph-one replicable. Some figures
are aleph-one replicable by translation or rotation, some by shrinkage,
some by translation plus shrinkage, some by rotation plus shrinkage. I
rashly reported in my column that all figures topologically equivalent
to a line segment or a simple closed curve were aleph-one replicable,
but Robert Mack, then a high school student in Concord, MA, found a
simple counterexample. Consider two unit squares, joined like a verti-
cal domino, then eliminate two unit segments so that the remaining
segments form the numeral 5. It is not aleph-one replicable.
Bibliography
Farey numbers
A. H. Beiler, Recreations in the Theory of Numbers. Dover, 1964, Chapter 16.
G. S. Cunningham, "Farey Sequences." Enrichment Mathematics for High School,
National Council of Teachers of Mathematics. 1963. Chapter 1.
338 INFINITY
R. Honsberger, Ingenuity in Mathematics, The Mathematical Association of Amer-
ica New Mathematical Library, 1970, Chapter 5.
Transfinite numbers
J. Breuer, Introduction to the Theory of Sets, Prentice-Hall, 1958.
E. V. Huntington, The Continuum, Dover, 1955.
M. M. Zuckerman, Sets and Transfinite Numbers, Macmillan, 1974.
Cohen's proof
P. J. Cohen, Set Theory and the Continuum Hypothesis, W. A. Benjamin, 1966.
P. J. Cohen and R. Hersh, "Non-Cantorian Set Theory," Scientific American, De-
cember 1967, pp. 104-16.
D. S. Scott, "A Proof of the Independence of the Continuum Hypothesis." Mathe-
matical Systems Theory, Vol. 1, 1967, pp. 89-111.
R. M. Smullyan, "The Continuum Problem," The Encyclopedia of Philosophy,
Macmillan, 1967.
R. M. Smullyan, "The Continuum Hypothesis," The Mathematical Sciences, MIT
Press, 1969, pp. 252-71.
Alephs and cosmology
R. Schlegel, "The Problem ofInfinite Matter in Steady-State Cosmology," Philoso-
phy of Science, Vol. 32, January 1965, pp. 21-31.
R. Schlegel. Completeness in Science, Appleton-Century-Crofts, 1967, pp. 138-49.
S. Ulam, "Combinatorial Analysis in Infinite Sets and Some Physical Theories,"
SIAM Review, Vol. 6, October 1964, pp. 343-55.
Aleph-Null and Aleph-One 339
Chapter 26
Points
Have no parts or joints.
How then can they combine
To form a line?
-J. A. LINDON
Supertasks
Every finite set of n elements has 2
n
subsets if one includes the
original set and the null, or empty, set. For example, a set of three ele-
ments, ABC, has 2
3
= 8 subsets: ABC, AB, BC, AC, A, B, C, and the null
set. As the philosopher Charles Sanders Peirce once observed (Col-
lected Papers Vol. 4, p. 181), the null set "has obvious logical pecu-
liarities." You can't make any false statement about its members
because it has no members. Put another way, if you say anything logi-
cally contradictory about its members, you state a truth, because the so-
lution set for the contradictory statement is the null set. Put
colloquially, you are saying something true about nothing.
In modern set theory it is convenient to think of the null set as an
"existing set" even though it has no members. It can also be said to have
2
n
subsets because 2 = 1, and the null set has one subset, namely itself.
And it is a subset of every set. If set A is included in set B, it means that
every member of set A is a member of set B. Therefore, if the null set is
to be treated as a legitimate set, all its members (namely none) must be
in set B. To prove it by contradiction, assume the null set is not in-
cluded in set B. Then there must be at least one member of the null set
that is not a member of B, but this is impossible because the null set has
no members.
The n elements of any finite set obviously cannot be put into one-to-
one correspondence with its subsets because there are always more
than n subsets. Is this also true of infinite sets? The answer is yes, and
the general proof is one of the most beautiful in all set theory.
It is an indirect proof, a reductio ad absurdum. Assume that all ele-
ments of N, a set with any number or members, finite or infinite, are
matched one-to-one with all of N's subsets. Each matching defines a
coloring of the elements:
340
1. An element is paired with a subset that includes that element. Let us
call all such elements blue.
2. An element is paired with a subset that does not include that ele-
ment. We call all such elements red.
The red elements form a subset of our initial set N. Can this subset
be matched to a blue element? No, because every blue element is in its
matching subset, therefore the red subset would have to include a blue
element. Can the red subset be paired with a red element? No, because
the red element would then be n c l u d ~ d in its subset and would there-
fore be blue. Since the red subset cannot be matched to either a red or
blue element of N, we have constructed a subset of Nthat is not paired
with any element of N. No set, even if infinite, can be put into one-to-
one correspondence with its subsets. If n is a transfinite number, then
2n-by definition it is the number of subsets of n-must be a higher
order of infinity than n.
Georg Cantor, the founder of set theory, used the term aleph-null for
the lowest transfinite number. It is the cardinal number of the set of all
integers, and for that reason is often called a "countable infinity." Any
set that can be matched one-to-one with the counting numbers, such as
the set of integral fractions, is said to be a countable or aleph-null set.
Cantor showed that when 2 is raised to the power of aleph-null-giving
the number of subsets of the integers-the result is equal to the cardi-
nal number of the set of all real numbers (rational or irrational), called
the "power of the continuum," or C. It is the cardinal number of all
points on a line. The line may be a segment of any finite length, a ray
with a beginning but no end, or a line going to infinity in both direc-
tions. Figure 26.1 shows three intuitively obvious geometrical proofs
that all three kinds of line have the same number of points. The slant
p
P A A P B
Figure 26.1. The number of points on a line segment AB is the same as on a longer line
segment (left), a ray (center), and a line (right).
Supertasks 341
lines projected from point P indicate how all points on the line segment
AB can be put into one-to-one correspondence with all points on the
longer segment, on a ray, and on an endless line.
The red-blue proof outlined above (Cantor published it in 1890) of
course generates an infinite hierarchy of transfinite numbers. The lad-
der starts with the set of counting numbers, aleph-null, next comes C,
then all the subsets of C, then all the subsets of all the subsets of C, and
so on. The ladder can also be expressed like this:
1 h 11 C 2
c 22c 2
22C
a ep -nu , , , , , ....
Cantor called C "aleph-one" because he believed that no transfinite
number existed between aleph-null and C. And he called the next num-
ber aleph-two, the next aleph-three, and so on. For many years he tried
unsuccessfully to prove that C was the next higher transfinite number
after aleph-null, a conjecture that came to be called the Continuum
Hypothesis. We now know, thanks to proofs by Kurt G6del and Paul
Cohen, that the conjecture is undecidable within standard set theory,
even when strengthened by the axiom of choice. We can assume with-
out contradiction that Cantor's alephs catch all transfinite numbers, or
we can assume, also without contradiction, a non-Cantorian set theory
in which there is an infinity of transfinite numbers between any two
adjacent entries in Cantor's ladder. (See the previous chapter for a brief,
informal account of this.)
Cantor also tried to prove that the number of points on a square is the
next higher transfinite cardinal after C. In 1877 he astounded himself
by finding an ingenious way to match all the points of a square to all
the points of a line segment. Imagine a square one mile on a side, and
a line segment one inch long (see Figure 26.2). On the line segment
every point from 0 to 1 is labeled with an infinite decimal fraction:
The point corresponding to the fractional part of pi is .14159 ... , the
point corresponding to 1/3 is .33333 ... , and so on. Every point is rep-
resented by a unique string of aleph-null digits, and every possible
aleph-null string of digits represents a unique point on the line seg-
ment. (A slight difficulty arises from the fact that a fraction such as
.5000 ... is the same as .4999 ... , but it is easily overcome by dodges
we need not go into here.)
Now consider the square mile. Using a Cartesian coordinate system,
every point on the square has unique x and y coordinates, each of
which can be represented by an endless decimal fraction. The illustra-
342 INFINITY
.73205 ... - ---<