Logic of Not
Logic of Not
3, 2000
The Logic of the Diamond Sutra: A is not A,
therefore it is A
SHIGENORI NAGATOMO
ABSTRACT This paper attempts to make intelligible the logic contained in the Diamond
Sutra. This `logic is called the `logic of not. It is stated in a propositional form: `A is not A,
therefore it is A. Since this formulation is contradictory or paradoxical when it is read in light
of Aristotelean logic, one might dismiss it as nonsensical. In order to show that it is neither
nonsensical nor meaningless, the paper will articulate the philosophical reasons why the Sutra
makes its position in this contradictory form. The thesis to be presented is that as long as one
understands the `logic of not from a dualistic, either-or egological standpoint, it remains
contradictory, but in order to properly understand it, one must effect a perspectival shift from
the dualistic, egological stance to a non-dualistic, non-egological stance. This thesis is advanced
with a broader concern in mind: to reexamine how the self understands itself, how it
understands others, and how it understands its intra-ecological relationship with nature.
When one side is illuminated,
the other side remains in darkness.
Do gen (12001253), Genjokoan
I. Introduction
An early phase of Mahayana Buddhism witnessed the development of a genre of
literature that Buddhologists call prajn a pa ramita , which is translated in English as the
`perfection of wisdom. To this genre of literature belongs a treatise that is named the
Diamond Sutra. (Hereafter, it will be abbreviated as the Sutra; Skt.: Vajracced-
hika prait a pa ramita ) This paper attempts to render intelligible the logic that is used in
this Sutra in which a seemingly contradictory assertion is made to articulate the
Buddhist understanding of (human) reality. The renowned Japanese Buddhologist,
Hajime Nakamura, calls it a `logic of not (Skt.; na pr thak).
1
The `logic of not can be
stated in propositional form as: `A is not A, therefore it is A. When this is read and
interpreted in light of Aristotelean logic, the linguistic formulation of this logic is
outright contradictory, and one may therefore dismiss it as nonsensical.
2
As I think such
a pronouncement is based on an un-informed and misguided judgement when it is
assessed in light of Mahayana Buddhism in general, and the Diamond Sutra in
particular, I should like to elucidate its signicance by clarifying the philosophical
reasoning that informs the formulation of the `logic of not. In order to do so, I will
develop in this paper the position that it remains contradictory only as long as one
understands the `logic of not in light of Aristotelean logic, which assumes a dualistic,
either-or egological
3
stance, but to understand it properly, I shall argue that one must
read it by effecting a perspectival shift to a non-dualistic, non-egological stance. Only
then can one see that it is not contradictory, and hence that it is not nonsensical.
ISSN 0955-2367 print/ISSN 1469-2961 online/00/030213-32 2000 Taylor & Francis Ltd
DOI: 10.1080/09552360020011277
214 Shigenori Nagatomo
In order to show unequivocally that the `logic of not does indeed appear to be
contradictory, or if not that, paradoxical, it is best to cite some of the representative
examples from the Sutra. To this end, note the following examples of the `logic of not.
(1) `The world is not the world, therefore it is the world (section 13-c).
(2) `All dharmas are not all dharmas, therefore they are all dharmas (section 17-c).
(3) `The perfection of wisdom [prajn a pa ramita ] is not the perfection of wisdom,
therefore it is the perfection of wisdom (section 13-a).
(4) `A thought of truth [bhu tasam jn a ] is not a thought of truth, therefore it is the
thought of truth (section 14-a).
Although these instances obviously do not exhaust all the occurrences of the `logic of
not in the Sutra,
4
it is clear that the `logic of not uses the form, `A is not A, therefore
it is A, where A stands for a linguistic sign, such as `the world, `all dharmas, `the
perfection of wisdom, and `a thought of truth, mentioned in the above sample
sentences. Each of these terms can be systematically placed into this propositional form
to formalise the logic as: `A is not A, therefore it is A.
5
Upon reading these example sentences, we would intuitively judge that they are
contradictory or paradoxical at best. A question arises as to why we intuit them in this
way. Is there in our conceptual scheme something that compels us to make this
judgement? Contrary to our ordinary conceptual scheme, could it be that the Sutra has
its own conceptual scheme which is different from ours? If so, what is it? Could it have
its own philosophical reason to formulate its position in this contradictory or paradoxi-
cal form?
As a way of specically addressing these questions, this paper will assume the
following order of presentation. In Section II, I will provide a brief introduction to what
the Sutra takes its goal to be, i.e. the `perfection of wisdom, for it provides the
necessary background information for those who are unfamiliar with the Sutra. In
Section III, based on the Sutras basic theme of the perfection of wisdom, I will
articulate the conceptual scheme of the Sutra, by spelling out some of the fundamental
characteristics given to the bodhisattva, while contrasting them with a conceptual
scheme of what the Sutra identies as the `foolish, ordinary people. With this contrast
in mind, I will analyse in the following two sections the rst two components in the
`logic of not namely, an afrmation of A, and the negation of A. Based on this two-part
analysis of `A is not A, I will clarify the meaning of the perspectival shift in Section VI,
showing a transformation from the dualistic eitheror egological stance to the non-du-
alistic, non-egological stance, the topical concern of this paper. In Section VII, I will
briey attempt to clarify the meaning of the reafrmation of A after it is negated, i.e.
`therefore it is A. In Section VIII in lieu of a conclusion, I will draw implications of this
`logic of not that may be pertinent in reecting upon the contemporary situation.
Before proceeding to follow the above outline, the methodological orientation that
this paper assumes may briey be indicated in order to avoid an unnecessary accusation
and criticism. This paper on the philosophical articulation of the `logic of not does not
intend to be a philological piece that scrutinises the text from within the standpoint of
the Sutra itself, although an inter-textual study may yield fruitful results, especially in
connection with the works of Nagarjuna. It will not entirely ignore a philological aspect
of the text, but it will probe into the text and textual evidence from the philosophical
viewpoint wherever an issue in question is relevant to the thesis of this paper. This
orientation is necessary because the text in question is a sutra, not a commentary; it
The Logic of the Diamond Sutra 215
simply makes declarative statements concerning the philosophical and experimental
background for the formulation of the `logic of not without explicitly stating its reason
or structure in analytical terms that are intelligible to the contemporary reader. For this
reason, I do not believe that a purely philological or textual investigation can render the
`logic of not intelligible. The paper must proceed from a philosophical point-of-view,
which is suggested in the way the thesis of this paper is formulated, and it must take
into account an experiential background that informs the formulation of the `logic of
not, though this experiential component is embedded in the text and requires unveil-
ing.
II. The Goal of the Diamond Sutra
As preparatory to making the `logic of not intelligible, it will be helpful to have in our
purview the original meaning of the Sanskrit title of the Diamond Sutra, for the Sutra
develops on its meaning as the thematic focus. The Sanskrit title for the Sutra is
Vajraccedhikaprajn a pa ramita , which is usually divided into two components, as each
forms a linguistic unit: vajraccedhika and prajn a pa ramita . According to Hajime Naka-
mura, the rst component of the title, vajraccedhika , means to `cut like a diamond or
to `sunder like a thunderbolt where `diamond or `thunderbolt is used metaphorically
to designate the power of severing all doubts and attachments
6
from the cognitive
activity of the human being. In the Sutra, this idea of `severing all doubts and
attachments is conceived to be a project of pra xis. That is, since they are deeply
connected to the somaticity and the unconscious of the cognitive subject, the act of
severing doubts and attachments must be distinguished from the suppressive power of
a conscious, non-meditative `rational will as Kant, for example, conceives of handling
the issue in his rst Critique.
7
The second component of the title, prajn a pa ramita , as mentioned at the beginning,
designates the `perfection of wisdom,
8
where wisdom (prajn a ) operates in the form of
knowledge that is non-discriminatory in nature.
9
In this sense, it should also be clearly
demarcated from the meaning of wisdom in which a theoretical knowledge of the
universal is singled out as the genuine form of wisdom, as, for example, Aristotle
proposes in his Metaphysics.
10
In light of the practical nature of `severing all doubts and
attachments, the perfection of wisdom is an existential project aiming at achieving and
embodying a non-discriminatory basis for knowledge. That is to say, the `perfection of
wisdom designates an achieved state of personhood.
11
To put it differently, wisdom is
posited as a practical ideal for those who have not achieved it, in which case it involves
a process of perfecting it, while when it is taken to mean the achievement of an
awakened state, it describes a state in which the `perfection of wisdom is embodied
vis-a -vis the emancipation from the fundamental ignorance of not knowing how to
experience reality as it is.
What needs to be noted methodologically in this connection is that the Sutra
presupposes that the perfection of wisdom is realised by letting the practical take
precedence over the theoretical.
12
As we gather the foregoing senses of vajraccedhika
and prajn a pa ramita together in light of this methodological attitude, the thematic
concern of the Sutra emerges; it centres on the idea of practically perfecting the goal of
wisdom that functions like a diamond or a thunderbolt, such that it severs `all doubts
and attachments from the cognitive activity of the human being where the metaphors
`diamond and `thunderbolt designate the non-discriminatory activity of the mind.
This practical meaning of perfecting wisdom is a leitmotif of the Sutra and it is
216 Shigenori Nagatomo
developed throughout this text in a series of dialogues between the Buddha and
Subhuti,
13
one of his disciples, wherein the Buddha is depicted as an incarnate
embodiment of wisdom, while Subhuti appears as an interlocutor who raises questions
to the Buddha as to how this practical goal of perfecting wisdom is realised, and how
it should be articulated when appealing to language. This sense of perfecting wisdom
is established early in the Sutra. For example, in section 2 of the Sutra Subhuti asks a
question to the Buddha concerning how one should go about achieving the perfection
of wisdom. It reads:
How then, O Lord (Bhagavad), should a son or daughter of good family, who
has set out in the Bodhisattva-vehicle (bodhisattva-ya na), stand, how progress,
how control their thoughts?
14
This question can generally be posed as: `how should one go about the practice of
perfecting wisdom? as Conze suggests.
15
According to his interpretation, `standing
refers to ones determination to bring the practical, existential project to perfection,
`progress refers to the seekers steady development in concentration and wisdom, and
`control refers to the seekers ability to ward off distractions in the calm of meditative
stillness.
16
The above quote identies the practice of perfecting wisdom as the `bod-
hisattva-vehicle (bodhisattva-ya na), wherein it is metaphorically spoken of as a vehicle
(ya na) upon which a bodhisattva rides. There are many interpretations of how to
understand the idea of the bodhisattva,
17
but in the context of the Sutra it refers to `a
being who intends on [the achievement of] enlightenment
18
for ones own sake as well
as for the sake of beneting others, wherein the priority is placed on the rst rather than
on the second aspect, although they are integral to each other in that one without the
other cannot be established as a full-edged person.
19
Such a person is the type whose
activity is depicted as `energetic, courageous, heroic and victorious.
20
The Sutra
alternatively calls the goal of perfecting wisdom as `the supreme, right, equal enlighten-
ment
21
(anuttara samyak-sam bodhi). To recapitulate the goal of the Sutra, then, its
thematic focus is placed on the bodhisattva who strives toward realising the `supreme,
right, equal enlightenment, and who embodies the basis for the nondiscriminatory
knowledge that is the perfection of wisdom.
III. The Conceptual Scheme of the Sutra: the Bodhisattva
With this understanding of the goal of the Sutra in mind, I will examine some of the
fundamental characteristics which the Sutra gives to the person of the bodhisattva, while
drawing philosophical implications from them, insofar as they are pertinent to render-
ing the `logic of not intelligible. In so doing, the conceptual scheme of the Sutra will
become evident.
In order to have a clear idea of how the bodhisattva is depicted in the Sutra, it is
perhaps informative if we rst examine how it understands the `foolish, ordinary people
(ba la-pr thag-jana n ),
22
so that we can put the idea of the bodhisattva in clear relief in
contrast to it. In a passage taken from section 25 of the Sutra, we nd the following
description of the `foolish, ordinary people. It reads:
[T]he foolish, ordinary people [ba la-pr thagana n ] think that they have a self
[a tman]. Therefore, they seize on (or have an attachment to) it.
23
Bala-pr thag-jana n , if translated literally, means `those who were born separately but in
its plural form it designates, as Nakamura and Conze inform us, `the fools and `the
The Logic of the Diamond Sutra 217
ordinary people,
24
and hence their present rendition of ba la-pr thag-jana n as the
`foolish, ordinary people. Because the phrase `foolish, ordinary people is ambiguous in
that it may be taken to mean that there are either ordinary people who are foolish or
those who are not, it is important to specify the intent of qualifying the ordinary people
with the adjective `foolish. The phrase does not suggest that there are ordinary people
who are not fools, rather all ordinary people, according to the Sutra, are `fools. It does
implicitly suggest, however, that there are people who are not `fools. One of the
representatives of that class, according to the Sutra, is the bodhisattva who is on the way
to perfecting wisdom.
Here we need to pose the question as to why the Sutra maintains that having the idea
of a self (a tman) is a characteristic of `the foolish, ordinary people. This calls for a
philosophical articulation of the conceptual scheme
25
of the Sutra which regards `the
foolish, ordinary people as holding the idea of a self, and in virtue of which the idea
arises in them such that they believe it worthy of accepting it to be true. The above
quote thematises the epistemological stance of such `foolish, ordinary people in terms
of `seizing on; it states that the `foolish, ordinary people seize on the idea of a self.
Generally speaking, we can take `seizing on to refer to an act-aspect of the mind, in the
present context, that of the `foolish, ordinary people. It is philosophically signicant to
note here that the idea of a self that is seized on, to use Husserls terminology, is
`correlative with the (noetic) act of seizing.
26
According to Husserl, the subject casts a
(thematic) intentionality to an object in virtue of the basic structure of consciousness
that he characterises as `consciousness-of, where `of connotes a linkage between the
act of consciousness and its (noematic) content, i.e. an object. Consequently, an object
is thematically constituted in the eld of consciousness. In the terminology of the
Mind-only
27
school (`Vijn a ptimatra) of Mahayana Buddhism, this is formulated as the
relation between the grasping-aspect (gra haka ka ra) and the grasped-aspect
(grahya kara); the (noetic) act is that which grasps and the self is that which is grasped
as object, where the latter arises in virtue of the former, although the Sutra would
maintain the reverse is also true. Because of this relationship, which is integral to the
epistemological stance of the `foolish, ordinary people, the Sutra, in agreement with
Husserl, maintains that the correlative relationship between them is structurally estab-
lished. When we analyse this relationship, it suggests that one is nothing without the
other, i.e. they are mutually dependent on each other for their raison detre. The
ordinary people are called `fools for the very reason that they do not realise this
correlative, mutual dependency. That is to say, there is no awareness on the part of the
`foolish, ordinary people that the idea of a self arises as that which is grasped in virtue
of the act of `grasping. However, they are co-determinative with each other. Since this
is the case, it is clear that the idea of a self cannot obtain independently of this
epistemological stance; it is relative to, and co-determinative with, the act of grasping.
28
Therefore, the sense of independence and autonomy, if ascribed to the idea of a self,
can only be relative in nature. The self is neither self-contained nor is it self-sufcient,
as the `foolish, ordinary people may want to believe.
Psychologically speaking, the act of `seizing is an expression of the autonomous
activity of an unconscious
29
desire that surfaces in the eld of consciousness where it
permeates the act aspect of the mind of the `foolish, ordinary people, and because it
is unconscious in origin, it is also constituted somatically.
30
Specically, it is a deep-
rooted desire to connect with the idea of an object such that the act of grasping and that
which is grasped, in the present case, the idea of a self, become identied with each
other such that the `foolish, ordinary people can declare: `I am my self, whether one
218 Shigenori Nagatomo
interprets this self to be empirical or metaphysical in nature, although the Sutra takes
the latter interpretation to be an issue that needs to be dissolved. Psychologically
speaking, this urge for identication arises due to an instability from which the `foolish,
ordinary people suffer, and the act of grasping is an expression of the yearning to
stabilise it. The stabilisation also `frames the `foolish, ordinary people, although they
are again unaware of it. In this connection, we must point out that there are degrees to
this identication, depending on the intensity and the nature of the grasping involved
in the constitution of the idea of a self, ranging from a mere recognition of it from the
point-of-view of theoria to an intense emotional attachment to it, as in the case of `fatal
attraction. In spite of the differing degrees of its expression, however, the driving force
is undoubtedly a passion of grasping. According to Buddhism, the degree of its intensity
is reective of a pattern or a conguration of the affective dispositional tendency of `the
likes and dislikes which every one of `the foolish, ordinary people embodies as a
contingent being. What is signicant to note regarding the act of grasping is that this
affective dispositional tendency permeates the (noetic) act with this unconscious
affectivity, and the noetic act is consequently affected by the affective disposition in
spite of the alleged transparency of its act.
31
Its alternative rendition of `seizing as
`attaching
32
captures this point, where the (noetic) act moves affectively toward the
identication with the idea of a self which, as an object of the (noetic) act, however, is
extrinsic to the (noetic) act itself. Gathering these points together, it is noteworthy that
both the `seizing and `attaching discernible in the (noetic) act are operative uncon-
sciously in the `foolish, ordinary people, i.e. the (noetic) act that is allegedly purely
cognitive in nature, is permeated by the affective dimension of the cognitive subject.
33
What is signicant in weighing both the cognitive and affective dimensions together
is the Sutras value-judgement that having the idea of a self and an attachment to it is
`foolish. We will further examine the epistemological structure of why the Sutra deems
it `foolish, but for now we shall simply characterise the conceptual scheme, a la early
Heidegger, as the everyday standpoint, for one of the characteristics of the `foolish,
ordinary people is that they are immersed in the everydayness of the world, oblivious
to the question of their existential ground.
34
The preceding analysis informs us that
such immersion is due to their unawareness of the correlative, epistemological structure
that holds between the grasping and the grasped.
Now, contrast the characteristic of the `foolish, ordinary people with the characteri-
sations which the Sutra gives to the bodhisattva, where the qualication for the
bodhisattva is expanded beyond the ascription given to the `foolish, ordinary being.
This includes a negation of such ideas as a living being (sattva-sam jn a ), an individual
soul (ji va-sam jn a), a person (pudgala-sam jn a ), all of which are metaphysicalised with an
air of eternity. Thus, section 3 of the Sutra reads:
If in a Bodhisattva
35
the thought of a `being should take place, he could not
be called a `bodhi-being [bodhisattva]. `And why? He is not to be called a
bodhi-being, in whom the thought of a self [a tman-sam jn a ] or of a being
[sattva-sam jn a ] should take place, or the thought of a living soul (jiva-sam jn a ),
or of a person (pudagala-sam jn a ).
36
In order to qualify as a bodhisattva, then, the Sutra maintains that one should not seize
on the thoughts
37
of a self (a tman), a living being (sattva-sam jn a), an individual soul
(ji va-sam jn a ), or a person (pudgala-sam j a ), where `should not carries a sense of
negating the `foolish thoughts that are ascribed to the `foolish, ordinary people as their
characteristic, thereby moving away from foolishness toward the perfection of wisdom.
The Logic of the Diamond Sutra 219
For now, we can understand the bodhisattva to mean a seeker of the path who does not
attach him/herself to the metaphysical or substantialistic `thoughts of a self (a man), an
individual being (ji va), a living being (sattva), or a person (pudgala). As such, it is
advocating for the bodhisattva the stance of non-attachment. I will deal with the logical
structure of what it means to hold a stance of non-attachment when I examine the
meaning of negation in the Sutra.) At this point, it will be sufcient to take note of the
fact that the above analysis suggests that it conceives of the epistemological stance of
the bodhisattva as departing from the conceptual scheme of the `foolish, ordinary
people that is everyday in nature. That is to say, the Sutra conceives of an epistemolog-
ical stance unique to the bodhisattva that is not found in the epistemological stance of
the `foolish, ordinary people. What distinguishes the bodhisattva from the `foolish,
ordinary people in regard to their conceptual schemes is whether or not there is
`seizing or `attachment in the act-aspect of the cognition.
38
Now with these observations in mind, we will see a further qualication given to the
idea of the bodhisattva, this time regarding the object of both sensory perception and
mind. We nd the following in section 14-e:
Do not generate a mind that dwells on the material things, nor on the objects
of sight, sound, touch, fragrance, nor on the objects (dharma) of the mind.
39
To qualify as a bodhisattva in search of `the supreme, right and equal enlightenment,
40
the Sutra stipulates in this passage that the bodhisattva must not dwell on material
objects, objects of external sensory perception, or objects of mind. What is the
philosophical signicance of specifying these three classes of objects as a possible source
of non-attachment for the bodhisattva? Is there a common denominator in the bod-
hisattvas conceptual scheme which, contrary to the standpoint of the `foolish, ordinary
people, generates non-attachment? Let us take the example of a material object as an
instance of generating attachment, and infer from it the conceptual structure of the
bodhisattva. In the everyday standpoint of the `foolish, ordinary people when they
assume the `natural standpoint,
41
a subject stands `here, while a material thing exists
`out there as an object, wherein a spatial distance separates them. In coming to know
a material thing, the subject must objectify it and thus distance itself from the object,
although in this operation no question is asked regarding the presuppositions and
projections which the subject brings to the process of knowing. Note that the distinc-
tion between `here and `there is established in the subject as a referential point from
the side of the subject, and as such this distinction is relative to the subject. In this
scheme, knowledge does not obtain if there is no subject apart from the object, or
conversely if there is no object apart from the subject. One presupposes the other for
knowledge to obtain. If, for example, the primacy falls on the subject, it takes on an
idealistic stance, and if, on the other hand, it focuses on the object, it assumes an
objectivistic stance as in the case of natural science. In either case, what is known is
relative to the nature of the structural relationship that is sustained between the subject
and the object. Here the relationship between the subject and the object is taken to be
ontologically dualistic, however nai ve it may be. Moreover, note that this spatial
distance between them is constituted by a relation of opposition: the subject stands
opposed to the object, for they `face each other. For this opposition to be a constituting
factor in this relationship, there must be an act of discrimination on the part of the
subject, for the discrimination does not arise, under normal circumstances, from the
side of the (material) object.
In fact, the oppositional relationship between the subject and the object structurally
arises from the discriminatory function of the subject in relating itself to the object the
220 Shigenori Nagatomo
discriminatory function, for example, that enables the subject to differentiate one object
from another object, which is a thematising function of the (noetic) act of the mind.
This is no different when examining objects of external sensory perception or objects of
the mind. Both are constituted as objects by the epistemological subject, although the
object that is so constituted is no longer `out there but instead `in here, in the mind
of the subject, i.e. it is constituted immanently in the eld of the subjects conscious-
ness. The differentiations arises due to a thematic intentionality that is driven by
ego-interest and concern.
42
Even this difference is self-generated; the `distance between
the subject and the object still remains structurally, because the subject, by denition,
is that which cannot become an object; there is a structural gap between them. It is a
structural gap intrinsic to its epistemological stance that cannot be closed due to the
limitation which this epistemological stance imposes on the nature of experience. In all
of these instances, however, we are led to accept that the subject is the generative factor
for establishing the discriminatory and oppositional relationship, wherein the subject
operates by relying, to use modern terminology, on the ego-consciousness, whose
primary function of discrimination is triggered by its own ego-desire and interest. In
other words, the material object, the object of external sensory perception and the
object of mind are all egologically constituted, where I understand the term egological to
mean an oppositional, discriminatory attitude issuing from the ego-consciousness of the
subject that is driven by an unconscious desire. (Later we will see a fuller development
of this term.) We will conclude, then, that because of this egological constitution, the
`seizing and `attachment to the object of cognition occur. It is this egological consti-
tution that the Sutra admonishes to negate and avoid, i.e. it encourages us to go beyond
the egological constitution of internal and external objects which `foolish, ordinary
people habitually `seize upon in their everyday standpoint. According to the Sutra, this
is because:
if, Subhuti, these Bodhisattvas should have a thought
43
of either a dharma or
a no-dharma, they would thereby seize on a self, on a being, on a soul, on a
person. And Why? Because a Bodhisattva should not seize on either a dharma
or a no-dharma.
44
Here in this passage, the Sutra introduces the most comprehensive category of Bud-
dhism, dharma, to subsume the idea of a self, a being, etc., and states that the ideas
such as the objects of external sensory perception and the objects of mind arise in virtue
of `having a thought of either dharma or no-dharma. The intent of introducing the idea
of `dharma is clear: to cut off, once and for all, an `idle discourse in the mind arising
from the everyday, dualistic standpoint the `idle in the sense of a `chatter which
makes Heideggers Das Man inauthentic for the term dharma is the most comprehen-
sive category in Buddhism that includes in its scope both the conditioned and the
unconditioned. Hence, if a bodhisattva can also do away with the thought of either a
dharma or a no-dharma, it naturally follows that the bodhisattva can do away with the
idea of a self, a being, etc.
To give the general, philosophical point of this passage, then, the act of `seizing on
(or attaching to) either a dharma or a no-dharma creates a one-sided attitude. For
example, if a bodhisattva seizes on a dharma, it leads to the postulation of a metaphysical
substance, i.e. the creation of substance ontology, when dharma is metaphysicalised.
When this is applied to the idea of a self, for example, it leads to the postulation of an
eternal self, i.e. it substantialises and absolutises the idea of a self such that it takes on
a metaphysical meaning. On the other hand, if the bodhisattva seizes on a no-dharma,
The Logic of the Diamond Sutra 221
it leads to nihilism.
45
Both of these positions are entailed by the egological act of
`seizing intrinsic to the epistemological stance of the everyday standpoint. More
importantly, this occurs unconsciously in the case of the `foolish, ordinary people, as
was noted in the foregoing. That is, without conscious awareness one commits oneself
to a homocentric understanding of ones self, and thus to ones interpersonal relation-
ships, and ones ecological relation to nature. The standpoint of the `foolish, ordinary
people is homocentric because whatever arises, be it eternalism or nihilism, arises out
of the very structure of the dualistic egological constitution by means of the act of
`grasping.
When we examine the linguistic aspect that accompanies the egological constitution
of the object, it entails the following consequences. Seizing on (or attaching to) either
a dharma or a no-dharma translates into accepting a dichotomy of either afrmation or
negation as the standard for making a judgement, which presupposes either-or logic as
its modus operandi. Here, the either-or attitude is a logical stance that prioritises one over
the other by dichotomising the whole, usually saving the explicit at the expense of the
implicit, hence resulting in the one-sidedness of `seizing on either dharma or no-
dharma. As such, it favours an imbalanced attitude that is invested by ego interest and
desire. In this context, we have a clearer understanding of the term `egological consti-
tution wherein the `logical designates the either-or logic operative in the constitution
of an object when making judgements or when discerning an object. Once it is accepted
as the standard of thinking, it is easy to create various kinds of dualisms. The use of the
terminology, `dualistic, egological is thus justied in such dualisms as mind vs body
(matter), good vs evil, along with a host of others, for dualism of any kind is seamlessly
interwoven with the epistemological structure that frames the ego-consciousness
through either-or logic, i.e. it either afrms or negates a statement. In other words, the
egological constitution of an object inherently involves the necessity of dichotomising
the whole, and this in turn is linked to the act of prioritising one part of the whole over
the other parts. (I will examine another implication of this structure when we analyse
the nature of afrmation in a subsequent section.) What is troublesome is that this
process appears `natural and reasonable to the `foolish, ordinary people, for it is
propelled and guaranteed by the structure of their epistemological stance. As a conse-
quence of prioritisation by means of either-or logic, dualism is accordingly legitimized
in the mind of the `foolish, ordinary people.
By contrast, the Sutra admonishes the bodhisattva against taking either-or logic as the
modus operandi for making judgements or understanding reality. Rather, it recommends
taking the logical stance of `neither-nor propositional form. Linguistically, it advocates
neither afrming nor negating a `dharma or a no-dharma, or ontologically, it maintains
neither being nor non-being. One of the important points that deserves special atten-
tion, here, is that the neither-nor propositional form offers a holistic perspective to the
bodhisattva because this attitude does not admit a dichotomisation as a way of organis-
ing reality, as does the either-or attitude. In this recommendation, we have a glimpse
of the bodhisattvas departing from the egological stance to a non-egological stance,
from dualism to non-dualism, although this transition is only implicit at this stage of
our inquiry. What is established at this point is that the Sutra rejects either-or logic in
favour of neither-nor logic, and in so doing adopts the process of reasoning that aims
at freeing `the foolish, ordinary people from their dualistic, either-or egological consti-
tution that is structurally imposed by the everyday standpoint of the `foolish, ordinary
people, although this freedom, when understood conceptually, is simply intellectual in
nature. In order to actually embody freedom, a perspectival shift must be effected, as
222 Shigenori Nagatomo
we shall see, through an existential transformation through meditation to the non-dual-
istic, non-egological stance.
Let us pursue further how the bodhisattva is characterised in the Sutra in order to
hold in our purview a still clearer idea of how the bodhisattva is conceived. In section
14-e, we nd the following description of the bodhisattva:
the bodhisattva must depart from all thoughts, and aspire to the mind of the
supreme, right, equal enlightenment (anuttara samyak-sam bodhi).
46
How should we philosophically understand the Sutras recommendation that the
bodhisattva `depart from all thoughts (dharma-san jn a?
47
`All thoughts here refers to any
characteristic, sign or object that the discriminatory mind (manas) or sensory percep-
tion of ego-consciousness may entertain as its object. In light of what we have already
observed in the foregoing, we interpret this recommendation to mean a taking of the
neither-nor stance, i.e. neither afrming `all thoughts nor negating them. The Sutra
advances the idea of `departing from all thoughts as an existential remedy for `seizing
either on a dharma or a no-dharma. When seen from the logical point of view, it
becomes evident that such a stance is antithetical to the either-or attitude.
However, this interpretation is still short of the Sutras intention, because simply
taking the neither-nor stance does not enable the bodhisattva to `depart from all
thoughts. That is to say, when attempting to assume this stance, there still remains the
act of taking the attitude of neither afrmation nor negation, which means that there
still exists an ego-consciousness which takes this stance the postulation of the
ego-consciousness that acts. Of course, we conceive of this act as having the power to
free conceptually (but not existentially) from the dualistic, egological constitution of
objects, because we believe that the neither-nor stance transcends the either-or attitude.
Here, we have a glimpse of a difcult idea of negation that is thematised in the Sutra.
We will examine the meaning of negation later, but at this point, we must note that the
Sutra does not accept a straightforward, simple negation by following either-or logic. In
order to fully understand the idea of the negation in question, it is necessary to
incorporate in our understanding, in addition to the operation of negation based on
either-or logic, an existential negation by means of meditational practice, which enables
the bodhisattva to embody non-attachment. It is enough for now, however, to note that
when the Sutra advocates the neither-nor alternative, it is opting for a third perspective
that cannot be accommodated by either afrmation (e.g. substantialistic ontology) or
negation (e.g. nihilism) which the either-or egological stance stipulates.
For this reason, the Sutra qualies further: `If a person is versed in [the experience]
that all thing-states (dharma) are without self, the Tatha gata says that such a person is
truly a bodhisattva.
48
This is where we nd textual evidence for the use of the term
`non-egological. The idea of `all thing-states are without self which appears to be
logically entailed by the negation of the idea of a self must be applied to the
ego-consciousness as well. Otherwise, the ego-consciousness posits the idea of a self as
performing the act of neither afrming nor negating `all things (or thing-states). In
short, there must be a disappearance of the ego-consciousness from the eld of
awareness for anyone to qualify as a bodhisattva. The Sutra explicitly makes this point
in the following:
If a bodhisattva says that `I will lead innumerable sentient beings to nirvana,
such a person cannot be said to be a bodhisattva This is because there is no
such a thing [dharma] that is called bodhisattva.
49
The Logic of the Diamond Sutra 223
We have so far dealt with the bodhisattva as the thematic focus of the Sutra, but here
we are now told, to our great surprise, that `there is no such a thing (dharma) that is
called a bodhisattva. The reason for this denial is found in the very establishment on
the one hand, `I qua the bodhisattva who performs an act of grasping (gra hya), and, on
the other, the `innumerable sentient beings as that which is grasped (graa hya). Again,
this is predicated on the idea that dualism is epistemologically and ontologically the
standard of understanding reality, in this particular case, the nature of interpersonal
relationships. In the terminology we have used previously, it demonstrates an instance
of dualistic egological constitution. Hence, in the second half of the above quote we see
the Sutra denying `I qua the bodhisattva as an object of thought (dharma-sam jn a ). This
is an issue concerning the negation of ego-consciousness that is framed from within the
egological constitution of the self, i.e. whether or not one can negate ones ego-con-
sciousness by relying on either-or logic (either afrmation or negation) to embody the
stance of non-attachment. (I will examine this issue when dealing with nihilism.) Along
with this negation, the above passage further implies a negation of the dualistic stance
that the ego-consciousness employs for engaging its self, its interpersonal relation to
others and its intra-ecological relation to nature. Consequently, the negation of the
dualistic, egological stance suggests an introduction of the non-dualistic, non-egological
stance as its modus operandi, wherein we see a hint for a non-discriminatory activity of
the mind (prajn a )
50
which the bodhisattva existentially attempts to bring to perfection,
for the non-discriminatory activity of the mind arises only through the non-dualistic,
non-egological stance.
51
With this brief articulation of the conceptual structure which the Sutra gives to the
bodhisattva, we are now ready to analyse the meaning of the `logic of not that is
formulated as: `A is not A, therefore it is A. However, before probing into the
philosophical nature of this propositional statement, there is a point that is worthy of
special mention.
52
Until the present, we have never questioned the status of this
propositional statement, whether it is applicable only to specic instances or if its
application is universal. If it is not universal, it has only a local applicability, that is, only
within the domain of Buddhist scholarship and practice. On the other hand, if it is
universal, it is necessary that the form of the statement be capable of instantiating any
A, insofar as it is a thingevent of the world and insofar as it can be realised as a subject
in the subjectpredicate structure
53
of language. The Sutra intends the statement to be
universally applicable to any (linguistic) sign used in subjectpredicate structure and
this is textually suggested by the use of the term dharma, the most comprehensive term
in Buddhism. When this is translated into ordinary language, it means that A can be a
(linguistic) sign for anything that is of and in this world. Accordingly, this means that
A is linguistically a sign for a noun, a noun-phrase, or a noun-clause in the subject
predicate structure of a language, where the language may designate a logical, articial
or natural system of signs. Given this observation, then, we are led to think that A
stands for anything whatsoever of this world as well as that which occurs in this world,
where the world refers to a domain in which thingevents, including objects of the
mind, are thematised through language and experience.
54
The above specication of A
is the most inclusive and comprehensive, and hence universal in the widest sense of the
term, for it purports to exclude nothing of the world, including the idea of nothing, so
long as it functions as a nominative in the subjectpredicate structure of a given
language, so long as we can thematise it in a discourse.
In order to see its universal applicability, then, it will be our task to articulate the
process of reasoning that has led to the formulation of the `logic of not. What makes
224 Shigenori Nagatomo
us judge that the statement `A is not A, therefore it is A is contradictory or paradoxical
is the presence of the syncategorimatic word `not, and if it werent for the occurrence
of this word, it simply states an identity statement that reads: `A is A, therefore it is A.
In this case, it makes an identity statement to the effect that `A is the same as A. There
will be allegedly no problem of understanding it, but this statement is vacuously true,
since it is tautological, i.e. it does not give us any additional information about A. The
Sutra obviously does not want to make a statement that is vacuously true. Instead, it
casts the statement in a contradictory or paradoxical form, by inserting `not. It
maintains its position by making the paradoxical statement that A is A only when A is
negated, only when it goes through the logical moment of negation. In this case, the
rst occurrence of A must be different in meaning from the second occurrence of A
when it is seen from the perspective of the bodhisattva. That is, the rst occurrence of
A is seen from the perspective of the `foolish, ordinary people, but the second
occurrence of A appears only after putting the rst occurrence of A into the logical
momentum of negation. Otherwise, we fail to see both the practical and logical
necessity of negating A. It seems then, that the intelligibilit y of the statement `A is not
A, therefore it is A lies in how we should understand the meaning of negation as the
Sutra conceives of it. How, then, does the Sutra understand negation? In the following
section, I will proceed to examine how the Sutra recognises A, and how it conceives of
the meaning of afrming A. After clarifying these two points, I will examine, in the
following section, the meaning of negating A as the Sutra conceives of it. And lastly, I
will analyse the status of A that is reafrmed after it is negated.
IV. Afrmation of A
What, then, does it mean to afrm A? Here I will examine the logical structure of
afrming and recognising A as A. There are two logical senses on which I will focus
with regard to the idea of A when it is seen in light of either-or logic: in afrming A,
A is taken to be (1) self-same such that `A is the same as A, and (2) A is taken in
relation to not-A without postulating a strict self-sameness where `strict means that
there is no gap or ssure in identifying A as A. The former takes the position that it is
meaningful to make an identity statement by taking A to be self-same, while the latter
does not take this position, because it believes that A can be understood only in
relational terms, i.e. only in relation to not-A. Here I will examine only the rst sense
of A, so as to better clarify the second, relational sense of A later.
That A is a sign means that it can become a subject of a sentence, wherein an act of
thematisation gives rise to A. Generally speaking, the act of thematisation is an
operation of the ego-consciousness that is propelled by or invested in ego-interest and
desire. For this reason, it is a homocentric way of understanding A.
55
Moreover,
although A is originally a uid thing-event in the world, the thematisation, once it is
realised as a subject of a sentence, suggests that A is `frozen or `xed so that any
speaker of a language can engage it, to borrow Wittgensteins terminology, in a
`language game.
56
Once it is frozen in this manner, it enters into, and is situated in, a
conceptual space that a speaker creates for the use of language. This suggests that it
departs from experience and that it is oblivious to the original fact that A is an
experience; a phenomenon of thing-event in the world. In other words, A functions in
the mode of `as if by disregarding the temporalisation of time. It becomes `frozen as
a sign in the language, and conforms to the syntax of a given language. That is to say,
A appears to gain an atemporal status, for whenever a speaker uses (but not just
The Logic of the Diamond Sutra 225
mentions) A in any given domain of discourse, all other users can appeal to its `same
meaning.
When the self-sameness is asserted in respect of A, then, we tend to forget the factors
mentioned above, as if A can stand on its own. By forgetting these factors, however, the
idea of A qua A arises disregarding the fact that A is an articial sign, where `articial
means that it is divorced and abstracted from a ux of the changing world.
57
This is so
because the idea of A in the sense of the self-sameness is a linguistic and conceptual
reication; it is linguistic because A is realised as A in the language, and it is conceptual
because it is thought of as being atemporal or enduring through time. It occurs in the
mind of a person who thinks of A.
58
It needs to be pointed out, however, that
experience subsumes the use of a language.
As we have seen in the previous section, the idea of self-sameness presupposes the
graspinggrasped relationship, which Buddhism rejects as delusory, because it is a
product of the discriminatory mind. Moreover, the self-sameness arises as a conse-
quence of substantialising A.
59
Once it is substantialised, it gives rise to an ontology in
various formulations, ranging from a naturalistic to a metaphysical understanding of
being. Substantialisation
60
and ontologisation psychologically derive from the stance of
attachment, and focus on a meaning that is intra-linguistically dened. Here we need
not reiterate the argument concerning the grasping and grasped relationship. What
needs to be noted, however, is the logical implication of the act of afrmation. The idea
of self-sameness is predicated on a one-sidedness or on a prioritisation that accompa-
nies the modus operandi of either-or logic. The act of afrmation presupposes this
scheme. At the very foundation of the act of afrmation, with its egological either-or
attitude, is the philosophical belief that discrimination is a proper way to approach and
understand A. When the afrmation of A is pronounced, it moves to prioritise that A
which is being afrmed.
Now, in connection with the idea of prioritisation, we need to think through its
meaning from a logical point of view. Take an example of holding the idea of `a self,
which can be realised as A in the propositional statement: `A is not A, therefore it is A.
To hold the idea of a self means to afrm its being or its meaning. But what is the
logical structure of this afrmation? When the idea of a self is afrmed, in order to
legitimise its act of afrmation, it must implicitly negate all that is not the idea of a self.
Or conversely, when the idea of a self is negated, this act of negation must implicitly
afrm all that is not the idea of a self. That is, when A is afrmed as A, for example,
it means that its isolation is accomplished only in a domain where there is not-A. In
other words, A is topicalised by a thematic intentionality chosen out of this domain.
Where there is no A in a domain, it would be meaningless to afrm that A is A. This
analysis suggests that the idea of self-sameness is predicated on the acceptance of
either-or logic as the standard for thinking, as the modus operandi for making judgments.
Either-or logic prioritises a thematic concern which is realized as A. In this respect, the
act of afrmation and the act of negation presuppose each other, as long as they are
framed within the structure of either-or logic. Here, there is a mutual dependency and
relativity between them. From this analysis, it is clear that the idea of a self is an idea
of a self if and only if both the afrmation and the negation of it are together in
operation. Although the one is explicit, the other is implicit. When explicitly afrming
A, its negation is implicit. Since the implicit does not surface in the afrmative
judgement, the negative judgement recedes into the background. On the other hand,
when explicitly negating A, the afrmation is implicit, and recedes into the background.
To bring out more clearly the relationship between the explicit and the implicit,
226 Shigenori Nagatomo
between afrmation and negation, one can take an example from Gestalt psychology
which makes the distinction between foreground (A) and background (not A). When I
see a little squirrel running in the garden, the foreground (a running squirrel) cannot
appear without the supporting function of the background (the garden), nor can the
background appear without the supporting function of the foreground. The determi-
nation of what becomes a foreground in ones perceptual eld or in ones eld of
consciousness depends upon a human thematic interest, as well as upon judgements
which a human deems to be true. A philosophical point we can derive from this analysis
is that the act of afrmation is an afrmation qua negation and the act of negation is a
negation qua afrmation when viewed from a holistic point of view. To understand an
afrmation only as an afrmation without realising this explicitimplicit structure, then,
is only to have a surface understanding of afrmation. In other words, as long as one
makes judgement relying on either-or logic, there is no afrmation qua afrmation pure
and simple just as there is no negation qua negation pure and simple. The `foolish,
ordinary people ignore this logical interdependency. They pretend to focus only on the
explicit while believing that afrmation is an afrmation pure and simple, and negation
is a negation pure and simple. This is an egological constitution.
What follows further from this analysis, however, is that in order for any thing to
qualify as an A, whether it is perceptual or conceptual in nature, the act of discernment
must embrace both afrmation and negation, however contradictory it may seem, when
it is seen from a holistic standpoint. Afrmation pure and simple ignores this fact, and
fails to see the `depth of discernment and judgement. In fact, without this contradic-
tory nature, no thing can appear as an A. What this analysis informs us, then, is that
any thematic interest, when either afrmed or negated, is realised as such, to use
Kitaro s Nishida terminology, as an instance of `the self-identity of contradiction
(mujunteki jiko doitsu). In spite of this, the `foolish, ordinary people ignore it, because
they cannot bring this logical structure to self-awareness, i.e. they suffer from the
limitation and constraint of their standpoint. But what is more fundamental than a
recognition of this paradoxical `identity of contradiction is the fact that both `identity
and `contradiction are twin brothers of the dualistic and egologically constituted,
conceptual scheme of either-or logic. What this reveals is that A is a matter of language
which champions distinction-making as its primary function.
When A is taken to be self-same, i.e. `A is the same as A, there must be a logical
moment of self-reexivity between the rst occurrence of A and the second occurrence
of A in the mind which makes this identication, such that they coincide with each
other without jeopardizing the unity of each occurrence, and without creating a gap
between them. That is, they must be conceptually juxtaposed with each other, wherein
there must be a conceptual `distance between the rst occurrence of A and the second
occurrence of A, whether the self-sameness is taken numerically or qualitatively. The
establishment of the self-sameness in this regard is a bridging act of identication
between these two occurrences. One must function as a subject and the other must
function as an object in the subjectpredicate relationship, and the former must be used
as a standard to measure the latter to determine if they the are same with each other.
In this case, the act of identication stands outside of the domain in which the
self-sameness is to be asserted. That is, it is as if the act of identication is extrinsic to
the idea of self-sameness. As long as there occurs a distinction between the subject and
the object in the establishment of the sameness, a question arises if it is logically
possible for the subject to identify or to judge the rst occurrence of A and the second
occurrence of A as being the same as itself. In order for the rst occurrence as a subject
The Logic of the Diamond Sutra 227
to determine the second occurrence of A as A, there must be a difference between them.
Otherwise, it is impossible to identify or judge that the rst occurrence of A and the
second occurrence of A are the same as itself. If this is the case, the idea of self-same-
ness presupposes a difference and only through this difference is it logically possible to
identify A as the same as itself. In other words, the self-sameness is the self-sameness
qua difference. There is no idea of self-sameness pure and simple. Here we can witness
an operation of the prioritisation as well as interdependency intrinsic to either-or logic,
when A is taken to be same as itself.
When ontology is envisioned by relying on the dualistic, either-or egological stance,
while disregarding the above point, A stands for whatever is perceived and/or conceived
to be. The Sutra does not make, however, distinctions among being, being qua being,
Being, or Being of being. The Sutra neither distinguishes among these senses of being,
nor does it take a stance of dismissing them, and therefore it does not raise an objection
to accommodating them. Simply put, these distinctions are not crucial or central to the
thematic concern and focus of the Sutra. In other words, this kind of distinction making
is foreign to the Sutra. As long as the graspinggrasped relationship is operative in the
theoretical construction of ontology, it does not object to them, for any ontology
constructed in this way is that which the Sutra negates as delusory. However, it does
provisionally recognise the ontological status of A, however A may be ontologised,
either naturalistically or rationalistically. The Sutra grants a provisional sense of reality
to A. The granting of the sense of reality to A is correlative with the nature of the
ontologising activity of the cognitive subject. Yet, it is performed, we must note, by our
everyday, commonsensical understanding of the world in which A can be singled out as
a subject of discourse or as an object of experience. This leads us to the next section
where I shall delve into the meaning of the negation of A as the Sutra conceives of it.
V. A is not A
In the preceding section, we have examined the idea of A as being self-same, wherein
I pointed out that the idea of self-sameness presupposes the idea of difference in order
for the idea of self-sameness to be intelligible. Along with this I also pointed out that
prioritisation and interdependency are concurrent in establishing the idea of self-same-
ness. In this section we are concerned rst with specifying the meaning of the negation
of A, and secondly with specifying the meaning of negating A that includes `neither-nor
propositional form which implies a third perspective, i.e. one that cannot be accommo-
dated by either-or logic.
Now, a question arises: `Can A in the sense of the self-sameness which the foolish,
ordinary people accept stand on its own without reference to other things? `Can A
just be A outside of a domain of discourse where both A and not A are logically
constituted together as the essential components? The answer is no; one without the
other is unintelligible in making either an afrmative or a negative statement. If we are
to understand `standing on its own in the sense, for example, of having an essence in
light of this logical foundation, the `standing on its own must be relative in its being
and meaning, because without other things, i.e. not A, there is no A. That means that
A is dependent for its being and for its meaning on other things. For this reason, the
`standing on its own cannot be taken as absolute or essential in meaning. It cannot
fully or completely `stand on its own, because it is relative to, and dependent on, other
things. The fact that A can be singled out as A (i.e. that it can be thematised as A in
a given discourse by taking the subjectpredicate sentence structure), already discloses
228 Shigenori Nagatomo
this dependency and partiality, for it presupposes both its context and its relationship
with other things. That is, without the context in which A is singled out as A, there can
be no not-A either. This context is the ground out of which and upon which either the
act of afrmation or negation can be made. This implies that when we attribute a
self-sameness to A in its own right, we must understand it to be partial and relative in
respect to its ground as well as to that which is not self-same. In other words, a
self-same A cannot be conceived as the `foolish, ordinary people want to have it. It
entails, therefore, that A is absolutely neither self-sufcient nor self-contained. To
believe, then, that A is absolutely self-same and that it can stand on its own is a
linguistic ction or illusion.
This linguistic ction or illusion surfaces in the use of language when the speaker
substantialises A in the conceptual space created by language, which entails the
appearance of atemporality. Textually, we have dealt with this essential substantialising
or eternalising of objects when we discussed the qualication for the bodhisattva who
does not hold reied ideas of a self or dharma. The `not of `A is not A then functions
to de-substantialise the A that is substantialised by `foolish, ordinary people through
their everyday standpoint. What is specically negated, according to the Sutra, are
categories that are classied as material objects, objects of sensory perception, objects
of mind, all of which are subsumed under the most comprehensive category of dharma.
Accordingly, by negating all these categories of dharmas, the Sutra strives to lead the
`foolish, ordinary people away from their everyday standpoint toward the standpoint of
bodhisattva-like non-substantialisation. Thus, the standpoint of non-substantialisation
rst is reached by way of de-substantialising A. It is advanced as a counter-thesis to the
standpoint of substantialisation which essentialises and/or eternalises either material
objects (materialism), objects of sensory perception (phenomenalism), or objects of
mind (idealism). This is the rst meaning of negating A.
Coupled with this idea of non-substantialisation is the Sutras intention to de-ontol-
ogise these objects, i.e. material objects, perceptual objects and objects of thinking.
Here, `de-ontologisation means to go away from the intellectualisation of these objects;
moving away from the dualistic oppositions of being and non-being, eternalism and
nihilism that are framed by the egological constitution based on either-or logic. The
preposition `de in fact designates a freedom from understanding A as being self-same
in its absolute sense. When we understand substantialisation in this way, the idea of A
as being self-same is something that is thought of, or intellectualised independently of
the impermanence of the world. The act of thinking or intellectualisation, when seen
diachronically, is no exception to it. Alternatively, the de-ontologisation may be
conceived as discarding either-or logic as the modus operandi that governs the act of
thinking and judging, for it is through either-or logic with its intrinsic characteristic of
becoming one-sided that a thinking subject contributes to the postulation of A as being
self-same.
To further illustrate the point that the stance of non-substantialisation and hence an
embodiment of non-attachment, cannot obtain simply by engaging in the logical act of
negation let us consider nihilism. Although it arises from the same conceptual scheme,
nihilism is a counter-thesis to eternalism, i.e. they both arise from the dualistic,
egological constitution that accepts either-or logic as the standard for understanding
reality. Nihilism attempts to negate the being of A together with its meaning. In order
to negate A as an object (whether that be a material object, an object of sensory
perception or an object of mind), one must logically presuppose an afrmation of
not-A. That is, in the terminology of the Sutra, it must afrm no-dharma. However, as
The Logic of the Diamond Sutra 229
long as one afrms not-A when negating A, it cannot but gain a relative status, for what
is negated rests on what is afrmed for its meaning. This is because there is something
that nihilism still afrms, namely, the act-aspect of the cognitive subject; the noetic act
afrms itself in the act of negating. To put this point in terms of the earlier category of
`attachment as opposed to `non-attachment, nihilism attaches itself to the act of
negation without actually negating the act itself, where attachment remains. For this
reason, nihilism always remains partial and incomplete in virtue of its failure to negate
this act of afrmation. This incompleteness is structurally framed within either-or logic.
It cannot surpass itself in spite of its intention. In order for it to become a full-edged
nihilism, it must also negate the afrming act itself such that the act becomes
no-dharma itself. For this reason, nihilism can only hope to turn into cynicism, without
being able to realise its own original intention. The nihilist must be content with
him/herself celebrating the task half-completed.
Recognising that this incompleteness is structurally embedded in either the act of
afrmation or negation, the Sutra advocates the stance of non-attachment. From the
above analysis, it should be clear that this stance is not derived from the mere logical
negation of the substantialist position. In order to understand the non-substantial,
de-ontologising position, the act of negation must be expanded to operate not only on
the object but also on the act of negation itself. The Sutra makes this point by saying
that `all dharmas are without a self, where `self means that which can stand on its own,
without dependence on anything else. From it arises the idea of self-sameness, which
is an essence, or a substance that is intellectually fabricated.
For this reason, the Sutra introduces a third perspective in order to avoid the
positions entailed either by substantialism or nihilism. This position is expressed as
`neither A nor not-A, where one avoids either-or logic that leads the human being into
mistakenly believing that prioritisation or one-sidedness is a structural necessity in the
act of judgement and a correct way of discerning (human) reality. This is the second
sense of the negation in saying that `A is not A. The third perspective of `neither nor
states that a correct way of discerning reality can obtain by taking neither afrmation
nor negation (logically or linguistically); and by siding ontologically with neither being
nor non-being. A `neither-nor proposition understood in this way is a deepening of the
idea of the either-or logical negation, for the mere logical act of negating A as that
which is an object of negation fails to fully accomplish its original intention, that is, it
fails to embody the stance of non-attachment. In other words, nihilism which accepts
relative nothing must be radicalised. To illustrate the point which the neither-nor
stance makes, let us examine further the idea of non-attachment as a qualication for
being a bodhisattva.
We must note that the stance of non-attachment is not merely the consequence of
logically negating the stance of attachment, although the Sutra does linguistically state
it rst in terms of the logical negation, as we illustrated above. That is, psychologically
speaking, `foolish, ordinary people may negate their attachment with a view to yielding
non-attachment, but there arises in them an attachment to non-attachment. In other
words, there arises an afrmation of what is negated. Since there is this afrmation,
they need to further negate the afrmative attitude that is entailed by the initial act of
negation. It is, however, impossible to logically achieve the stance of non-attachment by
means of this logical or linguistic process, because it involves an innite regress. That
is, as soon as one negates the stance of attachment that arises out of an initial negation,
there occurs an afrmation of this negation and then one must negate this afrmation,
and so on ad innitum. As long as the `foolish, ordinary people remain on the logical
230 Shigenori Nagatomo
plane of negating the stance of attachment, or as long as they approach the task as an
intellectual issue, it is impossible to free themselves from repeatedly referring back to
the previous stance of afrmation. At best, this process can yield a nihilistic stance, as
we have just seen in the preceding paragraph. It can not yield the stance of non-attach-
ment.
What causes the above-mentioned innite regress is the fact that in addition to the
content (i.e. the attitude of attachment) that needs to be negated, there remains in this
process the act of negation that also needs to be negated in order for the negation to be
complete, i.e. in order to embody the stance of non-attachment. However, there is no
logical end to negating the act of negation, either. This path also involves an innite
regress, as long as the `foolish, ordinary people remain in the egological and intellectual
place, for it yields only a nominal sense of non-attachment. This arises because the
issue of negating the attitude of attachment is conceptually framed within the stand-
point of dualistic either-or egological structure. To embody an existential stance of
non-attachment, the `foolish, ordinary people must depart from the dualistic egological
standpoint. This was stated in the Sutra that a bodhisattva must depart from all `objects
of thought. The issue is not logical or intellectual in nature; it is deeply connected to
the unconscious and the somaticity of the `foolish, ordinary people which, for this
reason, is more fundamental than the intellectual or logical approach to the issue of
non-attachment, because the unconscious and the body support the activity of ego-con-
sciousness without its knowledge. It demands an existential transformation of the
negating subject. This is the very reason that the Sutra adopts the third perspective of
the neither-nor propositional form, which advances neither attachment nor non-attach-
ment.
It must be noted, however, that the third perspective of the Sutra relies on the
egologically constituted either-or logic to advance its position. Thus, it is true that the
Sutra does not provide a system of its own logic that is different from either-or logic.
We can only speculate as to why it does not. It may be due to the fact that the Sutras
main concern is not a construction of a logical system per se, but rather an existential
concern for freeing the `foolish, ordinary people from the linguistic binds which
either-or logic imposes on them. Moreover, either-or logic, or the act of afrmation and
the act of negation, is the most familiar and readily accessible means of thinking for the
`foolish, ordinary people. By pointing out its inherent limitation, the Sutra attempts to
guide the `foolish, ordinary people away from it. Whatever the reason for the lack of
its own logical system, the point is clear. When the third perspective is assessed in light
of either-or logic, one sees that the Sutra rejects the ordinary understanding of an
absolute, self-same A. Thus, the Sutra rejects this allegedly `correct way of discerning
(human) reality.
The Sutra advocates the stance of non-attachment, the negation of material objects,
objects of sensory perception and objects of mind, and this is due to a very practical or
experiential concern. In short, the Sutra addresses the problem of image-experience
that people encounter in dreams, hallucinations and meditation. This concern reects
the historical period in which the Sutra was composed. For example, Kajiyama notes:
[T]he period in which the prajn apa ramita sutras were written was a time
which witnessed an increasing stu pa worship, along with the faith in future
buddhas such as Maitreya. This meant an increase of the number of seekers
who wanted to see various buddhas in dreams, hallucinations and in medi-
tation. However, the prajn a paramita sutras did not afrm their wish to see
The Logic of the Diamond Sutra 231
the image of the buddhas, but instead it attempted to teach people about the
buddha in a higher dimension, by rejecting their wish of image-experience of
the buddha and transcend it. What the Sutras had in mind when it spoke of
`a buddha in a higher dimension was the `mother of the buddhas, i.e., the
mother who gives birth to the buddhas.
61
The mention of a `mother of the buddhas in this quotation is signicant when we
probe psychologically into the nature of `perfection of wisdom.
62
It suggests that the
Sutra adopted the feminine principle, rather than the masculine principle, as the
foundational source of knowledge. This point has a bearing on the nature of `wisdom
(prajn a ) that is linked to `all knowing (sarvajn a ). The masculine principle is related to
logos, and when it takes the form of knowledge, its strength lies in intellectual analysis
by bifurcating and dissecting the whole. By contrast, the feminine principle of knowl-
edge has the strength of bringing contradictions together and of dissolving conicts. As
such it functions to establish harmony.
63
When we take note of this point, we can see
that the Sutras contradictory position arises as a collision or incongruity between the
masculine principle that is represented by the use of language relying on either-or logic
and the feminine principle that is represented by wisdom. Seen in this psychological
manner, the `logic of not insofar as it is a `logic is a casting of the feminine principle
into the masculine terms of logos in an attempt to subsume the latter under the former
by using terminology foreign to it. Because of this forced subsumption, the
Sutra states its position in the contradictory form when its `logic of not is stated in
the propositional form as: `A is not A, therefore it is A. In other words, its
logical subsumption cannot be complete, given the neither-nor stance which the Sutra
adopts.
When people, focusing on an object, engage in meditation, it eventually disappears
from the eld of meditative awareness, along with its shape, its name, attributes, and
function(s).
64
If the categories subsumed under dharma are real (i.e. material objects,
objects of sensory perception, and objects of mind), they should not disappear from
the meditative eld as a consequence of focusing on them. The fact that they do
disappear in meditation, however, signies that these objects are not independently
real. In other words, the reality of these objects are mind-dependent. It would be a
mistake, then, to disregard this interdependency and attribute a reality to them. In the
process of meditation, then, we should be able to nd the experiential origin for the
logical negation that is formulated as `A is not A. The Sutra was quite familiar with
the autonomous character of the human psyche in that when the suppressive power of
the ego-consciousness is somatically reduced by means of the seated form of medi-
tation, the psychic energy naturally surfaces by taking the form of various images from
within the meditative awareness that is rooted in the depths of the psyche and the
world. Furthermore, it is known that in a deeper state of meditation images of various
luminous beings start appearing in the meditative eld. The sight of these images is so
attractive and transformative that the meditator will develop an attachment to them,
for it gives the adept a glimpse into a world about which the ego-consciousness knows
nothing. The Sutras negation of this sort of image-experience is a warning against this
tendency, for the images are nothing but a projection of the unconscious mind. This
warning is given to the meditator for the purpose of guiding him/her to experience the
`Mother of the buddhas in the meditative state of neither afrmation nor negation. It
is given so as to transcend such image-experience,
65
in favour of a luminous experience
of total transparency, which the Sutra designates by `Mother of the buddhas.
232 Shigenori Nagatomo
VI. Perspectival Shift
When the Sutra thematises the perspectival shift, it appeals to an analogy. As a
preparatory to the examination of the perspectival shift which the Sutra proposes, it will
be helpful, then, to assess the Sutras analogical way of describing it. This analogy is
informative for it explicitly states a transformation from darkness to light, from `not
seeing to `seeing. The passage in question reads:
Subhuti, analogically speaking, it is like a person who cannot see anything
when entering darkness even if he has an eye. The bodhisattva who has fallen
into things (vatsu-patita) should be regarded accordingly [But] Subhuthi, it
is like a person with the eye who can see many things when the night has
become light and the sun has arisen. The bodhisattva who has not fallen into
things should be regarded accordingly.
66
Here, the night metaphorically designates the fundamental ignorance of not knowing
how to experience reality as it is, and the way the `foolish, ordinary people experience
their self, their interpersonal relationships with others, as well as their engagement with
the ecological world. The transformation from `not-seeing to `seeing, is, among other
things,
67
an epistemological translation of the transformation from night to light, which
I propose to interpret to mean a transformation existential in nature such that it effects
a perspectival shift from the dualistic, egological stance to the non-dualistic, non-ego-
logical stance. I use the term `existential here because the transformation must be
effected by changing the unconscious-somatic dimension of the `foolish, ordinary
people. That is, this transformation cannot be effected simply by intellection, i.e. by
thinking or imagining it. `Not seeing is a failure of seeing, because this seeing is
constituted dualistically and egologically. It fails to `see non-dualistically and non-ego-
logically. Instead, the seer, to quote Kitaro Nishida must `see in the mode of nothing,
68
wherein the seers mind is rendered no-mind. When the seer is rendered nothing, no
cognitive activity associated with the ego-consciousness is in operation. The Sutra only
hints at what this `seeing is by appealing to such words as the `Buddha Eye and
`Buddha cognition.
69
It is an activity of, to use Hiroshi Motoyamas terminology,
70
`superconsciousness which has become a `place, within which the course of birth and
death, generation and extinction of all that is, occurs. But this `place is `no place,
because no-mind does not have a boundary or determination save its own determi-
nation via negation. Alternatively, it is a `seeing without a seer,
71
wherein there is only
the activity of seeing without the ego-consciousness positing the self as a structuring
and organising principle of experience. This activity of seeing is the activity of super-
consciousness. As long as the `foolish, ordinary people assume the dualistic, either-or
egological stance, `seeing in the sense indicated here cannot take place.
In order for the mind to `see in the mode of nothing or to `see without being a seer,
the Sutra recommends that one:
generates the mind of no place to dwell on, because the dwelling of the
mind is not the dwelling of the mind.
72
From what has been said of the negation of the dualistic, either-or egological stance in
the foregoing section, we can understand the phrase to `generate a mind of no-place to
dwell on
73
to point to an experience that is based on the non-dualistic, non-egological
stance. It is not that there is no `dwelling of the mind, but that the mind in question
is not a mind in which the ego-consciousness is posited and acts. Rather, to use Kitaro
The Logic of the Diamond Sutra 233
Nishidas terminology again, the mind in question is `a place of no-thing [mu no basho],
in which no privileging occurs between the act of grasping itself and what is being
grasped by it. That is to say, the discriminatory mind achieves an equality with respect
to them by transcending them, and when it does, the mind becomes non-discrimina-
tory. This becomes possible when a de-tensionalised intentionality is at work, where the
term `de-tensional means a doing away with the dualistic tension created by either-or
egological constitution intrinsic to the everyday standpoint. This is the meaning of
`generating the mind of no-place. It means entering into the original bodymind
oneness,while the intentionality issuing from the detensional modality of the mind
body oneness is in attunement
74
with the activity of the world. To articulate it still
further, the mind must become no-thing, free from the positing of the ego-conscious-
ness as well as from various complexes arising from the unconscious. The mind that
becomes no-thing is no-mind and when it becomes no-mind, it can become anything,
for there is nothing to hinder its original activity. It should be noted, however, that this
does not occur at the physical dimension as the external sensory perception is wont to
grasp it. This point is clearly shown in the following poem, which is presented in the
Sutra as the words of the Buddha. It declares:
Those who by my form did see me, and those who followed me by voice,
Wrong efforts they engaged in, Me those people will not see.
75
As long as `foolish, ordinary people rely on either-or logic to posit a self that frames
itself dualistically and egologically in an oppositional relationship to the things consti-
tuted by the ego, they cannot `see the Buddha, nor can they hear the voice of the
Buddha, for buddhahood transcends the dualistic, either-or egological stance. That is
to say, unless the `foolish, ordinary people can assume the non-dualistic, non-egologi-
cal stance, they cannot experience the Buddha, i.e. an emancipation from the funda-
mental ignorance that is constituted by the binding of the dualistic, either-or egological
stance. This is an instance of what Buddhism calls `self-binding without a rope. In
order to assume the perspective that transcends it, the `foolish, ordinary people must
effect the above mentioned existential transformation through practice, particularly the
practice of meditation.
The Sutra notes that this dualistic, either-or egological stance also applies to the way
in which ordinary language is incapable of dealing with dharma. Not only are dharmas
incapable of being grasped dualistically and egologically, but they `cannot be even
talked about. The following passage introduces this idea:
This dharma which the Tatha gata has fully known or demonstrated it cannot
be grasped, it cannot be talked about, it is neither a dharma nor a no-dharma.
And why? Because an Absolute exalts the Holy persons.
76
[emphases added]
As long as the `foolish, ordinary people assume a dualistic, egological stance, `this
dharma which the Buddha embodies cannot be `grasped, for the reason I have
provided in the foregoing. But to repeat the point briey here, what is grasped is
correlative and co-determinative with the act of grasping, and both are mutually
dependent on each other. This is characteristic of the structure of the epistemological
stance rooted in the dualistic, either-or egological stance, i.e. its thematising intention-
ality that issues out of the ego-consciousness of the everyday standpoint. In this case,
dharma becomes that which is thought, and not that which is experienced. However, one
understands dharma only when it is `grasped non-dualistically and non-egologically,
234 Shigenori Nagatomo
where this `grasping is no longer an act on the part of ego-consciousness, but is the
`act of that which transcends it, i.e. the world of emancipation.
But what about the statement that `dharma cannot be talked about? How should we
interpret it? It cannot be `talked about, for `this dharma
77
is extralinguistic; `this
dharma is that which appears in a meditation experience which ordinary language is
not prepared to adequately express. Here, we need to examine what `extralinguistic
means in order to understand the statement that the `dharma cannot be talked about.
I propose it to mean that it is outside conventional, ordinary language
78
which employs
subjectpredicate structure, while accepting either-or logic as the standard for its modus
operandi. In the subjectpredicate structure of language, all that happens, including the
experience of dharma, is gathered together into the subject, when in fact the experience
itself must be expressed phenomenologically by the predicate. In this case it is the
subject that is subsumed by the predicate, but not vice versa. In Nishidas terminology,
it is the transcendental predicate [choetsuteki jutsugo] that subsumes the subject. If,
however, the predicate is subsumed under the subject, and if an experiencer is posited
as the referential framework for the experience, it reveals that the experience of dharma
is grasped dualistically and egologically. For the experience of dharma to be had and
embodied, it must be had non-dualistically and non-egologically. That is to say, it can
not be either subject or predicate in which the experience occurs, for it occurs in the
stillness of meditation, i.e. in the state experientially and logically prior to the bifurca-
tion between the subject and the object. It is `pure experience admitting of no
bifurcation between the experiencer and the experienced. Or put differently, when the
`foolish, ordinary people remain under the sway of either-or logic embedded in
ordinary language, the prioritisation intrinsic to either-or logic occurs for the subject,
because it believes that it operates under the subjectpredicate structure. Consequently,
a judgement made from this standpoint fails to achieve a balanced discernment,
because it does not know the whole. It is made from within a partial or one-sided
perspective. It is a human judgement that privileges the interests of ego-desire. For this
reason, the Sutra has no choice except to say of `this dharma that `it is neither a dharma
nor a no-dharma
79
to indicate an (experiential) transcendence beyond and trans-
descendence into, the dualistic, either-or egological framework. This transcendence is
actualisable only when it is accompanied practically by the trans-descendence into the
human psyche by means of meditational practice. Meditational practice opens up both
the transcendence and the trans-descendence, for meditation is a way of probing into
the ground of being that is extra-linguistically nothing.
The thesis advanced in this paper may now be recapitulated in summation, namely
that one must effect a perspectival shift from the dualistic egological stance to the
non-dualistic, non-egological stance in order to understand the `logic of not that is
formulated as: `A is not A, therefore it is A. The dualistic, egological stance is the
everyday standpoint of the `foolish, ordinary people who attach themselves to the
objects of their own constitution that structurally frames this stance. It may be taken
either naively, perceptually, or conceptually, by postulating the idea of A as being
self-same, where there occurs an unconscious or conscious substantialisation of A. This
postulation on the part of the `foolish, ordinary people is derived from the `attachment
that is driven by the unconscious instinct `to live, and hence it is an expression of the
instinctual `self-preservation. Because ones ego-investment directs the dualistic postu-
lation of the idea of a self and the object it engages itself with, any object that is framed
from this standpoint is an instance of egological constitution.
The meaning of negation that appears in the form of `A is not A brings out a change
The Logic of the Diamond Sutra 235
of this perspective. It is an attempt to free the `foolish, ordinary people from this
dualistic, egological constitution, i.e. to effect their perspective to the non-dualistic,
non-egological stance. This is done rst by way of negating the idea of A as self-same,
which is a move to de-substantialise and de-ontologise the status of A granted by the
everyday standpoint of the `foolish, ordinary people. This de-substantialisation and
de-ontologisation is fully accomplished by transcending to a standpoint which language
formulates as a neither-nor propositional form, because it is a logical formulation
accessible to the everyday standpoint of the `foolish, ordinary people. The neither-nor
propositional form, as a momentum of negation that is achieved through the practice
of meditation, offers a third perspective which does not fall into the traps of either
eternalism nor nihilism, or either being or non-being, both of which are entailed by
either-or logic in virtue of the act of prioritising either afrmation or negation that this
logic stipulates as its modus operandi of thinking as well as the structuring of experience.
When expressed linguistically, this momentum of the negation takes on the `neither-
nor propositional form, and designates the existential transformation into the non-du-
alistic non-egological stance that is achieved with the embodiment of the stance of
non-attachment. This embodiment cannot obtain as long as the `foolish, ordinary
people adhere to their dualistic, either-or egological stance, because in attempting to
reach the stance of non-attachment, the logical act of negation inherent in this
standpoint only produces an innite regress as shown in the analysis of nihilism.
VII. Therefore it is A
In order to understand the last component in the `logic of not, i.e. `therefore it is A,
it is necessary to examine briey meditational experience, for it gives us an experiential
background that informs us of the Sutras formulation. In the Sutra, there are only two
explicit references to meditation,
80
but it is also implied by mention of the hierarchical
rankings of achieved personhood. The rst explicit reference is found in section 1-a
where the Buddha is described as `mindfully xing his attention in front of him.
81
The
second reference occurs in section 3 in the depiction of being, in which we nd a
mention of `neither image nor non-image.
82
It is the second reference that offers us a clue to understanding the experiential
nature of the `neither-nor propositional form, for the state of `neither image nor
non-image is a meditative stage recognised in the Pali Buddhist texts, in which the
experience of emptiness (su nyata ) initially obtains. Prior to this meditative state, Pali
Buddhism recognises the hierarchical order of such meditative states as `awareness of
[empty] sky with no boundary and `awareness of no boundary, and `no-thing existing.
Briey, the meditative state of `awareness of [empty] sky of no boundary is a state in
which attachment is broken through, for there is nothing that one can attach oneself to
once the meditator experiences the `[empty] sky of no-boundary. Here, however, an
image of the empty sky still remains. That is, the noetic act is still operative, however
subtle it may be. Next, the meditative `awareness of no boundary is a state in which
`names and forms cease, and the mind becomes freed from its discriminatory function,
because the name and form arise through the discriminatory function of the mind. Such
a mind does not posit any object (noematic content), and because of this, its act is
non-positional in nature, i.e. it does not take any attitude toward any object, it neither
afrms nor negates it. The meditative state of `no-thing existing is a further develop-
ment of the meditative state of `awareness of no boundary, but signicantly differs
from the latter in that the mind becomes free from the self-projective image-experience.
236 Shigenori Nagatomo
Here, there is the realisation that there is nothing one can claim to possess or to own.
In addition, one gains insight into how the discriminatory activity of the mind operates,
because the noetic act of the mind diminishes the act of the ego-consciousness.
The achievement of these meditative states is followed by the meditative state of
`neither image nor no-image. Such a state provides the experiential ground for the
Sutra to advance its third perspective, i.e. `the middle perspective, where the middle
means that the being of the meditator is here as well as there but at the same time,
it is neither here nor there .
83
In the preceding quote, we see two moments: the
rst is an afrmation of the specic spatial determinations `here and `there, which
sensory perception can determine. In the meditative state of `neither image nor
no-image, however, there occurs an interchangeability between `here and `there. The
second moment is thus a negation of the spatial determinations that are represented by
`here and `there. The negation of ordinary spatial determinations suggests that the
mind in this state of no-mind is no longer bound by the spatial determination to which
a particular thing is physically subject in the everyday standpoint. In no-mind, the
discriminatory activity of the mind associated with the previous states of meditation is
rendered inoperative and it suggests that the minds non-discriminatory functions are
activated. No-mind is no-place. That no-mind is no-place means that it can be any
place without being subject to spatial determinations that are imposed on objects of
perception by virtue of ones everyday epistemological stance. Hence, there is an
interchangeability of `here and `there. As such, it is an extraordinary experience when
assessed from the everyday standpoint. Yet, their spatiality can be determinable as to
their specic spatial location of `here and `there, because their spatial determinations
are not `xed or a priori, for they are an empty determination. The no-mind can move
from `here to `there. This is suggested by the statement that `it is neither here nor
there, a perspective that allows an interchangeability between `here and `there,
because it transcends the stance from which `here and `there are viewed. In other
words, the relationship between `here and there and `neither here nor there is an
instance of determination qua indetermination and indetermination qua determination
a freedom from ordinary spatial determination.
84
What is signicant to note in this
regard is that `here and `there in the state of no-mind (or no-place) are not simply
determined in reference to the physicality or materiality of objects that are either `here
or `there, for `here and `there are images that appear in the meditative state of `neither
image nor non-image. This is a rough construal of what it means for an object to be
non-dualistically, non-egologically `constituted where I enclose the word `constituted
in quotation marks to avoid the implication that there is some-thing that is doing the
constitution, for here there is no such a `thing per se.
`Neither here nor there, which is formulated by rejecting either-or logic, is a third
perspective which the Sutra attempts to express in stating `A is not A. The third
perspective means that A is identiable with not-A. For example, A is B where A and
B belong to the same domain and where B is a member of the set comprising not-A.
A and B are `identiable in the course of impermanent thing-events, insofar as the
intelligibility of the destinies of A and B is concerned, where A and B, in this case, do
not include anything that is conceptually or intellectually `frozen in conceptual space.
The statement `A is not A is thus an attunement of identifying A as B in the matrix of
impermanent causality. It refers to an experience of emptiness. It is also an experiential
basis for the non-discriminatory knowledge (prajn a ), which, according to the Sutra, is
an initial phase in the perfection of wisdom. In other words, the Sutra attempts to
express the experience of emptiness by using the `neither-nor propositional form.
The Logic of the Diamond Sutra 237
What is signicant for our present concern with the perspectival shift is that in the
meditative experience of emptiness, there is no essence or substance which the substan-
tialistic understanding of A can ascribe to A. If this were not the case, it would be
experientially impossible to be `here as well as `there but at the same time, it is neither
`here nor `there. That is, if there is an essence of A, there obtains no logical possibility
of experiencing `the middle, for an essence is that which a being is in and of itself, i.e.
self-contained and self-sufcient with a sense of closure. In light of the experience of
and the idea of emptiness, we must conclude that the idea of essence, or substance is
a linguistic illusion or ction.
`A in this formulation embraces the momentum of negation which includes in its
embodiment the `neither-nor perspective as a third alternative which the dualistic,
either-or egological stance cannot offer. Once this is embodied, A as that which is
self-same is stripped of its substantialistic import. This means that A and not-A are the
same insofar as they are both non-substantial, in which case they are not `two, but one.
They are both empty of substance. In virtue of this fact, it is possible for the meditator
whose no-mind is no-place to identify himself/herself in a place where `this is `that and
`that is `this. Nevertheless, there is a difference between the place in which `this and
`that occur and the actual occurrences of `this and `that in that place. In this respect,
they are not `one, but `two. Taken together, it is an instance of discrimination by
nondiscrimination, i.e. the fact that `this and `that are distinctly in the place. And yet,
it is also non-discrimination by discrimination, i.e. the fact that the place reveals both
`this and `that because of their emptiness. The preceding analysis gives us a glimpse
into an instance of non-discriminatory knowledge (nirvikalpa jn a na) that is the perfec-
tion of wisdom (prajn a ).
To recapitulate the foregoing, there are two senses of negation concealed when the
Sutra declares `A is not A: (1) the negation of the substantialistic understanding of A
in the sense that A is the same as itself, and (2) a third perspective which does not
commit itself to the pitfalls of either-or logic. It is this second sense of the negation
which enables us to see a transformation from the dualistic, either-or egological stance
to a non-dualistic, non-egological stance.
The third occurrence of A in the formulation: `A is not A, therefore it is A signies
the idea of As non-substantiality. A had been rst posited conceptually or linguistically
in the understanding of the `foolish, ordinary people. The non-substantiality of A,
however, arises in virtue of the negative momentum involving the two senses of
negation mentioned above. In this regard, the negative momentum may be considered
the existential act of de-substantialisation and de-ontologisation, as I have indicated. A
that is reafrmed after it goes through this existential act is an A that is experienced
from the point-of-view of non-substantiality, and experientially it is A seen through the
experience of emptiness that is achieved through the process of meditation.
VIII. Concluding Remarks
The preceding inquiry has enabled us to conclude that the Sutra provisionally relies on
either-or logic to advance its philosophical position, and because of this reliance, its
philosophical position is stated in a contradictory or paradoxical form. Its provisional
use is based on the Sutras concern for the `foolish, ordinary people because their
either-or logic is a method of discourse most readily understandable and familiar to
them in their use of ordinary language. In so doing, however, the Sutra was not
successful, because it usually mysties the `foolish, ordinary people, or if not that, it
238 Shigenori Nagatomo
simply leads them to dismiss the linguistic formulation of its philosophical position as
nonsensical. I have attempted to demonstrate that it is not nonsensical by articulating
the epistemological standpoint of the `foolish, ordinary people, while disclosing the
logical limitations that either-or logic intrinsically contains in its modus operandi. In
point of fact, the Sutras philosophical position cannot be accommodated by either-or
logic, which simply offers an either-or alternative, i.e. either afrmation or negation
when translated into a linguistic formulation. The Sutras own position is a third
perspective that cannot be accommodated by relying on either-or logic, and for this
reason it chooses to express its philosophical position by relying on a `neither-nor
propositional form. In adapting this way of expressing its philosophical position, it
rejects either-or logic as a proper way of discerning thingevents of the world and their
linguistic articulation.
In spite of the Sutras recommendation for the non-dualistic, non-egological perspec-
tive, this perspective has not survived the demands of contemporary times. In fact, it
has been almost obliterated
85
in the face of the superiority of Western science and
technology, not to mention her economic power which the US, for example, is
exercising over the rest of the world. Because of her inuence over the world vis-a -vis
these activities, the world is on the way to globalisation, ignoring the traditional national
boundaries and cultures which each ethnic group has long fostered and cherished. The
process of globalisation, however, has also taught us the idea of interdependency which
Buddhism has long cherished as one of the cardinal teachings between thingevents
that we observe in natural phenomena, industrial pollution and the economic activity
between the nations, not to mention interpersonal relationships. Today, we are also
facing an unprecedented task of how to deal with various environmental issues such as
global warming, the thinning of the ozone layer and melting of ice in the antarctic
regions. I wonder if human beings can collectively deal with these issues by relying on
the dualistic, either-or egological standpoint which has promoted the development of
science and technology.
Shigenori Nagatomo, Department of Religion, Temple University, Anderson Hall, 1114 W.
Berks Street, Philadelphia, PA 191226090, USA
NOTES
[1] The Sanskrit na pr thak embraces such meaning as `not, `non and `difference, where we can take
`not to mean a negation, `non to designate contrary and `difference to connote an instance of
contrary. The Japanese rendition of this phrase is sokuhi, which linguistically means `is not, but
syntactically there is no presence of `is. This suggests that `na pr thak, when understood as `soku,
cannot be treated either as a copula or as a linking verb. Rather `soku, is used as a connective
between two heterogenous elements that are `immediately or `directly conjoined as is `one soku
many and `many soku one.
[2] In fact, a renowned specialist, Edward Conze reports his friends complaining that his commentary
`is unhelpful, inconclusive, tedious, uninspiring and positively confusing. He attributes the failure
to the texts `invincible obtuseness. See CONZE, EDWARD (1958) Buddhist Wisdom Books (New
York, Harper Torch, p. 51.
[3] The term `ego-logical is a neologism proposed by Nathan Levith, a student of political science
at Haverford College, Haverford, Pennsylvania. It also appears in HUSSERL, EDMUND (1997)
Cartesian Meditations (The Hague, Martinus Nijhoff).
[4] The other instances of this formulation include the following where the section number indicates
Conzes division: `accumulation of merits (section 8); `arhat (section 9-c); `construction of the
buddha-eld (sections 10-b and 17-g); `the thirty-two marks of the tathagata (section 13-d);
`leading innumerable beings to nirvana without the substrate [annupadises a-nirvan a] (section
The Logic of the Diamond Sutra 239
17-a); `the dharma demonstrated by the tathagata (17-d); `the ow of mind [cittadhara] is not the
ow of mind, and therefore it is the ow of mind. (section 18-b); `the perfection of the
proportionate body [upeta-kayo] (section 20-a); `the endowment of the bodily characteristics
[laks ana] (section 20-b); `the tathagatas achieving the supreme, right, equal enlightenment
[anuttara samyak-sam bodhi] (section 22); `the sentient beings (section 21-b); `good dharmas
(section 23); `the collection of particles of dust (section 30-a); `The attachment to a whole
[pin da-graha] is not the attachment to a whole, and therefore, it is the attachment to a whole
(section 30-b); `A thought of thing [dharma-sam ina ] is not a thought of thing, and therefore it is
the thought of thing (section 31-b).
[5] To formulate the `logic of not in this way is an issue concerning the universality of this logic.
Unless it is formalised in the propositional form: `A is not A, therefore it is A, however, the `logic
of not will be conned primarily to the interest of Buddhist scholars, and hence it will not appeal
to people beyond its own home ground. Certainly, this is not the intent of the Sutra and we can
see it briey by thinking philosophically through the examples mentioned above as they are
framed in the formalised statement. Take Example 1, which reads: `The world is not the world,
and therefore it is the world. (section 13-c). If we take the category `world to mean the most
inclusive category in a domain of discourse in which everything excluding none occurs, i.e. it can
subsume every other category that is of and in the world, insofar as it is understood from the
everyday standpoint, it is evident that this logic is not to be conned locally, since the Sutra
applies the `logic of not to this category. Especially, when we regard the human being as that
which is, to use Heideggers terminology, `thrown into the world, a `being-in-the-world, who
suffers from the fundamental passivity for this reason, anything the human being engages in
occurs in this world and it is of this world. HEIDEGGER, MARTIN (1962) Being and Time (JOHN
MACQUARRIE ET AL.) (New York: Harper & Row). Now, take Example 2, which reads: `All
dharmas are not all dharmas and therefore they are all dharmas. In Buddhism, `dharma is the most
comprehensive category under which both the conditioned and the unconditioned thingstate are
subsumed, i.e. anything is either the conditioned or unconditioned dharma, and nothing escapes
from this category, where the force of this statement is to break down the distinction between the
conditioned and the unconditioned that was upheld by the previous schools of Buddhism (see
WALPOLA, RAHULA, (1974) What the Buddha Taught (New York, Grove Press). Given this
understanding of dharma and what we have said of the world, it is self-evident that the `logic of
not is to be expanded universally but not regionally, however A may be construed to mean,
insofar as A is of the dharma that is in and of the world. The Sutras application of the `logic of
not is in fact relentless, because it is applied to the very goal for which the Sutra is written, i.e.
achieving the perfection of wisdom, as it is seen in Example 3. It reads: `The perfection of wisdom
[prajna paramita] is not the perfection of wisdom, and therefore it is the perfection of wisdom.
Moreover, any truth claim one wants to make concerning dharmas or the world is also stated in
the same propositional form as is seen in Example 4: `A thought of truth [bhutasam jna] is not a
thought of truth, and therefore it is the thought of truth (section 14-a). In fact, no statement,
including self-referential statements, can be excluded from the formulation: `A is not A, therefore
it is not A. From the preceding analysis, it is clear that the Sutra intends to endow the `logic of
not with a universal applicability to any statement appearing in any given discourse.
[6] NAKAMURA HAJIME & KINO KAZUYOSHI (Trans. and Ed.) (1996) Hannyashinkyo, Kong
ohannyakyo (The Heart Sutra and the Diamond Sutra) (Tokyo, Iwanami shoten, p. 195. Since
doubt and attachment are depthpsychological issues for the ego-consciousness, I shall deal with
them later.
[7] KANT, IMMANUEL (1965) The Critique of Pure Reason (New York, St Martins Press), p. 633.
[8] NAKAMURA & KINO, op. cit., note 6, p. 17. This interpretation follows the theory that parami (to
reach the other shore) is combined with the abstract noun that indicates a state (ta), wherein the
whole phrase pa ramita means `reaching the other shore. And hence it means `perfection. The
other dominant interpretation follows the analysis that paramita is the feminine form of the passive
past participle param (the other shore) that is conjoined with the verb ita (to reach).
KAJIYAMA, YU
ICHI (1976) Hannya shinkyo (The Prajn aparamita Su tra) (Tokyo, Chu okoron), pp.
100101, also discusses the term paramita in two senses and opts for the meaning of `perfection.
According to Kajiyama, paramita can linguistically be analysed in two ways: (1) pa ramita means
`reaching an ultimate or perfection, and it is an abstract compound noun consisting of parami,
which is derived from the adjective parama that means `paramount and the postposition ta and
(2) paramita means `the other shore and is a compound consisting of (a) pa rami, which is the
240 Shigenori Nagatomo
objective case of the noun param, meaning `the other shore (b) it is conjoined by the nominali-
sation of the verb i (to go), wherein the whole phase comes to mean `that which goes to the other
shore, when the postposition ta is added to it. He says that linguistically the former is more
appropriate than the latter, but he notes that the latter is also widely accepted in view of the
dogmatic, philosophical interpretation. Having stated this, however, he seems to opt for the
`perfection, because the `other shore means nirvana or satori, which is `to go to reach the
paramount ultimate.
Kanaoka gives the same interpretation on this point, see KANAOKA, SHU
YU
(1973) Hannya
shinky o (The Heart Sutra) (Tokyo, Ko dansha), pp. 3839.
[9] NAKAMURA & KINO, op. cit., note 6, p. 17. This `non-discriminatory knowledge is contrasted
with `discriminatory knowledge (vijna na). I shall discuss the difference between `non-discrimina-
tory knowledge and `discriminatory knowledge in the section dealing with `dualistic, ego-logical
stance and `non-dualistic non-egological stance respectively.
[10] Compare, for example, Aristotles hierarchy of knowledge in which wisdom as a knowledge of the
universal is placed as the highest form of theoretical knowledge. See ch. 1 of HOPE, RICHARD
(1975) Aristotle Metaphysics (Ann Arbor, MI, The University of Michigan Press) or MCKEON,
RICHARD (Ed.) (1941) The Basic Works of Aristotle (New York, Random House).
[11] In the terminologies of the Sutra, the achieved personhood includes, from the higher to the lower
in ranking, an awakened one (a buddha, a thus-come: Tathagata), the three ranks of arhat, which
are the never-returner (ana gamin), the once-returner (sakr dagamin), and the stream-entrant
(srota-apanna). These categories will be important when considering the hierarchy of meditative
experience.
[12] YUASA, YASUO (1987) The Body: Toward an Eastern MindBody Theory (Trans. SHIGENORI
NAGATOMO & T.P. KASULIS) (Albany, NY, State University of New York Press).
[13] Subhuti is depicted in the Sutra as foremost in having achieved a meditative state wherein is
experienced an absence of `battle (arana-viharina m-agryah). The `battle refers to conict and
delusion when it is psychologically interpreted.
[14] CONZE, op. cit., note 2, p. 22.
[15] CONZE, op. cit., note 2, p. 24.
[16] CONZE, op. cit., note 2, p. 24. In Nakamuras translation, this passage is rendered as: How should
a son or daughter of a good family, who turns to the path of a seeker, live, and act, and maintain
their mind? See NAKAMURA & KINO, op. cit., note 6, p. 45. In Kumaraji vas translation: `set out
in the Bodhisattva-vehicle is rendered as `set their mind on the unexcelled, supreme enlighten-
ment (see ibid, p. 44).
[17] They include the meanings such as `a seeker, `a being on the way to enlightenment, and `a being
who postpones ones own enlightenment until he/she carries the innumerable beings to nal
nirvana. In addition to the perfection of wisdom, the bodhisattva is required to bring to perfection
such things as giving, patience, making efforts, keeping precepts, and meditation. For the purpose
of this paper, I shall focus just on the idea of perfecting wisdom.
[18] KAJIYAMA, op. cit., note 8, p. 121, and NAKAMURA & KINO, op. cit., note 6,
[19] It should be noted that primacy applies only to those who are on the way to perfecting wisdom,
but not to those who have already embodied it.
[20] KAJIYAMA, op. cit., note 8, pp. 120121.
[21] CONZE, op. cit., note 2, p. 22.
[22] NAKAMURA & KINO, op. cit., note 6, p. 154. CONZE, op. cit., note 2, translates this terms as `the
foolish common people. This would correspond in meaning to Neitzsches `herd or `little man.
[23] NAKAMURA & KINO, op. cit., note 6, p. 115. Also see CONZE, op. cit., note 2, p. 62. What is
quoted here regarding the `foolish, ordinary people is not the nal characterisation which the
Sutra gives to them. The `logic of not is also applied to them as found in section 25 which reads:
`The foolish, ordinary people [bala-pr thaganah] are not the foolish, ordinary people, and therefore
they are the foolish ordinary people.
[24] NAKAMURA & KINO, op. cit., note 6, p. 154.
[25] I understand the phrase `conceptual scheme to mean a holistic operation of epistemological,
ontological, linguistic and experimental categories that frame the way a person understands the
world. In other words, the understanding of the world is analytically accessible in part through a
specic conceptual scheme.
[26] HUSSER, EDMUND (1967) Ideas: A General Introduction to Phenomenology (New York, Collier,
1967), p. 80.
The Logic of the Diamond Sutra 241
[27] In this context, the mind specically means the act aspect of its operation, rather than a general
concept of the mind. See HATTORI, MASAAKI (1973) Bukkyo no shiso: Ninshiki to choetsu (Buddhist
Thought: Cognition and Transcendence) (Tokyo; Kadokawa shoten), p. 98. Historically, the
Mind-only school arose after the tradition of the prajna paramita literature. Strictly speaking, then,
the interpretation advanced here does not necessarily reect the positions of the Diamond Sutra.
This may invite a criticism that I am superimposing an interpretation that is not intrinsic or
germane to the Sutra. This is a valid criticism when we adhere and conne ourselves to the textual
evidence, for we can nd no such interpretation in the Sutra. But when we consider the historical
development of prajnaparamita literature, it is known that it arose as a counter-movement to the
Abhidhami c tradition, notably, Sautrantika and Sarvastivadin, both of which maintained the
categorisation of experience. Hence distinction-making was considered the primary business of
scholastic activity. Sarvastivadin, in particular, adapted the stance of substantialisating the 75
concepts (dharmas), and thereby claimed their eternality. Philosophically, in opposition to a
nominalist position, this is a realist position, which is analogous to the Western counterpart in
which an idea is maintained to be real. Since the Sutra in question rejects the idea of a self, whose
idea arises by accepting the realist position, I am inferring from this rejection that the Sutra will
endorse the interpretation of the noetic act in terms of the relationship between grasping-aspect
(gra hakakara) and the grasped-aspect (gra hyakara).
[28] If we think that there is experience rst a la Nishida (see NISHIDA KITARO
ICHI (1971) Bukkyo no shiso. Ku no ronri (The Buddhist Thought: The Logic of
Emptiness) (Tokyo, Kadokawa shoten), p. 31.
[65] Historically speaking, Nagajuna later conceptualised the meditative state of neither afrmation
nor negation as emptiness (sunyata).
[66] NAKAMURA & KINO, op. cit., note 6, p. 85.
[67] I insert this qualication here because physiological changes also occur. To mention just a few;
the reduction of breathing, and hence the decreased consumption of oxygen, the alternation of the
competitive balance between the activities of sympathetic nerves and parasympathetic nerves
through the establishment of a breathing pattern, the enhancement of immune system, and the
secretion of dopamine and b-endorphin.
[68] NISHIDA, KITARO