theUnblinkingGaze PDF
theUnblinkingGaze PDF
nz
ResearchSpace@Auckland
Copyright Statement
The digital copy of this thesis is protected by the Copyright Act 1994 (New
Zealand).
This thesis may be consulted by you, provided you comply with the
provisions of the Act and the following conditions of use:
!
An Unblinking Gaze:
On the Philosophy of the Marquis de Sade
Geoffrey T. Roche
ABSTRACT
Throughout the 20th Century, a number of philosophers, writers, artists and film
makers have implied that there is some profound significance to the work of Donatien
Alphonse Franois, the Marquis de Sade (1740-1814). The project at hand is to
evaluate the claim that Sade, in some sense, is a philosopher, and to assess what his
philosophy amounts to. There are two aspects to this task. Firstly, I will consider the
various philosophical interpretations of Sades work. This part of the study will serve
as a guide into the Sadeian labyrinth, and will establish some of the more central
interpretive themes, in particular the claim that Sades thought anticipates that of the
Nazis, or that he brings early Modern thought to its logical conclusion. Secondly, I
will inquire into Sades writings themselves. Of particular interest are Sades thoughts
concerning the nature of sexuality, psychology, and the human condition in general,
his critique of conventional morality, and his description of the nature of power.
ii
Acknowledgements
First and foremost, thanks are due to my supervisors, Stefano Franchi and Robert
Wicks, without whom this project would have been both unthinkable and impossible.
In particular, I wish to thank Stefano for helping with the construction of the thesis,
and his insistence that deeper insights were available in regions where I could only
see an inky darkness. I am also indebted to family and friends who aided this project
in less direct ways, in particular my parents, for their encouragement and support over
the years. I also wish to thank Caroline Warman, David Martyn, Jeff Love, Robert
Nola, Dennis Robinson, Stephen Davies, Charles Pigden, Karen Riley, Tim Rayner,
Barry Moffatt, Amanda Lennon, Sterling Lynch, Adle de Jager, Lauren Ashwell, and
Robert C. Solomon, for suggestions, advice, support and assistance. I thank Sbastian
Charles, Masha Mimran and Syliane Charles for providing copies of unpublished
articles. For helping me with my French, I thank Rosemary Arnoux, Selma Kradraoui,
and the teachers at Alliance Franaise in Lyons. I also thank The Foundation for
Research, Science and Technology, Tuapapa Rangahau Putaiao, for the award of
Bright Futures Scholarship (Doctoral) 664, and the opportunity to attend conferences
overseas, and the University of Auckland for both the Doctoral Scholarship and, with
the assistance of the Overseas Exchange programme, the opportunity to study in
Lyons. I am also grateful to Tessa Laird, David Carman, Astrid Scott, Brian Soppit
and the late John Park, for their inspiration.
iii
My manner of thinking, so you say, cannot be approved. Do you suppose I care? A poor
fool indeed is he who adopts a manner of thinking to suit other people! My manner of
thinking stems straight from my considered reflections; it holds with my existence, with
the way I am made. It is not in my power to alter it; and if were, Id not do so.
...philosophy, Justine, is not the art of consoling the weak; it has no other aim but to bring
soundness to the mind and to uproot prejudices.
iv
Contents
Key to Abbreviations, Sources and Translations viii
Preface
Introduction 5
Chapter I.
Reconnaissance
Chapter II.
2.1 Introduction 93
2.2 God and Creation 94
2.3 The Non- Uniqueness of Humans 96
2.4 Death 98
2.5 Naturalism vs. Non-Naturalism 101
Chapter III.
vi
Chapter VI.
Chapter VII.
Conclusion. 291
Appendix: Sade and Nazism 295
Bibliography 307
vii
KEY TO ABBREVIATIONS,
SOURCES, AND TRANSLATIONS
[the story of] Juliette [or, Prosperities of Vice] trans. Austryn Wainhouse
(New York: Grove, 1968). [Part two of] La nouvelle Justine, ou Les malheurs de
la vertu, suivie de Lhistoire de Juliette, sa sur, the second part of the third
version of Justine, published in 1797.
LNJ : La Nouvelle Justine (2 vols). (Paris: Collection 10:18, 1978).
LP : Letters from Prison. trans. Richard Seaver. (New York: Arcade
Publishing, 1999).
MV: The Misfortunes of Virtue and other Early Tales trans. David Coward
(Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1999). (This is the first version of
Justine).
MM: The Mystified Magistrate and other writings trans. Richard Seaver (New
York: Arcade Publishing, 2000).
: uvres (3 vols.) ed. Michel Delon, Jean Deprun (Paris: Bibliothque de la
Pliade / Gallimard, 1990, 1995, 1998).
PB: Justine, Philosophy in the Bedroom and Other Writings trans. Richard
Seaver (New York: Arcade Publishing, 2000).
120: The 120 Days of Sodom and other writings trans. Austryn Wainhouse and
Richard Seaver (New York: Arrow, 1990).
viii
Preface
Contemporary high culture: I have in mind in particular the work of Jake and Dino Chapman, Wim
Delvoye, Jeff Koons, Zhu Yu, and Paul McCarthy. Zhu Yu ate a stillborn baby in a performance piece
entitled Eating People (2000). For discussion, see Fei Dawei, Transgresser le principe cleste:
dialogue avec le groupe cadavre, Artpress : reprsenter lhorreur Hors Srie (mai 1 2001) : 60-64.
2
Literary references: Sade is referred to in passing in Nabokovs Lolita (Claire Quilty tries to get
Dolores Haze to perform in a film based on the Philosophy in the Bedroom). Milan Kundera
(Slowness), A.S. Byatt (Babel Tower) and Michel Houellebecq (The Elementary Particles) discuss
Sade in their works. Angela Carters engagement with Sade will be discussed in Chapter I. Plays and
Movies: The two most important plays written on Sade are Peter Weisss Marat/ Sade (1966) and
Yukio Mishimas Madame Sade (1965). Philip Kaufmans Quills (2000), based on a play by Doug
Wright, is only the latest of a long line of filmic treatments of Sade, and limits him to the 1960s radical
clichs of liberator of sexuality and satirist of official hypocrisy. Pier Paolo Pasolinis Salo or the
120 Days of Sodom (1975) comes as close as a filmic treatment could come to Sades vision without
being banned (it has in fact been banned in the United States owing to questions concerning the age of
some of the actors) or unwatchable. Spanish director Luis Buuels films are filled with references to
Sades work, in particular The Milky Way (1969) and Lge dor (1930). The most interesting
cinematic references to Sade are, however, obscure. The Russian ambassador in Kubricks Dr.
Strangelove (1964) is named Ambassador Desadeski; the main character of Nagisa Oshimas The
Realm of the Senses (1976), who asphyxiates her lover (at his request), before cutting off his penis, is
named Sada.
3
A number of critics refer to the victims of torture described in Sade as patients or unfortunate
creatures -the same terminology used by Sades characters- and describe the hideous medical
experiments in Sades works as poetry. Critics also tend to describe those whom Sade found
disagreeable (his gaolers, in particular) in the same sarcastic terms used by Sade himself. Also, notably,
the words rape and murder scarcely appear in secondary literature in Sade, despite the frequency of
these acts in Sades work. See, for example, Batrice Didier Sade Un criture du dsir (Paris: Denol/
Gonhier, 1976) p.187; Chantal Thomas Sade, la dissertation et lorgie (Paris: ditions Payot, 1978)
pp.96, 148,149; Nelly Stphane Morale et nature, Europe: Revue littraire- mensuelle 522
(1972):23-42, p.35.
4
R.F. Brissenden La Philosophie dans le Boudoir; or, A Young Ladys Entrance into the World, in
Harold E Pagliaro, ed., Irrationalism in the Eighteenth Century (Cleveland, Press of Case Western
Reserve University, 1972): 113-141, p.137.
The project at hand is to evaluate the claim that Sade, in some sense, is a
philosopher, and to assess what his philosophy amounts to. There are two aspects of
this task. Firstly, I will consider the various philosophical interpretations of Sades
work. Secondly, I will inquire into Sades writings, independent of previous
interpretations. I will not be concerned with those aspects of his life and work that
have somewhat distracted most writers from the actual intellectual content of his
work- that is- the arguments, presuppositions, and doctrines that it communicates.
This is what it means to treat Sade as a philosopher, as opposed to treating him as the
arcane enigma Sade (or- more preposterously- the divine Marquis). If Sades work
is a labyrinth inhabited by monsters, its walls will be breached, its inhabitants will be
captured for study, and their secrets will be yielded.
INTRODUCTION
The intention of this project is to seek out Sade the philosopher. Related to this task is
the surveying of the various interpretations of Sade as philosopher, in part for the sake
of assessment, but also in order to find a pathway into his work. Here I will outline
some interpretive and methodological issues that have arisen.
Two types of literature have been surveyed; a). secondary literature written by
literary specialists, a fraction of which touches upon philosophical themes, or is
theoretical in nature, and b). philosophical literature which treats Sade, in a critical
way, as a thinker in his own right. Work of the latter type is limited to a handful of
references, most of which are brief.
Several issues concerning the specialist literature need to be addressed. Firstly,
there is the question concerning the very idea of reading Sade as a philosopher, this
being a minority view amongst Sade specialists. Not only are most specialists more
interested in biographical, textual, or purely interpretive treatments of Sades work;
many explicitly reject the idea that Sade could be read as a philosopher in a literal
way. Sade is, on this view, an amateurish plagiarist, his philosophy best understood
as a hateful revenge attack against the cosmos on a purely abstract plane. 1 In keeping
with such interpretations is the tendency to reduce Sade to pure fiction, or pure text. 2
Roland Barthes, the most prominent member of this school, describes Sade as the
creator of a new language in which bodies and their intersections take the place (in
some sense) of grammatical units. Accordingly, Barthes holds that Sade was not
See Thomas Moore Dark Eros: the imagination of Sadism (Woodstock, Connecticut: Spring
Publications, 1990) p.54; Nol Chatelet Le libertine table in Michel Camus, Philippe Roger, eds.
Sade crire la crise (Paris: Pierre Belfond, 1983): 67-83, p.78; David Coward, Introduction, the
Marquis de Sade The Misfortunes of Virtue and other early tales trans. David Coward (Oxford
University Press, 1999) p. vii.
2
See for example Marcel Hnaff The Invention of the Libertine Body trans. Xavier Callahan
(Minneapolis: University of Minnesota Press, 1999) p.290. This is in spite of Hnaffs own claims of
Sades significance in diagnosing the black heart of late capitalism, which aligns him with the
interpretation offered by Adorno and Horkheimer, to be discussed in Chapter I. Muriel Schmid, in Le
soufre au bord de la chaire: Sade et lEvangile, agrees with this view (Genve: Labor et Fides, 2001)
pp.51, 125, 152. I thank Rosemary Arnoux for bringing this book to my attention.
interested in discussing the real world, reasoning that written shit has no odour. 3
Other critics hold that Sades work is simply too horrific to be read in a literal way.
Rather, argues John Phillips, Sade is to read as a writer of black comedy. 4 A number
of points can be made here. Firstly, Sade himself asserted that he was a philosopher,
both in private correspondence (as expressed in the quotes at the beginning of this
essay), and in the presentation of his works. This must surely inform our
hermeneutics. Secondly, Sade was quite clearly preoccupied with ethics and
psychology - what he knew of as moral science and the inquiry concerning the
human heart. That he was engaged in a recognizably philosophical discussion and a
central one at that there is little doubt. Finally, the argument that Sades works are
fictions, therefore not philosophical, is to assume a questionable dichotomy between
narrative and philosophy. The Narrative (the Platonic dialogue, the philosophical
tale, the libertin novel, Nietzsches Zarathustra, the fictional work of Dostoyevsky,
Camus or Sartre) has frequently been used to communicate philosophical ideas, and
was a wisely chosen vehicle in an age when personal identification with atheism was
particularly dangerous. Further, Sade frequently blurs the line between fictional
narrative and prescription, most significantly in giving the reader advice as to how
one ought to live ones life. Finally, for a thinker who has gone beyond the limits of
purely linear reasoning and the standard oppositions of truth and falsity, description
and prescription, sincerity and insincerity, or good and evil, literary form may be a
superior means of philosophical expression. 5 Sades work, as this essay will show,
presents a number of intractable interpretive problems, in particular his relationship
with the text and the reader, and there is a bewildering amount of contradiction within
his work. 6 The problem of the intention of the author goes beyond the scope of this
3
Roland Barthes Sade, Fourier, Loyola (Paris: Seuil, 1971) .Quoted in Laurence L. Bongie Sade: A
Biographical Essay (Chicago and London: The University of Chicago Press, 1998) p.297.
4
John Phillips Laugh? I nearly died! : Humor in Sades fiction, The Eighteenth Century. Theory and
Interpretation 40 (1) (fall 1999):46-67, p.55, 61; John Phillips Sade in the Corridor, Nottingham
French Studies 37 (2) (autumn 1998): 26-36, p.34.
5
Here I am virtually quoting Jacob Golomb, Nietzsche and Zion (Ithaca and London: Cornell
For discussion on Sades style, lack of sincerity, and attempt to brainwash or nauseate the reader,
see Timo Airaksinen The Philosophy of the Marquis de Sade (London and New York: Routledge,
1995) p.13, Susan Neiman Evil in Modern Thought: An alternative history of Philosophy (Melbourne:
Scribe publications, 2002) p.180; Geoffrey Bennington Sade Laying Down the Law, Oxford Literary
project. In any case, I have no interest in writing a What Sade Really Said, a project as
philosophically uninformative as it would be impossible. Using Sades text as a
framework for a more generally applicable inquiry into morality and human nature,
whilst maintaining fidelity to the text, I feel, will be a more philosophically
informative approach. A balance must be found between structured, distanced
analysis and the more nuanced approach of thinking through the text; between
Marcelin Pleynets ideal of a reading that thinks through the multiplicitous
articulations of textual contradictions and which thinks its own insertion into the order
of these contradictions, and Jules Jenins advice that we study Sade as an
entomologist studies a scorpion. 7
In reply to Phillips, for whom Sades work is too horrific to be read as an account
of reality, I note that this a particularly un- Sadeian approach. That is to say, it is to
assume that the world is not, to a large extent, a frightening and obscene place, and
that man is not capable of atrocity. A Nouvelle Juliette, rewritten for the early 21st
Century, would be a project banal in its obviousness. The sex slave-traders of Eastern
Europe, the rapist priests, the warlords of Africa who use mass starvation as a
strategic tool; the Board of Directors of DynCorp, Their Excellencies Robert Mugabe,
Kim Jong-Il, and Teodoro Obiang Nguema; Huda Ammash, Army Specialist Sabrina
Harman, Father Athanase Seromba, Armin Meiwes, Jeffrey Dahlmer, and Marc
Dutroux; - these are the real-life Juliettes, Minskis, Durands and Noirceuils. The
Review 6(2) (1984):38 -56, p.54; Batrice Didier Sade: Un criture du dsir (Denol/Gonthier, 1976)
p. 199. Sades work contains a few clues as to how he saw himself in relation to the text and how he
viewed the reader. He was apparently aware of his stylistic shortcomings, as his marginal notes show
(120:568, 570). He frequently made direct addresses to the reader, extolling them to follow his advice
(AV: 346). His characters also insinuate that they are not to be trusted ([w]e do have something of the
treacherous, yes; a touch of the false, you may believe it; PB: 278). Sade also argued that the opinions
of the characters in a text were not necessarily those of the author. See Jean-Pierre Han, Jean-Pierre
Valla A propos du systme philosophique de Sade, Europe 522 (October 1972): 105-123, p.108.
7
Marcelin Pleynet The Readability of Sade, The Tel Quel Reader ed. Patrick ffrench (sic) and
Roland-Franois Lack (London and New York: Routledge,1998):109-122,p. 119; Jules Janin Le
marquis de Sade, Revue de Paris, 1834, pp.321-322. Quoted in Franoise Laugaa-Traut Lectures de
Sade (Paris: Armand Colin, 1973) p.125.
horrors of Silling (the castle of Sades the 120 Days of Sodom) are as much a part of
our world as are Haengyong and Abu Ghraib. 8
Of the work on Sade that takes a more philosophical approach, problems remain,
and some perhaps surprising omissions need to be explained. Firstly, much of this
material is hampered by a lack in critical rigor, or is philosophical without engaging
with the philosophy in Sades work. That is, it is philosophy about Sade. Philippe
Sollers, in Sade dans le texte (1967), argues that Sade has disproved the principle
of causality and hence the underlying principle of all civilisation, religion and
philosophy, which Sollers refers to as a neurosis. 9 An oft-cited and influential essay
by Jacques Lacan, Kant avec Sade (Kant with Sade), also falls into this category
(Lacan reduces all of Sade to the Law of jouissance), as does the work of Philippe
Mengue, for whom Sade has given a new type of law. 10 Other studies are hampered
by an incomplete knowledge of the theoretical content of Sades works, which
accounts for the wild variation in interpretation. Timo Airaksinen, in The Philosophy
of the Marquis de Sade, does not so much interpret as misidentify Sade as a Kantian
thinker, for whom the joy of sin is the perverse pleasure of being irrational (as,
8
At the time of writing (2004), Haengyong is thought to be an operational death camp in North Korea.
See Antony Barnett Revealed: the gas chamber horror of North Korea's gulag, Observer, Sunday
February 1, 2004. URL: www.guardian.co.uk/korea/article/0,2763,1136483,00.html. (accessed
November 11th 2004).
9
Philippe Sollers Sade dans le texte In Tel Quel 28 (1967) :38-50. For discussion, see Caroline
Warman Sade: from Materialism to Pornography (Oxford: Voltaire Foundation, 2002) pp.8-9.
10
Lacan reduces all of Sade to a single aphorism: the right to jouissance (jouissance is defined in
the Larousse dictionary as intense pleasure, but it also means orgasm, which is closer to Sades
typical usage of the term. It has no exact English translation). This principle appears to be taken from a
single line in Sades Philosophie dans le Boudoir. But Lacan does not find a corresponding philosophy
in Sade to back it up: [o]f a treatise truly about desire, there is thus little here, even nothing (Lacan
p.75). See Jacques Lacan Kant with Sade trans. James B. Swenson, Jr. October 51 Winter (1989):55104. I Thank David Martyn for pointing this text out to me. For an analysis of this essay, see Jean
Allouch a de Kant, cas de Sade : Erotologie analytique III (Paris : Lunebevue, 2002). Philip
Mengues work is strongly influenced by that of Jacques Lacan, Gilles Deleuze and Jean- Franois
Lyotard. Mengue regards Sade as a nihilist of meaning, and yet also reads Sade as introducing a new
concept of law, an ethic that does not ignore or deny the unconsciousness (p.228). Given that
Sade had no concept of a subconscious, and was ambiguous on the subject of laws, this reading would
appear to owe to Lacan more than to Sade himself. Philip Mengue Lordre Sadien : Loi et narration
dans la philosophie de Sade (Paris : ditions Kim, 1996).
for a Kantian, doing immoral things is tantamount to causing moral harm to ones
moral self). 11 Airaksinen then proceeds to analyse the structure of perverse will
(the pleasure of doing that which the agent knows is irrational), but his discussion
here has more to do with the insights of Edgar Allen Poe than Sade (for whom doing
good simply makes no sense for the strong). Simone de Beauvoirs essay Must
We Burn Sade? is another case in point; she makes no stronger, or informative,
claim than that Sade disturbs us and that he rejected all the easy answers.12
I give a final note concerning the censorship of Sades works. Roger Shattuck
describes Sades work as potential poison, polluting our moral and intellectual
environment, and his status in literary and academic circles as indicative of an eerie
post- Nietzschean death wish. 13 Sade specialists dismiss this view as moralizing
hogwash, but the view is an interesting one. 14 To fear Sade, to acknowledge his
power to morally corrupt- is to grant his work a great deal of negative respect; more,
in fact, than do a number of specialists. Further, as Lorna Berman notes, it would
seem that those who have banned Sades works have done so precisely out of fear of
just such a latent destructive impulse in human nature. 15 If Sades philosophy is
really so poor, it has to be asked how such a doctrine could be so dangerously
seductive. As philosophers, we wish to know how it is even possible to poison
people simply by writing philosophically informed pornographic novels.
11
I thank Caroline Warman for clarifying this point for me. Timo Airaksinen The Philosophy of the
Marquis de Sade (London and New York: Routledge, 1995). pp.156, 168.
12
See Simone de Beauvoir Must we Burn Sade? trans. Annette Michelson (120:3-64).
13
Roger Shattuck Forbidden Knowledge: from Prometheus to Pornography (New York: Harcourt
For Michel Delons reaction to Shattuck, see Michel Delon Du danger de la littrature, Europe
Lorna Berman The Marquis de Sade and his Critics, Mosaic 1 no.2 (1968):57-72. Quoted in
Colette Verger Michael The Marquis de Sade: The Man, His Works, and His Critics, An Annotated
Bibliography (New York& London: Garland Publishing Inc, 1986) p.308.
On Andr Breton and Sade, and Swinburne and Sade, see Franoise Laugaa-Traut Lectures de Sade
(Paris: Armand Colin, 1973) pp.151, 207. On Samuel Becketts reading of Sade, see James Knowlson
Damned to Fame (London: Bloomsbury, 1997) p.293. I Thank Craig Matthews for bringing this
passage to my attention. See also Patricia Mines The role of the Marquis de Sade in the late novels of
Victor Hugo, Nottingham French Studies 36 no. 2 (autumn 1997): 10-23. Three essays that discuss the
relationship between Sade and Dostoyevsky: William C Brumfield Thrse philosophe and
Dostoyevskys Great Sinner, Comparative Literature 32 (1980), 238-253; Robert Louis Jackson
Dostoevskij and the Marquis de Sade, Russian Literature Vol. IV-1 (13) (January 1976):27-45. Jeff
Love Sade et linnocence divine in Norbert Sclippa, ed. Lire Sade, (Paris: l' Harmattan, 2004)
pp.157-172. On Sade and Kafka see Brad Epps Technoasceticism and Authorial Death in Sade, Kafka,
Barthes and Foucault, Differences: A Journal of Feminist Cultural Studies 8.3 (1996); Gustav Janouch
Conversations with Kafka trans. Goronway Rees (New York: New Directions Books, 1971) p.131.
(The torture described in Kafkas In the Penal Colony, in which the sentence of a convict is inscribed
into the body, appears in various forms in the work of Sade ;120: 611; J:619). For Aldous Huxleys
thoughts on Sade, see his Ends and Means (London: Chatto and Windus, 1938) p.271.
17
For an anecdote concerning the difficulty of finding Sades works in 1920s Paris, see Luis Buuels
autobiography, My Last Breath trans. Abigail Israel (London: Vintage, 1994) pp.217-218. I thank
Astrid Scott for bringing this text to my attention.
18
Guillaume Apollinaire uvres compltes (Paris : Andr Balland et Jacques Lecat, 1966) Vol. II
p.231. Surrealist artists that were preoccupied with Sade include Man Ray, Salvador Dal, Hans
Bellmer and Clovis Trouille. Dalis works and writings are full of references to Sade, usually involving
excrement, anuses and so on.
19
10
Gilbert Lely Sade (Paris : Gallimard, 1960); Maurice Heine Le Marquis de Sade (Paris : Gallimard,
1950).
21
For discussion, see: Jean Deprun Sade et labb Bergier, Raison Prsente 67 (1983) :5-11 ; Pierre
Klossowski Sade my Neighbour trans. Alphonso Lingis (Evanston, Illinois: Northwestern University
Press, 1991); Jean Paulhan The Marquis de Sade and his Accomplice in Justine, Philosophy in the
Bedroom and Other Writings (London: Grove Press, Arrow Books, 1991):3-37; Batrice Didier Sade
thologien in Michel Camus, Philippe Roger, eds. Sade crire la crise (Paris: Pierre Belfond, 1983)
219-240: 220, 221,223.
11
with Nazism as merely superficial; those who regard Sade as essentially beyond the
categories and restraints of philosophy tend to dismiss literal analysis of his texts as
beside the point. Of the classicist camp, only Caroline Warman, in Sade: From
Materialism to Pornography (2002), has taken the trouble to critique the dominant
strands of Sade scholarship in a systematic and thorough way (yet even here she
scarcely mentions Michel Foucault and Georges Bataille, key intellectual figures,
although not regarded highly by most Sade scholars).
Two dominant trends have emerged in the last twenty years. Firstly, a great
deal of research has been done on Sades relationship with his intellectual, historical
and literary context. This has revealed Sade, to some extent, to be preoccupied with
the same basic themes as the philosophers of his age, and has somewhat reduced his
mythic status as a figure of absolute otherness (this does not, however, negate his
status as a figure of absolute revolt). Secondly, there have been a number of papers
and books written from a particular doctrinal perspective, whether Bataillian,
Foucaultian, Barthesian, or Lacanian. Some of these schools appear to be quite cut
off from Sade scholarship as a whole, with particular students only referring to and
considering the works of their own particular interpretive lineage. In short, Sade
scholars offer a number of markedly different interpretations of Sades works, like
explorers with incredible, contradictory tales of some unknown continent. That
continent, to a large extent, remains uncharted.
In order to illustrate the central themes and preoccupations of the existing
literature, and to find a passage into Sades work, I will present the work of ten critics
whose work I take to be representative of philosophical interpretation. These
approaches fall roughly into three groups. Firstly, I will present the work of Geoffrey
Gorer and Angela Carter, who both treat Sade as a thinker in a conventional sense,
and who have found Sades work to be of some merit in the political and social
sphere. That is, they read Sade as a positive thinker, though exclusively in the radical
sense of overturning values. Secondly, I will discuss those who consider Sade to be
the link between the Age of Enlightenment and the rise of Nazism. Finally, I will
address the more positive, and dominant, liberator reading, according to which Sade
12
is both a figure of cultural revolt, and in some sense stands radically outside the
intellectual mainstream. The authors I will consider here are Maurice Blanchot,
Georges Bataille, and Michel Foucault. This general discussion will end with a
consideration of the interpretation offered by Annie le Brun, a critic whose position
can be read as a synthesis of Sade reception hitherto. Bataille and Foucault, given
their role in bridging the gap between Sade criticism and philosophy proper, will be
given extended treatments.
It should be kept in mind that these distinctions are not mutually exclusive. Annie
le Brun, for example, prefers to work more closely with Sades text than others, and is
consequently highly critical of the more interpretative approaches of Bataille and
Foucault. As such, she has a certain affinity with those who prefer a more literal
approach to Sades work. More significantly, the liberator reading of Sade does not
necessarily negate the belief that Sade has ideological affiliations with the Nazis and
other totalitarian regimes. The Surrealists, Breton and Bataille in particular, took Sade
to be the advocate of a radical break with Christian morality. Although a clean break
with Judaeo-Christian morality or belief does not necessarily lead to total moral
nihilism, this is, apparently, a point that Sade insisted upon and that his less critical
readers accept. Le Brun and Bataille are apparently enthusiastic about this leap into
the abyss; Crocker, Adorno and Horkheimer, clearly, are not. The disagreement,
then, is not one of interpretation of Sade but of absolute moral values. What passes
for Le Brun and Bataille as liberation of the passions appears to other critics as the
megalomania of a self-anointed few. Ultimately, the project of interpreting Sade may
lead to a deepening and reconciliation of existing interpretations of Sades work,
rather than a simple process of elimination.
A final word should be said concerning Sades personality. Various attempts
have been made to assess Sades character, whether by sifting through the
biographical data or through the psychoanalysis of his prose style. 22 Sades text
elevates egocentricity, deceitfulness, and lack of guilt or empathy to the level of
philosophical doctrine, and his vision of human nature shows, as Philippe Roger puts
22
Jenny H. Batlay and Otis E. Fellows have suggested that the very tedium of Sades texts is
symptomatic of the death drive; Timo Airaksinen suggests that Sades work is itself an act of sadism
against the reader (hence, revealing the reader to be a masochist). See Airaksinen p.13;
Jenny H Batlay, Otis E. Fellows Diderot et Sade: Affinits et divergences, LEsprit Crateur 15 no.4
( winter 1975): 449-459, p.456.
13
I finish with a disclaimer. In this project, I will not be concerned with, as it were,
auditing the Sadeian text for intellectual royalties owing. Scholarly work of the last
thirty or so years has already well established that Sades work is very much part of
his age. Of his age, true, but in the sense that all extraordinary creations are. To write
off Juliette as a pastiche of plagiarisms of better thinkers would be like describing
Wright Flyer I as a motorized kite. The conclusions that Sade draws from found
premises and hypotheses bear little relation to anything that his intellectual elders
could have imagined.
23
Philippe Roger Sade : la Philosophie dans le pressoir (Paris : Bernard Grasset, 1976) p.18 ; Muriel
Schmid Le soufre au bord de la chaire : Sade et lEvangile (Genve : Labor et Fides, 2001) p. 143.
24
Airaksinen p.29.
14
To the reader: In this project, I shall quote and discuss passages in Sade that many
will find extremely offensive. Most of the secondary literature on Sade, and some
anthologies, avoid such explicitness. To treat this subject in an accurate and scholarly
manner, I feel, requires that the material at hand is not bowdlerized; to do is to
seriously misrepresent his work.
15
16
Chapter I: RECONNAISSANCE
Literature Review
When critics disagree, the artist is in accord with himself.
Geoffrey Gorer The Life and Ideas of the Marquis de Sade (London: Panther, 1963).
17
actual beliefs. The novel features a tangential incident set in a socialist utopia, the
Kingdom of Tamo. Tamo is located off the coast of New Zealand, and is ruled by
Zam, an absolute monarch. Zam spends some time lecturing a visiting European on
the social ills of Europe, and explains the principles by which his kingdom is
governed. The narrative, as Gorer has it, serves as a soap-box from which Sade
lambastes mans inhumanity to man, in particular the ills of colonialism, war, the
prison system, prostitution, private property, torture, and racist exploitation. The
institution of the nuclear family is criticized, as it promotes inequality. Gorers Sade
also makes sound suggestions on education, agriculture (described as the source of all
true wealth), and optimal population growth, and how to attain it. Sade also proposes
a European Union, in order to bring about an everlasting peace (LI: 105-114).
Gorer also has high praise for Sades insights into psychology, in particular his
psychology of sex and pleasure. As such, he takes Sade for a precursor of Kinsey and
Freud (LI: 146-147). His Sade is also an aesthete and epicurean, an advocate of the
personal cultivation of new routes to sensory stimuli. Writes Gorer: The study and
development of the arts has no other aim than to enable us to perceive beauty and
harmony in shapes, sounds and colours that were before either meaningless or
repulsive. What one individual or cultural group may find delicious another will find
revolting. Over time and through practice, individuals may be able to override what
they considered to be objectively based notions of revulsions, as one learns to
embrace the exotic tastes of another culture (150).2
Gorer goes on to systematize Sades psychology of sex. Sade, according to Gorer,
describes people into three categories- the weak or repressed, the natural
perverts, and the libertines. The weak lack the imagination or psychological
strength to go beyond normal sexuality, and erroneously associate their own lack of
sexual vigour or imagination for virtue. Unlike the natural perverts, the libertines
consciously imitate the obsessions of the second class to enlarge their experience. It
is almost exclusively with these two categories that de Sade deals, though the first
class furnishes the vile bodies with which the experiments are made (LI: 147).
Gorers interpretation of Sade as social critic, utopian political theorist and sexual
liberator leads to irreconcilable contradictions, however. He insists that Sades scenes
2
Sade uses the same analogy between exotic sexual practices and gamey- tasting food in La Nouvelle
18
19
Angela Carter The Infernal Desire Machines of Doctor Hoffman (London: Penguin, 1972) pp.122 -
123.
4
Angela Carter The Sadeian Woman and the Ideology of Pornography (New York: Harper Colophon
Books, 1978). I thank Dennis Robinson for bringing this book to my attention.
20
This is not strictly accurate. Catherine Cusset notes that the 18th Century Libertine novel was
frequently allegorized by a female character and her adventures. Catherine Cusset No Tomorrow: The
Ethics of Pleasure in the French Enlightenment (Charlottesville & London: University Press of
Virginia, 1999) p.12.
6
Sade himself refers to Hobbes, and there are certainly similarities, but Sade does not appear to have
read Hobbes in the original. Han and Valla have noted the similarity, describing Sades vision as that
of Hobbes without a contract. See Han and Valla A propos p.117. Sade writes, in La Nouvelle
21
In the two texts that Carter concentrates on, Juliette and Philosophy in the
Bedroom (1795), Sades characters endlessly argue for sexual freedom for women.
Not only is no sexual possibility not considered and analyzed in detail; Sade, writes
Carter, argues for the womans being free to enjoy herself in whatever way she
pleases. Anything that may impede her sexually, Sade often attacks for this reason
alone. The institution of marriage is questioned, as is any notion of biological destiny.
Sade, writes Carter, is also ahead of Freud and European men in general in another
respect- he knows exactly what the clitoris does, and where it is. 7
Whatever else he says or does not say, Sade declares himself unequivocally for the right
of women to fuck- as if the period in which women fuck aggressively, tyrannously and
cruelly will be a necessary stage in the development of a general human consciousness of
the nature of fucking ; that if it is not egalitarian, it is unjust. Sade does not suggest this
process as such; but he urges women to fuck as actively as they are able, so that powered
by their enormous and hitherto untapped sexual energy they will then be able to fuck their
way into history and, in doing so, change it (SW: 27).
Carter also points out that for Sade, sex and politics are aspects of the same
economy- he offers an absolutely sexualized world where sexuality underlies
everything. Sex is not a moral issue but a political reality. People, on this view, get
into politics for the sex, or the pleasure of power; sexual freedom implies political
power over ones own destiny. According to Carters reading, Juliette is Sades
master morality personified: [i]f Justine is a pawn because she is a woman, Juliette
transforms herself from pawn to queen in a single move and henceforth goes wherever
she pleases on the chess board (SW: 79). Her life is an arithmetical progression from
one atrocity to the next. Of Juliettes monstrous penchant for mass destruction, Carter
observes that a free woman in an unfree society will be a monster (SW: 27) and
asks, if we admire the campaigns of a great general, is it hypocrisy to refuse to
Justine, [l]a justice ou linjustice dune action, dit Hobbes, dpend du jugement seul de celui qui la
faite...ce qui le tirera hors de blme et justifiera son procd... (LNJ 2:112).
7
The clitoris was already known in Sades time (by European men). Renaldus Columbus claimed to
have discovered the clitoris in 1559. Writes Thomas Laqueur, [h]e tells his most gentle reader that
this is pre-eminently the seat of womens delight. Columbus De re anatomica (Venice, 1559)
pp.447-448. Quoted in Thomas Laqueur Making Sex: Body and Gender from the Greeks to Freud
(Cambridge, Massachusetts, London: Harvard University Press, 1990) p.64, n.7.
22
Carter reads Sade as recognizing the master type who will succeed in the
economic arrangements of modernity - the fiscal morality of a market place red in
tooth and claw. Sade is presenting a virtue ethics for capitalists, on this view, one in
which intellect, talents and insensitivity are supreme. Juliette is rationality
personified and leaves no single cell of her brain unused. She will never obey the
fallacious promptings of her heart. Her mind functions like a computer programmed
to produce two results for herself- financial profit and libidinal gratification (SW:
79).
Carter notes a number of slips in Sades thinking. Firstly, his moral discussions
run into contradiction- he dismisses the elements of morality as fictions, yet insists on
the pleasure to break rules. Secondly, his feminism (assuming Carters interpretation
is correct, that Sade is in fact a feminist to begin with) is incomplete, insofar as it
tends to fall back on a male model of sexuality. Sade dithers, as Carter puts it, on
crucial points of sexuality and sexual roles, undermining any simple positive reading
of Sade as a friend of the feminist movement. Women become men through strapping
on dildoes, or by having huge clitorises; the phallus retains its centrality. The
character Clairwil, in Juliette, is so obsessed with the prick that she is convinced that
a dissection will reveal one lodged in her brain. Says Carter, this is one of the
contradictions of Sades female libertines that they ingest, but do not integrate within
themselves the signs of maleness (SW: 90).
Ultimately, Carters reading of Sade is not straightforwardly positive. As she says
of Juliettes throwing her own daughter into a fire- for fun (J:1186-1187), Juliette is
absolutely free from any of the lingering traces of the human responses that can only
23
be learned through the society of others who are not accomplices, who are not aspects
of the self that confirm the omnipotence of the self (SW: 99). This, for Carter,
suggests the natural egoism and narcissism of the child. Here, Carter agrees with
Adorno and Horkheimers treatment of the character Juliette; despite her iron selfcontrol and her triumph of the barriers of pain, shame, disgust and morality, she is,
fundamentally, an embodiment of intellectual pleasure in regression (SW: 148). As
for Sades obvious misogyny, Carter takes it as a single strand in total revulsion
against a mankind of whom, unlike Swift, he cannot delude himself he is not a
member. Somewhat inconsistently, Carter states that
Swift saw mankind rolling in a welter of shit, as Sade does, but Sades satire upon man is
far blacker and more infernal than Swifts- for Sade, mankind doesnt roll in shit because
mankind is disgusting, but because mankind has overweening aspirations to the
superhuman (SW: 34).
This does not quite reconcile with Carters reading of Sade as inculcating, in suitably
confident people, the wish to transcend their species through acts beyond Good and
Evil. The superhuman aspirations of Juliette themselves may appear infantile,
insofar as they stand as a childish rebellion against the demands of socialization.
Carter (as many others do) describes Sade as both the diagnostician and symptom.
This tension in Carters reading is not fully resolved or addressed.
Although Carter acknowledges Sades wish for a secular republic and other
social changes, at bottom, despite his talk of overcoming and of libertinism, he is
above all a pessimist. Carter cites Sades description, for example, of humanity as a
fallen race (SW: 140). Likewise, in the short story Eugnie de Franval, a character
denies a daughter the right to bear children, arguing that the human race ought to die
out, stating that [a] plant whose only product is poison cannot be rooted out too
quickly (SW: 136-136). Sade, Carter notes, is too intelligent to be a SatanistSatan is
a redundant concept in a world so manifestly evil.
When an atheist casts a cool eye on the World, flesh and the devil fuse; when an atheist
casts a cool eye on the world, he must always find Satan a more likely hypothesis as
ruling principle than a Saviour. Criminality may present itself as a kind of saintly selfmastery, an absolute rejection of hypocrisy (SW: 33).
24
Carter also reads Sade as a pessimist of the future. There is Durand, an alchemist
accomplice of Juliettes, who uses the black art of poisoning and her knowledge of
biology to destroy. An early pioneer of weapons of mass destruction, she wipes out a
citys population with bubonic plague (SW: 115). Durand, for Carter, represents the
return to pure mythology- the reduction of Enlightenments lofty hopes of harnessing
nature through technology to pure chaos. Carters Sade also sees in the future a new
age where the commercial class takes the reigns of power, and where knowledge of
the natural world brings neither peace nor harmony, but will certainly make a
minority very rich and powerful (SW: 113).
Before fleeing to the United States, Hermann Rauschning was a Nazi party member and mayor of
Danzig. During the Second World War he wrote several books on what he felt to be the nihilism at the
centre of Nazi ideology. Having exaggerated the amount of contact he actually had with Hitler, his
worth as a historical source is in dispute. See Hermann Rauschning The Revolution of Nihilism:
Warning to the West trans. E.W. Dickes (New York: Alliance Book Corporation, 1939).
25
10
This refers to a biography by Jean Desbordes, Le vrai visage du Marquis de Sade (Paris: ditions de
Raymond Queneau Lectures pour un front, in Btons, chiffres et lettres (Paris : Gallimard,
26
the other hand, can only be understood from the perspective of his own thoughts on
the human condition.
11
For discussion, see Jean Gassin Le sadisme dans luvre de Camus in La Revue des Lettres
Modernes 360-365 (1973):121-144; Raymond Gay-Crosier Camus et Sade: Une relation ambigu,
Zeitshrift fr Franzsische Sprache und Literatur 98 (1988): 166-173.
12
Albert Camus The Myth of Sisyphus trans. Justin OBrien (London: Penguin, 2000).
27
Camus goes on to describe Sade as the prophet of barbed wire and observation
towers (R: 42). His association of Nazism and Sade is not fully developed; Camus
reads his own existential assumptions into Sade and Nazism, and does not dwell on
the actual ideological content of either, besides making the observation that, like
Camus himself, both are opposed to traditional religious belief.
13
Albert Camus The Renegade in Exile and The Kingdom trans. Justin OBrien (New York: Vintage,
1986):34-61; Albert Camus LEtranger (Paris: Gallimard, 1942); Albert Camus Caligula (Paris:
Gallimard, 1993).
14
Albert Camus The Rebel trans. Anthony Bower (New York: Vintage Books, 1984).
15
Theodor W. Adorno, Max Horkheimer Dialectic of Enlightenment trans. John Cumming (London:
Verso, 1997).
28
16
Adorno observes in his Minima Moralia that [t]heory must needs deal with cross-grained, opaque,
unassimilated material, which as such admittedly has from the start an anachronistic quality, but is not
wholly obsolete since it has outwitted the historical dynamic. Theodor Adorno Minima Moralia
trans. E.F.N. Jephcott (London: Verso, 1974) p.151.
17
29
As will be discussed in later chapters, Sades characters are in fact preoccupied with crimes on a
20
This negative description of sport may owe something to Schopenhauers scathing remarks on
parlour games as a means of evading boredom, which, in turn, repeats Kants assertion in the
Anthropology.
30
Sade does not recognize, as does Kant, any moral law within, but instead identifies it
as a myth, along with the myth of civilization. Sades character Juliette a rake
without illusions- (DE: 109) lives by this insight, and revels in attacking
Enlightenment civilization with its own clearly corruptible instruments. In the
following passage, Juliette is described as the Anti-Kant.
In regard to self-control, {Juliettes} directions are at times related to Kants as the special
application as to its basic proposition : therefore virtue, to the extent that it is founded
upon inner freedom, also contains an affirmative commandment for men, which is to
bring all of their abilities and inclinations under its control [i.e., of reason], and therefore
under self-control, which prevails over the negative commandment not to be ruled by
ones emotions and inclinations [the duty of apathy]; because, unless reason takes the
reins of government into its hand , emotions and inclinations will be in control. 21
Juliette preaches on the self-discipline of the criminal : Work out your plan a few days
beforehand ; consider all its consequences ; be attentive to what might assist you what
might betray you, and weigh up all these things with the same callousness you would
apply if you were certain to be discovered[ J:640-641] (DE:95). (Square brackets are
Adorno and Horkheimers).
Both Kant and Sade advocate apathy, but for wholly different reasons. They are
identified as signs of the same crisis, nevertheless. Adorno and Horkheimer appear to
regard this onslaught on compassion by philosophy as the central problem of
modernity. In Sade, the removal of compassion from the outlook of the characters
leads to (what Adorno refers to as) the barbaric success-religion of today, and a
fragmentation of society through the abandonment of all linkages between
individuals. Here, Adorno links the rejection of compassion with a return to preChristian morality: The barbaric success-religion of today is consequently not simply
contrary to morality: it is the homecoming of the West to the venerable morals of our
[non-Christian?] ancestors 22 (Sades advocacy of a return to the morality of the PreChristian peoples is discussed in Chapter VI). Love, companionship, marriage, and
familial ties are all dismissed as untruths, as they cannot be verified. We are all
alone as is often said of the modern age when everyone is expendable. Sade is not
21
Metaphysische Anfnge der Tugendlehre, ed.cit.,Vol. VI, p.408 (Adorno and Horkheimers
footnote).
22
31
the first to have made such scandalous suggestions, however- Adorno and
Horkheimer point out that even Democritus had denounced parental love as
economically motivated (DE: 116). But Sade pushes further, towards the destruction
of civilization, or at least the transformation of its institutions into the tools of a
privileged elite.
The authors finish the chapter in stating that Sade stands as a writer who told us
the truth- that the world is cruel, and that a fortunate life in a world of cruelty is a
vicious contradiction ... in the light of the mere existence of that world (DE:
118).The memories of the war are fresh in the minds of the authors- both Jewish
Germans, whose text frequently refers to the Nazi experience, beatings, deportations
and pogroms. For them, Sade represents all that the Enlightenment spawned and
failed to control. Only a thinker as awful as Sade, they insist, could shed light on the
abominations of the present. As for those naves that point out the obviously
fictional nature of the Sadeian universe, Adorno and Horkheimer reply- only
exaggeration is true (118). Other thinkers are dismissed as giving assurances seeking
only to console - as was Sades own view.
Adorno and Horkheimer differ from other critics of Sade in that they emphasize
the logical, methodical nature of Sades works, as opposed to the more figurative and
symbolic treatments. Adorno and Horkheimers understanding of Nazism as primarily
a movement grounded on ruthless efficiency is problematic, as is their association of
Nazism with the bourgeoisie (and the bourgeoisie with Nazism). 23 (In particular,
Nazi doctrine prioritized the destruction of the Jews ahead of heavy industrys
demand for slave labour; wholesale destruction on racial- ideological grounds, rather
than ruthless efficiency, appears to have been the dominant trend). 24 Further, Adorno
and Horkheimer do not treat the specific doctrines of Nazism, instead focusing on
their prior theoretical interpretation. I will return to this issue in Chapter VI.
23
For discussion of this criticism, see Richard Rorty The Overphilosophication of Politics,
Constellations 7 (March 2001):128-32, p.130. I thank Sterling Lynch for bringing this article to my
attention.
24
For discussion see Ian Kershaw Hitler 1936-1945 Nemesis (London: Penguin, 2001) p.492; also
Daniel Jonah Goldhagen Hitlers Willing Executioners (London: Abacus, 1996) p.296; Robert S.
Wistrich Hitler and the Holocaust (London: Weidenfeld & Nicholson, 2001) p.2.
32
De nombreux lecteurs ont tendance rejeter les crits de Sade. Peu agrables lire, ils
sont souvent ennuyeux et frisent mme le ridicule. Ils sont insignifiants tant du point de
vue littraire que pornographique, en dpit de leur influence sur la-littrature. Pour ce qui
est du style, il est mdiocre et plat. Cependant, aprs avoir surmont ces obstacles
considrables, on dcouvre en Sade un vritable penseur. Sans tre un esprit profond, ce
penseur nen prsente pas moins une perspicacit terrifiante, et la ligne de pense quil a
rvle est aussi importante que provocante.
Lester G. Crocker An Age of Crisis: Man and World in Eighteenth Century French Thought
(Baltimore: the Johns Hopkins Press) 1959.
Nature and Culture: Ethical Thought in the French Enlightenment (Baltimore: the
Johns Hopkins Press, 1963
Au Cur de la pense de Sade, Thmes et figures du Sicle des lumires. Mlanges
offerts a Roland Mortier. ed. Raymond Trousson (Genve : Droz, 1980) : 59-71, p.59.
26
Laugaa-Traut p.290.
33
architects of political philosophy, such as Rousseau, were deeply uncertain about the
applicability of democracy, and feared that all political organization would degenerate
into despotism, remarking that full democracy was for gods, not men. 27 Crocker
writes of Rousseau, Diderot, Laclos and Sade, that Their pessimism stems partly
from their answer to this question: To what does the world give its approbation,
esteem and admiration? To follies, or to sheer success and power, was the reply. 28
For Bayle, human life was fundamentally corrupt and reason the slave of the passions,
and that, were humanity a product of Nature, it is apparently a product of a natural
order in a state of sickness. 29 Voltaires views were scarcely less pessimistic, once
describing the world as a little ball of mud upon which insects eat each other.30
Sades comments on the horrors of the world are to be read in this context. 31
Utilitarianism is another cause of the nihilist dissolution, insofar as it proposed,
with the new emphasis on the individual, to induce a revolt of the ego against the
frustration of its demands, against sacrifice for others, and simultaneously a revolt
against rationalistic ethics in favor of the instincts and the effective elements of the
personality (NC: 334). Among Sades chief influences, Crocker notes that the
elements of Sades materialism, and its philosophical implications, can be traced to
Count Buffon (1702-1788), Marie-Jean Antoine Nicolas Caritat, Marquis de
Condorcet (1745-1784), Denis Diderot (1713-1784), Paul-Henri Thiry, Baron
dHolbach (1723-1789), Julien Offray de La Mettrie (1709-1751) and Lucretius (c.
27
Rousseau The Social Contract trans. Maurice Cranston. (London: Penguin Books, 1968) pp. 30-32,
125; also pp. 131, 134-135, 323. Rousseau A Discourse on Inequality trans. Maurice Cranston
(London: Penguin 1984) pp.133-134.
28
29
Lester G. Crocker an Age of Crisis pp.25, 221; Pierre Bayle Historical and Critical Dictionary
(1697) (selections) translated with introduction and notes, by Richard H. Popkin (Indianapolis, New
York, Kansas City: The Bobbs-Merrill Company, Inc. 1965) pp.290-291.
30
Voltaire, Zadig (Paris: Larousse, 1993) p.91; also Voltaire Candide and Other Tales introduction by
H.N. Brailsford; trans. Tobias Smollett (London: J.M.Dent & Sons, 1937) pp.74, 99, 249, 329.
31
In Reflections on the Novel, for example, Sade writes that [t]here was not a man alive who had not
experienced in the short span of four or five years more misfortunes than the most celebrated novelist
could portray in a century. Thus, to compose works of interest, one had to call upon the aid of hell
itself, and to find in the world of make-believe things werewhith one was fully familiar merely by
delving into daily life in this age of iron (120:109). Similar: J: 557, 1160; 120:778, 784; J: CL:73;
GT:25. Sade refers to Voltaires Zadig on the first page of both versions of Justine.
34
99-c.55 B.C.E). Sades sensationalism is drawn from the writings of Nicolas Frret
(1688-1794) ( Vol.III:1393, fn.1-4). 32 None of these thinkers were overtly
nihilistic, yet, according to Crocker, the implications of their thought lead directly to
Sades dark pool: [n]ihilism (not only as a philosophy, but as a psychology) is the
worm at the core of our culture. It is the flaw we must constantly overcome. Sade was
the first to bring the full truth of this danger into the general consciousness of the
Western World (NC: 398-400).
Crocker gives a brief summary of Sades system. The obvious internal flaws of
Sades system are noted; Sade simply denies our natural tendency towards
cooperation and kindness towards one another; that is, most of what we mean when
we speak of humanism. Sade, writes Crocker, denies that pity, sympathy, justice,
the surpassing of self, and the demand for limit are natural, whereas in fact they
constitute a large part of the initial adjective in the phrase, human nature (NC: 428429). Sade also contradicts himself when he speaks of the illusory basis of all values,
and yet speaks of pleasure as a valuable thing in itself (NC: 425). Sades project also
fails as it leads directly to exhaustion. The pursuit of higher levels of sensation and
pleasure, Crocker holds, can only lead to ennui (NC: 427). But Crocker feels that
these are minor shortcomings compared to the enormity of what he achieved, and the
difficulty of coming to terms with his revelation.
Nazism and Sades immorality are drawn together in Crockers history of ideas
(NC: 58). The taste for the superhuman, in Camus words, is in fact the denial of our
instinct for collective harmony (to go beyond other humans) enhanced by cultural
development. For Crocker, it emerges as a known possibility in Sades time and texts
and is fully expressed by the Holocaust and similar atrocities.
Accompanying these developments [denial in philosophy of validity of norms
available to reason] was the desire for a total integration of man in nature, with refusal of
any transcendence, even though it was admitted that his more complex physical
organization gave him certain special abilities and ways of living. The important thing, as
La Mettrie, dHolbach, and others made clear, is that he is submitted to the same laws;
everything is response to need mechanically, some added, like a tree or a machine. Man
32
For discussion of Sades materialism, see in particular Jean Leduc Les Sources de lathisme et de
limmoralisme du marquis de Sade, Studies on Voltaire and the Eighteenth Century 68 (Genve:
Institut et Muse Voltaire, 1969):7-66; Warman Sade: from Materialism to Pornography; Jean-Pierre
Han, Jean-Pierre Valla A propos pp.110, 111.
35
merely carries out natural forces- without any freedom whatsoever- in all he does,
whether he loves or hates, helps or hurts, gives life or takes it.[a]n unbroken line of
thought leads from such eighteenth-century views to Hitlers Mein Kampf and the Nazi
infamies ...
Nihilism is the rejection of the prevailing organization of instincts which is imposed
by any culture, and ipso facto of all moral restrictions to the id (a revolt against repression
of the instincts). Totalitarianism is a defense of culture based on the acceptance of the
truth of nihilism; it pretends to nothing more than a tyrannical and arbitrary imposition of
a superego and contemplates the remaking of the individual, through the pressures of total
conditioning, so that the id is inhibited and the ego enslaved. If the effort toward
humanistic self-control and voluntary co-operation does not succeed, culture is left with
no other way to defend itself (NC: 333-334, 395).
Crocker regards Sade as posing the most important question facing, not merely
philosophy, but civilization itself. In his novels, we are not only confronted with a
vision of planetary holocaust (NC: 428). We are presented with a premonition of the
collapse of the values that distinguish us from base nature and guide us towards
higher ideals; the will to prevent such a global catastrophe from occurring. The world
has not become a kinder or more just place in the two hundred years since Sade wrote
36
his books, or even in the last fifty years, despite the promises our leaders made
following the Second World War. Sade is dangerous as he affirms this abyss, rather
than proposing a solution, or denying that such an abyss exists at all.
33
Svein- Eirik Fauskevg Sade ou la tentation totalitaire : Etude sur lanthropologie littraire dans La
Nouvelle Justine et lHistoire de Juliette. (Paris: Honor champion diteur, 2001). I thank Caroline
Warman for bringing this book to my attention. Caroline Warman Sade: from Materialism to
pornography (Oxford: Voltaire Foundation, 2002).
34
Michel Onfray Antimanuel de philosophie: leons socratiques et alternatives (Rosny: Bral, 2001)
pp.141-142.
35
This is slightly different to John Mackies error theory, according to which all moral sentences are
false. See Richard Joyce the Myth of Morality (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2001). I thank
Charles Pigden for pointing this passage out to me.
37
36
Neiman p.173.
38
Neiman does concede that Adorno and Horkheimer make a valid point: Kants moral
law has no basis in the structure of reality. It rests instead on what he calls the fact of
reason. This means that reason justifies itself. Kant would not justify morality on
instrumental grounds, so he offers no arguments to persuade us to be moral. Rather,
he says, its a fact of reason that we should be. But as Adorno and Horkheimer point
out, facts do not help us when theyre not there (EMT: 193). Neiman sees in fact a
commonality between Sade and Kant on this point- the rejection of the idea that there
is a relationship between authentic virtue and reward. The entire argument of Justine
and Juliette, she notes, is to illustrate this.
37
39
Rather than presenting virtue triumphant, he sought to show it in disrepair. For only when
love of virtue is disconnected from all questions of reward can it be seen as sublime. Such
revelation is particularly needed by those of us who live in corrupted ages. If we expect
virtue to be rewarded, we may easily abandon it when its not. If we know in advance
how often it is ill-requited, well be better prepared to meet adversity with the virtue that
is its own reward. Was he telling the truth here, he could almost pass for Kant (Neiman:
180).
Neiman notes, however, that Sades project is closer to that of Hume, insofar as they
are both sceptics: [w]hile Hume undertook to humiliate reason, Sade sought to
torture it (Neiman: 194). Humes position is unstable. He shows that the traditions
upon which we rely for our morality are supported by nothing more than custom and
habit, yet prescribes that the wise few can forgo them. Sades solution, notes
Neiman, is to wholeheartedly accept the disjuncture. Neiman reads Sades enthusiasm
for the entire destruction of the world as a solution to the gap between reason and
nature: [i]f nature leads to its own obliteration, you may, of course, decide to view
annihilation as a natural goal (196). She notes that this may be an entirely consistent
outcome of a possible defence of the unity of nature and purpose. This reading is
interesting, and perplexing. For Neiman, Sade represents the terminus of 18th Century
moral thought on the question of ethics and the problem of evil. As such, Neiman
meshes the interpretation offered by Camus and Crocker; Sades thought is at once a
howl at a godless sky, and a lucid (if laboured) exposition of the darker thought of the
period.
38
This originally appeared in a book entitled Lautramont et Sade (Paris: Les ditions de Minuit,
40
other. Even if it is the case that Sades psychology is simply wrong- that people are
naturally social and cannot really stand true solitude (it is used as a punishment for
criminals, after all) Sades unique individuals, Blanchot claims, are powerful
through their solitude. These are the individuals who have chosen- and are able tobreak off from the rest of civilization: Sades cast of characters is composed
primarily of a tiny number of omnipotent men who have the energy and initiative to
raise themselves above the law and place themselves outside the pale of prejudice,
men feel that nature has singled them out and, feeling themselves worthy of this
distinction, strive to assuage their passions by any and all means (ibid: 41). Blanchot
notes also a paradox in Sade - Sade may advocate (in places) that all men are equal,
but for Blanchot this merely means that
...no one is worth more than any other, all are interchangeable, each is a unit, a cipher in
an infinite progression. For the Unique Person, all men are equal in their nothingness, and
the Unique One, by reducing them to nothing, simply clarifies and demonstrates this
nothingness (54).
41
The true libertine loves even the reproaches he receives for the unspeakable deeds he has
done. Have we not seen some who loved the very tortures human vengeance was readying
for them, who submitted to them joyfully, who beheld the scaffold as a throne of glory
upon which they would have been most grieved not to perish with the same courage they
had displayed in the loathsome exercise of their heinous crimes? There is the man at the
ultimate degree of corruption (51). 39
Blanchot takes the character Amlie, in Juliette, as merely the extreme of this trend.
She actually wishes to die (this interpretation and example is adopted by Bataille, as
discussed below). Finally, Blanchots Sade has discovered negation as the means to
power- negation of the other; denial that the other even exists in any meaningful
sense.
...the true man knows that he is alone, and he accepts it; everything in him which relates
to others-to his whole seventeen centuries heritage of cowardice- 40 he repudiates and
rejects: for example, pity, gratitude, and love are all sentiments he crushes and destroys;
by destroying them, he recuperates all the strength that he would have had to dedicate to
these debilitating impulses and, what is even more important, from this labor of
destruction he draws the beginning of a true energy (67).
Here Sades Unique One appears as a figure who is guilty of either inconsistency or
bad faith, for to negate the reality of the other is to deny that oneself exists in any real
sense, insofar as the other is basically a member of the same class. Sade recognizes
this, his character Saint-Fond stating that he and anyone else who achieves such
destruction is a god in comparison to the average person (59). Blanchots Sade is
clearly a proto- Nietzschean figure, insofar as he is depicted as passing through this
field of absolute negation to arrive at a life-affirming hero- the Unique One. Yet
Blanchot appears to render Sade harmless, or at least admirable, by presenting him as
a positive thinker whose apparent advocacy of mass destruction is merely incidental
to the expression of energy (65). Blanchot also marks Sade as a proto-Freudian.
Dreams, says Blanchots Sade, are recognized as the work of the mind restored to
39
Blanchot does not give a citation here. A passage similar in spirit is in Juliette (J: 1039), but the
42
instinct and thus delivered from the influences of waking morality (69). 41 Finally,
Blanchot describes Sades system as a personal product- a standpoint epistemology of
the pervert, but one that illuminates the experience of everyman.
Blanchots interpretation of Sade has been critiqued on a number of points. Le
Brun has questioned the view that Sades characters are propelled by a death wish.
Sadeian heroes, she says, want to stay alive at all costs (this will be discussed below
in the discussion on Bataille). Jane Gallop questions the rendering of an absolutely
isolated sovereign man, noting that there is in fact a lot of talk of friendship (lamiti)
in the 120 Days, a lighter, friendlier aspect that Batailles reading omits. 42
Caroline Warman questions Blanchots trivialization of those aspects of Sades
philosophy that place him in the stream of Enlightenment thought. As Warman notes,
Blanchots reading of Sade omits much of the content of Sades actual philosophical
speculations, in particular on the topic of materialism, which Blanchot dismisses as
les theories la mode. 43 Warman also questions the reduction of Sades thought to
a celebration of The Unique One, given the degree to which Sades libertines rely on
teamwork. 44 Blanchot has also written of Sade in the context of his philosophy of
language, the merits of which have also been questioned by Le Brun (Blanchots
theory of language will be discussed below, in the discussion on Foucault). 45
The authenticity of this citation is in doubt. Sade refers to dreams once in a short story:
When we are awaiting the outcome of some event, and the way it will affect us occupies our mind all
day long, we are quite certain to dream about it; now, our mind, which is exclusively occupied with its
objective, nearly always causes us then to see one aspect of this event about which we have not thought
much the previous day. Sade, Faxelange, or The Wrongs of Ambition (CL: 22n). The only other
reference to dreams Sade makes is in a letter to his wife, in which he calls them very ridiculous
things. Sade; Gilbert Lely, editor LAigle, Mademoiselle, lettres publies pour la premire fois sur les
manuscrits autographes (Paris: Les Editions Georges Artigues, 1949) p.151, quoted in Lorna Berman
Thoughts and Themes of the Marquis de Sade (Kitchener, Ontario: Ainsworth Press Ltd, 1971) p.150.
42
Gallop associates this idea with Nietzsches concept of star friendship, although it seems doubtful
that there is anything in 120 that is light and friendly. Jane Gallop Intersections A reading of Sade,
with Bataille, Blanchot, and Klossowski (Lincoln and London: Nebraska University press, 1981) p.73.
43
Maurice Blanchot La Raison de Sade in Maurice Blanchot Sade et Restif de La Bretonne (Brussels
45
43
Annie Le Brun (b.1943), writes Lawrence Bongie, is indisputably one of the more
significant figures in recent Sade criticism, a latter-day surrealist and possibly the
Marquis most ardent contemporary champion. 46 She has written a number of studies
on Sade, the most important being Sade: a Sudden Abyss (Soudain un bloc dabme,
Sade, 1986, hereafter SSA). 47 The text swings between analytic and purely figurative
registers, between philosophy and poetry; as such, it takes some effort to extricate
Le Bruns interpretation. Yet it is there, and it is significant for several reasons.
Firstly, Le Brun, unlike Camus, Adorno and Horkheimer, rejects the association of
Sade with any political ideology, in particular Nazism. Le Bruns Sade is close in
spirit to the Surrealists, in particular Bataille. For both Le Brun and Bataille, Sade
represents absolute freedom of the passions, and a complete rejection of morality.
Secondly, Le Brun considers Sade the first, if not the only, author to have seriously
conceived of a universe without God (SAA: 152). If one embraces atheism with the
wholeheartedness of Sade, she argues, everything follows, as atheism leads to a
reconsideration of the social position man has usurped in the universe. Ordinary
atheists, lacking Sades stark gaze, merely fall back onto an ideological mire
(152). Le Brun has, consequently, little patience for Klossowskis interpretation of
Sade as a closet theist (74).
Le Brun holds that theoretical writings on Sade have largely missed the point of
his works. She rejects the interpretations offered by Barthes and Foucault, charging
them with neglecting Sades concern with reality, in particular the concrete
relationship between the body and thought. Le Brun reads Sade as insisting that there
are neither ideas without bodies nor bodies without ideas (147), and takes Sade to
46
Laurence Bongie Sade: a Biographical Essay (Chicago & London: University of Chicago Press,
1998) p.297.
47
Annie Le Brun Sade : A Sudden Abyss trans. Camille Nash (San Francisco: City Lights Books,
1990).
.Sade and the Theatre In Deepak Narang Sawhney, ed. Must we burn Sade? (New
York: Humanity Books, 1999): 99-113.
. Sade, aller et dtours (Paris: Plon, 1989)
. Les chteaux de la subversion (Paris : J.J. Pauvert aux Editions Garnier Frres,
1982)
. Volupt perdue ? In Revue de la Bibliothque national de France 7 (Jan
2001) :19-24
44
for order (53). Discussion of these metaphors of optics and machines takes precedence
over text-based analysis of ideas, and no argument is offered as to why these readings
are accurate (66, 68, 98, 130, 154, 157). This is significant, as Le Brun evaluates other
interpretations against her own notions of Sade as a scourer of ideologies. In
particular, as with others, she takes Sade to be opposed to any particular political
orientation. 48 She discusses at length the lack of political orientation in Sades Aline
et Valcour, in which the narrator openly admits to writing a text that is politically
ambiguous (again, an aspect unaccounted for in Geoffrey Gorers account). Sade
offers three choices of political attitude: acceptance, reform, or individual revolt; it
is left to the reader to decide for themselves (106-109). Political decision, in Sades
view, Le Brun argues, is subordinate to individual taste.
Much of Le Bruns discussion holds that Sades text has no core doctrine or
consistency of ideas beyond the imperative to abandon ideas, to return to the purity
of body and desire. In the following passage, Le Brun portrays Sade as revealing
the truth that we are all criminals, and that Fascism is the very opposite of this
ideological cleansing (67, 73). All crime is an expression of human nature (for Le
Brun, as for Sade, only cruelty is considered a true expression of human nature); the
notion that crime is simply due to an aberrant ideological choice is
...a comfort Sade does without and makes his readers do without. In laying bare the most
unjustifiable passions in the heart of Silling, Sade foils that questionable play of
justifications which can be made to serve any feelings, especially the loftier ones, from
motherly love to heroism. The fact that these justifications are all equally inadmissible
alters nothing. They all dress up human savageness in ideological uniforms. Fascism,
which draws on all the gaudy stereotypes of race, family, fatherland and countryside,
constitutes one of the most spectacular examples of this ideological masking, so utterly
opposed to the disrobing found in Sade.
Le Brun then states that those who associate Sade with Fascism are in denial about
their true selves, without offering, beyond the authority of Sade himself, evidence to
support this assessment of human nature (67). Finally, she offers a curiously non48
Slavoj iek gives a similar, though more straightforward, argument. Interpreting Sade through
Lacan, iek insists that Sade represents absolute autonomy, whereas Nazism represents the exact
opposite- the rhetoric of sacrifice of the few for the good of the state. See Slavoj iek and Glyn Daly
Conversations with iek (Cambridge: Polity, 2004) p.126.
46
exist. The victims, she writes, are those who lack this sense: ...if Sades victims are
indeed characters who do not resist excess, falling by the thousand before the
excessiveness of libertines, isnt this more on account of their inability to conceive of
excess, than their inability to tolerate it physically?(182). Le Brun assumes that the
victims die because they cannot conceive of the excess that kills them. This notion of
excess may be given a more prosaic formulation- Sades serial killers are successful,
like real life serial killers, because their acts cannot be anticipated by normal, trusting
people until it is too late.
Le Bruns treatment of Sade as an ethicist (broadly construed; that is, ethics as
concerning the highest values and virtues for a particular doctrine) is complex. Le
Brun identifies (correctly, I think) a close affinity between the ethics of Sade and
Nietzsche, and regards Sades tirade against traditional morality and religion as akin
to Nietzsches Genealogy of Morals, reading both as holding the Christian God
accountable as the thief of energy (137-138). The two thinkers diverge, she
suggests; Nietzsche diagnoses Christian ethics as decadent, whereas Sade allegedly
withholds judgment, and merely illustrates. 49 Also insightful is Le Bruns reading of
Sade as revealing the naivety of the moral thought of the age, that is, as engaging in
the early modern debate on moral theory (47). More problematic is Le Bruns attempt
to show Sade as morally superior to the normative morality he attempts to undermine.
She notes that Sade opposed the death penalty (141,172). Le Brun also contrasts
Sades ethics with what she takes to be the worse evils of conventional, bourgeois
morality. According to Le Bruns Sade, conventional morality demands the
subordination of the particular to the general will, and makes demands on our conduct
that are allegedly impossible to live up to (70,170).
Le Brun also makes a number of associations between conventional morality,
the morality of the Revolution, and the (alleged) aesthetic horrors of the Social Realist
school. The moralizing of the bourgeoisie and the revolutionaries, writes Le Brun, are
accomplished at the cost of a systematic dematerialization of the bodythe orthodox
art of the revolutionary era can be said to anticipate the future horrors of socialist
realism. She goes on to describe the horror of this transformation: one encounters
49
I question this reading. Sades libertine novels are peopled by protagonists who speak with one
voice on the question of that stupid religion, and their largely silent victims. The only victim
character who argues in turn is Justine, but her arguments seldom go beyond pious clichs. Sades
critique of Christianity is discussed in Chapter VI.
48
the same violence: a violence perpetrated against the individual body to transform it
into anonymous human material for nourishing the ideological machine (144-145).
Morality, for Le Brun, is associated with ideology, weepy sensibility and
revolutionary virtue (145). 50 She contrasts Robespierre, who executed in the name of
morality, with Sade, in particular the latters criticism of the use of the guillotine
(171). Robespierre, writes Le Brun, writes in the cold, white, cutting tones of death,
in contrast to Sades humanity and his awareness that ideas have bodies. So which
of the two do we call moral? asks Le Brun: Robespierre, for whom the end justifies
the means? Or Sade, showing that the means justify the end? (171). Le Brun
associates Robespierre with morality itself, although it would be more accurate to say
that he was merely hypocritical, or inconsistent, rather than being a representative of
morality as such. Le Brun appears to think that killing people for enjoyment is
morally superior, due to its honesty, than killing in the name of ideology. There is an
incompatibility here between the assertion that Sade is heroically beyond all morality,
on the one hand, and, on the other, the wish to show that Sade is morally superior,
through emphasising a single purported virtue- Sades honesty or life-affirmation.
More to the point, it is unclear how Le Brun can object to the violence of bourgeois
ideology, and consistently praise the erotic torture machines in Sade that
themselves reveal the nothingness of bodies (161). 51
Finally, Le Brun attributes the erotic with moral significance, or at least a
significance that overrides other values. Sade, for Le Brun, proposes a new scale of
values that ranks desire and the erotic at the pinnacle. She describes The 120 Days of
Sodom variously as a sumptuous banquet, shimmering like myriad rare pearls
slipping through the folds of night, and praises Sade for freeing eroticism from the
blinkering idea of beauty (88,188). The one passage she cites from 120 illustrates
what she means to be the erotic is as follows:
They leave the scalpel, they plunge into a hand, they search inside her bowels and force
her to shit through the cunt; then, through the same opening, they set about splitting the
wall of the stomach. Then they turn back to her face: they cut off her ears, burn the inside
50
51
One of Sades characters, a reader of Sade, in fact (he reads Philosophy in the Bedroom as he kills),
murders people with a guillotine. Accordingly, Le Bruns disjunction between the horrors depicted in
Sade and those of the Terror is problematic (LNJ 2:377-378).
49
of her nostrils and extinguish her eyes by pouring molten Spanish wax in them, they cut a
circle around the skull and hung her up by the hair while attaching stones to her feet, so
that her body is weighed down and the cranium torn off (74-75; similar: 193). 52
The reader can decide for oneself whether this could be taken to be a sumptuous
banquet. In any case, Le Bruns claim that Sade is not preoccupied with beauty is
actually inconsistent with the text. Sades brand of absolute horror requires an
acknowledgement of beauty in order to rail against it, or to soil it. States his character
Saint-Fond, [b]eauty [in a victim] tends to excite us further; virtue, innocence,
candour embellish the object...all these qualities tend to enflame us more (J: 270).
Sades works are full of clichd descriptions of feminine beauty; in Juliette, victims
are described variously as having the face of love with the most beautiful eyes
possible; never in my life had I feasted my eyes on a more beautiful body,
nothing so fresh, nothing so plump, nothing so pretty, radiant as an angel; Venus
herself would be envious, and so on (J: 1012, 1073, 1053, 1126, 1073).
Le Bruns discussion of Sade takes several other tangents, such as her proposal
that Sade is a critic of reason itself, that he exposes the fierceness of desire, that
he frees us from power relationships exercised by knowledge, and that he marks the
end of man (54, 60, 156). These Foucaultian avenues are not explored further in Le
Brun (such themes will be discussed later in this chapter and in Chapter VII).
This completes the survey of those who have interpreted, or treated, Sade as a
philosopher. Yet to be discussed is the view that Sades work is of some vital,
philosophical significance, yet cannot be approached as one would a philosophical
text. That is, the philosophical dimension of Sades work is considered a mere surface
feature, whether a part of a deeply subversive distortion, or secondary to some deeper
insight or project far removed from philosophical practice. This is the view of
Georges Bataille and Michel Foucault.
52
Even more bizarrely, Le Brun refers to the other passage cited here as showing erotic brutality,
despite the fact that it only concerns the spectacle of mass execution. It is apparently not sex that Le
Brun is interested in. The citation in Sade is 120: 658, 659.
50
53
Georges Bataille The Use Value of D.A.F.Sade (an open letter to my current comrades) trans.
Allan Stoekl, in David B. Allison, Mark S. Roberts and Allen S. Weiss, editors, Sade and the Narrative
of Transgression (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1995) pp.16-32. See also Michel Surya
Bataille: An Intellectual Biography trans. Krzysztof Fijalkowski and Michael Richardson (London and
New York: Verso; 2002) p.264.
51
particular Erotism (hereafter ER, 1957), the Accursed Share (hereafter AS, written
1949, published 1967) and Tears of Eros (hereafter TE, 1961). 54
Bataille shares with Sade a number of thematic preoccupations. Batailles
fictional work, in particular Story of the Eye, is similar to that of Sade to the point of
appearing derivative. As in Sade, in Bataille there is a great deal of scatology, sex
scenes in churches, blasphemy, humiliation, rape, torture, and necrophilia. 55 There are
also philosophical similarities, although these have often been exaggerated. The most
obvious theoretical commonality is in their ethical orientation. Sades view that
civilization and morals have softened man is close to Batailles attitude (J: 776). Both
writers draw a link between the absence of God and the nullity of morality, suggesting
a traditionally religious view of moral thought ( Batailles project of founding an
anti-ethics, without reason or justice, is explicitly a Godless ethics ). 56 Bataille
54
Georges Bataille Erotism: Death and Sensuality trans. Mary Dalwood (San Francisco: City Lights
Books, 1986)
.
Literature and Evil trans. Alaister Hamilton (New York and London: Marion
Boyars, 1997)
-.
Story of the Eye by Lord Auch trans. Joachim Neugroschel (San Francisco: City
The Tears of Eros trans. Peter Connor (San Francisco: City Lights Books, 1989)
The Accursed Share (in three volumes) trans. Robert Hurley (New York/ Zone
Evil in Platonism and Sadism trans. El Albert, in Deepak Sawhney, editor Must
In Batailles Novel Story of the Eye, for example, a scrumptious streetwalker from Madrid is raped
in a pigsty full of liquid manure, and the spectacle of a decapitated car crash victim- a young girl- is
described as very beautiful. In an outline for a sequel (set fifteen years after the original, placing the
action in 1943), the heroine accidentally finds herself in a torture camp and is beaten to death in a
scene Bataille describes as, again, very beautiful (SE: 5, 55,102). According to Batailles biographer
Michel Surya, in 1944 Bataille planned to make a pornographic film based on The 120 Days of Sodom.
The main character, a soap manufacturer, acts out scenes from Sades The 120 Days of Sodom with
some prostitutes, eventually killing one of them. See Surya p.349.
56
52
states that Sade took the mentality of the aristocracy to its limit under the pretence of
criticizing it (ER: 166). Bataille also notes that, though Sades work remains on the
fictional plane (ER: 175; AS Vol. II: 183) he stated his [principles] but never really
put them to practice (TE: 142). Bataille admires Sade for his nihilism and his total
disregard for his fellow man, and notes that he was a connoisseur of torture (ER:
171-172, 189; TE: 206). 57 Yet he also describes Sade as in some sense an ethical
figure. In Erotism, Bataille holds that, because violence is silent, Sades attitude is
diametrically opposed to that of the torturer (ER: 186, 252). The paragraph below
illustrates the tension in this account. Sade, for Bataille, represents both the attitude of
sovereignty that stands beyond concern for the fellow man, and the (assumedly)
moral attitude of the revolutionary.
He was an enemy of the ancien rgime and fought against itHe worked out his criticism
but he was a Jacobin and the secretary of a section. He worked out his criticism of the
past along two lines: on one he sided with the Revolution and criticized the monarchy, but
in the other he exploited the infinite possibilities of literature and propounded to his
readers the concept of a sovereign type of humanity whose privileges de Sade visualised
were outrageous compared with those [of] kings and lords (ER: 166).
For discussion of Batailles moral nihilism, see IE: 136; E: 171 AS I p.152-153; III: 370; 448 n37;
Bataille frequently dismisses traditional philosophers as system builders, babblers, insects and
careful little men (IE: xi, xxii, 14, 66) and reason itself as puerile (AS Vol. III p.256).
For explanations for Batailles mystic epistemology, see ER: 123, 149,162, 256; AS Vol. I: 58, 191.
53
thought highly, noting its incoherence and its lack of persuasive force (ER: 179,
188,191,195; AS Vol.II:177; LE: 110-111). Instead, Bataille associates Sade with his
own interest in the interrelationship of taboo, sacrifice, transgression, and sexuality.
Sade, largely informed by the 18th century philosophe tradition, was familiar with a
very different philosophical outlook, and lacked a concept of the sacred (as Sade
wrote in the poem La Vrit [1787], [i]l nest rien de sacr). 59 Bataille, like Sade,
describes life as endless flux and destruction, and holds that harmony would destroy
the natural order (ER: 55, 86; AS Vol. I p.23; Sade J: 768, 771). The ontological
similarities end there. Bataille, unlike Sade, holds that humans have a certain dignity,
a certain nobility and a sacred truth that distinguishes them from animals, whereas
(as to be discussed in Chapter II) Sade emphasises the continuity of humans and other
animals (ER: 29, 149,150). Further, unlike most of Sades libertines, Bataille
maintains that there is a soul that survives the physical annihilation of the body (I E:
19; Sade, J: 401). These differences have lead Michael Richardson to remark that,
whereas Bataille implicitly admits idealism, Sade was the materialist that Bataille
claimed to be, for his materialism was consistent and unyielding. 60
Another divergence between Sade and Bataille is their use of Christian sources.
Sades discussion of the Bible and other Christian texts betrays an encyclopaedic
knowledge of scripture and religious scholarship. Yet, unlike Bataille, his attitude
towards the Christian heritage is entirely negative, using his knowledge of Christian
sources purely order to discredit their doctrine. He would not, unlike Bataille, cite
the Saints or Christian religious art in defence of the claim that a womans body is
dirty, that sex leads to death, is basically sinful, or is linked with sex and sadism
(AS Vol. I: 38; ER: 230-231; TE: 83). 61
Throughout his writings, Bataille retains two psychological assumptions; a). there
is an innate human instinct for sadism; and b). This instinct for sadism is inseparable
from the sexual instinct. In defence of both of these associations, Bataille relies
59
La Vrit In uvres compltes du Marquis de Sade edited by Annie Le Brun and Jean-Jacques
Surrealism trans. Micheal Richardson (London and New York: Verso, 1994):1-27, p.19.
61
Nevertheless, Bataille insists that he is in fact free from Christian doctrine and, further, that there is
an indefinite and general taboo against sexual liberty as opposed to that associated with Christianity;
ER: 92.
54
largely on the authority of Sade. Sade, in The 120 Days of Sodom, Juliette and la
Nouvelle Justine in particular, insists that the taste for cruelty is shared by all with the
strength to express it, and typically describes heterosexual intercourse as ideally
involving rape, sadism and murder ( Writes Sade: [m]urder is a branch of erotic
activity, one of its extravagances; J:940). Like Sade, Bataille insists that all men
have a desire for violent, destructive behaviour. Bataille also notes the publics
universal taste for violence in the manifestation of barbaric activities in the most
sophisticated cultures (Bataille notes for example lynch law as practiced in the
United States; ER: 186). Bataille goes on to suggest that all people desire dangerous
and expensiveas he calls them sovereign, activities, in proportion to their
strengths and means, noting that most people must fulfil this need through the
imagination, in spy novels and suchlike ( ER: 72, 86-87, 186). Bataille also takes at
face value Sades contention that there is a natural association (Bataille calls is a
general mechanism) linking erection, ejaculation and breaking the law:
[i]ndependently of Sade, the sexual excitement of burglars has not escaped notice.
But no one before him had grasped the general mechanism linking the reflex actions
of erection and ejaculation with the transgression of the law (ER: 196; Sade J: 124).
The most important associations Bataille makes with his own thought and that of
Sade are those concerning sexuality. To a large extent, this association is apt. Neither
has a conception of sexual relationships as such, nor sexual love or mutual care. Sex is
described entirely in terms of the attainment of a sensation. Bataille occasionally
discusses more commonplace, though by no means less disturbing, associations of sex
and death, for example the association of sexual jealousy or possession (ER:20). But,
for the most part, Bataille does not seek to diagnose or explain such tendencies.
Instead, he describes violence as essential to sexual activity. Bataille holds that
[p]hysical erotism has in any case a heavy, sinister quality, that sexuality, when
taken to its natural limit, leads to murder, and that Sade was the great pioneer who
affirmed this truth (ER: 19; TE: 140). Bataille describes sex above all as a limitexperience, which, in general terms, involves the experience of merging with the
universe (AS Vol. II: 168,169,171). As filth, for Bataille, is the secret of being,
this does not in itself entail a positive account of sexuality (AS Vol. II: 118). It is
frequently the violence and disorder of sex that Bataille regards as of central
55
importance, rather than the sex itself. 62 As such, actions as torture may suffice to
attain this state also, insofar as such an activity would be both violent and nauseating.
The following passage, from Inner Experience (1943, published 1957), makes clear
this association of limit-experience independent of actual penetrative sex torture,
beating up ones spouse, or simply laughing may suffice.
The extreme limit of the possible We are there in the end. But so late?...what,
without knowing it we reached it? (in truth, nothing is changed) by a detour: one man
bursts out laughing, the other is goaded and beats his wife, we become dead drunk, we
make others perish in torture (IE: 37). 63
A recurring theme in Batailles discussion of Sade is the idea that the sovereign
invariably a male- plays the active role, whereas the female is described variously as a
victim or as sacrificial victim. To take sexuality to be concerned with communication
or harmony at all, according to Batailles Sade, is to deny its truth.
De Sade makes his heroes uniquely self-centred; the partners are denied any rights at all:
this is the key to his system. If erotism leads to harmony between the partners its essential
principle of violence and death is invalidated. Sexual union is fundamentally a
compromise, a half-way house between life and death. Communion between the
participants is a limiting factor and it must be ruptured before the true violent nature of
eroticism can be seen, whose translation into practice corresponds with the notion of the
sovereign man. The man subject to no restraints of any kind falls on his victims with the
devouring fury of a vicious hound (ER: 167; similar AS Vol.II:174-178)
Again, the male is in the active role, whereas the woman is dissolved. The two
sexually engaged people realize their discontinuity; they merge into the one entity.
Yet a non-symmetrical relationship remains- the male remains as an active subject;
the female loses her identity. 64
62
Paul Hegarty Georges Bataille: Core Cultural Theorist (London: SAGE Publications, 2000) pp.105-
106.
63
In The Story of the Eye, Bataille describes going beyond all limits as sucking the breast of a
girlfriend and simultaneously urinating in the presence of her mother. Story of the Eye p.39-40.
64
Critics of Bataille often describe his work as preoccupied with play and communion, as opposed
to total egotism and the treatment of the other as a mere victim of aggression. Roland Champagne
writes that [e]rotism for Bataille is an avenue of access into the playfulness of human sovereignty and
56
What does physical eroticism signify if not a violation of the very being of its
practitioners?A violation bordering on death, bordering on murder?
The whole business of erotism is to strike to the inmost core of the living being, so that
the heart stands still. The transition from the normal state to that of erotic desire
presupposes a partial dissolution of the person as he exists in the realm of discontinuity.
In the process of dissolution, the male partner has generally an active role, while the
female side is essentially the one that is dissolved as a separate entity (ER: 17-18).
Later in this same text, Bataille states that the woman is not fully alive when being
penetrated, suggesting that, were she to be killed during sex, she would not actually be
present. She is not merely sick; she is already dead. Bataille discusses the surprise a
person would feel, were he ignorant of the association between madness and
eroticism, if he were to watch some woman who had struck him as particularly
distinguished passionately making love.
He would think she was sick, just as mad dogs are sick. Just as if some mad bitch had
usurped the personality of the dignified hostess of a little while back. Sickness is not
putting it strongly enough, though; for the time being the personality is dead. For the time
being its death gives the bitch full scope, and she takes advantage of the silence, of the
absence of the dead woman. The bitch wallows-wallows noisily- in that silence and that
absence... (my italics; ER: 106).
On most of the points outlined above the association of sexuality with the desire to
kill the partner (the victim, in fact); the inauthenticity and inferiority of shared
erotic pleasure; the reduction of the other (typically a woman) to the level of inert
object- Bataille is quite correct in reading Sade as advocating much the same doctrine
(J: 268-269). In the passage above, like Sade, Bataille tends to conflate the living
with the dead- an erotics that denies the presence of the other person. It is,
essentially, masturbatory or even necrophilic, as neither Sade nor Bataille can
distinguish between sex with another person from merely penetrating a cadaver.
the abyss, an image crucial to Batailles literary art of death and anxiety. In similar terms, Micheal
Richardson writes: [w]hat is at stake in sex for Bataille is communication between two beings, and in
pushing sexuality to its limits, he wants to test to breaking point the emotional boundaries of the
personality of the man and the woman. Batailles treatment of Sade complicates this interpretation.
Roland A. Champagne Georges Bataille (New York: Twane Publishers, 1998) p.65; Richardson p.16.
57
Bataille briefly considers the possibility that only neurotics are attracted by the
thought of sexual murder, or that sadism is merely an atavistic throwback. In a section
of Erotism entitled Vice is the deep truth at the heart of man, Bataille writes:
It might be said that we wear our sadism like an excrescence which may once have
had a meaning in human terms but now has lost it, which can easily be eradicated at will,
in ourselves by asceticism, in others by punishment. This is how the surgeon treats the
appendix, the midwife the afterbirth, and the people their kings. Or are we concerned on
the contrary with a sovereign and indestructible element of mankind, yet one that evades
conscious appraisal? Are we concerned; in short, with the heart of man, not the muscular
organ, but the surge of feelings, the intimate reality that it symbolizes?
If the first of these alternatives holds, the reasonable man would be justified; man will
produce instruments for his own well-being indefinitely, he will subdue all nature to his
laws, he will be free from war and violence without having to heed the fateful propensity
which has hitherto bound him to misfortune. (ER: 184).
But Bataille rejects this interpretation, hence aligning himself with Sades account of
the human condition. Bataille reasons that sadism cannot be dismissed as a nonessential human trait, for two reasons. The first is that sadism brings humanity into
harmony with the ceaseless and inevitable annihilation of everything that is born,
58
grows, and strives to last. This principle is very similar to the naturalistic thinking of
Sades character Pope Pius VI, in Juliette, who reasons, In all living things the
principle of life is in no other than that of death; that is, as death and destruction are
part of the natural order, so too is the instinct to destroy (J:769). (Yet, in both Sade
and Bataille, this is an argument as to why destruction, not sadism per se, is a part of
the natural order). The second reason offered by Bataille is essentially a restating of
Batailles affirmation of destruction, and its association with the sacred and the
sovereign. This reasoning is uniquely Bataillian- Sade, as noted above, has no
concept of the sacred.
Secondly [sadism] bestows a kind of divine or, more accurately, sacred significance on
that excess and that harmony. Our desire to consume, to annihilate, to make a bonfire of
our resources, and the joy we find in the burning, the fire and the ruin are what seem to us
divine, sacred. They alone control sovereign attitudes in ourselves, attitudes that is to say
which are gratuitous and purposeless, only useful for being what they are and never
subordinated to ulterior ends (ER: 185). 65
Bataille also credits Sade for revealing a link between sexuality and a wish to destroy
oneself; this tormenting fact: the urge towards love, pushed to its limit, is an urge
towards death (ER: 42). (One could perceive here a hint of the Surrealists interest in
love, and sexuality, as a rendering asunder of the categories of the reasonable).
Besides appealing to the authority of Sade in defending this claim, Bataille cites
examples from natural history, of animals who expend themselves in coitus
(suggesting the danger of sex), the mystic insights of St. Theresa, and the association
of sex and death implicit in the French expression for orgasm, la petite mort (the
little death) (ER: 29,170, 234-240, AS: Vol. II: 105, 177; TE: 20). Bataille also notes
that childbirth is dangerous (although its relevance to the sex-self destruction
association is not clear) and that depression following the final spasm [of orgasm]
may give a foretaste of death (ER: 102, 232). Bataille takes the character Amlie (in
Juliette) to be representative of this association of sexuality with the will to self
destruction. Amlie, an impressionable young woman, tells Borchamps that she
wishes to be killed as the victim of the cruel passions of a libertine. She adds: [n]ot
that I wish to die tomorrow- my extravagant fancies do not go as far as that; but that is
65
Note that this argument does not actually concern sadism as such, but the destruction of objects.
59
the only way I want to die; to have my death the result of a crime is an idea that sets
my head spinning (ER: 175-176; similar; AC Vol.II:182). In Erotism, Bataille writes:
An impersonal denial, an impersonal crime!
Tending towards the continuity of beings beyond death!
De Sades sovereign man does not offer our wretchedness a transcendent realityBut in
[the character] Amlie de Sade links infinite continuity with infinite destruction.
(ER: 176). 66
Sades characters are extremely glib about life and death, so it is not possible to
dismiss Batailles interpretation out of hand (Durand, in Juliette, states that she once
avoided execution merely for forms sake; J: 1025). It is, however, problematic to
interpret Sade as a theorist of a universal death drive on the strength of a single minor
character in a single novel, who is given only twelve lines of a text of some 2,000
pages. As noted above, Le Brun has argued that Batailles assertion that eroticism
opens onto death contradicts fundamental aspects of Sades thought, observing that
the chief Sadeian characters do virtually anything in order to survive. 67 The character
Borchamps cited in the passage above thinks in fact that Amlie had not been sincere
in her desire to be killed: what she had told me about the way she wanted to end her
days, this, the more I pondered it, had simply been an effort on her part to be
ingratiating; it did not correspond to her real feelings (Amlie is killed in appalling
agony regardless; J: 876). The lesson to be drawn would seem to be that one should
be careful with what one agrees to when dealing with post-morality sophisticates. But
Annie Le Bruns criticism of Bataille is not entirely correct either- it could simply be
that Bataille has cited the wrong example. In Juliette, the character Durand contends
that sensual excitement may even bring on thoughts of death and induce in one an
eager expectancy of death, and Juliette herself suggests that death would be orgasmic
(J: 1014; 1039). 68 Sades characters also enjoy strangling or hanging themselves to
66
67
68
Juliettes argument is poor. She reasons that, as all of lifes necessities carry some element of
pleasure, and death is a necessity, then death must be pleasurable. Juliette states that it is common
knowledge that death is accompanied by a discharge, probably referring to the common knowledge
that a hanged man has an erection and ejaculates. This illustrates Sades understanding that female
60
enhance orgasm, and deliberately catch sexually transmitted diseases (LNJ2: 328,
340n, 344; J: 1147). 69 (Even Justine exhibits an eroticized death wish; she falls in
love with the evil Marquis de Brassac despite his depravity, and states that she would
gladly sacrifice her life to him; MV: 35). Sades characters, although perverse, do not
kill themselves in self- annihilating paroxysms as a rule.
A more complex theme in both Sade and Bataille is the relationship between
sexuality and sin. Bataille acknowledges that there is no such thing as obscenity in a
fundamental sense, accepting that it exists entirely in the mind(ER: 215). Batailles
work incessantly associates sex and sin nevertheless. His numerous comments on the
physical, sexualized body, on the sex act, on prostitutes, and childbirth suggests a
negative attitude concerning sexuality and the body in general, as does his obsession
with the filthy. Bataille describes sex as infernal, anguished, and disgusting, and
avoids discussing any particular sexual act. He describes prostitutes as fallen
beings, vomited forth from nature, who live like pigs (E: 135, 246; AS Vol. II:
140, 147,178). According to Bataille, nudity is, in a fundamental way, obscene, and
the sight of a womans breasts the pure incarnation of sin (ER: 17, AS Vol.I:5; IE:
127). The penis is variously described as accursed, as a larvae, and a bestiality
(ER: 138-139; SE: 74); semen as a type of excrement (UV: 21); the vagina as a
swampy region (SE: 21); or a wound about to suppurate (AS Vol. II: 130,149).
He writes of the womb as muck, and refers to the stench of the bodies of mothers
and sisters (SE: 49; AS Vol. II: 63). He describes the cycle of birth, sex and death a
shipwreck in the nauseous, and cites Leonardo da Vinci and St. Augustine to defend
this association of sexuality with disgust (TE: 23, 66, 69; ER: 58; 144-145; 178; AS
Vol.II:126; 81; 62-63 104). Even childbirth is described as a transgression:
orgasm, like that of men, is accompanied by a discharge. The idea that death could be sexually
exciting is one of the central themes of Nagisa Oshimas film the Realm of the Senses (1976).
69
La Mettrie, for whom death is not without a certain voluptuousness, may have had an influence on
Sade on this point. La Mettrie also wrote that he wished to die accompanied by beautiful women,
preferably while having sex- I want it to be difficult to say which contributed most to my end, Fate or
voluptuousness. Julien Offray De La Mettrie Machine Man and Other Writings translated and edited
by Ann Thomson (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1996) pp.107-108, 114). This image is
repeated in Sades Dialogue between a Priest and a Dying Man; PB: 175.
61
The menstrual discharge is further associated with sexual activity and the accompanying
suggestion of degradation: degradation is one of the effects of violence. Childbearing
cannot be disassociated from this complex of feelings. Is it not itself a rending process,
something excessive and outside the orderly course of permitted activity? Does it not
imply the denial of the established order, a denial without which there could be no
transition from nothingness to being, or from being to nothingness? There may well be
something gratuitous about these assessments (ER: 54).
With this outlook, Bataille must explain why anyone would want to have sex at
all. He gives three responses. Firstly, he holds that we express our true love for
someone by overcoming our nausea of the physical act of having sex (AS Vol.II:9596, 113). 70 Secondly, Bataille suggests that every horror conceals a possibility of
enticement (AS Vol. II: 96). This claim becomes problematic however, as Bataille
cannot explain why corpses are not sexually attractive (AS Vol.II:97). 71
Finally, for Bataille it is the very sinfulness of sexual activity that makes it
significant. Without the sin of breaking taboos, according to Bataille, sex is not
erotic. Therefore, sex within marriage, where there are no traditional taboos against
sex, is not erotic; marriage itself providing only a narrow outlet for pent-up violence
(ER: 109- 112). Batailles affirmation of the sinfulness of sex, rather than sex in and
of itself, is clearest in the introduction to his pornographic novel Madame Edwarda.
In this text, Bataille lambastes against freethinkers who would seek to eradicate
sexual sinfulness (ER: 17, 128, 135, 266).
Batailles work suggests a commonality with Sade that overcomes the overt
theoretical differences of the two thinkers. On the one hand, Batailles association of
sex with sin seems to have little in common with the stated views of Sades
characters. Sade, in particular in Philosophy in the Bedroom and Juliette, writes
repeatedly on the groundlessness of sexual prudery. Accordingly, he refers to
70
The proof of love theory does not really explain why anyone would want to show their love
though overcoming their physical revulsion with sex. One could show ones goodwill or even love by
cleaning or unblocking a friends toilet, but this is done for the benefit of having a toilet that works and
is clean. In Batailles scheme, there is no parallel function to sex, as it is not pleasurable as such. In any
case, the lack of fit with psychological reality hardly requires comment.
71
Sade discusses the piquancy of sex with hideously ugly people in The 120 Days of Sodom, but his
theory is based on a comparatively straightforward theory of pleasure (120: 233). Bataille discusses
necrophilia in le Mort. See Bataille Madame Edwarda, Le Mort, Histoire de lil (in one volume)
(Paris: Collection 10:18, 1973).
62
72
Bataille makes a single reference to coprophilia, in the novel Le bleu du Ciel (Paris: Jean-Paul
For discussion of the absence of vaginal penetration in Bataille, see Paul Hegarty Georges Bataille:
Edmond and Jules de Goncourt (1860) and J.K.Huysmans (1885) regarded Sades apparent hatred of
the body as a symptom of Catholic atavism. For discussion, see Laugaa-Traut pp. 147,165; Herbert
Josephs Sade and Woman: Exorcising the Awe of the Sacred in Studies in Burke and his Time 18
(177): 99-113 pp.102, 104, 111. In La Nouvelle Justine, Sade does indeed refers to the excrables
chairs (execrable flesh) of his characters victims (LNJ 2: 73).
63
violence. They take the perverse for the ideal, and the natural (specifically the
instinct for mutual care, and for reproduction) for the perverse.
On this theme, it can be argued that Batailles intuitive method, his sweeping
claims and juxtapositions, discloses aspects of Sades thought that a more scholarly,
textual approach would miss. Bataille places Sade in the context of the Occult, in the
shadows cast by Christianity, rather than in the light of the Enlightenment. Bataille
writes that, in pre-Christian societies, passions were unleashed and taboos temporarily
lifted in particular ritualistic contexts, which allowed for the controlled release of
psychic forces. In Erotism, Bataille writes that [t]ransgression in pre-Christian
religions was relatively lawful; piety demanded it (ER: 126). Under Christianity, the
possibility of transgression is no longer sanctioned; it is made evil, and the ritual
transgressions are transformed into Christianitys imagined other- the Witchs
Sabbath and its attendant horrors. Writes Bataille, [i]maginary or not, the stories of
the Sabbaths mean something; they are the dream of a monstrous joy. The books of de
Sade expand these tales; they go much further but still in the same direction (ER:
127). On the face of it, this association is questionable. There are no positive
references to witchcraft or other superstitious beliefs in Sades surviving works, and a
number of explicit rejections. In the short story An Inexplicable Affair Vouched for by
an Entire Province, Sade writes of feeble-minded people who believe that they can
summon the prince of darkness through strange rituals (MV: 170). In the same
Enlightenment spirit, a character in Aline et Valcour criticises supernatural beliefs (an
astrologer and voyant who exploits the gullibility of his clients; AV: 523).
Nevertheless, insofar as it brings to light the relationship between the notion of sin
and Christianity in Sades work, Batailles association is illuminating. As Nietzsche
noted, Eros and sin were associated by Christianity: Christianity gave Eros poison to
drink - he did not die of it, to be sure, but degenerated into vice. 75 The implication
here is that Bataille and Sades association of sexuality and sin is an artefact of the
Christian age. Both Sade and Bataille frequently return to it in their work, despite
avowals to the contrary.
According to Batailles general economics, any system (the biosphere, or a
nation, for example) receives more energy than it can expend in simply maintaining
75
Friedrich Nietzsche Beyond Good and Evil trans. R.J. Hollingdale with an introduction by Michael
64
itself. Bataille holds that the supply of energy available is endless, owing to the output
of the sun, and that growth is limited only by the roundness of the earth. 76 Part of the
excess has to be expended, whether destroyed or lost without profit (it is not clear if
Bataille is offering a descriptive or prescriptive thesis; insofar as he extrapolates from
an is to an ought about how the worlds works, his theory appears to commit a
straightforward naturalistic fallacy). 77 Bataille discusses this spending in terms of
luxury or sovereign spending, yet his use of language suggests that it is not a
straightforward economic model. He associates this sovereign economics to
erotism itself taken to be a spending of resources the sacred, in turn defined in
terms of overturning taboos, and to the notion of sacrifice, in particular human
sacrifice. In turn, as noted above, Bataille associates sexuality with human sacrifice.
Sade takes a central place in Batailles association of spending, sadism, violence, and
eroticism, and implies rather than directly imposes these associations onto Sades
work. In Erotism, Bataille writes that Sade does not formulate the principle of
wasteful expenditure, but he implies them by asserting that pleasure is more acute if
it is criminal and the more abhorrent the crime the greater the pleasure (ER: 169;
see also AS Vol. I: 23).
[Erotism] demands a boundless energy which, stopping at nothing, limits the destruction.
In its ordinary form, it is the vice to which physicians gave the name sadism; in its
reasoned, doctrinaire form, elaborated by the Marquis de Sade himself in the interminable
solitude of the Bastille, it is the pinnacle, the fulfilment of limitless eroticismeroticism
responds to mans determination to merge with the universe (Batailles italics) (AS Vol.
II: 168).
Bataille here assumes both an innate instinct for destruction, and that such destruction
is associated with a will to unify with the cosmos. The following passage, from the
same discussion, is more problematic.
76
Geoffrey Bennington Introduction to Economics I In Bailey Gill, Caroline, ed. Bataille: Writing
the Sacred (London and New York: Routledge, 1995): 46-57, p.49.
77
Where Bataille- paradoxically- offers reasons as to why one should spend excessively, his goals
seem reasonable. For example, Bataille held that the extravagant spending of resources would prevent
wars. Bataille had not considered the opposite claim- that wars are frequently brought about by
competition for scarce resources or territory. See Bennington Introduction to Economics I p.50.
65
De Sades doctrine is nothing more nor less that the logical consequence of these
moments that deny reason. By definition, excess stands outside reason. Reason is bound
up with work and the purposeful activity that incarnates its laws. But pleasure mocks at
toil, and toil we have seen to be unfavourable to the pursuit of intense pleasure. (E: 168;
similar: AS Vol.II:180)
Bataille makes the following assumptions here and elsewhere: a). Sade is concerned
with excess; b). excess stands outside of reason; c). reason is bound up with
purposeful activity and toil; d). hence Sade is not concerned with reason. The first
assumption- that Sade stands for excess, is sound, to a point (in La Nouvelle Justine,
the character Madame dEsterval remarks, que serait la volupt sans excs?; LNJ
2:107), as is the association of Sade with destruction and limit experience. In Sade,
there are numerous descriptions of ruinous luxury, wastage and excess. Juliette
features elaborately staged orgies that follow the roughly the same plan. There is a
description of the scene, in Baroque style, detailing the drapery, the bouquets and so
on, accounts of the types of food and drink, the table settings; the costumes worn by
the libertines and those to be raped and killed. The action moves on to frenzied
rutting, the participants and their victims dissolving into a single mass of flesh.
Finally, the scene is laid waste- dead and injured victims and animals are piled high,
and the pyre- described variously as the Greek sacrifice or holocaust- is lit
( J:240-241, 585, 873, 747, 963-965, 1112, 1178; 120: 672). Sade, like Bataille,
discusses the sublime of the spectacle of destruction, and his characters express the
will to become volcanoes, that is, pure agents of destruction (Bataille IE:125; Sade
LNJ2:43-45; J: 522, 1016-1018). Although Sade did not discuss mystic or alternate
states of consciousness in his work, as Bataille implies (LE: 115-116, 119), his
characters indeed speak of the attainment of the greatest possible upheaval in the
nervous system, and the final limit of what our human faculties can endure (J:
340). Transgression and the overcoming of restraints through ultimately murderous
acts are clearly a commonality between the two thinkers. Yet there are other aspects
of Sades work that elude Batailles general economy. In particular, Batailles
opposition of reason, purposefulness and toil, on the one hand, and pleasure, the
sovereign, and the cessation of thought, on the other, is problematic (the relationship
between pleasure and reason in Sade will be more fully discussed in Chapter III).
Here I will note that Batailles association of Sade with excess is problematic, and
66
suggest that Sades accounts of economics, and pleasure, are very different to those of
Bataille.
Sades characters, in particular in Juliette, are certainly concerned with
destruction and chaos on a large scale, and spending their resources in pointlessly
extravagant ways. Although they appear to reason in terms of utility, their
rationalizations are quite clearly just that- rationalizations. Where they offer reasons
as to why the poorer regions of Rome should be torched, or the entire Catholic
population of France should be killed, the reasons offered- usually the pretext of the
health of the nation- are frequently revealed to be secondary to the urge to destroy
(J:499-501, 726). A dialogue in Juliette, between Chigi and Olympia, illustrates this
deep complicity between the two thinkers. Chigi, in attempting to rationalize his call
for universal anarchy, makes the following claim:
I grant you that without laws the sum of crime increases, that without laws the world turns
into one great volcano belching forth an uninterrupted spew of execrable crimes; and I tell
you this situation is preferable, far preferable to what we have at present (J:732).
Likewise, in the essay The Use Value of D.A.F. Sade, Bataille calls for a total
overturning of the established moral order, and describes Sade as the figurehead of
such a revolution. His rationale, like Sades in the passage above, is that total chaos is
preferable to the present situation- the crushing...yoke of morality (UV: 27).
Without a profound complicity with natural forces such as violent death, gushing blood,
sudden catastrophes and the horrible cries of pain that accompany them, terrifying
ruptures of what had seemed to be immutable, the fall into stinking filth of what had been
elevated- without a sadistic understanding of an incontestably thundering and torrential
nature, there could be no revolutionaries, there could only be a revolting utopian
sentimentality.
[s]ince it is true that one of a mans attributes is the derivation of pleasure from the
suffering of others, and that erotic pleasure is not only the negation of an agony that takes
place at the same instant but also a lugubrious participation in that agony, it is time to
choose between the conduct of cowards afraid of their own joyful excesses, and the
conduct of those who judge that any given man need not cower like a hunted animal, but
instead can see all the moralistic buffoons as so many dogs (UV: 29, 30).
67
Here the similarity is clear- both Sades Chigi and (the early, pre-World War II)
Bataille call for total surrender to a purported human potential for complete chaos and
destruction, on the grounds that such disorder is morally right as morality,
commonly understood, is oppressive. Both essentially argue that morality should be
abandoned, on allegedly moral grounds. Sades characters do not propose a way out
of this impasse, yet are apparently aware of a deeper structure at work. On several
occasions in the text of Juliette, Sades characters note that irrational forces are
responsible for the doctrines proposed (Noirceuil, notes Juliette, has few peers where
it comes to constructing rational bases to ones irrational extravagances ;J: 139).
Likewise, Saint-Fond suggests that Juliettes vaunted atheism is grounded on nothing
more than personal taste, or some cognitive error:
Profoundly an atheist, I [Juliette] replied, arch enemy of the dogma of the souls
immortality, I will always prefer your system to Saint-Fonds, and I prefer the certitude of
nothingness to the fear of an eternity of suffering.
There you are, Saint-Fond rejoined, always that perfidious egoism which is the
source of all the mistakes human beings make. One arranges ones schemes according to
ones tastes and whims, and always by drifting farther from truth. Youve got to leave
your passions behind when you examine a philosophical doctrine (my italics; J: 401).
Hence, Sades work coheres, although not in a straightforward way, with the notion of
an unreason that, for Bataille, in some sense lies beneath or outside of reason. Sades
characters tastes and whims, in this text, usually involve the desire to destroy and
kill. As such, he notes the ease with which the most malignant urges can present
themselves to the council of reason. Insofar as Bataille takes Sade to see in man an
innate, irrational drive for destruction, and that reason plays a secondary causative
role in human activity that leads to such destruction, his interpretation is correct.
Batailles adoption of Sade is less accurate with regards to his economic theory,
however. According to Batailles general economy, the economics of scarcity,
concerned with utility, is a denial of the vitality of life. Bataille holds that societies
produce more than required, and their defining operation, rather than their modes of
accumulation, is exuberant spending; the purposeless destruction of resources (AS
Vol. I: 23). Yet it is straightforward to read Sade as the opposite of Batailles
characterisation.
68
69
the destructive principle of the world, but Sades characters, and their societies, are
equally concerned with the simple acquisition of pleasure, and with fiscal stability.
With regards to other interpretations of Sade under consideration, it should be noted
that Batailles outlook has points of contact with that of Adorno and Horkheimer,
moral views excepted. Like Adorno and Horkheimer, Bataille is critical of what he
considers the superficiality of contemporary thought, and, in similar tones, writes of
modern thought as having reduced itself to banality, to the belief in machines
(IE:28). Bataille also associates the Nazi death camps with the government of
reason. In keeping, seemingly, with Adorno and Horkheimers negative dialectics,
Bataille places the Holocaust and Hiroshima squarely in a historical dialectic. In a
review of Sartres Rflexions sur la question juive, Bataille writes: comme les
Pyramides ou lAcropole, Auschwitz est le fait, est le signe de lhomme. Limage de
lhomme est insparable, dsormais, dune chambre gaz (B Vol. XI: 226). 78 If
one does not hold, like Bataille, that Sades killers are opposed to the exercise of
reason in their killing, his interpretation of the Shoah approaches that of Adorno and
Horkheimer. As Sade, according to Bataille, is opposed to legalized, orderly killing
(clearly, not killing per se), Bataille takes it to be an error to associate Sade with the
atrocities of the Nazis. In a lecture given in 1947, Bataille states that the definition
of evil given in Philosophy in the Bedroom is the profound condemnation of
everything that we have seen the Germans do. Because it is clear that compared to the
executions of the Terror that Sade contemplated in Philosophy in the Bedroom, Nazi
executions responded still more to the images, to the suggestions of Sade. 79 But also,
they responded continually to the fundamental objection that Sade made to the
executions of the Terror since, from beginning to end, the unchaining of the passions
that raged at Buchenwald or Auschwitz was an unchaining that was the government of
Reason (EPS: 253-254, also 244; similar AS Vol.III:253). Interestingly, in this very
statement, Bataille states that there is a direct relationship- that the Nazis had
responded to Sade, itself a claim that goes even further than that of Camus or
78
For discussion of Batailles thoughts on Hiroshima revealing a new morality, see Surya pp. 360-
There are no Terrors or executions actually described in Bedroom, although there are allusions to the
Terror in the inserted pamphlet, Yet Another Effort, Frenchmen, If You Would Become Republicans.
Bataille may also be referring to the executions that Sade witnessed during the Terror, which took place
as Sade was writing this text.
70
Adorno and Horkheimer in associating Sade with Nazism. (Whether or not Sades
characters are entirely passionate killers, as Bataille insists, or more closely
resemble the Nazis, is a question to be answered in Chapter VII).
In conclusion, there are two related problems with Batailles merge with Sade.
Firstly, Batailles interpretation is informed by only one principle text, The 120 Days
of Sodom, and his comments on other texts are cursory. Batailles interpretation
misses Sades complexity. His reading is not incorrect as such; it merely fails to
acknowledge a number of basic contradictions, or juxtapositions, within Sades work.
There are a number of other generally un-Bataillian suggestions in Sades work,
suggesting that any monolithic interpretation is incorrect. Sades narrative voice
describes St. Peters as a wastage of talent and resources, and criticizes duelling,
dismissing it as a revolting anachronism. Additionally, his philosopher- king, Zam,
rejects state execution precisely because it is merely a secular version of human
sacrifice rituals, based, as they were, on the absurd supposition that there is nothing
more dear to the Gods than human blood (J: 657, 948; AV: 332).
The second problem with Batailles relationship with Sade is that he (and his
critics) reduces Sade to the status of esteemed but superseded antecedent of himself;
someone who knew nothing about the basic interrelation of taboo and
transgressionbut [who] took the first step. (ER: 196). 80 Nevertheless, Batailles
interpretation can be said to reveal a deeper animus within Sades text that goes
beyond the myriad contradictions at the surface level of meaning.
Roland A. Champagne, for example, writes that Bataille projects Sades insights farther than could
be seen in the Eighteenth century. Ronald A. Champagne Georges Bataille (New York: Twane
Publishers, 1998) p.25.
81
James Miller The Passion of Michel Foucault (Cambridge, Massachusetts: Harvard University Press,
2000) p.108; David Macey The Lives of Michel Foucault (New York: Vintage, 1995) p.76.
71
some critics suggesting that Foucaults interpretation owes more to these critics than
Sade himself. 82 Both Foucault and Bataille take Sade to stand radically outside the
dominant streams of his culture; that he represents, in some sense, a dialectical,
occulted other, a deeper truth, omitted from the ordinary understanding of humanity.
Whereas Bataille discusses Sade in terms of sovereignty and the sovereign man,
Foucault refers to Sade in relation to the Unreason and of mans unacknowledged
twin. Also, both thinkers assign to Sade the role of expressing desire in a radical
way. Whereas Sade, for Bataille, represents desire as physical, sexualized violence,
Foucault understands Sades desire as a literary phenomenon.
We have already seen a bewildering range of interpretations of Sades work, many
of which are incompatible. Foucaults reading, to some extent, notes that Sade had
taken ideas from the discourses of his age, yet places Sade far outside the categories
of official discourse. As such, Foucaults reading, unlike those already discussed, has
the merit of being consistent with the inconsistency and excesses of Sades work, and
of suggesting that the entire project of reading Sade as an ideologist or philosopher in
a fixed, stable sense may be simply incorrect.
Foucault gives three interpretations of Sade, two of which overlap. In Madness
and Civilisation (hereafter MC, 1961) Sade appears as a representative of the shadowside of human nature, locked away by new forms of control and classification. In the
essays Language to Infinity (hereafter LI, 1963) Prface a la transgression (1963)
and in The Order of Things (hereafter OT, 1966), Foucault discusses Sade as a
primarily literary phenomenon, yet links this interpretation with the previous
reading. 83 Finally, in an interview given to the film magazine Cinmatographe in
1975, Sade, sergeant of Sex (hereafter SS), Foucault gives an entirely different
interpretation Sade, Foucault concedes, could be taken to be the very representative
of the forms of institutional control, rather than its opposite. 84 Sade is also mentioned
82
83
Macey p.113.
Michel Foucault The Order of Things (London: Routledge, 1994).
Madness and Civilization trans. Richard Howard (New York: Vintage, 1988).
84
Michel Foucault Sade, Sergeant of Sex an interview conducted by G. Dupont, trans. Robert J.
72
Hurley, in Aesthetics, Method, and Epistemology: essential works of Michel Foucault vol. 2 ed. James
D. Faubion. Paul Ranibow (London: Penguin, 1998):223-227. This originally appeared as
Sade sergent du sexeCinmatographe 16 (Dec.1975): 3-5. I thank Tim Rayner for bringing this
text to my attention.
85
Michel Foucault The Will to Knowledge: History of Sexuality vol.1 trans. Robert Hurley (Penguin,
1998).
The Use of Pleasure: History of Sexuality vol.2 trans. Robert Hurley (Penguin, 1992).
The Care of the Self: History of Sexuality vol.3 trans. Robert Hurley (Penguin, 1990).
86
Michel Foucault Discipline and Punish: The Birth of the Prison. trans. Alan Sheridan (New York:
Vintage, 1995).
87
George Canguilhem The Death of Man, or the Exhaustion of the Cogito trans. Catherine Porter. In
The Cambridge Companion to Foucault. ed. Gary Gutting (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press,
1994) p.326. See also MC: 76-78.
73
In Sades calm, patient language, the final words of unreason are collected
together; an irrepressible psychic force that emerges into the world through a
sovereign discourse that runs counter to that of the voice of reason (MC: 188,198,
282; OT: 336). The Classical period had stored, within an enormous reservoir of the
fantastic, a memory of its own opposites; madmen, libertines, invalids; a dormant
memory of abstract unreason, transmitted intact from the sixteenth to the nineteenth
century (MC: 209). Whereas sadism itself, notes Foucault, is as old as the world,
the transformation of language into a discourse of desire is concurrent with the work
of Sade, and hence, the beginning of literature.
Sadism appears at the very moment that unreason, confined for over a century and
reduced to silence, reappears, no longer as an image of the world, no longer as a figura,
but as language and desire. And it is no accident that sadism, as an individual
phenomenon bearing the name of a man, was born of confinement and, within
confinement, that Sades entire oeuvre, is dominated by the images of the Fortress, the
Cell, the Cellar, the Convent, the inaccessible Island which thus form, as it were, the
natural habitat of unreason (MC: 209-210).
74
Sade is taken to be the bridge at which discourse and desire - that which is
unknowable to reason and discourse- intersect. Sades writing, rather than as a means
of transparent communication, is used to communicate something, paradoxically,
beyond communication, yielding a literature that is the very negation of the very
function of classical discourse, which seeks to represent. The impossibility of
expressing desires unreason by means of languages representative properties forces
other techniques. It is, instead, the force of accumulation and combination of scenes in
Justine and Juliette that allow the possibilities of desire to rise to the surface, from
the depths below (OT: 210-211). This interpretation of Sade is again similar to that of
Bataille, who perceived in the very repetitiveness of Sades work its meaning: due to
the decision to subordinate literature to the expression of an inexpressible
event...[b]oredom seeps from the monstrosity of Sades work, but it is this very
boredom which constitutes its significance (TE:115-116). It is also similar to
Batailles idea of excess as revealing the limits of the established order. For Foucault,
it is the excess of Sades discourse that reveals the limits of the classical episteme.
Foucault goes on to characterise Sades work as a manifestation of the precarious
balance between the law without desire and the meticulous ordering of discursive
representation:
Here, the order of discourse finds its Limit and its Law; but it is still strong enough to
remain coextensive with the very thing that governs it.the libertine is he who, while
yielding to all the fantasies of desire and to each of its furies, can, but also must, illumine
their slightest movement with a lucid and deliberately elucidated representation. There is
a strict order governing the life of the libertine: every representation must be immediately
endowed with life in the living body of desire, every desire must be expressed in the pure
light of a representative discourse (OT: 209).
Foucaults account holds that a). Sades work incorporates elements from other texts
and discourses, and yet b). stands radically outside all other discourses. Literature
differs from classical discourse in that it abandons the idea of language as a
transparent or pure medium of communication, and which turns in on itself, much as
modern art began with the surrender of paintings purely illusory role to
75
Sean D. Kirkland The Spectre of Literature in Foucaults The Order of Things, Henry Street: a
John Johnston "Discourse as Event: Foucault, Writing and Literature," Modern language Notes 105
See Roland Barthes Inaugural Lecture at the Collge de France, 7 January 1977 trans. Richard
Howard. Richard Kearney and Mara Rainwater, eds, The Continental Philosophy Reader (London:
Routledge, 1996) :364-377
91
Maurice Blanchot The Work of Fire trans. Charlotte Mandell (Stanford: Stanford University Press,
1995) p.106, quoted in Gerald L. Bruns Maurice Blanchot: The refusal of Philosophy (Baltimore &
London: The Johns Hopkins University Press, 1997) pp.41, 43.
76
tissue, and through their uncontrolled growth, they kill the organism within which
they live, of which they are a part of, even as they are nourished by it. Cancer, for
Blanchot, destroys the very idea of a program, blurring the exchange and the
message... one of... the ways to dislocate the system, [is] to disarticulate, through
proliferation and disorder, the universal programming and signifying power. 92
Sades endless repeatings of everything that had been and will ever be said are an
insubordination of the discourse that seeks towards its annihilation.
As noted above, and as following chapters of this study will show, almost every
individual element of Sades literature and philosophy can be traced to a particular
source text (Foucault himself notes that Sade had assembled his work from, among
other things, heavy borrowings from Rousseau; MC:283). Yet there is still something
that eludes the attempt to dismiss Sade as merely an eccentric plagiarist. Sades work,
in particular the texts with philosophical themes, frequently inverts the intended moral
ideals of the philosophers he has borrowed from, in particular the philosophes. He
scathingly notes the shortcomings of the moral philosophies of the age, and he fills his
works with mutually incompatible theories. Detailed analysis of Sades text reveals a
constant pattern of deliberate, perhaps malicious, ideological juxtapositions (i.e.
women are equals vs. women are inferior; nature guides conduct vs. nature does not
guide conduct; crime is pleasurable vs. crime does not exist). Sades work is also,
plainly, an artifact of an incessant desire to say everything- everything that the
dominant discourses of the time refused to confront. Sades encyclopaedia of
inhuman practices, insofar as it has a single significance at all, is not straightforward
(J: 1130). There is, therefore, something unnerving to Sades work that Foucaults
interpretation captures. 93 Foucault suggests that Sade is writing about language; its
limits, and its possible roles outside discourse. In deliberately writing a text that
enfolds all possible discourses, all philosophies, all thoughts- thinkable and very
nearly unthinkable-; and regurgitates them up as an uninterrupted stream of atrocities,
Sade did not merely corrupt the idea of the author as unifying principle. Foucault
92
Maurice Blanchot Lcriture du dsastre (Paris: ditions Gallimard, 1980) p.137. Quoted in Bruns
pp.30-31
93
Sade occasionally refers to the limits of language usage and the way in which language encodes
moral categories, and his own word usage is often highly idiosyncratic (the sublime for Sade typically
involves the highly vulgar or horrific, for example). See J: 418.
77
implies that Sade has reduced thought itself - ethics, metaphysics, the lot- to
meaningless babble, to rubble.
Three questions are- is this how Sades text actually functions? Which texts does
Sade invert, and at what level of meaning does the inversion take place? Is it a
knowing, sophisticated inversion of values, principles and theoretical meanings, or
merely a game played with sense and meaning? And, if so, is it a successful strategy?
A thorough exegesis of Sades work is required to answer these questions. Foucaults
account poses several other questions. What this language of desire amounts to, and
what it may suggest concerning understanding Sade, requires elaboration. Also
requiring discussion is Foucaults assumption of an opposition of two entities; the
Sadeian text and the official discourse, variously framed as an opposition between
classical discourse and that of literature, of sovereign discourse and the voice of
reason. There is also an assumed opposition in Foucaults discussion between
desire and reason. I will suggest that the field of vectors, as Foucault would put
it, is more complex than his account suggests.
In Madness and Civilization, Foucault places Sade firmly within the context of the
Great Confinement. He writes in particular of Sades cell as the natural habitat of
Unreason (MC: 210) and identifies him with error, illusion, dreams and madness,
and all that is unaccounted for by Descartes (OT: 323). 94 But Foucaults association
of Sade with the mad is not straightforward, and there is some doubt as to whether
Sade was himself a part of the Great Confinement of the unemployable, the
libertines, invalids, and the insane. Sade was not, initially, one of the population
Foucault describes as without resources or social moorings he was an aristocrat with
property, and who had served with a certain distinction in the military. Nor was he
particularly unemployable. Sade proved himself a highly versatile employee when
necessary, as evidenced by his successful (insofar as he, an aristocrat, survived it)
political career during the Terror. Nor was he treated like an animal, as Foucault
describes the mad in Madness and Civilisation. Once in prison (at least, until
Napoleon), he was treated as a member of his class and was envied by other prisoners
for his privileges. It would be ironic if Foucault were to classify Sade as mad in the
strictly clinical sense, given that only psychiatrists such as Iwan Bloch and Jacobus
94
Sade, given his admiration for Descartes, may well have found this statement perplexing (AV: 712).
78
X have classified Sade as such. 95 Sade certainly fits into the grey zone of those
diagnosed with derangement of morals (MC: 66). But Foucault does not describe
Sade as mad in this sense. He notes, in Madness and Civilisation, that Sade was
described by an unnamed official as a dreadful lunatic who wrote in order to
corrupt the time to come; elsewhere, he describes Sade as not suffering from an
organic madness (MC:228; 202; also Sergeant of Sex, hereafter SS, p.225). Rather,
Foucault describes Sade as standing outside of the dictates of social control and of
official designations of the socially acceptable. More specifically, Sade is associated
with a discourse which is beyond the dictates of official discourse.
In the preface of Madness and Civilization, Foucault associates Sades Juliette
with Thrasymachus and Callicles (MC: xi-xii). 96 This association may hold the key to
understanding what, in Foucaults dialectic, Sade represents. In the Socratic
dialogues, Thrasymachus (Republic) and Callicles (Gorgias) both argue against
Socrates on the nature and validity of moral principles. Both reject Socrates defence
of morality, and for this insolence in the face of officially approved philosophical
discourse, they are reduced to infuriated silence. In Sade, writes Foucault, vengeful
destruction
...is only the first phase of Sades thought: the ironic justification, both rational and
lyrical, the gigantic pastiche, of Rousseau. Beyond this demonstration-by-absurdity of the
inanity of contemporary philosophy beyond all its verbiage about man and nature, the real
decisions are still to be made: decisions that are also breaks, in which the links between
man and his natural being disappear
The famous Society of the Friends of Crime, the project of a Swedish constitution,
once we remove their stinging references to the Social Contract and to the proposed
constitutions for Poland or Corsica, establish nothing but the sovereign vigour of
subjectivity in the rejection of all liberty and all natural equality (MC: 283). 97
95
Dr. Iwan Bloch Marquis de Sade his life and works (Marquis de Sade: Der Mann Und Seine Zeit)
trans. James Bruce (New York: Castle Books, 1948); Dr. Jacobus X*** Le Marquis de Sade et son
uvre (Paris : Charles Carrington, 1901). Both names are nom de plumes.
96
Jean Deprun notes that Sade may well have known of Platos Gorgias (hence Callicles), and that
there was available to Sade an excellent translation of Gorgias, by one P. Grou. See Jean Deprun Sade
devant la Rgle dor In Corrado Rosso, Carminella Biondi, eds. La qute du bonheur et lexpression
de la douleur dans la littrature et la pense franaises (Genve: Droz, 1995): 307-311, p.309.
97
Foucault associates the Society of the Friends of Crime (which forbids its members from interfering
with politics) with a Swedish Masonic conspiracy, which confuses two different episodes in the novel
Juliette.
79
The madness of Sade, for Foucault, is not madness at all, but the sovereign refusal to
take the dogmas of traditional philosophy seriously, in particular the call to keep the
appetites in check, and the doctrine of the harmony of reason with morality. The
Western canon, on this view, confines to the category of the un-reason and
madness every viewpoint that rejects morality, just as Socrates rhetorically reduces
Thrasymachus to spluttering and coughing. Sade, then, is identified with an ancient
lineage of anti-moralists; the dialectical other of Western thought, present since its
very inception. The association in the passage above with the Society of the Friends of
Crime, the secret society featured in the novel Juliette, is also significant. When
Socrates asks Thrasymachus how he would plan to live a life beyond the constraints
of the law, he replies that it would be necessary to form secret societies. 98 On this
reading, Foucaults Sade is similar to that of Crocker, insofar as he takes Sades voice
to be a voice in a sense acknowledged by the philosophical literature itself.
Thrasymachus is an early instance of the imagined opponent of the philosopher who,
realizing the possibility of denying morality, seeks to defend it. Socrates had
Thrasymachus, Voltaire had his Fox, Kant had those who dismiss all morality as the
mere phantom of the imagination. Sade, in taking the place of this imagined opponent,
continues this discourse, as it were, from the other side.
Even if we grant Foucault a very broad conception of the mad, and assume that
the unreason incorporates the reasoned counter-morality of Thrasymachus, there is
still the issue of Sades placement in relation to other discursive practices.
Foucaults rigid dichotomy of reason, philosophy and official discourse, on the one
hand, and incarceration, madness, and refusal of official discourse, on the other, does
not acknowledge the plurality of discourses in Sades period. If we assume, like
Foucault, that Sades work stands apart as a discourse of its own, it can be said that
there are at least two other discourses besides official philosophical discourse; the
libertin discourse, and the philosophe discourse. The dominant, official philosophical
discourse of 18th Century France was dominated by Catholic thought. As such, it was
largely confined to doctrinal disputes, such as that between the Jansenists and Jesuits.
The philosophes, in particular La Mettrie, Diderot, dHolbach, and Helvtius,
constitute a different discourse altogether. These thinkers, tending towards
98
Plato The Republic trans. Desmond Lee (London: Penguin, 1987) p.112.
80
materialism and atheism, were a small, radical minority, and were considered
dangerous, as were any other writers who challenged the established order. Voltaire
had his books publicly burned by the state executioner. La Mettrie went into exile, as
did Rousseau; Diderot and Mirabeau had been locked up; Sade had himself been
imprisoned with Laclos for a time. The vanguards of atheism- dHolbach and La
Mettrie in particular- published anonymously and went to considerable lengths to
ensure that they could deny authorship. In Sades age, philosophical writing, in
particular atheistic writings and critiques of religion, was itself subjected to a
confinement of sorts (Sades insistence that it was his philosophical writings that had
led to his imprisonment, and not his sadistic rapes, {and certainly not his insanity}
suggests that Sade himself associated imprisonment with intellectual status). 99
A third distinct, para-philosophical discourse had also emerged owing to the
persecution of any publisher or author who challenged the clergy, the government, the
throne, or sexual mores. The Libertin novel, a mixture of atheistic freethought,
political satire, and pornography, constitutes a historically important discourse to
which Sades work is closely related. There is no sharp distinction between the
libertin novel and the work of the philosophes, they themselves having written a
number of key works, for example Diderots Les bijoux indiscrets (1748) and Boyer
dArgens Thrse philosophe (circa 1780). The philosophes also wrote tracts on such
topics as the joy of guilt-free sex (La Mettries La Volupt, 1746), or the
establishment of a state brothel system for the public good (Helvtius Treatise on
Man of 1758). 100 Rousseaus penchant, in his youth, for public exhibitionism and
other paraphilias, and Helvtius for having himself whipped in Parisian brothels,
further blur the distinction between Sade the libertine and his intellectual
predecessors. 101 Philosophical (philosophe) writing in Sades time, simply put, was
as socially respectable as punk rock and, for anyone with something to say, was
considerably more dangerous to get involved in. This makes problematic Foucaults
association of confinement, libertinage and irrationality, or the implied
99
Sade attributed his imprisonment to his considered reflections, although he did not start writing
For discussion on the relationship between philosophy and libertine writing, see Patrick Wald
Lasowski Prface, in Romanciers libertins du XVIIIe sicle ed. Patrick Wald Lasowski (Paris:
Gallimard, 2000): ix- lx.
101
Neil Schaeffer The Marquis de Sade: A Life (New York: Knopf, 1999) pp.61-62.
81
identification of censorship with rationality, given that it appears that rationality was,
in the case of Sades philosophical influences, in a basic sense being locked away.
Foucault, we have seen, grants that Sade has enfolded all other discourse into a
new discourse all of its own, in sovereign isolation from all other discourses. Another
possibility is that Sade is aligned with another sovereign discourse, that of the more
militant philosophe or libertin writers. Despite the garbled nature of his writing, Sade
no doubt had a point in arguing, for example, that homosexuality should be
decriminalized, and that marriage was to be avoided until it outgrew its status as
socioeconomic exploitation. In a basic sense, at least some of Sades work is
eminently sane. Yet there are aspects of Sade that put him beyond the designations of
rogue philosophe or even libertin author. It is common for Sade scholars to refer to
Sade as a libertine writer, and to his characters as libertines (as, indeed, they refer to
themselves). Sade referred to himself as a libertine. 102 Sades work is clearly
associated with this original sense of the term, being both pornographic and
philosophical, and, for the sake of convenience, I will use the term libertine in
Sades sense as a convention. Yet the term libertine did not originally refer to people
who were sadistic mass murderers. Virtually every person who has written on Sade
has accepted Sades usage of the term, despite the fact that it appears to be a serious
distortion of its original sense. 103 No writer, philosopher, philosophe or libertin, went
to Sades extreme in rejecting, not only conventional morality, but any morality at all.
It may simply be irrelevant that Sade borrowed and inverted the intended sense of
three other discourses rather than one- the libertines and philosophe authors, no doubt,
would have been as appalled at what Sade had done to their work, given that they held
essentially the same values in common. 104 The question is, once again, - is there an
internal, essential relation between Sades work and any other discourse, official or
102
See Sade My Grand Letter, February 20th 1781. Letters from Prison trans. Richard Seaver (New
The Larousse dictionary defines libertin as Qui est de murs trs libres, qui mne une vie
dissolue, essentially the same as the English definition: dissolute or licentious person. Both English
and French terms have associations with free thought, especially during the 17th and 18th Centuries,
and the libertine novel of the same period. The sense of the term has softened since the 18th century.
104
Cusset characterises libertin literature as continuous with the values of the Enlightenment, in
particular in its critique of social, moral and religious prejudice, and in bringing pleasure and reason
into harmony. See Cusset No Tomorrow p.90.
82
clandestine? And precisely which discursive practices did Sade seek to absorb and
distort? That even the libertin discourse was corrupted by Sades treatment, perhaps
for all time, perhaps suggests the scope and depth of his disruption.
Two other points can be made against Foucaults classification of Sade. In
Madness and Civilisation, Sade is described as an atavistic figure; a representation of
a long, silent memory of the Occidental psyche. There is certainly something of the
arcane in Sades writings, in particular the preoccupation with torture. But there are
many strikingly modern aspects also; - biochemical weapons, electrocution,
descriptions of the machines of mass destruction incorporating such features as
conveyor belts and rotating knives, all arguably closer to the early modern world than
the world of centuries past (J:337-338; LNJ 2:377). 105 Also problematic is Foucaults
association of criminality with the unreason. Criminality in Sades age was
frequently simply a matter of life and death. Sade, through the character Dubois, notes
that for those born into poverty, the choice is between Wealth, by any means
necessary, or the Wheel (MV: 127). The whole point of Sades Justine (subtitled, as
it is, the Misfortunes of Virtue) is that only the mad would adhere so stubbornly to
morality in a world so corrupted and unjust. Some criminal groups of the period, in
particular pirates, were not only reasonable but in fact politically sophisticated.
Two critics have noted that Sades work has more in common with the
mechanisms of power than its opposites, a theme that will be pursued later in the
study. Sbastian Charles describes Foucaults Sade as representinglintroduction du
dsordre du dsir dans un monde domine par lordre, la rgularit et la
classification, but concludes by noting that Sade himself seems to represent
mechanisms of power. 106 In similar terms, Stephen Pfohl, a sociologist, focuses on
what he perceives as an intimate connection between Classical reason and Sades
105
On the role of the guillotine in Sades work, see Lucienne Frappier-Mazur Writing the Orgy: Power
and parody in Sade trans. Gillian C. Gill (Philadelphia: University of Pennsylvania Press, 1996)
pp.124-125; Michel Delon Sade dans la Rvolution, Il Confronto Letterario Supplemento 15
(1991):157-165, p.162.
106
plaisir, First International Congress Sade in North America, March 12-15; Charleston, South Carolina.
pp.7, 10.
83
work, noting what he considers to be sadism within Classical reason. 107 In his book
Images of Deviance and Social Control, Pfohl notes what we have all known for half
a century now- that the truly dangerous people in the world are not, in fact, the
schizos who talk to themselves or the aliens, but those that are, as far as psychology
is concerned, completely sane; the ones that make difficult decisions that are too
complicated for the rest of us to understand. 108 This is the group that Pfohl sees in
Sades novels. In particular, he notes the extreme individualism of classical thought.
Insomuch as classical theorizing strips individuals of all but the most instrumental
forms of calculative judgement, good intentions aside, the question must be asked: is
there not something sadistic about the isolated individual application of classical
reasoning? Pfohl suggests that sadism, as described in Sades work, is an
unacknowledged and shadowy double of classical reasonings abstract commitment
to rational hedonism.
De Sades arguments concerning the rational benefits of systematically administered pain
resemble the arguments of his early criminological counterparts. Like sadistic
pornography, classical criminology advocates the application of strict disciplinary
punishments in isolation from the complex, contradictory, and often unequal social
landscapes within which people make choices between conformity and deviance. This is
not to reduce the logic of classical thought to the logic of sadism. It is, however, to note
disturbing historical connections between these two excessively rational modes of
thought. Each in its own way seeks to pin punishment onto individuals in isolation from
the historical complexities of their social context. Does this mean that the logic of
classical reasoning and the logic of sadism are historically intertwined? This much may
be said for sure: without some commitment to equalizing the human social conditions in
which choices for or against deviance are culturally made, the classical perspective will
favour a very specialized form of rationality- there rationality of the advantaged, the rich,
and the powerful. The rationality of the disadvantaged, the poor and the powerful will
either be denied or classed as deviant.
107
109
Stephen Pfohl Seven Mirrors of Sade: Sex, Death, CAPITAL, and the Language of Monsters of
Sade In Deepak Sawhney, editor, Must we Burn Sade? (Amherst, New York: Humanity Books,
1999): 51-77.
108
Stephen Pfohl Images of Deviance and Social Control: A Sociological History second edition (New
84
By 1975, Foucault himself had come to accept that Sade may have been more of a
disciplinarian than a figure of resistance. In a lecture dated 29th January 1975, given at
the Collge de France. In the context of a discussion on the relationship between the
monstrous individual and the law, Foucault identifies the libertines of Sade as
110
111
For discussion see Pfohl Deviance p.471-4; Foucault DP: 202; HS Vol. I: 45, 48.
112
113
85
criminal- despots- those who have elevated their own irrational, homicidal whims to
the state of general law.
In most of [Sades] novels, in Juliette in any rate, there is this regular coupling of the
monstrosity of the powerful with the monstrosity of the man of the people, the
monstrosity of the minister with the monstrosity of revolt, and their mutual complicity.
Juliette and la Dubois are obviously at the centre of this series of couples of ultrapowerful
monstrosity and rebellious monstrosity. In Sade, libertinage is always linked to the
corruption of power... [t]here are no politically neutral or average monsters in Sade;
Either they come from the dregs of the people and have risen up against established
society, or they are princes, ministers, or lords who wield a lawless superpower over all
social powers. In any case, power- the excess of power, the abuse of power, despotism- is
always the operative element of libertinage in Sade. It is this superpower that transforms
simple libertinage into monstrosity. 114
114
Michel Foucault Abnormal: Lectures at the 1974-1975 ed. Valerio Marchetti and Antonella
Foucault is probably referring to Liliana Cavanis film The Night Porter (1974). For discussion on
the Sadeian themes in this film, see Primo Levi The Drowned and the Saved trans. Raymond Rosenthal
(London: Abacus, 1988) pp.32, 33.
86
Hes a disciplinarian, a sergeant of sex, an accountant of the ass and its equivalents (SS:
227).
Given Foucaults musings on Sades importance over a number of years, this can
easily be read as a flippant response. Sade is reduced to a pornographic clich (Nazis
could not be associated with Sade, according to Foucault, because they were not
erotic,), and the Holocaust is completely removed from its social, historical and
intellectual contexts. Further, that there may be psychological commonalities between
the perpetrators of the killers and Sades characters (sadism, in particular) is not
considered. 116 At the end of the interview, however, Foucault appears to
acknowledge a certain similarity between Sade and Nazism after all, noting that both
are characterized by an excessive preoccupation with discipline and order. (Foucault
does not, however, make the association here with the January lecture, in which he
describes Sades libertines as figures of the corruption of power).
You know I am not for Sades absolute sacralization. After all, I would be willing to
admit that Sade formulated eroticism proper to a disciplinary society: a regulated,
anatomical, hierarchical society whose time is carefully distributed, its places partitioned,
characterized by obedience and surveillance (SS: 226).
It was also common for staff of the death camps to take photographs and films of killings for their
own enjoyment, and both gas chambers and gassing-trucks had observation windows. Pleasure in
seeing the suffering of others was clearly a commonality. For discussion, see Aleksander Lasik
Historical-Sociological Profile of the Auschwitz SS in Yisrael Gutman and Michael Berenbaum, eds.
Anatomy of the Auschwitz Death Camp (Bloomington: Indiana University Press in association with the
United States Holocaust Museum, 1994): 271-287, p.285.
Foucault describes the Holocaust as a petite-bourgeois dream of cleanliness, adding: Millions of
people were murdered there, so I dont say it to diminish the blame for those responsible for it, but
precisely to disabuse those who want to superimpose erotic values on it (SS: 226). Even so, Foucaults
assessment does not explain how so many Germans could have gotten the idea into their heads that
Jewish Germans, a majority of whom were bourgeois themselves, were dirty.
87
Michel Foucault The Archaeology of Knowledge trans. A. M. Sheridan Smith (London: Routledge,
1995).
118
Georges van Den Abbeele discusses the lightning bolt that kills Justine in detail, noting that, for
Foucault, it represents the end of the classical episteme, the close of the age of reason, and the birth of
literature. Georges Van Den Abbeele Sade, Foucault, and the Scene of Enlightenment Lucidity,
Stanford French Review 11, no.1 (1987): 7-16, pp. 10, 15.
88
derived from the confessional (HS Vol. I: 20-21). 119 Foucault also makes assertions,
without textual support, which take on significance as his interpretation of Sade
unfolds. For example, he claims that Sade wrote his works solely for his own
consumption, as shown by their unreadability and hence their status at the limit of
expression (HS Vol. I: 23; LI: 64-65). (Sade was in fact eager to have his work
published, {although he strenuously denied authorship of Justine and Juliette}, and to
get his plays performed in public. Money was a motive also, and Justine- far from
being unreadable, was a commercial success in its time). 120 The second problem with
Foucaults account is its vagueness. Sade is said to represent the discourse of desire,
but what exactly this desire is, and how it is to be expressed in a purely literary sense,
is not specified. Even were it a plausible account of the relationship between the
practice of writing and the will, its relevance to Sade is not explained. The same could
be said of Foucaults account of the unthought. It could be that the unthought can
only be defined in negative terms, according to what it is not, but again, more work
needs to be done to demonstrate that it really is that which Sade was concerned with.
A tension emerges- Foucault both asserts that Sade is beyond a fixed representation,
as the confabulation of all representations, all theory, and yet there is the suggestion
that there is a correct interpretation. As Georges Van Den Abbeele notes, instead of
clarifying whatever worth there may be in Sades work, Foucault uses the term Sade
as a term for the obscure. 121 The mythos of the poisonous de Sade (MC: 228) would
seem to play a greater role for Foucault than his actual writings, raising questions
concerning his account of both madness and literature.
In Foucaults work, we have some suggestions as to what may be found, but a
detailed exegesis an internal- account, of Sade- is necessary to assess its claims.
Firstly, to reiterate, Foucault cautions against finding a fixed reference, or any simple
relationship between the author, the text, and the theorizing therein. The literary
119
This view is well argued for by Batrice Didier, who notes the similarity between Sades lists of
virtues to be vexed for Justine and the catechism. See Batrice Didier Sade thologien In Michel
Camus, Philippe Roger, eds.: 219-240.
120
See Maurice Lever Sade: A Biography trans. Arthur Goldhammer (San Diego, New York and
Georges Van Den Abbeele writes that, given Foucaults preference for instantaneous illumination,
one can argue over whether we really know anything more or less about Sade after reading Foucault.
Van Den Abbeele pp.12, 16.
89
version of the first interpretation- that Sade has created a mirrored, infinite repeating
of all previous discourses in order to create a new literature- may well be both
implausible and irrelevant to us, given that we are concerned with philosophical
interpretations of Sade. Yet, a philosophical version of the same account may be
pertinent. That is, Sade may have deliberately set up an endless mirroring of
philosophical doctrines, leading to the loss of all perspective, to theoretical paralysis.
Secondly, Foucaults interpretations raise the question of what relationship Sade
has with other discourses. Was Sade standing in the position of sovereign unreason,
or the accountant of the ass? Was Sade the subject of the Confinement, or its
doctrinal Overlord? Could he have been both at once? Where does the wedge go,
exactly?
Regardless of whether we accept Foucaults treatment of Sade, a study on Sade
remains a project of Foucaultian interest, and there are a number of points of
association between the writings of the two figures. There is a certain resemblance,
for example, between the later Foucaults ethic or style of self-overcoming, of
learning to think differently than one thinks, and the apparent objective of Sades
educational Philosophy of the Bedroom in which the reader is encouraged to follow
the example of Eugnies libertine education. (HS Vol. II p.8, also p.11, 69) Both
Foucault and Sade are preoccupied with the legal and medical classification of
sexual practices. 122 There is also a common interest in the status of hermaphrodites
and other intragendered people. Sades novels feature many near-hermaphroditeswomen with obstructed vaginas and penis-like clitorises a grouping whose marginal,
quasi-moral classification Foucault was preoccupied with (HS Vol. I: 38; Sade J: 23,
1032; 120:221; LNJ vol. 1: 172; vol. 2:122, 136.). 123 Further, both Foucault and Sade
are concerned with the pleasures of power, and the injustices, class interests and
122
Both Sade and Foucault were preoccupied with the legal and moral status of sexual practices, and
both encountered the institutional control of sexuality. Sade was hung in effigy for sodomy; Foucault
was diagnosed as a homosexual whilst in his teens. For Foucaults discussion of the medicalisation of
homosexuality, see HS Vol. 1:40, 101,105, 119. For comments on the medicalisation and persecution
of homosexuality in Sade, see J: 237; MV: 179, 212; MM: 55; 120: 113,495.
123
Michel Foucault Les Anormaux : Cours au Collge de France, 1974-1975. (Paris : Hautes tudes -
Gallimard- Seuil, 1999); Michel Foucault. Herculine Barbin dite Alexina B. (Paris : Gallimard,
collection Les vies parallles 1978).
90
ulterior motives of the judicial system and related institutions (HS Vol.I:95). Yet,
despite these commonalities of interest, and Foucaults apparent preoccupation with
Sade, Foucault does not address them in his work. As the exegesis of Sade unfolds,
we find that the relationship between Sade and Foucault, between interpreted and
interpreter, may be reversed- we may find that we learn about Foucaults project
through reading Sade, rather than the other way around.
1.12 Conclusion.
The various interpretations of Sades work discussed in this chapter fall roughly
into two categories. There are those in particular Le Brun, Adorno and Horkheimer,
Neiman, and Joyce who either treat Sade as a philosopher in a straightforward
manner, or hold that within his work is a coherent philosophical doctrine, and hold
that it is this doctrine that is of interest, rather than other traits ( such as textual or
symbolic qualities). Others, in particular Foucault and Bataille, find Sades work of
philosophical interest, yet withhold from Sade the honorific philosopher, deeming
the philosophical passages in Sade of secondary importance. Bataille and Foucault
hold that Sade reveals a side to human nature that is typically occulted from
philosophical discourse, yet Bataille dismisses Sades philosophical passages as
merely tiresome, and Foucault describes his work variously as a pastiche, or as a
textual sublimation of desire. Likewise, for Camus, Sade is not so much a thinker as a
dreamer of revenge.
The question is: Sade a philosopher, or not? If not a philosopher exactly, is he of
philosophical interest, nonetheless? If so, what is it about his work that is so
interesting? Does he have some utility as an object of philosophical speculation (on
the nature of sexuality, or of evil, perhaps), or is he a thinker in his own right who
ought to be engaged with as such? If Sade engages with other thinkers and
discourses, what is the nature of this engagement? Does Sade merely absorb other
thinkers into a satirical collage, or hurl abuse, or does he approach other thinkers in a
thoughtful and sophisticated manner? What are Sades primary philosophical
concerns, and are they the same concerns that have been attributed to him by his
admirers and critics? And what, exactly, is the range and depth of Sades thought?
Finally, is his thought readable in a straightforward manner, and is it coherent (as
suggested by Gorer and Le Brun), or is it purposefully multidimensional and resistant
91
to linear interpretation? The remainder of this study will attempt to clarify these
issues.
92
2.1 Introduction.
>
VX
E4+s :assa8' 5a7 allo1 ,or a Na)a+ll+an r'a.+n83 E4' )ra.+)+onal asso6+a)+on o, Zr'ason 1+)4 )4'
Z6os5os +s s'9'r'.T r'ason +s no) )4' ro7al roa. )o )4' C*solu)'3 E4' un+9'rs' 5a7 s+5:l7 *' :ur'
64aosT )o a64+'9' un.'rs)an.+n8 4'r' 5a7 r'/u+r' surr'n.'r+n8 r'ason +)s'l,3
VY
?n La Nouvelle Justine @a.' .+s6uss's 5an as *'+n8 a Z:ro.u6) o, 5o9'5'n) also3 ?n a )7:+6all7
a::all+n8 :assa8'= a 64ara6)'r .'s6r+*'s )4' 6on9uls+9' 5o9'5'n)s o, a r'6'n)l7 2+ll'. 9+6)+5 as
Z:roo, o, )4' Z5o9'5'n) 14+64 +s an +nna)' :ro:'r)7 o, 5a))'r3 E4+s +s 5os) :ro*a*l7 a r','r'n6' )o
)4' 'B:'r+5'n)s 6on.u6)'. *7 Ju+8+ bal9an+ H>\X\]>\V^M 1+)4 ,ro8s l'8s an. 'l'6)r+6al 6urr'n)s HLNJ
SQ SYYM3
Y
E4+s )4's+s +s s+5+lar )o )4' r'6ons)+)u)'. @a)an+s5 o, Cla+s)'r ;ro1l'7 H>^\R]>VY\M an. Cn)on JaU'7
H>VXg]>VV\M= a66or.+n8 )o 14+64 @a)an +s a :'rson+,+6a)+on o, na)ural ,or6's3 @a+n) Don. 'B:la+ns )4a)
)4' Z5al',+6'n) 5ol'6ul's O6o5:os' 14a) :o')s an. o)4'rs o, ar.'n) +5a8+na)+on 4a9' na5'.
.'5onsP HJQ XV^M3
VR
s)a)'s )4a) @a+n)]Don.s s7s)'5 +s O)4' 5os) *+harr' o, all )4' s7s)'5s 7') )o 4a9'
o66urr'. )o )4' 5+n. o, 5an=P su88's)+n8 )4a) 4' 4as s+5:l7 +n9'n)'. 4+s o1n 8o. +n
or.'r )o 4a)' 4+53 @a+n)] Don.s )4'olo87 +s no) 'n.ors'. *7 an7 o)4'r 64ara6)'r= *u)
,un6)+ons as a s6a)4+n8 sa)+r' on r'l+8+ous *'l+', Hs+5+larQ LNJ SQ Yg= AVQ YX>=
YXX=YXYM3 W
@a.' also .ra1s a))'n)+on )o )4os' na)ural :4'no5'na )4a) 6oun) a8a+ns) )4'
no)+on o, a *'n'9ol'n) bo. 14o 6r'a)'s 4u5ans +n 4+s o1n +5a8'= or +n a66or.an6'
1+)4 )ra.+)+onal 8'n.'r +.'n)+)7 or s'Bual rol'= su64 as Z5ons)'rs= or 1o5'n 1+)4ou)
u)'rus's or 1+)4 :'n+s] l+2' 6l+)or+s's HJQ SX= >gXST 120QSS>=WgST LNJ3 >Q >\ST SQ >SS=
>XW=M3 E4' 8'n'ral :o+n) 4'r' +s )4a) .+r'6) o*s'r9a)+on o, )4' 1orl. :ro9+.'s a5:l'
8roun.s )o .ou*) )4' 9'r+)7 o, +)s )ra.+)+onal .'s6r+:)+ons3
Dor .+s6uss+on= s'' @645+. Le soufre au bord de la chaire :3X>3 J'an K3 boul'5o) 1r+)'s )4a) )4'
+.'a )4a) '9+l +n so5' s'ns' *alan6's )4' 8oo. +n )4' 1orl. +s .'r+9'. ,ro5 L+.'ro) HAVQ n3 XWW= :3^XSM3
Kan+64a'+s5 1as a :o:ular )o:+6 a5on8 )4' :4+loso:4's +n 8'n'ral3 @a.' also 1r+)'s +n a :os+)+9'= +,
a5*+8uous= 1a7 a*ou) L'+s5 +n Aline et Valcour HAVQ SXR= XRYM3
VW
H>M Cs a6)+9' :r+n6+:l' +) +s .+9+s+*l'Q ,or )4' 4'ar)= lon8 a,)'r +)s s':ara)+on ,ro5 )4' *o.7=
:r's'r9's +)s a6)+on 6on)+nu+n8 )o *'a)T \ no1= 14a)'9'r +s sus6':)+*l' o, .+9+s+on +s
5a)'r+al3 HSM d4a)'9'r +s sus6':)+*l' o, s)ru6)ural .'8'n'ra)+on +s 5a)'r+al= )4a) 14+64 +s
'ss'n)+all7 s:+r+) 6anno) .')'r+ora)'T 1'll )4' soul +s a,,'6)'. *7 )4' 6on.+)+on o, )4' *o.7=
)4' soul +s 1'a2 +n 7ou)4,ul *o.+'s= .'6r':+) +n su:'rannua)'. ,ra5'sT +) )4us un.'r8o's
6or:or'al +n,lu'n6'= an7)4+n8 )4a) .'8'n'ra)'s s)ru6)urall7 +s 5a)'r+alQ )4' soul .'6l+n's
an. 4'n6' +) +s 5a)'r+al HJQYV]RgT s+5+larQ LNJ >Q > VY= SYX= SYRT LNJ S Q SXS= SY> T
AVQSWY= SWWM3
@a.' .'s6r+*'s 5'n)al '9'n)s +n )'r5s o, :47s+6al :4'no5'na3 E4' ,ollo1+n8 :assa8'
+s )7:+6al Hno)' )4a) @a.' only .+s6uss's 5'n)al '9'n)s 14'n .+s6uss+n8 :l'asur'T 4'
.o's no) .+s6uss n'r9's= 'l'6)r+6al ,lu+. an. so on +n an7 o)4'r 6on)'B)M3
E4os' l+))l' 5ur5urs 7ou 4'ar= 57 8oo. ,r+'n.= ar' 6aus'. *7 57 'B)r'5'l7 s'ns+)+9'
n'r9ous s7s)'5 T )4' o*F'6)s 14+64 'B6+)' our :ass+ons 6r'a)' su64 a l+9'l7 6o55o)+on +n
)4' 'l'6)r+6all7 64ar8'. ,lu+. )4a) ,lo1s +n our n'r9's= )4' s4o62 r'6'+9'. *7 )4' an+5al
s:+r+)s 6o5:os+n8 )4+s ,lu+. +s o, su64 a .'8r'' o, 9+ol'n6'= )4a) )4' 'n)+r' 5'64an+s5 +s
ra))l'. *7 )4's' ',,'6)s= an. on' +s Fus) as :o1'rl'ss )o su::r'ss on's 6r+'s 14'n
o9'r14'l5'. *7 )4' )'rr+*l' *lo1s +5:ar)'. *7 :l'asur'= as on' 1oul. *' 14'n assa+l'.
*7 )4' :o1'r,ul '5o)+ons o, :a+n H120QY^VT also LNJ >QXWST SQ>>gM3
@a.' r'F'6)s )4' no)+on o, 4u5an un+/u'n'ss on )4' 8roun.s )4a) )4'r' ar'
:47s+olo8+6al s+5+lar+)+'s 1+)4 o)4'r an+5als3 ^ ?n La Nouvelle Justine, @a.'s
64ara6)'r Nr'ssa6 ar8u's )4a) )ur)l's= 5+.8's an. 4u5ans ar' 'ss'n)+all7 )4' sa5'= as
)4'7 ar' *rou84) +n)o *'+n8 *7 )4' sa5' Z5o9'5'n)s an. ar' 'a64 '/uall7 Z5o.+,+'.
)o su+) )4'+r 1a7 o, l+,'= an. 6on6lu.'s )4a) +) +s no) 6orr'6) )o s:'a2 o, )4'
Zsu:'r+or+)7 o, on' or8an+s5 o9'r )4' n'B)3 @+5+larl7= +n Juliette, Nras64+ Hb+o9ann+
Cn8'lo Nras64+= <o:' <+us U? l>\>\]>\VVmM ar8u's )4a) O)4' ro)]s:a1n'. 1or5 +s o,
no l'ss nor 5or' 6ons+.'ra*l' 9alu' +n 57 '7's )4an )4' 5+84)+'s) 2+n8 on 'ar)4P HLNJ
\
E4+s +s s+5+lar )o Ja K'))r+'= 14o .'s6r+*'s an 'B:'r+5'n) +n 14+64 )4' 4'ar) +s r'5o9'. ,ro5 a l+9'
@a.' ,ollo1s )4' )4ou84) o, 4+s a8'3 C8a+ns) L's6ar)'s ar8u5'n) as )o )4' un+/u'n'ss o, 4u5ans=
Na7l' 4a. no)'. )4' 6on)+n8'n6+'s o, 4u5an +n)'ll+8'n6'= r'F'6)+n8 )4' +.'a )4a) )4'r' 1as su64 a )4+n8
as a un+/u'l7 4u5an soul3 ?n 4+s Dictionary, 4' r','rr'. )o 'arl+'r )4+n2'rs 14o 4a. :ro:os'. )4'
+n)'ll'6)ual su:'r+or+)7 o, *+r.s an. '9'n so6+al +ns'6)s o9'r 4u5ans3 @'' Na7l'Q S>X= SSY]SS^= SXY=
SYg3 @'' also ;ro62'r Age of Crisis :3 ^R3
V\
SQ SXY]SXRT s+5+larQ LNJQ >Q >R>= SQSXY= SXRT JQ \^>M3 ?n .'n7+n8 )4' un+/u'n'ss o,
4u5an+)7= 4u5an r'ason +)s'l, +s .'5o)'. ,ro5 s+8n o, our .+9+n' na)ur'= or )4' 5'ans
)o a 4+84'r )ru)43 ?ns)'a.= +) +s .'s6r+*'. as 5'r' a.a:)a)+onT )4' Os6al's 1' 1'+84
o*F'6)s +n333 )4' ,a6ul)7 8+9'n 5' *7 Ga)ur' 14'r'*7 ? 5a7 .+s:os' 57s'l, +n a
,a9oura*l' s'ns' )o1ar. su64]an.]su64 an o*F'6)3333.':'n.+n8 u:on )4' a5oun) o,
:l'asur' or :a+n ? .'r+9' ,ro5 )4's' o*F'6)s333PJQ XYM3 @a.'s 9+s+on r'.u6's )4'
4u5an= 4'n6' )4' :ol+)+6al or.'r= an. 4u5an 4+s)or7= )o )4' :47s+6al or.'r o, )4+n8s3
Dor @a.'= )4'r' ar' no K'ss+a4s= ano+n)'. 2+n8s or 4'ro's= no .+9+n' :lan an. no
4+s)or+6al :ro8r'ss3 K'ns a6)+ons ar' no)4+n8 5or' )4an )4' ou)6o5' o, na)ural la1s
HJQ >S>M3 I+s)or7 +s s+5:l7 )4' r'6or. o, a)ro6+)+'s :'r:')ua)'. *7 'B6':)+onall7
:o1'r,ul +n.+9+.uals= :ro:'ll'. *7 )4'+r :ass+ons ra)4'r )4an *7 r'ason= )4'+r lus) ,or
:o1'r an. )4'+r 6ru'l)+'s )4' r'sul) o, +nna)' .+s:os+)+ons3 I'r' @a.' ,ollo1s )4'
r'ason+n8 o, I'l9i)+us= 14o 4a. su88's)'. )4a) )4' .'s)ru6)+on o, Z:o:'r7 +n
`n8lan. 1as .u' )o )4' O8r'a) a6r+5on7 o, )4' s'5+nal 5a))'rP o, I'nr7 U???= an.
.Iol*a64= 14o 4'l. )4a) O*loo. )oo 5u64 'n,la5'. +n a 6on/u'ror= a :a+n,ul
+n.+8's)+on +n )4' s)o5a64 o, a 5onar64= a 14+5 )4a) :ass's +n )4' 5+n. o, a 1o5an=
ar' so5')+5's 6aus's su,,+6+'n) )o *r+n8 on 1ar= )o s'n. 5+ll+ons o, 5'n )o )4'
slau84)'r= )o roo) ou) an 'n)+r' :'o:l'333)o s:r'a. .'sola)+on ,ar an. 1+.' u:on )4'
sur,a6' o, our 8lo*'3P V E4' br'a) Kan +s 5'r'l7 a 9ol6ano= a s4u..'r o, )4' )'6)on+6
:la)'s= O9o5+)'. ,or)4 ,ro5 na)ur'333)o a+. 4'r +n .'s)ru6)+onP HJQ R^S]R^XT LNJQ
SQSYSM3 @a.' .'s6r+*'. :ol+)+6s 'B6lus+9'l7 +n )'r5s o, )4' )7rann7 o, su64 br'a) K'n=
a )o:+6 .+s6uss'. +n ;4a:)'r U??3 Go)a*l7= @a.' .o's no) a62no1l'.8' )4' lo8+6al 8a:
*')1''n )4' r'F'6)+on o, )4' )ra.+)+onal )'l'olo87= an. )4' r'F'6)+on o, )4'
5'an+n8,uln'ss o, 4u5an 4+s)or73
2.4 Death.
@a.' .'s6r+*'s l+9+n8 s7s)'5s as *'+n8 6on)+nuous 1+)4 .'a. 5a))'r= a 9+'1 .'r+9'.
,ro5 )4' )4ou84) o, )4' philosophes. I'l9i)+us s)a)'s )4a) )4' *loo. )4a) O6arr+'s
nu)r+)+on )o all )4' 5'5*'rs o, a 64+l.= an. su66'ss+9'l7 'nlar8's '9'r7 :ar)= +s a
:r+n6+:l' o, .'s)ru6)+on=P as +) '9'n)uall7 Ooss+,+'s )4' 9'ss'ls= .'s)ro7s )4'+r s:r+n8s=
LIol*a64 System of Nature Uol3 ?3 C.a:)'. ,ro5 )4' )rans3 *7 I3L3 _o*+nson HJon.onQ ;l+na5'n
<r'ss= >VVVM :3YST I'l9i)+us A Treatise on Man; his Intellectual Faculties and his Education H>\R^M
)rans3 d3 Ioo:'r HS 9ols3M HG'1 !or2Q Nur) Dran2l+n= >VWVM ?Q XY3
V^
an. :ro.u6's )4' s''.s o, .'a)43P >g J+2'1+s'= ,or Na7l'= l+9+n8 )4+n8s ar' 'ss'n)+all7
O5a))'r 5o.+,+'.3P >> E4+s 'ra.+6a)+on o, )4' .+64o)o57 o, )4' l+9+n8 an. )4' .'a. +s a
.+r'6) 6ons'/u'n6' o, )4' .'n+al o, )4' 'B+s)'n6' o, an +55or)al soul3 L'a)4 +s )a2'n
)o *' n'6'ssar7 as:'6) o, )4' 676l' o, 6r'a)+on= .'s)ru6)+on an. r'8'n'ra)+on3 Nras64+
'B:la+nsQ
?n all l+9+n8 )4+n8s )4' :r+n6+:l' o, l+,' +s no o)4'r )4an )4a) o, .'a)4T a) )4' sa5' )+5' 1'
r'6'+9' )4' on' 1' r'6'+9' )4' o)4'r= 1' nour+s4 *o)4 1+)4+n us= s+.' *7 s+.'3 C) )4'
+ns)an) 1' 6all death= '9'r7)4+n8 s''5s )o .+ssol9'T 1' ar' l'. )o )4+n2 so *7 )4'
'B6'ss+9' 64an8' )4a) a::'ars )o 4a9' *''n *rou84) a*ou) +n )4+s :or)+on o, 5a))'r 14+64
no lon8'r s''5s an+5a)'3 Nu) )4+s .'a)4 +s onl7 +5a8+nar7= +) 'B+s)s ,+8ura)+9'l7 *u) +n no
o)4'r 1a73333e)f4'r' +s= +n )4' ,+nal anal7s+s= no 'ss'n)+al .+,,'r'n6' *')1''n )4+s ,+rs) l+,'
1' r'6'+9' an. )4+s s'6on.= 14+64 +s )4' on' 1' 6all .'a)4 HJQ\WV]\\gM3
E4' :r+n6+:l' a66or.+n8 )o 14+64 .'a)4 +s a :ar) o, )4' na)ural 676l' .o's no) 'n)a+l=
as @a.' su88's)s= )4a) l+,' +)s'l, +s +llusor73 cn' 6an assu5' )4a) .'a)4 +s a :ar) o, l+,'
an. s)+ll 5a+n)a+n )4a) )4'r' ar' so5' *as+6 .+,,'r'n6's *')1''n s'n)+'n) l+,' an. )4'
8'n'ral ,urn+)ur' o, )4' 1orl.3 Clso +5:laus+*l' +s @a.'s 6ru.' r'.u6)+on o, 4u5an
l+,' )o na)ural :ro6'ss's3 I' assu5's )4a)= *'6aus' our *o.+'s nour+s4 ,ur)4'r l+,'
H,ru+) )r''s= +ns'6)s= an. so onM 1' ours'l9's .o no) .+'3 >S ?n 2'':+n8 1+)4 4+s
r'.u6)+on o, 4u5an 'B+s)'n6' )o )4' na)ural or.'r o, )4+n8s= 4u5ans ar' r'.u6'. )o
un.+,,'r'n)+a)'. *+o5ass3 >X I' .o's no) a62no1l'.8' a r'l'9an) ')4+6al .+s)+n6)+on
*')1''n ,'r)+l+h'. '88s an. n'1*orn *a*+'s= or *')1''n :'o:l' an. .+r)3 C66or.+n8l7=
@a.'s 64ara6)'rs .'s6r+*' 5ur.'r+n8 a :'rson as )r+9+alT l+2' *r'a2+n8 a 8lass= or
2+ll+n8 a 64+62'n3 U+6)+5s Han. only 9+6)+5sM ar' r'.u6'. )o :ur' 5'ans= or :47s+6al
64ara6)'r+s)+6s= or a 5'r' Zs6u5 or Z9a:our )4ro1n u: *7 5un.an' 'ar)4 :ro6'ss's3
E4'7 ar' r','rr'. )o 9ar+ousl7 as O:l'asur' n 5a64+n's=P Oro*o)sP HautomatesM= or
Olus)]o*F'6)sPT O5a)'r+al su+)a*l' )o ans1'r 9olu:)uous :ur:os'sP 1+)4 O64ar5+n8
>g
I'l9i)+us A Treatise on Man; his Intellectual Faculties and his Education H>\R^M3 )rans3 d3 Ioo:'r
Na7l' :3Xgg3 @'' also Uol)a+r' Candide :3 XgVT L'n+s L+.'ro) Political Writings )rans3 Jo4n Io:'
Kason an. _o*'r) do2l'r H;a5*r+.8'Q ;a5*r+.8' on+9'rs+)7 <r'ss >VVSM :3 BBB++T also Diderots
Early philosophical works )rans3 Kar8ar') Jour.a+n HG'1 !or2Q Nur) Dran2l+n= >V\SM ::3>S]>X= XV3
>S
>X
VV
E4' 9+'1 )4a) .'a)4 +s no) )o *' ,'ar'. +s on ,+r5'r 8roun.T as )4' )+5' *',or' on's
l+,' +s +5:oss+*l' )o +5a8+n'= +) +s no) r'asona*l' )o ,'ar .'a)43 C.9+s's L'l*[n'T
Cn.= :ra7 )'ll= 14a) 1'r' 7ou *',or' *+r)4a 333@'9'ral un/ual+,+'. lu5:s o, unor8an+h'.
5a))'r as 7') 1+)4ou) .',+n+)' ,or5 or a) l'as) la62+n8 an7 ,or5 7ou 6an 4o:' )o
r'5'5*'r3 d'll= 7our' 8o+n8 )o )urn *a62 +n)o )4os' sa5' or s+5+lar lu5:s o, 5a))'r=
7our' 8o+n8 )o *'6o5' )4' ra1 5a)'r+al ou) o, 14+64 n'1 *'+n8s 1+ll *' ,as4+on'.= an.
)4+s 1+ll 4a::'n 14'n na)ural :ro6'ss's *r+n8 +) a*ou)3
333 e'f4 Jul+'))'= 4a9' 7ou 'B+s)'. s+n6' )4' *'8+nn+n8 o, )+5'a GoT an. .o's )4a) ,a6) 5a2'
7ou 8r+'9' an. .'s:a+ra Ia9' 7ou an7 *'))'r 6aus' )o .'s:a+r a) )4' ,a6) )4a) 7our' no)
>Y
>R
@a.'s 5u64 9aun)'. 6alls ,or )4' a*ol+)+on o, )4' .'a)4 s'n)'n6'= a66or.+n8l7= ar' +n6ons+s)'n) HAVQ
Go)' )4a) @a.'s 64ara6)'r +ns+s)s o, )4' +n6orr'6)n'ss o, Z:r+.'= .'s:+)' )4' ,a6) )4a) )4' Zl+*'r)+n's
ar' 6l'arl7 :rou. o, )4'5s'l9's an. r'8ar. 5o.'s)7 a Z,als' 9+r)u'3 Dor .+s6uss+on= s'' Ja6o5*' Sade
et ses masques H<ar+sQ <a7o)= >V\YM ::3 S>\= S>^=SSg= SS>3
>gg
8o+n8 )o 'B+s) )+ll )4' 'n. o, )+5'a Ja la= 6al5 7ours'l,= 57 :+8'onT )4' 6'ssa)+on o, *'+n8
a,,r+84)s onl7 )4' +5a8+na)+on )4a) 4as 6r'a)'. )4' 'B'6ra*l' .o85a o, an a,)'rl+,' HYVM3 >\
?n The Misfortunes of Virtue, a .+,,'r'n) a::roa64 +s 8+9'n3 d4'r'as L'l*[n' s:'a2s o, .'a)4 as a
1'l6o5' r'l'as' )o '9'r7on'= Jus)+n' a62no1l'.8's )4a) 4'r o1n .'a)4 +s onl7 1'l6o5'. *'6aus' o,
)4' l+,' s4' 4as l'a.] OL'a)4 +s )o *' ,'ar'. onl7 *7 )4os' ,or)una)' 'nou84 )o l'a. :ur'= 6lou.l'ss
l+9'sP HMVQ >YSM3
>^
`r+6 @3 _a75on. 5a2's )4+s analo87 1+)4 r'8ar.s )o )ra.+)+onal 9'rsus o:'n nsour6'= J+nuB] )7:'
>g>
;4a:)'r U?= ? 1+ll .+s6uss )4' non])rans6'n.'n)al )'l'olo87 )4a) @a.'s 64ara6)'rs
:ro:os'3 E4+s .o6)r+n' 4ol.s )4a) )4' 1orl. +s .r+9'n *7 an un.'rl7+n8 E'los= a Ga)ur'
64ara6)'r+h'. *7 'n.l'ss s)r+,' an. .o5+na)+on= an. )4a) 4u5ans ar' o*l+8'. )o
:ar)+6+:a)' +n +) )4rou84 r'5ors'l'ss ass'r)+on o, )4'+r s)r'n8)4 an. :o1'r3 ?n )4'
,ollo1+n8 64a:)'r= @a.'s r'.u6)+on+s) 6on6':)+on o, 5'n)al :ro6'ss's +s ,ur)4'r
.+s6uss'.3 ?n ;4a:)'r ?U= )4' +5:l+6a)+ons o, )4' r'F'6)+on o, a )ra.+)+onal Ju.a'o]
;4r+s)+an )'l'olo87 as r'8ar.s )o s'Bual+)7 1+ll *' .+s6uss'.3
>gS
Helvtius 1
3.1 Introduction.
On the subject of psychology, Sade presents himself as engaged in several tasks.
Firstly, he presents himself as a diagnostician of the human condition, in particular the
capacity for the enjoyment of cruelty and destruction. This aspect of Sades writing is
continuous with his literary self-image of scientific thinker. Sade frequently insists
that his tableaux will help toward the development of the human spirit, and
lambastes the stupid restraint of those who venture to write upon such matters...
Inhibited by absurd fears, they only discuss the puerilities with which every fool is
familiar, and dare not, by addressing themselves boldly to the investigation of the
human heart, offer its gigantic idiosyncrasies to our view (PB: 670, 671; similar
120:106, J: 175n, 1122). As such, Sade makes a significant, if somewhat obvious,
advance over those philosophers (Hobbes, for example) who had claimed that a desire
for cruelty in the human soul simply does not exist. 2 Sade also contributes to moral
thought in discussing the appeal of immoral conduct, although this was apparently not
his intention.
Sades second adopted role is that of the defiant critic of conventional morality,
and what we would term normalization. In the essay Reflections on the Novel
(1800), Sade adopts the role of one who has evaluated, according to the standards of
Helvtius Essays on the Mind (De LEsprit, 1758) trans. Anon. (New York: Burt Franklin, 1970)
p.120.
2
Hobbes writes: [c]ontempt, of little sense, of the calamity of others is that which men call
CRUELTY, proceeding from security of their own fortune. For, that any man should take pleasure in
other mens great harms without other end of his own I do not conceive it possible. Thomas Hobbes
Leviathan (Indianapolis/Cambridge: Hackett Publishing Company, Inc, 1994). p.32.
103
philosophy and science (in particular materialism), the assumptions that have branded
him a deviant, and found himself vindicated.
when man has weighed and considered all his restrictions, when, with a proud look his
eyes gauge his barriers, when, like the Titans, he dares to raise his bold hand to heaven,
and, armed with his passionshe no longer fears to declare war against those who in
times past were a source of fear and trembling to him, when his aberrations now seem to
him naught but errors rendered legitimate by his studies-should we then not speak to him
with the same fervor as he employs in his own behavior? (Sades italics; 120: 113-114).
That role for which Sade is best known is that of the proponent of the doctrine of
libertinage, a proposal for a project, on ostensibly hedonistic grounds, of
psychological self-sculpting for the attainment of superior pleasures. In the absence
(in non- Naturalist mode) of any Telos or higher ideal, the libertines have only this
project to pursue. This chapter will outline these aspects of Sades work, and the way
in which the three roles interrelate.
3.2 Theory of Pleasure: Materialist model
Sade holds that the experience of pleasure is due to the movement of animal spirits
or molecules within the brain, and that the intensity of pleasure is proportional to the
violence of the movement of these objects. Hence, Sade associates extremes of
experience with extremes of pleasure. The following description of the pleasure of
violence, from The 120 Days, is typical: [the Duc] noticed that a violent commotion
inflicted upon any kind of an adversary is answered by a violent thrill in our own
nervous system; the effect of this vibration, arousing the animal spirits which flow
within these nerves concavities, obliges them to exert pressure on the erector nerves
and to produce in accordance with this perturbation what is termed a lubricious
sensation (120:200). The taste for the horrific, the hideous and the nauseating are
explained in similarly reductionist terms- the most pleasing experience is simply that
which exerts the greatest force on the nervous system (120: 233, 489; J :95, 286-287,
845, 1172 ; LNJ 2 :108). 3
3
This idea is probably derived from Helvtius, who describes the sublime in materialist terms: [t]he
more lively the sensation is, the more beautiful the verse appears, and when it makes the strongest
impression possible it becomes sublime. It is therefore by the greater or less force that we distinguish
the beautiful from the sublime. Helvtius Treatise on Man Vol. II p.229.
104
Yet Sade does not hold that there is a direct correlation between bodily sensation
and pleasure. He also rejects the assumption, made by Bentham, that pleasure and
pain are opposite poles of a single continuum. 4 Like Gilbert Ryle, Sade notes that
ones mood determines whether a particular sensation is experienced as pleasurable or
unpleasant, and that neither pleasure nor pain can be defined in terms of a localized
bodily sensation; like Nietzsche, Sade occasionally describes pleasure and pain in
terms of gradients of the same physical processes. 5 As noted in the quote above,
Sade holds that the imagination of the subject will dictate whether a stimulus is
experienced as pleasurable or painful. Each person, he argues, experiences pleasure
in their own unique way. 6 Painful sensations become pleasurable to very blas
people. Observes Sade, [i]s there anything commoner to see, on the one hand, people
who have accustomed their palates to a pleasurable irritation, and next to them, others
who couldnt put up with that irritation for an instant? (J: 267; similar; PB: 280).
From the short story Eugenie de Franval:
happiness is an abstraction, it is a product of the imagination; it is a way of being moved,
which depends entirely on our way of seeing and feeling; apart form the satisfaction of
our needs, there is no one way of making all men feel equally happy; every day we see
one individual become happy through something which is totally displeasing to another;
there is therefore no certain happiness, no other can exist for us except that which we
William P. Alson Pleasure, In Paul Edwards, Ed. The Encyclopedia of Philosophy Volume 6 (New
York: The Macmillan Company & the Free Press, 1967) 341-347, p.341.
5
See Gilbert Ryle The Concept of Mind (London: Hutchinson, 1958) chapter 4. Writes Nietzsche:
There are even cases in which a kind of pleasure is conditioned by a certain rhythmic sequence of little
unpleasurable stimuli: in this way very rapid increase of the feeling of power, the feeling of pleasure, is
achieved. This is the case, e.g., in tickling, also the sexual tickling in the act of coitus; here we see
displeasure at work as an ingredient of pleasure. Friedrich Nietzsche The Will to Power trans. Walter
Kaufman & R.J. Hollingdale (London: Weidenfeld and Nicolson, 1967) section 699 (March June
1888) p.371.
6
This view coheres with recent findings in neurobiology. Recent research conducted by Patrick
MacLeod suggests that the neurons associated with the sensation of pleasure are not specialised.
Instead, they integrate the images given by the different senses, of which some are called up by
memory, and others may be set by ones culture. Further, no-one has the same sensation of taste. JeanYves Nau Les neurosciences dcouvrent les sources du plaisir sensorial, Le Monde Mercredi 31
Dcembre 2003.
105
make for ourselves as a result of our constitutions and our principles! In Eugenie de
Franval (GT: 46; similar: J: 317).
Fauskevg notes a similarity here with the description of the imagination offered by Nicolas Bergasse
(1750-1832) (Fauskevg p. 74). Sade scholars frequently note, erroneously, that Justine and Juliette go
through the same experiences, and yet only Juliette experiences them as pleasurable, owing to her
greater sophistication as a libertine. Whilst working as a prostitute, Juliette complains of rough,
insulting handling at the hands of clients, and negotiates with the Pope and other characters so that
she does not come to harm (J: 128, 199, 756). Juliette is a moderately powerful figure throughout the
novel, being both politically connected and wealthy, and for most of the time she is in complete control
of her situation. Justine, on the other hand, is powerless throughout the novel. She is brandedphysically, with an iron, as a prostitute (as was customary in Sades age), has toes cut off and is finally
killed by a bolt of lightning. Juliette never suffers such things. For discussion, see Jean-Pierre Han,
Jean-Pierre Valla, A propos p.109.
8
This is similar to the view of La Mettrie, who held that illusions were preferable to reality, so long as
Sades account of the imagination is not entirely positive. In Juliette, Madame Delbne states that the
106
imply that the imagination is not subordinate tot the will; as soon as the sexual act is
complete, notes one character, the voluptuous illusion vanishes) . 10
The materialist model cannot account for more complex pleasures, in particular
that of overcoming the chimerical ties that prevent us from doing terrible things to
one another, or of the pleasure of cruelty (LNJ 2: 190). Accordingly, Sade discusses
intellectual pleasures, in particular the sense of liberation afforded by intellectual
analysis, and the pleasure of reflection and analysis itself.
10
La Nouvelle Justine, in Sade uvres compltes dition mise en place par Annie le Brun et Jean-
Jacques Pauvert (Pauvert: Paris, 1986-1991) Vol. 9 p.448; quoted in Fauskevg p.76.
11
Steven Pinker holds a similar view. He notes that the poor of industrialized nations are materially far
better off than the aristocracy of a century ago, yet are still less happy (and die younger) than the more
wealthy. This is because, he says, peoples sense of well-being comes from an assessment of their
social status. Steven Pinker The Blank Slate (London: Penguin, 2002) p.304
107
This association is found in the work of Sade scholars. Batrice Didier, for example, draws a
distinction between sadisme dgnr and sadisme proprement dit [....] Ce serait une excitation du
dsir produite par la vue ou par la reprsentation mentale ou esthtique de la souffrance dautrui.
Didier Sade: Un criture du dsir p.129.
13
In his Voyage dItalie, Sade writes of a cocagne he witnessed in Naples: the most barbarous
spectacle in the world that one can possibly imagine. This involved a public festival in which food
was displayed in a public square; at the shot of a cannon, people were permitted to grab what they
108
could, resulting in a bloody riot. In Voyage dItalie (Paris: Tchou, 1967) p.440; cited in Berman
Thoughts and Themes p.141. This same spectacle appears in Juliette (J: 999-1000). Lacombe notes the
influence on Sade of abb Banier and abb Le Mascriers Histoire des Crmonies religieuses de tous
les peuples de la terre (Paris, 1741), which detailed the variety and inventiveness of torture in history.
See Roger G. Lacombe Sade et ses masques (Paris: Payot, 1974) p.215; also J: 70n, 262n. Sade most
probably accepted an association made by Helvtius: But suppose a man to have extreme sensibility,
what follows? That he will sometimes have sensations unknown to the common rank of men: that he
will feel what a less delicate organisation will not permit another man to feel. Helvtius Treatise on
Man Vol. I p.159.
109
for Sade, the intellectual satisfaction of resolving of a conceptual problem, but the
ecstasy of a cleansing fire.
How many and various are the desires aroused by the thought of a crime! I liken it to a
spark which swiftly sets alight everything combustible at hand, whose ravages increase in
proportion to the fuel it finds, and which ends up producing a blaze in us such as is not to
be extinguished save by rivers of fuck. But, Juliette, some theory must exist governing
this as there is a theory governing everything else, and it too must possess its principles, it
rules...teach me, my angel, you know what my dispositions, my penchants are, teach me
how to regulate all this (J:634; also 308; also similar:120: 239). 14
Sade also combines intellectual and physical pleasures. Delbne explains: theres
more to it than just experiencing sensations- they must be analysed. Sometimes it is as
pleasant to discuss as to undergo them; and when one has reached the limit of ones
physical means, one may then exploit ones intellect(J:60). Were Juliette of our
epoch, she would discuss the sensations of sex in terms of endorphins and serotonin
uptake. After being penetrated both vaginally and anally, Juliette is asked by Madame
Delbne which is the more pleasurable sensation. She replies:
...each gave me such pleasure I cannot decide which gave me the more. Reverberations
are yet going through me of sensations at once so confused and so voluptuous that I
would be hard put to assign them their proper origins.
Then wed best try it again, Tlme observed; The Abbot and I will vary our
attacks, the lovely Juliette will have the goodness to interrogate her sentiments and to
favour us with a more exact account thereof (J: 56).
Sade also holds that criminal acts are in themselves intellectually satisfying, although
there are no arguments in his surviving works as to why this is the case. 15
14
Catherine Cusset argues that Juliette is the most successful Sadeian character for this reason : Ce
que nous apprend Sade avec linvention de Juliette, cest que la libert est le choix de la limite. I
personally find this reading implausible; Juliette kills literally dozens of people and finally immolates
her own daughter during an orgy, so it is not clear that she could be said to embody an ethic of keeping
to limits, even in relation to other libertines. Catherine Cusset la passion selon Juliette, LInfini 31
(fall 1990):17-26, p.25.
15
For an account of the intellectual pleasures of going beyond morality, see Emil M. Cioran On the
Heights of Despair trans. Ilinca- Zarifopol- Johnston (Chicago &London: University of Chicago Press,
1992). p.120.
110
Friedrich Nietzsche 16
16
17
Airaksinen p. 14
18
19
For discussion, see Jeffrey H. Goldstein, ed. Why We Watch: The Attractions of Violent
Entertainment (New York and Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1998); Jonathan Glover Humanity: A
Moral History of the Twentieth Century (London: Pimlico, 2001). p.55.
20
John Richetti The Marquis de Sade (1740-1814) and the French Libertine Tradition in George
Stade, ed. European Writers: The Age of Reason and the Enlightenment Vols. 3-4 (New York:
Scribner, 1984):615-638, p.632.
111
(LNJ1:213). 21 The taste for fantastical, violent sexual (or sexualized) spectacle is also
common enough, and is scarcely confined to the purely pornographic; one only has to
consider the works of Delacroix. 22 Nietzsche formulates this insight in Beyond Good
and Evil: [a]lmost everything we call higher culture is based on the spiritualization
and intensification of cruelty that is my proposition; the wild beast has not been
laid to rest at all, it lives, it flourishes, it has merely become- deified. 23
The association of mass homicide, spectacle and aesthetics is not unusual in our own
time. In the days following the destruction of the Twin Towers, a number of
prominent cultural figures applauded their destruction as worthy on purely aesthetic
grounds. (Like the Crucifixion, the imagery of the 9/11 attack acquired instant and
enduring iconic power which is, arguably, merely a pious gloss. Sade would perhaps
suggest that Christian iconography, like the endless replays of some catastrophe on
the nightly news, merely satisfies a desire to see suffering on a spectacular scale). 24
Where Sades libertines differ from the aestheticians of 9/11 is their desire to actually
cause such spectacular acts of destruction for purely aesthetic purposes (note that,
despite Sades talk of refinements and style, the pleasure is still to be found
primarily in the infliction of pain). From Juliette:
Refinements enter into the thing, as happens with all pleasures; from this moment this
personal stamp is added, all limits are abolished, atrocity is wound to its topmost pitch,
21
Sade asks whether Michelangelo would have felt pangs of conscience if, for the purposes of
rendering the Crucifixion more accurately, he had crucified a young boy. He also states that everyone
knows that a girl was killed in the production of a painting by Guide (perhaps Guido Reni, known also
as Le Guide {1575-1642}), Madeleine en pleurs. Theodore Gericault (1791 - 1824), whilst working on
his masterpiece The Raft of the Medusa (1818), kept corpses and severed limbs in his studio for
reference.
22
Eugne Delacroixs (1798-1863) The Death of Sardanapalus, featuring an indifferent king watching
his men massacre his concubines in cold blood, is as brutal as anything in Sade.
23
24
Karlheinz Stockhausen, a German composer, described the terrorists actions as the greatest work of
art one can imagine; Damien Hirst, similarly, stated that the terrorists need congratulating because
of their artistic achievement. See Rebecca Allison 9/11 wicked but a work of art, says Damien
Hirst (Guardian, Wednesday September 11, 2002). Gail Haffern, a New Zealand artist, in agreement,
has produced a number of sculptures honouring the aesthetics of the attack. Linda Herrick Tribute to
the Towers, New Zealand Herald September 9, 2002.
112
for the sentiment that produces it exhales it in keeping with the increase or worsening
of the torture; all ones achievements now lie short of ones intentions. The agonies
must be now slow and abominable if they are to quicken the soul at all, and one wishes
that the same life could revive a thousand times over, in order to have the pleasure of
murdering it that often, and that thoroughly.
Each murder is a commentary and critique of the others, each demands
improvement in the next; it is shortly discovered that killing is not enough, one must kill
in hideous style; and though one may be unaware of the fact, lewdness almost always
has the direction of these matters (italics mine;J:791). 25
Sades libertines soon tire of the art of torturing and murdering individuals; eventually
even city-wide arson with sophisticated incendiary munitions, or even genocide,
cannot sate them (LNJ 1:297, 366 ; LNJ 2 :243 ; J :501, 729). The prospect of a
planetary holocaust becomes their ideal. States Curval (in The 120 Days of Sodom):
There are, said Curval, but two or three crimes to perform in this world, and they,
once done, theres no more to be said; all the rest is inferior, you cease any longer to feel.
Ah, how many times, by God, have I not longed to be able to assail the sun, snatch it out
of the universe, make a general darkness, or use that star to burn the world! Oh, that
would be a crime, oh yes, and not a little misdemeanour such as are all the ones we
perform who are limited in a whole years time to metamorphosing a dozen creatures into
lumps of clay (120: 364; similar: J: 774-775, 1185; LNJ 1: 296, 297, 366).
An entire aesthetics of the sublime is implied here and in similar passages. Sades
thought is compatible with two possible explanations. The passage above, and others
like it, expresses the wish to participate in the cosmic processes of destruction, like
Hindu gods: we devastate the planet...and repeople it with new objects, and immolate
these in their turn... (J: 522). Implied here, in a sense similar to Batailles reading, is
the notion of the attainment of oneness with the cosmos through direct involvement
with its processes. Cosmic unity, the Sadeian imperative to maximize destruction, and
the aestheticizing of crime, are united. In what resembles a diabolical fusion of the
principles of Sartre and Nietzsche, Sade proposes an entire lifestyle infused with full
25
A similar tract is Thomas de Quinceys Murder Considered as One of the Fine Arts (1827). See
Thomas de Quincey On Murder Considered as One of the Fine Arts and Other Related Texts
(Whitefish, MT: Kessinger Publishing, 2004).
113
knowledge of the horrors of the world, and also the acceptance that oneself is
responsible for its horrors, through actively participating in them.
This is the external aspect of a Sadeian aesthetics of mass destruction. An
internal aesthetics of the sublime is also compatible with Sades account.
For Kant, the aesthetic experience of the sublime discloses knowledge of ones moral
nature. The sublime experience involves a spectacle of awe-inspiring grandeur; the
starry stars above, or some spectacle of Natures awesome power. Either one feels that
one is physically overwhelmed, or one senses ones utter insignificance. Yet this very
experience reveals to ourselves the metaphysical truth of our intellectual freedom.
Sades description of the sublime resembles this account, but in an inverted way. For
Kant, the moral reality disclosed is our capacity to shape the world as a moral world.
Sade, like Kant, claims to be disclosing an important feature of human psychology,
but in a sense that brings to mind J. Robert Oppenheimer rather than the Moral Law
Within. Sades characters see in volcanic eruptions a confirmation that the world is
characterized by endless, meaningless destruction- it is nature that is the primary
object of sublime contemplation, rather than, for Kant, the moral self. Yet the
aesthetics of the libertines is even more direct than romantic contemplation they also
cause disasters (volcanic eruptions, mass arson and so on ) through the application of
scientific knowledge that is, their rational faculties, and hence their power to
manipulate the natural order of things, and to destroy its inhabitants (LNJ 2 :42).
Sades characters, hence, feel a sense of awe of their own intellectual capacity for
destruction. Further, in discovering in themselves the capacity for such destruction,
and of finding this pleasing, the libertines disclose to themselves the capacity for
absolute moral disregard. Where Kant saw a moral law within, Sade sees, in the
interior of man, only an endless abyss, or the Rausch of Godhead.
3.5 Apathy
The pleasure of mass destruction, or of murder, does not come automatically. Sade
proposes a doctrine of apathy, a complex merging of hedonistic and stoical
principles, in order to encourage the reader to overcome innate resistance to such
pleasures. The reasoning is as follows: the greatest pleasures are criminal; the sense of
guilt prevents one from enjoying committing criminal acts; hence, one must overcome
the feeling of guilt. This is achieved through repetition of the act until the discomfort
is overcome, and the act becomes pleasurable. Many everyday pleasures require a
114
27
This is similar to the opponent process theory, proposed by Richard L. Solomon and John D.
Corbit. In short, the theory is that the overcoming of deep seated repugnances is followed by a rush of
elation, in order to return the body to homeostasis. The theory was originally proposed with drugs in
mind; Baumeister applies it to the pleasure of sadism and killing. R.L. Solomon, J.D. Corbit An
Opponent process theory of motivation: I. Temporal dynamics of affect, Psychological Review 81
(1974):119-145; cited in Roy M. Baumeister Evil: Inside Human Violence and Cruelty (New York:
A.W.H Freeman/ Owl Book, 1999) pp.234-236.
28
Concerning the attractiveness of ugly people, the character Severino remarks: ne voyez-vous pas
tout plein de gens prfrer le gibier faisand la viande frache? (do people not prefer gamey game
to fresh meat? LNJ 2: 83).
115
degradation deal a far stouter blow, the commotion they create is much stronger, the
resultant agitation must hence be more lively (J: 340; 120: 233 also J: 744). Sade
never discusses the overcoming of disgust concerning sexual acts per se, however;
only with regards to unusual paraphilias. 29
Moral apathy involves a different process and rationale. Its attainment is the
excision of normal emotional response, in particular the moral sentiments, principally
guilt and pity. 30 A key assumption here is that ones moral disposition is malleable. 31
Sade, as noted above, confuses this with organic apathy, and on one occasion
proposes that organic apathy causes moral apathy: [i]t is regrettably only too
commonly observed that sensual excess drives out pity in man....[w]hether this is
because most carnal excesses require a kind of apathy of soul or whether the violent
effect they produce on the nervous system weakens the sensitivity by which it
operates, it nevertheless remains a fact that a professional libertine is rarely a
compassionate man (MV.30 ; 263fn). The two types of apathy are quite distinct,
however. Despite his insistence that moral sentiments are due entirely to chimeras
and false education, Sades characters clearly regard the attainment of moral apathy
as a considerable achievement, a fact which acknowledges of the reality of moral
sentiments (J: 450, 548-549, 845, 1053). 32 Organic apathy, on the other hand, is
merely the outcome of simple debauchery.
Sades reasoning is as follows. As the voice of conscience prevents one from
committing terrible crimes, and it is terrible crimes that afford the most shocking
therefore the most pleasurable sensations, it is necessary to overcome conscience.
29
Freud considered the capacity and pleasure of overcoming disgust (in particular the disgust of
seeing the genitals) an essential part of the sexual instinct. Sigmund Freud Volume 7: On Sexuality;
Three Essays on the Theory of Sexuality and other Works. trans. under the general editorship of James
Strachey; ed. Angela Richards (London: Penguin, 1977) p.64.
30
This contradicts the libertines insistence that they cannot help themselves from committing crimes,
or become better people as, clearly, they think that they can become increasingly bad. The malleability
of the moral sense is a recurring theme in Aline et Valcour. Lonore, in the course of her voyage
around the world, loses the moral sentiments of her youth, and Sainville, surrounded by captive slavegirls in Africa, realizes for an instant that he no longer misses his beloved Lonore (AV:274, 639).
32
This fits with the actual experience of people involved in mass murder- they will feel normal,
animal guilt, but will learn to overcome it. For discussion, see Baumeister pp.305-342.
116
Various means are proposed as to how this is accomplished. Clairwil advises Juliette
that this voice is silenced through the application of strength, discipline, and a certain
ruthlessness with oneself (J: 450, also p. 274). A more concrete piece of advice is
that repeated performance of a particular forbidden act will lead to an overcoming of
nausea, fear, or pangs of conscience. Eventually, the student will cross the morality
barrier and learn to enjoy the specified pleasure or task, leading eventually to the
experience of pleasure, or even ecstasy (MV: 124; CL: 35). 33 Explains the character
Tergowitz: accustom yourself awhile to the idea that frightens you, youll soon come
to cherish it: thats the method I have followed to familiarize myself with all known
crimes: I yearned to commit them, but they scared me; fixing my mind upon them, Id
masturbate, and I perform them today as effortlessly as I blow my nose (J: 888).
Sade also notes that moral reorientation is easier for children than adults, suggesting
that moral malleability is a child-like trait. Clairwil gives the following comment on
libertine training:
... the necessary procedure for a young person one was endeavoring to train up for life
would be to blunt [their] sensibility; blunting it, you will perhaps lose a few weak virtues,
but you will eliminate a great many vices, 34 and under a form of government which
severely castigates all vices and which never rewards virtues, it is infinitely better not to
do evil than to strive to do good (J: 278).
Similarly, a young executioner tells Juliette that the training for his rationalized and
scientific ferocity begins early: from childhood on we are taught a system of values
wherein human life is nothing and the law everything (J: 307).
Sades characters also hold the apathetic state to be epistemically privileged; that
is, its attainment is taken to be necessary for deeper insights into the nature of the
world. 35 This is partly because the libertines find that the attainment of new
33
For discussion of the psychology of enjoying overcoming social instincts, and the pleasure of killing,
see C. Fred Alford What Evil means to us (Ithaca: Cornell University Press, 1997) p.102. For a
discussion on the enjoyment of criminal activity, see Baumeister pp.203-249.
34
35
Michel Camus contrasts the apathy of Sades characters with that of the Stoics, for whom apathy was
required for receptivity to the Logos, conceived as cosmic harmony. For Sade, according to Camus, it
is openness to Nature that leads to openness to the Logos. Michel Camus Limpasse mystique du
Libertin In Michel Camus, Philippe Roger, eds.:259-276, p.270.
117
perspectives is itself pleasurable (J: 18). Numbness in some senses is said to enhance
others: ...by numbing two or three of the faculties of sensation one may extract
astonishing things from the others...it is when we have achieved depravation,
insensibility, that Nature begins to yield us the key to her secret workings...(J:710).
Sade associates moral apathy with reason, and interior sensations with morality,
hence, falsity or error. To become apathetic, for Sade, is to encounter the truth that
moral precepts are lies and that the moral conscience is not an intrinsic feature of
human existence. This dichotomy is expressed by the character Prsident de Balmont,
in Aline et Valcour: [q]uand vous cdez au sentiment de la piti plutt quaux
conseils de la raison, quand vous coutez le cur de prfrence lesprit, vous vous
jetez dans un abme derreurs, puisquil nest point de plus faux organes que ceux de
la sensibilit. (Non- libertine) Madame de Blamonts reply reinforces this
dichotomy: jaime mieux tre imbcile et sensible que de possder le gnie de
Descartes (AV: 712).
Sades characters do not apply this principle consistently. They value the interior
sensations associated with pleasure, including the delicious vibrations made by their
moral sense as it is being overridden. Sade associates only moral feelings with error;
pleasurable feelings are invariably described as grounded on truth.
Two problems arise from the attainment of apathy. Throughout Juliette, Sades
characters indicate that the Libertine lifestyle leads to the acquisition of tastes and
manias that cannot be satisfied. Towards the end of the novel, Juliette states that,
despite her enchanted life, I do not cease to want; I consider myself poor; my
desires are infinitely in excess of my possibilities; I would spend twice as much as I
had it; and I leave no stone unturned to increase my wealth, criminal or not, there is
nothing I am unwilling to do for money (my italics; J: 1168; 598, 120: 364).
Secondly, the libertines find that, due to over- stimulus, they are incapable of physical
pleasures at all. Only intellectual pleasures, if any, are left. 36 Rather than taking up
intellectually demanding hobbies, Sades characters propose to imaginatively
reconstruct the notion of crime, hence, morality, despite the fact that they consider it
an arbitrary and meaningless word (J: 170-171). In some cases, notes Chantal
36
Sades account is partly continuous with the views of his contemporaries on the problems related to
libertinage. Firstly, Sade appears to be in agreement with dHolbachs claim that endless debauch
leads to ennui and weariness. DHolbach pp. 99, 256. Cusset notes that this was a common theme in
libertine literature. For discussion, see Cusset No Tomorrow p. 145.
118
Thomas, Sades characters hold that prejudices should remain where their violation
can become pleasurable. 37 This is, on their own terms, an escape into illusion. (An
impoverished conception of pleasure seems to be at play here. Sade appears to hold
that only crime can be pleasurable, even if crime does not exist. It is like saying that
you can only truly enjoy eating bacon if you were brought up an observant Jew or
Muslim, and therefore sense that it is sinful). Clairwil explains that it is illusion
which invests crime with its attractiveness, and a weak spirit encounters greatest
difficulty committing it when, totally self-possessed, illusion there is none (J: 450).
Sade also makes a curious association of the failure of libertinage as a purely
hedonistic project, the sense of emptiness its failure imparts, and the cheapening of
human life. He declares that this sense of emptiness (what we might perhaps call
existential despair) is a proof of the non-divine origin of humanity.
theres the effect of irregular desires: the greater the height they arouse us to, the
greater the emptiness we feel afterward. From this cretins derive proof of Gods
existence; whereas for my part I find here only the most certain proofs of a materialistic
attitude: the more you cheapen your existence, the less Ill be inclined to believe it is the
handiwork of a deity (J: 312).
37
119
The first view is that of Helvtius; the second is that of Nietzsche. The association of power and
pleasure had also been considered by the philosophes. Rousseau notes within himself the potential for
becoming a tyrant, observing that if I were rich, [I would be] a disdainful spectator of the miseries of
the rabble. Jean-Jacques Rousseau Emile or On Education trans. Alan Bloom Penguin (London:
Penguin, 1979) p. 344; Helvtius Treatise on Man Vol. I, pp.130, 134, 201, 310, 311.
For discussion, see Fauskevg p.93. For Nietzsches criticism of Helvtius on this point, see The Will
to Power 751 p.397.
39
40
African tribespeople, initiation into adulthood may require rituals involving flagellation, exposure to
stinging ants or extensive tattooing or scarification. Boris de Rachewiltz Eros Noir: Moeurs sexuelles
de lAfrique de la prhistoire nos jours (Paris : La jeune Parque, 1963) p.191. Sade often associates
coprophilia with sexuality, but this association is not straightforward. Freud discusses the pleasure of
defecation, and of the rituals involving faeces typical of neurotics. For Freud, such pleasures are
120
accounts for Juliettes claim that eating excrement is one of the culminating episodes
of the libertine experience (J: 163). Robert F. OReillys suggestion that coprophilia
and cannibalism in Sade represents a Nietzschean practice of devouring and
reshaping the world may be off the mark, but not by much. Katherine Landolt, more
accurately, suggests that the cultivation of exotic pleasures is a means of overcoming
nature, and bestows upon the libertine the sign of uniqueness, in being able to
overcome an unspeakable nausea. 41
Sades characters, as discussed in the section on Bataille, attain mastery over the
fear of death, whether for the sake of self- mastery or for the pursuit of physical
pleasure. They treat death as utterly trivial; a last cheap thrill, possibly accompanied
by a final arc of ejaculate. Having no truck with either God or the good of the
community, they have no problem with suicide or death through misadventure. Timo
Airaksinen, as noted in Chapter I, reads Sade as essentially an advocate of a profound
perversion. He associates the libertines death wish with the conceptual failure of
Sades entire a-morality. Airaksinen defines genuine good as what is desirable in
the long run: safety and pleasure. Accordingly, he characterizes Sades perversity as
being essentially self deception and negligence: evil is damage- but never
injury-and appears to be a decisional error that is brought about by some kind of
ignorance, mistake, or weakness. [...] One cannot aim at evil, because logically
speaking ones aims are the good of the person. All evil collapses back into akrasia,
intelligible owing to the richness of nerve endings in the mucous membrane of the anus, but he does
not discuss actual coprophilia (Freud Sexuality p.104). Havelock Ellis repeats Freuds suggestion that
an association of faeces and urine with eroticism is due to childish theories concerning sexuality. Ellis
also takes the childs fascination for urination and defecation to be a rudimentary form of the artistic
impulse, and at the same time a manifestation of power. Havelock Ellis Psychology of Sex: A
Manual for Students third impression (London: William Heinemann {Medical Books} Ltd, 1934)
p.139.
41
Katherine Landolt The Attempt and Failure to Break Out of a Materialist Framework as performed
by the Characters of the Histoire de Juliette under the direction of the Marquis de Sade in Papers in
Romance Vol. 2 No. 3 (spring 1980):182-193: 186, 191; Robert F. OReilly Desire in Sades Les 120
journes de Sodome, Studies on Voltaire and the 18th Century Vol. 217 (1983):249-256, p.251. See
also Nolle Chtelet Le libertine table in Michel Camus, Philippe Roger, eds.: 67-83, p.76. Note
also that, curiously, Sades libertines demonstrate their transcendence over merely human instinct in
the manner of medieval penitents- by filling their mouths with filth. For discussion of this practice, see
Simone de Beauvoir The Second Sex translated by H.M. Parshley (London: Picador, 1988) p.685.
121
42
43
Airaksinen p. 36
Most philosophers have died in their beds. A. Quinton Deaths of philosophers In the Oxford
Glanville Williams writes: [a] study by E. Stengel and Nancy Cook indicated that the great majority
of so-called attempted suicides were not on fact single-minded efforts at self destruction but had a
hidden appeal character; in other words, the suicide seemed to gamble with his life, consciously or
subconsciously hoping that either the attempt would succeed or, if it failed, his life would be improved
as a consequence of the attempt. Glanville Williams Suicide in The Encyclopedia of Philosophy
Vol. VIII. Paul Edwards. ed. (New York: Macmillan, 1967) p.44.
45
122
over another person. 46 Clairwil, commenting on the rush she obtains from poisoning
people, comments that it is exquisite to have the lives of others arbitrarily in ones
power (J: 523). Likewise, states Princess Borghese, [s]tripping people of their
liberty amuses me, I like holding captives; I know that while they are incarcerated my
victims suffer: this perfidious idea excites me, I should love to be able to maintain
entire nations in this cruel situation (J: 712). Sade also assumes that that all powerful
politicians, in fact anyone with any authority at all, whether judges, teaches, surgeons,
or priests- will abuse their positions.47 Sade portrays all political figures as being
equally cynical, and equally in the thrall of the pleasures of total power. The figures of
the ancien rgime are described as monsters; the revolutionaries of Juliette plan to rid
the world of ideological imperfections, by using assassination or other terroristic
tactics, or through massacring entire economic or religious classes. 48 Whether power
corrupts or simply attracts the already immoral is unclear, as Sades characters assume
that desire for power over others is a universal trait. States Juliette: I affirm that the
fundamental, profoundest, and keenest penchant in man is incontestably to enchain his
fellow creatures and to tyrannize them with all his might (J: 317; also pp. 861, 966n;
AV: 461). Sade also suggests that the character traits of the despot are the
requirements of political ascendency rather than purely its negative effects on the
personality (AV: 462; J: 757).
46
For discussion of this phenomenon, see Baumeister pp.242-243; Ervin Staub The Roots of Evil: The
origins of Genocide and other Group Violence (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1989)
pp.128, p.133, 139,149, 226.
47
Despite his political incertitude, Sade presented himself as an acute observer of the abuse of power,
commenting in an official pamphlet: [c]itizens...I know where the abuse of power leads...I have
studied men and know them; nothing is more difficult than to set limits on delegated authority. Sade
uvres compltes (Paris: Cercle du Livres Prcieux, 1964) 11:173. Quoted by Shelby Spruell: The
Marquis de Sade- Pornography or Political Protest?, Proceedings of the Annual Meeting of the
Western Society for French History 9 (1982):238-249, pp. 246-247. Helvtius, La Rochefoucauld,
Montesquieu, la Mettrie and Rousseau had already noted the egoism in human nature, and the resulting
problems concerning the selection of leaders. For discussion, see Fauskevg pp. 93, 105.
48
In the name of a global revolution and a universal republic, the Northern Lodge of Stockholm plans
on exterminating all the kings of the world, the extermination of Catholicism, and establishing the
liberty of the world. Yet the means to be employed include poisoning water supplies and causing
epidemics in order to weaken despotic governments, and the elimination of individual freedom (J:
864-870). For discussion on the dangers of moral absolutist thinking, see Baumeister Chapter 6,
pp.169-203; Staub p.76, 88.
123
49
Fauskevg p. 70. Sades description of the very wealthy largely follows Helvtius dictum that gold
is a sorcerer that frequently converts an honest man into a knave, and that wealth is continuous with
power. Voltaire also made a close association of wealth, economic arrangements and human rights
abuse, in particular slavery. See Candide and other tales pp.160, 165. See also Helvtius Treatise on
Man Vol. II p.282n; Fauskevg p.69.
50
The preponderance of castles, dungeons, caves and fortressed islands in Sade is frequently
commented upon, as are the feudal relationships that Sades libertine characters maintain with their
victims and employees (who are never free to simply leave, and are frequently killed; LNJ 2: 17-18).
For discussion see Fauskevg pp.110, 112,116, 117.
51
In Juliette, Ferdinand, King of Naples, holds a public event each year in which the poorer townsfolk
are allowed to fight each other in the rush to grab items from a huge pile of luxury goods and
foodstuffs. Hundreds of people are crushed in the struggle (J: 1000-1001). This scene is similar to that
witnessed by Sade himself in Italy (see note 13, in this chapter).
52
For discussion see Michel Camus, Limpasse Mystique du Libertin In Michel Camus, Philippe
124
science associated with the 18th Century, Sades characters conceive of science as the
power to destroy in spectacular fashion. 53 The chemist Almani declares that he has
spent his life studying natures secrets simply because he wants to cause a volcano to
erupt at his prompting (LNJ 2 :42-43); Count Bracciani uses advanced incendiary
weapons to set fire to all Rome, and so on. This marks the zenith of the Libertine
vision.
For discussion, see Robert S. Baker The Nightmare of the Frankfurt School: the Marquis de Sade
and the Problem of Morality in Aldous Huxleys Dystopian Narrative In Nugel- Bernfried, ed. Now
More than Ever: Proceedings of the Aldous Huxley Centenary Symposium: Munster, 1994 (New York:
Peter Lang, 1995):245-260, p.258. Philippe Roger suggests that the increasingly sophisticated torture
machines in Sade are a parody of scientific progress. Philippe Roger La Philosophie dans le pressoir
p.60.
54
Sade, in Voyage dItalie, notes that the very rarity of the bizarre mania of doing evil for the sole
pleasure of doing it... spares me the trouble of offering an analysis, although he suggests that it is due
to a disordering of the imagination. Voyage d Italie (Paris: Tchou, 1967) p.356. Quoted in Berman
Thoughts and Themes p.163.
125
(Borchamps, commenting on his rape and torture of a girl: [c]an you tell me what it
was bred such feelings in me? I myself do not know; I simply describe to you what I
experienced; J: 901; Similar; 120; 492, 495).
In general, as noted above, it is the thirst for the sensation of power that Sades
characters crave, which itself suggests an inner weakness. This weakness, owing to
the lucidity, vigour and thoroughness of the libertines, cannot be reduced to simple
akrasia, that is, weakness of will, self-deception and negligence. A naturally strong
person, assumedly, is not preoccupied with acquiring a sense of power, or would even
know what such a sense would be like, given that this is a continuous state. A
different type of strength is the ability to overcome fear, and to confront stronger
adversaries. Sades characters are, on this view, weak, typically attacking, with
overwhelming force, the physically weak, defenceless and unsuspecting (a large
number of their victims are children, a fact seldom mentioned by the specialists). The
libertines are essentially bullies. They very rarely destroy or even challenge their
equals, and when they kill their peers they do it by stealth and deceit, typically using
poison, or a quick shove over a precipice. It is not the vanquishing of a worthy
adversary, and the possibility of defeat, that gives the libertine pleasure, but the sense
of total power: [t]he more atrocious the hurt he inflicts upon the helpless, the greater
shall be the voluptuous vibrations in him (J: 119; similar: 120:251).
Sade makes a number of specific observations concerning the nature of sadism.
Saint-Fond, Prime Minister of France, enjoys humiliating, degrading and torturing his
victims before, or whilst, killing them. When Juliette notes that he would be quite
terrifying to his many victims, Saint- Fond gives the following reply : the very
essence of my enjoyment is in making those victims so suffer in the selfsame way
from the thing which plagues my existence (my italics; J: 248). Saint-Fond is driven
to torture through the wish to project his pain onto someone else, although he does not
go into details as to what this pain is. Similarly, Omphale, a pious friend of Justine,
observes that [t]hose who are wretched are consoled when they see those around
them suffer (MV: 77). The desire to inflict pain, then, is a desire to project ones own
psychic pain onto another person. 55
55
This matches the observations of C. Fred Alford, who applies a similar model to the psychology of
sadistic behaviour, and Richard G. Rappaport with regards to serial killers. Alford interviewed working
people, prisoners, and college students to discover how people understand evil. He concluded that
126
127
56
This is a mistranslation. Delon notes that taquinisme in fact meant sadism in Sades time. See
The male libertine characters are often described as having problems with maintaining erections,
discharge or orgasm, which is often described as more violent and painful than pleasing (J:1097;
120:274, 292, 313). Restif (also spelled Rtif) de la Bretonne wrote that old men are especially sadistic,
and that they derive pleasure in proportion to the youth and beauty of the victim (an observation that
perhaps coheres with Sades suggestion of a link of sadism and impotence). Rtif de La Bretonne
Lanti-Justine ou les dlices de lamour (Paris: La Bibliothque prive, 1969) p.1. Cited in Franoise
Laugaa-Traut pp. 89-91.
128
the authors own views, or is meant to appear to be representative of the authors own
thoughts. The second observation, concerning vengeance, is made by Bersac, an actor
and a minor character. Though not a sadistic and homicidal libertine, he shares with
them the view that crime is natural, and holds that wars and tyranny are necessary to
the order of things (AV:624- 626). His point of view, therefore, is not opposed to that
of Sades dominant voice. It is also significant that Sade makes these comments in
Aline et Valcour, the only full length novel which he desired to be publicly associated
with, being published (unlike Juliette and Justine, which he strenuously disavowed)
in his own name. 58
Several other suggestions have been made concerning Sades work and the
psychological dynamics of sadism, weakness and loneliness. Bourbon Busset reads
Sades sadism as symptomatic of a spiritual weakness, stating that [p]ersonne de plus
loign de lrotisme sadique quun homme fort, qui trouve dans la sexualit
lpanouissement normal de sa vitalit. 59 The will to inflict suffering, according to
Geoffrey Gorer, is related to the desire to alter ones environment and its inhabitantsthat is, the creative desire in man (this could be aligned with Bussets interpretation,
insofar as weakness can be taken to be, or is analogous to, a lack of creativity). In its
positive mode, for Gorer, this desire takes the form of creativity. The sadist lacks the
talent to enjoy the power of pleasing or impressing others with his art, and so is
limited to torturing people for his egoistic gratification. A healthier person who feels
the satisfaction of having an impact on others, of a less malignant sort (Rousseaus
feeling of satisfaction of others enjoying his opera, for example) does not require that
others are crushed or reduced to a subhuman state. 60
58
One could hazard a Freudian reading of the relationship between Sades anonymous, libertine texts,
Justine, Juliette and The 120 Days of Sodom, and those texts that he gladly had published under his
own name. His libertine works are the dream state (they were anonymous, and Sade always
strenuously disavowed them), where the narcissistic ego, disinhibited, lives out its fantasy of wish
fulfilment, and the official Aline et Valcour represents the superego; the socialized mask. The
perspective of the waking state of Aline et Valcour allows for an understanding of the mentality of the
other works, which is not possible from within the libertine perspective.
59
60
Jacques de Bourbon Busset La ngation rotique, La Table Rond 19, no.1 (1963) :109-112, p.111.
Gorer defines sadism as the pleasure felt from the observed modifications on the external world
produced by the will of the observer. I would add a). that this extends to both the world and its
inhabitants, and b). it is not appropriate do define sadism as a general will to power, although the
129
The observations of Gorer and Busset fits closely with the Motive Psychology of
Hans Morgenthau. Power and love, for Morgenthau, spring from the same root of
loneliness. Love seeks to unite people by dissolving the boundary between them;
power involves the imposing of one will over the other. Power can be manifested, in a
positive way, through creativity, or negatively, through control, which in an extreme
form involves the inflicting of pain. 61 In this sense, it is significant that Sades
characters, even when they associate with each other, frequently express loneliness,
whether because they are physically separated from others, or because they regard
everyone else as mere tools or objects (J:583; LNJ 1 : 152, 237, 299; 2 :42). Minski
the Russian cannibal giant, the most isolated of Sades characters, takes his despotism
to the point of turning human beings into furniture, or food. He is cut off from his
species to such an extent that he wishes he had not already raped and killed every
member of his family so that I might have the pleasure of butchering them anew.
Yet he feels empty: [w]hats left for me these days? he laments, surrounded by his
victims: I have nothing but ordinary victims to sacrifice, my heart grows heavy, all
pleasures fade, they pall, the enjoyment is gone- (J: 598, also 584). Sades characters
have no intimate relations with others and have no creative projects. 62 They leave
nothing but corpses and ash in their wake.
In short, aspects of Sades work imply that his sadists are not sophisticated
eroticists, but spiritually weak people, in some emotional pain, who lack meaningful
contact with others, and have an overwhelming need to feel that they have power over
others or their environment. Not only does this portrait undermine a straightforward
reading of the Sadeian text as an advocacy of sadism; it also undermines Sades (and
Batailles) claim that there is a direct and natural link between the sexual instinct and
the will to inflict pain and death (Sades account of human sexuality, discussed in the
next chapter, is disturbing nevertheless). 63
association is basically sound. Gorer p. 156; Jean-Jacques Rousseau The Confessions trans. Anon
(1904). (Ware: Wordsworth, 1996) p.368.
61
For discussion, see H. Morgenthau Love and Power, Commentary 33 no.3 (March 1962), 247-251.
Sades characters have sex with each other, and are occasionally on friendly terms, but the two
domains are kept distinct. This will be discussed in the following chapter.
63
Simultaneous orgasm of the killer, typically described as a dlicieuse jouissance, and the death of
the victim is also a common motif (LNJ 1:214, 433, 434; LNJ 2: 12, 19 28, 29, 73, 186, 232, 278; J:
130
A final word on the relationship between weakness and sadism is required. In all
of these observations, the sadistic will is associated with pain and misfortune, and the
inability to passively accept ones inflictions. But weakness alone does not account
for the manifestation of cruelty. Further, not every libertine character goes through
hardships something else is necessary to enable sadism. The difference between
the two psychological types (the sadist, and the individual who merely endures
hardships) is, in short, the difference between Justine and Juliette. Justine goes
through trials that do not even harden her heart, let alone make her a sadist, yet she is
not so different from her sister. She is equally capable of irrational, risky behaviour,
and falling in with the wrong crowd, as evidenced by her love for the bisexual
matricide the Marquis de Brassac, despite his depravity(Sades term; MV: 35). She
is also as familiar with the doctrine of the libertines as is Juliette, and also seems a
little morally autistic, for example when she tests out a suspected poison on the family
dog (MV:46:) Unlike Juliette, who for the most part merely agrees with and repeats
what she has been told, Justine frequently engages in debate with her captors, at times
with aggression. She is also, by the end of La Nouvelle Justine, suspiciously reluctant
to adopt a more normal lifestyle. Although not a twin (Juliette is a year older), Justine
and Juliette are psychically connected- when Juliette experiences a pang of remorse,
she has a prophetic dream involving her sister (J: 549).There are two, crucial,
differences between Justine and Juliette. Firstly, Justine adheres to absolute moral
principles. Secondly, Justine has inner restraints that prevent her from following
destructive or criminal impulses (or even to follow common sense, such as going to
the police, or trusting monks, regardless of what they do to her). 64 Juliette would
attribute her lack of restraint- her freedom from the chimeras of remorse and
1183; 120: 570-762). Many of Sades critics take it for granted that this association of libido and
destruction is valid, yet in defending the association they typically go no further than appealing to
Sades authority as a psychologist. See, for example, Lorna Berman The Marquis de Sade and
Courtly Love, Eighteenth Century Fiction 11 no. 3 (April 1999):285-300, p.286; Frances Ferguson
Sade and the Pornographic Legacy, Representations 0 issue 36 (Autumn, 1991):1-21, p. 7 ; Josu V
Harari Dun raison lautre: le dispositif Sade, Studies on Voltaire and the Eighteenth Century 230
(1985) :273-282, p.282; Josephs Sade and Woman p.99 ; Beatrice Fink The Case for a Political
System in Sade, Studies in Voltaire and the Eighteenth Century vol. 88 (1972): 493-512, p. 506;
Camille Paglia Sexual Personae ; the cancelled preface In Paglia Sex, Art and American Culture
(London: Viking, 1992) 101-124, pp.105-106.
64
131
conscience to her philosophical education; yet Justine has received essentially the
same education. This suggests that the crucial difference between the two sisters is not
reducible to intelligence or education. It could be innate; on the other hand, it could be
grounded in the freedom to choose between good and evil.
132
133
4.1 Introduction.
There is little agreement on what Sades writings on sex and gender entail. Angela
Carter, Camille Paglia, and Annie le Brun hold that Sade gives a positive message of
liberation to women; others hold that Sade is the very embodiment of misogyny. 1
Sade has been praised as a great erotic liberator; others find in his writing only
coldness, prudery and nausea. 2 As for the common claim that Sade was a pioneering
sexologist, he was clearly preoccupied such paraphilias as necrophilia, incest,
paedophilia and bestiality, though he made no attempt to explain such practices
(LNJ1:199; 2: 12, 192, 385; J: 189, 745, 746; AV: 512; 120:297, 306). 3 Sade argued
in favour of legalizing paedophilia, and the theme of child prostitution and sexual
slavery frequently appears in his work. In Philosophy in the Bedroom, the rape of
children is discussed and apparently advocated (PB: 320; LNJ 2: 28, 29, 66).
Otherwise, Sades thoughts on sex and prudery are largely in keeping with that of the
philosophes, in particular Diderot, Voltaire, Helvtius (who proposed the use of
women captured from vanquished states as sex slaves), La Mettrie (who expressed the
1
For an account of Sade as claustrophobic, mechanical or prudish, rather than erotic, see Didier Sade :
Un criture du dsir p.7 ; also Crocker Au cur p.60; Michel Delon Le Corps Sadien, Europe
835-836 (Nov- Dc. 1998) :22-33,27 ; Batrice Fink La Langue de Sade, French Literature Series
10 (1983) :103-122, pp.108-109. Roger La Philosophie dans le pressoir p.56.
3
For discussion, see Batrice Didier Inceste et criture chez Sade, Lettres Nouvelles, Mai-Juin
(1972) : 150-158 ; Stphane Morale et nature, p.39 Richetti p.624; Roger G. Lacombe Sade et ses
masques pp.261, 262.
133
wish to die surrounded with beautiful women, an image repeated in Sades Dialogue
between a Priest and a Dying Man) and the libertin writers, as mentioned in Chapter I
(PB: 175; J: 515; 522). 4 Sade also refers to earlier philosophers on the topic of sexual
mores, for example Diogenes the Cynics penchant for having sex in public (J: 63).
The accounts of the explorers Louis Antoine de Bougainville (1729-1811) and Cook
also exerted an influence on the sexual imagination of 18th century France, Sade
included. 5 On the subject of sex, another major influence on Sade was Restif de la
Bretonne. Bretonne sought to distinguish himself from the work of Sade, arguing that
his own works were concerned with erotic pleasure (so that women could better
serve their husbands), and described Sade as a vivisector. One of the few writers of
the time to address Sades work directly, Bretonne wrote an antidote to Sades
Justine, entitled the Anti-Justine. What is indisputable, despite these intellectual links,
is that Sades treatment of sex goes far beyond all other discourses, whether the
relative reserve of the philosophes or the jovial innocence of the libertin authors. 6
There are two distinct ideologies in Sades work concerning sexuality and
gender, a fact that accounts for the bifurcation of interpretations. Each is directly
related to the two doctrines that emerged in Chapter II. The first ideology, which
describes sexuality in terms of consumption and aggression, is linked to the principle
of a natural order characterized by destruction, and the view that human agency as
continuous with this natural order. Call this the Bataille doctrine. 7 The second
If either a beautiful slave or concubine become among the people the reward of talents, virtue, or
valour, the manners of that people will not be readily corrupted. It was in the heroic ages that the
Cretans imposed on the Athenians the tribute of ten beautiful virgins, from which Theseus released
them. Helvtius A Treatise on Man (ii.291). See also Helvtius A Treatise on Man Vol. I p.129, 146;
Vol. II pp.75, 219-221; Helvtius Essays on the Mind pp.83, 114; La Mettrie p.111
On the relationship between Diderot and Sade on sexuality, see Brissenden.
5
Available in Sades time were the following: Louis Bougainville Description dun Voyage autour du
monde (Paris: 1771-72); James Cook Journal dun voyage autour du monde en 1768, 1769, 1770, et
1771, traduit de lAnglais par M. de Frville (Paris: 1773). Sade gives paginated references to both
Cook and Bougainville in the footnotes to Aline et Valcour (AV: 226n, 261n).
6
Laugaa-Traut pp.90, 176. Sade mentions Bretonne in Juliette and Reflections on the Novel (J: 461;
The Bataille doctrine coheres with that aspect of Sades work that Bataille correctly identifies, rather
than being an accurate reflection of Batailles thought. More pedantically, it could be termed the
134
doctrine rejects all teleology, treats sexuality as merely the means to physical
pleasure, and (ostensibly) adheres to the Utilitarian ethic of pleasure maximization
across a population. Call this the Benthamite doctrine. I will discuss these two
doctrines in turn, before noting their commonalities, and the way in which Sade
attempts, with difficulty, to bring them together.
Batailles Sade doctrine. I do not mean to say that what I call the Bataille doctrine is an accurate
portrayal of Batailles philosophy.
8
For a discussion of Sades relation to Diderot, see Batlay and Fellows Diderot et Sade, p.455.
135
David M. Buss The Evolution of Desire: Strategies of Human Mating (New York: Basic Books, 2003)
p.130.
10
Obviously, evolutionary theory strongly suggests the implausibility of Sades account of human
nature. Sades characters typically rape, tend to kill every woman they rape, and kill all the infants
present, in particular their own, or abandon them to the seraglios (harems) of their secret societies.
For discussion on the relationship between orgasm and insemination, see Buss pp.230, 231. On the
Renaissance view that female orgasm played a role in conception, see Laqueur p. 102.
136
as wolves love lambs so lovers love their love. 11 There are also similarities in the
thought of Kant, Sartre, and Freud). 12 Some have rejected the association of sexuality
and sexual license with aggression entirely, dismissing the notion as groundless
conservative scaremongering. 13 Another possibility is that sadism and sex go together
insofar as sexualized violence and humiliation is all the more traumatizing, given the
deeply intimate nature of sexual contact. The psychological torture and humiliation of
Iraqi prisoners in Abu Ghraib prison in 2004 was clearly sexualized, insofar as it
involved nudity, forced masturbation and sexualized poses, but the motive was not
straightforwardly sexual. Whether such acts were primarily sadistic or primarily
sexual, or whether rape is primarily sexual or primarily an act motivated by cruelty, is
11
Lucretius On the Nature of the Universe trans. R.E. Latham (London: Penguin, 1983) p.164; Plato
Phaedrus in The Phaedrus, Lysis and Protagoras of Plato trans. J. Wright (London: Macmillan and
Co, 1888) p.37. The latter quote is cited in Crocker Au cur p.68.
12
Sigmund Freud considered the need to respect the sexual partner as detrimental to sexual satisfaction,
writing that the man almost always feels his respect for the woman acting as a restriction on his sexual
activity, and only develops full potency when he is with a debased sexual object; and this in turn is
partly caused by the entrance of perverse components into his sexual aims, which he does not venture
to satisfy with a woman he respects. Sigmund Freud Volume 7 On Sexuality: Three Essays on the
Theory of Sexuality and other Works trans. James Strachey; ed. James Strachey & Angela Richards
(London: Penguin, 1977) p.254, also p.236. See also Freud Collected papers (London: Hogarth Press,
1950) IV, p.210. Yet Freud also associated sadism with primitive or childish associations of sex with
blood and violence, or (in the context of penis envy) a sense of powerlessness (Freud Sexuality pp. 71,
111, 115, 198,199, 200, 252, 268, 321). Havelock Ellis, like Freud, associates sadism with childishness
and impotence, and also suggests that sadism is not sexual at all, instead viewing it as active
schadenfreude. Ellis Psychology of Sex pp. 76, 173, 175.
Immanuel Kant also held that the sexual act to be deeply degrading for both parties, but in
particular because it leads to the objectification of the other person, and because it leads to animality.
His only solution- a contract to use each others genitalia- suggests an essentially masturbatory
conception of sex. Immanuel Kant Lectures on Ethics ed. Peter Heath & J.B. Schneewind; trans. Peter
heath. (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1997) p.156, 159, 378. 404. I thank Robert C.
Solomon for bringing this text to my attention. Finally, Jean-Paul Sartre describes sexual desire as
fundamentally an urge to subjugate and enslave the other person. Masochism occurs for Sartre where
one attempts to escape ones essential freedom, and making oneself an object; sadism occurs where the
sadist attempts to make an object of the other. Jean-Paul Sartre Being and Nothingness: a
phenomenological essay on ontology trans. by Hazel E. Barnes (New York: Washington Square Books,
1992) pp 474- 482, 511-522,781.
13
For discussion, see Fred R. Berger Pornography, Sex and Censorship in Alan Soble, ed.
Philosophy of Sex (Totowa, New Jersey: Rowman & Littlefield publishers, Inc., 1980) :322-347; !
137
in fact a question that Sades work is not clear on. This is because he makes little
distinction between simple sexual pleasure, cruelty, and the pleasure of arson or
poisoning, all of which are associated with sexual excitement (J: 240, 704, 987).
According to the Bataille doctrine, simply put, ideal sex is sadistic rape, insofar as it is
violent, cruel, and non-consensual. 14
Sades description of sex as simple pleasure is common to both the Bataillian
and Benthamite modes. It clashes with a deeply held belief that sexuality is, or ought
to be, associated with direct, positive communication with a loved one, or at least
someone one feels both physical and emotional attachment to. In the words of
Aristophanes, sexual love is to heal the wound in human nature. 15 Call this the
communicative account of sexuality. Several philosophers, notably Robert C.
Solomon and Thomas Nagel, have attempted to define sexuality as such, Nagel
going as far as to define sex (following Sartre) as having a relational structure: it
involves a desire that ones partner be aroused by the recognition of ones desire that
he or she be aroused. 16 Consequently, non-communicative sex (insofar as it does not
follow this structure) is considered perverse, or at least problematic. A small-scale
orgy, for example, reasons Nagel, may degenerate into mutual epidermal
stimulation by participants otherwise isolated from each other. 17
Sades account is no doubt distasteful for anyone who takes the communicative
model to be morally, qualitatively, or even aesthetically superior, and it is tempting to
reject his picture of sexuality as simple consumption as merely a reflection of his
autistic understanding of human relations. This is too easy.
It is necessary to distinguish between the prescriptive and descriptive roles of a
philosophy of sex- that is, between a sexual morality and a natural history of human
sexuality. We can fully agree that non-communicative sex is bad sex; but it is still
14
15
Solomon does not think that communicative sex need be necessarily pleasant, suggesting that the
expression of dislike or anger may be non-perverse. Robert C. Solomon Sexual Paradigms In Alan
Soble, ed. Philosophy of Sex: Contemporary readings (Totowa, New Jersey: Rowman &Littlefield,
Publishers, Inc: 1980): 89-98; pp.96, 97; Thomas Nagel Sexual Perversion In Soble ed. Philosophy
of Sex: 76-88, p.84
17
138
sex, and may still reflect something of our nature. As a prescriptive account of sex,
Sades Bataille doctrine can be dismissed out of hand for obvious reasons. But the
insistence that non-communicative sex or even rape is less enjoyable for all men, or
even perverse (in the same sense that any immoral act is not necessarily perverse)
for all men and across cultures and history- is questionable. Sade bases his account of
sexuality on the historical record, and accounts of other cultures, a well as his own
psychological speculations. By contrast, Solomon and Nagels treatment of sexuality,
insofar as it is a description of sexuality, may well reflect the philosophers vice of
assuming local cultural norms, or even personal preference, to be universal truths.
Further, there is something of a false dichotomy in the debate between
communicative sex and (merely) pleasurable sex. One can accept the prescription
of sexuality as communication without denying the idea of sexual activity as
pleasurable in its own right, or even as an art or an aesthetic. By the same token, nostrings, merely indulgent sex with another willing hedonist may still give the
momentary Heimlichkeit of shared pleasure. Nagels suggestion that a preoccupation
with sexual technique is sadistic, as it prevents one from renouncing the role of
agent, I think, reflects the narrowness of this dichotomy. 18
On the one hand, the Communicative Model is found in a number of cultures.
Shared sexual pleasure, communication, and psychological compatibility are central
principles of the Kama Sutra of Vatsyayana and other erotic texts of the East. 19
Religious teaching (notably, not Christian teaching) also emphasises the importance
of communication and shared erotic pleasure. In Talmudic law, sexual satisfaction of
the wife is regarded as so central that its absence is considered just grounds for
divorce; likewise, the prophet Muhammad emphasises the importance of foreplay,
stating that sex without it is a form of cruelty. 20 Lucretius, one of the few classical
thinkers that Sade cites, also thought that the pleasure of sex is shared. 21 Even
mainstream pornography maintains the illusion of direct communication; the model
18
19
The Kama Sutra of Vatsyayana trans. Sir Richard Burton and F.F. Arbuthnot (London: Thorsons,
1999).
20
Adin Steinsaltz The Essential Talmud trans. Chaya Galai (New York: Bantam, 1976) p.133.
Geraldine Brooks Nine Parts of Desire: The Hidden World of Islamic Women (New York: Anchor
Doubleday, 2003) p.39.
21
Lucretius p.168.
139
makes eye contact with the camera, as if to simulate face to face communication with
the masturbator. 22
Yet, in fact, the principal of communicative, mutually pleasurable sex is not a
cultural universal, and anthropological data tends to support Sades (descriptive)
conception of sexuality rather than that of Nagel and Solomon. Many cultural
practices are consistent with the view that sex is the use of anothers body as a means
to pleasure, or that the pleasure of the other person (usually the woman) is irrelevant,
if not actually undesirable. Otto Kiefer, in Sexual Live in Ancient Rome, writes that
the Romans of antiquity regarded sexual activity as sensual satisfaction and woman
as mans plaything, noting that this was the opinion of Ovid. 23 David M. Buss notes
that some cultures (typically those where women are not granted the same rights as
men) lack a concept of female orgasm. Where the existence of female sexual pleasure
is acknowledged, it is, in some cultures, deliberately eradicated through
clitoridectomy. 24 Prostitution is also a widespread cultural phenomenon (frequently
supported by local cultural practises, as in the case of the Devadasis of India, who
are forced into slavery as temple prostitutes), as is the sequestering of women for the
exclusive sexual use a handful of powerful men (J: 317). 25 Buss also notes that male
fantasies often involve large numbers of practically anonymous partners, and focus on
physical aspects of the partner rather than feelings. 26 Evolutionary anthropologist
22
For discussion, see Jennifer Lyon Bell Character and Cognition in Modern Pornography
Otto Kiefer Sexual Life in Ancient Rome trans. by Anon, from Kulturgeschichte Roms unter
Besonderer Berckschtigung der Rmischen Sitten ( London : Abbey Library, 1976) p.225.
24
W. H. Davenport writes: in most of the societies for which there are data, it is reported that men
take the initiative and, without extended foreplay, proceed vigorously toward climax without much
regard for achieving synchrony with the womans orgasm. Again and again, there are reports that
coitus is primarily completed in terms of the mans passions and pleasures, with scant attention paid to
the womans response. If women do experience orgasm, they do so passively. W. H. Davenport Sex
in cross-cultural perspectives in F.A. Beach, ed. Human sexuality in four perspectives (Baltimore: the
Johns Hopkins Press, 1977):115-163. Cited in Buss p. 226; see also Buss p.138.
25
. The monopoly of a powerful minority of men of sexual access to women of fertile age (whether as
Bruce Ellis and Donald Symons write: [t]he most striking feature of [male fantasy] is that sex is
sheer lust and physical gratification, devoid of encumbering relationships, emotional elaboration,
140
Barbara Smuts has observed that societies in which men rarely attack or rape women
are the exception, not the norm. 27 Susan Brownmiller, in Against Our Will, notes that
rape in warfare is a widespread practice that goes as far back as there have been
written records. 28 Sade writes: Greek commanders gave their soldiers the right [to
rape] as a reward for valour. After the capture of Carbines, the army of Tarentum [les
Tarentins] collected all the boys, the virgins, and the young women who could be
unearthed in the town, stripped them and exposed them in the market place, where
everybody chose what he wanted... (J: 182; III: 340). Sade also notes the custom
of lending wives and daughters out to travellers and guests: [a] traveller arriving in
Pegu rents a girl for the duration of his stay in the country; with her he does whatever
he pleases; afterward, much enriched by her experience, she returns to her family and
if anything finds a surfeit of suitors eager to marry her (J: 183). Ritual uses of sexual
intercourse (the rites of Dionysus for example), and the use of sex purely for
procreation (as in Catholic tradition) also fall outside the communicative model,
insofar as the Other is merely a means to an end.
The rejection of the communicative model is not, of course, unknown in our
own culture. A number of writers (Catherine Millet, Michel Houellebecq, and Henry
Miller, for example) have written of the pleasures, or the state of ecstasy peculiar to
commitment-free sex with strangers, or the orgy. 29 As Buss argues, there is no
compelling reason to think that this attitude is particularly neurotic, immature or
perverse (whether it is moral is a separate issue). 30 Hence, Sades account of sex as a
description of human, in particular, male sexuality cannot be ruled out.
complicated plot lines, flirtation, courtship, and extended foreplay. These fantasies betray a
psychology attuned to seeking sexual access to a variety of partners. B.J. Ellis and D. Symons Sex
differences in sexual fantasy: an evolutionary psychological approach, Journal of Sex Research 27
(1990): 527-556. Quoted in Buss p.82.
27
Barbara B. Smuts Male aggression against women: An evolutionary perspective In Human Nature,
Susan Brownmiller Against Our Will: Men, women, and rape (New York: Bantam Books, 1975).
For discussion, see Arno Karlen, Threesomes: Studies in Sex, Power and Intimacy (New York:
Buss p.215.
141
Only in these multiple and iterated extravagances does a girls true virtue reside; the more
she gives herself, the more lovable she is; the more she fucks, the more happiness she
distributes and the more she is instrumental to her countrymens happiness [t]hey are
sordid barbarians, these husbands who stick by the vain pleasure of plucking a rose: its
despotism, they claim this right at the expense of other mens well-being (J: 62).
Sade proposes that mutual aid, hence, having as much sex as possible with as many
(here, men) as possible, is the meaning of human existence, again appealing to the
general interest.
Is anyone able to tell me, for I sincerely wish to know, of what use a prudent, wellbehaved woman can be to society? And whether there is anything more superfluous than
the practice of this virtue which, with every passing day, only further numbs and mines
our sex?Up until the time a girl marries, of what conceivable advantage can preserving
her virginity be to her? And how can folly be carried to the point where one believes a
female creature is worth more or less for having one part of her body a little more or less
enlarged? For what purpose has Nature created every human being? Is it not for giving
mutual aid one to the other, and consequently for giving others all the pleasures it is in
ones power to dispense? (italics mine; J: 60-61).
142
microcosms of this same general economy of sexual pleasure. They do not make
love or have sex with each other, nor are they interested in such paradigmatically
romantic states as simultaneous climax, for example; they essentially use each others
bodies to masturbate with (accordingly, Sade tends to elevate the masturbation
fantasy, or even writing about it, to the status of an actual sexual act; J: 640-641).
Sades preoccupation with necrophilia, bestiality and mechanized sexual toys fits this
account. Insofar as sex is reduced to pleasure with an object, the partner may as
well be a toy, a statue, corpse or dog (LNJ 2: 12, 385; J: 188, 189, 367, 745, 746,
1190). In the following passage from Juliette, it is not clear if the sexual objects
even exist. Durand the alchemist describes her ability to produce what appear to be
interactive erotic spectacles in her own home; that is, sexuality removed from reality
entirely.
There is not a single passion, replied Durand, not a single whim or fancy, not a living
being on this globe, nor an extravagance or eccentricity, however unusual or picturesque
it be, that cannot be enjoyed here; merely give me several hours forenotice, I will procure
you anything under the sun; let your desire be irregular, let it be fantastic, let it be
gruesome, and this in no matter what degree, I solemnly promise to provide you the
means to execute it. Nor is that all. If there be any men or women anywhere in the world,
with whose tastes or practices you were eager to be acquainted, I will have them here; and
unseen by them, you will watch them in action through a gauze curtain...all individuals,
all races, all nations, all sexes, all ages, simply specify what you wish... (J: 542-543).
Whether this passage describes a drug induced state, an optical illusion or some
other sort of virtual reality is unclear. 31 In any case, it illustrates perfectly three
aspects of the Sadeian wish fulfilment fantasy. Firstly, the sexualised other is reduced
to an object (I will procure anything under the sun). Secondly, sex is conceived of
as something one does to someone (or something) - quite possibly, something deeply
unpleasant. Thirdly, sexual pleasure is voyeuristic; sex is described here as something
that one watches, through a gauze curtain. Direct physical contact, that is, intimacy
with another human being, is apparently marginalized.
31
Drug induced state: substances that cause hallucinations appear in Sades works elsewhere. From the
tortures in The 120 Days: [h]e has her swallow a drug which unhinges her imagination and causes her
to see horrible things in the room (120:608, 60).
143
33
Rousseau Emile: 333-334; Alan Soble Kant and Sexual Perversion In the Monist 86:1 (2003): 57-
92.
34
See La Mettrie: 11, 23, 25, 30, 101; Helvtius Essays on the Mind: 83,106, 116.
35
For discussion, see William F. Edmiston Plots, Patterns and Challenges to Gender Ideology in
Gomez and Sade, The French Review Vol.73, No.3 (Feb 2000): 463-474.
36
Durand Clestine and Madame dEsterval (in Juliette) are such characters. Sades male sadistic
characters are frequently described as having feminine features (J: 23, 1032; 120:221; LNJ. 1: 172; 2:
144
is the first Western writer to propose the possibility of surgical transformation from
one gender to the next, but the brutal sex change operation described in the 120
Days of Sodom seems to be a form of torture rather than a positive contribution to the
discussion on gender identity; 120: 655). 37
4.5 Homosexuality
Sade declares that the naturalness of heterosexuality and the unnaturalness of
alternatives is a myth, citing the frequency of homosexuality and bisexuality in other
cultures. 38 From The Philosophy in the Bedroom: [w]e discover a hemisphere, we
find sodomy in it. Cook casts anchor in a new world: sodomy reigns there. Had our
balloons reached the moon, it would have been discovered there as wellO my
friends, can there be an extravagance to equal that of imagining that a man must be a
122, 136). Foucault has noted that during the 18th Century such physiological abnormalities were
regarded as actually immoral; it would seem that Sade makes this association as well. Rousseau
appears to have believed this; when unable to accept that the prostitute Zulietta is at once beautiful,
regal and witty, he is relieved to find that she has only one nipple (C: 310). For discussion, see Patrick
Graille Les Hermaphrodites aux XVIIe et XVIIIe sicles (Paris : Les Belles Lettres, 2001). Gender
fluidity was in fact not such a rare idea in, or just prior to, Sades time. Thomas Laqueur notes that
gender identity was relatively fluid until the early modern period. He notes, for example, the cryptic
gender of Elizabeth I, and the widely held medical belief, during the 16th and 17th centuries, that women
could spontaneously become men. Michel de Montaigne, in his Travel Journal (first published in
1774), writes of a group of girls in Chaumont-en-Bassagni who plotted together a few years ago to
dress up as males and thus continue their life in the world; one of the pair fell in love with another girl
and married her, and was eventually hanged for using illicit devices to supply her defect in sex.
Laqueur pp.125-127. Although Sade (in his feminist mode) tends to eliminate the physiological
distinction between men and women, he also presents the traditional and, in his own time, dated view
that women are a degenerate expression of the male form (J: 510-511).
37
The section from The 120 Days of Sodom is as follows: [a]fter having sheared off the boys prick
and balls, using a red-hot iron he hollows out a cunt in the place formerly occupied by his genitals; the
iron makes the hole and cauterizes simultaneously: he fucks the patients new orifice and strangles him
with his hands upon discharging. For positive discussion of this passage, see David Martyn Sublime
Failures: The Ethics of Kant and Sade (Detroit: Wayne State University Press, 2003) p. 210.
38
It should be noted that Sade was not particularly advanced in his own time in this respect. Louis
Crompton notes that the law against homosexuality was abolished in France in 1791; Philosophy in the
Bedroom appeared in 1795. Louis Crompton Homosexuality & Civilization (Cambridge, Massachusetts,
and London, England: The Belknap Press of Harvard University Press, 2003) p 524. I thank Shanon
Daly for bringing this text to my attention.
145
monster deserving to lose his life because he has preferred enjoyment of the asshole to
that of the cunt [...] ? (PB: 277). Sade also notes the implausibility of the doctrine that
all semen is intended by nature for production. 39 There is, however, a tension in
Sades treatment of homosexuality. On the one hand, Sade portrays homosexuality
and anal sex as deeply transgressive; a shocking, and therefore exciting, violation of
nature (J: 312). Sades comments also suggest that a certain degree of homosexual
desire is normal for all males (J: 455n; 1124). But if homosexuality is due to a
physiological difference, or even normal, it is not a freely chosen rebellion. Sades
arguments concerning the morality of homosexuality seem more defensive than
defiant, such as the claim that ...lhomme dou de gots singuliers est un malade;
cest si vous le voulez, une femme vapeurs hystriques (LNJ 1: 357). 40
Sade dismisses the principles of monogamy and prudery on similar grounds,
rejecting both as being artefacts of Christian influence (PB: 323-4; J: 69). A woman
who does not follow her natural sexual inclinations is a victim of her opinions and of
the chilly esteem she hopes for, almost always in vain, from men, shell have lived
dry and joyless and shall die with her regrets ( J: 492; also LNJ 1 :39). Women are
said to be naturally vulguivaguous (vulgivagues)- that is, not belonging to any
particular males of the group, adding that [s]elf interest, egoism and love degraded
these primitive attitudes, at once so simple and natural (PB:318; similar, AV: 633;
LNJ 1: 41). 41 From Juliette;
In Tahiti, Cook discovered a society in which all the women give themselves indifferently
to all the assembled men. 42 But if a later consequence of this rite is pregnancy, the woman
39
Nocturnal emissions are taken to be proof that wastage of semen is not contrary to nature (LNJ 1:
79).
40
See also MV: 179, 212; MM: 55; AV: 310. Sade also refers to his own sentencing for pederasty (120:
495).
41
Sade here describes egoism as unnatural; by contrast, in Bataillian mode Sade describes egoism
as in fact natural. Delon notes that Sade has probably adopted la Mettries term here, as used in a
discussion on the sexual mores of Sparta, in the Anti-Seneca. The etymology is based on the Latin term
vulgivalgus, vagabond, which appears in Lucretius. La Mettrie writes that women are vulgivagous,
like dogs (the term is missing from the English translation, rendering La Mettrie simply as women
were shared and were common ( III: 132n 2, p.1340; La Mettrie: 136).
42
This is what Cook actually writes: A very considerable number of the principle people of Otaheite
[Tahiti], of both sexes, have formed themselves into a society in which every woman is common to
146
smothers the child the instant it is born: splendid evidence this, that there do after all exist
people of sufficient intelligence to set their pleasures on a higher plane than the futile
laws enjoining us to increase numerically! a similar society thrives at Constantinople
(J: 69).
Accordingly, laws against adultery are rejected as cruel and unjust (AV: 569), and
spousal jealousy and concerns for the honour of the husband are dismissed as selfrighteous manifestation of a mans arrogance, pride and fear of humiliation (J: 259260 PB: 221, 224 AV: 310, 365). 43
Prudish, God-fearing, or otherwise timorous women, take daily and confident use of these
counsels, it is for you the author intends them.
The evolutionary psychological line seems to give a more plausible explanation for this than simple
45
The complexity of the relationship between Sade and Rousseau is reflected by the divergence of
opinion in the secondary literature. Philippe Roger notes that Sade admired Rousseau and collected his
works. (Sade expresses his admiration for Rousseau in Aline et Valcour; the novels principals go on a
pilgrimage to visit him; AV: 69; n. p.811). Nelly Stphane takes Sade to be the anti-Rousseau; Alice
Laborde has suggested that Sade harboured a secret desire to become Rousseaus equal. Sade agreed
with Rousseau on some matters, for example the absurdity of making suicide a criminal offence.
Elsewhere, however, Sade refers to Rousseau as a misanthrope (LNJ 2: 223). Michel Delon comes
closest to identifying the commonality between the two thinkers, observing that Rousseau et Sade se
147
overlap in the moral thinking of the two thinkers, which will be discussed in the
following chapter. Here I will discuss Sades relation to Rousseau on the topic of
sexuality. Rousseaus Confessions (hereafter C; 1781) is replete with Sadeian themes,
in particular Rousseaus masochism, his penchant, in his youth, for stealing and
exposing himself in public, his homoerotic encounters, his clothing fetishism, his
confession of such tastes; his infatuation with a Venetian prostitute (a woman named
Zulietta, who has more than a passing resemblance to Sades Juliette), his
involvement with child prostitution, and his own libertine friends and acquaintances
(C:13-16, 26, 33, 63,84, 160, 291,426). 46 Pertinent to the discussion at hand, Sades!
treatment of the subject of women appears to be a direct reply to Rousseau, and is
based on principles Rousseau himself held to. Sades statements on women and their
role are an implicit response to this doctrine, as well as the entire cultural edifice it
situent sur les marges des Lumires, Rousseau car il refuse lquivalence entre progrs et bonheur,
Sade parce quil dnonce la convergence du bonheur individuel et de la prosprit collective. Michel
Delon Sade contre Rousseau, en marge des Lumires, Magazine- Littraire 389 (July- August
2000) :39-43p.42. See also Stphane Morale et nature, p.39; Alice M. Laborde Sade: lrotisme
dmystifi, LEsprit Createur15 (1975):438-448: 446; Philippe Roger Rousseau selon Sade ou JeanJacques travesti, Dix-huitime sicle 23 (1991):383-405, p.402.
46
Zulietta, like Juliette, is beautiful and intelligent, quick tempered and potentially lethal; she threatens
to shoot Rousseau with her pistols for his insolence. She is also a brunette, like Juliette, and like
Durand, is physically unusual; she only has one nipple, which makes her, for Rousseau, a monster.
Like Juliette, she avoids vaginal sex to avoid pregnancy. Rousseau met her in Italy, the scene of much
of the action of Juliette, including Juliettes stint as a prostitute. Confessions pp.304-311, 415. In 1741,
when Rousseau was 29, together with his friend Carrio, Rousseau purchased a girl of 11 or 12, named
Anzoletta. He notes that this is an arrangement common in Venice (C: 311). (Rousseau made this
purchase whilst secretary to the French Ambassador; In Juliette, the French ambassador to Venice
himself has a girl of 16 abducted from her family; J: 1084). Rousseau also discusses his acquaintance
Klpfel, the preacher and chaplain to the Prince of Saxe-Gotha, who kept a little girl. Rousseau says
of a meeting with Klpfel that I indulged in a somewhat coarser enjoyment with this girl, who was,
Rousseau notes, at everybodys disposal and little adapted for her profession. (C: 433, 434).
Rousseau refers to three personages in the course of the Confessions that fit the designation libertine;
Friedrich Melchior Grimm (1723-1807), who apparently did not believe in morality, his friend
Gauffecourt, who (at the age of sixty) attempted to seduce his wife with money and a libertine book,
and Mme (Franoise Louise lonore de La Tour) de Warens (1699-1762), who, according to
Rousseau, could have slept with twenty men in one day with a calm conscience (C: 223, 380, 457).
148
represents. 47 Sades treatment goes beyond simple parody, although parodic elements
are present. 48
In his introduction to his translation of Emile (hereafter E, 1762), Allan Bloom
reads Rousseau as predicting the feminist movement, portraying it as the final act in a
complete cultural bourgeoisification of the world. For Blooms Rousseau (and, it
appears, for Bloom himself), rationalism and egalitarianism would end sexual
differentiation. The designations man and woman, husband and wife, parent
and child, it is feared, will become roles, and not designations that refer to natural
properties. Bloom writes that this would inevitably lead to the reduction of all of us to
the level of the selfish Hobbesian individual, striving for self- preservation, comfort,
and power after power. Marriage and the family would decay and sexes be
assimilated. Children would be burdens and not fulfillments (all the worse for
questionable theories of natural kinds; if the institutions of marriage and filial piety
are so vital, they should have stronger foundations than such a questionable ontology;
E: 24). Blooms own reading of Rousseau supports the reading of Sade as the AntiRousseau, given that he wrote enthusiastically of exactly this cultural shift, and
advocated the elimination of such apparently concrete social roles and institutions as
the mother, the wife or the marriage.
Both Sade and Rousseau note the contingent relationship between sexual
behavior and human relationships. Both hold there is no natural bind that attaches
sexual partners- for Rousseau, marriage and monogamy are a moral institution; the
very reason why Sade rejects them (E: 16). Rousseau recommends absolute honesty
with children on sexual matters, as a single proved lie told by the master to the child
would ruin forever the whole fruit of the education (E: 216; 171). Yet Rousseaus
sexual revolution is very limited, and, as Deutscher notes, his arguments on sexual
47
In Philosophy in the Bedroom for example, Rousseau is cited as saying that adultery is wrong, as the
wife could have a child who is not her husbands, to which Madame de Saint-Ange replies- avoid
pregnancy (PB: 223).
48
Sades libertine education, (the setting of the Philosophy of the Bedroom is described as
Dolmancs academy; PB: 185) appears to be a parody of Rousseaus educational ideal, and his role
as author of guidebooks for the young. It is also no coincidence that Sades most famous character,
Justine, goes by the name of Sophie, the name of the ideal female partner for Rousseaus Emile. For
discussion see Jacques Broche Sade ou le langage terroriste, La Petite revue de philosophie 2,
(spring 1981): 25-36.
149
matters tend towards kettle logic and the ad hoc. 49 To teach sexual propriety, which
he takes to be a natural good, Rousseau recommends that one take the student to a
ward of syphilitics (E: 231). Sade, taking the side of rigorous pragmatism, instead
recommends frequent medical checks (J: 424). Where Rousseau suggests that adultery
may lead to an unwanted pregnancy, Sade recommends condoms and sponges (J: 424;
PB: 223). In an ironic touch, Sade adopts Rousseaus advice to women not to grant
their favors too eagerly, to make your favours rare and precious, if you know how to
make them valued (E: 478,479). Writes Sade, [if] your husband [proposes] sodomy
to you... dont be overhasty accepting the invitation: one must always have the look of
refusing what one covets. If fear of having children forces you to suggest the thing
yourself, advance the excuse that you are afraid of dying in labor; maintain that one of
your friends has told you that her husband manages matters with her in that fashion
(J:79).
In Benthamite mode, Sade disagrees with Rousseau on three specific points.
Firstly, Sade questions both the claim of physical and psychological difference
between men and women, and its relevance. Women, according to Rousseau, are
made to please man and are unsuited to traditionally male-dominated activities, such
as carpentry or running (E:437). 50 Women are child-like in both appearance and
psychology, and are intellectually weak, being incapable of independent or abstract
thought (E: 211,386, 387). 51 They are insidiously manipulative and incapable of self
control (E: 377). Rousseau rejects the charge that he is claiming that women are
inferior, but that they have a role, which is complementary to that of men (E: 361).
Her function, he argues, is to please and console men in their pains- she is to look
49
Penelope Deutscher Yielding Gender: feminism, deconstruction and the history of philosophy
(London and New York: Routledge, 1997) p.97. In a kettle logic, several mutually contradictory
explanations are sustained at once, suggesting that the actual motive for retaining the defended point of
view is repressed. The term derives from a joke discussed by Freud. A man lends another a kettle, and
it is returned damaged. When confronted, the borrower says that, firstly, he never borrowed a kettle,
second, the kettle had a hole in it already, and thirdly, hed returned the kettle undamaged. See
Sigmund Freud, Jokes and Their Relation to the Unconscious, trans. James Strachey, Standard Ed.
(New York: Norton, 1990) p. 72. See also Freud The Interpretation of Dreams trans. James Strachey
(New York: Avon, 1970), 152-3.
50
Robert Wokler Rousseau: A Very Short Introduction (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2001) p.126.
51
Wokler pp. 127-128. This is despite the fact that Rousseau acknowledges the materialist framework,
noting that, between men and women, the machine is constructed in the same way (E: 358).
150
pretty and to remain submissive (E: 358, 365, 366, 437, 442,437). (Significantly, the
tasks that Rousseau holds to be appropriate for women- lace-making, dancing and
singing, and cooking for the home, are economically trivial; women are largely
withheld from economic relevance and independence; E: 425, 394). Yet, according to
Rousseau himself, economic inequality is a cause of tyranny). Rousseau insists that
he is simply clarifying that the sex roles are established in the physical and moral
order of things, and yet his Emile is filled with admonitions and advice on how one is
to best embody the good woman- a state which is assumed to be natural. As
Deutscher notes, Rousseau conflates the descriptive with the prescriptive. 52 Much of
this advice is quite explicitly related to the enforcement of a natural hierarchy
between men and women; women should be pretty and entertaining, but not too
pretty, educated or intelligent, as she will become a source of grief, sexual jealousy, or
an embarrassment to her husband (E: 409, 363, 409). 53 Women are to remain without
knowledge, art or education, lest they become too powerful (that is, independent); an
obvious impossibility if women were simply incapable of such cultivation.
Maintenance of power over a woman is frequently behind Rousseaus reasoning;
when choosing a wife, Rousseau advises, one should choose a mediocre woman to
avoid jealousy or conflict (E: 410). 54 Rousseau also holds that any woman who
wishes to liberate herself from men to be a victim of philosophical fashion (E:
386).Were a woman to betray the destiny of her sex, she would become weak,
having abandoned her only strength (meaning, of course, her feminine weakness and
passivity), which is inextricably tied up with her sex (E: 363, 364). Rousseaus
assumption that the natural is the good, and that anything with a cultural origin is
bad, is the origin of his confusion here, and it is precisely on this point that Sade turns
to in his response. In legislating on what is natural, and privileging the natural over
the good, Rousseau leads to incoherence as he mistakenly assumes the division and
specialisation of the sexual roles to be entirely a natural kind, and not, at least to a
certain extent, a cultural construct.
52
53
Note that Sade makes exactly the same association of virtue and mediocrity that Rousseau makes,
Again, Rousseau makes the same association of mediocrity and morality that Sade (and later,
Nietzsche) makes.
151
Yet, albeit rejecting such principles dear to Rousseau, Sade has apparently adopted Rousseaus
intellectual self image as existing above and beyond all stultifying convention, as the great liberator and
iconoclast: I am cynical, impudent, violent and fearless, he declares in the Confessions; I thought
that I was born to destroy all illusions(C:33,405).
56
Rousseau The Social Contract translated by Maurice Cranston. (London: Penguin Books, 1968); A
Sades footnote: Women are unaware to what point their lasciviousness embellishes them. Let one
compare two women for roughly comparable age and beauty, one of whom lives in celibacy, and the
other in libertinage: it will be seen by how much the latter exceeds in clat and freshness; all violence
does Nature is far more wearing than the abuse of pleasure; everyone knows bed improves a womans
looks (PB:323).
152
us ; have no fear of absurd approaches ; pedantry and superstition are things of the past ;
no longer will you be seen to blush at your charming delinquencies ; crowned with myrtle
and roses, the esteem we conceive for you will henceforth in direct proportion to the scale
you give your extravagances (PB: 323).
58
This follows the thought of Helvtius. See Essays on the Mind pp.339-340.
59
For a critique of the natural complement theory and the question of physical differences between
men and women, see Ann Ferguson, Androgyny as an Ideal for Human Development in Alan Soble,
ed. Philosophy of Sex 232-255, p.234-238.
153
AV :310). 60 Sade also notes that a womans capacity for sexual union and pleasure
has no relation at all to how often she can become pregnant (PB: 228).
One may object that Sade, like Rousseau, has buttressed his rhetoric with
characters that are fantastic and implausible. But Sade, being a connoisseur of the
fantastic and factual, packs Juliette with references to women who apparently lived in
blissful ignorance of Rousseaus feminine ideal. He refers to, among others, Empress
Theodora, wife of Justinian (c.500-548 C.E; PB:256; J:1187), the poisonesses La
Voisin (born Catherine Deshayes Monvoisin; burned for poisoning and sorcery in
1680) and Marie Madeleine dAubray, marquise de Brinvilliers (c.163076 ; J :
262) , Empress Agrippina 1(5 59 C.E; J: 172, 564), Empress Valeria Messalina,
third wife of Claudius (CE c.22-48), the poet Sappho (6th Century B.C.E ; J: 60),
Queen Zingha of Angola (1583-1663; PB : 256 ; J ;69; III: 242), Zo, a Chinese
emperors wife(possibly Empress Wu Zetian, a ruthless autocrat, 625-705 C.E. ; PB:
256, III:133) and Sades contemporary, Catherine II, Empress of Russia (17291796; J:874- 885). A key Sadeian principle of psychology- that absolute power
liberates absolutely- applies equally as to women as to men. In reply to the objection
that such characters are the exception, not the rule, it could be the case that women
like Catherine the Great are rare, as women were rarely given the opportunity to enjoy
such circumstances. If anything, Sades list shows that ambition and ruthlessness may
be normal for women in positions of power. (Rousseau, in the Confessions, oddly,
describes such colourful women; consequently, he presents counterexamples to his
own ideal characterization of womanhood. Therein we find quite positive descriptions
of Comtesse de Menthon, a woman of great wit, Zulietta, and Madame de Warens
[C: 185]. In fact, Rousseau attributes his own good education to the women in his life
[C: 289]).
60
This was not an original position. Robert Burton, in his Anatomy of Melancholy (1621), writes of a
girl who was cured of amenorrhea by having sex with fifteen men in one night. Cited in Laqueur p.107.
La Mettrie, too, considered celibacy a risk to mental stability. See La Mettrie pp.8, 72.
154
abortion (MV: 90; PB: 225-230; J: 79; AV: 516). As Nature does not consider murder
a crime, Sade reasons, then abortion is not criminal either (Sade here assumes that
abortion is on a moral par with murder; J: 67n). From Philosophy in the Bedroom:
there is not the least wrong in diverting a mans semen into a detour by one means or
by another; because propagation is in no sense the objective of nature; she merely
tolerates it; from her viewpoint, the less we propagate, the better; and when we avoid it
altogether, thats best of all.deflect that perfidious liquor that whose vegetation serves
only to spoil our figures, which deadens our voluptuous sensations, withers us, ages us
and makes us fade and disturbs our health; get your husband to accustom himself to these
losses; entice him into this or that passage tell him you detest children, point out the
advantages of having none (PB:248; similar, J: 435).
Sades characters argue that there is no particular reason as to why a rational agent
should want to have children, and sufficient reasons as to why it is immoral to do
so. 61 The world, they insist, is no place for human beings, and that the human race is
a plant that should simply be rooted out (GT: 25; J: 373, 1009). 62 It is in the context
of willed sterility that the significance of anal sex in Sade is to be understood. As
Marcel Hnaff notes, anal sex in Sade is a total symbolic affirmation of sterility over
fertility; a principle that, if universalized, would end the human race. 63 On this point,
Sades advice against reproduction and non-fertile sex departs from both the
Benthamite and Bataillian doctrines as described above. In denying that pleasure
could possibly make up for the pain of being alive, Sade appears to counter the
Benthamite principle (which would, on such grounds, merely recommend suicide).
61
Helvtius, for example, felt that people only married and had children out of imprudence. Helvtius
Note that this view is incompatible with the view that there is a teleology according to which one
should participate in the cycle of destruction and creation; in this context, to father more warriors.
Sade can only conceive of participating in nature in terms of destruction. This will be addressed again
in Chapter VI.
63
Notably, by the 250th page of the 120 Days of Sodom, the only approximately sexual act described is
thigh-fucking. Playing with and eating human excrement, which are not sexual activities in any sense,
are the main themes of the first part of the text. For discussion, see Marcel Hnaff Libertine Body
pp.204-205. For Sades comments on the arcane allure of anal sex, see J: 312; LNJ 1: 47n, 49, 78.
Frottage against the thighs was the preferred method of sexual intercourse in Classical Greece, which
may indicate that Sade is making a specific allusion. See Kenneth James Dover Greek Homosexuality
(Cambridge, Mass: Harvard University Press, 1977).
155
Similarly, the declaration that the human race should simply end does not cohere with
the principle of participating in Natures cycle of domination and destruction. 64 A
third, even more nihilistic position appears; a direct assault on the very principle of
reproduction. Call this the Sterile doctrine.
Whereas the Benthamite Sade associates non-fertile sex with simple prudence,
and liberates women from the reproductive role, the sterile Sade expresses both an
absolute horror of the reproductive role, an abhorrence of all female sexual
characteristics, and a form of misogyny which identifies women with this role.
65
Characters have their female victims cover their breasts in bandages, and anally
penetrate them on principle (120: 298, 306, 440). Women, frequently pregnant, or
with infants, are tortured precisely because they have committed the crime of being
mothers. It is for this reason, assumedly, that torture of women in Sade is typically
concentrated on the reproductive organs- vaginas are ritualistically sewn shut or
mutilated, wombs are ripped out, babies are crushed in front of their mothers
(alternatively, mothers are forced to kill their own children, before being slaughtered
in turn). 66 Duclos, in 120 Days of Sodom, holds that all mothers are all guilty as they
have taken the unnecessary risk of exposing us to all the ills and sorrows the world
64
Rather than consistently affirming a life of struggle, Braschi argues that propagation of the human
race is a wrong, as [man] usurps from Nature the honour of a new phenomenon - our existence as a
species prevents Nature from bringing forth new species of organism (J: 767). Compare: One gives
birth only to unhappy children! And they too are preachers of death. Friedrich Nietzsche Thus Spake
Zarathustra trans. R.J. Hollingdale (London: Penguin, 2003) p.73.
65
The difference between a man and a woman, of this we may be perfectly confident, is quite as
pronounced, quite as important as between man and ape; our grounds for refusing to include women in
our species would be quite as valid as for refusing to consider the chimpanzee our brother. Next to a
naked woman stand a man of the same age and naked too; now examine them attentatively, and you
will be at no pains to discern the palpable and marked difference which (sex aside) exists in the
composition of these two beings; you will be obliged to conclude that woman is simply man in an
extraordinarily degraded form; there are internal differences as well, and these are brought to light by
anatomical comparison: the dissection should be performed carefully and simultaneously. Footnote, J:
511. Similar: 120 422, 440; LNJ 2: 164. J: 486, 498, 519, 656, 894, 913-924, 988-990, 1100, 1110;
120:650).
66
There are literally dozens of examples of this: J: 1100- 1110; 120:650); PB: 367; 120: 611-665;
LNJ; 1; 235; 2: 12, 73. For discussion, see Caroline Weber The Sexist Sublime in Sade and Lyotard,
in Philosophy and Literature 26 (2002): 397-404. I thank Stephen Davies for bringing this article to my
attention.
156
holds in store for us (120: 476; MV: 41). Our relationship with other humans, and the
world itself, begins with our mothers. The ripping apart of the pregnant mothers
body, a key image in Sade, is an expression of profound hatred and disgust for both.
Universalizing to all women the crime of bringing oneself into the world hardly
speaks of a heroic affirmation of the world, or a positive appreciation of its natural
workings. The sexualized mutilation of women for being women also coheres with the
idea of sadism as revenge, rather than due to a deep seated psychic and sexual urge.
This aspect also makes the very identification of women with the reproductive role
that the Benthamite doctrine explicitly denies (it is also one-sided; no-one in Sade is
tortured to death for being a father).
A final point can be made here. As Carter notes (as discussed in Chapter I), Sades
women characters are not free from the phallus. Clairwil is bisexual, but so deeply
identifies with the phallic that she at once embodies and worships it: I live in the
name of nothing but the penis sublime; and when it is not in my cunt, nor in my ass, it
is so firmly anchored in my thoughts that the day they dissect me it will be found in
my brain (J: 492-493). Juliette, too, literally suffers from penis envy. 67 Again, the
framework of the Christian worldview appears in Sades text. St. Augustine held the
erect penis as the revolt of the flesh over the spirit; through worshipping it, for an
Augustinian, the materialist revolt against spirit is complete. 68
Manlike in my tastes as in my thinking, how bitterly I regretted that I was unable to burn some more
Thomas Nagel Sexual Perversion in Soble ed. pp.76-88, p.84. A direct affront to the Augustinian
attitude, and a confirmation of the potency of the symbol, is Sades footnote noting the pleasure of
seeing ones own erection (J: 455).
69
For discussion on the 18th Century attitude towards the emotions, see Cheshire Calhoun and Robert
157
Fond to Juliette, [w]hatever originates in the heart is false; for my part, I believe in
the senses alone, I believe alone in carnal habits and appetitesin self-seeking, in
self-aggrandizement, in self-interest (J: 232). Yet other characters acknowledge the
reality of romantic sentiments through cautioning against emotional involvement,
recommending, rather, that one simply use other people for simple sexual
gratification. 70 Two extended discourses, one addressed by a woman to women
(entitled Instructions to Women Admitted into the Sodality of the Friends of Crime)
the other by a man to men, are offered in Juliette. The first such discussion is a
brochure issued to female members of the Society of the Friends of Crime. Apathy
is recommended in sexual relations, not only for the sake of maximizing pleasure, but
to avoid the entrapment that marriage entails. Sade describes love as (as we would
now say) a psychopathological condition; an instinct for attachment to men which
should simply be purged, like wisdom teeth or the appendix. 71 Sade also assumes an
economy of lack concerning sexual pleasure; love is the veritable and certain kiss
of death to enjoyment, reasons the author of the Instructions to Women, as her
inevitable concern to give pleasure to her lover will prevent her from tasting any
herself (J: 432). The monologue given by the Comte de Belmor (Juliette) is more
illuminating.
The word love is used to designate that deep-seated feeling which propels us, as it were
despite ourselves, toward some foreign object or other; which provokes in us a keen
desire to become united to it, to ever lessen the distance between it and ourselveswhich
delights usravishes usrenders us ecstatic when we achieve that union, and which
casts us into a despond, which tears us asunder, whenever the intrusion of external
considerations constrain us to rupture this union. If only this extravagance never led to
anything more serious than pleasure intensified by the ardour, the abandon, inherent in it,
would merely be ridiculous; but as it leads us into a certain metaphysic[s], which,
confounding us with the loved object, transforming us into it, making its actions, its
needs, its desires quite as vital and dear to us as our own- through this alone it becomes
exceedingly dangerous, by detaching us from ourselves, and by causing us to neglect our
interests in favour of the beloveds; by identifying us, so to speak, with this object, it
70
Sade revives the old philosophical view that sexual pleasure is superior to romantic love, and that the
latter will only cause pain. Both Epicurus and Lucretius, in particular, taught this. For discussion, see
Simon Blackburn Lust (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2004).
71
For discussion of this view, see Elizabeth Rapaport On the Future of Love: Rousseau and the
158
causes us to assume its woes, its griefs, its chagrins, and thus consequently adds to the
sum of our own ( J: 502).
The braggadocio of the libertine here gives way to, quite simple, fear of getting
emotionally hurt. Belmor holds that the torment of romantic love is a cross (Sades
word) simply too painful to bear.
If the reward for so many pains, or their counterpart, were anything beyond an ordinary
spasm, I might perhaps recommend risking it; but all the cares, all the torments, all the
anguishes and nuisances of love never yield anything but what might be conveniently
obtained without it; why then must one put on these chains! (J: 502).
This attitude coheres with the observation made in the previous chapter concerning
the relationship between sadism, emotional vulnerability, and a lack of inner restraint
to violence. Belmor, elsewhere in the novel, proposes the execution of Frances
fifteen million Catholics, and professes the wish to kill six small boys per week (J:
499, 500, 521). Yet he states that he could not bear the emotional hurt associated with
romantic love. He appears to be an emotional cripple, able to engage with others only
in killing them.
The libertine characters of Juliette do, however, frequently fall in love with each
other. 72 Where such partnerships emerge, they are invariably described in terms of a
love of extraordinary equals, proud of each others achievements. 73 Belmor himself
states that [f]riendship requires openness and equality; when one of two friends
dominates the other, friendship is destroyed. Belmore insists that women cannot be
friends with men for this very reason (J: 505). The notion of friendship dovetails into
the doctrine of superiority (to be discussed at length in later chapters) in passages such
as this, in which Noirceuil seduces Juliette.
Noirceuil glanced their way. Feeble-minded creatures, he murmured; pleasuremachines, sufficient to our purposes, but, truly, their appalling insensitivity depresses
me. His eyes now rested meditatively upon me. You, Juliette, your subtler mind
72
There is, for example, the lesbian relationship between Durand and Juliette, between Juliette and
Clairwil (although Juliette later poisons Clairwil), the sexual relationship between Clairwil and her
brother Brisatesta, and between Brisatesta and fellow Gulag convict Tergowitz.
73
159
conceives me, understands me, yes, anticipates me, I relish your company. And, he
added, further narrowing his eyes, you cannot hide it: you are in love with evil (J: 147148; 592; similar: LNJ 2:98-99, 174) 74 .
Sade also suggests that, by their nature, such relationships between higher types
will soar beyond such base prejudices as the prohibition on incest, or even (it should
be kept in mind) killing each other. 75 Yet- and this is a curiously Kantian pointSades characters insist that the ground of the relationship is not sexual, but
intellectual, in nature. Friendship between libertines is entirely bracketed off from
physical sexuality; the friendship comes first. Duvergier gives a very positive
description of love, yet makes it quite clear that it is entirely distinct from sexual
pleasure.
There are two manners of loving a man: morally and physically. A woman can morally
idolize her husband and morally and momentarily love the young blade who pays her
court; she can cavort with him without in any sense or decree offending the moral
sentiments she entertains for and owes him she worships: every individual of our sex who
is of a different opinion is an idiot who is steering nowhere but toward disaster (J: 151).
Noirceuil continues:
Belinda is ugly, shes forty-two, not one hint of the gracious anywhere about her person,
not a single attractive feature, no, shes a slug, grossly ill-favoured. But Belinda is clever,
she has wit, a delicious character, a million things which mate nicely with my sentiments
and tastes; Id have no desire to bed with Belinda, but Id be wild about her conversation
nevertheless. Id intensely desire to have Araminthe, but Id cordially detest her the
74
Catherine Cusset notes that the equally close relationship between Juliette and Durand similarly
contradicts the libertine doctrine of complete isolation. She notes that it is not a contractual relationship
between two libertines but a link based on exclusivity and sentimentality. Consequently, it is a major
contradiction of the novel. See Catherine Cusset la passion selon Juliette.
75
In the story Eugnie de Franval (1800), Eugnie is trained do dismiss the incest prohibition. The
father maintains that their love transcends social norms: [t]he domination of beauty and the sacred
rights of love know nothing of futile human conventions; their ascendancy annihilates these just as the
rays of the sun purify the earth from the fogs that enshroud her at night (GT: 31). The principle that
true love overrides local custom or even morality has a certain family resemblance to Friedrich
Nietzsches aphorism, That which is done out of love always takes place beyond good and evil.
Beyond Good and Evil 153 p.103.
160
moment the fever of desire had abated, because in her I have found a body only, and none
of the moral qualities which would win her a place in my heart (J: 260).
76
Buss notes that a negative shift in attraction after orgasm, for men, is not atypical. Buss suggests
that this is more common in men who are not interested in a committed relationship. Buss pp.83-84.
161
Indeed, Eugnie, consider the young girl scarcely out of her fathers house or her pension,
knowing nothing, without experience: of a sudden she is obliged to pass thence into the
arms of a man she has never seen, she is called to the altar and compelled to swear to this
man an oath of obedience, of fidelity, the more unjust for her often having nothing in the
depths of her heart but the greatest desire to break her word. In all the world, is there a
more terrible fate than this, Eugnie? However, whether her husband pleases her or no,
whether or not he has tenderness in store for her or vile treatment, behold! She is married;
her honor binds her to her oaths: it is attained if she disregards them; she must be doomed
or shackled: either way, she must perish or despair. Ah, no! Eugnie! It is not for that end
we are born; those absurd laws are the handiwork of men, and we must not submit to
them. And divorce? Is it capable of satisfying us? Probably not. What greater assurance
have we of finding the happiness in a later bondage that eluded us in an earlier? (PB:
223). 77
A man ridiculous enough to demand that a woman never give herself to anyone except
himself would be behaving quite as absurdly as he who would not tolerate his mistress or
wife ever dining with someone else; not only would such an attitude be downright queer,
it would be tyrannical; for by what right, being incapable of satisfying the woman singlehanded, can he require that this woman suffer and not seek to console herself by whatever
means at her disposal? ...she is under no obligation to cede to her keeper save when her
pays for her services, and while she does definitely owe him the use of her body when he
77
Sade writes elsewhere that [m]ismatched individuals are imprisoned all their lives in nightmarish
For discussion, see Alison M. Jaggar Prostitution in Soble ed. Philosophy of Sex 348-368, pp.353-
356.
79
Frederick Engels The Origin of the Family, Private and the State (New York: International
162
contracts for it, before the bargain is struck and after she ahs fulfilled her part of it, she is
free, the rest of her hours are her to employ as she likes, and it is then that, business
attended to, she may devote herself to pleasure and the inclinations of her heart; and why
should she not, since her only commitment to her keeper is physical?
The paying lover, or the husband, must perfectly well understand that he cannot exact
from the object of his doting those feelings of the heart which obviously cannot be
boughtfrom a woman a husband or a lover expects not virtue but the appearance of
virtue (J: 152-153; III: 314).
In the society of Sades time (and to this day, in many places), prostitution was the
only form of employment available to women that would bring in an income
comparable to that of men, or an adequate standard of living without getting married.
Sade, notes Carter, makes prostitution look like the more attractive option through the
depiction of marriage as socioeconomic entrapment. 80 Unsurprisingly, Juliettes one
marriage is for money (J: 551). She and Clairwil know the economic worth of their
bodies, even though they claim to prostitute themselves for enjoyment, but it is
evident that, in Juliette, sex for money is a paradigmatic relationship. Sades advice
here is continuous with the libertine association of money and sex. For the libertines,
as discussed in the previous chapter, money is the means to force ones will upon
others, whether through simply paying for sex, or through payment of legal aid,
bribery, or for the abduction of victims (LNJ 2: 28, 29, 66,173; AV: 258). Notes
William C. Brumfield, the doctrine of libertinism is largely a rationalisation of
sexual exploitation based on economic dependency. 81 Sade warns the woman reader
not to fall victim to this very entrapment. This, and Sades portrayal of libertines as
abusive and sadistic husbands, complicates the view that Sade is simply proposing the
doctrine of his characters (assuming that he intended to be read by women; 120:192.
J: 225; LNJ 2:137). Significantly, in the utopian kingdom of Tamo, divorce is legal,
and perfect economic equality between boys and girls is required to ensure that
marriages are for love alone (AV: 319).
80
81
163
82
The women and children kept in these brothels are apparently not free to leave, and
may be punished for giving resistance. Their differential treatment is justified
according to a Natural Aristocracy of the Strong and the Weak, and according to the
Bataille-doctrine view that to share pleasure (meaning- to restrain from inflicting
82
Shaeffer notes that an actual revolutionary petition made proposed a national brothel system. See
Schaeffer p.436. Helvtius identical proposal has been noted above. See A Treatise on Man Vol. I
pp.129 p.291-292.
164
83
The issue of her well-being, I repeat, is irrelevant. As soon as concern for this
consideration threatens to detract from or enfeeble the enjoyment of him who desires her,
and who has the right to appropriate her, this consideration for age ceases to exist; for
what the object may experience, condemned by Nature and by the law to slake
momentarily the others thirst, is nothing to the point; in this study, we are only interested
in what agrees with him who desires (PB: 320).
Applying the same principle, Sade also writes that men have an absolute natural right
to rape women, owing to their physical weakness, and to punish those that resist
rape and to compel their submission (PB:319; similar, p.174). He attempts to avoid
contradiction with the principle of equality in the following footnote:
Let it not be said that I contradict myself here, and that after having established, at some
point further above, that we have no right to bind a woman to ourselves, I destroy those
principles when I declare now we have the right to constrain her; I repeat, it is a question
of enjoyment only, not of property; I have no right of possession upon that fountain I find
by the road, but I have certain rights to its use; I have the right to avail myself of the
limpid water it offers my thirst; similarly, I have no real right of possession over suchand-such a woman, but I have incontestable rights to the enjoyment of her; I have the
right to force from her this enjoyment, if she refuses me it for whatever the cause may be
(319n).
...wrongs ones neighbour less than theft, since the latter is destructive to property, the
former merely damaging to it. Beyond that, what objections have you to the ravisher?
What will you say, when he replies to you that, as a matter of fact, the injury he has
committed is trifling indeed, since he has done no more than place a little sooner the
object he has abused in the very state in which she would have been put by marriage and
love (PB: 325).
83
165
The backgrounds assumptions here are noteworthy. Sade refers to the rape victim as
an object. Accordingly, Sade does not acknowledge the psychological pain of rape,
only the physical (this is remarkable, for an authority on sadism). Further, Sade
considers rape a crime against the husband, not the rape victim herself- in accordance
with the view that women are possessions. Yet Sade employs the rhetoric of
utilitarianism and uprooting prejudices in defending the sexual freedom of women.
Women can be sexually free so long as this freedom is on the males terms.
If we admit, as we have just done, that all women should be subjugated to our desires, we
may certainly allow them ample satisfaction of theirs... I say that women, having been
endowed with considerably more violent penchants for carnal pleasure than we, will be
able to give themselves to it wholeheartedly, absolutely free of all encumbering hymeneal
ties, of all false notions of modesty, absolutely restored to a state of Nature; I want laws
permitting them to give themselves to as many men as they see fit; I would have them
accorded the enjoyment of all sexes and, as in the case of men, the enjoyment of all parts
of the body; and under the special clause prescribing the surrender to all who desire them,
there must be subjoined another guaranteeing them a similar freedom to enjoy all they
deem worthy to satisfy them (PB: 321).
4.11 Conclusion.
In conclusion, I note that Sades account of sexuality is in fact two accounts. One, the
Benthamite doctrine, anticipates the state of sexuality as it is widely understood in the
21st Century - an arena of sensation, with only historical ties to its biological function.
The other appears to be a hypertrophy of the total subordination of women, divorced
from its traditional, theological justifications. There is one significant continuity; both
accounts have essentially masturbatory notions of sexuality- sex is merely the use of
the others body for physical pleasure.
To reiterate- this chapter has discussed, in passing, the two moral schemes
introduced in Chapter II. The first holds that morality is to be derived from the laws
of nature, and that this nature is characterized by strife and the struggle for
dominance. The other is an attempt, in the absence of any such teleology, to
coordinate action in the absence of absolute moral truths. The two following chapters
will discuss each of these in turn.
166
167
5.1 Introduction
As discussed in preceding chapters, there are two general approaches to the problem
of morality in Sade. The first, the Bataille doctrine, to be discussed in the following
chapter, holds that it is possible to derive a morality from the natural order. The other
view- that it is impossible to derive a morality from the natural order- and the
alternatives that it proposes, is discussed in this chapter.
Much of the ethical discussion in Sades work assumes the latter view, yet only in
Juliette is the former explicitly rejected. Braschi, in the midst of a monologue which
is largely faithful to libertine (Bataillian) Orthodoxy, momentarily rejects this view,
stating that morality must be grounded entirely upon its subjects- the human, and
states perplexingly- that there is a moral law inherent in us.
Man ... has no relationship to nature, nor Nature to man; Nature cannot bind man by
any law, man is in no way dependent upon Nature, neither is answerable to the other, they
cannot either harm or help each other; one has produced involuntarily- hence has no real
relationship to her product; the other is involuntarily produced- hence has no real
relationship to his producer. Once cast, man has nothing to do with Nature; once nature
has cast him, her control over man ends; he is under the control of his own laws, laws that
are inherent in him. With his casting man receives a direct and specific system of laws by
which he must abide, under which he must proceed ever after; these laws are those of his
personal self-preservation, of his multiplication, laws which refer to him, which are of
him, laws which are uniquely his own, vital to him but in no way necessary to Nature, for
he is no longer of Nature, no longer in her grip, he is separate from her (italics mine) (J:
766-767; also p.923).
167
Braschi does not develop this line of reasoning, and does not elaborate on what the
laws of man entail. As such, this is another of Sades orphaned passages, and its
function in the Sadeian matrix is unclear. This chapter will discuss the options that
Braschi leaves open to his libertine colleagues- whether to simply accept moral
nihilism, or to formulate a strategy (with morality- like features) in the absence of all
moral absolutes or teleological schemes. The first part of the chapter concerns the
various meta-ethical positions in Sade, and his critique of existing moral thought. The
remainder of the chapter will deal with Sades response to the traditional claim that it
is irrational to be immoral.
For recent defences of Ethical Nihilism and Error Theory, see Charles Pigden The Reluctant Nihilist
Minski befriends Juliette and her entourage, but kills her best friend (J: 591). In order to escape with
their lives, Juliette knocks Minski out with a dose of stramonium (J: 599, 609).
168
recognize that they are most profoundly relative, and profoundly lacking in anything
intrinsically real. Similar to concepts of virtue and vice, they are purely local and
geographic ; all that which is vicious in Paris turns up, as we know, a virtue in Peking,
and that is quite the same thing here [a]midst these manifold variations de we discover
anything constant? Only this: each countrys peculiar legal code, each individuals
peculiar interests, provide the sole basis for justice. (my italics; J: 605).
Noirceuil comes to the same conclusion, arguing that all acts are indifferent from the
standpoint of Nature. That is, he holds that a). if ethics is to hold, nature is the
foundation of moral beliefs, and b). nature gives no such foundation. Unlike Braschi,
he does not consider the possibility that ethics could be grounded on human needs
rather than nature.
...all acts are indifferent; that they are neither good nor bad intrinsically, and if man now
and then so qualifies them, the sole criteria by which he performs his judgment are the
laws he has elaborated for himself or the form of government under which he chances to
live; but from the standpoint of Nature, and barring all else from consideration, all are
acts are as one, none better, none worse than the rest [my italics].
Consequently,
...if from somewhere within us there arises a murmur of protestation against the acts of
wickedness we concert, this voice is nothing whatever but the effect of our prejudices and
education, and that if we had been born and reared in some other climate, it would address
us in a very different language (J: 170-171; similar: LNJ 2:111).
169
Sade writes: ... [o]ne might as well doubt the reality of a river, because it divides into a thousand
different streams. Well, what better proof is there both of the existence of a virtue and of its necessity
than mans need to adapt it to all his different ways of life and to make it the basis of all of them? Show
me a single race that lives without virtue, a single one among whom good deeds and humanity are not
the fundamental bonds, I will go further, show me even a band of villains who are not kept together by
some principles of virtue, I will renounce my cause; but on the contrary it is show to be useful
everywhere, if there is no nation, no state, no society, no individual who can do without it, if man, in
fact, cannot live happily or safely without it, would I be wrong, my child, in exhorting you never to
relinquish it?(GT: 104-105).
170
that ethics is not supposed to be, the conclusion is unavoidable. What is not a
straightforward claim, however, is the view that ethics is the mere work of men, a
recurring claim throughout Sades work. 4 Like Rousseau, Sade had difficulty with
the idea that ethics could manage without God to underwrite it. The implication is that
ethics cannot be merely human, as humans themselves are not in a sense eternal and
universal. To be good is to be associated with something universal and eternal;
something divine. This intuition is expressed clearly in Rousseaus Emile:
[the good man] is ordered in relation to the common centre, which is God, and in relation
to all the concentric circles, which are the creatures. If the divinity does not exist, it is
only the wicked man who reasons, and the good man is nothing but a fool (E: 292;
similar: E: 91; DI: 70, 101). 5
The loss of the Absolute only leads to Moral Nihilism only if one assumes that
such a link to the Absolute is necessary. Sade himself recognizes that the rejection of
Ethical Naturalism does not necessarily lead to Moral Nihilism, as noted by Braschi.
Braschi rejects both forms of Ethical Naturalism (that of Rousseau and that of the
Bataillian doctrine), yet concludes that man must develop his own laws: he is under
the control of his own laws, laws that are inherent in him (J: 767).
(One possible solution to the problem of morality, which will not be pursued in
this study, is to abandon the principle that an absolute moral ground to morality is
necessary. Charles E. Larmore, for example, argues that moral scepticism is based on
a questionable assumption of the relevance of metaphysics to ethical thought. Writes
Larmore, Our deepest moral commitmentsare commitments whose meaning for us
[whatever their origin] is that we come with them to the world, and not that we infer
Sade also reverses this thinking; as morality is the work of men, not of God, to go beyond morality is
to become superhuman. In The 120 Days the four friends- ( the four main characters) speak of what
mortals call crimes, for example, as if placing themselves beyond their species (120:293).
5
The reading of Rousseau as a reluctant Sadeian is reinforced by an earlier passage in this text- [h]ow
many times in my researches have I grown weary as a result of the coldness I felt within me! How
many times have sadness and boredom, spreading their poison over my first meditations, made them
unbearable for me! My arid heart provided only a languid and lukewarm zeal to the love of truth. I said
to myself, Why torment myself in seeking what is not? Moral good is only a chimera. There is nothing
good but the pleasures of the senses (E: 291).
171
them from the world. 6 Similarly, Simon Blackburn describes what he calls the
Rationalist approach to moral theory as an artefact of a bygone age). 7
The four meta- ethical standpoints in Sades work are set out in the two tables
below. Braschi (for a single paragraph, as noted) believes neither in deriving morals
from Nature, nor Moral Nihilism. Therefore, he holds a view compatible with the
Benthamite principle (as discussed in Chapter IV). The Bataille principle does hold
that a morality of sorts can be derived from Nature. Finally, Minski and Noirceuil
assume that Ethical Naturalism is false, and conclude that Moral Nihilism is true.
Meta-ethical positions in Sade.
Braschi
Benthamite Principle
Bataillian
Minski, Noirceuil
Principle
Ethical Naturalism
No & Yes
No
Yes
No
Moral Relativism
No
No
Yes
Moral Nihilism
No
No
Yes
Rousseau / Zam
yes
Bataillian Principle
Ethical Naturalism?
Braschi
Benthamite Principle
No
Nihilism
Notably, the only meta-ethical approach in Sades work that logically entails
destructive and homicidal acts is the Bataillian doctrine. This is because it affirms
6
Charles E. Larmore Patterns of Moral Complexity (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1992)
p.149
7
Simon Blackburn Being Good (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2001) p.133.
172
173
Sades engagement with Utilitarianism has already been introduced; both his
problematic application to Benthamite principles to sexuality, and his criticism of
classical Utilitarianisms psychological assumptions. Besides a number of sarcastic
comments, Sade also reveals some of the theorys shortcomings. 9 In particular, Sade
notes that it yields counterintuitive conclusions. Utilitarianism holds that pleasure is
the highest good, yet demands that one regard the interests of others as important as
ones own. To adhere to the demands of societys principles or the greater good, as
Sade puts it, is to inflict cruelties upon oneself (J: 143). In overriding the principle
of justice, Utilitarianism also justifies causing pain to the innocent (medical
experiments, for example- Sades preferred example; LNJ 1: 212; MV: 57, 59,104; J:
727-728). Rather than deal with such inconsistencies, Sade simply endorses
hedonism, presenting himself to the reader as an ethicist of a distinctly Epicurean
stripe: Imitate me, if you wish to be happy, he tells the reader; I guarantee
happiness (LNJ 1: 138, 366; 2:77). As such, Necali Polat notes, Sade anticipates the
very critique of Benthams utilitarianism offered by Rawls: what the Sadean
intervention does is to merely extract from the Benthamite principle, as superfluous,
the priority of the greater number over the lesser number, down to one single
DAlbert, in Juliette, discusses his corrupt political plans, adding that ...it is impossible to render all
men equally happy; therefore we hold our mission fulfilled when we have been able to satisfy several
among the many (J: 215). In La Nouvelle Justine the character Chrysostme asks rhetorically, estil essentiellement utile que les autres soient heureux? (is it necessarily useful that others could be
happy?; LNJ 2:34; similar: LNJ 1: 294).
174
individual. Which is precisely the move one finds in later liberal political theories,
such as that of John Rawls, against Utilitarianism. 10
The applications of Utilitarian thought in the novel Aline et Valcour are especially
ambiguous (the utopian society of Tamo therein, based on Utilitarian principles, will
be discussed at length in Chapter VII). Sades application of Utilitarian thought to
legal matters in particular seems more an unintentional critique of Utilitarianisms
incompatibility with justice than an endorsement. Sade describes a Bohemian criminal
gang leader- a free-thinking hero- who presides over a rape case. Instead of punishing
the rapist (who, incidentally, threatened to shoot the victim in the head), he states that
the rapist took as he had to (prise comme il fallait) and orders the plaintiff and
defendant to marry, adding that le devoir dun juge nest pas de punir, il est de
rendre les deux parties contentes autant quil est possible (the responsibility of a
judge is not to punish- it is to render both parties as content as is possible; AV: 539) 11
In keeping with the thought of both Kant and Hume, Sade also notes the inability
of instrumental reason (that is, confined to truths about the formal relations of ideas)
to formulate an ethics. Sade notes that it would not be contrary to reason to prefer the
destruction of millions for the sake of a minor pleasure. Juliette explains:
If from immolating three million human victims you stand to gain no livelier pleasure
than that to be had from eating a good dinner, slender though this pleasure may appear in
the light of its price, you ought to treat yourself to it without an instants hesitation; for if
you sacrifice the good dinner, the necessary result is a privation for you, whereas no
privation results from the disappearance of the three million insignificant creatures you
must do away with to obtain the dinner, because between it and you there exists a
10
Necati Polat Three Contemporaries: The International, Bentham, and De Sade, Social Text 65,
Robert Nozick writes of such suggestions :Deterrence theorists of the utilitarian sort would suggest
(something like) setting the penalty P for a crime at the least point where any penalty for the crime
greater than P would lead to more additional unhappiness inflicted in punishment than would be saved
to the (potential) victims of the crimes deterred by the additional increment in punishmentThis
utilitarian suggestion equates the unhappiness the criminals punishment causes him with the
unhappiness a crime causes its victim. It gives these two unhappinesses the same weight in calculating
a social optimum. Robert Nozick Anarchy, State and Utopia (New York: Basic Books, 1974) p.61.
175
relationship, however tenuous, whereas none exists between you and the three million
victims (J: 642). 12
Perversely, Sade draws the same conclusion as Hume, stating that it is sensibility, not
reason, which is the basis of making moral judgements. Clairwil- totally out of
character- describes a person without sensibility as an inert mass, equally incapable
of good or evil, and human only insofar as he has a human shape (J :277). Sade turns
Humes logic against itself by prioritizing reason, and instrumentality, over morality.
On her own terms, through attaining the state of apathy, Clairwil transcends humanity
and renders herself incapable of being a moral agent.
Finally, Sades characters universalize principles with disastrous consequences,
thus throwing a spanner in the works for Kant. For Kant, one decides whether an act
is moral or not through the universalization test. If one can consistently will that
every one perform the same act, the act passes the test. There are acts, however, that
appear to be ethically neutral, yet their universalization would have disastrous
consequences (a common example is paying up the full balance of ones credit card at
the end of every month-were every card holder to do this, the credit card companies
would collapse). A more striking example is voluntary extinction of the human race.
In the short story Eugnie de Franval, Monsieur de Franval speaks with his wife
concerning their daughters plans to marry. Monsieur de Franval warns that all
husbands are treacherous, unfaithful, cruel or despotic and that their daughter
should avoid marriage and having children (Sade here takes the two to be
synonymous).
12
David Hume, in 1739, Adam Smith, in 1759, and Jean Jacques Rousseau, in 1762, had already
made essentially the same point. Adam Smith, in 1752, writes of the typical persons attitude towards
the extermination of all China: [i]f he would lose his finger tomorrow, he would not sleep to-night;
but provided he never saw them, he would snore with the most profound security over the ruin of a
hundred million of his brethren. Adam Smith The Theory of Moral Sentiments. (Indianapolis: Liberty
Classics, 1976) pp.233-234. Rousseau, in Emile, writes: [p]rivate interest, which in case of conflict
necessarily prevails over everything, teaches everyone to adorn vice with the mask of virtue. Let all
other men do what is good for me at their expense; let everything be related to me alone; let all
mankind, if need be, die in suffering and poverty to spare me a moment of pain and hunger. This is the
inner language of every unbeliever who reasons (E: 314). Finally, Hume wrote that it was rational to
prefer the destruction of the whole world to the scratching of my finger. David Hume, Humes Moral
and Political Philosophy ed. Henry D. Aiken (New York: Hafner Press, 1948) p.25.
176
Philosophy, for Sade, is to combat, discredit, destroy, extirpate- he leaves the slate
clean, leaving others to do what they will with the empty space (J: 592). Sade
undermines every major ethical proposal of his age without need of a coherent ethics,
just as a virus can fell a donkey without teeth and claws.
La Mettrie 14
In keeping with his materialism and determinism, Sade assumes that all human acts
are determined and that, consequently, there is no free will. Hence, there is no
morality, or just grounds for punishment. 15 Writes Sade (through Madame Delbne):
All moral effects...are to be related to physical causes, unto which they are linked most
absolutely: the drumstick strikes the taut-drawn skin and the sound answers the blow: no
physical cause, that is, no collision, and of necessity theres no moral effect, that is, no
noise. Certain dispositions peculiar to our organisms, the neural fluids more or less
irritated by the nature of the atoms we inhale, by the species or quantity of the nitrous
particles contained in the food making up our diet, by the flow of humours and by yet a
13
La Mettrie p.103.
15
Here Sade follows La Mettrie, who held that some unfortunately born could not help but find
criminal activities intensely pleasurable, and that the sentiment of guilt is in fact the erroneous fruit
of education, and dHolbach, who thought that there were no criminals, only those unfortunately
born, who could not help themselves from committing acts deemed deviant or criminal by the rest of
society (La Mettrie pp.141, 155; dHolbach System of Nature pp. 7, 50, 59, 137, 172, 212). Abb
Bergier, similarly, held that some people required stronger sensations of pleasure than others due to
their natural constitution. See Jean Deprun Sade et labb Bergier, p.8.
177
thousand other external causes- this is what moves a person to crime or to virtue and
often, within the space of a single day, or both... 16 And so it is madness, it is simply
extravagance to refrain from doing whatever we please, and, having done it, to repent of
it. (J: 15).
The sense that we have free will is dismissed as a mere cognitive illusion. The
character Bernis (Juliette) states that ...in the moment when the decision is taken it is
not we who determine it, it is enjoined upon us... and as a consequence our will is not
free (J: 677). Elsewhere, Sade writes that personality traits are determined in the
womb: [i]t is in the mothers womb that are fashioned the organs which must render
us susceptible of this or that fantasy; the first objects which we encounter, the first
conversations we overhear, determine the pattern; do what it will, education is
incapable of altering the pattern (LNJ 1:356). Sade concludes that, with sufficient
information, it would be possible to predict all of a persons behavior: l homme est
une espce de machine presque toujours dtermine par lhabitude (AV: 522). Sade
also holds that ones capacity for feeling pity is physiologically determined (AV: 644,
645). Hence, the libertines hold that they may lack an innate moral sense through no
fault of their own, as they had no choice but to act on their desires, which they did not
consciously choose (AV:344). 17 The libertines insist that one cannot be punished for
ones tastes (sommes-nous les matres de nos gots?), that these tastes cannot
be changed through education, and that they themselves are blind instruments of the
will of Nature or even mentally ill (LNJ 1: 362, also 356, 357; 120: 499; AV: 344;
CL: 30). (An unstated assumption here is that criminal tastes entail an uncontrollable
desire, and that the desire to commit crime is simply a taste; LNJ 1: 358, 361). 18
Consequently, any punishment for crimes, Sades characters insist, is an injustice. In
dissolving the distinction between human agency and the natural order, Sade dissolves
St. Augustines distinction between natural and moral evil. Writes Sean Spence, a
neurologist, the more we know how sociopaths and killers differ at the neurological
16
17
Roy F. Baumeister largely rejects the idea that people lack self control, regarding it as a dangerous
cultural artefact. He concludes that the very notion of an irresistible impulse seems to me to be a
cultural construction and one that is highly questionable on psychological grounds. Steven Pinker, on
the other hand, thinks that sociopathy and other anti-social traits may be hereditary. Baumeister pp.274277; Pinker pp. 259-263.
18
For discussion, see also Fauskevg pp.21- 25; Han and Valla A propos p.111.
178
level, it seems that the space for moral evil contracts - exactly as dHolbach, La
Mettrie and Sade suggested. 19 Significantly, Sade repeats this doctrine in both the
pornographic, libertine works (The 120 Days of Sodom, Justine, La Nouvelle
Justine, Juliette) and the non-pornographic Aline et Valcour. Zam, who gives some
rather crude arguments for hard determinism, suggests that even the most gentle laws
are unjust (AV: 346-347). There is perhaps some merit to making, as did Hobbes, a
distinction between premeditated crime and passionate crimes. 20 But Sades subjects
appear to be claiming to be blind instruments of passion continuously, which
Hobbes would classify as madness. Sades apologetics for murder, were it
consistently applied, amounts to no more than an insanity defence.
As Carter and others have noted, there are some obvious contradictions in
Sades works concerning free will. The libertines consider themselves free of the pull
of social convention and the natural, yet also pride themselves on apparently
following the authority of the passions, despite the fact that they are, in effect,
agencies of the given order of things. Further, crime, within the terms of Sades
scheme, is conceptually impossible, the very notion of crime being reliant upon the
traditional moral framework. Juliette compares herself and her friends to
mountainous peaks, ...and virtuous folk resemble those flat stretches of Piedmont
countryside whose mournful evenness depresses, but she must also accept that,
according to her own philosophy, she did not choose to become a serial killer any
more than a volcano chooses to kill villagers (J:951). Sades character Chigi makes
this explicit: we all, through some blind force that is in us, a force both irrational and
essential, we are but stupid machines of the vegetation whose secret workings,
explaining the origin of all motion, also demonstrate the origin of all human and
19
Sean Spence Bad or Mad? New Scientist 181 (20 March 2004):38-41, p.40. For discussion on this
topic, see also James Waller Becoming Evil: how ordinary people commit Genocide & Mass Killing
(Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2002); Jonathan H. Pincus Basic Instincts: What makes Killers Kill
(New York: Norton & Company, 2001).
20
A crime arising from a sudden passion is not as great as when the same ariseth from long
meditation Thomas Hobbes Leviathan Edwin Curley, ed. (Indianapolis/ Cambridge: Hackett
Publishing Company, Inc.1994) p.200. There is one case of passionate murder in Aline et Valcour, in
which a man, named Don Juan, blinded by tempestuous passion, stabs his lover to death and then is
overcome with remorse (AV: 566). Goulemot notes that this episode is highly ambiguous (847, n. 584).
179
animal activity (J: 743; also 120: 199, 784; similar: LNJ 1:356). This doctrinal
tension is never resolved in Sades work.
I will now turn to the Why be Moral? question.
21
John Van Ingen Why Be Moral? The Egoistic Challenge (New York: Peter Lang, 1994) p.37-55.
22
Brian Medlin Ultimate Principles and Ethical Egoism, Australasian Journal of Philosophy 35
(1957), 111-118. Quoted in Van Ingen p.79. Paul W. Taylor holds that this ultimate question is not
decidable through reason. Paul W. Taylor Principles of Ethics: An Introduction. (Encino, California:
Dickenson Publishing, 1975) p. 225, quoted in Van Ingen p.20.
23
F.H. Bradley Why should I be moral? In Ethical Studies (selected essays), 3-28 (New York:
180
Juliette does not debate Lorsange, but refutes him by means of a practical
demonstration- she poisons him (noting that he becomes increasingly pious as the
poison takes effect in his brain), takes all his money, and continues in her exploits. In
the structure of the novel, her methodology functions as a response to the imprudence
argument.
Sades characters do not advocate just any criminal lifestyle, which would simply
be irrational. 25 They give several specific pieces of advice for successful criminal
24
This is the so-called Socratic View as taken in Socrates early dialogues. For discussion, see
Martha C. Nussbaum The Fragility of Goodness: Luck and Ethics in Greek Tragedy and Philosophy
(Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1986). Hobbes (in a quote that illustrates the intellectual gulf
that separates him from Sade), expresses this view also: ... [t]he source of every crime is some defect
of the understanding, or some error of reasoning, or some sudden force of the passions. Thomas
Hobbes Leviathan ed. Edwin Curley (Indianapolis and Cambridge: Hackett Publishing Company, Inc,
1994) p.191.
25
181
Thirdly, the student must be mindful of the inconsistencies of the law. Sade observesand this is still largely true today- that punishments for criminal offences are classbased. White-collar crime is typically punished much more leniently than more
working class crime (J: 215, 124). 27 The poor petty thief is executed, whereas
Juliette gets away scot-free when she declares herself bankrupt and ruins the
livelihoods of dozens of people. 28 Clairwil advises:
...having regard to the laws of the country where he resides, in such sort that if the pettiest
is punished and the most frightful is not, then it is very assuredly the most frightful you
26
This suffices as a reply to Robert Nozicks argument as to why criminal activity does not pay.
Nozick writes that the antisocial being tends to overestimate ones chances of success in evading
detection and punishment, and that we have an uncontrollable tendency to feel guilt and shame, and to
communicate this to others. See Robert Nozick Invariances: The Structure of the Objective World
(Cambridge, Massachusetts: The Belknap Press of Harvard University Press, 2001) pp. 272-273.
27
Stephen Pfohl notes that corporate, organizational, or white- collar crime, whilst being among the
most costly forms of lawbreaking to society as a whole, is relatively lightly punished. Pfohl Images of
Deviance p.84.
28
Again, this was a complaint made by earlier philosophes. See Denis Diderot Jacques the fatalist and
his Master (1796) trans. J. Robert Loy (Washington Square: New York University Press, 1959) p.220;
La Mettrie p.131.
182
must let [your student] commit. For, once again, it is not from crime you must shelter
him, but from the sword that smites the perpetrator of crime: crime entails no
disadvantages, its punishment entails many (J: 279-280; see also 116, 204, 487,
777). 29
The most important advice in Sade concerning crime is to simply evade the reach of
the law. Sade proposes three ways in which this can be achieved. One can operate in
collusion with those in power, become powerful oneself, or establish secret societies
and coordinate with other immoral people. Sades thought here follows that of
Thrasymachus and Glaucon, in Platos Republic, and Callicles, in Platos Gorgias. 30
Thrasymachus seeks a satisfactory reply to the suggestion that morality is simply
whatever is convenient for those in positions of power. After Socrates rejection of
this proposal, Glaucon restates the argument in a different form, adding that it could
be in ones best interests to be a tyrant, and gives a detailed description of what being
a successful tyrant would entail. The prospective tyrant requires a secret society of
colleagues who have also secured important offices in government. They will have a
vested interest in keeping society as safe and stable as possible, so that they may
predate upon it all the more easily. They will behave in an honorable manner whilst in
the public eye, only committing crimes against others when no one can catch them
out. The tyrant will have to be deceitful. Socrates says that such a life will be
difficult, to which Glaucon replies, nothing worth while is easy. 31 Sades characters
reason in much the same manner. Yet his treatment of the secret society is more fully
sketched out than that of Glaucon, and exposes some of its doctrinal problems. Before
treating these, I will address what I will term the self- harm argument and the dont be
a schmuck argument.
29
Thrasymachus, in Platos Republic, makes the same point; when a man succeeds in robbing the
whole body of citizens and reducing them to slavery, they forget these ugly names and call him happy
and fortunate... Plato The Republic pp.85-86.
30
Whether Sade had read the Republic or not is not known, although he had certainly seen the name
Glaucon; Rousseau refers to Glaucon in his demonstration that the honest life is superior to that of the
wealthy tyrant (E: 19). Jean Deprun has noted the similarity between Sade and Callicles, and that there
was an excellent translation available in Sades time. Jean Deprun Sade devant la Rgle dor,
p.309. Foucault makes the association of Juliette and Thrasymachus, as noted in Chapter I (MC: xi-xii).
31
183
Although Socrates describes this aspect as a part of all of us, he thinks that to give
in to its demands is to become enslaved, and to allow the divine part of ourselves to
be starved. Furthermore, owing to the dynamics of the tyrants social arrangements,
he will by necessity be surrounded by rather base people; anyone of quality would be
32
Voltaire Philosophical Dictionary (1764) trans. Theodore Besterman (London: Penguin, 1972) p.68.
Plato Republic p.392. In Gorgias Socrates resorts to a rather weak analogy between the body and the
state, and to punishment after death, which he admits may simply be ludicrous old wives tales. Plato
Gorgias trans. Robin Waterfield (London: Penguin, 1994) p.126.
184
Voltaire Philosophical Dictionary p.29. Similarly, Hume holds that one must sacrifice inward peace
of mind, consciousness of integrity, a satisfactory review of [his] own conduct; that he loses
fellowship with his peers for the sake of the feverish, empty amusements of luxury. David Hume
Enquiry Concerning the Principles of Morals (1751) (Cambridge: Hackett Publishing Company, 1983),
p.82. Writes Richard Joyce, This is a more promising argument [than moral harm to self], but it has
inevitable limits. Our stipulated criminal participates in a sincere and caring manner in his local
community, and wouldnt dream of cheating his friends. It is only upon a neighbouring community that
his harmful activities are visited. Joyce p.33.
35
Sades Justine and Juliette were published anonymously for this very reason; when arrested for their
authorship in 1799, he claimed to be merely their copyist (PB: 111-112). He also attributed his
dangerously blasphemous poem La Vrit to La Mettrie. In uvres compltes du Marquis de Sade
ed. Annie le Brun, Jean-Jacques Pauvert (Paris: Pauvert, 1986). Vol. I p.551.
185
of philosophy was itself essentially illegal rather complicates Socrates assertion that
lawless pleasures block the path to philosophy. For Sade, quite literally, philosophy
was itself a lawless pleasure (as it was for Socrates himself, in the end); and obeisance
to the law in 18th century France, for an intellectual, would itself be self-harm for
those who sought to go beyond the confines of accepted doctrine. Further, where
Sade associates immorality with the crime of anal sex or homosexuality, his thinking
is typical of the period (Kant not only accepted that sodomy, homosexuality and
masturbation were immoral, but argued the case in the terms of his own ethical
thought). 36
Whether Sadeian characters could have truly satisfying relationships with their
peers is not a straightforward question, and will be discussed more fully in the
discussion of the Secret Society below. As discussed in the previous chapter, Sades
characters do have a conception of love and friendship amongst other libertines.
Competition with ones peers is welcomed; fear of conflict is dismissed as a trait of
the weak. Sades characters are birds of a feather, and would assumedly not be able to
enjoy, or keep, any other company (all of this contradicts both the reading of Sade as
advocating absolute isolation from other people, and the Machiavellian principle,
stated by Juliette, of avoiding the use of accomplices).37
36
For discussion of Kants sexual morality, see Soble Kant and Sexual Perversion.
37
Machiavellis name appears frequently in Sade, yet Sade does not discuss or borrow from
Machiavelli at length. Instead, he repeatedly states the same two Machiavellian principles; a). if you
use accomplices, destroy them as soon as possible; and b). maintain power through violence, fear, and
ruse (J: 147, 316; 479-480, 637, 934 AV: 725). Sade tends to vulgarize Machiavelli, attributing him
such advice as using mass starvation or murder to maintain power (PB:315,336). For discussion of
Sades use of Machiavelli, see Fauskevg pp.104, 124; Catherine Cusset Sade, Machiavel et Nron,
Dix-huitime Sicle 22 (1990): 401-411.
186
There are two kinds of wicked men in the world: those whom great wealth and prodigious
influence put beyond the reach of so tragic an end [the scaffold], and those who, if
apprehended, will not avoid it. The latter kind, born with nothing, if they have any wit at
all, can have only two prospects in view: either Wealth or the Wheel (MV: 127). 38
Again, Sade applies rigid notions of right and wrong (the poor, he writes, must
become wicked to escape the Wheel) to a scenario that cannot justify such
classifications or condemnations. 39 Only a severely dogmatic moralist could declare
Juliette immoral simply because she turned to prostitution, or Justine truly virtuous
because she foolishly trusts every monk, no matter how many times she is abused. It
is an open question as to whether the laws and institutions of a state are ethical at all if
people incur the full force of the law in merely stealing food, or cohabiting out of
wedlock, as was frequent in the 18th century. Sade makes a point in noting that being
rational is only contingently related to being law-abiding (in 1797, for a British
woman to avoid wedlock yet enjoy sex, as Sade recommends, would have
automatically made her a criminal in the eyes of the law; sufficient grounds for being
sent to Australia). 40 Yet this is quite different to a critique of being moral. In an
environment in which not even killing is forbidden, as Simon Blackburn notes,
society (for those that cannot protect themselves) has simply dissolved, and no
decision concerning moral orientation can be made. 41 Sade also uses the dont be a
schmuck argument in a dishonest way. He demonstrates that, in some cases, it is
necessary to break the law to acquire the basic necessities of life (as this world is
38
The Wheel, notes David Coward, was a form of torturous execution. The criminal was
spreadeagled on a horizontally slung cartwheel and his limbs were broken by successive blows with an
iron bar until death ensued. When mercy was recommended, the victim was strangled before the
sentence was carried out or, to expedite matters, the executioner was allowed to deliver heavy blows
(the coups de grce) to the chest or stomach (MV: 269-270, n127).
39
Sades characters use exactly the same cynical logic in a political context, as discussed in Chapter
VII.
40
Patrick Colquhoun, in his Treatise on the Police of the Metropolis (1797), claimed that 115,000
people- one in eight- was a member of the criminal class of the City of London. Colquhoun classified
scavengers and gypsies as members of this class, as well as 50,000 harlots, many of whom were
simply women cohabiting out of wedlock, in an age when divorce was impossible. Cited in Robert
Hughes The Fatal Shore (London: Pan, 1987) p.24.
41
Simon Blackburn Being Good (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2001) p.71.
187
utterly corrupt) as a defence of breaking the law for the mere pleasure of it (the
libertines- by definition- never commit immoral acts out of necessity).
Sades case for the rationality, if not the reasonableness, of immorality is
strengthened if this argument is dropped. To be truly immoral actually requires that
many others are not immoral. Accordingly, John Van Ingen notes that the why be
moral? question should really be why should I be moral in a society with a relatively
stable political and legal system in which a large majority of the population not only
respects the law but also holds similar versions of a conventional morality?42
Likewise, John Bigelow suggests immoral conduct may be adaptive to the
environment under stable social conditions. 43 He has illustrated this with his Rats
and Lemmings computer model, which is based on research into Simpsons Paradox
and Game Theory. Bigelow explains: [i]magine the lemmings to be altruistic and
self-sacrificing, or alternatively imagine them to be irrational, inefficient or lazy
either way, by one means or another, imagine that they behave in ways that benefit
their neighbours at their own expense. Imagine the rats to be selfish, rational and
efficient, and regularly to gain benefits at the expense of their neighbours. Bigelow
has found that, in populations in which the lemmings outnumber the rats, the rats
flourish, so long as their numbers remain small. In populations in which the rats
dominate, life is made worse for both lemmings and rats. Therefore, being a rationally
self interested, lazy and parasitic person- that is, a Sadeian libertine- may be
advantageous so long as the population only sustains a limited number of beings such
as oneself. Bigelow concludes: In these games [of the type similar to Bigelows Rats
and Lemmings] it is a surprising result that populations robustly sustain a proportion
of Suckers or Lemmings in the long term. Sharks and Rats never disappear
completely, but nor do they ever take over completely. Thus, Simpson's Paradox
42
43
are drawn from individual sets of data, and yet the opposite conclusion can be drawn if the data sets are
all added together. This indicates a way, in particular, in which patterns could evolve under Darwinian
natural selection which runs strongly against adaptationist expectations. In a similar way, business
inefficiencies could be unexpectedly resilient even in an ideally free market. Bigelow; paper
abstract: Simpson's Paradox and the Game of Life Centre for Biomedical Engineering, University of
Adelaide. Wednesday 8th August 2001. Sourced at:
www.eleceng.adelaide.edu.au/Groups/centre_bme/seminars/2001/Bigelow01.html
188
places a constraint on how selfish, how efficient and how rational businesses or
organisms can become. On balance, this is probably cheerful news. 44 Ultimately,
Sades contention that adopting a ratty strategy in a society of other rats is not
plausible. The flourishing of his characters (if one can call it that) is largely due to
their wealth and power, or assets that can be converted into the protection of the
wealthy and powerful (such as sexual attractiveness, in the case of Juliette), and not
primarily because of their lack of morality. Whether one is a rat or a lemming in a
totally corrupt age may in fact be trivial, and ones fate may be more or less the
same unless one attains enough power over other rats (the theme of power in Sade
will be further developed in following chapters). In fact, Bigelows finding- that being
a rat only pays off when everyone else is a lemming- exactly matches the world of
Sades novels. Sades libertine characters do not live in utterly corrupted
environments. They are able to lie, cheat, steal, and deceive people precisely because
their victims are trusting and assume that others are trustworthy, parasiting upon the
ethical structures of the society upon which they prey. What is not so cheerful news is
the possibility that, so long as there are not many other sociopaths, sociopathy may
map onto, or constitute, a perfectly rational strategy. 45
Sade associates the attainment with power with immorality, and being moral with
being weak. In a ratty society, clearly, being powerful is better than being weak, but
it is not obvious that there is such a link between the attainment and holding of power
and immorality. 46 If one assumes that weak people can be evil, and strong people can
be moral, Sades account founders. 47
44
Gary Malinas, John Bigelow, "Simpson's Paradox", The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy
Linda Mealey has suggested that psychopaths may represent a minority strategy. Linda Mealey
The Sociobiology of sociopathy: An integrated evolutionary model, Behavioural and brain Sciences
18 (1995): 523-99.
46
One could become more powerful through cultivating a reputation for being trustworthy, for
example. Democracy, ideally, forces such a situation. A business example could work just as well; in a
189
I suspect that this association of virtue and the renouncing of worldly power is due to Sades
Christian heritage.
48
49
Sades account is not novel, however; discussions of secret societies and their exotic moralities
appear in the writings of Rousseau, Helvtius and Diderot. Rousseau was preoccupied with secret
societies, and his speculations concerning shadowy conspiracies are similar to those of Sade. He
discusses the secretive Council of Ten who ran Venice by stealth, and suggested that wars had been
started by cynical financiers with profits to be made thereby. He also refers to the machinations of the
Jesuits (C: 595; SC: 170, DI: 149). Both Helvtius and Diderot had considered the moral systems of
criminal groups; Helvtius Treatise on Man vol. II p.309; Diderot Droit naturel In uvres politiques,
ed. Paul Vernire (Paris: Garnier, 1966): 29-35, p.34. Quoted in Bennington Sade Laying Down the
Law, pp. 40-41.
50
Deepak Sawhney, Stephen Pfohl, Adorno and Horkheimer and others have noted the similarities
between Sades description of the Libertines and the negative aspects of Capitalism. In reply, I suggest
that the real source of the problem is the nature of organizational structures, rather than the economic
190
second group is the shadow government, which typically plans vast conspiracies
involving mass murder. Two notable examples are the Northern Lodge of Stockholm,
a Masonic group, which conspires to lead France to revolt and cause global anarchy,
and the Secret Government of Venice, which plots to destroy entire rebellious villages
with biochemical agents (J: 864, 1150, 1188, 1192). 51
The third group are made up of wealthy, powerful individuals (typically made up of
pillars of society, such as ministers, high court judges, and police chiefs) who seek
to pool their resources for the pleasures of raping, torturing and murdering women
and children (the only difference is of scale; that described in 120 has only four core
members; that in Juliette has four hundred). The most thoroughly described such
society is the Society of the Friends of Crime, described in Juliette.
The text of Juliette includes the full statutes of the Society, which covers all
aspects of its functioning. This text, running to ten pages and forty-five particular
dynamic as such, given that socialist systems also create oppressive structures. Deepak Sawhney
Unmasking Sade In Sawhney ed. Must we burn Sade? (New York: Humanity Books, 1999): 1530:27; Stephen Pfohl Seven Mirrors p.56.
51
Many of the most bizarre and horrifying schemes described in Sades work are derived from the
paranoia of the period, in particular the conspiracy theories that were circulating during the French
Revolution. In Juliette, Sade suggests that French government officials were plotting to starve the
population through manipulation of the grain supply, that an international Masonic conspiracy
dedicated to exterminating all the worlds monarchies was responsible for the fall of the Swedish
government, and that plans were afoot to kill the entire Catholic population of France (the latter idea
was not so much a conspiracy theory as a continuation of the trend of systematic imprisonment and
execution of clergymen; J:478-479, 500-501, 549, 850-871). Sades text also states that the French
Revolution had been instigated by the Jacobins and Jesuits (J: 501n). Lacombe cites several texts that
detail such conspiracy theories that bear a textual resemblance to Sades work, in particular Le
Tombeau de Jacques Molay by Cadet- Gassicourt (which details the role played by the Masons in the
fall of the Swedish government), and the work of abb Barruel. Barruel accused the Masons for
instigating the French Revolution. He also linked the Masons with the atheistic philosophes, an
association that Sade also makes. Barruels conspiracy theory involves a plot to kill all the kings and
the pope, demoralise the people, exhaust the population, corrupt morality, and ruin the public treasury.
It was also commonly believed that the Templars and Masons engaged in elaborate and bizarre orgies,
another Sadeian motif. Lacombe pp.62-83; 94-100. For discussion on the roll played by the
Freemasons in disseminating Enlightenment ideas and a-religious literature, see Margaret C. Jacob The
Radical Enlightenment: Pantheists, Freemasons and Republicans (London: George Allen & Unwin,
1981).
191
We can therefore describe the Sodality as being -micro-Benthamite and macroBataillian. Benthamite principles are adhered to with regards to its own members (cooperation for maximum pleasure) but, with regards to non- members, in particular the
six hundred children imprisoned in the seraglios, adheres to the principle that the
strong should predate upon the weak. Whether Sades doctrine here stands depends on
whether this dual ideology can be sustained without inconsistency.
Two other aspects of the Sodalitys principles sit uneasily with the rest of Sades
works. Firstly, for the purposes of maximizing utility, the Sodality adheres to what
appears to be a social contract, despite Sades mockery of it, as noted earlier in the
chapter. Secondly, there is a sense of fraternity and mutual support (romantic love is
banned, in keeping with the observations concerning love and friendship discussed in
52
Such codes exist in The 120 Days of Sodom and La Nouvelle Justine also; the Statutes of the Sodality
of the Friends of Crime differs in that it is written specifically for the libertines themselves (120:241249; LNJ 1:316-319)
53
One statute suggests that the Sodality is Sades fantasy of a place where he could feel at home.
192
Chapter IV; J: 423). 54 The eighth statute reads: [t]he Members of the Sodality,
united through it into one great family, share all of their hardships as they do their
joys; they aid one another mutually in all lifes situations... (J: 420, 423).
Accordingly, members are required to address each other en tutoyant, to express
fraternity (J: 423; III: 556n.2).
The ethics of the Sodality are enforced with an elaborate political and legal
structure. The Sodality elects, by secret ballot, a President each month, of either sex,
whose chief duty is to see that the Sodalitys laws are respected (J: 420). The
Sodalitys membership of four hundred members is to be made up of equal numbers
of men and women (J: 424). 55 The rules and regulations of the Sodality fulfil several
functions, besides merely pooling resources. Firstly, the rules protect the members
from each other. Bullying, dueling, and the carrying of weapons- not so much as a
walking stick- within the Sodalitys premises are all forbidden (suggesting a certain
amount of distrust; J:421, 424, 425). Murder is banned, except of the victims in the
seraglios. Cruelty towards another member is forbidden: no cruel passion, save
whipping upon the buttocks only, may be given vent to (J: 421). Sexually transmitted
diseases are checked by the Sodality surgeon, and seriously diseased members are
expelled (J: 424). The role of the Censor, the Sodalitys disciplinary officer, is to
maintain decorum and a propitious atmosphere...to see to the preservation of quiet,
moderating laughter and conversations and everything else that is not in the spirit of
libertinage or that is damaging to it (J: 423). As noted above, an emergency fund is
maintained for members in legal trouble (J: 420).
The rules also protect the society as a collective. Betrayal of its secrets is
punished with execution; involvement in politics (which would assumedly attract
undue attention) is banned also (J: 421, 424, 425). The society is also protected from
54
Juliettes natural instinct for fellow feeling is expressed as camaraderie for other moral outsiders:
By some quirk of the imagination, by some curious way of reckoning, thanks to some feeling Id
perhaps had difficulty explaining clearly, even to myself, I never wanted to wrong anyone as corrupt as
I. It is doubtless here the old story of honor among thieves, or of mutual respect; but it was operative in
me (J: 159; similar: 969).
55
In keeping with Sades commitment to ideological vertigo, and in matching every doctrine with its
opposite, the Societys president gives a talk on misogyny, whilst the societys female members are
issued with a pamphlet advising on the viciousness of men (J: 431; 502).
193
56
The same pattern is found in the 120 Days, in which a story-teller, brought to Silling for the purpose,
194
57
Jean Imbert Le droit antique (Paris : Presses Universitaires de France, 1961) p.112. Quoted in Hnaff
p.219.
58
la solidit de notre association devient utile sa conservation et que, pour son maintien, nous
prfrons quelques sacrifices dont tous les moyens que nous avons ici de faire de mal savant nous
ddommager amplement. Ne timagine pas que nous nous chrissons beaucoup pour cela ; nous nous
voyons tous les jours de trop prs pour nous aimer : mais nous sommes obligs dtre ensemble, et
nous nous y maintenons par politique, peu prs comme les voleurs dont la sret de lassociation na
dautres bases que le vice et la ncessit de lexercer (LNJ 1 :381).
195
rational. 59 Insofar as Sades libertines do, after negotiations, settle on rules of conduct,
hence, notions of justice and punishment, this makes problematic his dismissal of
true justice as being chimerical(J:171).
Pinker pp.255-258; Steven Kuhn "Prisoner's Dilemma" In The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy
In The Fable of the Bees or, Private Vices, Publick Benefits (1725), Bernard Mandeville (1670-1733)
had argued that humans are by nature base and egoistic, and that vice, corruption and the satisfaction of
desire were the only viable basis for building a thriving economy. For the greatest publick benefit, he
argued, it is only necessary that we act in accordance with our instinct for private vices, but conduct
ourselves in a rational manner; the invisible hand of the market place (as Smith would later refer to it)
would sort out the rest. Sade appears to have known of this principle. Sades Aline et Valcour the
philosopher-king Zam states that, in his Utopian state, je tche de profiter des dfauts ou des vices
pour les rendre les plus utiles possible au reste des citoyens (AV: 365). See Bernard Mandeville The
Fable of the Bees or Private vices, Publick Benefits, 2 vols. (Indianapolis: Liberty Classics, 1988). I
thank Charles Pigden for pointing this text out to me. DHolbach, too, effectively reduced morality to
rational self interest; DHolbach System of Nature pp. 99,108, 221.
In Invariances, Nozick writes: The function of ethics is to protect and promote voluntary
cooperation and coordination between people, to guide this cooperation (through norms of division of
benefits), and to demarcate the domain of such cooperation (which people are to be the participants):
also, to specify what is to be done when the above rules, norms, etc. are not followed, that is, to
specify norms of response to different kinds of non- cooperation (should it be met by boycott,
punishment, retribution?) ;and to guide or mandate character virtues relevant to cooperation, and to
peoples response to noncooperators (Nozick Invariances pp 266-267). As for the notion of ethics as
196
arrangements that foster mutual altruism are typically symmetrical; that is, the
rewards, punishments and temptations concerning cooperation or defection from the
social contract are the same for each player.61 The fact is that the real world is not
an even playing field. In this sense, Sade is correct to reject the supposition that it is.
The members of Sades Society of the Friends of Crime are all extremely wealthy
and hold high offices in the government- their power is evinced in the fact that a
statute bans them from using their influence in politics (J: 425). They cannot afford to
harm each other (Necati Polat notes that Sades libertines interact with one another as
equal sovereigns, that is, as nation-states). 62 Accordingly, Sades characters do not
cooperate with people who give nothing in return, are more valuable to them against
their own free will (children to be raped and killed, primarily), and people who do not
pose a threat. 63 Individuals who are too weak to participate as equal players are
reduced to their exchange value, as sex objects. 64
Maurice Blanchot 65
To succeed as an immoral agent, one must operate in conjunction with other
immoral agents- that is, as a society. This solution leads to some doctrinal problems.
This is because, as Fink notes, Sade never fully develops the mechanics of libertine
assisting people (or other entities) that may not, or cannot, directly cooperate with us, Nozick writes of
these Higher levels of ethics that they are matters of personal choice or personal ideal, rather than
the core of morality (ibid. p.281).
61
62
Polat p.14. President Saint-Fond can afford to expel Juliette precisely because she has no political
rank, and her monetary assets are essentially gifted to her by wealthier people with higher connections
(J: 550).
63
Rousseau had essentially made the same point: There is no profit so legitimate that it cannot be
exceeded by what can be made illegitimately and an injury done to a neighbour is always more
lucrative than any service (DI: 147-148; see also SC: 21).
64
Monsieur Dubourg explains the principle of capitalism to Justine, a girl of 12, when she refuses to
have sex with him for money: on what grounds do you believe that Wealth should extend a helping
hand seeing that you serve its purpose in no way whatsoever? (MV:13).
65
Maurice Blanchot Sade (Preface to La Nouvelle Justine and Juliette) in uvres Compltes (Paris:
Cercle du livre Prcieux, 1966-1967) VI : 11-43, p.20. Cited in Fink Political system in Sade p.511.
197
relationships, namely those of power with power. 66 Firstly, membership of the secret
society apparently entails the same conflicts and anxieties that (for Sade) characterize
conventional morality and social compromise; that human legislation which forces
one to forego certain things (J: 143). This places Sades insistence on the injustice
and impossibility of social compromise in an interesting light. Delbne, earlier in
Juliette, states that words like punishments, rewards, commandments, prohibitions,
order, and disorder are merely allegorical terms drawn from what transpires in the
sphere of human events and intercourse (Sades italics; J:41). At this, one can replyso what? The libertines of the Sodality themselves do not consider their own
commandments and prohibitions as merely allegorical (again, note the curiously
religious tone in Delbnes reasoning; ethics is merely human, therefore is in some
sense diminished).
Secondly, there is a basic doctrinal contradiction involved in the Secret Society, of
which there are two aspects. Firstly, there is a tension between the Benthamite and
Bataillian principles. Secondly, there is a tension between the contractual nature of the
Society, and the libertines disdain for such contracts (expressed less elegantly there
is a tension between the Benthamite-Contract doctrine and the Bataille-Isolationist
doctrine). The libertine position, writes Hnaff, is to affirm naked, undisguised
strength or to recognize it wherever it is obliged to operate in disguise. As such, the
contractual relationship is an abdication or domestication of strength. 67 Sades
disdain for contractual agreements, to be consistent, ought to apply whether the
contract is in the name of good or evil (especially so if such a dichotomy has been
dismissed as groundless, as is the case for the resolutely nihilistic characters). Beatrice
Fink notes this problem also: Although master libertines overtly pledge loyalty to
one another as a measure of enlightened self- interest, at times they dispose of one
another when they are so inclined, eg. la Durands false accusations intentionally
leading to Clairwils murder by Juliette 68
Likewise, the conflict between Benthamite and Bataillian principals is evident in
the first lines of the Statutes. The introductory passage states clearly that there are no
crimes; even to murder is allegedly to act in accordance with Nature. Were a member
66
67
Hnaff p.221.
68
198
to start killing other members in the midst of an orgy, they would only be
contradicting the Benthamite principal. Yet the members contradict this principal
insofar as they imprison and torture children. It cannot be both ways.
Imagine that Minski travels up to Paris and joins the Sodality (suppose that he
convinces the President that he is in fact from Paris, which is a requisite). He agrees to
submit to the one-month probation period, and swears to atheism and the god of
pleasure, as required, in accordance with Statute N3 (J:419). (Note that the Statutes
do not require that one swear on Statute N8, which unites all members as one great
family). A welcoming orgy ensues. Minski cannot penetrate anyone without killing
the recipient of his enormous member, so he glumly accepts passive anal sex and so
forth. Yet, if he is to honour his vows and worship pleasure, he will simply have to
start killing. The Censor calls a stop to the orgy, and tells Minski that he must leave,
as he has broken the rules. Suppose that Minski replies as follows:
a). I was asked to swear to atheism, and the god of pleasure; I was not asked to swear to
any other principal. I am a man of my word (just a quirk, mind you- I am a nihilist, after
all).
b). The 8th statute is groundless. Even if every Sodality member here really was a family
member, this gives no grounds for mutual care- the rules of the Sodality themselves state
that all offspring of Sodality members are abandoned to the Seraglio, as child sex slaves,
at the age of seven. I myself raped and killed every member of my own family, male and
female (J: 580). I do not understand such irrational sentiments as love for family
members. Frankly, I doubt that you do either. Perhaps you refer to your peers here as
siblings in a metaphorical sense; this is not, however, an argument.
c). I am a giant, forty- five and in my prime, and can easily overpower every one of you,
in particular as you have banned all weapons from the chamber. You see yourselves as
superior to all others by the grace of your intelligence and wealth. I personally own an
entire Italian district. I note that your doctrine is absurd and contradictory, hence
demonstrating my intellectual superiority. In keeping with the Law of the Strong, the
reduction of all value to my own sovereign pleasure, and out of sheer boredom, I will,
without contradicting either myself or your principles- take my pleasure with every one of
you until you are all dead, wondering vaguely what it must feel like to be amongst the
weak of this world whilst doing so.
As the Censor screams for mercy, Minski wryly cites the 8th Statute again, which
states that alms or charities to non- members in distress are strictly forbidden (J: 420).
(Noticing the hint of incomprehension on the Censors terrorized face, Minski adds
199
that the Society is hereby dissolved- its more or less plausible, if contradictory,
doctrine unworthy of such pathetic wretches). Another tries to reason with Minski; certainly, His Honour is clearly a superior specimen, but the rules of the Sodalitybased, as they are, on the principle of maximizing pleasure, must be adhered toReason demands it. Minski notes that, as he absolutely must kill in order to acquire
pleasure, adherence to his own pleasure maximization requires it. He adds that the
laws of the Sodality are merely the work of men, and weak men at that, to protect
themselves from the strong with a spurious notion of brotherhood. The Sodality and
its laws is merely a means to maximizing the pleasure of a small group; the
Brotherhood of Man is not a central principle of either the Sodality or Minski (J: 593).
Insofar as immediate execution is the fate of anyone who breaks the rules of the
house, he notes that the Sodality has essentially the same scorn for hospitality as
himself (J: 591). Absolute contempt for the lives of others is another key Libertine
principle, as is the acknowledgement of any contractual reciprocity. Through ripping
apart every member of the Sodality, Minski according to the logic of the Libertines
themselves- makes them his inferiors, and proves his superiority through mocking
their laws. 69 In turning the Hall of Pleasure into his own private abattoir away from
home, Minski merely concentrates the same logic of destruction to a smaller point.
This doctrinal conflict illustrates a crucial point concerning the behaviour of
criminal society. Minski is an incredible character, who lives an utterly implausible
life. His household is staffed by fifty evil-looking blackamoors, and seven hundred
victims, regularly restocked by one hundred agents (J: 580-582). He has no equal or
familiar in his house, relying entirely on his wealth and his physical strength to
maintain security. His only engagements with others are literally- penetrating and
then eating them. Whether such a character could survive with such simple, bestial
master-slave relationships is doubtful. The Sodality, on the other hand, is no more
implausible than any other paedophilia ring. The immorality of Minski- insofar as it
does not even admit of the possibility of cooperation- is so pure that it has no realworld plausibility. The Sodality makes compromises with Libertine orthodoxy,
insofar as it requires for its implementation a certain fellow feeling, a certain notion of
virtue- quasi-virtue, perhaps, quasi-punishment and so on. Immorality, to function
with any degree of cooperation, requires an impoverished moral sense, but a moral
69
Hnaff p.244.
200
sense all the same- the minimal social glue for the predatory corporate organisation to
function. (A consequence of this analysis is that a secret society of criminals is far
more stable, hence dangerous, if the members actually believe in the moral code of
that society). Libertines and their affiliates must have just enough social sense to
cooperate with each other, but not enough to make them feel pity for the nonmembers who they harm. For this to work, Libertines must also be able to distinguish
members, or potential members, from non-members. 70 Without a). a doctrine that
distinguishes between members and non-members, and b). the belief that such a
difference could be ethically relevant (or that all, or most, non-members are hostile, in
accordance with the dont be a schmuck argument), it would be impossible, or at
least very difficult, to maintain the balance between disdain for outsiders and respect
for insiders. 71 Without such an aristocratic principle, Sades libertines cannot act in
accordance with two distinct moral codes. The following chapter will discuss this
doctrine, the Natural Aristocratic Principle in Nature.
5.12 Conclusion
Sades texts are so horrific that he may have in fact overstated the argument against
being moral, insofar as a more subtle account of criminality may have appeared more
appealing. Perhaps it is more honest to describe criminality in such a way, in
revealing its essential truth. If Sade had merely wanted to encourage vice, he would
have described criminality in abstract, poetic language, and through avoiding
unpleasant details. By forcing an association of immorality with the most brutal
violence and degradation- ( in the manner of Goya, rather than Tarantino) - it is as if
Sade wishes to inoculate the reader. 72
Minski rapes and kills his victims without remorse. He proclaims himself
intelligent enough to destroy every creed, to flout every religionproud enough to
70
Juliette presents herself to new acquaintances with paperwork concerning her earlier contacts and
allegiances, and impresses with her philosophical sophistication, suggesting a combination of economic
and intellectual elitism. Even so, negotiations with more powerful libertines, such as Minski and
Braschi, are especially tense (J: 579, 756, 937,981, 993; also 120: 639).
71
This schema maps onto what anthropologists refer to as in-group out-group bias. For discussion,
see Richard Wrangham and Dale Peterson Demonic Males: Apes and the Origins of Human Violence
(Boston, Ma: Mariner Books. 1997) pp.195, 196.
72
Roger Shattuck considers, and rejects, this position. See Shattuck p.292.
201
abhor every government, to refuse every tie, to ignore every check, to consider myself
above every ethical principle... (J: 583). It seems enough to declare him evil without
having demonstrated that he is irrational also. It is also tempting to write off Sades
proposal as a doctrinal structure that collapses into itself, like a dying star. Yet
characters the equal of Sades Minski, from Pyongyang to Kampala, appear in the
newspapers all the time. That such monsters actually thrive is a question for ethical
counterintelligence and forensic psychology, rather than an exercise in pure theory. 73
Sade gives no straightforward reason as to why a life of crime or despotism
should be pursued, and illustrates the shortcomings of such a life even in the absence
of interception by the law. Yet he shows also shows the difficulty, or futility, in trying
to argue why such a life should be abandoned using reason alone.
This chapter has discussed Sades negotiation with ethics from a thoroughly amoral standpoint. The following will explore the other approach in Sade- the attempt
to derive a morality from the order of things.
73
Ian Hinckfuss writes: ...society not only harbors the mere possibility of the free rider. It positively
generates an entire class of them. Hinckfuss p.55. Hinckfuss sense is different to mine; he holds that
it is morality itself that is morally questionable, as, he argues, it is essentially a means of controlling
society for the benefit of the few. I merely agree that human society is full of syndicated, egoistic free
riders. Hinckfuss vision of a society ruled by shadowy immoral elites, where what passes for morality
really is mere crowd control, is not far off the mark, however. North Korean society could well be such
a situation. South Korean filmmaker Shin Sang-Ok had this to say of his captors, the Government of
North Korea, The North Koreans were all talented and good people; only 200 or so were evil, and they
were in charge. The Madness of Kim Jong-Il, The Observer Sunday, November 2nd, 2003.
202
6.1 Introduction
As was noted at the end of Chapter II, two distinct doctrines are proposed in Sade
concerning the relationship between ontology and morality. Firstly, as discussed in the
previous chapter, Sade holds that there is no relationship at all between the order of
things and morality. The second view, to be discussed here, is a teleological
philosophy according to which one should live in accordance with nature. Sade rejects
not only the specific beliefs and doctrines of Christianity, but also its morality,
dismissed as a psychic artefact of a spiritual sickness. In its stead, Sade proposes a
philosophy according to which Man is to live according to his innate nature,
characterized by a desire to subjugate and destroy others. Accordingly, the doctrine of
equality and the notion that life is sacred are rejected. Christianity is dismissed as
detrimental to the spiritual health of the state. Accordingly, Sades characters propose
to kill every Catholic in France. This chapter will track the vector of this thought.
Friedrich Nietzsche The Birth of Tragedy and the Genealogy of Morals (in one volume) trans. Francis
203
For Sades observations on the hypocrisy of the church, see MV: 5, 15, 276; 120: 217, 266, 268, 270,
274, 335, 446; J: 24, 57,461, 573, 630, 707. For discussion on the depiction of clergy as sexual
predators in 18th Century pornography, See Jean - Marie Goulemot Ces Livres qu'on ne lit que d'une
main: Lecture et lecteurs de livres pornographiques au XVIIIe sicle (Paris: Editions Alinea, 1991).
3
For comparable views in Voltaire, see his Philosophical Dictionary pp. 331- 332. For discussion of
Sades borrowings from Voltaire, see Jean Deprun Quand Sade rcrit Frret, Voltaire, et dHolbach,
Obliques 12-13 (1977):263-266.
204
This apparent erudition may be due to such secondary sources as Bayles Dictionary, however,
205
Vivekananda 5
Sades characters propose a teleology that emphasizes war, strife, and destruction
as fundamental natural principles (introduced in previous chapters as the Bataille
doctrine). As with the doctrine of Rousseau, Sades teleology assumes that a).
morality can be derived from the Natural order, and that b). Man, if only he can learn
to overcome the restraints of Christian morality, is at home in a world whose harsh
truth is continuous with his own inner nature. This teleology is explained on three
levels of organization; at the cosmic level, at the ecological, or biological level, and
as a general theory of human nature. At each of these strata, Sade associates energy
with evil, and virtue with stasis. Hence, good and evil map onto stasis and energy.
William Blake (1757-1827) gives a more formulaic and ethically neutral expression of
this idea.
Without contraries is no progression. Attraction and Repulsion, Reason and Energy, Love
and Hate, are necessary to Human existence.
From these contraries spring what the religious call God & Evil. Good is the passive
that obeys Reason. Evil is the active springing from Energy. 6
At the cosmic level, Sades characters hold that the cosmos is steady by a balance of
chaos and order, and that both are necessary parts of the world. Noirceuil explains:
Quoted in Ajit Mookerjee Kali: The Feminine Force. (New York: Destiny Books, 1988) p.71.
William Blake The Marriage of Heaven and Hell Plate 3, In William Blake Selected Poems ed. P.H.
Butter (London: Everyman, 1991) p.52. This duality of passive vs. active, matter vs. reason is the
standard Stoic principle as described in Cicero. In a letter dated April 17th 1781, Sade claimed to have
learned Cicero by heart. Sade, LAigle, Mademoiselle, lettres publies pour la premire fois sur les
manuscrits autographes. Gilbert Lely, ed. (Paris: Les Editions Georges Artigues, 1949) p. 89. Quoted
in Berman Thoughts and Themes p. 702.
206
A totally virtuous universe could not endure for a minute; the learned hand of Nature
brings order to birth out of chaos. And wanting chaos, Nature must fail to attain anything:
such is the profound equilibrium which holds the stars aright in their courses [...] She
must have evil, it is from this stuff that she creates good, upon crime her existence is
seated... (J: 172; similar: LNJ 1:154, 296).
Sade, of course, is preoccupied with affirming destruction, yet reasons that chaos is
necessary for the maintenance of a higher order of stability. Sade also considers only
destructive acts as those which cohere with Natures dictates-not even the breeding
of warriors, as proposed by Nietzsche. 7 Sades system, being a mirror image of
Rousseaus, runs into similar problems. That is, Sade classifies those who have no
innate inclination to do evil of being immoral (Sade-immoral), according to his own
scheme. This point is directly addressed in The Misfortunes of Virtue. Dubois argues
that conscience is nought but the fear of being caught; the gloomy mind-workings
which are but the product of ignorance, cowardice and education (MV: 125). In
reply, Justine argues against the theory that conscience is unnatural, noting that it is
her own nature to follow the good.
You admit that there is a finite quantity of good and evil in Nature and that it follows
therefore that there must be a certain number of people who do good and another category
of persons who do evil. The policy which I have chosen is, by your principles, natural.
You cannot therefore ask me to depart from the laws which Nature prescribes for me.
Furthermore, since you say you have found happiness in the career which you have
followed, I should in my turn find it equally impossible to meet with felicity by departing
from the course on which I am embarked (MV:126).
Dubois does not address this objection. Without proposing another normative
principle, Sade can only suggest that choosing to do evil is to choose the more
7
Man shall be trained for war and woman for the procreation of the warrior. All else is folly.
207
Sades characters are not consistent on this point. A chemist who wishes to cause a volcanic eruption
states that nature is a minotaur: instructed in her frightful secrets, I imitate her, in detesting her
(LNJ2:44, 45). Accordingly, Marcel Hnaff interprets Sades characters as fundamentally opposed to
Nature, and holds that Sade distinguishes himself from the Materialist vulgate on precisely this point.
Also, Juliette cites Machiavellis view that Nature must be mastered, rather than simply obeyed:
nature is a woman to be mastered only by one who goes to her whip in hand (J: 526). See also
Marcel Hnaff Sade and the Enlightenment Project Presented at the First International Congress
Sade, Charleston, South Carolina; USA March 12-15, 2003. Trans. Norbert Sclippa p.11.
208
impossibility. 9 In short, the best that Sade can argue is that, for some, crime is
natural and beneficial to the general order, and then only if the empirical
assumptions can be supported (i.e. murdering large numbers of people is actually
necessary to sustain the world). Insofar as everyone, in any case, is mortal, this seems
unlikely.
A more fluid interpretation of the Bataille doctrine may be more fruitful. Sades
central claim, again, is that Christianity and the thought of Rousseau have suppressed,
or skirted around, some vital truth of the nature of Man. The affirmation of calm over
chaos is to deny the way the cosmos actually works, and to deny that our fate and our
destiny is continuous with the cosmos in which we dwell. It is also, Sade holds, to
deny the facts of human nature. As such, Sade aligns himself, to a point, with the
doctrines of Hinduism, which affirms both the cycles of creation and of dissolution.
The figure of Kali, goddess of Destruction, could be said to be the symbolic analogue
of what Sade is attempting to reintroduce into his philosophy (writes Carter: Clairwil
and Juliette, like Tantric devotees of Kali, engage in sexual rituals in a graveyard, at
Durands instigation. Kali herself dances upon severed heads, juggles with limbs,
wears necklaces of skulls and copulates with corpses. Snakes issue from her vulva.
Durand is as destructive as Kali, a sumptuous infecundity whose masterpieces are
plagues). 10 Yet Kali is only one part of a duality, and to emphasise the will to Chaos
at the neglect of the other is to commit exactly the same error that Sades critique
makes of Christianity, as Justine has noted.
It should also be noted that Sades conception of virtue - as being necessarily
opposed to violence, or even action- is characteristically Christian, or perhaps, more
accurately, Buddhist, and is not universally held ( as previous chapters have shown,
Sade assumes an especially pure form of morality, only to discredit it). The God of the
Torah gives clear approval for wars of conquest, despite the Messianic hope for peace
expressed in Isaiah. 11 Acknowledgement that war and strife are part of the order of
things does not alone lead to the abandonment of all moral principles.
To be convinced of the truth of a miracle, I should have to be quite certain that the event which you
call miraculous ran absolutely counter to the laws of Nature, since only events occurring outside
Nature can be deemed a miracle (MV:156).
10
Carter p.115.
11
209
In La Nouvelle Justine, the same doctrine is offered, linked to the more general
dynamic of the equality of good and evil in the world.
[d]es loups qui mangent des agneaux, des agneaux dvors par des loups, le fort qui
sacrifie le faible, le faible la victime du fort, voil la nature, voil ses vues, voil ses
plans : un action et une raction perptuelle, une foule de vices et de vertus, un parfait
quilibre, en un mot, rsultant de lgalit du bien et du mal sur la terre, quilibre
essentiel au maintien des astres, la vgtation, et sans lequel tout serait linstant
dtruit (LNJ 1:364).
In associating the Law of the Jungle with the dynamics of economics (the wolf eats
the lamb, the rich fatigue the poor) Sade aligns himself with Nietzsche and the Social
12
Builders and Titans: Twenty innovators who Change How the World Works, Time Magazine
210
Darwinists of the 19th Century, as well as industrialists such as Ray Kroc. 13 Charity,
in reversing this natural order, is dismissed as merely encouraging indolence: cest
sopposer celui de la nature; cest renverser lquilibre qui est la base de ses plus
sublimes arrangements; cest travailler une galit dangereuse pour la socit; cest
encourager lindolence et al fainantise... (LNJ 2 :347, 348). At this level, the
association of wolves with capitalism does not go beyond a loose metaphor, or
beyond the bare assertion that there is a sublime arrangement according to which
there are supposed to be rich and poor classes.
Again, at a strictly literal level, Sades analogy is problematic. Caroline Warman
tracks the view that destruction is part of the natural order of things to the biologist
Count Buffon (1707-1788), who had written that violent death was as a natural part of
the order of things, insofar as the activities of carnivores kept population numbers in
check. 14 If Warmans understanding of Sade is correct, Sade has extended to the
behaviour of human beings the conclusions derived from biological observations on
inter-species behaviour. But it is difficult to see where he could find support for this
transposition. Sade has assumed that human existence is constrained by the same
Malthusian principles that dictate animal life, which is simply not the case. Even
where economic pressures force communities to abandon or kill the very young or
very old, this scarcely equates to legitimating wanton killing, or the imposition of
crushing economic hardships upon others. At best, economic constraints on
population levels would legitimate infanticide, contraception, abortion, or euthanasia,
if anything at all (admittedly, contraception was not an option for most people in
Sades age, or even in our own, for Catholic populations). Further, intra-species
killing amongst predators, even in competition for mates or territory, is extremely
rare. Humans do not kill each other (any more) in the same way that the fox kills the
13
For wolf and lamb imagery in Nietzsche, see Zarathustra pp.309-310, Genealogy of Morals in The
Birth of Tragedy and the Genealogy of Morals p.178. For Nietzsches association of socialism with
slave morality, see Nietzsche The Will to Power p.398.
14
Buffon Les Animaux carnassiers, In Histoire naturelle, vol. vii, ch. I. Quoted in Warman p.164.
For discussion on the relationship between Sades biologic thinking and that of his age, see Jean
Deprun Sade et la philosophie biologique de son temps. In Le Marquis de Sade, centre aixois
dtudes et de recherches sur le XVIIIe sicle (Paris: Librairie Armand Colin, 1968):189-205.
211
hare. 15 Yet it is a fact of history and anthropology that humans kill each other, and
compete for resources in a vigorous way, though not in a manner typical of
carnivores. The beast in Man is above all a calculating, reasoning, human beast.
Consistent with the Bataille doctrine is the view that rapine, theft, and war are not a
problem to be solved, but a basic truth of Man that must be embraced. Like Harry
Lime, Sade does not go into details as to how warfare and non-reciprocal exchange fit
into a broader general economics (as opposed to the narrow economics of
reciprocal, beneficial exchange). Sade is not interested in a straightforward, a-moral,
inquiry into, for example, the relationship between war and cultural development, or
the economic importance of the sex industry in 18th Century Paris. His resolute
15
Whether cannibalism was ever a widespread practice in human populations, or whether it was
practiced beyond merely eating those killed in war, is a controversial topic. Nevertheless, the
anthropological data rather supports Sade rather than Rousseau; there is no doubt that cannibalism was
practiced in Fiji and New Zealand, for example. For discussion, see Bill Arens The Man-Eating Myth:
Anthropology and Anthropophagy (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1980) and Timothy Taylor The
Buried Soul: How Humans Invented Death (London: Fourth Estate, 2002). Sade discusses cannibalism
at length in Aline et Valcour, citing Cook, M. M. Meunier and Paw as anthropological references (AV:
227n).
16
Trevor Royle A Dictionary of Military Quotations (New York: Simon & Schuster, 1990). Quoted in
Buss p.277.
212
immorality limits him to pointing out, in a slightly puerile way, the paradox that
theft or war could be construed as beneficial. Nevertheless, Sade has a point that is
(like all his better points) at once obvious, disturbing, and profound. That is, there is a
considerable gap between how our civilization operates, or has operated historically,
and our day to day morality. The view proposed is a more bloody version of
Mandeville- were everyone to live according to Christian meekness and piety, very
little would ever get done. Mandeville was content to note that people are industriousand benefit society- out of such vices as greed and pride. Sade takes this a step
further, in asserting that the wheels of human progress are driven by the Will to
Domination; the desire to kill, to wipe out entire civilizations, to instrumentalize the
vanquished to our own ends.
Again, Sade follows Rousseaus reasoning in an unfaithful (that is to say,
highly original) manner. Rousseau holds that introspection will disclose the inner
voice of Natural Law; the voice of conscience. Sade, similarly, holds that ruthlessly
honest introspection will disclose the Passions greed, lust, violence, destruction- the
voice of Khan, rather than Kant. He describes the passions as blind instruments or
laws of the will of Nature: the means that [nature] employs to accelerate her
designs (LNJ 1: 55, 148, 149, also 151, 214, 293). Where Sade admits of instincts for
common feeling, he adds that they are subordinate to the higher passion of egoism
(in La Nouvelle Justine, a man kills his brother over a quantity of gold, stating that
mon action vous prouvera, mes camarades, que vos intrts me sont plus chers que
tous les liens de la nature, et que je sacrifierai toujours tout, ds quil sagira de vous
servir ( LNJ 2: 292).
The Bataille doctrine, as stated, is present within Rousseaus thought. Rousseau
had considered the possibility of one who advocates a right of the strongest,
dismissing him as the man who brings terror and chaos into the human kind (SC:
52-53; DI: 77). 17 Nevertheless, Rousseau believed that such a doctrine was at the
heart of civilized society, and that it was there for all to see who were willing to peer
behind the mask: my hero will cut every throat until he is sole master of the universe.
Such is the moral portrait, if not of human life, at least of the secret ambitions of the
17
This doctrine appears also in the work of Restif de la Bretonne. His morally nihilistic character
Gaudet states: [m]y friend, there are only two classes in the world, that of slave, and that of master.
Restif de la Bretonne Paysanne pervertie, ou les dangers de la ville (A la Haie, 1784) 2 vols. Quoted in
Crocker Age of Crisis p.440.
213
heart of civilized man (DI: 149). 18 Rousseau blames civilization for this evil; Sade
assumes that it was there in the human heart all along (how Rousseau can hope that
we can all find the same moral law within, despite our civilized state, is a question
that goes beyond this project). Hence, Sades thought follows a vector similar to
Rousseaus. That is, Sades doctrine goes something like this: that which is good is
that which is natural. How do I know which inclination or impulse is good? I inquire
into my heart, and I do as it tells me. Rousseau himself states that the heart of
civilized man is a rapacious killer; the rest follows. Only the complexities of
Rousseaus understanding of human nature separates the two doctrines.
Concerning war, Sade merely asserts that it is in accordance with Natures plans.
Braschi, in Juliette, explains:
These wars, these famines she hurls at us, these pestilences she now and again looses with
the aim of wiping us off the face of the earth, these great villains she fabricates in
profusion, these Alexanders, these Tamurlanes, these Ghengis Khans, all these heroes
who lay the world waste, by these tokens, I say, does she not plainly demonstrate that all
our laws are contrary to hers, and that her purpose are to destroy them? [...] these murders
[...] are in some sort instrumental to her, since she is a great murderess herself... (J: 768).
As such, Sades discussion does not go beyond Kali- veneration; war plays a role
insofar as it returns the living to the movement of matter which renews and
reorganizes itself within the entrails of mother earth...the regenerating womb (J:770).
A single line alluding to Heraclitus of Ephesus leaves open other possibilities,
however. Braschi again:
18
In fact Rousseau appears to have known people (or claimed as much), who lived by this ideology
personally. In the Confessions Rousseau writes of the doctrine of his acquaintance and onetime
friend, Friedrich Melchior, Baron von Grimm (1723- 1807): I remembered the compendium of his
morality, which Madame dEpinay had told me of, and which she adopted. This consisted of one single
article, namely, that the sole duty of man is, to follow in everything the inclinations of his heart. This
code of morality, when I heard of it, afforded me terrible material for thought, although at that time I
only looked upon it as a witticism. But I soon saw that this principle really was his principle of
conduct, and, in the sequel, I had only too convincing proof of it at my own expense. It is the inner
doctrine, of which Diderot has so often spoken to me, but of which he has never given me any
explanation (C: 457).
214
Crimes [are] essential to the laws of the kingdoms, and essential to the laws of Nature. An
ancient philosopher [Heraclitus] called war the mother of all things. The existence of
murderers is as necessary as that bane (J: 771). 19
Another reads:
One should know that war is common, that justice is strife, that all things come about in
accordance with strife and with what must be. 21
These passages suggest a way in which Sades doctrine concerning war can be further
developed. The Sadeian implication of these aphorisms is that war is good, as it
creates distinctions among men. Elsewhere, Sade holds that feudalism and economic
inequality are requisites of economic and cultural flourishing (LNJ 2:225). The
relationship between war and cultural strength is straightforward. One plunders the
other group for their resources, and reduces the vanquished to slavery, so that ones
own community can concentrate on more tertiary-sector activities, like the arts and
sciences. The principle here is that reciprocal exchange is not the typical, or the most
efficient, mode of economic development, or territorial expansion, for a group with
overwhelming physical or strategic superiority. To assume that economic relations are
independent of the threat of violence is nave. 22 Dorval speaks:
19
Nietzsche offers an identical argument, writing that [n]o act of violence, rape, exploitation,
destruction, is intrinsically unjust, since life itself is violent, rapacious, exploitative, and destructive,
and that to counter the radical life- will with legal or moral systems can only bring about mans utter
demoralization and, indirectly, a reign of nothingness. Nietzsche Genealogy of Morals in the Birth of
Tragedy and the Genealogy of Morals p.208.
20
From Hippolytus Refutation of All Heresies, translated by Jonathan Barnes. Quoted in Jonathan
Origen, Against Celsus VI xliii Quoted in Barnes Early Greek Philosophy p.114.
22
There are, of course, more complex relationships between warfare and economic activity. A stronger
power can force open a countrys market against the will of its leaders, such as the Opium/ AngloChinese Wars of 1839-42, 1856-60. A stronger state can also coerce other, less powerful states into
215
Kind friends, by a single feature alone were men distinguished from one another when,
long ago, society was in its infancy: the essential point was brute strength. Nature gave
them all space wherein to dwell, and it was upon this physical force, distributed to them
with less impartiality, that was to depend the manner in which they were to share the
world. Was this sharing to be equal, could it possibly be, what with the fact that naked
force was to decide the matter? In the beginning, then, was theft; theft, I say, was the
basis, the starting point; for the inequality of this sharing necessarily supposes a wrong
done the weak by the strong, and there at once we have this wrong, that is to say, theft,
established, authorized by Nature since she gives man that which must necessarily lead
him thereto (J: 114).
Sade also associates the art of thievery with (what could be termed) his virtue ethicsIf we glance at the history of ancient times, we will see theft permitted, nay, recompensed
in all the Greek republics; Sparta and Lacedaemon openly favoured it; several other
peoples regarded it as a virtue in a warrior; it is certain that stealing nourishes courage,
strength, skill, tact, in a word, all the virtues useful to a republican system and
consequently to our own (PB: 313).
Sade does not explicitly associate war up with theft, or any other economic
Realpolitik, perhaps because, again, he is more intent on merely thumbing his nose at
the Decalogue than proposing a more complete schema (in The 120 Days of Sodom,
the wars of Louis XIV are said to merely drain the States treasury and exhaust the
substance of the people, as well as enriching a swarm of bloodsuckers, including
the Four Friends; 120:191). On the one hand, his account of both war and economics
is simplistic and narrow. Where war is discussed at all, it is either good because it
kills people, and for no other reason, or bad, for the same reason. Sade does not even
refer to the grandeur or spectacle of battle (this is unusual, given the Libertine attitude
towards violent spectacle as discussed in Chapter III). Just as Rousseau considered
the mechanical sciences as mere ambition and mathematics an expression of avarice,
Sade sees all economic activity as theft (CS: 16). From Juliette:
participation in its own wars in exchange for access to its markets, such as the case with New Zealands
relationship with the United States, since the Vietnam War to the present day.
216
...theft, instituted by Nature, was not ...banished from the face of the earth; but it came to
exist in other forms: stealing was performed juridically. The magistrates stole by having
themselves feed [sic] for doing the justice they ought to render free of charge. The priest
stole by taking payment for serving as intermediary between God and man. The merchant
stole by selling his sack of potatoes at a price one-third above the intrinsic value a sack of
potatoes really has (J:115).
Sades purist notions of what is and is not theft, and his woolly notion of intrinsic
value, do not detract from the essential point. A great deal of wealth and territory,
historically, has been acquired through what was essentially theft. Warfare is no
longer the economic or political strategy it once was, but for entirely Sadeian- that is,
instrumental, reasons- it is too expensive, its arts now too effective. 23
To conclude: The analogy of the beast of prey applied to economic activity is
crude, but perhaps not that crude. Corporations will discontinue products that are
known to be lethal, will maintain safety standards in offshore manufacturing plants,
will maintain humane standards for their employees, or stop selling weaponry to
poorer nations, only when the legal costs are no longer in the interests of the
shareholders- that is, in the interests of the Board of Directors.
A reconstituted Sade, or perhaps, more accurately, Harry Lime, would add that it
is this same ruthlessness that drives the wheels of civilization. Human progress is
driven along by impulses for wealth and power, which, in the past, frequently took the
form of open war. Further, warfare itself- or its sublimated forms (for example the
Cold War) has always been a powerful catalyst of technological and scientific
progress (the jet aircraft, the ballistic and cruise missiles, the first operational
computers, the helicopter, radar, and the nuclear bomb saw fully functional, active
service for the first time during World War II ). If humanity has any form of nontranscendental Telos, it is assumedly associated with the progress of civilization, in
particular economic and technological progress (artistic progress is arguably only
possible where economics and technology are developed to the point where an artistic
and intellectual elite can flourish, and is historically related to advances in technology,
in particular optics and information systems). Hence, the Telos is expressed through
this competitive drive, and through individuals that embody it, whether Napoleon,
Ghengis Khan or Ray Kroc.
23
I thank Aaron Davidson for the discussion that gave shape to this thought.
217
Concerning the Jews, Sades writing largely repeats the anti-Semitism present in the writings of
Voltaire. In Frenchmen, Yet One More Effort, Sade writes that Jews are natural murderers; in Aline et
Valcour a character ridicules a Marrano Jews observance of kashrut laws, and in La Nouvelle Justine,
Sade describes a Jewish lawyer, Abraham Pexoto, as a deeply immoral scam artist (PB:334, AV:520,
521; LNJ 1: 425-429).
Jewish slave: this comment comes from one of Sades Revolutionary pamphlets. Oeuvres compltes
du Marquis de Sade ed. Annie le Brun and Jean-Jacques Pauvert (Paris: Pauvert, 1986-91) 3:364,
quoted in Schaeffer p.437.
218
flay us! Nature says one must not do unto others that which unto oneself one would not
have done! Fools! How could Nature, who always urges us to delight in ourselves, who
never implants in us other instincts, other notions, other inspirations, how could Nature,
the next moment, assure us that we must not, however, decide to love ourselves if that
might cause others pain? (PB: 253; similar: J: 178; PB: 283, 309, 310, 360, LNJ 1:283,
363; 2: 264-265).
Sade describes the French Revolution in similar, if more subtle, terms. The following
is a footnote to Juliette, added to later editions.
Lgalit prescrite par la Rvolution, nest que la vengeance du faible sur le fort, cest ce
qui se faisait autrefois en sens inverse ; mais cette raction est juste, il faut que chacun ait
son tour. Tout variera encore, parce que rien nest stable dans la nature, et que les
gouvernements dirigs par des hommes, doivent tre mobiles comme eux.
25
The thought is similar- the revolution is revenge of the strong against the weak- yet,
as the narrator adds, each will get his turn, as nothing is stable in nature.
Sade also proposes that Christian morality is motivated by resentment towards the
rich and powerful, and the desire to merely drag others down to ones own level:
[t]he proponents of that absurd doctrine of equality will always be recruited from the
ranks of the weak; it is never espoused save by him who, unable to rise to the class of
the strong, can at least find comfort in pulling that class down to his own level (J:
418n, also 748). The doctrine of hell is suspected of being little more than a
sublimated revenge fantasy ([d]oes not the act of imposing a punishment out of all
proportion to the fault speak far more in behalf of vindictiveness and cruelty than of
justice? ; J: 378).
25
The Wainhouse translation gives the incorrect sense. The phrase that everyone should have his
turn is only meet should perhaps read It is necessary that each has their turn.
The equality prescribed by the Revolution is simply the weak mans revenge upon the strong; its just
what we saw in the past, but in reverse; that everyone should have his turn is only meet [sic]. And it
shall be turnabout again tomorrow, for nothing in Nature is stable and the governments men direct are
bound to prove as changeable and ephemeral as they (J:120, n12a; Vol. III: 287). In this section
the character Dorval complains that the noble have become the slaves of the kings (again, Sades
characters show inconsistency between thoughts and deeds; Dorval himself specializes in robbing
noblemen).
219
Sade also makes a direct comparison of Christian and Classical cultures. Sade
declares that [i]t is to strong passions alone invention and artistic wonders are due;
the passions should be regarded...as the fertilizing germ of the mind and the puissant
spring to great deeds Those beings who are not motivated by strong passions are
mediocre beings (J: 731). Christianity, in denying the passions, promotes mediocrity
as a virtue, and has made humanity soft (J: 776). Accordingly, its emphasis on
sobriety and temperance would be catastrophic if strictly adhered to: ...si la
temprance et la sobrit dominaient malheureusement dans le monde, tout y
vgterait il ny aurait plus ni mouvement ni force et tout retomberait dans le chaos
(LNJ 1:192). By contrast, the idols of Greece and Rome, writes Sade, elevated the
soul, electrified it, and more: they communicated to the spirit the virtues of the
respected being. Whereas the Greek and Roman pantheons inspire wisdom and
heroism, Sade describes the saints of the Christian Elysium lacking in any
greatness, heroism or virtue. Sade adds: [s]o alien to lofty conceptions is this
miserable belief, that no artist can employ its attributes in the monuments he raises;
even in Rome itself, most of the embellishments of the papal palaces have their
origins in paganism, and as long as this world shall continue, paganism alone will
arouse the verve of great men (PB: 299; similar: LNJ 1:139, AV: 454). The ancient
past is frequently referred to as a source of superior moral principles.
Remember that sect of Greek philosophers who maintained there was crime in seeking to
meddle with the various shades in the Nature- ordained spectrum of social classes [...] Be
equally certain...that men of the stamp of Denis, Nero, Louis XI, Tiberius, Wenceslas,
Herod, Andronicus, Heliogabalus, Retz based their happiness upon similar
principles...(J:283).
In accordance with the doctrine of master morality, the moral sentiments- remorse,
guilt and conscience- are dismissed as either chimerical, due to faulty reasoning, or
psychological weakness; the mark of an easily enslaved mind, or the psychological
artefact of Christian indoctrination (J: 13; MV: 124). In Aline et Valcour, Sade makes
clear the divide between reason and moral sentiment. States Prsident de Balmont,
Quand vous cdez au sentiment de la piti plutt quaux conseils de la raison, quand
vous coutez le cur de prfrence lesprit, vous vous jetez dans un abme
derreurs, puisquil nest point de plus faux organes que ceux de la sensibilit....
220
26
Sade Aline et Valcour (Paris:Jean-Jacques Pauvert, 1956) Vol. IV pp.17-18., Quoted in Lorna
Berman Thoughts and Themes p.238. Sades thought here resembles that of Helvtius, who dismissed
remorse merely the foresight of bodily pain (Treatise of Man Vol. I p.127). See also Nietzsche
Writings from the late Notebooks ed. Rdiger Bittner, trans. Kate Sturge (Cambridge: Cambridge
University Press, 2003) p.172; Genealogy of Morals in The Birth of Tragedy and the Genealogy of
Morals pp.200-202. For recent discussion of the error of guilt, see Hinckfuss p.44.
221
Yet the classification of masters and slaves, or libertines, and their victims,
is far from straightforward. In an attempt to explain or justify their dominion (that is,
in an attempt to reduce power to another category), the libertines seek to clarify a
doctrine of innate superiority. Superiority across three categories is discussed;
biological, or physical superiority, intellectual superiority, and economic superiority
(that libertine power is simply a terminal category {that is, irreducible to innate
caste characteristics} is not considered).
Sade takes the Celts, our earliest ancestors, to be a paradigmatically superior
people, noting that Celt in German meant courageous or Lords of War. He
attributes to the Celts his own counter-morality, implying that his doctrine is a
renewal to an older, more authentic moral outlook. Noirceuil states: the Celts...held
that the highest and most sacred of our rights was that of might, which is to say, of
Nature; and they considered that when Nature deems wise to assign a superior quality
of potential to some of us, she does so only to confirm the prepotency over the weak
which she invests in us strong (J: 173). 27 Noirceuil attempts to link the natural
aristocracy of the age of the Celts to modern economic inequalities. He continues:
[i]f since Celtic days matters have changed physically, they havent morally. The
opulent man represents what is mightiest in society; he has brought up all the rights;
he ought therefore to enjoy them... [i]ts all the same thing, whether I filch my
neighbours purse, rape his son, his wife, or his daughter: these are mere pranks, of
too slight importance and scope ever to be of any utility to Nature... (J: 173-174). 28
In order to enforce his power and satisfy his caprices, Noirceuil adds that one must
enforce discipline, forbearance, and compliance from the subordinate class of men
(J: 174).
27
For discussion of Sades admiration of the Celts, see Lacombe Sade et ses masques p.28.
28
Compare Nietzsche, on the higher morality of the nobles: we can imagine them returning from
an orgy of murder, arson, rape, and torture, jubilant and at peace with themselves as though they had
committed a fraternity prank... Friedrich Nietzsche Genealogy of Morals in The Birth of Tragedy and
the Genealogy of Morals p.174. It should also be noted, to put Sades work in context, that neither
Diderot nor Helvtius took rape particularly seriously. In his Supplment au Voyage de Bougainville,
Diderots idyllic Tahitians rape a woman upon her arrival. The scene is supposed to be comic- the
woman is disguised as a man, and the Tahitians, being more in tune with nature, immediately realize
the deception. Diderot Political Writings p.46. Helvtius brothel proposal, as discussed in Chapter IV,
is also indifferent to the issue of forced sex.
222
Two extended monologues in Sades surviving work also describe the masterslave relationship in terms of caste (we would now consider this race theory). 29
Minister Saint-Fond argues against those theorists who had suggested that apparent
intellectual differences between master and slave castes could be accounted for as
differences in education. He proposes an experiment. Placing two infants, one of
each class, side by side, youll observe that the child of the first class manifests
tastes and aims most unlike those the child of the second class demonstrates; and you
will perceive the most striking dissimilarity between the sentiments and dispositions
proper to each. Saint-Fond goes on to assert that natural slaves are no more humans
than are chimpanzees: [n]ow perform the same study upon the animal resembling
man the closest, upon, for example, the chimpanzee; let me, I say, compare this
animal to some representative of the slave caste; what a host of similarities I find! The
man of the people is simply the species that stands next above the chimpanzee on the
ladder; and the distance separating them is, if anything, less than that between him
and the individual belonging to the superior caste(J:322-323).
Sade also notes that the oppression of an inferior population is a widespread
cultural and historical phenomenon, if not actually an anthropological norm.
In La Nouvelle Justine, the character Verneuil states that humans are naturally divided
into natural masters and natural slaves, and that each people has a corresponding
despised caste (caste mprise): les Juifs formaient celle des gyptiens, les Ilotes
celle des Grecs; les Parias celle des Brames; les Ngres celle de lEurope (LNJ 2 :
222-223). 30 If it is a racial distinction that is applied here, it is not Eurocentric. Sade
makes the same distinction between the Greeks and Helots, both European
populations, and between the Ancient Egyptians and Jews, who are both Semitic. In
fact, Saint- Fonds conclusion to his discussion indicates that, in Sade, the doctrine of
inequality runs much deeper than differences between races. After comparing
29
Sade also briefly discusses race theory, in particular the gradations of different classes of men and
primates, in Quatrime cahier des Notes ou Rflexions; extraites de mes lectures ici ou fournies par
elles, written in the dungeon of Vincennes between June 1780 and August 1780. In Sade uvres
compltes de Sade ed.Annie Le Brun and Jean-Jacques Pauvert (Paris: Pauvert,1986) Vol. I :469-485,
p.471.
30
For discussion of this passage, see Fauskevg p.104, 129; Jean Pierre Faye Juliette et le Pre
Duchesne, foutre In Camus, Roger, ed. Sade crire la crise 289-302, p.301. See also Han and Valla
A propos p.119
223
inferior peoples with chimpanzees, Saint- Fond states: You should certainly never
lump Voltaire and Frron in the same class, any more than you would the virile
Prussian grenadier and the debilitated Hottentot. Therefore, Juliette, cease to doubt
these inequalities... (J: 322-323). lie Frron (1718-1776) was a critic and journalist
who attacked the principles of the Enlightenment, and Voltaire frequently made him
the butt of his ridicule. 31 Yet Frron and Voltaire, obviously, are of the same
ethnological and social group; the difference being that Frron is an anti-philosophe
Catholic, whereas Voltaire is not. Other texts suggest again that the distinction
between libertines and their victims has little to do with race. Ben Macoro, the
Cannibal King of Batua in Aline et Valcour, is clearly a libertine figure, despite being
African, and is enthusiastic about acquiring white sex slaves (who would be, by
definition, victims). Likewise, the killers of The 120 Days of Sodom make a point of
selecting as victims the children of their own race and economic group (120: 226227). Race can therefore be ruled out as the defining distinction between libertines
and victims (expressed here in terms of that between masters and slaves).
The superior strength and intelligence of the libertine are typically given as
defining characteristics. The character Dorval associates the natural rights of the
Nobleman with historical ties with vagabondage, and with superior strength, and the
Rousseauian ideal of a return to natural ways.
There was a time when the German magnates counted among their rights that of highway
robbery. This right derives from the earliest and most fundamental institutions in
societies, where the free man or vagabond got his livelihood in the manner of the beasts
of the forests and the birds of the air: by wresting food from whatever convenient or
possible source; in those days, he was a child and student of nature, today he is the slave
of ludicrous prejudices, abominable laws, and idiotic religions. All the good things of this
world, cries the weak individual, were equally distributed over the surface of the globe.
Very well. But by creating weak and strong, Nature with sufficient clarity announced that
she intended these good things to go to the strong alone... (J: 122).
31
For discussion on the anti- philosophes, see Darrin M. McMahon Enemies of the Enlightenment: The
French Counter-Enlightenment and the Making of Modernity (New York: Oxford University Press,
2001).
224
Sade also suggests that intellectual traits have supplanted brute strength as the
deciding qualities of the strong. Dalville, in the Misfortunes of Virtue, states: [t]he
adroitness and wit of humankind determined the relative positions of individuals, for
soon it was not physical strength which decided rank but the strength a man acquired
through wealth. The richest man was the strongest man, the poorest was the weakest
(MV: 110).
Sade also attempts to demonstrate a close link between economic strength, power,
and innate, superior traits. In Juliette, Dorval, a thief, argues that there is a nonarbitrary distinction between the powerful man, who exploits a subject population,
and the poor thief. 32 The poor thief who robs from the natural masters, states
Dorval, is doing nothing that isnt completely natural, he is trying to redress the
balance which, in the moral as well as the physical realm, is Natures highest law...
yet, adds Sade, this isnt quite what I was aiming to prove; however, proofs arent
needed ... [w]hat I should like to convince you of is that neither does the powerful
individual commit a crime or an injustice when he strives to despoil the weak.
Dorval then makes the following moral claim: ...theft perpetrated by a strong man is
assuredly a better and more valid act, within the terms and from the standpoint of
nature (my italics). This is because, in attempting to take from the strong, the weak
man must make use of physical forces he does not possess, he must adopt a character
that has not been given him, in short, he must in some sense fly in the face of nature
(my italics; J:117). Sade/Dorval adds an additional moral principle in order to
justify such a distinction: That sage mothers [Natures] laws... stipulate that the
mighty harm the feeble (J: 117). At this point, Sades case risks collapsing into a
tautology (simply put, the master is the one who masters). To avoid this, Sade needs
to identify essential traits that distinguish between the natural master and the natural
slave. He eventually settles upon a vaguely defined notion of authenticity.
The strong individual, unlike the weak, never dons masks, he at all times acts true to his
own character, his character is the one he has received from Nature, and in whatever he
does is an honest and direct expression thereof and in the highest sense and degree
natural...his tyrannies and outbursts...pure emanations of what he is... (J: 117).
32
This is a clear case of a character being body-snatched by Sades voice. Dorval is arguing from the
perspective of someone who believes that the wealthy- who he himself specializes in robbing- are more
honest in being despotic than the poor thief who steals from them.
225
The powerful man, then, a). despoils the weak and b). acts in accordance with
nature out of c). an authentic expression of his true nature. By contrast, the weak man
goes against nature, in using physical forces that he lacks. Dorval assumes, in making
this charge, that a). it is possible to go against nature, b). that it is somehow wrong
(invalid) to go against nature, and c). that it is possible to use resources (whether
intellectual or physical) that one does not have. He also assumes that d). honest and
direct expressions of ones actual powers are in a sense virtuous.
To a point, it could be argued that Sades characters are applying a double
standard. When discussing the first Christians or the French Revolutionaries, cunning,
craft and sneakiness are considered vices (J: 119- 121). Yet when Clairwil- a
libertine- succeeds in defeating some men, she declares: how sweet are the victories
the weak contrive to win over the strong (J: 520). Sades introduction of the notion
of honesty fits awkwardly both with the Sadeian rejection of all morality, and with
the conduct of his characters. Humaneness is dismissed as due to fear and egoism:
this chimerical virtue, enslaving only weak men, is unknown to those whose
character is formed by stoicism, courage, and philosophy (PB: 360; similar: LNJ1:
138). Yet the libertines tend to view bravery as simple stupidity, and pride themselves
on their own egoism ([t]o disesteem a man because he fears danger- is to hate him
for loving life; J: 949, also 248). The weak, according to the libertines, formulate a
collective strategy and a doctrine of equality to convince others not to harm them. The
Four Friends retreat to an impregnable fortress, and the Sodality of the Friends of
Crime adopt a Social Contract for essentially the same reasons. The charge that the
first Christians were dishonorable in avoiding hurt through proposing their doctrine
cannot be a moral charge, as, for the libertines themselves, the highest of all goods is
the pursuit of happiness (J:910). Nor can the subterfuge of the Slave Revolt in Morals,
or the inauthentic expression of ones true strength, be moral (that is, Sade-moral)
wrongs on Sades view.
The defining characteristic of the libertines is not, therefore, racial, reducible to
specific caste traits, or explicable in terms of authenticity, and remains unstated.
Certain rankings of the superior and inferior in Sade in fact appear to be deliberately
juxtaposed, perhaps in order to undermine the whole notion of innate superiority.
Characters in Juliette, for example, argue variously that men and women are equal;
that men are superior to women, and vice versa (J: 354, 505-506). Nor is intelligence
226
the deciding factor. Justine, who is forced to work as a slave at one point, is quite
capable of discussing philosophy (MV: 111). Five factors, in general, distinguish the
libertines from their victims- their atheism, their cynicism, their immorality, their lack
of a sense of pity or remorse, and their power, whether in the form of wealth or
political influence. Wealth is only a necessary condition; being, like power itself, an
enabler of libertine exploits; there are plenty of cases of innocent people in Sade
who are slaughtered for their money (wealth trumps high birth- for the Sodality of the
Friends of Crime, only the income of prospective members is considered ; J:424). Not
even atheism, it appears, is a necessary condition of being a libertine, as evidenced by
the case of Saint-Fond ( who believes in God only to hate him, as discussed in
Chapter I), Mondor (who makes confession after killing people) or Abraham Pexoto,
a Jew (LNJ: 425-429; J:547). The capacity for remorse or guilt is unusual for
libertines, but Juliette has to fight it nevertheless (J: 549). Cynicism is necessary for
libertinage (that is, harming and killing for pleasure), though not sufficient.
Brigandos, the leader of a criminal gang (in Aline et Valcour) is cynical, and his
notion of justice is problematic (as discussed in Chapter V), yet he never oppresses,
tortures or kills other people. The same can be said of Le Chevalier, in Philosophy in
the Bedroom (discussed below).
Ultimately, only one factor universally distinguishes the master from the
slave in Sades work. The libertine possesses power. The master is the dominant
member of a power relationship, and lacks the restraints that would prevent him, or
her, from harming or killing the victim. The term master is, therefore, largely a
relational term. The relationship between Saint-Fond and Juliette illustrates this. They
have the same general libertine traits- passion, cynicism and intelligence. Yet Saint
Fond is far more powerful. Not only is he the source of Juliettes wealth early in her
career (seven million francs a year) if she does not cooperate with him and become
his poisoner and spy, which requires that she betray her own friends, he threatens her
with imprisonment in the Bastille (J: 231, 237). Juliette herself seems confused about
the nature of the relationship, referring to Saint-Fond as an accomplice and to
herself as his slave, and feeling it necessary to express her submission to him by
eating his excrement (J:236). Saint-Fonds clarifies the situation for us. He advances
Juliettes career purely to magnify his own sense of power over others: ...Ill raise
you so high in the world youll have no more trouble believing in your superiority
over others: you cannot imagine the joy I derive in advancing you to atop the very
227
pinnacle, and making your pre-eminence conditional upon profound humility and
unbounded obedience toward me alone. I wish you to be the idol of others and, at the
same time, my slave... (J: 323). 33 Whilst listening to a plan to two kill thirds of
France through famine, Juliette involuntarily shows human feelings of moral concern.
Having betrayed herself to the Libertine equivalent to the Thought Police, she is
forced to leave Paris (J: 549, 550). Juliette is coerced and exiled by other libertines.
Further, Juliette loses members of her own entourage to the murderous impulses of
Minski, again indicating her lower ranking. Sades claim that power is anchored by
innate superiority is therefore problematic.
Sades libertines themselves in fact discuss the possibility is that there is no such
thing as innate superiority, and that there are no such morally relevant distinctions
between themselves and those upon whom they exploit. Le Chevalier, in Philosophy
in the Bedroom, is that rarest of creatures in Sades menagerie the libertine
moderate: I am libertine, impious, I am capable of every mental obscenity, but my
heart remains to me... (PB: 341). He rejects Dolmancs view that economic
difference can justify inhumane treatment of others.
Look at those others wasted by the drudgeries that support your existence, and at their
bed, scarcely more than a straw or two for protection against the rude earth whereof, like
beasts, they have nothing but the chill crust to lie down upon; cast a glance at
themBarbaric one, are these not at all human beings like you? And if they are of your
kind, why should you enjoy yourself when they lie dying? (PB: 340-341).
Saint-Fond also uses the tu form of informal address when talking with Juliette (J: 245).
228
(PB: 342-343). The objection that power is assigned arbitrarily occurs also in Juliette.
Juliette has this to say to Archduke Leopold, a libertine:
How did you get your rank? By luck. What did you do to merit your rank? That first of
kings who earned it through his courage or his cunning, he could perhaps claim to some
esteem; but he who has it through mere inheritance, may he hope for more than
compassion? (J: 616-617).
In the first of these passages, Juliette notes that there was once a meritocracy- of
courage and cunning- that dictated rank, but no more. In the second passage, Sade
implies that paperwork is the only remnant of the relationship between the Kings of
the past and their present representatives. It is also significant that Juliette accuses the
most powerful heads of state of lacking any qualities that could justify their posts, as
it is these very characters who give the most extreme expressions of the master/ slave
relationship, seeing themselves as gods, and their subjects as swarming insects
(J:243; 748, PB:216). Regardless of Sades intended sense, his characters serve to
illustrate Helvtius view that people with absolute power frequently fell to the
delusion that they were a higher order of being. 34
Sades characters largely fail to reduce, or validate, their power in terms of a
single trait, and entertain the possibility that, within larger power structures, there
could be very little relationship between power and innate qualities. The power of the
libertines (in Juliette in particular) is not due to any one personal trait, but ones place
in the socioeconomic matrix, in particular the specific relationships that one has
within that matrix, as shown by the emphasis on secret societies, wealth, and official
power. The administration, relations and mechanisms of power will be discussed in
chapter VII.
34
229
36
See, for example, John Locke: A Letter Concerning Toleration In Focus edited by John Horton and
230
or exile are not ideal solutions -these are royal atrocities (PB: 306; similar: J: 970972). The Comte de Belmor, of Juliette, suggests a more extreme solution. He
proposes genocide; the death of every Catholic in France. He reasons that this would
eliminate irrational superstition, and because it would be a hundred times better that
our fair part of Europe be inhabited by ten million honest folk rather than by twentyfive million rascals. He goes on to describe Catholicism and its adherents as a
plague, and the coming destruction as the end of eighteen hundred years of thorns
in Frances side (J: 499, 501).
States Belmor:
... we must arrest and slaughter all the priests in a single day and deal similarly with all
their followers; simultaneously, inside the space of the same minute, destroy every last
vestige of Catholicism ; and concurrently proclaim atheistic systems, and instantly entrust
to philosophers the education of our youth ; paint, publish, distribute, give out,
everywhere display those writings which propagate incredulity, unbelief, and for fifty
years persecute and put to death every individual, without exception, who might think to
re-inflate the balloon (J:499-500).
Belmor proposes the establishment of a death squad of twenty-five thousand men for
the execution of this operation: ...the elements of success are some political support,
secrecy, and firmness: no flabbiness, thats essential, and no keeping people waiting
in line. You fear martyrs, youll have them so long as a single worshipper of that
abominable Christian god is left alive (J: 500-501; similar: LNJ 2:403). Belmors
genocidal scheme is consistent with the acts of Sades primary libertine characters,
who make a point of torturing and killing those who express Christian morality or
piety. This is most explicit in The 120 Days of Sodom, in which children are killed for
breaking the regulations concerning religious observance (120: 248).
37
231
first Christians as living under a hypocritical submission until the time was right to
usurp that authority which they made a show of respecting while they were weak,
prefiguring Sades and Nietzsches view that Christian morality originated as a
psychological subterfuge (SC:178-179, 184). Following the reasoning of Machiavelli,
Rousseau considered Christianity incompatible with the needs of a warlike state, and
proposed that it be replaced with a minimalist Deism, explicitly subordinate to the
needs of politics (SC:87). Further, Rousseau proposed the reintroduction of Roman
symbols, including the Fascis, such was his enthusiasm for ancient Rome (E: 322; SC:
184).
The most extreme and sustained expression of the pagan Return, however, was
that of dHolbach. In his LEsprit du Judasme ou Examen Raisonn de la Loi de
Moyse, & de son influence sur la Religion Chrtienne (The Spirit of Judaism or
Reasoned Examination of the Law of Moses and its Influence on the Christian
Religion, 1750) -a copy of which Sade owned- dHolbach called for the elimination
of the influence of the Jews. 38 DHolbach reasoned that the religion of Jesus,
described as a pollution, had been foisted upon the Romans by the Jews as an act of
vengeance. Further, dHolbach argued that Judaism itself emerged as a deception by
Moses and, later, the Priests and Prophets to subjugate the people and the Kings of
Israel. In order to free Europe of this irrational creed, dHolbach calls for the
elimination of the entire cultural edifice, although he does not specify how this is to
be accomplished. He finishes his work with these words: Europe! Happy land where
for so long a time the arts, sciences, and philosophy have flourished; you whose
wisdom and power seem destined to command the rest of the world! Do you never tire
of the false dreams invented by the impostors in order to deceive the brutish slaves of
the Egyptians? [...] Leave to the stupid Hebrews, to the frenzied imbeciles, and to the
cowardly and degraded Asiatics these superstitions which are as vile as they are mad
.... 39 As noted above, Sade explicitly associates the origins of Christianity with the
38
For discussion on this text, see Arthur Hertzberg The French Enlightenment and the Jews (New
York: Columbia University Press, 1968/ The Jewish Publication Society of America Philadelphia,
5728) p.310. Alain Mothu lists dHolbachs Lesprit du Judasme among those in Sades library. Alain
Mothu Les lectures ncessaires du Marquis de Sade, La lettre clandestin 3 (1994):311-319 p.317.
39
[Baron dHolbach] LEsprit du Judasme ou examen raisonn de la loi de MOYSE, & de son
influence sur la Religion Chrtienne (Londres [probably false] 1750) p. 200-201. Quoted in Arthur
Hertzberg The French Enlightenment and the Jews p.310.
232
Jews, and largely repeats the slave revolt theory, though in a more straightforward
manner. Sade also repeats the view, promulgated by Voltaire, dHolbach, and others,
that that all of the great religious figures were ambitious charlatans: Lycurgus,
Numa, Moses, Jesus Christ, Mohammed, all these great rogues, all these great
thought-tyrants, knew how to associated the divinities they fabricated with their own
boundless ambition...they were always... to consult [their Gods] exclusively about, or
to make them exclusively respond to what they thought likely to serve their own
interests (PB:300). 40
Nor was Sade the first to express interest in the morality of the Pagans as a
possible alternative. Notably, where Sade describes the early Christians as a horde of
troublemakers, he alludes to the same Classical authors (Tacitus and Lucian) that
Voltaire and Rousseau had turned to (J: 283, 758, 759). 41 Rousseau felt that
seventeen centuries of Christianity had made Europe decadent and soft, and called
upon Europe to ...reclaimyour first innocence (DI: 153). Children should be
taught to steal, as practiced in Sparta, Rousseau suggested, rather than being glued to
books, and he thought that hunting should be encouraged, as it hardens the heart
to blood and cruelty (E: 119,128, 320). Even where Rousseau is discussing
Christian (that is, conventional) morality in a positive way, he tends to align himself
with Sades association of morality with weakness and a lack of passion. We have
morality, Rousseau reasons, as we are weak: [i]t is mans weakness which makes
him sociable; it is our common miseries which turn our hearts to humanity; we would
owe humanity nothing if we were not men (E: 221; also: SC: 77). Diderot and
Helvtius were similarly suspicious of Christian morality. Diderot suspected
40
On this subject, one particularly influential anonymous tract was the Three Impostors, known also
by its Latin title, De Tribus Impostoribus. It is thought to have first appeared in French in 1719, but its
actual origins are obscure. See Anonymous, Treatise of the Three Impostors and the Problem of
Enlightenment, A New Translation of the Traite Des Trois Imposteurs (1777 Edition) With Three
Essays in Commentary, translated by Abraham Anderson (Lanham, Maryland, U.S.A.: Rowman &
Littlefield Pub Inc, 1997). For discussion, see Silvia Berti, Francoise Charles-Daubert, Richard Henry
Popkin, editors, Heterodoxy, Spinozism, and Free Thought in Early-Eighteenth-Century Europe:
Studies on the Traite Des Trois Imposteurs (Archives Internationales D'histoire Des Ides, 148)
(Boston: Kluwer Academic Publishers, 1996).
41
For discussion, see Hertzberg pp.299-300. Lucian satirized the Christians in his Passing of
Peregrinus, a story of a philosopher sage who at one point becomes a leader of the Christians to take
advantage of their gullibility.
233
It is against this intellectual nostalgia that Sade offers his thoughts on the
greatness of the Celts, discussed above. Whereas Helvtius is content to note the
passion and the poetry of the Vikings, Sade makes a more direct claim- the morality
of the Celts ought to be revived and applied directly to the modern world. Sade
emphasizes just how different the morality of the pre-Christian peoples of Europe
really was, and that it was based on very different standards and principles. Notes
Christopher Hibbert, the European understanding of crime and punishment was
completely transformed by the adoption of the Mosaic Law. Punishment was often
settled with a fine, or a duel, which of course would place the wealthy and strong, and
those trained in the art of war (that is, the nobles) at an advantage (an institution Sade
proposes in Aline et Valcour, to be discussed in Chapter VII). Until the rediscovery of
Roman law, murder, robbery and rape were regarded, not as sins, but as torts that
could be settled by compensation. Rape was regarded not as a crime against the
42
43
44
Ibid. p.349.
45
234
46
Christopher Hibbert The Roots of Evil: A Social History of Crime and Punishment (London: Penguin,
1963). p.18
47
Ibid. p.17
48
49
50
Catherine Cusset Sade, Machiavel et Nron, Dix-huitime Sicle 22 (1990): 401-411, p.402.
235
What people were at once greater and more bloodthirsty than the Romans, and what
nation longer preserved its splendour and freedom? The gladiatorial spectacles fed its
bravery, it became warlike through the habit of making a game of murder. Twelve or
fifteen hundred victims filled the circus arena every day, and there the women, crueller
than the men, dared demand that the dying fall gracefully and be sketched while still in
deaths throes. The Romans moved from that to the pleasures of seeing dwarfs cut each
other to pieces; and when the Christian cult, then infecting the world, came to persuade
men there was evil in killing one another, the tyrants immediately enchained that people,
and everyones heroes became their toys (PB: 334, also 299; similar: J:784).
Note that Sade links up the greatness of Rome precisely with its brutality, and its
collapse with the softening of the belief that human life is sacred. Exactly the same
group of associations- the grandeur and barbarity of Rome, and the doctrine of
inequality- is made in an official letter Sade wrote whilst serving as a Revolutionary
functionary. On November 7th 1793, Citoyen Sade, vice- president of the Section des
piques, was given the job of rechristening the streets of the neighborhood in his
jurisdiction with appropriately revolutionary names. Included in his letter to the
Comit de surveillance is the following proposal:
La rue de lArcade sappellera
RUE DE SPARTACUS
Citoyen Sade- in terms identical to the official Revolutionary view, proposes to name
a street after the celebrated Roman slave. Even though Sades official morality is the
exact opposite of that of the libertines, he consistently makes the association of Rome,
its grandeur, and its barbarity, as if to point out a lacuna in the Revolutionary
penchant for the Classical world. Unlike Rousseau or Voltaire, Sade notes that the
51
236
Romans were inhuman. Whichever Sade is the true one Citoyen Sade or Libertin
Sade- whether Sade wanted to warn of the actual implications of returning to Rome,
or was sincerely in favour of razing Jerusalem- is unclear.
In the following chapter, the doctrine of the Natural Right of the Strong, as
applied to the political domain in Sades work, will be discussed.
237
238
Pirelli slogan.
7.1 Introduction.
On the subject of politics, there is no consensus on what Sade had in mind, what his
work amounts to, or whether he treated the topic, as such, at all. The political aspect
of Sades work is a relatively neglected area, and a number of influential scholars (in
particular Hnaff, Le Brun, Blanchot, Bataille, and Klossowski) scarcely mention it at
all, giving the reader the impression that Sade only depicts isolated libertines, entirely
cut off from the rest of the world. Sades one direct statement on his political
orientation only clarifies that he was, at least publicly, unable to commit to any
particular political ethic or ideology. 1 In 1792, he wrote the following lines to his
lawyer and friend, Gaufridy:
It is not, in truth, for any of the parties, yet it is a composite of all of them. I am an antiJacobin, I hate them to the death; I love the King, yet I detest the former abuses; I love the
vast majority of the articles of the Constitution, others of them revolt me; I would like the
nobility returned to their glory, because taking it away from them accomplishes nothing; I
wish the King were the head of the nation; I do not at all want the national Assembly, but
two houses as in England, which gives the King a mitigated authority, balanced by the
concurrence of a nation necessarily divided into two orders, the third [i.e., the clergy] is
unnecessary, I want nothing of them. There you have my profession of faith. What am I
now? Aristocrat or democrat? Please tell me, lawyer, because, as for me, I do not have the
faintest idea. 2
For discussion, see Thomas Sade, la dissertation et lorgie p.14 ; Alain Verjat Limaginaire de Sade
Letter to Gaufridy, December 5th 1791. In Sade Correspondance indite du Marquis de Sade de ses
proches, et de ses familiers ed. Paul Bourdin (Paris : Librairie de France, 1929) pp.301-2. Quoted in
Shaeffer pp.414-415.
239
Juliette is full of lurid caricatures of living political and church figures. Juliette herself meets Gustav
of Sweden, Pope Pius VI, Ferdinand of Naples, Victor-Amde of Savoy, and Leopold of
Tuscany. Another character, Brisatesta, brother of Clairwil, is an intimate of Catherine the Great
(Juliette pp.874-880). In The 120 Days of Sodom Sade refers to a certain Bishop de X***,insinuating
that this was a real serial killing cleric, and refers to himself as the Marquis de S***, who was burned
in effigy for the crime of sodomy (120:191, 495). Sade also writes that a particular vivisecting doctor is
based on an acquaintance (J: 729) Further, throughout Juliette there are a number of assertions that
particular plots and atrocities are based on fact, such as a plot to set fire to every hospital in Rome:
[t]his project was actually conceived while I was at Rome, and I alter nothing but the names of the
actors (J: 726,762, 858). He also alludes to the sexual exploits of Marie Antoinette (934) and the link
between the sex trade industry and the Italian church (980).
4
For discussion of Sades political career, see Michel Delon Sade Thermidorien In Michel Camus,
Philippe Roger, eds Sade, crire la crise:99-118 ; Michel Delon Sade dans la Rvolution pp.160161 ; Michael La Chance Marat, Sade: Despotiser de corps in 1789: Confrences 1989 (Montral:
240
7.2 Antipodes
Oh Sainville! A great revolution will come to your people!
Dpt. dtudes franaises, Universit de Montral, 1990):5-32, pp.17, 23; Lucienne Frappier Mazur
A Turning Point in the Sadean Novel: The Terror In Sawhney, ed. Must We Burn Sade? : 115-131;
Marcelin Pleynet The Readability of Sade in The Tel Quel Reader ed. Patrick ffrench (sic), RolandFranois Lack (London and New York: Routledge, 1998):109-122, p.188; Michal La Chance Marat,
Sade: Despotiser de corps in 1789: Confrences 1989 (Montral: Dpt. dtudes franaises, Universit
de Montral, 1990):5-32, p.17.
For discussion on the sources of Sades thoughts on politics and population control, see Jean Ehrard
Pour une lecture non sadienne de Sade: mariage et dmographie dans Aline et Valcour In Roger,
Camus ed. Sade, crire la crise: 241-258; Yves Giraud La ville du bout du monde: Sade, Aline et
Valcour In Studi di letterature francese 11, 1985:85-100, p.98. Lacombe p.156-161, 168 -178 ;
Giraud p.92 ; AV:866, fn. 406. Philippe Roger La trace de Fnelon In Camus and Roger, eds. Sade
crire la crise pp.149-175. Sade also mentions abb de Saint-Pierres proposal for a Pan- European
republic (AV: 531).
5
Batrice Didier and Philippe Roger both take Sade to be engaged in a destruction of the confines of
language itself. See Philippe Roger Sade La Philosophie dans le pressoir pp.189-190; Didier Sade: Un
criture du dsir pp 129, 203, 222. James N. Glass Rousseaus Emile and Sades Eugnie: Action,
Nature and the Presence of Moral Structure, The Philosophical Forum: a Quarterly 7, no. 1 (Fall
1975):38-55, pp.340. Kazuhiko Sekitani, Rvolution franaise et rotisme vus travers les textes
politiques de Sade, Etudes de langue et littrature franaises 62 (March 1993):16-28.
6
There are socialist aspects of Sades libertine works. The libertines are frequently described by the
241
philosophical novel that Sade admitted to have written, and the first to have
appeared under his own name. 7 Like his short stories, it has a moral orientation quite
unlike that of the libertine works. Within this text are a number of unremarkable and
unoriginal suggestions concerning economic and defense policies, such as the
importance of agriculture to national wellbeing, and the necessity of strengthened
naval power to defend trade routes (AV: 236; 237). It is Letter XXXV, however, that
has received the most interest.
In Letter XXXV, Lonore is kidnapped by Turkish pirates and is feared sold to
a Sultan. Sainville, in the course of his rescue attempt, and following a rumour that
Lonore is aboard Captain James Cooks research vessel Endeavour, travels the world
in search of her. 8 On his travels he encounters two exotic societies; the Kingdom of
Batua, in West Africa, and the Kingdom of Tamo, a tiny Republic off the coast of
New Zealand (AV :279). 9 As interpretation of Sades politics has focused on the latter,
I will begin here.
Upon arrival in Tamo, Sainville meets Zam, self-described philosopher king of
the island (AV: 281). Sainville is surprised that Zam understands French. In reply,
Zam explains that he is familiar with the ways of Europeans, and tells his story.
Many years earlier, a French battleship discovered the island, and for a month, the
crew took advantage of the weakness and innocence of the islanders, committing
many disorders (AV: 388). Nevertheless, Zam took the chance to see the world,
and travelled to Europe, remaining there for three years. Having seen the hypocrisy
and absurdity of European laws and practices, he returned to Tamo, and transformed
the Republic into the ideal state, based on the lessons learned.
The figure of Zam, and his doctrine, is largely in keeping with the political
thought of his age. He is an enlightened despot, or, as Fink describes him, a
between rich and poor (LNJ 1: 68; 83). Only in Aline et Valcour, however, is economic difference and
exploitation discussed as an actual wrong.
7
Schaeffer p.455.
Captain James Cook of the Royal Navy (1728-1779) was the first explorer to circumnavigate and
accurately chart New Zealand, and has the status of ancestor figure for European (Pakeha) New
Zealanders. It may amuse the reader to know that the author was born in New Zealand, in a region
called The Bay of Plenty, a rather Utopian name given by Captain Cook himself.
9
This appeared as a separate book in the 10:18 series. Marquis de Sade Histoire de Sainville et de
242
paternalistic autocrat. 10 He rules entirely in accordance with his own education and
judgement. Like Voltaire, Diderot and Rousseau, Zam is distrustful of the notion of
Democracy (notably, even Rousseau feared that democracy was only suited to small,
poor countries, remarking that full democracy was for gods, not men; SC: 30-32,
125). 11 When Sainville asks him why the island lacks any political or legal apparatus
besides his own authority, Zam states: [s]i les lois sont justes, elles nont pas besoin
dtre dposes ailleurs que dans le cur de chaque citoyen, et elles sy placeront
naturellement. He adds that a British- style parliamentary system would be
undesirable: [m]oins de danger pour le peuple, sans doute, mais bien plus dentraves
pour moi; plus je diviserai mon pouvoir, plus je laffaiblirai, et comme je nai envie
que de faire le bien, je ne veux pas que rien men empche (AV: 298).
Every aspect of life on Tamo is dictated by principles laid down by Zam, and
many of his directives appear (to modern eyes, at least) draconian. Reasoning based
on his experiences in Europe that luxury goods harm the economic wellbeing of the
state, and that crime is entirely due to economic difference, Zam has (or claims to
have) eliminated all luxury, economic inequality, and private property. 12 An
extremely limited diet is enforced; meat is banned, as is every beverage other than
water (AV: 283, 285, 352, 357). All property is held in common, and there is no hard
currency. Zam boasts that this system (call it Zamism) is closer to nature, citing
the authority of Diogenes and Epicurus (not, curiously, Rousseau) on the virtues of
natural living (AV: 294). He declares: []tablissez lgalit des fortunes et des
conditions, quil ny ait dunique propritaire que ltatet tout les crimes dangereux
disparatront; la constitution de Tamo vous le prouve (AV: 319, 321, 337, 339). The
Republic is both an autarky (all trade, and all interaction with other states is
prohibited) and a command economy. Industry on Tamo is restricted to agriculture,
10
11
Candide and Other Tales p.398; Diderot Political Writings pp 32, 91. For discussion, see also Isaiah
Berlin the art of Being Ruled In Times Literary Supplement February 15th 2002 p.15. For discussion
on the theory of Enlightened Despotism in the 18th Century, see Geoffrey Bruun The Enlightened
Despots (New York: Holt, Rinehart and Winston, Inc, 1967).
12
Juliette makes similar pronouncements, describing the city as a pit that swallows up all the wealth
of the nation, and thereby impoverishes it; a place where inequality, that all-destroying poison, is
visible everywhere (J: 928). Rousseau, on such grounds, proposed that Paris be destroyed (E: 469).
243
textiles, construction and defence, despite the presence of significant gold deposits on
the island (AV: 288, 289, 329).
Zamism permeates all aspects of life on Tamo. Zam, who clearly does not
believe in the principle of separation of church and state, holds that it is necessary
to have a god in order to maintain control (again, this view is in keeping with the
thought of the 18th Century, in particular that of Voltaire, Rousseau, and the architects
of the Cult of Reason proposed during the French Revolution. People, it was thought,
need a religion; a rational religion stripped of dogma is better). 13 Zam is both the
founder and the high priest of the islands religion (a combination of rationalist Deism
and solar worship), and leads the entire population in its daily dawn Prayer to the Sun,
at which the following prayer is said: [y]ou who steer our thoughts, who regulates
our actions, who purifies our hearts, our sentiment, of respect, and love, you inspire
(AV: 354, 355). He has everyone on the island brought up to regard him as their
father, and to love a deity which is essentially a personification of the established
order (AV: 322). As such, he is both a cult leader and the only personality cult in
Sades work.
Censorship on Tamo is strictly enforced, and all art and entertainment is
subordinate to the interests of the state. All publishing is limited to the necessities of
education and industry, and all theatrical works (some written by Zam himself) are
written for the purposes of the moral education of the community. 14 Anything more
elaborate, notes Fink, would stimulate creativity and controversy and thus a desire
for change. 15 Education, too, is subordinate to the needs of the state. Besides
religious (that is, cult) indoctrination, Childrens tastes are consciously shaped for
good citizenship at an early age (AV: 361). Writes Fink, [i]nstruction is purely
factual; there is no teaching of aesthetic, speculative or policy-oriented disciplines.
The child, that is, is educated to understand the system and meet its technical
requirements, not to innovate or make decisions for himself. 16 Education is also
13
During the Revolution, Sade himself served as an official in the ceremonies of the Cult of Virtue. See
Lever, pp.445-449.
14
One play that is mentioned, written by Zam himself, deals with the subject of adultery. The function
of the play is not to provide catharsis but to allow the public to see their own guilt (Goulemots note;
AV: 359).
15
16
244
used to give children the belief that it is to the State, and not to their families, that
allegiance is owed (an idea derived from Rousseau). 17 States Zam: it is the state
which feeds the citizens, who raises the children, which treats them, judges them;
which condemns them; and I am nothing other than its first citizen (AV: 366).
Education in Tamo, being focused on civic virtue and practical skills, mirrors
education in our own society. To varying degrees, the educational systems of all
modern states emphasise practicality (over the emphasis, in Sades day, on such
subjects as Latin and Greek), and civic duty. The emphasis on civic duty is more
explicit in the education systems of, say, South Korea and France than in New
Zealand or Canada, yet even here the values and principles that the State upholds,
such as multiculturalism, are instilled at school. Insofar as it is a society in which
Rousseaus proposals for educational reform has been implemented, Tamo is
prophetic. The same could be said of Zams subordination of the family to the
authority of the state. This is a common enough idea in our age, yet, again, a recent
idea that was only officially implemented from the time of the French Revolution.
Now, it is taken for granted in Western- style democracies that the state is the sole
authority in family matters, and that laws of the state have precedence over family
ties. We take it for granted that the State has the power, and the right, to remove
mistreated children from their parents, to take husbands from their wives in order to
serve in the military, and so on. Further, under the ancien rgime (under the lettre de
cachet system) one could be imprisoned, not by order of a court of law appointed by
the state, but by the request of a family member. The universal and absolute nature of
state power, now so familiar to us, is only visible at all through the distorting lens of
Sades strange utopian vision. Insofar as we may regard Zams edicts concerning
eating meat both presumptuous and paternalistic, the same may be said of his laws
concerning civil identity.
Other aspects of Tamoean social engineering are also of note. No health care,
besides the policing of diet and the banishment of the sick from the island, is
provided. Special permission has to be granted to avoid marriage; men are whipped to
17
Rousseau, in The Government of Poland, proposes that infants see nothing but the Fatherland from
the moment of birth, so that their mothers milk is laced with love for their country. Rousseau
The Social Contract and Other Later Political Writings, ed, trans., and annotated by Victor Gourevitch
(Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1997) p. 189. Quoted in Robert Wokler Rousseau: A very
Short Introduction (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2001) p. 118-119.
245
recover virility. The unmarried (clibataires) and the rpudis de lun et de lautre
sexe are housed in a separate part of the island (AV: 364, 367). Adultery is banned,
although divorce is permitted (AV: 283, 365). Sades description of the inhabitants of
Tamo, in terms of race and blood, is also consistent with the preoccupation with
social engineering. 18
It is the town planning of Tamo that betrays its nature as an architectonic of
total power. The whole of the island, as Jean M. Goulemot puts it, is un systme
gnralis de contrle (AV: p.837, n.424). The streets and buildings are laid out in a
perfectly circular pattern so that one of Zams representatives is able to observe his
subjects from a central observation point: afin que lil vigilant du commandant
de la ville pt stendre avec moins de peine sur tous les sujets de la contre (AV:
368-370). It is, in fact, Benthams Panopticon; in contemporary terms, every citizen is
on closed-circuit television. The enforced isolation of the island is also significant.
The citizens are forbidden from leaving (a privilege granted Zam, but denied
everyone else), and all but military vessels are destroyed to make departure
impossible. There is no interaction with other states, despite the opportunity to trade
with gold. Notes Fink, [i]solation notably precludes comparisons with other life
styles and thus minimizes the unsettling weighing of alternatives. 19 Zam, for an
avowed pacifist, spends a considerable amount of time discussing military
preparedness. He proudly shows off the precision and might of his navy in a mock
battle, and discusses the strict meritocracy of the army, a defence force of 42,000
personnel (a militia of 3,000 soldiers for each of Tamos fourteen towns; AV:314,
326, 330, 329, 370). This is curious, as the island has not been visited by foreigners in
at least sixty years, suggesting that there is an ulterior motive for such militarism. 20 In
18
Although Tamo is off the coast of New Zealand, Sade describes its inhabitants as white and blond
with blue eyes, wearing European dress and living in European style dwellings, provoking one critic to
suggest that Sade is immune to exoticism. See Yves Giraud, La ville du bout du monde: Sade, Aline
et Valcour, Studi di letteratura Francese 11 (1985):85-100, p.92. Sainville, in describing the women,
states that en gnral, le sang est superbe Tamo (AV: 315, 331, 363, 367). This old idea of blood
being the agency of biological heritage reappears elsewhere in the novel. For example, the character
Valcour states that le sang de mes anctres coule pur dans mes veines (AV: 676).
19
20
Zam states that the island was visited by the French navy at the end of the reign of Louis XIV,
which ended in 1715. Sainvilles travels are contemporary with the third voyage of Cook, 1776 -1779
(AV: 277, 288).
246
Juliette, written two years later (1797), a clear association is made between the
maintenance of authoritarian rule and military readiness. A king is, states Juliette, to
the body politic as a doctor is to the physical body: you may call him when you are ill,
you must show him to the door once health returns, else hell prolong the malady so
as to be of eternal aid, and while pretending to cure, hell bide with you to the grave
(Sade adds in a footnote: Not until the fatherland was in danger did the Romans
name a dictator J: 936&n).
The Laws of Tamo (the bans on controlled substances such as meat and
alcohol, censorship, forbidden sexual activity, and so on) are enforced with a range of
punishments. Whilst milder crimes are punished with public humiliation (clearly a
chastisement, or even collective revenge, rather than a correction), or being forced
to wear specially marked clothes, more serious violations are punished with exile in a
canoe with a weeks provisions- in the middle of the South Pacific Ocean, banned
from returning on pain of death (AV: 325, 344). Another of Zams suggestions- that
murderers are punished according to the economic value of the dead to the community
shows that individuals are not judged as equal in the eyes of the law (AV:343). 21
The most intriguing aspect of Zams doctrine is his belief that he rules his
kingdom without the use of laws. Laws, he states, are not only unjust but vain- a
spiders web in which flies are killed and from which the wasps always escape (AV:
337). 22 He also argues that laws create crime : Plus vous leur offrez de digues, plus
21
Zam notes that this was the custom of the ancient Francs and Germans. This reflects Sades interest
in a return to the ethics of the pre-Christian Europeans, as discussed in the previous chapter.
22
Here Zams discussion matches that of the libertines, who frequently complain that the justice
system is blind, corrupt, or insufficient. These criticisms are made in monologues that typically involve
slips from Bataillian to Benthamite mode and back again. For example, the highwayman Dubois argues
that his crimes are themselves the fault of the law rather than his own. He has to kill all the people he
robs, as the punishment for aggravated robbery is death. Yet he observes that murder gives him a
pleasurable tickling (LNJ 1: 85). Similarly, a character in La Nouvelle Justine complains of absurd
laws that prevent me from treating my wife as I see fit, namely, imprisoning her and drinking her
blood (LNJ 2:168). Other, general comments made concerning the legal system: a man may do many
good things in his life, but will be harshly punished for doing one bad thing; the courts will find guilty
that person that they think is most likely to have committed the crime; people can change their ways;
the justice system punishes those who are ignorant of the law; some laws are patently arbitrary, in
particular the lettre de cachet system; the judges and magistrates are corrupt and hypocritical (AV: 16,
337, 344; MV:21; J:376, 215, 358; LNJ 2:404). Further, the theme of the judge who derives sexual
247
vous leur prparez de plaisir les rompre ; cest, comme vous dites, linfraction seule
qui les amuse ; peut-tre ne se plongeraient-ils pas dans cette espce de mal, sils ne le
croyaient dfendu (AV :340; also 338, 339). 23 His justice system, he declares, is
based on prevention and the hope of correction (lespoir de corriger), on the grounds
that to imprison and punish merely embitters the wrong- doer (AV: 327). 24 Zam also
assumes (in keeping with Sadeian ontology) that hard determinism is true. The
criminal is merely a hapless instrument of blind nature; hence, perhaps even the
softest law is tyrannic (AV: 347). He also argues against the death penalty, his
arguments ranging from the well- known (miscarriages of justice cannot be reversed)
to the irrelevant (the execution of criminals originated with Celtic rites; AV: 332, 336).
25
As people cannot be improved through legislation, Zam holds that they can only
be made compliant through changing their motives, and through examples and
compensations. He explains this principle to Sainville:
Voyez cet arbre, poursuivit Zam, en men montrant un dont le tronc tait plein de
nuds; croyez-vous quaucun effort puisse jamais redresser cette plante?
Non.
Il faut donc la laisser comme elle est ; elle fait nombre et donne de lombrage ; usons-en
et ne la regardons pas. Les gens dont vous me parlez sont rares. Ils ne minquitent point ;
jemploierais le sentiment, la dlicatesse et lhonneur avec eux, ces freins seraient plus
srs que ceux de la loi. Jessaierais encore de faire changer leur habitude de motifs, lun
ou lautre de ces moyens russirait : croyez-moi mon ami, jai trop tudi les hommes
pour ne pas vous rpondre quil nest aucune sorte derreurs que je ne dtourne ou
nanantisse, sans jamais employer de punitions corporelles. Ce qui gne ou moleste le
physique nest fait que pour les animaux ; lhomme, ayant la raison au-dessus deux, ne
doit tre conduit que par elle et ce puissant ressort mne tout, il ne sagit que de savoir
le manier ( AV:340).
Given that, as noted above, Tamo has both (by our standards) draconian laws,
and applies harsh punishments to offenders, we have a portrait of a society in which
pleasure from sentencing people to death occurs frequently in Sades work (J: 126, 222; 237; 120:363,
531; AV: 334). For commentary see Bongie p. xi.
23
24
25
Chigi, the chief of Police in Juliette, makes the same claim (J: 734).
This complaint is made in Juliette (J: 730).
Many of Sades characters argue against the death penalty. Zams case differs, as his arguments are
consistent here with his own ethics (LNJ. 1:152, 153; J: 122 AV: 739).
248
the reality of the penal system scarcely matches the official rhetoric of humanistic
values and the principle of correction (if not in New Zealand, certainly in other
Western states). Again, Tamo is uncomfortably similar to contemporary society.
A global reading of Sades corpus mitigates against reading the Tamo episode
as a straightforward expression of political ideology. In particular, the morality of
Tamo is based entirely on principles that Sade savages elsewhere- namely, the
principle of equality, the undesirability of luxury, and the idea that a commonplace
morality can be derived from nature. The doctrine of enforced equality is taken to an
extreme that would lead to immediate conflict even on Zams own grounds (because,
as Zam explains, laws simply make more attractive the forbidden, prohibition would
create a black market economy of everything banned, and a desire to simply leave the
island, or perhaps even to mutiny). 26 Zam, a benevolent philosopher- king, is a
psychological impossibility for Sade (as discussed below, power is closely associated
with its enjoyment, and Sade typically warns that the powerful are not to be
trusted). 27 Yet one suspects that he returned from Europe as much a Sadeian as a
Rousseauian. Zam makes several doctrinal lapses whilst conversing with Sainville,
betraying thoughts that would be catastrophic for his subjects to seriously consider.
For example, he suggests that the same set of rules could not possibly suit everyone,
or that criminals are chained to the superior laws of nature, even though the official
doctrine is ostensibly grounded on the same laws of nature (AV: 348, 352). These
incongruities are brought to a head as the episode concludes. Sainville informs the
reader that the citizens of Tamo are un peuple doux, sensible, vertueux sans lois,
pieux sans religion, despite clearly having both laws and a state religion, and lacking
the freedom to truly exercise the virtues (AV: 371). Finally, in order to aid Sainville
in his travels, Zam gifts Sainville with 7,570,000 livres in gold bullion, despite
having claimed to be the equal of his citizens, and to have banned luxury and wealth
26
Given his penchant for marshmallow syrup, roast beef, and only the most expensive rosewater, it is
hard to believe that Sade himself could have considered Tamo a Utopia. Marquis de Sade Letters from
Prison pp.295, 154, 157, 160-161, 169, 295.
27
This may not necessarily be an indication of actual parody, given that, throughout the novel,
characters frequently adopt theoretical points of view that do not cohere with their behaviour. Lonore
is both a good Christian and a devout atheist, for example (AV: 570, n. 587). For discussion, see Pierre
Favre Sade utopiste : sexualit, pouvoir et tat dans le roman Aline et Valcour (Paris : Presses
universitaires de France, 1967).
249
from the island (AV: 375). Again, he grants to himself, and to his guest, that which is
denied his subjects. 28
Tamo was not, in fact, intended to be read in isolation. As noted above, it
makes up one half of a diptych, the other wing being the Kingdom of Batua. Le Brun
and Roger note that in both Aline et Valcour (with regards to political doctrine) and
the 120 Days of Sodom (with regards to sexual penchants) the author invites the
reader to choose their favourite position from within the text. Sade states, in the
introduction to Aline et Valcour: the wiser reader should amuse or occupy himself
with the different political systems presented, whether for or against, and adopt those
which best promote his ideas or inclinations (AV: 46, also 120:254). 29
Batua is a Kingdom somewhere on the West Coast of Africa, with a population
of 30,000. Like Tamo, Batua is ruled by an absolute monarch, Ben Macoro.
The kingdom is essentially Minskis Castle on a larger scale- a totalitarian sexual
utopia for one- and makes as little sociological sense. Principal economic products are
maize, monkey meat, human flesh and the trade in sex slaves (AV: 257, 258). Political
control is maintained through brute force, rather than the finely calibrated system of
indoctrination of Tamo (AV: 236, 238). Writes Fink: ... [b]rainwashing is
accomplished by a priestly class which, in exchange for social privileges, inculcates in
the inhabitants the principles of superstition, fear and contempt for others. 30 Only
women perform any function besides the role of King or Village Chief, making up all
of the countrys labourers, sex slaves, or soldiers (the only functions Sade lists). Yet
they are taught to be absolutely submissive to men, and are locked up, punished, or
condemned to death for the least misdemeanour, or sacrificed to the Cult of the
Serpent, despite the fact that, bizarrely, they hold all the arms and do all the
productive labour (AV:223, 248). Women are also considered lowly whilst pregnant,
28
The sum is so vast that Sainville can buy a new vessel and have it fully crewed without making a
dent in his fortune, and the sum of gold he carries causes him serious legal problems upon arrival in
Europe. On the continuity of socioeconomic elites in Sades work, see Michel Delon Sade
Thermidorien p.107.
29
Le Brun Sudden Abyss pp. 106, 108-109 ; Roger La trace de Fnelon pp.165, 167.
30
Beatrice Fink Political Systemp.508 See also Shelby Spruell The Marquis de Sade- Pornography
or Political Protest?, Proceedings of the Annual Meeting of the Western Society for French History 9
(1982):238-249.
250
and, if the Kings concubines, are killed if made pregnant by the King- customs in
keeping with the will towards sterility outlined in Chapter IV. 31
Upon arrival in Batua, Sainville meets Sarmiento, a Portuguese expatriate,
whose function is to inspect pleasure objects(that is, women for the harem) for the
delectation of the King (AV:239, 272, 274). Sarmientos philosophy- which is that of
his adopted home- is of a piece with that of other libertines. Sarmiento speaks of the
same ontology and reductionist psychology of violent irritations and shocks of
the atoms as the Libertines (AV: 240, 264). Likewise, he denies free will, and blames
his acts on his natural despotism, concluding, in classic Sadeian style, jai trouv le
bonheur dans mes systmes, et ny ai jamais connu le remords (AV: 243). Sarmiento
argues that, as destruction is natural, and that mans nature leads him to destruction,
war is not criminal. 32 He argues that the weak are created by Nature to be dominated,
and that crime does not exist. When Sainville criticizes the trade in black slaves,
Sarmiento replies that the very fact that they were enslaved at all proves their natural
inferiority. 33
Direct comparison of Batua and Tamo is revealing, and perhaps discloses
Sades intentions. Zam is the weakest philosophe character in all of Sades surviving
works. Unlike the likes of Juliette or Clairwil, Zam never discusses the actual
premises of his doctrine- rather, he imposes the doctrine of equality and mediocrity
onto the people, and presents the aberrant individual with the threat of a certain death
in the middle of the Pacific Ocean. Further, every point he makes is countered
somewhere else in the novel. 34 His dialogue is also one- sided, lacking the back-andforth of the discussion between Sainville and Sarmiento that immediately precedes it.
Zam is deeply inconsistent, in sharp contrast to the frequently unassailable logic of
the lone-wolf libertines such as Minski. The two figures have theoretical
31
Accordingly, Sarmiento argues that Nature merely tolerates reproduction (AV: 254).
32
D.N. Beach The Marquis de Sade: First Zimbabwean Novelist, Zambezia VIII (i) (1980): 53-6,
pp.56, 58.
33
Beach p.58. This is more or less Aristotles argument in the Politics, Aristotle The Politics, ed. S.
Everson (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1988) Book I, chapters iii-vii. For discussion on
Greek philosophical views on slavery, see Stephen L. Esquith, and Nicholas D. Smith (1998).
Slavery, In E. Craig, ed, Routledge Encyclopedia of Philosophy (London: Routledge). Retrieved
November 17, 2004, from http://www.rep.routledge.com/article/S055SECT1.
34
The importance of the market for luxury goods to the economy is discussed later in the novel (AV:
643).
251
commonalities. Neither Sarmiento nor Zam believe in free will, or accept normative
notions of ethics or justice. Both Zam and Ben Macoro use religious indoctrination
to maintain power (AV: 260), and both societies are monolithic, as opposed to open,
societies. Neither trusts their citizens to follow instructions without either thorough
indoctrination, constant surveillance, or the direct threat of punishment, and neither
assume that the citizens will simply see the reasonableness of their legislation. Zam
holds to the principle of equality and respect for all, Ben Macoro does not. More
importantly, power in Batua is visible and crude, its relationship plainly linked to
brute force, whereas, on Tamo, it is invisible but meticulously organized.
Reading the Tamo and Batua episodes in a literal way- that is, as a political
proposal or manifesto, may not be the most profitable approach. A great deal of
thought went into Tamo, but apparently more thought went into the planning of the
ultimate micromanaged state than into political doctrine as such. With regards to
Tamo, Fink writes:
The hallmark of a serious political philosophy, whether analytical or normative, is a
preoccupation with the phenomenon of power in society: its origins, magnitude,
distribution, limitation, validation etc. Immediately we are confronted with the fact that
Sades writings demonstrate an almost ubiquitous concern with the concept of power and
its ethical validation, use and consequences at the level of interpersonal and intergroup
relationships. 35
Whether Tamo and Batua are to be read as satires (Tamo, as one of revolution, Ben
Macoros Batua, as Fink suggests, as a parody of the absolute Monarchy) is
unclear. 36 What can be ruled out is the reading of either as being a positive political
treatise, or even as an open- ended smorgasbord: there are only two options offered:
Darfur or North Korea. If Aline et Valcour was intended as a straightforward
statement of Sades political views, the overall picture is one of utter hopelessness. 37
35
36
Ibid. p.500.
37
Unsurprisingly, no critic who has carefully read Sade as a political theorist has given him a positive
reception. Giraud takes Aline et Valcour to be a confession of absolute political pessimism that secretes
boredom, uniformity and general anaesthesia. Giraud La ville du bout du monde, p.100. Roger G.
Lacombe notes sardonically that Sade seems more concerned with discussing punishments to be meted
252
Finks approach-according to which Sades political thought concerns the tools and
mechanics of psychological conditioning and control- appears to be the most fruitful
one, and will be returned to below. 38
39
And what goes beyond all understanding is that the Jacobins of the French Revolution wanted to
smash the altars of a God who spoke precisely their own language. Yet more extraordinarily, they who
253
French Revolution has not gone far enough in eliminating the very morality of
Christianity or, perhaps b). the Revolutionaries have not understood what the return to
Rome entails, is not clear.
Also discussed above (in Chapter IV) is the proposal for the establishment of
brothels, which conflates Benthamite and Bataillian principles. Sade asserts that there
is a relevant distinction between the excesses of existing political institutions and
those of the libertines; the distinction Sade makes between labsurde despotisme
politique and the trs luxurieux despotisme des passions de libertinage (the absurd
political despotism and the luxurious despotism of the passions of libertinage):
The poverty of the French language compels us to employ words which, today, our happy
government, with so much good sense, disfavours; we hope our enlightened readers will
understand us well and will not at all confound absurd political despotism with the very
delightful despotism of libertinages passions (PB:344,fn).
Several critics have mentioned this distinction without directly addressing its basic untenability, for
example Chantal Thomas Isabelle de Bavire: Dernier heroine de Sade in Camus and Roger, ed.,
Sade, crire la crise 47-66:56; Michel Delon Sade Thermidorien p.110; Mengue Lordre
Sadien p.256.
254
is proposed (305,314); yet the text also proposes the preparation of the entire state for
war, the elimination of the nuclear family (as a rival source of authority to the State),
life imprisonment for clergymen, and (unspecified) punishment for those that resist
rape in the state brothels (PB: 314, 306, 318-319, 322, 334). 41
There are two further, dizzying, conflations. On the one hand, Sade argues in the
terms of his own core ontological assumptions. On the grounds of his rejection of free
will, he rejects the principle of laws that are equally applicable to all (PB: 310). 42 On
the grounds of his ontology (according to which the lives of humans are trivial),
murder is not a crime; on the grounds of (a cynical abuse of the) principle of self
defence, it is a political necessity (PB: 330-335). Yet, finally, Sade condemns the
Revolution as a crime of metaphysical proportions- the murder of the very concept of
Law (note the conservatism here- there is no higher morality or ideology that
transcends that of the ancien rgime, and its anchor- point- the life and body of the
King). 43
41
Sade reasons that, if the slander is an exaggeration, it may yet reveal ugly truths about the person
slandered. If it is unfair, the person will work all the harder to show that he is virtuous.
42
This appears to be a non sequitur- if there is no free will for anyone, there ought to be the same
regulatory principles applied to all. If some are incapable of exercising judgement, one simply
recognizes a category of people who should be withdrawn from circulation.
43
Sade himself, in particular in the earlier works such as Dialogue between a Priest and a Dying Man
(1782), shows a marked conservatism. This conservatism does not concern this study, as is not
supported by any doctrinal standpoint in Sades work (although, of course, it has a vague resemblance
to the Aristocratic principle). In the Dialogue, the dying man states: I forgive all errors save those
which may imperil the government under which we live; kings and their majesty are the only things
that I take on trust and respect. He goes on to state that The man who does not love country and his
king does not deserve to live (MV: 157). Sades nostalgia for the old order is also expresses disdain for
the immorality of the emergent bourgeois class, and repeated statements to the effect that feudalism is
necessary for cultural flourishing (L N J 2:225; J:116, fn.).
Writes David Coward, Sades pre- Revolutionary political views reflect a mixture of patrician
conservatism and the progressive values of the Enlightenment. Like many of the old nobility, he
resented the erosion of aristocratic power and privilege which had been the centralizing monarchys
policy since the time of Richelieu; yet at the same time he was opposed to the excesses of the old
feudal tyranny (MV: 282). Even Aline et Valcour, the most socialist of Sades works, contains
passages that suggest this; in a critique of the virtue of charity, beggars are described by a central
character as vermin who are sure of a living at the expense of dupes; and the hero of the novel (an
aristocrat, who has a butler) insults a rival by stating that mon valet demain peut tre votre gal.
(tomorrow my servant may be your equal; AV: 642; 673).
255
Sade argues that the revolution, to follow its trajectory to the bitter end, requires
the end of law: Is it though that goal [the progress of our age] will be attained when
at last we have been given laws? (296). He goes on to describe the newly established
Republic as an institution grounded upon and dependent on criminality, and its
victims, the Aristocrats, as honourable suicides (PB: 338). Murder, Sade reasons,
can no longer be regarded as a crime, asking rhetorically [i]s it not by murders that
France is free today? (PB: 332). Republican France, having made a complete break
with the laws of the ancien rgime, is taken to be addicted to ferocity and
dynamism. In keeping with Sades reductionist ontology, he argues that crimes are
necessary to politics as the political organism is essentially plant-like. The
Republic, he states, is essentially criminal; and crime is associated with vigour and
health, stating, [w]hat happens to the tree you transplant from a soil full of vigour to
a dry and sandy plain? All intellectual ideas are so greatly subordinate to Natures
physical aspect that the comparisons supplied us by agriculture will never deceive us
in morals (PB: 333).
Encore un effort is too problematic to be treated as a straightforwardly
revolutionary tract, or even a parody of one- its lattice of contradictions protect it from
instrumentalization to any particular doctrine. Literal philosophical analysis may
simply be inappropriate. Scrambling the jabbering of all available discourses, text is
deployed in the service of Nothing and No-One.
7.4 Anarchy
Given Sades endless tirades against everything that stands, it is understandable that
he has been read as an exponent of anarchy. Yet, as my discussion has, to some
extent, already shown, this is not the principled anarchy of theorists such as Ptr
Kropotkin. 44 As noted in Chapter V, Sades libertines are dependant upon power
structures as tools of domination, and they require a concentration of power, not its
dissipation. It is, therefore, particularly problematic to simultaneously praise Sades
libertin doctrine and (what is taken for) Sades call for radical overthrow of the very
political and economic structures that enable libertine activities. Where Sades
44
Jacques Broche, for example, considers Sade as endorsing an absolute freedom that calls for a
complete destruction of all sources of authority, stating that the employment of liberty involves the
complete abolition of all forms of power.Jacques Broche Sade ou le langage terroriste, La Petite
revue de philosophie 2, (spring 1981):25-36, p.34.
256
characters call for anarchy, it is necessary to identify what principles, if any, are
behind such calls.
The libertines hold that personal and general interest are incompatible. Dolmanc,
in Philosophy in the Bedroom, states:
...laws, being forged for universal application, are in perpetual conflict with personal
interest. Good for society, our laws are very bad for the individuals whereof it is
composed; for, if they one time protect the individual, they hinder, trouble, fetter him for
three quarters of his life; and so the wise man, the man full of contempt for them, will be
wary of them, as he is of reptiles and vipers which, although they wound or kill, are
nevertheless sometimes useful to medicine; he will safeguard himself against the laws as
he would against noxious beasts; he will shelter himself behind precautions, behind
mysteries, the which,[sic], for prudence, is easily done (Il sen mettra labri par des
precautions, par des mystres, toutes choses faciles la richesse et la prudence) (PB:
287-288; Vol. III:102-103; similar J:176).
So long as the laws are well formulated and simply prevent harm inflicted upon
others, they serve to regulate desires (as with the rules of the Sodality of the Friends
of Crime). As Clairwil of all people observes: it is the duty of every society to
eliminate from its midst such elements whose conduct may be prejudicial to the
community; and this justifies a quantity of laws which, when viewed alone from the
standpoint of the individuals self- interest, might appear monstrously unjust (J:
377). Dolmanc also appears to make a false dichotomy, insofar as he does not
recognize that the interests of a society is assembled of individuals (there is no such
false dichotomy, however, if he simply accepts the Bataille doctrine, and actually
believes that the ban on homicide is against his personal interest). Other discussions
in favour of anarchy in Sade tend to conflate the Bataillian and Benthamite doctrines.
From Encore un effort:
Cruelty is natural. All of us are born furnished with a dose of cruelty education later
modifies; but education does not belong to nature, and is as deforming to Natures sacred
effects as arboriculture is to trees. In your orchards compare the tree abandoned to
Natures ministry with the other your art cares for, and you will see which is the more
beautiful, you will discover from which you will pluck the superior fruit.
Cruelty is simply the energy in a man civilization has not yet altogether corrupted:
therefore it is a virtue, not a vice. Repeal your laws, do away with your constraints, your
chastisements, your habits, and cruelty will have dangerous effects no more, since it will
257
never manifest itself save when it meets with resistance, and then the collision will always
be between competing cruelties; it is in the civilized state cruelty is dangerous, because
the assaulted person nearly always lacks the force or the means to repel injury; but in the
state of uncivilization [dincivilisation ] , if crueltys target is strong, he will repulse
cruelty; and if the person attacked is weak, why, the case here is merely that of assault
upon one of those persons whom Natures law prescribes to yield to the strong-tis all
one, and why seek trouble where there is none? (PB: 253-254; Vol. III: 69; similar: J:
1120).
The first half of this paragraph is in keeping with the Bataille doctrine. Cruelty is
natural and sacred (note the inversion of Rousseau here), and is merely an
expression of mans innate energy, which has been corrupted by the influence of
civilization. The release of energy through cruelty is considered beneficial here,
although Sade does not explain how, and his fruit-tree metaphor is vague (in any case,
the metaphor is poorly chosen; pruned trees, as with all domesticated organisms, are
of course vastly superior sources of food to their wild varieties). In giving a
straightforwardly Utilitarian justification for anarchy, Sade switches back to
Benthamite mode. He argues that laws are undesirable, as they create a situation
where the cruelty of official power is dangerously powerful (similarly, Chigi argues:
Id rather be oppressed by my neighbour who I can oppress in my turn than to be
oppressed by the law before which I am helpless; J: 732). All justice would
therefore be vigilante justice (which is in fact criticized by Sade in the tale milie de
Tourville {1787}; MV: 203).
The view that civilization creates excessive cruelty (which is a category that
Sade, in Bataille mode, cannot recognize) contradicts the previous claim that
civilization (and its prohibitions of open cruelty) corrupts our natural cruelty. The
passage above also assumes some hydraulic theory of criminality; that is, cruelty is
said to only manifest itself when pressure is exerted by prohibition, which, again, does
not fit with Sades own psychology of pleasure (as discussed in Chapter III). Further,
as with any advocacy of anarchy, it is assumed here that a state of incivilization is
even possible. In any case, by the end of the passage, it is clear that Anarchy is not
really being advocated at all, but an intensification of power relationships, validated in
accordance with Natures Law of the Strong.
Similar passages in Juliette only continue this doctrinal conflict. Juliette argues
that universal anarchy will simply open wide the door to every sort of horror (J:
258
733). Chigi responds with the Benthamite principle: crime is...not a plague in the
world since, although rendering half the worlds population unhappy, it renders the
other half very unhappy indeed (J: 734; similar: PB: 313). Conceding that this might
not actually be the case, he insists that general anarchy will always be less dangerous
than a country ruled by the corrupt, even if without laws the world turns onto one
great volcano belching forth an uninterrupted spew of execrable crimes (J:733). The
only options on offer, it is assumed, are a deeply corrupt political order,
indistinguishable, in fact, from organized crime, or a world in flames. We have here a
fusion of utter despair, contempt for humanity, and the desire for destruction- not so
much a political principle as a wish to see the whole ant heap dowsed in kerosene.
Sades minimal claim- that pure anarchy is not as dangerous as corrupt, inept or
immoral government- cannot be dismissed out of hand, and the view that civilization
has actually made men crueller than hitherto has been considered by Hinckfuss,
Baumeister and others. 45 Yet pure anarchy is not, for Sades characters, either a
desirable state or a political possibility. Simply put, Sade is too pessimistic to
advocate anarchy.
For discussion, see Baumeister p.381. Ian Hinckfuss notes that the state of nature was quite
possibly preferable to modern civilization. He notes in particular The massacre of the moral Catholic
highlanders by the moral Protestants at Culloden and its aftermath, the genocide of the peaceful and
hospitable stone-age Tasmanians by people from moral Britain, the mutual slaughter of all those dutiful
men on the Somme and on the Russian front in World War I, the morally sanctioned slaughter in World
War II, especially in the area bombing of Hamburg, London, Coventry, Cologne, Dresden, Tokyo,
Hiroshima and Nagasaki, and the subsequent slaughter in Korea, Vietnam, Northern Ireland and the
Middle East all of this among people the great majority of whom wanted above all to be good and who
did not want to be bad. If life in a state of nature was less secure than this, things must have been very
exciting indeed for our stone-age ancestors. Hinckfuss p.29.
46
The definitive work on this topic- the relationship between Sades philosophy and its relationship to
totalitarianism is that by Svein- Eirik Fauskevg, Sade ou la tentation totalitaire : Etude sur
lanthropologie littraire dans La Nouvelle Justine et lHistoire de Juliette (Paris : Honor champion
diteur, 2001).
259
over the interests of the individual, but his characters frequently affirm the oppositethe tyranny of the minority over the many. Though despotism is occasionally
denounced in the libertine novels, these denunciations are highly ambiguous. 47 The
powerful libertines (Braschi, Catherine the Great, the King of Naples, Minister SaintFond) regard statecraft purely as a means of maintaining power for sake of personal
pleasure; every other libertine (in particular Juliette) is either a satellite of the more
powerful, or (like Minski) has complete control over a smaller, more tightly
controlled population, such as a prison or convent.
Sades despots dictate according to five distinct principles. The first, grounded
on Sades theory of pleasure, is simply that ones own happiness takes precedence
over the welfare of the subject population. States Saint- Fond: [a] contemptible fool,
that statesman who neglects the State finance his pleasures; and if the masses go
hungry, or if the nation goes naked, what do we care so long as our passions are
satisfied? Mine entail inordinate spending; if I thought gold flowed in their veins, Id
have every one of the people bled to death (J: 234).
The second principle holds that power itself is pleasurable. the more powerhence, the more pleasure, the better. For Sade, this means domination and
exploitation. 48 As Fauskevg notes, what this amounts to is little more than the
elevation of egoism to the level of political ideology; the elevation of individual
whims to the status of absolute ideals. 49 Intellect, power, and money are considered
47
Fauskevg p.128. Juliette gives a lengthy political and economic critique of Naples for the benefit of
its King, specifically noting the all-destroying poison of economic inequality, and the extravagance
of the people. Yet Juliette arrives at the Kings palace in a six-horse coach, the equivalent of a stretch
limousine. The discourse ends with an orgy, during which the King casually strangles a page (J: 924941).
48
This view was common amongst the philosophes. Rousseau feared that even he himself would
succumb to the pleasures of power, given the chance: I have a hundred times thought with terror that
if I had the misfortune today of filling a particular position in a certain country, tomorrow I would
almost inevitably be a tyrant, an extortionist, a destroyer of the people, and a source of harm to the
prince; due to my situation I would be an enemy of all humanity, of all equity, of every sort of value.
if I were rich [I would be] a disdainful spectator of the miseries of the rabble. (E: 344; see also 224,
SC: 30-33.). Helvtius held the same view. See Helvtius A Treatise on Man: Vol. II p.126. What is
remarkable is that both Helvtius and Rousseau proposed political systems that required technocrats or
law-givers that were not prone to such human failings.
49
260
50
51
Human society, wrote Rousseau, contemplated with a tranquil and disinterested eye [,] appears at
first to display only the violence of powerful men and the oppression of the weak (SC: 21).
52
261
many crimes threatening to be unleashed, how can you expect the energy of the governor
to be anything different? (J: 480). 53
The fourth principle is simply that of the Bataille principle- the attainment of
absolute mastery over the weak is in accordance to the laws of nature. The suffering
of the poor is described as being in accordance with a law of nature and useful to
the general plan, and that they were created to serve the rich (LNJ 1: p. 90; 2: 286,
389, 391). In accordance with this distinction between natural masters and natural
slaves, the subjects of political control are reduced to a faceless mass, or to the
categories of the natural sciences. 54 The libertines frequently describe their subjects as
polluting vermin, dangerous animals, common excrement or scum thrown up
by nature, fit only to be thrown to the lions comme on faisait des chrtiens,
autrefois, Rome (LNJ 2: 224, 368, 392-395).
The fifth principle is that terrible things must be done for the sake of the greater
good, or glory, of the State. This principle is only offered in discussing mass murder,
whether Catholics, peasants or the handicapped. Sades characters, for example,
suggest that feudal law is superior as it is the best for the grandeur and prosperity of
the state (again, lexemple de Rome), LNJ 1: 295; 2:225), and use the language of
medicine to justify bloodshed: [b]lmeriez-vous un homme surcharg dhumeurs qui
prendrait une mdicine, pour se rendre plus dispos et plus sain? Cest absolument la
mme chose. (LNJ 2:392; also J: 726).
Whilst not appearing to be a positive contribution to political thought as such,
Sades pencil-sketch of a political doctrine is interesting, nevertheless, and for the
same reason as to why his counter-ethics is interesting. It is an attempt to express the
doctrine of a resolutely despotic regime as honestly as possible, hence revealing its
key assumptions.
53
Note also the association of virtue with weakness, and crime with energy.
54
262
One does not establish a dictatorship in order to safeguard a revolution; one makes the
revolution in order to establish the dictatorship. The object of persecution is persecution.
The object of power is power.
I think and discourse like Hobbes and Montesquieu Juliette tells Ferdinand,
King of Naples (Ferdinand IV, 1751-1825) during one of her lectures. But she does
not discourse like Hobbes or Montesquieu. Rather, she and her libertine accomplices
are preoccupied with maintaining political power. Their understanding of politics, as
method and theory, is essentially a methodology of total control and domination of the
masses for their own ends. Juliette continues: it is not despotism I forbid you, I am
too familiar with its charms to deny it to you; I simply advise the suppression or the
rectification of whatever jeopardises or interferes with the maintenance of this
despotism, if it is upon the throne you choose to stay (J:934). Fauskevg, following
Hannah Arendt, notes that Sades work explores a number of methods typical of
totalitarian regimes, in particular the use of isolation, propaganda, terror, and secrecy.
56
neutralized or instrumentalized to ones own ends. Both options are suggested with
regards to organized religion. Clairwil sees the church entirely as a rival source of
authority, and advises Prince Ferdinand accordingly: atheize and incessantly
demoralize the people whom you wish to subjugate, so long as they cringe before no
god but you, so long as there are no morals except yours, you will always be their
sovereign (J :971). Zam, as noted above, and Madame Delbne are more moderate;
Delbne noting that the revolting dogmas of Christianity are indispensable to those
who have taken upon themselves the chore of infecting public opinion (J:48). On the
same grounds, the obliteration of the nuclear family and the collectivising of child
55
56
Orwell p.276.
Fauskevg pp.105-.109.
263
rearing, is recommended by Zam and the author of Yet Another Effort alike (PB:
322; AV: 317, 364). 57
Secondly, Sade recommends the maintenance of a false front. Power is always
associated with secrecy, which is in turn associated with isolation. 58 Absolute
remoteness from the common people is also recommended. As Saint-Fond says to
Juliette, do not forget that if the kings are beginning to lose their credit in Europe,
its the vulgarity theyve become attainted with that has been their downfall; had they
remained aloof and invisible like the sovereigns of Asia, the whole world would yet
tremble at the sound of their names (J:316). Propaganda is also recommended.
Errors are necessary to us, states Braschi (Pope Pius VI, who is, of course, both the
Pope and an atheist), adding that it does not follow that we must deceive ourselves
(J: 677). Braschi explains the principle of propaganda, the art of making pygmies
appear to be giants: The foremost preoccupation of man and of the statesmanis to
penetrate others without letting his own thoughts be known (J: 480, 759). 59
Philosophers, for the character Francavilla, are left with the authority only to
promulgate the interests of the government- that is- philosophers are to be employed
as propagandists (J: 969). 60 One of the most disorientating passages in Sade concerns
a proposal to incorporate the libertine text into the machinery of social control. SaintFond, in a monologue on despotism, proposes the dissemination of works that
promote loose morals in order to flush out dissenting voices, in exactly the same
manner as Mao Tse-Tungs Let a Thousand Flowers Bloom campaign. When the
weak are encouraged to break their bonds, the strong will find instruction therein
upon how to load further and heavier chains upon the captive masses (J: 319). In
keeping with the need to disseminate untruths, education is regarded as a threat to
power by the libertines of Juliette, or as a carefully managed tool of thought control,
57
For discussion see Fauskevg: 110. This proposal reflects the social engineering proposals of
On this point, Fauskevg notes Hannah Arendts observation that secrecy is the beginning of real
power. Hannah Arendt Le systme totalitaire, traduit de lamricain par Jean- Loup Bourget, Robert
Davreu et Patrick Lvi. (Paris : France Loisirs, 1989) p.181.Quoted in Fauskevg p.116.
59
60
La Mettrie gives the same proposal, writing: Use the force of specious arguments to prop up their
tottering faith, bring their weak genius, by the force of your own, down to the level of your own, down
to the level of their fathers religion and, like our sacred Josses [editors note- A character in Molires
Amour mdicin] lend the most revolting absurdities an appearance of plausibility. La Mettrie p.169.
264
as on Tamo (J: 321; AV: 361). Further, various economic measures are also
suggested in order to maintain control over the populace. On the one hand, Juliette
proposes the encouragement of enfeebling debauchery in order to keep the
populaces minds from considering political matters, on the grounds that human
beings cease to be observant when they are happy (J: 320, 934). 61 On the other,
Saint Fond recommends the perpetuation of grinding poverty and economic
inequality. Saint Fond explains: [t]he common herd will be kept in a state of
subservience, or prostate bondage, which will render them powerless even to strike
for, let alone attain to, domination, or to encroach upon or debase the prerogatives of
the rich. Tied to the glebe as in olden days, the people will be held like any other
property, and, like it, will be subject to all the various mutations of value and
ownership (J:321). Clairwil advises Ferdinand:
their slavery must be perpetual and grinding, and every possible means of escape
from it must be denied them, as will assuredly be the case when the figures who support
and surround the government are there to prevent the people from breaking loose from
irons which it is in the upper class interests to tighten day and night. You cannot
imagine how far such tyranny is able to extend (J: 970-971).
Finally, Sades characters recommends state terrorism and mass killing as a political
tool; of cementing the throne of the sovereign through bloodshed (LNJ 1:300).
Sades explanation never goes beyond stating that population control is necessary,
hence, the necessity of killing people en masse. 62 In The Misfortunes of Virtue the
character Monsieur Dubourg states, France has more citizens than it needs. The
government sees everything in broad terms and is not overly concerned with
61
Helvtius had made the same point, which is somewhat ironic, given that his own utopian proposals
involved rewarding loyal citizens with brothel passes. He writes of Venice: Who but an ignorant and
voluptuous people could support the yoke of an aristocratic despotism? This the government knows,
and encourages it subjects to debauchery: it offers them at once fetters and pleasures: they accept the
one for the other; and, in their base souls, the love of luxury always outweighs that of liberty. The
Venetian is nothing better than a swine, that is nourished by his master, for his use, and is kept in a
stable, where he is suffered to wallow in the mire. Helvtius Treatise on Man Vol. II p.74.
62
This goes against the advice Juliette gives Ferdinand, King of Naples: [w]hen they weary of you,
265
individuals provided that the machinery runs smoothly overall (MV: 15; similar: J:
577). 63 Clairwil advises Ferdinand:
.The government must regulate the population, must command all the means of
snuffing it out if it becomes troublesome, for increasing it if that is esteemed
advantageous; its justice must never be weighed elsewhere in the scales of the rulers
interests or passions, combined solely with the passions and interests of those who, as
we have just said, have obtained from him all the allotments of authority necessary to
multiply his own a hundredfold when they are conjugated. [Sades footnote: See, on
this subject, the speech of the Bishop of Grenoble in the fourth volume of La Nouvelle
Justine, pp.275ff].Glance at the governments of Africa and Asia: all of them are
organized in accordance with these principles, and all invariably maintain themselves
thereby (J: 970-971).
In La Nouvelle Justine the character Dubois, in a political tract of some ten pages,
proposes that the government introduce various measures to control population
growth. Infanticide and the immediate execution of surplus members of peasant
families is also recommended. States Dubois, il ft permis de tuer comme les boeufs
quon vend nos boucheries (one would be permitted to kill them as cows are sold
in our butcheries; LNJ 2: 388). Dubois also recommends the establishment of public
wheat storage facilities, established purely for the purposes of financially ruining
peasants, who are then to be executed as punishment for being beggars
(LNJ 2:394). 64
63
Zam also discusses politics in terms understanding the secret of the machine (AV: 309).
64
Given both the economic absurdity of slaughtering peasants, and the fact that this very plan was
feared in a widespread Revolution- period conspiracy theory, Sade is probably in satire mode here.
All the same, Stalins creation of the Ukrainian famine of 1932-1933, intended to force peasants into
collectivisation, was no more reasonable.
266
institutions (organized religion, law, medicine) from their purported ideological, legal
or moral purposes, and incorporate them- with some alteration- into the will to
control. This pattern, in the case of Tamo, has been outlined already at the macrolevel. I will now turn to the patterns in Sades work that concern the domination of the
body and mind of the individual.
As discussed in Chapter III, the ultimate desire of the libertines is to have power
over the subject. Political power is simply the means of increasing the scope of this
power. The Sadeian structure is also a preoccupation with the intensification of this
power. This intensification involves a transposition of the ordering and disciplinary
mechanisms of the school, the convent, the barracks, the prison and the hospital to the
Sadeian space. The structures, symbols and rituals of the institutionalized space
reappear, divorced from any notion of legal or moral authority, transformed into the
pure signs of power. (Alternatively, Sades sites of coercion are schools, hospitals and
prisons; J: 982; LNJ1:170-172). This process is a direct consequence of the cynicism
of the libertines, their rejection of all traditional notions of justice or ethics, and the
instrumentalization of all institutions (the Church, for example) to their own ends.
Sades image of the libertines- dressed as executioners- torturing and murdering with
the aid of barbaric machines, is exactly as a state execution would appear to someone
who has completely rejected, or is incapable of understanding, the stated principles of
such an act.
The Architecture and equipment of the Sadeian space is one of the most
characteristic features of Sades work; every detail concerns either the maintenance or
the enjoyment of total control. Tamo, as noted, is isolated; all citizens know their
place, and all is arranged so that all are visible to the master. The libertines commit
their atrocities within an enclosed space which is essentially based on the same
principles, turned inwards. The most developed, and the prototype of such spaces in
Sade, is the Chteau of Silling, the setting of The 120 Days of Sodom. Silling is
situated on the summit of a mountain almost as high as the Saint-Bernard, in the
most treacherous sector of the Black Forest in south-west Germany (120:236). As the
Four Friends approach their destination, they destroy all the bridges behind them, and
arrive on November 1st, when it would be impossible to escape through the ice and
snow. As with all such locations in Sade, Silling is an impregnable fortress, with a
deep moat and thirty feet walls, with chambers and dungeons that extend far beyond
ground level. Another characteristic is the absolute secrecy of the place: ...to what
267
degree might not the villain be reassured who brought his victim here! What he had to
fear? He was out of France, in a safe province, in the depths of an uninhabitable
forest.... [in a redoubt which] only the birds of the air could approach (120:240). 65 In
order to forestall escape or external attack (which, notes the narrator, was a little
dreaded), all the gateways are walled up: there was no longer any trace left of where
the exits had been (120:240-241). The architecture of the Sadeian site is that of a
prison. In fact, the upper floors of Silling are converted into a prison at the end of the
narrative (120:671).
The interior is more thoroughly planned still, and, like the exterior, establishes a
pattern that recurs throughout Sades work. Like Tamo, the interior of Silling is
functionally identical to Benthams Panopticon. 66 The central chamber has a circular
or semi-circular form, as in an amphitheatre. It has niches in which the victims (the
subjects, as Sade refers to them) are on display, and an ottoman, in black upholstery,
in the centre in an elevated position (LNJ 2:201). The room is typically lined with
mirrors, often covering the walls and ceiling, is very well lit (Sade frequently gives
the exact number of candles used), and is linked to further niches, torture machines,
trap-door pulleys, laboratories, and dungeons (120: 237-238; LNJ1: 306; 2:376; J:195,
659, 975). Note that the subject (Sades term) must be able to see the symbols of
power lest they consider insubordination.
On either side of the central throne an isolated column rose to the ceiling; these two
columns were designed to support the subject in whom some misconduct might merit
correction. All the instruments necessary to meting it out hung from hooks attached to
65
Note the inconsistency with the Sadeian principle, discussed in Chapter V, according to which one
must become a criminal as the world is utterly corrupt and lawless. The precautions taken by the
libertines assume that people are in general just, and that they will intervene in concert if they view
actions as being morally wrong.
66
Allen W. Weiss has noted the functional similarity of Sades preoccupation with mirrors and the
Panopticon of Bentham. See Allan W. Weiss Structures of exchange, acts of transgression in David
B. Allison, Mark S. Roberts, Allen S. Weiss, eds. Sade and the Narrative of Transgression
(Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1995):199-212; p.204. For discussion of Sades
preoccupation with visibility and control, see Giraud La ville du bout du monde. Other examples of
panoptic systems in Sade: LNJ 2:306, 376, 120: 237-238.
268
the columns, and this imposing sight served to maintain the subordination so
indispensable to parties of this nature... (my italics; 120:237).
Variations on this theme emphasize the need for visibility and ease of control of the
subject. From the short story Eugnie de Franval:
Eugnie, on a pedestal, represented a young savage exhausted from the chase, leaning
against the trunk of a palm tree, the branches of which concealed an infinite number of
lights arranged in such a way that they illuminated [her] charms...this animated statue was
surrounded with a canal, six feet wide and filled with water which acted as a barrier to the
young savage... [a]t the edge of this encircling moat was placed Valmonts armchair, to
which was attached a silken cord. By operating this thread he could turn the pedestal in
such a way that he could see the object of his adoration from many sides... (GT: 56).
In the 120 Days of Sodom, as in Juliette, elaborate systems of pulleys and cables are
employed to control the subjects.
Each child in each quatrain shall have one end of a chain of artificial flowers secured to
his arm, the other end of the chain leading to the niche, so that when the niches
proprietor wishes any given child in his quatrain, he has but to tug the garland, and the
child shall come running and fling himself at the masters feet (120:245; similar: J: 588,
589).
The Sadeian space, then, is essentially a machine for controlling people, and reducing
them to objects.
67
moving the body of the coerced subject, en masse, as part of a larger unit. 68 In more
elaborate arrangements, the body of the subject disappears entirely, becoming a
component in a greater system of parts designed with a specific instrumental goal. In a
passage in Juliette, men are placed into a conveyor belt system for providing sexual
pleasure: a mechanism ensured that once those pricks had discharged, they
disappeared in a trice and were replaced by new ones the next instant (J: 973). From
another orgy scene: At the four sides of the room were that many raised platforms,
67
For discussion of this reading, see Philippe Roger Sade: La Philosophie dans le pressoir p.61.
68
For discission on this pattern, see Foucault DP: 158,164. On the relationship between the theatre and
power in Sade, see Pierre Frantz Sade: texte, Thtralit, in Camus and Roger, eds. Sade crire la
crise: 193-215, p.210.
269
upon each of which a couple of Negroes lashed a girl of sixteen or seventeen who,
once torn to shreds, would vanish through a trap door, to be replaced the same instant
by a fresh one (J:1112). Torture and death machinery incorporating rotating drums
and knives, pulleys, and trapdoors, all of which are put into action with the touch of
a lever, are frequently described in Sades work (J: 334, 338, 1010, 120: 665-669,
724, 784). The culmination of Sades list of tortures is the hell passion, which
involves the immolation of victims in a manner reminiscent of a meatworks.
before launching her [the torture victim], he slips a ribbon around her neck, thereby to
signal which torture, according to his best belief, will be most suitable for that particular
patient, which torture will prove most voluptuous to inflict upon her, and his acuity and
judgment in these matters, his tact and discrimination are truly wonderful (120:667).
Once the machines are running and the torturers are at work a villain spends fifteen
minutes contemplating each operationhe falls into a comfortable armchair whence
he can observe the entire spectacle (120: 669).
Already mentioned is the libertines preoccupation with formulating rules and
regulations for their own conduct. They are also preoccupied with formulating such
regulations for their victims, the most developed version being the Statutes (referred
to also as the protocols) of the Chteau of Silling in The 120 Days of Sodom
(120:238, 241-249). Two related attitudes are expressed concerning such rules. On the
one hand, there is the view that to be compelled to follow rules at all is associated
with weakness, of being dominated (Dorothe, in La Nouvelle Justine, states that laws
are a trap for the easily controlled, adding that il ny a de lois dans lunivers que les
vtres; LNJ 2: 196). On the other, a paradox already discussed in Chapter V, is that
the libertines impose rather obsessive rules upon themselves; even when outside a
particular disciplinary space. 69
The libertines frequently wish to make their victims think that they are being
punished, rather than being merely tortured, occasionally going to the length of
having a trial (J: 742). When Justine finds herself imprisoned in a remote convent
school, she is frequently beaten and raped, but before these beatings she is made to
69
The Statutes of Silling give details of strict monetary penalties for harming the cooks. Juliette gives a
particularly anal account of her daily routine, in which each hour is accounted for and assigned a
particular function (J: 409; 120: 241-249).
270
read aloud the particular rule that she is said to have broken (LNJ 1: 316-324; 34;
2:80-82). The following passage, from Juliette, illustrates the language and rituals of
discipline and punishment in the context of sadistic pleasure. The libertine approaches
the victims with his escort, conducts an inspection, and exposes culprits to be
punished.
The president gave orders that during his inspection nobody be admitted into the premises
apart from ourselves, who made up his escort; and he commenced his tour forthwith. Such
a man, with such prepossessions, was able, as you can imagine, to uncover a prodigious
number of culprits; he was accompanied on his rounds by a quartet of executioners, two
flayers, six flagellators to the lash he condemned thirty aged between five and ten,
twenty-eight between ten and fifteen, sixty-five between eighteen and twenty-one; three
children in the six-to-ten age group were condemned to be flayed alive (J: 517).
Two other features of the Sadeian disciplinary system- documentation and the
markings worn by the subject- are noteworthy. Administrative or official
documentation appears frequently in Sades work, in particular lists of people to be
killed, death warrants and lettres de cachet (J:216, 237,324,). 70 Juliettes links with
wealth and legal protection- the matrix of power relations upon which she, a minor
libertine power, depends, are maintained, in part, through the sheaf of letters of
recommendation she presents to every new acquaintance, as if visiting the local
prefecture (J: 981,994). Official documentation, Sade emphasises, is also an
instrument of administrative killing. I have but to put my signature to that
[document], notes a judge in Juliette; and a very attractive person dies tomorrow.
She is in prison at the moment; [her familys] only grievance is that she prefers
women to men (J: 237; similar: 213). When the character Belmor presents his plan to
kill every Catholic in France, he notes that most important logistic issue is the
identification of the target population, and the necessary paperwork: separating the
sheep from the goats would not take long. Compiling my lists should require no more
than a years work in shadow silence... (J: 501).
70
The lettre de cachet was a warrant by the French king for imprisonment or death. Originally the
privilege of the aristocracy, by the 18th century they were requested by middle and lower classes for the
institutionalisation of deranged or profligate family members. Sade himself was imprisoned through the
lettre de cachet system by his mother in law. For discussion, see Shaeffer p.168.
271
71
Notes Goulemot, this was a practice typical of Medieval and Classical societies to control heretics,
Jews and plague victims. In Diderots Supplement to the Voyage to Bougainville, also, sterile women
wear grey (AV: 325n 370).
72
Jean Leduc notes that Nero- a character frequently referred to by Sade, would dress in a tiger skin.
Jean Leduc Les Sources de lathisme p.45. According to the police records, Sade would terrorize his
victims in a manner reminiscent of official torturers. For example, he made a point of displaying before
a victim, Rose Keller, a range of torture implements, forcing her to select the whip with which she was
to be beaten. For discussion, see Lever p.119.
73
74
...he brands each [girl victim] upon the shoulder, imprinting a number on the flesh; it is to indicate
the order in which he [the torturer] will receive them (120: 666). In Justine the protagonist is also
branded (MV: 61-62). The tattooing of a victim with the text of their sentence is similar to the
tattooing- machine described in Kafkas short story In the Penal Colony (1919). Coward notes that
thieves and prostitutes were still frequently being branded in Sades time, and that convicts carried the
letters TF (travaux forces) until the ending of the practice in 1832 (MV: fn 265). Also J: 619; 120:610.
272
FINAL ASSESSMENT
Massacred prior to the 1st of March,
In the course of the orgies......................10
Massacred after the 1st of March............20
Survived and came back........................16
Total...............46 (120:673).
273
such a space, and on German, or French, soil. 75 Were anyone to survive such a place
as Silling (recall that only atheists, and those who are forced to participate in the
destruction of others, survive to the end of the book) they are unlikely to have the
same trust in the innate goodness of the world and its inhabitants ever again.
75
This is perhaps as the Terror could have looked to Sade himself. Yet 120 was written in 1785, before
Some passages in Sade appear to be a simple satire of the medical profession. A short story, The
Mystified Magistrate, contains an explicit satire on medical theory; a man posing as a doctor terrifies a
patient with aphorisms culled from Hippocrates and commentaries from Galen, and convinces him
that he is insane (MM: 13). A number of the tortures in The 120 Days of Sodom and La Nouvelle
Justine, in particular the bleeding of victims and the application of highly toxic enemas, are similar to
the medical procedures of the period (LNJ. 2:132; 120:613, 614,615).
77
Lacan Kant with Sade p.72. Also, see PB: 241, 243, 260.
274
measure, quantify and classify is also a desire to eliminate all the flaws in the
pattern. 78 In The 120 Days of Sodom, all such elements (Catholic piety, having
slightly imperfect teeth, being insufficiently subordinate) that are deemed
unacceptable or aberrant are destroyed in the person of the victim. The libertines
examine their child victims for blemishes: This done, the child was led away, and
beside her name inscribed upon a ballot, the examiners wrote passed or failed and
signed their names... one, as lovely as a day, was weeded out because one of her teeth
grew a shade higher from the gum than the rest.. Those that fail the test are thrown
out into the snow to die from exposure; those that pass are raped and tortured to
death later (120:225-231).
This pattern of systematic extermination of the aberrant occurs throughout
Sades work. The libertines advocate the killing of children, orphans (described as
vegetative parasites), the infirm and the unfortunate, the torching of public
schools, poorhouses and hospitals (LNJ 1:33; J: 604, 710, 726-729; PB: 335-336).
Sades characters differ from their real, 18th century counterparts in being all the more
thorough. Foucault notes the 1780 proposal to burn down the Bictre asylum
buildings to control a putrid fever; Sades characters plan to torch every hospital
and poor-house in Rome in order to eliminate the poor and sick themselves (J: 726;
Foucault MC: 204). Pinel notes that Catholicism causes insanity; Sades character
Belmor plans on solving the problem for all time by having every practitioner of the
irrational creed eliminated (J: 501; Foucault MC: 255). Both Philosophy in the
Bedroom and Juliette contain passages justifying such massacres in the name of the
greater good, and in the medical rhetoric of a necessary amputation. From Yet
Another Effort: Do you not prune the tree when it has too many branches? And do
not too many shoots weaken the trunk? (PB: 336-337). From Juliette: What does the
horticulturalist do when he espies that branch? He cuts it off, without qualms. The
statesman must proceed likewise: one of the basic laws of nature is that nothing
superfluous subsist in the world. my desire is that they be totally eliminated,
extirpated; exterminated, killed... killed as one kills a breed of noxious animals (J:
726; similar: 2:207, 209). This pattern is what sociologist Zygmunt Bauman takes to
be a key feature of Modernity; the mentality of the Gardeners who treat society as a
virgin plot of land to be expertly designed and then cultivated and doctored to keep to
78
Orwell p.267.
275
the designed form. 79 In the same way, the interests of the individual disappear in
discussion on the merits of medical experimentation. In Juliette, a character reports
on the practice of her doctor friends, summarizing the general attitude of the doctors
in Sades world.
Almost all of them use no other means of testing out a remedy, and its surely nothing to
them [vraiment un vide pour eux]; I am reminded, she added, of what young Iberti, my
personal doctor, said to me only the other day upon arriving at my bedside fresh from one
of those experiments. What concern to the State is the existence of the vile beings that
ordinarily crowd those dens? he said in response to the look of disapproval I assumed in
order to find out how he would justify himself; you would be doing society an enormous
disservice by not permitting us medical artists to test our talents upon societys
dishonoring dregs. These have their use; Nature, in making them weak and defenseless,
indicates what is to be... (J: 727; Vol. III: 833). 80
Further, Sade describes a medical gaze that tortures and murders in the name of
the abstract ideals of health. In Justine, Monsieur Rodin, a callous and brutal
surgeon, has imprisoned a twelve year old girl for medical experiments, and argues
for the utilitarian rationale for such a venture (MV: 57,59 ,104). The science and
technology of the human body is wrested from the purpose and principles of medical
practice. The patient disappears entirely; medicine is transformed into an inquiry
into the human machine, or into the most complex and painful way of killing
someone. Here, the pleasures of sadism and the pleasure of revealing truth
intersect. 81 In The 120 Days of Sodom, Sade gives a vast list of surgically or
scientifically informed tortures. One involves asphyxiation in a pneumatic machine;
another involves giving injections of a venereal distemper (120: 603-611, 629, 652659 MV: 57, 59). Still other experiments involve starvation (in order to study the
effects of famine), live organ transplantation, or removal, including the brain;
involuntary sex change surgery, and procedures which are specified as tortures (her
nerves were laid bare...the nerves are tied to a short stick... (120: 649, 653, 658, 652).
79
Zygmunt Bauman Modernity and the Holocaust (Ithaca, New York: Cornell University Press, 2000)
p.113.
80
In a corresponding footnote, Sade states that Iberti was a real figure, a friend, in fact, and that this
276
The operations are invariably agonizing and fatal (...he knows just enough about
surgery to botch all four operations; 120:655). In Juliette ( notably, predating
Shelleys Frankenstein by two decades), a victim is tortured and killed, then struck
with an artificial thunderbolt; in the same novel, a man raises his children dumb, like
animals, in order to study their psychological development (J : 741, 1176). In
similar fashion, chemistry is discussed only in discussing ways of killing thousands of
people: [a] treacherous bugger regularly deploys a drug which, sprinkled on the
ground, very wonderfully kills whosoever walks thereupon; he sprinkles it about
rather frequently, and over wide areas (120:637; similar: LNJ 2:207, 209; J:540,
1150).
Here I return to the discussion of Foucaults interpretation of Sade, as discussed
at the end of Chapter I. Sades work, according to the early Foucault, is a document
of the revolt against this rigorous reordering; Sade himself being the very voice of
that unnameable madness deemed unfit for the Age of Reason. I suggest that this
understanding of Sade is in fact upside-down. Sades description of the disciplined,
obedient subject, his colonizing of the disciplinary mechanism of the prison or the
hospital, the rituals of power and the accumulation of documentation, suggest that his
work is the ultimate discursive artifact of Foucaults Age of Control, of infinite
examination and compulsory objectification and inhuman vigour (DP: 189; MC:
234). Sade confirms the negative, Foucaultian view of society, as described in
Discipline and Punish, and particularly the view that this society is consistent with the
Enlightenment values and theories. In depicting every possible method of domination
and coercion, and the way in which institutional systems can be incorporated into a
universal and intensive mechanism of control, Sade appears to be Foucaults
precursor. 82 It was perhaps an awareness of this link that led to Foucaults
characterization of Sade as the exact flip- side of scientific discourse, writing, in The
Order of Things, that Les 120 Journes is the velvety, marvelous obverse of the
Leons danatomie compare [of Georges Cuvier {1769-1832}] (OT: 278). 83 Sade
had intimate and direct knowledge of the Prison, the Asylum, the Barracks, the
82
Fink does not make this association, but her appraisal of Sade is in very Foucaultian terms. Political
Systemp.512.
83
Concerning such Sadeian themes as the pleasure of institutional control, the creation of the obedient
subject, the importance of document accumulation, the rituals of power, See also DP: 40, 128-129,
181-182,189, 264. (HS I: 45, 48, 71-73).
277
School, and the Hospital, institutions which, for Foucault, represented the emergence
of new techniques of administration, so such a relationship between Sade and those
institutions that he was subjected to (institutions make the man, as Montesquieu said)
is only natural. 84
The most obvious similarity between Sades work and the account of the
hospital of the 18th Century is the incredible cruelty involved. Foucault notes that
there was a specific doctrine of using fear as a psychiatric technique (MC: 180, 245),
and many of the pronouncements given by psychiatrists that Foucault cites have a
distinctly Sadeian ring to them. There is, for example, the account of one Dr.
Sauvages, who advises that the physician must become a philosopher in the sense
identical to that of Sade- that is, one must purge all natural human feelings of
sympathy in favour of a particular notion of the good (MC: 183). There is Franois
Leuret, who advised other physicians of the mad as follows: [a] single string still
vibrates in [the patient], that of pain, have courage to pluck it (MC: 182). 85 The
details of the terrifying methods employed reinforce the association; for example the
spinning machine used by Joseph Mason Cox (1763-1818) to spin melancholia out
of the mad (eventually used simply as a punishment or threat), or the methods of
Hermann Boerhaave (1668-1738), who claimed to have cured convulsives in 1777 by
burning the patient to the bone with red-hot pincers. 86 Sades characters also use the
exact same methods to cure the mad that Foucault describes. In Madness and
Civilization, Foucault describes the curing of a man of the delusion that he is a king,
and another who believes himself to be God, through, essentially, the humiliation of
confronting banal reality. 87 Similarly, the character Vespoli (in Juliette) degrades
84
In his formative years, Sade was educated by Jesuits, well known for their discipline (and sexual
abuse of students). As a young man, Sade served with distinction as a captain in the cavalry, and during
the Revolution he served as an inspector of hospitals and as a judge. In the latter role, Sade found
himself representing the very institution responsible for the mass execution of fellow aristocrats.
Finally, of course, Sade spent twenty - seven years in prisons, and spent his final years in the Charenton
lunatic asylum. In a letter to his wife written in July 1783, Sade insinuates that he was sodomized by
his Jesuit teachers (120:132; LP: 313). Shaeffer makes the association of Sades treatment by the
Jesuits and the conduct of the libertines of his novels (Schaeffer p.23).
85
Franois Leuret, Fragments psychologiques sur la folie (Paris, 1834) pp. 308-321. Quoted in
Foucault MC :182.
86
87
278
humiliates, then murders, a man who believes himself to be God, another who thinks
that he is Jesus, and a woman who believes herself to be the Virgin Mary (J:982,
984).
Most interesting is the underlying theory of the psychiatrists, which was,
according to Foucault, that of the Materialists- the very same theorists that Sade draws
from. La Mettrie, dHolbach and Helvtius appear in both Madness and Civilization
and Discipline and Punish as the theoretical overlords of the Great Confinement and
the new technologies of control. 88 Just as La Mettrie, dHolbach and Helvtius
reduce man to a machine that can be manipulated according to elementary theories of
causation, Sades libertines, as torturers, crush their victims by reducing them to their
physical, earthly presence (DP: 106,128,136,138). The actual attempt to understand
the mind of the insane man, the criminal, the innocent victim or the people, to
attempt to see the world from the perspective of the subject, is not permitted. 89 As
Foucault notes, the medical authority figure knew madness only in that he had power
over it, just as the libertine knows the subject only in having the power to manipulate
(MC: 272). In the words of Sade, we hear a grotesque parody of the vulgarity of
positivism: il avait mieux le foutre que le comprendre. 90 This is, as Foucault puts
it, the merciless language of non-madness of those who confine their neighbours in
an act of sovereign reason (MC: ix).
In Chapter I, I outlined the discussion as to whether Sade can be associated with
Nazism. Those who have noted the similarity emphasize the role played by
organization and political power in Sade. Camus characterization of Sades work as
extolling of totalitarian societies in the name of unbridled freedom- the freedom of
the few- is essentially correct (R: 42). Adorno and Horkheimers association of Sade
with Nazism is based on similar observations- the advocacy of power, in both Sade
and Nazism, as its own justification; the association, or reduction, of scientific
thinking to the impulse, with ruthless efficiency, to destroy; the development of
organization without any substantial goal beyond the acquisition and exercise of
power; the transformation of political and economic power into a tool of the
88
89
Marcel Hnaff makes this point: The victim, irremediably mute, is only the guinea pig in an
uvres compltes (Paris : Editions Ttes de Feuilles, 1973) vol.13, p.280-281.Quoted in Mengue
p.103.
279
privileged elite, and the emergence of absolute political cynicism: the statement that
dictatorship is bad is rationally valid only for those who are not its beneficiaries, and
there is no theoretical obstacle to the transformation of this statement into its
opposite. 91 Such traits in Sade are acknowledged by Foucault, who grants that his
eroticism is proper to a disciplinary society: a regulated, anatomical, hierarchical
society whose time is carefully distributed, its places partitioned, characterized by
obedience and surveillance (SS: 226). One trait missing from these accounts of
Sades work however, is the pattern of systematic destruction of aberrant
individuals. This is precisely the trait Foucault attributes to the Nazis, and not to Sade.
Foucault describes the Holocaust as a petite- bourgeois dream of cleanliness- a
campaign to eliminate undesirable, aberrant elements, adding: [m]illions of people
were murdered there, so I dont say it to diminish the blame for those responsible for
it, but precisely to disabuse those who want to superimpose erotic values on it
(SS:226). Hence- Nazism and Sade cannot be confused, as Sade is erotic. Bataille
makes the disjunction of Sade from Nazism in a similar way, describing the
unchaining of the passions that raged at Buchenwald or Auschwitz as an
unchaining that was the government of Reason (my italics), and not of the passions
(EPS:253-254; also 244; similar: AS Vol. III:253). Le Brun takes Sade to be
concerned with the stripping away of ideologies, and returning to the authenticity of
bodies; Norbert Sclippa holds that Sades characters cannot be proto-Nazis as they
are not concerned with interfering with politics. 92
In reply, I note that Le Brun, Foucault (with the exception of the Sergeant of Sex
interview, where he adopts a different interpretation), Sclippa and Bataille are
working from a one- sided account of Sade that omits its meticulous ordering of
disciplinary relations, the descriptions of massive, politically enabled destruction of
human lives, and above all the doctrinal continuity of authoritarian rule and that of the
libertines. That which Adorno, Horkheimer and Camus emphasize in their reading of
91
92
Norbert Sclippa writes: I do not think personally that Adorno, Horkheimer or Camus have shown
that a link exists between Sade and Nazism. Sades materialism, as any other faith, proposes a
hopeful message of life, which extends to all men. And like any faith, it can be abused... a total
rejection of established laws and institutions [as in Sade] would be the opposite of Nazism, their
Epitome. Sclippa also adds that the Society of the Friends of Crime have in their rules NOT to
disturb the existing political order. Personal correspondence via e-mail, August 4th 2002.
280
Sade, and that which has been discussed in this chapter, is almost completely
unaccounted for in the work of Bataille and Le Brun. This is a serious error of
omission, and only out of a questionable taste for paradox could the similarity
between Sades dungeon and the practice of the Nazis be denied outright.
In similar fashion, girls are tortured if they fail to interpret a piece of music correctly
through their movements, forced to ice-skate an impossibly difficult obstacle course
whilst fireworks are thrown at them, or to dance barefoot on broken glass (J: 613,
626, 1182; 120:613, 640). What remains to be accounted for are the forms of torture
which are associated with control and coercion. Sades characters are not merely
concerned with the thrill of killing or the pleasure of inflicting physical or
psychological pain. They want the more staid pleasure of total submission: ... tous
les sujets que vous voyez ici ne sy runissent que pour obir vos ordres: la
soumission la plus compltes la prvalence la plus entire... (LNJ 2 : 196). This is
attained through three principal means: silence, terror, and degradation.
To silence the victim is to remove from them the most elemental freedom- the
capacity to communicate, whether to complain or to cry from help. In order to reduce
the victim to silence, they are tortured if they attempt to communicate with one
another, or even for the expression of feelings (120:248). Submission is also enforced
by more direct means, such as the removal or mutilation of the tongue or mouth, or
blinding the victim (J: 908, 1183, 620; 120: 620, 649).
281
Every means is used to terrorize the victim into submission. The mutilated
corpses of previous victims, or (as noted above) the tools of torture are placed on
display (J: 1059, 120:606). The least evidence given of lack of respect or lack of
submission is punished with instant death (120:248). Victims are also informed that
they have no hope of escape, as in the following passage from The 120 days:
Give a thought to your circumstances, think what you are, what we are, and may these
reflections cause you to quakeyou are beyond the borders of France [in the Black Forest
region in Germany] in the depths of an uninhabitable forest, high amongst naked
mountains; the paths that brought you here were destroyed behind you as you advanced
along them...insofar as the world is concerned, you are already dead... (120:250-251).
Various means are employed to humiliate and degrade the victims, both physically
and morally. They are forced to desecrate or defecate on religious ritual objects, and
are executed for the performance of any religious act; in The 120 Days, such
desecrations are intensified during Christian holidays (120: 248, 581, 589). Victims
are typically stripped naked, or given thin, inadequate clothing which is easily
removed, making it impossible to escape. Again, from The 120 Days: ...the little
boys and the little girls ...shall always be differently and splendidly costumed, ...but
all these costumes shall be of taffeta or of lawn; at no time shall the lower half of the
body be discomfited by any raiment, and the removal of a pin shall suffice to bare it
completely (120:245; similar: MV: 111).
Already discussed in Chapter III is the Libertines preoccupation with eating
excrement. What remains to be explained is the preoccupation with forcing others to
eat excrement, to prevent others from washing, or forcing them from defecating
anywhere but in a chapel, and then only according to a strict regime. Just as Sades
libertines demonstrate their own mastery over nausea through coprophagy, they
torture their victims through forcing them to violate that those deep seated instinctual
revulsions that they have silenced in themselves. In Yet another effort, being smeared
in filth in public places is the recommended punishment for the blessed charlatans
of the church (PB: 306). In other texts, victims are regularly forced to soil their own
clothes or to be prevented from relieving themselves, to eat excrement or defecate in
the full view of others, to be covered in excrement, or have excrement forced into
282
every orifice (LNJ 2 : 82, 210, 269, 290, 311, 383 ; 120 : 372, 373, 579, 621; J:906,
907, 916). From the Statutes of Silling:
...it is strictly forbidden to relieve oneself anywhere save in the chapel, which has been
outfitted and intended for this purpose, and forbidden to go there without individual and
special permission, the which shall often be refused, and for good reason, the months
presiding officer shall scrupulously examine, immediately after breakfast, all the girls
water closets, and in the case of a contravention discovered in the above-designated place
or in the other, the delinquent shall be condemned to suffer the penalty of death (120:242)
Excremental assault, a term used by Emil Fackenheim and Terence des Pres, defines
the methods used in Nazi death camps to abolish the prisoners sense of self worth
and psychologically break the victim. 94 Writes Fackenheim: excremental assault
was designed to produce in the victim a self-disgust to the point of wanting death or
even committing suicide. And this-nothing less- was the essential goal. The Nazi logic
of destruction was aimed, ultimately, at the victims self-destruction. 95
93
Micheline Maurel has this to say of this particular torture: [i]magine what it would be like to be
forbidden to go to the toilet; imagine also that you were suffering from an increasingly severe
dysentery, caused and aggravated by a diet of cabbage soup as well as by the constant cold. Naturally,
you would try to go anyway. Sometimes you might succeed. But your absences would be noticed and
you would be beaten, knocked down and trampled on. By now, you would know what the risks were,
but urgency would oblige you to repeat the attempt, cost what it may...I soon learned to deal with the
dysentery by tying strings around the lower end of my drawers. Micheline Maurel An Ordinary Camp
trans. Margaret S. Summers (New York: Simon and Schuster, 1958) pp.38ff. Quoted in Emil L.
Fackenheim To Mend the World: Foundations of Future Jewish Thought (New York: Schocken Books,
1982) p. 209.
94
Excremental Assault is Chapter 3 of Terence des Pres, The Survivor (New York: Oxford
University Press, 1976). Cited in p.208. Primo Levi uses the term excremental coercion. Primo Levi
The Drowned and the Saved translated by Raymond Rosenthal (London: Abacus, 1988) p.90. On this
topic, see also Danuta Czech The Auschwitz Prisoner Administration in Yisrael Gutman, Michael
Berenbaum, eds. Anatomy: 363-378, p.375.
95
Fackenheim p. 209.
283
This is also the goal of Sades libertines- to subjugate their victims to the point
that they willingly participate in their own destruction. Besides simply watching their
loved ones murdered in front of them, victims are frequently coerced into killing each
other. 96 This is the goal of their absolute submission (states Borchamps, about to
execute an unwitting victim: remember....its step by step to lead them gradually to
death: J: 917). Either the victims prefer that those close to them to die quickly rather
than slowly and painfully at the hands of the libertines, or they are only allowed to
live if they participate in the destruction of others. Mothers are forced to stab sons,
and lovers are forced to stab each other (J: 920, 120:663). Libertines force their
victims to kill and eat one another through starvation, to eat their own body parts, or
to cut off their own limbs in order to obtain food (120: 621, 647, 653, 656, 663) As
Juliette says of Saint-Fond: The great art of Saint-Fond consisted in always placing
his victims in such a situation that of two evils they had inevitably to elect the one
which more nicely suited his perfidious libertinage (J:363; also 922; 120: 650, 670).
This principal is basic to the administrative structure of Silling: ...Messieurs decide
to dispatch the rest of the subjects one by one. Messieurs devise new arrangements...
[they] agree to give a green ribbon to everyone whom they propose to take back with
them to France; the green favour is bestowed, however, upon condition the recipient is
willing to lend a hand with the destruction of the other victims(120:670). 97 This
deep coercion serves three functions: it is pleasurable for the sadists to witness the
moral destruction of the victims; it reduces the work that has to be done to physically
kill them, and it imposes upon any survivors the role of collaborator. 98 The objective
of such degradation is not simply to enjoy the pleasure of control. It is to reduce the
victim to the status of an animal. The Duc tells his victims:
96
scenes involving mothers watching the murder of their infants, or forced abortions, are especially
common (J: 988-990, 1010, 1122; 120: 619, 661, 664-665, 638, 639). In another, a man is forced to eat
his mistress (120:653).
97
Similarly, in the Misfortunes of Virtue, monks have survivors of an orgy-massacre swear not to go
In one scene in Juliette, an army captain orders two groups of ten soldiers to massacre each other,
perhaps a comment on the ease with which institutional control can be used to kill (J:922).
284
...consider that it is not at all as human beings we behold you, but exclusively as animals
one feeds in return for their services, and which one withers with blows when they refuse
to be put to use (120:252).
99
Primo Levi The Drowned and the Saved (London: Abacus, 2000) p.90. See also Danuta Czech The
Auschwitz Prisoner Administration in Gutman, Berenbaum, eds. Anatomy 363-378, p.370; Leo
285
7.10 Conclusion
go undress the four destined for holocaust and whose brows are wreathed in the foliage
of deaths tree, go strip them, and of their raiments, whereof there is no further need,
make the employment I have prescribed to you. The emissaries step forward; the four
victims are despoiled of every article of clothing, which is flung piece by piece into the
roaring blaze
Sade appears to be the first writer to associate the term holocaust with mass murder. In his age, the
word was applied to fires of great destructiveness- although his usage follows the original sense. Two
further examples: Laurette, leur mre, et mme de Verneuil devaient contenir les holocaustes (LNJ
2:216) atop the holocaust, bound hand and foot, the old crone was burned alive: (J: 747).
286
sheer logistical necessity (one exception to this rule a libertine activity which does
not require resources and planning is arson).
Work in this, and previous chapters, goes some way towards overcoming the
purely metaphorical nature of the association of Sade and Nazism, and in undermining
some of the reasons offered as to why the association is groundless. In Chapter VI,
the doctrine of Natural Aristocracy, an explicit (albeit problematic) doctrine of
master race and slave race, was discussed. In this chapter, it was noted that
rigorously systematized and reasoned killing are dominant trends in Sades thought.
What is missing, from both those who note the Sade-Nazi association and those who
reject it, is a commentary on the specifics of Nazi doctrine.
To conclude, there are a number of similarities between the descriptions of both
the doctrine and the exercise of power in Sade and that of the Nazis. There is the
doctrine of innate supremacy, of natural masters and natural slaves; the validation
of the right of the strong to capture and subjugate others; the systematic
extermination of religious or economic groups, or those unfit to live, or of the very
fabric of Judaeo-Christian morality; the nostalgia for the glories of Europes preChristian past- its (to recall Rousseau) first innocence. In terms of practice, in Sade
we see the rituals of control and humiliation, the use of surveillance, secrecy, terror,
propaganda and indoctrination; the mechanized killing, the medical experiments, the
branding, marking and tattooing of victims, even the rhetoric- the suggestion of
turning victims into soap, the rhetorical reduction of the target population to
vermin. 101 The differences between, say, the thought of Saint-Fond or Chigi, and that
of Hitler, Stalin or Marat, are minor, offering similar rationales (the greater good,
101
Only one Sade scholar- Schaeffer- has made explicit the association of the disciplinary system in
Sades 120 Days with that of the Nazi death camps (Schaeffer p.345). For discussion on starvationinducement experiments, see Berenbaum ed. p.270. For discussion of the use of Jewish sex slaves in
the camps, and Himmlers personal involvement of the punishment of Jewish women, see Czech
p.376, Wistrich Hitler and the Holocaust p.240.For discussion of the immediate killing of sick
prisoners in the Auschwitz camp, see Irena Strzelecka Hospitals In Gutman and Berenbaum, eds.
Anatomy: 379-392, p.389. For discussion of the experiments of Josef Mengele, see Helena Kubica The
Crimes of Josef Mengele in Gutman and Berenbaum, eds. Anatomy: 317-337, pp.321, 324, 324;
Robert Jay Lifton The Nazi Doctors: Medical Killing and the Psychology of Genocide (New York:
Basic Books, 2000). For discussion of forced abortions and murder of babies, the impossibly
contradictory rules, the destruction and desecration of religious ritual objects, and the coerced
destruction in the camps, see Fackenheim pp.213, 216. p.207, 218-219.
287
the health of the State) for the extermination of millions who fail to fit the
ideological model. One key difference is that, besides Zam, there is no personality
cult or Fhrerprinzip. Le Brun holds that fascism dresses up human savagery with an
ideological dress- the exact opposite of the honesty of Sade. In reply, I note that
Sades characters themselves discuss the importance of propaganda to hide their true
motives. It is not even clear whether, like Orwells OBrien, the libertines are simply
more lucid than most dictators concerning the nihilism that drives them. 102 The entire
libertine doctrine of natural aristocracy, in fact, could itself be an ideological
masking of human savagery, a view that Sades characters indeed occasionally ponder
([o]ne arranges ones schemes according to ones tastes and whims; J:401, also
p.555). The association of Sade and Nazism, to be brought to a close, would require
an analysis of the specifics of Nazi ideology. Although this topic goes beyond the
scope of this project, an attached appendix to this project addresses some key
similarities.
Whether Sade predicted any specific modern atrocity is a question concerning the
supernatural rather than philosophy. The correct question is- in driving the rhetoric,
the ideology, the philosophy, and the bureaucratized terror of his age to their
furthermost limits, did Sade see the direction in which the Occident, morally, was
headed? The reply seems to be- yes, he did. The question to follow is: what might this
mean for ideology and philosophy, and the culture of the Occident? ( Concerning
Sade scholarship and Sade- interpretation, an entirely different question is - why have
no Sade scholars noted the similarity between Sade and Nazism, and have rejected the
association without addressing the primary reasons offered for this association {the
emphasis, in Sade, on structure and organization in killing}? Hitherto, it has been left
almost entirely to non-experts philosophers, writers, film makers and biographersSchaeffer, Camus, Adorno and Horkheimer, Pasolini- to make the association at all).
What can we say, then, about the political relevance of Sade? As I claimed in
Chapter I, to associate Sades thought with that of the Nazis and other such
movements is to emphasise, rather than deny, his significance as a thinker, and on
Sades terms. On several occasions, Sade informs the reader that he had the power of
102
OBrien states: [w]e are different from all the oligarchies of the past, in that we know what we are
doing. All the others, even those who resembled ourselves, were cowards and hypocrites. The German
Nazis and the Russian Communists came very close...but they never had the courage to recognize their
own motives. Orwell p.275.
288
prophecy; in both Aline et Valcour and Juliette he tells the reader that he had
predicted the revolution itself. 103 In his Reflections on the Novel (1800), Sade states
that the craft of the novelist is to depict the possibilities of human existence (120:106).
Such a project requires, by extension, an investigation into the possibilities of political
reality as well (writes Fink, Sade opts to experiment with extremes, a laboratory
method resorted to by scientists in order to intensify and clarify the causes and effects
of their research). 104 If Sade had indeed anticipated the Shoah and other modern
Holocausts, or, more generally, a malignancy at the heart of Civilization, it would
appear that his project had been a success. Beyond the visions of Blake, the systems
of Hegel or even the frenzy of Nietzsche, Sade saw in the chaos and the anxious
meditations of his age another world, another Enlightenment, and another Revolution.
103
The frontispiece of Aline et Valcour reads crit la Bastille un an avant la Rvolution de France
(AV: 3). The same claim is made in a footnote in Juliette (J: 66).
104
289
290
Conclusion
The question that initiated this essay remains unanswered. That is, is Sade a
philosopher, or not? This study tends towards the view that Sade indeed is a
philosopher of sorts, whilst accepting that aspects of the less literal readings (that of
Foucault, principally) have their merits. As I hope to have shown, the most
interesting, and relevant, aspects of Sades work are only visible through the optic of
philosophy. Further, Sades texts resemble philosophical works, in particular the
populist philosophical tracts and pamphlets of his time. Sade clarifies the senses of the
terms used, uses footnotes, and italicizes words for emphasis. His characters argue,
cite Machiavelli, ridicule Rousseau, propose thought experiments and shoot each
others theories down. More crucially, Sades work functions as does all good
philosophical writing. Sade forces the reader to meditate on central, personal
questions of morality, such as the why be moral question, to a degree that is quite
possibly unsurpassed. Sade forces the reader, in asking oneself why one continues to
read at all, to confront their own most basic moral assumptions. What began as a hunt
for Jabberwocky ends as a glimpse at the world through the monsters eyes. No matter
how brief or unconvincing this vision may be, the experience is bruising. Sade will
not necessarily send the reader out into the street with an axe; nor will he necessarily
send the reader to Yeshiva or a monastery. Yet Sade cannot be taken lightly. If
philosophy begins in wonder, in Sade it ends in a shipwreck on a dark, boiling sea, far
from civilization. To read Sade, and to take him seriously, is to risk intellectual death
by misadventure.
Sade is not a typical philosophical writer, to be sure, and his intentions are far
from clear, but the same could be said of other, less obscure thinkers ( it is not clear
whether Mandeville wrote The Fable of the Bees in jest, for example). There is a
multidimensional and open- ended aspect of Sades thought that is captured by
Foucaults account, for whom Sade represents the enfolding and inversion of all other
291
discourses. Yet this interpretation does not do justice to Sade, insofar as it reduces his
work to an amateurish collage. Sade attacks moral ideas with a high degree of
sophistication that is seldom acknowledged. For this reason- and not for the endless
descriptions of rape and murder, Sade is a deeply subversive, and frightening, thinker.
The range and depth of Sades thought is considerable. From the beginning of the
study, it is clear that Sades philosophy possesses the traits of any complete
philosophical system, beginning with his rigorously scientific and rationalistic
ontology. On materialistic and rationalistic grounds, Sade classifies humans as a type
of animal, rejects the existence of souls, or free will, and so on. As such, Sade is
shown to be a student of the radical thought of his age, rather than a radical outsider.
In Chapter III, Sades doctrine as it pertains to psychology was discussed. Here,
his account of the psychology of sadism is found to be sophisticated and insightful,
and throws into doubt, rather than confirms, the association of sexuality with an
instinct for destruction. Rather, Sade associates the will to cruelty with the desire for
the sensation of power and control. Power, its pleasures, its distribution and its
techniques, appears to be the central theme in Sades thought. This chapter also tracks
Sades inversion, or continuation, of conventional theories concerning pleasure and
aesthetics.
Chapter IV further undermines traditional accounts of Sade as liberator and
eroticist, and the notion that Sade is primarily concerned with the sexual act itself, as
implied by Bataille. Instead, Sade is shown to be a forceful critic of Rousseaus
discussion of the role of women, and of the institution of marriage. Sades treatment
of the notion of homosexuality and perversion also places him far ahead of his
contemporaries. Sades misogyny, however, counts against a straightforwardly
positive reading.
In Chapter V, Sade is shown to be an imaginative and insightful moral thinker. He
relentlessly probes ethical systems for weaknesses, and explores their counterintuitive
implications. Sade exposes serious, and now widely acknowledged, flaws in
Utilitarian thought, and explicitly rejects attempts to reduce ethics to a rational,
mutually beneficial behavioural stratagem. Further, Sades applied a-moral
philosophy sheds light on the cooperative strategies of criminal society, and the
limits of the self harm argument.
In Chapter VI, Sades critique of Judaeo- Christian morality, and his inversion of
the teleology of Rousseau, were discussed. Sade cannot be said to merely destroy pre292
existing values, doctrines and philosophies, however. Sade also seeks to supplant
them with an entirely new Weltanschauung, one which affirms death and destruction
as necessary aspects of the order of things.
Whereas VI concerns the theoretical justification of absolute power, Chapter VII
concerns the way in which power is managed, at both the level of the state and at the
level of the institution. Through formulating a doctrine of absolute despotism, Sade
does us the service of identifying its salient features.
We need not agree with Sades verdict of the world, his pessimism, or his
assessment of human nature, to see the worth of his work. It takes, as Adorno and
Horkheimer realized, a disturbing thinker to shed any light at all on the horrors of our
age, a world that is frequently both frightening and obscene. Hegel wrote that
philosophy is the world as it is brought to consciousness, and that art is an unfolding
of truth. If this is so, and if the truth of the world is frightening, then Sade is both
artist and philosopher.
293
294
APPENDIX:
Sade and Nazism
I suggest that philosophy, if it is bad philosophy, may be dangerous, and therefore
deserves that degree of negative respect which we accord to lightning and tigers.
A.1 Introduction
This appendix supplements the discussion concerning the alleged connection between
Nazism and the thought of Sade. The doctrine of Nazism requires an entire, quite
different, study in itself; here I merely note what the ideological commonalities are.
The implication of this association is a serious one. Adorno, Horkheimer and
Crocker in particular take Sade to represent Enlightenment that is, Western thoughtat its logical terminus. Therefore, to make the association of Sade with Hitler is to
reveal the roots of Hitlerian ideology in the very heart of Western intellectual culture.
It should also be explained that it is an association that is at question- that is, whether
Sades thought anticipates the Nazis either their specific acts, or their doctrine.
Defenders of Sade, either implicitly or explicitly, approach the question as if they are
countering the accusation that Sade was actually responsible for Nazism. 2 Whether or
not this is a deliberate straw man, this approach is to misconstrue the issue. Such a
question is a case for historians of ideas (and an easy one at that) and does not
concern the inquiry into the economy of ideas and their implications.
As noted in the previous chapter, the association between Sade and Nazism is
not decisively established. Of those thinkers who have proposed the association, none
has made the distinction between drawing a specifically doctrinal comparison, or
between the acts committed by the Nazis and those depicted by Sade. Sade, for
1
Bertrand Russell Philosophy and Politics (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1947) p.7.
Sawhney writes that [t]he issue of whether or not Sade was responsible for Nazism and the death
camps is one which continues to generate controversy to the present day... Deepak Narang Sawhney
Unmasking Sade in Sawhney ed. Must We Burn Sade? : 15-30, pp.20-21.
295
Therefore, the imperative to kill every Jew is a feature of Hitlers thought of which
the Adorno & Horkheimer account cannot account for. This is because they do not
account for the unconventional war that Hitler was (or, rather, believed himself to be)
fighting, as I will explain below.
Because of this gap between interpretation and actual Nazi policy, the
association of Sade and Nazism made is at risk of appearing little more than
metaphoric (Nazism is sadistic; Sades thought is somewhat similar to that of an
inner- circle Nazi). A direct comparison of Nazi thought and that of Sade, however,
shows that there is in fact a deeper resemblance. Despite the range of ideologies,
racial myths, pseudo- sciences and so on that were grouped under the aegis of
Nazism, Nazi ideology was primarily Hitlers ideology. Further, that of his inner
circle (in particular Himmler) is largely continuous with that of Hitler, in particular on
the subject of race. As Goering put it, [i]n the last analysis, it is the Fhrer who
decides. 5 (It may be more accurate to speak of Hitlerism here, rather than Nazism,
when discussing particular doctrines).
One particularly weak treatment of this topic- and the only extant article dealing exclusively with it-
is Colette C. Peter Maurrassisme, Sadisme et Nazisme, Esprit 411 (1972):184-192. The author goes
no further than noting that Sade and Nazism embody violence. There is no discussion of the specific
content of either Sades works or those of the Nazis.
4
For discussion see Kershaw Hitler 1936-1945: Nemesis p.492; Wistrich Hitler and the Holocaust
p.2.also Daniel Jonah Goldhagen Hitlers Willing Executioners (London: Abacus, 1996) p.296.
5
Gerald Fleming Hitler und die Endlsung (Munich, 1982) p.64. Quoted in Wistrich Hitler and the
Holocaust p.77; see also p. 228. By all accounts, Nazi ideology was Hitlers ideology. Hitler was
296
Hitlers thought is clearly expressed in Mein Kampf (1924) and in his recorded
private conversations, in particular those recorded in the Table Talk (1941-1944;
hereafter MK and TT). These texts show clearly that Sade had clearly anticipated a
central possibly the only - guiding ideology of Nazism. 6
Many are reluctant to acknowledge that Hitler was a human being at all, much
less one that could think. This approach is understandable at an emotional level, but is
an error of strategic judgement, as well as, in elevating Hitler to supernatural status,
paying him unwarranted respect. I take to be a less extreme version of the same view
the reluctance among philosophers (though not historians) to accept the suggestion
that Adolf Hitler, or any other prominent Nazis, had what could be called a
philosophical outlook (or in any case an outlook that is related to philosophical
doctrines), or, had they one, that it was historically relevant. Kai Nielsen, for example,
has argued that Hitlers anti-Christian and anti-Jewish thought is historically
irrelevant. He writes that the association of Nazism with anti-religious intellectual
currents in Germany attributes far too much causal power to the beliefs of a few
intellectuals. 7 Similarly, Richard Rorty states that [t]he rulers of Nazi
Germany...were greedy selfish thugs, not people guided by a mistaken philosophical
outlook. 8
Nielsens comment presupposes that ideas are the sole domain of intellectuals;
that the rulers themselves were ideologues, (what is more, repeating popular
ideologies), is not considered. Rortys comment assumes a dichotomy between people
who are greedy selfish thugs, on the one hand, and people capable of sustaining a
dismissive of Nazi intellectuals, in particular the official Nazi philosopher, Alfred Rosenberg
(Hitlers Table Talk p.422).
6
Adolf Hitler Hitlers Table Talk 1941-1944 His Private Conversations introduced by Hugh Trevor-
Kai Nielsen Ethics without God (New York: Prometheus Books, 1989) p.13.
Richard Rorty and Chronis Polychroniou, On Philosophy and Politics, The Cold War, and the Left,
New Politics 8, no. 3 (summer 2001): 128-39, p.130. I thank Sterling Lynch for pointing this article out
to me. For a discussion of the interplay of Nazi ideology and dominant intellectual currents in Germany
(in particular the rejection of Christianity and humanistic values, and the celebration of power as its
own justification), see Hans Kohn The Mind of Germany: the Education of a Nation (New York:
Harper &Row, 1960).
297
This is not to deny that there is a link between conspiracy theories and traditional anti-Semitism and
Nazism. There is a direct link between The Protocols of the Learned Elders of Zion the anti-Semitic
tract that appeared in Russia in the 1910s and was later circulated as evidence of a global Zionist
conspiracy, and the political cynicism of Sades age. The Protocols was compiled by Sergei Nilus in
1911 for the Czars secret police, and was purported to be the mission statement of a secret cabal of
Jews who wish to take over the world through promoting, among other things, atheism, communism
and (!) Nietzsche. It is partly made up of text taken directly from Maurice Jolys 1864 satire on the
reign of Napoleon III, Dialogue aux Enfers entre Machiavel et Montesquieu (Dialogue in Hell
Between Machiavelli and Montesquieu). Both texts describe the type of conspiracy theory- a shadowy
Masonic or Jesuit conspiracy- that originated during the French Revolution. Most intriguingly, the
Protocols express exactly the type of absolute moral and political cynicism that Hitler embodied. The
Dialogue aux Enfers is available as a zipped file from Project Gutenberg at
www.gutenberg.org/etext/13187 (accessed November 2004). See also The Protocols of the Elders of
Zion trans. Victor E. Marsden (Florrisant, MO: Liberty Bell Publications, 2004); Benjamin W. Segel,
Richard S. Levy A Lie and a Libel: The History of the Protocols of the Elders of Zion (Lincoln:
University of Nebraska Press, 1995).
298
A.2 Weltanschauungskrieg.
Pope and Rabbi shall be no more
We want to be Pagans once again
No more creeping to churches
We are the joyous Hitler Youth
We do not need any Christian virtues
Our leader, Adolf Hitler, is our saviour.
Here I will outline Hitlers thought concerning Christianity, Judaism (or, rather, the
Jews), and Communism. 11 The purpose of this discussion is to point out the
ideological commonalities between Hitlers views on Judaeo-Christian morality and
that of Sade, as outlined in Chapter VI. Recall the dominant ideas in Sades thought
concerning Christianity; a). that its morality originated with the Jews, in particular
Jesus, dismissed as one of Titus slaves, and their historical experience as a
slavish people; b). that Christian morality originated as a psychological subterfuge
to defeat the Romans; c). that the acceptance of this doctrine, and the belief in the
sanctity of human life, led to the fall of Rome; and finally, d). that Christianity has
caused humanity to forget the truth that there is an essential, morally relevant
distinction between natural masters and natural slaves. Hitlers thought follows
this pattern.
As noted above, neither the task of murdering the Jews nor the war on Russia
made any sense in terms of conventional war. They did make sense in terms of
10
World: the Problem of Anti-Semitism, ed. Isacque Graeber and Stuart Henderson Britt (New York:
Macmillan, 1942) p.8; Quoted in Dennis Prager and Joseph Telushkin Why the Jews? (New York:
Touchstone/ Simon & Schuster, 1983) p.160.
11
In neither the Table Talk nor Mein Kampf does Hitler discuss the specifics of Jewish religious belief.
299
Hitlers ideologically driven goal. Hitler considered Communism and World Jewry
as essentially the same entity (Communism being the political instrument of the
Jews), and took its destruction as his primary task. Hitler referred to these campaigns
collectively as the Weltanschauungskrieg, a War of Worldviews. 12 Underpinning
this campaign, ultimately, is Hitlers doctrine of the Natural Aristocracy of Nature. In
short: the doctrinal commonality that Hitler shares with Sade is the very factor that
characterizes Nazi ideology.
Hitlers doctrine assumes the following: a). the principle of equality is false, as
b). there are large, and ethically relevant, differences amongst people. In particular, c).
there is a natural distinction between natural masters and natural slaves. The Jews
were accused of pioneering and promoting this doctrine in three ways- in instigating
Christianity, in promoting Marxism, and in advocating the doctrine of equality of
racial groups. To train Hottentots and Zulu Kaffirs in intellectual professions,
insists Hitler, is exactly like training a poodle: it is criminal lunacy to keep on
drilling a born half-ape until people think they have made a lawyer out of him
(MK:391). Hitler adds: the Jew shrewdly draws form [educating people of African
heritage] a new proof for the soundness of his theory about the equality of men that he
is trying to funnel into the minds of the nations (MK: 391). The Jewish doctrine of
equality is, Hitler writes, a violation of what he calls the natural principle in Nature:
[t]he Jewish doctrine of Marxism rejects the aristocratic principle in Nature and
replaces the eternal privilege of power and strength by the mass of numbers and their
dead weight (MK: 60). Further, Hitler holds that the Jews introduced Christianity
specifically in order to cause the ruin of stronger races through its unnatural morality.
From the Table Talk:
The Jew who fraudulently introduced Christianity into the ancient world-in order to ruin
it- re-opened the same breach in modern times, this time taking as his pretext the social
questionIt is Jewry that always destroys this [natural] order. It constantly provokes the
weak against the strong, bestiality against intelligence, quantity against quality. It took
12
On 30th March 1941, Hitler informed his military commanders that the war with the Soviet Union
would be a struggle between two opposing world outlooks [Kampf zweier Weltanschauungen
gegeneinander]. F. Halder, Kriegstagbuch, 1939-1942 (Stuttgart, 1962-4), vol. 2, pp.336-7; Lucy
Dawidowicz The War Against the Jews, 1933-45 (London/ New York, 1983), p.157. Quoted in
Wistrich Hitler and the Holocaust pp.103-104.
300
fourteen centuries for Christianity to reach the peak of savagery and stupidity. We would
therefore be wrong to sin by excess of confidence and proclaim our definite victory over
Bolshevism...[a] people that is rid of its Jews returns spontaneously to the natural order
(17 February 1942 ;TT:314).
Finally, Hitler holds that the fall of Rome was due to the corrupting influence of
Christian morality. 13 On the 21st of October 1941, as part of a talk comparing
Jewish Christianity with Jewish Bolshevism, Hitler compared the fall of Rome
with latter- day Bolshevism, the product, Hitler, believed, of Jewish influence. 14 The
following statement, made several months later, continues in the same vein:
But for the coming of Christianity, who knows how the history of Europe would have
developed? Rome would have conquered all Europe, and the onrush of the Huns would
have been broken on the legions. It was Christianity that brought about the fall of Romenot the Germans or the Huns One day ceremonies of thanksgiving will be sung to
Fascism and National Socialism for having preserved Europe from a repetition of the
triumph of the Underworld (27th January 1942; TT: 253).
Hitler expresses his hope for the future of the Nazi movement in terms virtually
identical to those used by Sades Belmor, who says of his planned Christian Genocide
that it will ensure Frances health and happiness forever (J:501). Note, in particular,
Hitlers discussion of genocidal ideological engineering in the name of tolerance.
Our epoch will certainly see the end of the disease of Christianity. It will last another
hundred years, two hundred years perhaps. My regret will have been that I couldnt, like
whoever the prophet was, behold the promised land from afar. We are entering into a
conception of the world that will be a sunny era, an era of tolerance What is important
above all is that we should prevent a greater lie from replacing the lie that is disappearing.
The world of Judaeo-Bolshevism must collapse (27th February 1942, TT: 343-344).
13
The theory is historically questionable. For discussion, see Henry Chadwick Envoi: On Taking
Leave of Antiquity in John Boardman, Jasper Griffin, Oswyn Murray, eds, The Oxford History of the
Classical World (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1986) 807-828, p.826.
14
Aufzeichnungen Hienrich Heims (Hamburg, 1980) p.99; Aufzeichnungen des persnlichen Referenten
Rosenbergs Dr. Koeppen ber Hitlers Tischgesprche 1941, Bundesarchiv R6/34a, Fols. 1-82 (Notes
of Dr Werner Koeppen, liaison of Alfred Rosenberg at FHQ, on Hitlers table talk, 1941) pp.60-61.
Cited in Kershaw Hitler 1936-1945 p.488.
301
Hitlers ideology, as shown in these passages, is similar to that outlined in Sade, down
to the same appeal to the natural order (and is analogous to the Bataille doctrine).
The one doctrinal difference is Hitlers appeal to providence or the Will of God,
although, of course, little seems to be left of any recognizably Judaeo- Christian
principle in Hitlers monotheism. 15 Hitler even uses the same racist clichs as does
Sade (referring, for example, to Africans as Hottentots, or comparing them to
monkeys; J: 323). Another commonality between the two doctrines is the attitude
towards the sanctity of human life. Robert S. Wistrich writes that Hitler consistently
regarded the ethics of Biblical monotheism as the curse of mankind, especially the
fifth commandment-Thou shalt not kill. 16 Again like Sades characters, Hitler held
conscience to be a creation of the pernicious influence of the Jews. Writes Jonathan
Glover, [t]he effort to break free from the constraints of conscience was one of the
central aspects of the Nazis own revaluation of values. They believed in crossing the
moral or emotional barriers against cruelty and atrocity. 17 Nazism emphasized the
ethics of hardness towards others, characterized humanitarian ethics as a poison,
piety a disease, and considered compassion as weakness, cowardice and selfdeception. 18
The details concerning the Final Solution concerning the Jews hardly requires
repetition. What is not so well known is that Hitlers attitude, and that of other
prominent Nazis (in particular Goebbels) towards Christianity was of a piece with this
same struggle. Christianity, for Hitler, was a continuation of the very worst aspects
of the intolerance of the Jews (Recall Sade: [a] careful examination of [Christianity]
will reveal...that the impieties with which it is filled come...from the Jews
15
This was a part of publicly stated Nazi doctrine; the belt buckles issued to German soldiers bore the
Wistrich Hitler and the Holocaust p.245. Ian Kershaw also states that the ideological objective of
eradicating Jewish-Bolshevism was central, not peripheral, to what had been deliberately designed as
a war of annihilation Kershaw, Hitler 1936-1945 p.461; also pp.488-489.
17
18
For discussion see Chapter 37, The Nazi Moral Identity, in Glover, Humanity pp.355-359; Robert
S. Wistrich The Cross and the Swastika in Jacob Golomb and Robert S. Wistrich, eds, Nietzsche,
Godfather of Fascism? (Princeton and Oxford: Princeton University Press, 2002) p.163; Kershaw
Hitler 1939-1945 pp.39-41.
302
ferocity...PB: 299). In Mein Kampf, Hitler has this to say of the intolerance of
Christianity:
Christianity could not content itself with building up its own altar; it was absolutely
forced to undertake the destruction of the heathen altars...intolerance is, in fact, its
absolute presupposition... such phenomena in world history arise for the most part from
specifically Jewish modes of thought, in fact, ...this type of intolerance and fanaticism
positively embodies the Jewish nature...with the appearance of Christianity the first
spiritual terror entered into the far freer ancient world...
Hitler concludes this line of reasoning with what appear to be a call for the end of
Christianity- through coercion and terror.
...since [the emergence of Christianity] the world has been afflicted and dominated by this
coercion, and that coercion is broken only by coercion, and terror only by terror. Only
then can a new state of affairs be constructively created (MK: 413).
Writes Ian Kershaw, [t]he assault on the practices and institutions of the Christian
churches was deeply embedded in the psyche of National Socialism. 19 Besides the
philosophical views concerning the nature of Christianity, Hitler viewed it as an
ideological rival, speaking ominously both of a showdown with the Church once the
war was over, and the necessity of purging it lest its influence lead to revolt against
the regime. 20 One well known case of the Nazi regimes executing Christians for
their beliefs was the guillotining, in 1943, of every member of the White Rose group
(their only action being the circulation of pamphlets that noted the incompatibility of
Nazi policy and Christian morality). 21 Official action against Christianity was
otherwise minimal, owing to the political risks entailed. In 1937, Hitler informed his
19
20
Elke Frhliche, editor Die Tagebcher von Joseph Goebbels. Teil II, Diktate 1941-1945, Munich
etc., 1993-1998 II/4, 177 (26 April 1942). Quoted in Kershaw Hitler Vol. II p. 509. See also Vol. II
pp.235, 516; Hitlers Table Talk pp. 409,607, 626. Karl Dietrich Bracher The German Dictatorship:
The Origins, Structure and Consequences of National Socialism trans. Jean Steinberg (London:
Penguin, 1970) pp.475, 478, 483.
21
Kershaw Hitler 1936-1945 pp.552, 663. I thank Selma Kradraoui for bringing the White Rose to my
attention.
303
inner circle that a Church Struggle would have to wait until the end of hostilities,
although individual followers tended to take matters into their own hands. 22 Notably,
elite units, the SS and the Nazi party pressured their members to leave both their
religious denominations and congregations. 23
23
I call Hitlers anti-Semitic writings intellectual anti-Semitism, as they have a closer resemblance to
philosophical writings on the Jews than to traditional Christian anti-Semitism (traditional antiSemitism being hostility towards Jews based on traditional, pre-Enlightenment notions of the Jews as
304
dHolbachs doctrine one step forward- in proposing the genocide of Catholicismstands as the most extreme expression of this doctrine. Similarly, the originator of the
term anti-Semitism, Wilhelm Marr (1819-1904), denounced Christianity as a
disease of the human consciousness, which he took to be a manifestation of
Judaism. 25 Eugen Dhring (1833- 1921), a political economist and philosopher,
argued that Christianity was itself Semitic, and, again in terms similar to those of
dHolbach and Sade, held that all monotheistic religions preach hatred of life. 26
Similar thoughts gained ground in England. In 1920, Winston S. Churchill, in a
newspaper article entitled Zion versus Bolshevism, wrote that the Jews were
conspiring to overthrow civilization with an impossible equality- essentially the
same doctrine promulgated by Hitler himself. 27
Despite all of these later thinkers on the Jewish Question, however, Robert S.
Wistrich notes that many of Hitlers comments on the Jews and Christians hark back
to the thinkers of Sades era. Writes Wistrich: ...Hitlers diatribes against the
barbarism, credulity, ignorance and poverty of spirit encouraged by the Christian
Churches also contain crude echoes of eighteenth-century rationalists like Gibbon and
being usurious, vampiristic, Christ-killers, and so on). Hitler, of course, was happy to encourage such
traditional expressions of anti-Semitism, but does not appear to have been a traditional anti-Semite,
especially given his negativity towards Christianity.
Other intellectual streams of anti-Semitism hold that the Jews are too superstitious to become
Enlightened (Fichte, Kant), or too materialistic (Houston Stewart Chamberlain, T. S. Eliot). Hitlers
Mein Kampf and Table Talk do not adhere to either of these views, although in Mein Kampf he repeats
the old Enlightenment canard that the Jews had bequeathed to the Christian church its intolerance and
fanaticism. Although Chamberlains The Foundations of the Nineteenth Century is widely regarded as
a central source of Nazi anti-Semitic theory, Chamberlain hardly refers to Judaeo-Christian morality,
much less criticize it. His attack on Judaism largely repeats the traditional Christian accusations that,
again, the Jews are materialistic, and that they have no idea of divine grace and redemption by faith,
and argues that Jesus was not a Jew. See Houston Stewart Chamberlain, The Foundations of the
Nineteenth Century (London: John Lane, the Bodley Head, 1910).
25
Antecedents, History, Reflections: Selected Papers ed. Yisrael Gutman and Livia Rothkirchen (New
York: Ktav Pub. House, 1976) p.94. Cited in Prager and Telushkin p.160.!
26
27
Winston S. Churchill, Zion versus Bolshevism: A Struggle for the Soul of the Jewish People,
305
Voltaire. 28 Hitlers admiration for Frederick the Great, King of Germany (17121786) also suggests an admiration for, if not actual influence, of 18th century thought.
Fredrick was close to, and frequently assisted, the French philosophes, in particular
Voltaire, dAlembert, and La Mettrie, and professed atheism to those close to him.
Hitler made a point of comparing himself with Frederick II specifically because
Frederick was both a great leader and a great theoretician.29 In particular, Hitler cited
the correspondence between Frederick and Voltaire as a favourite text, and admired
Frederickss policy concerning race policy and the control of Jewish internal
migration (TT: 84, 476).
28
29
306
Bibliography
Works by Sade.
Sade, Marquis de. Aline et Valcour ou le Roman philosophique. ed. Jean M.
Goulemot. Paris : le livre de poche, 1994.
LAigle, Mademoiselle, lettres publies pour la
premire fois sur les manuscrits autographes. Gilbert Lely, ed. Paris: Les Editions
Georges Artigues, 1949.
.Correspondance indite du Marquis de Sade de ses proches, et de ses
familiers. ed. Paul Bourdin. Paris : Librairie de France, 1929.
.The Crimes of Love. trans. Margaret Crosland. London: Peter Owen,
1996.
. The Gothic tales of the Marquis de Sade trans. Margaret Crosland
London: Picador, 1990.
. Histoire de Sainville et de Lonore. Paris: Collection10:18, 1963.
. Justine, Philosophy in the Bedroom and Other Writing. trans.
Richard Seaver. New York: Arcade Publishing, 2000.
. Letters from Prison. trans. Richard Seaver. New York: Arcade
Publishing, 1999.
. The Misfortunes of Virtue and other early tales. trans. David Coward
Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1999.
The Mystified Magistrate and other writings trans. Richard Seaver.
New York: Arcade Publishing, 2000.
. La Nouvelle Justine (2 vols). Paris : Collection 10 :18, 1978.
. Opuscules et Lettres politiques. Paris : Collection 10 :18, 1979.
. uvres compltes (15 vols). dition mise en place par Annie le Brun
et Jean-Jacques Pauvert. Pauvert: Paris, 1986-1991.
. uvres compltes (15 Vols). Paris: Cercle du Livres Prcieux, 1964.
. Aline et Valcour ou le Roman philosophique. ed. Jean M. Goulemot
Paris : le livre de poche, 1994.
. uvres (3 vols.) ed. Michel Delon, Jean Deprun. Paris:
Bibliothque de la Pliade / Gallimard, 1990, 1995, 1998.
. [the story of] Juliette [or, Prosperities of Vice]. trans. Austryn
307
The Tears of Eros. trans. Peter Connor. San Francisco: City Lights
Books, 1989.
Baker, Robert S. The Nightmare of the Frankfurt School: the Marquis de Sade and
the Problem of Morality in Aldous Huxleys Dystopian Narrative in Now More
than Ever: Proceedings of the Aldous Huxley Centenary Symposium: Munster,
1994. Nugel- Bernfried, ed, 245-260. New York: Peter Lang, 1995.
Batlay, Jenny H., Otis E Fellows Diderot et Sade: Affinits et divergences,
LEsprit Crateur 15 no.4 (winter 1975): 449-459.
Beach, D.N. The Marquis de Sade: First Zimbabwean Novelist, Zambezia 8 (1)
(1980): 53-6.
Beauvoir, Simone de Must we Burn Sade? trans. Annette Michelson. London: New
English Library, 1972.
Bennington, Geoffrey. Sade Laying Down the Law, Oxford Literary Review 6 (2)
308
(1984): 38 -56.
Berman, Lorna. The Marquis de Sade and Courtly Love, Eighteenth Century
Fiction Vol. 11 no. 3 (April 1999):285-300
. The Marquis de Sade and his Critics, Mosaic 1 no.2 (1968): 57-72.
. Thoughts and Themes of the Marquis de Sade. Kitchener, Ontario:
Ainsworth Press Ltd, 1971.
Blanchot, Maurice. Lautramont et Sade. Paris: Les ditions de Minuit, 1949.
.Sade. in uvres Compltes. Paris: Cercle du livre Prcieux,
1966-1967) 6 : 11-43.
Bloch, Dr. Iwan. Marquis de Sade his life and works [Marquis de Sade: Der Mann
Und Seine Zeit] trans. James Bruce. New York: Castle Books, 1948.
Bongie, Laurence. Sade: a Biographical Essay. Chicago & London: University of
Chicago Press, 1998.
Bourbon Busset, Jacques de. La ngation rotique, La Table Rond 19 no. 1
(1963) :109-112.
Brissenden, R.F. La Philosophie dans le Boudoir; or, A Young Ladys Entrance into
the World, Studies in Eighteenth-century Culture 2 (1972):113-141.
Broche, Jacques. Sade ou le langage terroriste, La Petite revue de philosophie 2
(spring 1981): 25-36.
Brumfield, William C. Thrse philosophe and Dostoyevskys Great Sinner,
Comparative Literature 32 (1980): 238-253.
Camus, Michel Limpasse mystique du Libertin in Sade: crire la crise eds.
Michel Camus, Philippe Roger, 259-276. Paris: Pierre Belfond, 1983.
Camus, Michel., Philippe Roger, eds. Sade crire la crise. Paris : Pierre Belfond,
1983.
Carter, Angela. The Infernal Desire Machines of Doctor Hoffman. London: Penguin,
1972.
. The Sadeian Woman and the Ideology of Pornography. New York:
Harper Colophon Books, 1978.
Chanover, E. Pierre. The Marquis de Sade: A Bibliography. Metuchen: Scarecrow
Press, 1973.
Chtelet, Nolle. Le libertine a table in Sade crire la crise. eds. Michel Camus,
Philippe Roger, 67-83. Paris : Pierre Belfond, 1983.
Charles, Sbastian. Foucault lecteur de Sade: de linfinit du discours la finitude
309
du plaisir. First International Congress Sade in North America, March 12-15 2003,
Charleston, South Carolina, United States of America.
Coward, David. Introduction, in The Misfortunes of Virtue and other early tales
Marquis de Sade, trans. David Coward, vii-xxxviii. Oxford : Oxford University
Press, 1999.
Crocker, Lester G. An Age of Crisis: Man and World in Eighteenth Century French
Thought. Baltimore: the Johns Hopkins Press, 1959.
. Au Cur de la pense de Sade, in Thmes et figures du Sicle
des lumires : Mlanges offerts a Roland Mortier. ed. Raymond Trousson, 59-71.
Genve : Droz, 1980.
. Nature and Culture: Ethical Thought in the French
Enlightenment. Baltimore: the Johns Hopkins Press, 1963.
Cusset, Catherine. la passion selon Juliette, LInfini 31 (fall 1990):17-26.
. Sade, Machiavel et Nron, Dix-huitime Sicle 22 (1990) :401411.
Delon, Michel. Du Danger de la littrature, Europe 835-836 (NovembreDcembre 1998) :3-8.
. Le Corps Sadien, Europe 835-836 (NovembreDcembre 1998) :22-34.
. Sade contre Rousseau, en marge des Lumires, MagazineLittraire 389 (July- August 2000) :39-43.
. . Sade dans la Rvolution, Il Confronto Letterario Supplemento
15 (1991):157-165.
. Sade Thermidorien in Sade : crire la crise eds. Michel Camus,
Philippe Roger, 99-118. Paris : Pierre Belfond, 1983.
Deprun, Jean.
(1977) :263-266.
. Sade et labb Bergier,Raison Prsente 67 (1983):5-11.
. Sade et la philosophie biologique de son temps. in Le Marquis de
Sade, centre aixois dtudes et de recherches sur le XVIIIe sicle, 189-205. Paris:
Librairie Armand Colin, 1968.
. Sade devant la Rgle dor In La qute du bonheur et lexpression
de la douleur dans la littrature et la pense franaises eds. Corrado Rosso,
Carminella Biondi, 307-311. Genve: Droz, 1995.
310
et Fides, 2001.
Sclippa, Norbert. ed. Lire Sade. Paris: l Harmattan, 2004.
Sekitani, Kazuhiko. Rvolution franaise et rotisme vus travers les textes
politiques de Sade, Etudes de langue et littrature franaises 62 (March
1993):16-28.
Sollers, Philippe. Sade dans le texte In Tel Quel 28 (1967) :38-50.
Spruell, Shelby. The Marquis de Sade- Pornography or Political Protest?,
Proceedings of the Annual Meeting of the Western Society for French History 9
(1982):238-249.
Stphane, Nelly. Morale et nature, Europe: Revue littraire- mensuelle 522
(1972) :23-42.
Thomas, Chantal. Isabelle de Bavire : Dernier hrone de Sade in Sade crire la
crise. eds. Michel Camus, Philippe Roger, 47-66 Paris : Pierre Belfond, 1983.
. Sade, la dissertation et lorgie. Paris : ditions Payot & Rivages,
2002.
Van Den Abbeele, Georges. Sade, Foucault, and the Scene of Enlightenment
Lucidity, Stanford French Review 11, no.1 (1987): 7-16.
Verjat, Alain. Limaginaire de Sade et la Rvolution in Mythe et rvolutions ed.
Chalas-Ives, 185-197. Grenoble: PU de Grenoble, 1990.
Warman, Caroline. Sade: from Materialism to Pornography. Oxford: Voltaire
Foundation, 2002.
Weber, Caroline. The Sexist Sublime in Sade and Lyotard, Philosophy and
Literature 26 (2002): 397-404.
Weiss, Allan W. Structures of exchange, acts of transgression in Sade and the
Narrative of Transgression. eds. David B. Allison, Mark S. Roberts, Allen S.
Weiss, 199-212. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1995.
X***, Dr. Jacobus. Le Marquis de Sade et son uvre. Paris : Charles Carrington,
1901.
Related Works.
Adorno, Theodor. Minima Moralia. trans. E. F. N. Jephcott. London: Verso, 2000.
Alford, C. Fred. What Evil Means To Us. Ithaca: Cornell University Press, 1997.
Alson, William P. Pleasure, in The Encyclopedia of Philosophy ed. Paul Edwards,
315
Volume 6, 341-347. New York: The Macmillan Company & the Free Press, 1967.
Arens, Bill. The Man-Eating Myth: Anthropology and Anthropophagy.
Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1980.
Aristotle. Ethics. trans. J.A.K. Thomson. London: Penguin, 1976.
Axelrod, Robert. The Emergence of Cooperation Among Egoists," The American
Political Science Review 75 (1981): 306-318.
Barnes, Jonathan. Early Greek Philosophy. London: Penguin, 1987.
Barthes, Roland. Inaugural Lecture at the Collge de France, 7 January 1977 trans.
Richard Howard, in The Continental Philosophy Reader, ed. Richard Kearney and
Mara Rainwater, 364-377. London: Routledge, 1996.
Bataille, Georges. The Absence of Myth: Writings on Surrealism. trans. Micheal
Richardson. London and New York: Verso, 1994.
. The Accursed Share (3 vols.) trans. Robert Hurley. New York/Zone
Books, 1991- 1993.
.
. Inner Experience. trans. Leslie Anne Bolt. New York: SUNY Press,
1988.
. Madame Edwarda, La Mort, Histoire de lil. (in one volume).
Paris: Collection 10:18, 1973.
. Ma Mre. Paris 10:18, 1966.
.
Soble, 322-347. Totowa, New Jersey: Rowman & Littlefield publishers, Inc., 1980.
Blackburn, Simon. Being Good. Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2001.
.
Blake, William. Selected Poems. ed. P.H. Butter. London: Everyman, 1991.
Blanchot, Maurice. Literature and the Right to Death trans. Lydia Davis, Paul
Auster and Robert Lamberton, in The Station Hill Blanchot Reader: Fiction &
Literary Essays ed. George Quasha, 359-399. Barrytown, New York: Station Hill
Press/ Barrytown, Ltd., 1999.
Bracher, Karl Dietrich. The German Dictatorship: The Origins, Structure and
Consequences of National Socialism. trans. Jean Steinberg. London: Penguin, 1970.
Bradley, F.H. Why should I be moral? in Ethical Studies. New
York: Liberal Arts Press, 1951: 3-28.
Brooks, Geraldine. Nine Parts of Desire: The Hidden World of Islamic Women. New
York: Anchor Doubleday, 2003.
Brumfield, William C. Thrse philosophe and Dostoyevskys Great Sinner,
Comparative Literature 32 (1980): 238-253.
Bruns, Gerald L. Maurice Blanchot: The refusal of Philosophy. Baltimore & London:
The Johns Hopkins University Press, 1997.
Buss, David M. The Evolution of Desire: Strategies of Human Mating. New York:
Basic Books, 2003.
Calhoun, Cheshire, and Robert C. Solomon. What is an Emotion? Classic Readings
in Philosophical Psychology. Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1984.
Camus, Albert. The Myth of Sisyphus. trans. Justin OBrien. London: Penguin, 2000.
.
The Rebel trans. Anthony Bower. New York: Vintage Books, 1984.
Language, Counter-Memory, Practice ed. D .B. Bouchard, 53-67. Ithaca, NY: Cornell
University Press, 1977.
.
Vintage, 1988.
.The Order of Things. London: Routledge, 1994.
.
Camp. Bloomington: Indiana University Press in association with the United States
Holocaust Museum, 1994.
Gutting, Gary, ed. The Cambridge Companion to Foucault. Cambridge: Cambridge
University Press, 1994.
Hare, R. M. Without Conscience: The disturbing world of the psychopaths among us.
New York: Simon & Schuster/Pocket, 1995.
Hegarty, Paul. Georges Bataille: Core Cultural Theorist. London: SAGE
Publications, 2000.
Helvtius, Claude Adrien. Essays on the Mind (De LEsprit, 1758) trans. Anon. New
York: Burt Franklin, 1970.
. A Treatise on Man; his Intellectual Faculties and his
Education (1758). trans. W. Hooper (2 vols). New York: Burt Franklin, 1969.
Hertzberg, Arthur. The French Enlightenment and the Jews. New York: Columbia
University Press, 1968/ The Jewish Publication Society of America Philadelphia,
5728.
Hibbert, Christopher. The Roots of Evil: A Social History of Crime and Punishment.
London: Penguin, 1963.
Hinckfuss, Ian. The Moral Society: Its Structure and Effects. Canberra: Department
of Philosophy, Australian National University, 1987). available from
www.philosophy.ru/library/hinck/contents.html (retrieved September 2004).
Hitler, Adolf. Hitlers Table Talk 1941-1944 His Private Conversations introduced
by Hugh Trevor-Roper, trans. Norman Cameron, R. H. Stevens. London: Phoenix
Press, 2000.
. Mein Kampf trans. Ralph Manheim. London: Pimlico, 1995.
Hobbes, Thomas. Leviathan. Edwin Curley, ed. Indianapolis/ Cambridge: Hackett
Publishing Company, Inc.1994.
Honderich, Ted, ed. the Oxford Companion to Philosophy. Oxford: Oxford
University Press, 1995.
Horkheimer, Max. Eclipse of Reason. New York: Continuum, 1974.
Hughes, Robert. The Fatal Shore. London: Pan, 1987.
Hume, David. Enquiry Concerning the Principles of Morals (1751). Cambridge:
Hackett Publishing Company, 1983.
. Humes Moral and Political Philosophy. ed. Henry D. Aiken. New
York: Hafner Press, 1948.
320
Huxley, Aldous Ends and Means. London: Chatto and Windus, 1938.
Jacob, Margaret C. The Radical Enlightenment: Pantheists, Freemasons and
Republicans (London: George Allen & Unwin, 1981).
Jaggar, Alison M. Prostitution in Philosophy of Sex: Contemporary readings ed.
Alan Soble, 348-368. Totowa, New Jersey: Rowman & Littlefield, Publishers, Inc:
1980.
Janouch, Gustav. Conversations with Kafka. trans. Goronway Rees. New York: New
Directions Books, 1971.
Johnston, John. "Discourse as Event: Foucault, Writing and Literature," Modern
language Notes 105 (fall 1990) 800-818.
Joly, Maurice. Dialogue aux Enfers entre Machiavel et Montesquieu ("Dialogue in
Hell Between Machiavelli and Montesquieu") Project Gutenberg
www.gutenberg.org/etext/13187 (accessed November 2004).
Joyce, Richard. the Myth of Morality. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2001.
Kant, Immanuel. Lectures on Ethics. ed. Peter Heath & J.B. Schneewind; trans. Peter
Heath. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1997.
Karlen, Arno. Threesomes: Studies in Sex, Power and Intimacy. New York: Beech
Tree Books / William Morrow, 1988.
Kershaw, Ian. Hitler 1936-1945 Nemesis. London: Penguin, 2001.
Kiefer, Otto. Sexual Life in Ancient Rome. trans. Anon, (from Kulturgeschichte
Roms unter Besonderer Berckschtigung der Rmischen Sitten). London: Abbey
Library, 1976.
Kirkland, Sean D. The Spectre of Literature in Foucaults The Order of Things,
Henry Street: A Graduate Review of Literary Studies 8:2 (fall 1999):15-35
Knowlson, James. Damned to Fame. London: Bloomsbury, 1997.
Kohn, Hans. The Mind of Germany: the Education of a Nation. New York: Harper
&Row, 1960.
Kuhn, Steven. "Prisoner's Dilemma" In The Stanford Encyclopaedia of Philosophy
(Fall 2003 Edition), Edward N. Zalta (ed.), URL =
<http://plato.stanford.edu/archives/fall2003/entries/prisoner-dilemma/>. (Accessed
September 2004).
La Mettrie, Julien Offray De. Machine Man and Other Writings trans, ed. Ann
Thomson. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1996.
Laqueur, Thomas. Making Sex: Body and Gender from the Greeks to Freud.
321
Estate, 2002.
Van Ingen, John Why Be Moral? The Egoistic Challenge. New York: Peter Lang,
1994.
Vatsyayana. The Kama Sutra of Vatsyayana trans. Sir Richard Burton and F.F.
Arbuthnot. London: Thorsons, 1999.
Voltaire Candide and Other Tales. introduction by H.N. Brailsford; trans. Tobias
Smollet. London: J.M. Dent & Sons 1937.
. Philosophical Dictionary (1764) trans. Theodore Besterman (London:
Penguin, 1972)
. Zadig. (Paris: Larousse, 1993)
Waller, James. Becoming Evil: how ordinary people commit Genocide & Mass
Killing. Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2002.
Wistrich, Robert S. Hitler and the Holocaust. London: Weidenfeld & Nicholson,
2001.
Wokler, Robert. Rousseau: A Very Short Introduction. Oxford: Oxford University
Press, 2001.
iek, Slavoj and Glyn Daly. Conversations with iek. Cambridge: Polity, 2004.
325
326
327