0% found this document useful (0 votes)
32 views

Justice and Dushan'S Legislature: Faculty of Law, Novi Sad

This document provides an overview and analysis of Dushan's legislature from the 13th century in Serbia. It discusses how Dushan's legislature consisted of three main legal texts - Matthew Blastaros' Abridged Syntagm, the Justinian Code, and Dushan's Code. The document analyzes these legal texts from a philosophical standpoint, examining the different forms of justice contained in them based on Plato and Aristotle's theories of justice. It establishes that Dushan's legislature demonstrated distributive justice, general justice, and other forms of justice in a sophisticated way for its time. The document provides important historical and legal context for understanding Dushan's legislature and its significance as one of the major law

Uploaded by

srdja
Copyright
© © All Rights Reserved
We take content rights seriously. If you suspect this is your content, claim it here.
Available Formats
Download as PDF, TXT or read online on Scribd
0% found this document useful (0 votes)
32 views

Justice and Dushan'S Legislature: Faculty of Law, Novi Sad

This document provides an overview and analysis of Dushan's legislature from the 13th century in Serbia. It discusses how Dushan's legislature consisted of three main legal texts - Matthew Blastaros' Abridged Syntagm, the Justinian Code, and Dushan's Code. The document analyzes these legal texts from a philosophical standpoint, examining the different forms of justice contained in them based on Plato and Aristotle's theories of justice. It establishes that Dushan's legislature demonstrated distributive justice, general justice, and other forms of justice in a sophisticated way for its time. The document provides important historical and legal context for understanding Dushan's legislature and its significance as one of the major law

Uploaded by

srdja
Copyright
© © All Rights Reserved
We take content rights seriously. If you suspect this is your content, claim it here.
Available Formats
Download as PDF, TXT or read online on Scribd
You are on page 1/ 29

UNIVERSITY OF NI

The scientific journal FACTA UNIVERSITATIS


Series: Law and Politics Vol. 1, No 3, 1999 pp. 295 - 323
Editor of series: Milan Petrovi, e-mail: [email protected]
Address: Univerzitetski trg 2, 18000 Ni, YU
Tel: +381 18 547-095, Fax: +381 18 547-950

JUSTICE AND DUSHAN'S LEGISLATURE


UDC 177.9.:340.13(091)(497.11)

Milijan Popovi
Faculty of Law, Novi Sad
Abstract. It is just 650 years since the passing of Dushan's Code, the final act of the
universal codification of the law of the medieval Serbia, which together with Matthew
Blastaros' Abridged Syntagm and the so-called Justinian Code make Dushan's
legislature.
Dushan's legislature, first of all Dushan's Code, was investigated from the axiological
standpoint, according to Plato's and Aristotle's paradigms. Such an approach has
enabled reasonableness of Dushan's legislature to be established, instead of
establishing historical phenomenon, what the historians do.
Dushan's estate monarchy was a timocracy (timarchy), which means a form of a state
which at least deviates from Plato's perfectly righteous state. Secular lords, as a
military estate, together with the ruler, the supreme military commander, performed the
principal function, military, in the Serbian medieval state, while the clergy performed
those religious, cultural and social. It is, therefore, that those were privileged estates.
According to the situational justice principle and in view of their merits in the state, the
privileged estates had the right of property to the land (dominium directum) and the
ruler the right of the supreme property to the land (dominium eminens), the so-called
free heritage and many other privileges beyond the economic field. Dependent
population, however, since its activities, although indispensable, were not directly
connected with the principal, military function, had the right to use the land (dominium
utile), the so-called subordinated heritage and in turn a lot of tributes and obligations.
Also, existing in Dushan's legislature, and first of all in Dushan's Code, was Aristotle's
general justice, understood as legitimacy, explicitly formulated at several places and
particularly in Articles 171 and 172. Mostly containing provisions of the public law
character, Dushan's Code feature distributive justice represented to a high degree,
which is demonstrated in distributing honours and goods in proportion with merits.
Also, there existed a special form of the distributive justice featured by an
outstandingly social function. Namely, Dushan's Code takes care of the poor, wretched,
sick and frees them from various burdens imposing obligations on the Church and
courts to help them. Finally, Dushan's Code recognizes Aristotle's court and criminal
justice as well, as a form of corrective or synalagmatic justice which is demonstrated in
Received December 30, 1999

296

M. POPOVI

establishing the middle between the good and the evil, i.e. equivalency, done by the
court. This special form of justice, however, was not consistently put into effect.
As for its depth and reasonableness, Dushan's legislature, and first of all Dushan's
Code, is an example of a majestic medieval law codification.
Key Words: Plato's justice, situational justice, general justice, distributive justice,
court justice, estate monarchy, timocracy

INTRODUCTORY NOTES
Emperor Caesar Flavius Justinian, pious and everlasting August, in the Constitutio
Tanta addressed to the Senate and all the peoples, pointed out, on the occasion of his
codification, that "something majestic emanates from these books, when seen that the old
multitude has now been replaced by the condensed and lesser one"1. He added "that only
divine things are really quite perfect", while "the form of the human law () always
endlessly changes, so that there is nothing that could last in it forever"2.
The above quoted evaluations of emperor Justinian can also be applied to Dushan's
legislature.
While Dushan's fragile empire has vanished in the sands of time, his codification, as a
majestic law monument, in the previously mentioned Justinian style, emanates with
depth, comprehensiveness and richness into centuries. It is one of the rare, at that time,
and in all times as well, universal codifications3. It is a golden treasury for all kinds of
historical, economic, sociologic, linguistic, cultural, law and philosophical studies.
I. MEANING OF THE EXPRESSION "DUSHAN'S LEGISLATURE"
narrower meaning has frequently been attached t the wording "Dushan's
Legislature". Under it Dushan's Code is understood, enforced at the parliament sessions
in Skoplje (1349) and Serez (1354). However, it was already in 1888 that Florinski
showed that there was a close connection of Dushan's Code with Matthew Blastaros'
Abridged Syntagm by and the so-called Justinian Code4. On the other hand, Aleksandar
Solovjev has proved in his doctoral dissertation Legislature of Stefan Duan, Emperor of
Serbs and Greeks, based on the paleographic-philologic and political-historical analysis
of Dushan's Code and on the basis of comparisons of law provisions of Blastaros'
Syntagm and the so-called Jusitinian Code with the provisions of Dushan's Code, that all
three acts make "one intended entirety"5. Hence, a logical conclusion resulted that

1
See: Justinian Digesta, Book One of Constitutions, Deo auctore, Tanta, Omnem rei publicae, translated by Dr.
Antun Malenica, Beograd, Slubeni glasnik, 1997, p. 35.
2
Ibid., page 37
3
See: Dr. Toma ivanovi, Sistem sintetike pravne filozofije (System of Synthetic Law Philosophy) 1
Sintetika filozofija prava 2 Sintetika filozofija pravnih nauka, Beograd, SANU 1959, pp. 125-136.
4
See:. , , ,
1888, pp. 172-268.
5
See: Aleksandar Solovjev, Zakonodavtsvo Stefana Duana cara Srba i Grka (Legislature of Stefan Dushan,
Emperor of Serbs and Greeks), Beograd, Pravni fakultet, 1928, p. V.

Justice and Dushan's Legislature

297

Dushan's Code was only "the third part of a tripartite code of the Serbian-Byzantine
(Roman) law"6.
Matthew Blastaros' Syntagm was translated from Greek to Slavic7, probably by the
end of 1348 or beginning 1349. It was reduced to one third. Retained were, first of all,
rules of civil law, while most of the ecclesiastical norms were left out. The contents of
Matthew Blastaros' Abridged Syntagm make regulations contained in the Byzantine
emperors laws. They were from earlier known to the medieval Serbia, as a part of
Nomocanon. Matthew Blastaros' Abridged Syntagm makes "the first part of the codifying
work of the new emperor"8. The second part of the codification is the so-called Justinian
Code. Those are, in fact, Agricultural Law (a certain number of articles) enacted by the
end of the 7th or beginning of the 8th century during Justinian II, Eklog (a short choice of
the most important provisions of the Justinian codification) of the year 726 or 741 and
certain parts of Procheiron (a short-form law handbook intended for courts) of the year
870 or 879. Since emperor Justinian was a personification of the codifying work, the
above mentioned law was named Justinian Code. Agrarian relations were regulated under
it and was "probably" used prior to Dushan's times as well9. Dushan's Code is the third
part, final chord of the universal codification in the Nemanji-dynasty state.
Dushan's Code closely corresponds, first of all, with Matthew Blastaros' Abridged
Syntagm. It is natural, since it is the most voluminous part of Dushan's codification.
Basically, Dushan's Code is only its supplement10. Matthew Blastaros' Abridged Syntagm
was given its "legal authorization"11 at the state parliament, most probably in 1349, when
Dushan's Code itself was enacted.
In addition to a lot of proofs, quoted by Solovjev in the above mentioned doctoral
dissertation on Dushan's Codex Tripartitus, an external reason can be cited
unsystematic nature of Dushan's Code. This unsystematic nature can be understood only
when Dushan's Code is related with Matthew Blastaros' Abridged Syntagm and
understood as its supplement. Particularly significant is the reason cited by Solovjev. In
all older transcripts of Dushan's legislature, Dushan's Code comes along with Matthew
Blastaros' Abridged Syntagm, "the which fact cannot be accidental"12.
II. HISTORICAL AND PHILOSOPHICAL STANDPOINT AND DUSHAN'S LEGISLATURE
Dushan's legislature has been mainly studied by the historians, which is a natural
thing.
6

See: Dr Sran arki i dr Dragoljub Popovi, Veliki pravni sistemi i kodifikacije (Great Law Systems and
Codifications), Beograd, "Savremena adminsitracija", 1993, p. 82; Aleksandar Solovjev, quoted work, p. 57
7
See: Teodor Taranovski, Istorija srpskog naroda u Nemanjikoj dravi (History of Serbian People in the
Nemanji-Dynasty State), Beograd, Slubeni list SRJ, 1996, p. 174; Laz. Uroevi, Pravosue i pisano pravo u
srednjevekovnoj Srbiji u svetlosti dananjeg pisanog prava, Beograd, 1939, pp. 30-32.
8
See: Dr Aleksandar Solovjev, op.cit., p. 89
9
Ibid., p. 89.
10
See: Dr Dragoslav Jankovi, Istorija drave i prava feudalne Srbije (XII-XV vek)(History of State and Law of
Feudal Serbia (12th-15th century) , third edition, Beograd, Nauna knjiga, 1961, p. 16.
11
See: Teodor Taranovski, op.cit., p. 174.
12
See: Teodor Taranovski, op.cit., p. 49

298

M. POPOVI

Basically, the historical standpoint is empirical and positivistic. In addition to other


authors, Hegel mercilessly criticizes it. He says that historians search for historical
details. Their ideal is "knowledge of all endless details" which are absolutely "needless to
an intellectual insight"13. Some historians features "carelessness, because of that
arrogance to think that the learned knowledge already has in itself an intellectual
comprehension"14.
In recent times, by the middle of this century, criticizing the historical approach was
also Leo Strauss. He says that for that approach "space and time factors are of greater
value than the universal one".15 He thinks that historical experience is "fully insufficient
to back up historicism" and that historicism "must be based upon philosophy, but not
history"16 because "historical knowledge is always fragmentary and sometimes shaky".17
Deficiencies of the historical attitude in studying Dushan's legislature vanish with the
best historians such as, for example, Stojan Novakovi, Teodor Taranovski and
Alerksandar Solovjev, although reasoning consciousness breaks out with them as well.
Taranovski, who was also a law philosopher, does not speak anything about justice,
although it is also mentioned in Dushan's Code and in Matthew Blastaros' Abridged
Syntagm. Description of the law as it is, is not sufficient. Its legitimisation, in addition to
the rest, is also necessary, which is impossible without justice. Also, without establishing
the nature of the things, a true explanation of Dushan's legislature is impossible.
Here, I would like to point to the need of the philosophic, which means intellectual
approach in studying Dushan's legislature, not bringing into question the historical
approach at all. For, the philosophy itself is "seeing through the intellectual", and thus
"understanding of the present and realistic"18. The philosophical standpoint should
express the spirit of time in which great Dushan's codifying work was created. That
pertaining to truth, what the philosopher is searching for, lies in Dushan's legislature
itself, not outside it. Dushan's legislature is not "abandoned by God", is not left to the
"atheism of the habitudinal world"19, so that one would search for the truth outside it.
After all, as pointed out by Hegel, "the truth on the law, habitude and state is as old as
explained and known in public laws, public morals and religion"20. The assignment of
philosophy is to find out intellectuality of Dushan's legislature, to recognize that what is
righteous in it, i.e. to establish the substantial essence of the habitudinal reality, but not
the essence of the historical phenomenon which is the business of (most of) the
historians.

13
See: Georg Wilhelm Friedrich Hegel, Philosophy of Right (with Hegel's own margins in his handy copy of the
law philosophy), (Yugoslav edition), Sarajevo, "Veselin Maslea" and "Svejtlost", 1989, p. 33.
14
See: Ibid, p. 33.
15
See: Leo Strauss, Natural Law and History, (Yugoslav edition), Sarajevo "Veselin Maslea", 1971, p. 21.
16
Ibid., p. 25
17
Ibid., p. 28
18
See: Georg Wilhelm Hegel, op.cit., p.16
19
Ibid., p. 11.
20
Ibid., p. 9.

Justice and Dushan's Legislature

299

III. CONTINUITY OF THE IDEA OF JUSTICE IN THE NEMANJI-DYNASTY SERBIA


From the times of Stevan Nemanja up to Dushan's codification, the idea of justice
was omnipresent in the consciousness of the Serbian people, in the customary law,
literature and in the law-creative activities of the Serbian rulers. In that regard, of
exceptional interest is Nomocanon (1219), particularly meritorious for which was St.
Sava. It was a systematized collection of Byzantine codes. It should have met the needs
of both the Serbian Church and the Serbian state. It is, therefore, that it contains both
ecclesiastical and secular regulations (excerpts from Justinian's novels and the whole
Procheiron city law). It is important to mention that St. Sava's Doctrine Nomocanon
(law rules), which laid the foundations of the Serbian law, contains a provision of social
justice as well, "that any poor man and any employee must not be deprived of his pay"21.
St. Sava's Ortodoxy Doctrine is, according to Justin Popovi, "entelechy, the supreme
principle, life-giving principle and the power of our soul, our history, our people, our
man; it is the soul of our soul, the heart of our heart, the life of our life"22.
The idea of justice, however, as a basic principle, found its adequate place only in the
Matthew Blastaros' Syntagm and Dushan's Code. It doesn't matter that it was taken from
the Byzantine legislature23. After all, that idea was also taken over by the Byzantine
legislature from the Roman law and the Roman lawyers from Plato and Aristotle through
the Stoic philosophy. If there were any imitations and takings over, emperor Dushan "has
accepted, in his legislative work, the best principles from Byzantium"24.
IV. JUSTICE AS A FOUNDATION AND PURPOSE OF THE LAW
I approach Dushan's legislature from the axiological standpoint. I start from the
attitude that justice is a foundation and purpose of the law. Under the purpose I mean
both the cause and the goal. Therefore, the purpose is both at the start and at the end. I
think that what is historical and present (in the Hegelian sense) is not a measure of the
law. Chronological sequence, what the historians hold to, is observance of illusory
movements and shadows (in the Platonic sense). Chronology is a consciousness of the
mere occurrence. More important than the chronological sequence is that ontological,
which, after all, is a basis of the chronological sequence. Rational form of the spirit may
have for its subject only that what is according to the intellect. Justice is the essence of
law. It should be used to measure that what is, i.e. reasonableness of Dushan's legislature.
21
See: urica Krsti, Srpsko srednjevekovno pravo i razvoj prava potonjeg vremena (Serbian Medieval Law
and Law Development in Suceeding Times), in the book Srbi u evropskoj civilizaciji (The Serbs in the European
Civilization), Beograd, SANU, 1993, p. 187.
22
See: Archimandrite Dr. Justin Popovi, Svetosavlje kao filozofija ivota (St .Sava Ortodoxy Doctrine as the
Philosophy of Life), phototype edition, Valjevo, 1993, p. 121.
23
See: Nikola Radoji, Duanov Zakonik i vizantisko pravo (Dushan's Code and Byzantine Law) , Zbornik u
ast este stogodinice Zakonika cara Duana, I, Beograd, SANU, 1951, p. 61. "It is only that comparative
study of law of all nations and all times has created a scientifically correct judgement that the law collections
can rightly be considered as a people's pride even when there are a wealth of borrwings. Namely, it is not their
number that is in question, but their law depth and their ethical highness. Wherever taken from, the best among
them become and remain characteristic of the people who accepted them.
24
See: Dr. Aleksandar Solovjev, op.cit., p.222.

300

M. POPOVI

Justice is both at the beginning, as an out-of-the-law concept, and at the end, as


reasonableness of Dushan's legislature. Justice as reasonableness, as something general
and true, is personified in Dushan's legislature as well. The true is only that what can be
justified by means of it. The rest is mere survival, empty existence, casual, final, untrue.
I do not accept a standpoint according to which one cannot determine what justice is.
For justice is, it is said, a value and "value judgements are subjective", and hence "very
different" and "mutually contradictory"25. Justice is a noble feeling, ethical ideal to be
longed for, says Kelsen, but cannot be conceptually determined. Such a standpoint is
dangerous. It claims that what is true, i.e. justice, cannot be found out. It is a humiliation
for philosophy. Philosophy is just searching for that what is eternal, unchangeable and
true. Instead of illusion of things, it establishes the very thing, i.e. the nature of things of
the law, its reasonableness, justice.
Truly, justice has been differently understood in different times. But there has always
remained an unchangeable core, which is proportion, equality.
A mention of justice has been frequently made in Dushan's Code. As found out by
Stojan Novakovi, at some places the word "justice" is used to denote the law26 or, for
example, a dispute or a lawsuit27. The key place in Dushan's Code, which is in Article
171 and which, translated by N. Radoji, reads: "Yet, my emperorship ordered to me: If
my emperorship writes a letter either out of fury, or out of love, or out of grace for
someone, and that letter destroys the code, and is not in accordance with justice and the
law, the judges are not to believe that letter, but to judge and do as it is in accordance
with the justice"28. Organically connected with this place also is Article 172 which,
translated by N. Radoji, reads: "All the judges to judge in accordance with the law,
rightfully and like it is written in the code, but not to judge for fear of my emperorship"29
The above provisions which are the "highest point"30 of Dushan's Code are, as found out
by Nikola Radoji, taken over from the Byzantine law (Basilike)31.
25

See: Hans Kelsen, ta je pravda (What is Justrice), (Yu edition), Beograd, "Filip Vinji", 1998, p. 16.
See: Stojan Novakovi, Zakonik Stefana Duana cara srpskog 1349 i 1354 (Dushan's Code of 1349 and
1354), Beograd, Izdanje Zadubine Ilije M. Kolarca, 1898, p. 220. Art. 123 of Dushan's Code, translated by
Nikola Radoji, redas: " On marketplaces; wherever the Saxons have cut the woods till this parliament, that
land may remain theirs; if they have taken land to a certain lord without any right (my italic M.P.), may lords
fight them s in court under the saint king's law, and from now on the Saxon is not to cut, and that what he cuts
not to till and no people to settle down, only the barren area to remain, the woods to grow; none is to forbid the
woods to a Saxon, as much needed for the marketplace, he is to cut down" (Beograd, SANU, 1960, p. 123). On
the meaning of the word "code" in Dushan's legislature, see: Sran arki, Zakon u glagoljskim i irilskim
pravnim spomenicima (The Law in Glagolitic and Cyrillic Law Documents) (from the 12th to the 18th century),
Novi Sad, 1994.
27
See: Stojan Novakovi, op.cit., p. 166, Art. 33 of Dushan's Code, translated by Nikola Radoji, reads:
"Ecclesiastical people in each lawsuit (my italic M.P.) to be put on trial before their metropolitans, and before
bishops and priors, and if both men are of one church, to be put on trial before their Church, but should litigants
be of two churches, to be judged by both Churches" (op.cit., p. 98).
28
See: Nikola Radoji, op.cit., p. 135.
29
Ibid., p. 135.
30
See: Nikola Radoji, Duanov zakonik i vizantinsko pravo (Dushan's Code and Byzantine Law), p. 63.
31
See: Nikola Radoji, Snaga zakona po Duanovom zakoniku (Force of Law According to Dushan's Code),
Glas CX SAN, 1924, pp. 100-139; Nikola Radoji, Sudije i zakon u srednjevekovnoj Srbiji i u Ugarsko (Judges
and Law in the Medieval Serbia), Letopis Matice srpske, 305, 1925, pp. 53-68.
26

Justice and Dushan's Legislature

301

There is no determination of the concept of justice in Dushan's Code. There it is,


however, in Dushan's legislature, in the first part of Codex Tripartitus and in Matthew
Blastaros' Abridged Syntagm. There, under justice "permanent and steady striving that
everybody should be done what he rightfully deserves" is understood, and under the
rightful "to live peacefully, not insulting the other and decently provide everybody with
what he deserves"32. He adds that "great () wisdom is in justice: to know divine and
human things, what is righteous and what is unrighteous"33.
Here we recognize Ulpian's words from Justinian's Digesta, from Book I of rules in a
somewhat clumsy translation. Originally, Ulpian says: "Righteousness is a continuous
and everlasting will everybody to be given what he rightfully deserves. 1. These are law
principles: to live honestly, not to insult the other, to provide everybody with what he
deserves. 2. To know law is to realize divine and human things, a science on righteous
and unrighteous"34.
The Roman law was, as recently found out by Ostrogorski, "in all times a basis ()
of the lawful life" of Byzantium and her "lawful consciousness"35. It continued to live in
numerous collections of Byzantine codes (particularly in voluminous Basilikes) and thus,
through Matthew Blastaros' Syntagm as well, into Dushan's Serbia, to be, as Taranovski
says, "lawfully authorized" at the state parliament in Skoplje in 1349.
The Roman-Byzantine understanding of justice (and the natural law) was mediated by
Cicero's "the law of nature", i.e. by Platonic-Aristotelian-Stoic understanding where "the
legal and political are not separated from ethical"36
Ulpian derives the word "right" (ius) from justice (iustitia)37. Referring to Celsus, he
says that the law is "the skill of good and equal" (ars boni et aequi)38, that the three law
commandments are: "Honeste vivere, alterum non laedere, suum quique tribuere"39. He
determines the natural law as "that which the nature has endowed to all living beings
born on the earth and under the sea, and which is common to the birds as well"40. Here, it
is easy to recognize Stoic-pantheistic understanding of God-like nature, as well as union
and reconciliation of the natural, rational and divine law. For, the nature, reason and God

32
See: Translation of law regulations entered into Matthew Blastaros' Syntagm (alphabetical collection of
Byzantine ecclesiastical and state laws in Slavonic translation of Dushan's time, edition of Stojan Novakovi),
Chapter I and On Justice, in the book Pravosue i pisano pravo u srednjevkovnoj Srbiji u svetlosti dananjeg
pisanog prava (The Judicary and the Written Law in the Light of the Modern Written Law), Laz. Uroevi
(Beograd, 1939, p. 61).
33
Ibid., p. 61.
34
See: Justinian's Digesta, p. 69.
35
See: Georgije Ostrogorski, Istorija Vizantije (History of Byzantium), Beograd, Narodna knjiga, Alfa, 1998, p.
53. "Byzantium is tied to Hellenism not only genetically but also with a deep substantial kinship. Hellenistic as
well as Byzantine culture have got something epigonic, eclectic. Both live on the heritage of cultures of greater
creative power and express themselves less in their own creation than in maintaining or adopting someone
else'e. But lack of spiritual freshness is compensated by the power of synthesis. The Roman state and the Greek
culture grow together on the Byzantian soil into a new living organism and inseparably merge with Christianity
within which the old state and the old culture had seen their strongest negation". (op.cit., pp. 52-45).
36
See: Ljubomir Tadi, Filozofija prava (The Philosophy of Law), Zagreb, Naprijed, 1983, pp.42'45.
37
Ibid., p. 44.
38
Ibid., p. 44
39
Ibid., p. 44.
40
See: Justinian's Digesta, p. 65.

302

M. POPOVI

are all "one and the same"41. According to Ulpian's determination the natural law is "a
form of a positive law, but not the ideal of law or boundary of worthiness of the positive
law"42. Therefore, the natural law, and the justice as well, is not anything of beyond, it is
not a form of personification and singularization of the eternal law, such as with Thomas
Aquinas. That reasonableness, justice, is in the positive law, its part and the higher one. It
is a paradigm for building and interpreting the rest of the positive law. Justice, therefore,
was not understood as an overburdened concept, such as with the rational and
revolutionary natural law of the new age. In the Roman-Byzantine law, there is a
uniqueness of the concept (in the Hegelian sense) and its realization. That mutatis
mutandis also refers to Dushan's legislature. Hence, it is indispensable that Dushan's
Code should be understood as a part of a wider entirety, of Codex Tripartitus, along with
Matthew Blastaros' Abridged Syntagm and the so-called Justinian Code as I have already
pointed out.
V. SITUATIONAL JUSTICE AND DUSHAN'S ESTATE MONARCHY
It is usually considered that, without further investigation and intellectual insight,
Middle Ages is "ill fate which had destroyed classical civilization and culture"43. Gibbon
describes Middle Ages as a "long night of illiteracy and violence, saved from the total
darkness only by some remaining traces of classical culture"44. Such a common-sense
view is explained by the fact that there were neither "great meditative undertakings nor
discoveries which raise dignity and creative power of mortal people to immense
heights"45. There are, however, authors which observe that the "highest medieval
achievements () are the fruits of deep thinking and sacrificing to the service of
mankind and God"46
The development of society can be measured both by the number and quality of social
spiritual creations. Such approach became legitimate in the second half of the 19th
century, first of all, thanks to the philosophy of values, the branch of the neo-Kantian
philosophy, so-called Baden or South-West German School, the leaders of which were

41

See: Ljubomir Tadi, op.cit., p.44-44.


Ibid., p. 46.
43
See: Veljko Kora and Branko Pavlovi, Istorija filozofije (The Histroy of Philosophy), 12th edition, Beograd,
Zavod za udbenike i nastavna sredstva, 1999, p. 103.
44
See: H.V.K. Davies, Srednjevekovna Evropa (Medieval Europe), (YU edition), edited by D. Nikoli and M.
Maksimovi, Ni, SKC/Zograf, 1999, p.8.
45
See: Veljko Kora and Branko Pavlovi, op.cit., p. 103.
46
See: H.V.K. Davies, op.cit., p. 9. "In other words, they had germinated from the soil and ripen in the air of a
civilized society" (p. 9). "What we like in the medieval standpoint on life is as follows; first, the idea of
humanness, as fraternity which surpasses national and political divisions, fraternity united in a common search
for truth, filled with the spirit of mutual love towards the close, the spirit of reciprocal support and endowed
with a stronger will and wisdom than those possessed by its members. Second, it is a deep faith in the
superiority of law with reference to power, of spirit with reference to the substance, of everlasting significance
of humanness with reference to ambitions and passions of temporary character. If there were no Christianity,
these goals of faith hardly would become a common heritage of all people, and if there were no Church, there
eventually would be little likelihood for Christianity to survive this period of half barbarism in which
foundations of the modern society were laid" (p. 115).
42

Justice and Dushan's Legislature

303

Wilhelm Windelband and Heinrich Rikert. Taranovski, our historian and law philosopher
has also accepted that orientation, particularly in his Encyclopaedia of Law47.
Instead an event of the worldwide historical importance to be seen in the Christian
principle, Christianity is just being accused for cultural backwardness. However, it was
only in Christianity that the spirit has emancipated from the nature. In the nature, a man
is completely unfree. It was only in Christianity that spirit turns towards its own essence.
It is a process of the proprietary production. In other words, a man is that what he makes
out of himself. A man is, therefore, a proprietary activity. And that is the selfproduction
of a man by proprietary work. It is with Christianity that a man has emerged as a free
spirit. That is why the Christian principle is, as shown by Hegel, the truth of classical
philosophy48.
Paradigms based upon which the development of society is to be estimated should be:
freedom, justice and human dignity. They make a whole, like a physical spectrum of
colours. Measured by these measures, the medieval society rises above the classical
slaveholding society. Human freedom spaces have widened within it, human dignity
level is higher, while the ideological form of justice, the so-called situational justice, is
above that justice of ancient times.
1. Plato's Justice and Dushan's Estate Monarchy
Constituents of justice in Matthew Blastaros' Abridged Syntagm and Dushan's Code
are, as it has already been mentioned, Plato's and Aristotle's justice as well, mediated by
the Stoic philosophy and partly by the Christian principle.
a) Perfect State and Perverted States
Plato's justice is, of course, a starting and central element in the Byzantine and
(Roman), i.e. Serbian medieval understanding of justice. Plato thought that positive law
can be founded on supralaw manner only, ontologically, by means of justice. Justice has
that power to impart truth to the law. Everything existing, exists according to it,. Also,
Plato's state is based on justice. Its purpose is accomplishment of the idea of justice.
Justice is, Plato says, virtue of a man as well as virtue of a state49. With an honest
man, parts of his soul are brought "into their natural position"50. Since soul is in
possession of the rational, willing, greedy parts, it is necessary that "the whole soul be
governed by that part of its which is love towards wisdom or by the philosophical part",
so that "no other part would rebel against that"51. It is only then that it is possible that

47
See my work Filozofija vrednosti, aksioloke filozofije prava i Enciklopedija prava Tranovskog (The
Philosophy of Value, Axiological Philosophies of Law and Encyclopaedia of Law of Taranovski), Zbornik
Matice srpske za drutvene nauke, 1998.
48
See: Wilhelm Friedrich Hegel, Istorija filozofije (The History of Philosophy) (Yu edition), third edition,
translated by Nikola M. Petrovi, preface by Dr. Veljko Kora, Beograd, BIGZ, 1975, pp. 81-82: Milenko A.
Perovi, Istorija filozofije (The History of Philosophy), Novi Sad, Filozofski fakultet, 1997, p. 168
49
See: Plato, Drava (State) (Yu edition), fourth edition, preface by Dr. Veljko Kora, explanations and
comments by Dr. Branko Pavlovi, Beograd, BIGZ, 1993, p. 47.
50
Ibid., p. 134.
51
Ibid., p. 287.

304

M. POPOVI

"each of them may act in accordance with its purpose, and thus be righteous"52.
Within his rational53 construction of the state, Plato has made, as he says, a perfectly54
good state. The goal of that state is not "that only one estate in it should be particularly
happy, but the whole state in far the greatest percentage"55. A perfectly good state is
"wise, brave, moderate and righteous"56. Wisdom is the knowledge of the general (i.e. the
idea of the good). That knowledge refers "to that what exists", and based on it "one
recognizes that what exists and how it exists"57. That what exists (i.e. the idea of the
good) "is always the same and unchangeable"58, which means "everlasting"59. Within the
hierarchy of ideas (of the true world), the idea of the good holds the first place. It is only
based on it that both the idea of justice "and everything connected with it is imparted the
value and become useful"60. Plato understands the idea of the good "as the cause of our
knowledge and as the cause of the truth which we learn by the reason61. Only the
philosophers can recognize that idea and that is why they should administer a state. Their
assistants and performers of decisions are guardians. They, in addition to other virtues
(reasonableness, piety, nobility) should possess courage62. Their assignment is to defend
the state "both from the external and internal enemies" so as to prevent "the ones in their
will and the others in the possibility to de evil"63. Moderation is "more similar to the
accord and harmony than the two previous virtues"64, and is expressed as "some
orderliness and governance over pleasures and passionate likings"65. It "spreads over the
whole state bringing into mutual accord all its members, the weakest and the most
powerful and those between them"66. Justice, as the fourth virtue, even ranks as the first
one, and in certain sense is the only one. Justice consists "in that everybody has his own
and that everybody does what he should do"67. It harmonizes other virtues and is for the
state "that what is the most supreme and the most necessary"68. It is justice that is in
question from the very beginning, and only the justice, for it is causa finalis.
Starting from the degree of feasibility of justice, Plato has differentiated proper and
perverted forms of a state. As many types of human characters there are, so are many

52

Ibid., pp. 287-288.


Ibid., p. 48. "Well, let us establish a state in thoughts"!
54
Ibid., p. 112. "I think that our state, if properly constructed, is perfectly good".
55
Ibid., p. 103. "You have forgotten, my friend - said I - that our laws do not tend one estate in the state to be
particularly happy, but to create welfare for the whole state, bringing citizens, by hook or by crook, into
harmony, providing them, first of all, with a share in businesses, which each individual can, according to his
capabilities, perform for the state" (op.cit., p. 211).
56
Ibid., p. 112.
57
Ibid., p. 169.
58
Ibid., p. 174.
59
Ibid., p. 175.
60
Ibid., p. 196.
61
Ibid., p. 201.
62
Ibid., p. 177.
63
Ibid., p. 99.
64
Ibid., p. 116.
65
Ibid., p. 116.
66
Ibid., p. 118.
67
Ibid., p. 120.
68
Ibid., p. 235.
53

Justice and Dushan's Legislature

305

types of states. Socrates (i.e. Plato) says: "Do you think that governmental structures
grow 'out of an oak or out of a rock', but not from the character of people who move the
state as they do a weight on the scales?"69 A proper (perfect) form of a state is "a
kingdom, when from among the heads one man particularly stands out which differs
from the others; the other name will be aristocracy, when there are more of such
people"70. Clearly, a supposition is that in such "mode of governing a state" (Plato),
everyone does his job in accordance with his capabilities, i.e. virtues, which I have
already described. Or, as Plato says: "If philosophers do not become kings in a state
said I or, if present kings and rulers do not become proper and good philosophers, and
if both: political power and philosophy (love for wisdom) do not become one thing, and
if those numerous natures longing for one, or only for the other thing, are not forcibly
excluded, then, my dear Glaucon, calamities will never cease not only for the states, as I
think, but for the human race as well, and the governmental structure we have just
depicted in words will neither become possible nor see the light of day"71. Such a perfect
form of a state, Plato is talking about, "exists only in mind, for I think that it can be found
nowhere on earth"72. After all, says Plato, "it is of no importance at all whether such a
state really exists anywhere or will exist in the future only. Because such a man will live
in accordance with it, but no with any other"73.
In contrast to the perfect form of a state, which "exists only in mind", the existing,
empirical forms of a state, perverted forms of a state can be found. Those are: timocracy
or timarchy, oligarchy, democracy and tyranny (tyrannis). Plato calls them "diseases of a
state"74. Diseases of a state are "those things which gradually destroy, corrode a state
inside, out of its own construction"75. Timocracy (timarchy) is "ambitious governmental
structure"76. It arises from the corruption of aristocracy "when there occurs discord
among those in power"77. Assistants to the rulers, i.e. warriors take over the power in the
state. They are afraid "of bringing the wise to power", being inclined to the "people more
capable to wage war than to make peace, they will appreciate deceits and agility in war
and will spend time permanently waging wars"78. Timocracy "involves both the evil and
the good", so that it is "in fact a mixture"79. Though, in such a form of a state "prevails
bravery" accompanied by "tendency towards competition and ambition"80. Then,
timocracy turns into oligarchy, which "is based upon the estimation of property, where
the rich rule and the poor do not participate in the power"81. With the passage of time,

69

Ibid., p. 238.
Ibid., p. 135.
71
Ibid., p. 164.
72
Ibid., p. 294.
73
Ibid., p. 294.
74
Ibid., p. 238.
75
See: Dr. Branko Pavlovi, Objanjenja i komentari teksta (Explanations and Comments of the Text), in Plato's
book Drava (State), p. 381.
76
See: Plato. Drava (State), p. 239.
77
Ibid., p. 239.
78
Ibid., pp. 241-242.
79
Ibid., p. 242.
80
Ibid., p. 242.
81
Ibid., p. 244.
70

306

M. POPOVI

timocratic people "who like competition and honour () become devotees of money and
getting rich, so that they praise a rich man, admire him and bring him to power, and
despise a poor man"82. Thus, timocracy turns into oligarchy, and this, due to further
degeneration, into democracy. Democracy is created when the poor win, who then kill a
part of the enemies and expel the other part, equally sharing power and civic rights with
the rest, and when the power is most frequently elected by gambling"83. It is one of the
"diseases of a state", since "anything is allowed" in it and "everybody does in it whatever
he wants"84. Everything in it is "anarchic, motley, which dispenses some equality to one
and all, both to the equal and to the unequal"85. Democracy favours superfluous wishes.
There flourish "impudence, lawlessness, luxury and shamelessness"86. All this destroys
democracy and tills the ground for tyrannis, the most pervert form of rule, to come into
existence. "Too much of freedom" destroys democracy, which in tyranny turns into "too
much of slavery both for an individual and for a state"87. At the beginning, the tyrant
"represents people"88, but later on, when he steps "into the state cart", there occurs his
transformation from the "representative" to a "perfect tyrant"89. Of all the states tyranny
is "the most unhappy"90 and "the most wretched"91 state, and the tyrant himself "much
more unhappy than all other people"92.
b) Plato's Timocracy and Dushan's Estate Monarchy
Plato's perfect state, such as devised in his mind, does not coincide with any empirical
form of a state to date. Accordingly, Dushan's estate monarchy is neither identical with
monarchy (in the Platonian sense) nor with aristocracy (aristocracy of spirit) as perfect
forms of a state. The question is only to what extent it deviates from the perfect form of a
state, which "disease" has afflicted it and how it corrodes the state inside, to which
82

Ibid., p. 245.
Ibid., p. 252.
Ibid., p. 252. "And there where everything is allowed, it is natural that everybody adjusts his life in his own
way to the best of his liking" (op.cit., p. 253). "One could say I added that this governmental structure is the
best of all; like a parti-coloured garment interweaved with all sorts of flowers, so that this governmental
structure as well, decorated with all sorts of characters, would appear the most beautiful, and perhaps would be
estimated as the best, such as the children and women do when watching motley objects" (op.cit, p. 253).
85
Ibid., p. 253.
86
Ibid., p. 257. "This happens, and the other such trifles as well: a teacher in such a state fears of his pupils and
flatters them; the latter scarcely respect teachers, the same as pedagogues. In general, the young make
themselves equal with the old and fight with them both in words and deeds; the old, again, in order to flatter the
young, give in, are helpful, full of jokes and imitate them only not to look unpleasant and despots" (op.cit., p.
259).
87
Ibid., p. 260.
88
Ibid., p. 262.
89
Ibid., p. 263.
90
Ibid., p. 274.
91
Ibid., p. 276.
92
Ibid., p. 276. "Although he is neither able to rule himself, he tries to rule the others, so that he looks like a sick
man, who, instead of staying at home, must lead his life fighting and competing with athletes".(op.cit., p.p. 277278). "Although he does not look like that, he is a very tyrant, in fact, a very slave, he mostly fawns over and
submits, flattering the worst people. Obviously, he cannot satisfy his passions; in the eyes of those who can see
his soul through he is obviously poor; all through his life he is filled with fear and leads his lifetime
overburdened with worries, unrest and troubles." (op.cit., p. 278).
83
84

Justice and Dushan's Legislature

307

perverted form of rule it belongs. Timocracy, oligarchy, democracy and tyranny, as


perverted forms of a state, are ordered as per the degree of deviation from the perfect, i.e.
fully righteous state. Even at first glance it is obvious that Dushan's estate monarchy
differs from tyranny, from democracy and from oligarchy as well. As for its organization,
basic structural elements, particular purposes and goals, principal functions of the
members of the estate and characteristics of their members, it approaches Plato's
timocracy (timarchy), which means that it represents the least perverted form of rule.
Thus, Dushan's estate monarchy proves itself partly as a righteous and partly as an
unrighteous state. The history of Serbia in Dushan's times was not quite a "land of
happiness" (Hegel). After all, it is also in the history of the world that, "periods of
happiness (i.e. periods of harmony M.P.) are empty leaves in it" (Hegel).
Now, I am supposed to show to which extent that reasonable (i.e. idea/justice/) has
come into the external existence and in which forms, occurrences and images it has
appeared.
The purpose and the goal of the Serbian medieval state under Dushan were
accomplishment of the idea of the utmost good for both all the Serbs and the rest of the
population involved. The idea of the utmost good should be understood in a relative, but
not absolute manner. Economic, political and cultural conditions and international
circumstances did not offer opportunities to accomplish the idea of the utmost good in an
absolute sense, to equally provide happy life for all, high degree of freedom and human
dignity. This is not attained even by the today's, modern and the most developed
countries.
Particular purposes and goals of Dushan's Serbia were to provide conditions for legal
security and peace. Hence, the principal functions of that state were those of military and
court nature93. In view of the degree of development of the society, the estate monarchy
was the most appropriate form of a state of that time. If it did not equally provide
freedom, equality and social justice for all, which was not even possible, the equality of
members of each estate was fixed by the legislature. Situational justice was established
by Dushan's Code. The principle of equality was applied to the members of the ruling
estates, and the principle of discrimination towards the dependent, subordinated estate.
Naturally, this did not exclude the principle of equality for the members of the
subordinated estate within their mutual relations. And that was the utmost degree of
justice that could have been attained in the Middle Ages. Should Dushan's estate
monarchy be observed in a process, then it is "not a lengthy crime () but a phase of
social evolution"94. It was an objective expression of social needs, performing, in
addition to other things, numerous civilizatory and cultural functions" (Taranovski).
From the standpoint of this paper, of no importance is the question whether the
process of establishing Dushan's estate monarchy was completed or if it was still, as
regards the dependent estate, "under establishing"95.
To understand the situational justice, as a particular ideological form of justice in
Dushan's Serbia, it is necessary to be well acquainted with all the moments of the then
93

See: Teodor Taranovski, (The History of the Serbian Law in the Nemanji-Dynasty State), pp. 40, 675.
Ibid., p. 30.
95
Ibid., p. 30
94

308

M. POPOVI

social structure, i.e. estates, their social and law status. Estates are social groups, which,
in modern science, together with castes oppose layers and social classes96. They are
constituted based on the position in the hierarchy of the social power. Taranovski
considers them as particular social classes: "Estate, () is nothing but a social class, only
one consolidated and precisely regulated under the law regulations, which have
converted factual demarcation lines among the classes into non-political law boundaries
and class benefits and burdens into estate rights and responsibilities"97.
The estate structure in the medieval Serbia, as, after all, the case is in other states, is
an expression and consequence of "mutual dependence between the military and
economic performance"98. In that case, military factors essentially impact the evolution of
estate society, particularly affecting "changes in the military structure".
Privileged estates in Dushan's Serbia were secular lords and the clergy. The secular
lords were "military estate by profession"99. Their basic legal duty was military service
("to wage wars under law", Article 42 of Dushan's Code). In this element, the secular
lords are similar to the ruler assistants in Plato's perfect state. In addition to the above
duty, there was also a duty of paying soa, a kind of direct tax on land, which was a
"straightforward expression of obedience and subjugation to the ruler"100. Other duties of
the secular lords were of less importance. One of these was guarding the roads (Article
157 of Dushan's Code) and hills (Article 158 of Dushan's Code). Such a duty, however,
was not performed directly by the secular lords, but through their subjects who lived on
their estates. Another duty of such nature was that of court service, indirect testimony on
which is Article 51 of Dushan's Code: "And he who gives a son or brother to the palace,
and the emperor asks him, should I believe him, and he says, believe as you believe to
me, if he does any evil, he is to pay who gave him; if he who has to do services at the
palace, as they are done at the emperor's palace, makes whatever mistake, he is to pay
himself"101. Responsibilities of the secular lords at the palace services consisted of their
helping the ruler in his legal activities: court, administrative and legislative. Then, in case
of need, which occurred frequently, "the lords personnel at the palace", as Taranovksi
says, had additional military function "both for his (the ruler M.P.) personal protection
and as a core of the army in case of campaign"102.
The principal duty of the secular lords, that military, is in correlation with their main
right a title to the land (heritage). That they could fully devote themselves to the
military profession, the lords had the title to the land, the so-called direct property
(dominium directum), not burdened by tributes and unpaid labour. Speaking of it in a
striking manner is Article 42 of Dushan's Code: "And all the heritages to be free from all
96

See: Dr. Milovan Mitrovi, Dr. Milan Tripkovi, Dr. Dragan Kokovi, Sociologija (Sociology), Beograd,
Nauna knjiga, 1987, p. 151.
97
See: Teodor Taranovski, op.cit., p. 29. "In short, estates are classes into which the people in a state is divided
based on differences in rights and legal duties. That difference is hereditary in the estate structure, so that an
individual according to the general rule must remain for life in the estate he was born in".
98
Ibid., p. 34.
99
Ibid., p. 45.
100
Ibid ., p. 54.
101
See: Zakonik cara Stefana Duana 1349 i 1354 (Dushna's Code of 1349 and 1254), translated and published
by Nikola Radoji, Beograd, SANU, 1960, p. 103.
102
See: Teodor Taranovski, The Histroy of the Serbian Law in the Nemanji-Dynasty State, p. 62.

Justice and Dushan's Legislature

309

unpaid labour and tributes to my empirorship, except to pay soa and wage wars under
law"103. It is because of that that this form of land property is called a free heritage. The
ruler had a supreme property (dominium eminens), while that of the dependent
population was a property to use (dominium utile), subordinated heritage.
Untouchableness of free heritage is guaranteed under Dushan's Code: "The lords and
gentry, residents of the state of my emperorship, Serbs and Greeks, whatever to whom
my emperorship has given as heritage and in chrysobulls, and in their possession to this
state parliament, heritages to be safe" (Article 39)104. And all the chrysobulls and
prostagmas, which my emperorship has given to whoever and which to whoever will
give, and those heritages to be safe, as of previous ortodox emperors, to be free with
them, or to give to the Church, or to leave for the soul, or to sell to whoever" (Article
40)105. The guarantee of the untouchableness of the free heritage is reinforced by the
provision contained in Article 43 of Dushan's Code: "And master emperor, or king, or
lady empress shall not be authorized to forcibly take the heritage from whoever, to buy
from or exchange heritage with whoever, unless he himself agrees"106. Thus, the
emperor's power was restrictted in this field.
From the situational justice point of view, it is essential here to point out that legal
equality among all the members of the secular lords has been established, both in view of
the rights and duties. There are several exceptions to this principle, which do not bring
into question the very principle. Namely, Dushan's Code takes over, by means of
chrysobulls and agreements in the 13th century, the already established division of secular
nobility to high and low. Thus, for example, Article 12 reads: "That the lord shall not be
authorized, neither low nor high, nor whoever, to hold back or prevent his people, or
other merchants, not to go to the emperor's marketplace, but each to go freely"107, and
Article 136: "The letter of my emperorship to be heard where it comes, or of lady
empress, or of king, or of nobility, high and low"108. High nobility represented only the
"honorary upper layer" in the secular lords, but not "certain particularly privileged estate
order"109. With reference to the members of low nobility, the members of high nobility
had a "privilege", stipulated under Article 61 of Dushan's Code: "A high lord to be
summoned by a judge's letter, the others with a seal"110. As for the composition of the
jury, there is a difference in the court procedure between the high and low nobility:
"What was the law of my emperoroship's grandfather, saint king, that high lords shall be
the jury to high lords, to middle people according to their company, to villeins their
company shall be the jury; and no relatives and malicious persons shall be in the jury"111
(Article 152). As it has already been pointed out in this country, the principle in effect in

103

See: Dushan's Code of 1349 and 1354, translated and published by Nikola Radoji, p. 100.
Ibid., p. 99.
105
Ibid., pp. 99-100.
106
Ibid., p. 100.
107
Ibid., p. 123.
108
Ibid., p. 126.
109
See: Teodor Taranovski, The History of the Serbian Law in the Nemanji-Dynasty State, p. 38.
110
See: Dushan's Code of 1349 and 1354, translated and published by Nikola Radoji, p. 107.
111
Ibid., p. 130.
104

310

M. POPOVI

the Middle Ages was "peer to peer to judge"112.


Belonging to the secular lords were also proniars. Their principal legal duty was that
military, as was the duty of the rest of secular lords. The name "proniars" was given to
them because they were holders and beneficiaries of pronias. A pronia is a law institution
taken over from the Byzantine law. The first mention of it dates back in 1300 in a
chrysobull of king Milutin113. By the look of it, it existed in the medieval Serbia much
earlier than the above mentioned year. Pronia was a state-owned field estate. It was
granted to brave people for life, who probably lived in the borderline area of the Serbian
state, border guards, without a title to alienate (ius abutendi). Article 59 of Dushan's
Code reads: "No one shall be authorized either to sell or to buy pronia, he who has no
heritage; out of pronia land no one shall be authorized to grant to the Church, if he does,
it shall not be valid"114. It is in these elements that it differed from the heritage. From the
law point of view it could not be inherited, in contrast to the heritage, but probably "there
existed factual succession"115. From the standpoint of the topic I am dealing with, it is
essential to point out that, as regards the estate point of view, there were no differences
between proniars and the rest of the secular lords. The fact that proniars were more
closely connected with the state, due to their permanent military service (hence the
proniars were probably border guards, as was also claimed by Stojan Novakovi116), was
irrelevant from the estate point of view.
That the origin of the secular lords in the medieval Serbia was connected with the
military factor, as a prevailing one, was shown by Taranovski. After all, it was military
factor that also played a deciding role in the origin of other medieval states. Taranovski
assumes that the Serbian state as well, has originated due to the "energy of certain
military undertakers who gathered a group of devoted and faithful military companions
around themselves"117. Having become rulers, they granted estates to the "devoted and
faithful military companions" (the so-called company), their principal obligation still
being "to wage wars". This is how the secular lords come into being, "combining military
services with large estates"118. Although it was with the advent of time that the institution
of lords stretched beyond the company circle, the company remained a "genetic core of
the lords"119. That the company also existed in Serbia, as an indirect testimony may serve
the right of the ruler, stipulated under Article 48 of Dushan's Code, "to take a horse and
arms of the dead lord"120. From this paper point of view, it is irrelevant that, with the
spreading of the Serbian state, coast and Greek lords (the origin of which differed from
that of the Serbian lords) were, in addition to the Rascian lords, also a part of the secular
lords.

112

See: Teodor Taranovski, The Histroy of the Serbian Law in the Nemanji-Dynasty State, p. 38.
Ibid., p. 62.
See: Dushan's Code of 1349 and 1354, translated and published by Nikola Radoji, p. 106.
115
See: Teodor Taranovski, The Histroy of the Serbian Law in the Nemanji-Dynasty State, p. 66.
116
See: Stojan Novakovi, Stara srpska vojska (Old Serbian Army) (separately printed from Ratnik) Beograd,
1983, p. 75.
117
See: Teodor Taranovski, The History of the Serbian Law in the Nemanji-Dynasty State, p. 75.
118
Ibid., p. 76.
119
Ibid., p. 76.
120
Ibid., p. 77.
113
114

Justice and Dushan's Legislature

311

Members of the secular lords were timocratic people, in the meaning attributed to
them by Plato. Their basic feature was ambition, a wish to compete and conquer. Plato
named timocracy ambitious governmental structure and timocratic people, suited for that
structure, ambitious people. Timocratic people long for possessing both estates and
wealth in general. Working on their estates should be, according to Plato, "peasants
without rights". This is an essential difference between them and the assistants to rulers
in Plato's perfect state. A timocratic man is full of arrogance, "desirous of power and
honours", justifying this by "his war deeds and activities referring to the war"121. On that
what the secular lords, as a military estate, looked like under emperor Dushan, and what
their role was in spreading the territory of the medieval Serbian state, writes Georgije
Ostrogorski in his work Dushan and His Lords in Fighting Byzantium. In the subject
work he says that "principal power which encouraged them to conquer Byzantine
countries was () a wish for expansion of the Serbian lords122. That was not only under
Dushan, "but long ago before Dushan". Both at the time he was stabilizing his position
and when he became powerful, war campaigns were not "undertaken out of his
selfishness, but because of the lords wishing further expansion and new countries"123.
The second ruling estate in Dushan's Serbia was the clergy. While the secular lords,
as a rule, were reproduced by succession, ecclesiastical titles were acquired by choice for
life. It is well-known what and how important was the role of the Church in Dushan's
Serbia. As a religious community, it was independent, "resembling a state", according to
Taranovski, having originaire power in the religious field124. As a special corporation, it
was exempted by the state from the competences of state courts. Large landed properties,
possessed by the Church, resulted from the ruler's gifts, and from the gifts of pious
private persons as well. The Church had a full right of possession to the land. The
Church property was untouchable and guaranteed by chrysobulls, also before Dushan,
issued to churches and monasteries. It enjoyed economic immunity. In contrast to the
secular lords, the Church did not pay soa and was not obliged to "wage wars". It was
exempted from duties to repair and guard cities and had, as we have already said, court
immunity. Estate rights of the Church, i.e. the clergy, were accompanied by the
corresponding obligations. Provided by the Church were spiritual needs of the state and
other estates. The Church was a centre and champion of culture and education. Care for
nation's health and nourishment, particularly in times of famine, was one of its concerns.
It supported the poor and disabled people, widows and orphans. The clergy was divided
into higher (large estate owners) and regular clergy (monks and parish clergymen
/priests/). The parish clergymen composed the lower ecclesiastical estate. They were

121

See: Plato, Drava (State), p. 243.


See: Georgije Ostrogorski: Duan i njegova vlastela u borbi sa Vizantijom (Dushan and his Nobility in
Fighting Byzantium), Zbornik u ast este strogodinjice Zakona cara Duana, I, Beograd, SANU, 1951, p. 80.
123
Ibid., p. 82. "He (Dushan M.P.) has landed his most telling blow to the Byzantine lords by depriving many
representatives of the Byzantine ruling layer of their positions and estates, granting them to his collaborators,
who inspired his policy of conquest and who reaped his fruits" (p. 86). "The question of cities meant () the
question of positions and estates. Those positions and estates were lost by the Byzantine religious and feudal
lords and granted to the Serbian lords, actual inspirers and promoters of the wars of conquest against
Byzantium, which Dushan , like his predecessors, waged, first of all, to their interests" (p. 86).
124
See: Teodor Taranovski, The Histroy of the Serbian Law in the Nemanji-Dynasty State, p. 29.
122

312

M. POPOVI

obliged to pay patrimonial tribute (bir and vrhovina).


The third estate was composed of the dependent population. Certain of our historians,
particularly Stojan Novakovi, based on provisions contained in Articles: 53, 55, 85, 94
and 106 of Dushan's Code, pointed out that the term villein referred to the whole
population, except the secular lords and the clergy. Taranovski, however, thinks, citing
Article 98 of Dushan's Code, that the term villein does not cover the whole "non-lords
population, but one narrower circle, the peasants"125. Taranovski here thinks of peasants
farmers, merophs, in Dushan's Code terminology. There were three kinds of them:
those of the ruler, Church and lords, depending on the fact whether the land they worked
on was that the ruler, Church or lords. They were entitled to use it (dominium utile), i.e.
it was a subordinated heritage (heritage under burden) which was hereditary. It was
under the direct property (dominum directum), consisting of using the fruits of the land,
under the burden of obligations (unpaid labour and tributes) in favour of the direct owner
of the land (the ruler, Church, secular lords). It was just that the hierarchical structure of
the land ownership corresponds to the hierarchical estate structure of Dushan's Serbia. It
is important to mention that merophs did not enjoy the freedom of movement, that they
were bound to the land, which means that they were private subjects. In addition to
merophs, dependent population also involved sokalniks (most of them worked in a kind
of "home industry" /Taranovski/) and craftsmen (bricklayers, blacksmiths, tanners,
potters, tailors, etc.). Alike merophs, they did farming, but also practiced the above
mentioned additional jobs. That is why their unpaid labour and tributes, they owed to the
direct owners, were less than those of merophs. The Vlachs were also a constituent part
of the dependent population. They were cattle breeders obliged to pay grass tribute to the
owners of free heritages, the pasture of which they used to graze cattle, or depending on
the type of cattle breeding, they had some other obligations. Their legal position was
basically the same as that of merophs. Distinguished from the Vlachs should be
shepherds from merophs circles, "who worked as paid servants or, in addition to farming,
did shepherds unpaid labour"126. They were paid in kind, and in the event of cattle lost
they were freed from obligations. Of all the layers of the dependent population, otroks
(not free or slaves) were in the gravest position. They were the property of the free
heritage holders. Like agrarian slaves, the otroks also existed in times preceding Dushan's
Code, to which numerous chrysobulls point to. In addition to the work on the land, they
did other jobs, such as personal servants and escort for the lord when on the way. In
addition to the agrarian, there were also palace slaves, on the legal status of which there
are no reliable testimonies. Finally, a part of the third estate (of dependent population)
were city dwellers. If coastal cities were exempted, i.e. city dwellers in them, of which
Dushan's Code even does not make any mention, as well as the conquered Greek cities,
the privileges of which, granted to them by the Byzantine emperors, were recognized by
the Serbian rulers to go on living in them, the city dwellers of the cities in the provinces
of Serbia were a "factual category of the city population" composed "of different estate
elements"127. Dushan's Code contains provisions on cities, but not on city dwellers, first
125

Ibid., p. 79.
Ibid., p. 113.
127
Ibid., p. 126.
126

Justice and Dushan's Legislature

313

of all, from the military, but from the economic point of view as well (free arrival to
marketplaces, freedom of markets, performance of goldsmith craft). Although the city
dwellers had certain privileges, they did not compose a particular estate in Dushan's
Serbia.
The instance of the dependent population, as the third estate, although very
heterogeneous, may show the principle of situational justice, the ruling principle in
Dushan's estate monarchy. The rights and obligations of the dependent population are in
direct correspondence with their role in the society. Since the military function (along
with that of the court) was the principal function in the Middle Ages, it was natural that
agrarian, cattle-breeding, artisanal, etc. jobs would be less valued and that the dependent
population would live under the burden of different obligations. It was only in that
manner that the privileged estates could devote their off-time to the principal functions in
the state. It was, therefore, that the rights of the dependent population were measured
according to their merits, i.e. according to their position (rank) in Dushan's Serbia. On
the other hand, inside each layer of the dependent population, the same degree of
equality, which was the central part of the justice, was provided by Dushan's Code to all
the members of the subject layers. The members of the ruling estate could not overstep
the threshold of the established rights and obligations of the dependent population. Legal
status of the dependent population was guaranteed by Dushan's code. Witnessing on that,
in addition to other things, is one provision from Article 139: "No lord shall be
authorized anything under the law against merophs of my emperorship, except that what
my emperorship has put down in the law, which is to provide him with the unpaid labour.
If he does anything illegal to him, my emperorship orders that each meroph shall be
authorized to be engaged in a lawsuit with his master, or with my emperorship, or with
the lady empress, or with the Church, or with the lords of my emperorship, or with
whosoever, that no one shall be authorized to keep him from the court of my
emperorship, but that the judges shall judge him according to justice, and if meroph wins
the lawsuit against his master, the judge of my emperorship shall guarantee him how the
master shall pay all to the meroph in due time, and then that that master shall not be
authorized to do any evil to the meroph"128. There are no reliable facts to which extent
this provision, pursuant to which personal and property freedom of the dependent
population was guaranteed, was applied in the court practice. But its very existence, even
if not applied, that it was fictitious, is, in view of the times it appeared in, of great
significance.
Finally, the very monarchic moment in the state is primarily connected with the
military obligation, i.e. function, which perfectly fits into the timocratic form of rule. The
ruler's obligation was to organize military forces and to command them (which was his
right). Even in this field, his power was restricted, since the army, as it has already been
pointed out, was estate-based. It should always be kept in mind that there "existed certain
power competition"129 between the ruler's power and that of the privileged estates (in
military questions of the secular lords). In addition, the ruler was a titular of the supreme
title to the land (dominium eminens). From the supreme property, as a real right, he
128
129

See: Dushan's Code of 1349 and 1354, translated and published by Nikola Radoji, pp. 126-127.
See: Teodor Taranovski, The Histroy of the Serbian Law in the Nemanji-Dynasty State, p. 187.

314

M. POPOVI

ceded direct property (dominium directum) to the secular lords and the clergy, and the
property to use (dominium utile) to the dependent population. His power over the land
was "his primary right", and that over the people "secondary"130. Consequently, the
power over the people was derived from his real title to the land. His power was direct
towards the privileged estates, in the fields where those estates had obligations towards
him, and towards the dependent population it was patrimonial.
Law-creative activity of the Serbian rulers was, before emperor Dushan, of a
particular character. Testimonies on that are chrysobulls. It was only under emperor
Dushan, autocrat, which is one of the trait of his title (Greek: autokrator), that the ruler's
law activity took a legislative form. Legislative activity in the Middle Ages was
exclusively connected with the empire131. Emperor Dushan put his signature as the
emperor of Serbs and Romania (i.e. Byzantium), so as to provide himself with the dignity
of a successor to the Roman Empire. Mostly, he wrote in Greek, as a worldwide
language, but not in Serbian. Otherwise, legislature was a common function of emperor
Dushan and the Parliament.
The ruler took part in the judiciary power as well (for example, in lawsuits pertaining
to the Church land /Article 78 of Dushan's Code/) or through the court at his palace (for
example, in criminal acts done at the palace /Article 175 of Dushan's Code/).
Administrative power of the ruler, in addition to that military, which, pursuant to the
tripartite division of power, falls into the administrative power, is made evident through
the power of the ruler's direct organs (cephalias) which, viewed from the personnel
standpoint, originated from the secular nobility (the so-called "security police"
/Taranovski/) and through the financial power. In addition to the "subordinated powers"
(cephalias), there were also "mediating powers" (privileged estate), which "mediated
between the ruler and the population"132. The germs of the administrative power,
understood in a narrower sense, like clerks (bureaucracy), as a professional part of the
governmental machinery, hardly existed.
What was the character of Dushan's estate monarchy? Was it constitutional or
absolute or monarchy sui generis? No doubt that it was not absolute monarchy. The
monarch, in an absolute monarchy, is not only a sovereign personality (personality
having exceptional privileges which put him above the law, politically and legally not
responsible personality), but he is also a sovereign (supreme) organ. Dushan's power,
however, was restricted by the existence of other organs he shared the power with. His
power was restricted both on the extrinsic and on the intrinsic side. On the extrinsic side,
by the Christian law he had to respect. On the intrinsic side, by the power of the secular
lords and the Church. The legislative power was restricted by the Parliament, regardless
of the fact that in a number of provisions of Dushan's Code it was stipulated that the
Code was emperor's. A mention has already been made that even his military power was
restricted due to the estate character of the army. That the ruler's judiciary power was
also restricted can be seen not only from the fact that it was bound by the Code, but also

130

Ibid., p. 186.
Se: Teodor Taranovski, Pravo drave na zakonodavtsvo ( The Right of a State to Legilsature), iiev
zbornik, Zagreb, 1929, pp. 371-379.
132
See: Teodor Taranovski, The History of the Serbian Law in the Nemanji-Dynasty State, p. 207.
131

Justice and Dushan's Legislature

315

from the fact that there existed different courts, in addition to that emperor's and the
palace court (church court, patrimonial court, estate court, /coastal and Greek cities/,
special court for foreign residents in the country, mixed court between the residents of
Dubrovnik and the Serbs, state court and military court, as a subgroup of the state court).
Finally, the administrative power of the ruler was also restricted. Financial power, as a
part of the administrative power, was restricted by the "economic immunity"
(Taranovski) of the privileged estates. In the remaining part, administrative power was
restricted through the secular power, the representatives of which made personnel
substratum of the "subordinated" and "mediating" power. A thesis that Dushan's
monarchy was, to a certain extent, a constitutive monarchy could be, partly, defended.
For, considered in a material sense, Dushan's Code also contained provisions of the
constitutional character. Since Dushan's Code is one of the rare examples of the universal
codification, it is completely evident that contained within it were also provisions of the
constitutional character. The provisions of the constitutional character are those dealing
with the organization of the state and the competence of the central governmental organs
(emperor and parliament). Also, the provisions relative to the basics of the social and
economic structure and, first of all, to the ownership relations, which are a legal
expression of the principal economic relations are of the constitutional character as well.
Finally, norms-principles of the criminal law and the court procedure, as well as of the
court organization, make a component part of the constitution in the material sense. Since
Dushan's Code was binding for emperor Dushan himself (a question is to what extent
factually, but normatively, yes), it seems acceptable to partly consider Dushan's
monarchy as a constitutional monarchy. In any event, as a estate monarchy, it represented
a form of a restricted, but not absolute monarchy, since the ruler's power was restricted
by the estate rights of the secular lords and the clergy.
I hope that I have shown that Dushan's estate monarchy was a well-organized state.
Due to the military function as a principal one, the secular estate, together with the
monarch, as a military estate, had a dominant influence and power in it, which was,
because of military needs, economically provided (free heritage), which rather resembled
the timarchy of Plato as a form of rule the least far from the perfect (fully righteous)
state. As for the dependent population, particularly merophs, titulars of the subordinted
heritages, their legal status, especially due to the lack in labour, was not worse than the
position of that category of population in other European countries. This also, mutatis
mutandis, refers to other layers of the population. Dushan's estate monarchy enabled
culture to flourish: people's literature, fresco painting, architecture If "buildings", as
reported by Jireek, "are the most magnificent monument of each previous cultural
period", then there are in Dushan's Serbia "a considerable number of great and beautiful
churches which speak for themselves on the one-time riches of the country and reign and
people's sense and love for art"133. As for the culture, the Serbian medieval state can be
freely said to have not lagged behind or at least to have not significantly lagged behind
the developed countries of the Catholic West.
133
See: Konstantin Jireek, Istorija Srba, (The Histroy of Serbs), (Yu edition), translated and supplemented by
Jovan Radonji, Book II (cultural history), second revised and supplemented edition, Beograd, Nauna knjiga,
1952, p. 218.

316

M. POPOVI

2. Aristotle's Justice and Dushan's Estate Monarchy


Aristotle, disciple of Plato, universal genius of the classical ages, along with Hegel
certainly the most versatile and deepest philosopher of all ages, has formulated, in his
work Nicomachean Ethics, classical teaching on justice. Aristotle's justice is the second
and more recognizable constituent of justice in Dushan's legislature.
a) General Justice and Special Justices
Like Plato, Aristotle puts justice inside the organized community, state, as "the most
powerful" of all communities134. Its purpose is, like with Plato, accomplishment of the
most supreme good. The state is, says Aristotle, "more important than an individual"135.
Only "a beast or God" can live outside it . As a man "without virtue is the most perverted
and the most splendid being", so a state "without a law and justice is the worst of all
because the armed injustice is something the worst"136. Thus, justice is with Aristotle by
fate connected with the state, as the case is with Plato. It is "a need of the state, because
justice makes a structure of the state community, and its function is to decide what is
righteous"137.
As we can see, Aristotle has explained in Politics his opinion of justice in grosso
modo. However, in Nicomachean Ethics, the work which "is one of his most original"138,
combining Plato's and Pythagorean teaching139, with his own working out, Aristotle has
explained, viewed from the formal standpoint, a teaching on justice unsurpassable to
date.
Like Plato, Aristotle understands justice as supreme and total virtue "which is almost
equal to the very bliss"140. Since ethics is a teaching on the supreme good, there is a
permanent unity of ethics and politics, as with Plato. For, as I have already pointed out,
each state is the accomplishment of the supreme good. Under the general justice Aristotle
understands the rule of law, i.e. performance pursuant to the law, legality. He says:
"Since the illegal man has proved himself to be unrighteous, and the legal man to be
righteous, it is crystal-clear that all legal things are somehow righteous as well, because
all the things that are set up based on legislature, they are legal, so that we say that each
of them individually is also righteous. The laws regulate all things, striving for common
benefit, either for all or for those best or for the powerful (according to strength) or
whatever similar; so that in a way we name righteous all the things which create and keep
bliss and its component parts in the state community"141. Here, naturally, it should be
134

See: Aristotle, Politika (Politics), foreword by Milo N. uri, third edition, Beograd, BIGZ, 1975, p. 3
Ibid., p. 5.
Ibid., p. 6.
137
Ibid., p. 6.
138
See: Danilo Pejovi, Aristotelova praktina filozofija i etika (Aristotle's Practical Philosophy and Ethics), in
the book Aristotel, Nikomahova etika (Nicomachenan Ethics, foreword and philosophical revision by Danilo
Pejovi, Zagreb, Globus and Sveuilina naklada Liber, 1988, p. V.
139
See: Giorgio del Vecchio, Pravo, pravda i drava (Law, Justice and State), (Yugoslav edition) treatises on
the philosophy of law with a foreword on idealism G. del Vecchio by Dr. ore Tasi, Beograd, Geca Kon,
1940, pp. 12, 18-22.
140
See: Danilo Pejovi, Aristotelova praktina filozofija i etika (Aristotle's Practical Philosophy and Ethics), p.
XIII.
141
See: Aristotle, Nicomachean Ethics, p. 89.
135
136

Justice and Dushan's Legislature

317

kept in mind that Aristotle under the law does not understand a mere state creation, but
an act based on the nature of the things, i.e. idea, reason. Thus, sophistic disagreement
between nomos and physis was overcome, and discussion on justice put into the
forefront. General justice is named "perfect strength" by Aristotle, and he points out that
"all the strengths are collected"142 in it. He says that "neither the evening star nor the
morning star are so beautiful" like justice.
In addition to the general, Aristotle singles out two particular kinds of justices as well:
distributive and corrective or synalagmatic. Distributive justice appears in the field of public
law. It is demonstrated in the relations of the state and individuals. It is applied "in
distributions of honours and money or other things that are divisible among the partners of
the state union (because one against the other can be equal or unequal in them)"143. It means
that in the division each obtains according to his contribution, i.e. merit, which confirms the
principle of equality (proportional equality). Corrective or synalagmaic justice is, on the
other hand, "that what makes corrections in mutual relations"144. This justice appears in the
field of private law. Instead of geometric proportion characteristic of the distributive justice,
corrective or synalagmatic justice features arithmetic proportion, principle of equivalency.
While the distributive justice is dispensed by the legislator, corrective justice is dispensed
by the judge when resolving disputes and when pronouncing sanctions for the delicts done.
Since Aristotle distinguishes between the willing (agreed upon) and unwilling agreements
(relations arising from a delict), it was properly done by Del Vecchio when he distinguished
commutative justice ("relations of exchange according to a certain measure") and judiciary
justice (relations arising from a delict "immediately after in the form of a court
proceedings") as subgroups of the corrective or synalagmatic justices145. While
commutative justice provides norms to the very contractual parties, so that "correcting
action of the judge may not be necessary", judiciary justice "should, against the will of one
of the two parties, correct some unjustly occurred damage"146.
Out of these two justices, distributive and corrective or synalagmatic, distributive
justice is "the original form of justice"147. For, corrective or synalagmatic justice
"supposes", according to Radbruch, "an act of the distributive justice which provided
equality, possibility of equal communications, equal status to the participants"148.
b) General Justice and Dushan's Code
If Aristotle's general justice is understood as a legal justice, i.e. as application of the law,
as legality, then Dushan's Code expresses, proves and affirms it in the best possible manner.
From the axiological standpoint, the most important provisions of Dushan's Code are
contained in Articles 171 and 172, which I have already mentioned. Regardless of being
taken over from the Byzantine law, they are of so high rank that could be found in the
142

Ibid., p. 89.
Ibid., p. 92.
144
Ibid., p. 92.
145
See: Giorgio del Vecchio, op.cit., p. 24.
146
Ibid., p. 24.
147
See: Gustav Radbruch, Filozofija prava (The Philosophy of Law), (Yu edition), foreword by Dr. Stevan
Vraar, Radbruhovo filozofskopravno stanovite, Beograd, Nolit, 1980, p. 47.
148
Ibid., p. 47.
143

318

M. POPOVI

modern law as well. It results from Dushan's Code that law and justice must be observed,
while the obligations of judges are "to judge pursuant to the law" but not "for fear of my
emperorship". In totalitarian structures, featuring the 20th century, neither law nor justice,
nor court actually do not represent anything but ideological haziness covering all the
society that the usurping regimes should be provided with the false splendour and
legitimacy. Whether the provisions contained in Articles 171 and 172 of Dushan's Code
were only declarative or realistic, it is hard, nowadays, to safely say because of a so long
time passed. Missing is reliable data on the court practice of Dushan's times. The
documents available do not provide evidence on the subject matter, while more indirect
information is poor and insufficiently reliable. I suppose that performance of judges,
because of the increased authority of emperor Dushan, reinforced due to his great
military successes, regardless of legal orders, was still burdened "for fear of my
emperorship". Even if they were only declarative, the above mentioned provisions of
Dushan's Code, they represent a high law outcome of Dushan's Serbia.
A high law achievement is also that of the provision contained in Article 105 of
Dushan's Code: "Emperor's letters, brought before the judges for whatever reason, and
which are refuted by the code of my emperorship, whatever letters I have written, refuted by
the court, to be taken by the judges and be brought before my emperorship"149. Though I
question myself here as well, when "emperor's letters (...) refuted by the court", how the
judge went "before my emperorship", if there were such cases, and how he returned and
whether he reached home "safe and sound", without any consequences for himself, his rank,
his property and his household. In any case, on the normative plan, the provision of the
subject article was one of the guarantees for court independence and the principle of
legality.
Whether adoption of Aristotle's general justice, i.e. the principle of the legality in
Dushan's Code, in addition to the decisive influence of the Byzantine law, was affected
by other sources as well, such as "western", and if there was "mediating" role of
Dubrovnik"150, is of irrelevance from the point of view of the subject discussed herewith.
Otherwise, Taranovski has established in his History of the Serbian Law in the
Nemanji-Dynasty Serbia that Dushan's Code "explicitly proclaims the principle of
legality" in view of "regulating the judiciary", "norming estate and social relations " and
"regulation of the administration performance of the state"151 so that there is no need to
discuss the subject.
c) Distributive Justice and Dushan's Code
Since Dushan's Code predominantly contains provisions of public law character, it is
obvious that distributive justice, applied in distribution of honours and goods, is
represented in it to a great extent.
In accordance with the distributive justice principle, distributed to the individuals by
the state are honours and goods in proportion with their contributions to the state. That
the distributive justice is also represented in Dushan's Code was observed by Taranovski,
149

See: Dushan's Code of 1349 and 1354, translated and published by Nikola Radoji, p. 119.
See: Teodor Taranovski, The History of the Serbian Law in the Nemanji-Dynasty State, pp. 299-300.
151
Ibid., pp. 294-296.
150

Justice and Dushan's Legislature

319

although he followed another course, empiric and positivistic: "Privileges increase or


decrease, but always come as the consequences of duties, thus like posterius with
reference to them, while duties remain as a basis of the governmental structure, as its
prius"152. The rights are, therefore, something secondary, originated and derived from
duties, which come to the forefront. Since the military function in Dushan's Serbia was a
primary function, it is quite natural that the secular lords, as a military estate, were
privileged. Out of their primary obligation to "wage wars", the secular lords were granted
a title to the land (dominium directum) and other rights by the state. Consequently, the
secular lords could require from the dependent population to fulfil only those obligations
which were stipulated under the Code. Testifying on that is, for example, Article 68 of
Dushan's Code: "The law to the merophs all over the country: in a week, for two days to
work for the proniar, and to give him emperor's perper a year, to mow grass for him one
day, as well as to do vineyard one day, and he who has no vineyard to have other jobs
done for one day, and what meroph has done to keep it all, and nothing more, against the
law, to be taken from him"153. Should the lord's obligation in the military service be
greater, he shall be granted more honours and rights. Thus, for example, Article 129 of
Dushan's Code stipulates: "In the army, in each one, voivodes to command as much as
the emperor, what they say to be obeyed, should anybody refuse to obey them in
anything, to be punished as well as those not obeying the emperor; and courts small and
great in the army to be judged by voivodes, and no one else"154. To what extent Dushan's
Code took care of fulfilment of obligations towards the state, and in connection with this
of the resulting privileges as well, Article 61, in addition to other articles, reads as
follows: "When a lord comes home from the war, or any other soldier, and if anybody
summons him to the court, he is to stay at home for three weeks, and then to go to the
court"155.
Since the clergy also had important obligations towards the state, which were highly
appreciated in those times, granted to them under the Code was also a significant
participation in the distribution of honours and goods, in real estates (dominium
directum) as well as in others, what I have already discussed.
The most important were the obligations of the emperor, particularly in the military
function of the state, so that is why the greatest honours and goods, economic (dominium
eminens and dominium directum) and others, were granted to him under the Code.
As for the dependent population: merophs farmers, Vlachs, cattle breeders, artisans
and others, no matter how much important jobs they did, their participation in the
distribution of honours and goods was proportionately lesser, since they did not belong to
the military estate, but it existed, anyway, both in economic field (dominium utile) and in
other areas.
There existed one more particular form of the distributive justice in Dushan's estate
monarchy, discussed by Leibniz. Leibniz's iustitia distributiva or aequitas, one of the
three subgroups of justice (the other two are iustitia commutativa and universalis) also

152

Ibid., p. 287.
See: Dushan's Code of 1349 and 1354, translated and published by Nikola Radoji, pp. 108-109.
154
Ibid., p. 126.
155
Ibid., p. 106.
153

320

M. POPOVI

contains in the subgroup suum quique tribuere a duty of beneficialness and charity,
which is provided for and regulated under Dushan's Code as well. Thus, for example,
Article 28 of Dushan's Code, which speaks of food for the poor, regulates: "With all the
churches the poor shall be fed, as is bequeathed by the founder, and he of the
metropolitans or bishops or priors who does not feed them up shall be removed from his
office156. Also, in Article 64 of Dushan's Code: "A poor hemp producer to be free like a
priest"157. Then, Article 73 of Dushan's Code stipulates: "A poor woman who is not able
to engage herself in a lawsuit or to answer, shall provide replacement, who will answer
for her"158. Recognized in this provision is the right of the poor, a law institution in the
modern procedural law. In the sense of this particular form of the distributive justice
(Leibniz's) also indicative is Article 179 of Dushan's Code: "Judges shall walk the
country, visiting their respective regions, and shall maintain the justice of the poor and
the wretched"159. Radoji thinks that this form of the distributive justice, which
corresponds to the philanthropic duties, here of churches and courts, also originates from
the Byzantine legislature, and even further back, from the Roman law160.
d) Corrective or Synalagamatic Justice and Dushan's Code
Out of the two corrective or synalagmatic justices (commutative and judiciary) in
regard of Dushan's Code, it is only the judiciary justice that can be presented. As I have
already said, commutative justice is applied in the civil law. However, Dushan's Code
only slightly contains provisions of the civil law since they are contained in Matthew
Blastaros' Abridged Syntagm, i.e. in the legal part of Dushan's codification. The judiciary
justice, however, is applied in the criminal law with, as Aristotle says, unwilling
agreements, i.e. legal relations arising from a delict. Hence, only the judiciary justice is
being made problematic here.
A question is being raised why Aristotle has placed the judiciary justice, as a criminal
justice, within the frame of the corrective or synalagmatic justice, i.e. private law justice,
but not distributive, i.e public law justice? For, criminal delicts do not offend only an
individual, but the state as well. A generally accepted standpoint today is that the
criminal law is a part of the public law. Aristotle's intention, however, was to reestablish,
by means of the court (criminal justice), "the disturbed balance between the injurer and
the injured", almost overseeing the difference "between the indemnity of a damage and
the penalty"161. Both Pufendorff and Vico have also observed this illogicality or
"anomaly"162, according to Del Vecchio.
While the distributive justice is determined by Dushan's Code itself, the criminal
justice is determined by the judge, by juging the cases arising from a delict. That is why
Aristotle says that "to go to the judge means to go to that what is righteous, for the

156

Ibid., p. 96.
Ibid., p. 107.
Ibid., p. 110.
159
Ibid., p. 137.
160
Ibid., p. 137. Radoji's note accompanying Article 179 of Dushan's Code.
161
See: Giorgio del Vecchio, op.cit., pp. 24-25.
162
Ibid., p. 25.
157
158

Justice and Dushan's Legislature

321

property of the judge is to be the very rightiousness"163.


In pronouncing criminal justice, the judge searches for the middle "between the loss and
the gain". Aristotle says: "If one is wounded and the other has wounded, or if one has killed
and the other is killed, then suffering and action are unequally distributed, so that the judge
strives, by penalty, to make equals, taking away from the gain"164. It is equality that is also
in question with the criminal justice, but not in geometrical (as with the distributive justice)
but arithmetic propotion (equality between the criminal delict and the penalty).
The simplest example of the criminal justice, which is considered primitive
nowadays, is the justice based on the talion principle, i.e. on vengeance, that is to say on
revenge. Thus, for example, Article 96 of Dushan's Code provides for: "He who is found
to have killed his father or mother or borther or a child of his, that killer shall be burned
on fire"165. There are cases in Dushan's Code in which the criminal justice is
demonstrated in returning to the previous conditions. Thus, for example, is the case of
the Latin heresy: "As for the Latin heresy, that has converted Christians to communion
by Host, to be reconverted to Orthodoxy, and if anybody is found not to hear that and
does not reconvert to Orthodoxy, shall be punished pursuant to the law of the holy
fathers" 166. Similarly, Article 159 of Dushan's Code regulates: "Purchasers, passing by
night, whereto they come to remain for the night, if not admitted by the ruler or the lord
of the village to spend the night in the village, pursuant to the emperor's law, as stipulated
under the law, if a traveller lose anything, that lord, and ruler and the village shall pay
everything because they did not admit them to the village"167. There are, here, elements
of collective (village) responsibility, which is, from the criminal law standpoint, of
importance. Sometimes, the intention of Dushan's Code, when pronouncing criminal
justice, is to establish equivalency between the delict done and the punishment, most
frequently in the form of money, according to the then- understanding. Thus, for
example, Article 99 of Dushan's Code regulates: "He who is found to have put a house or
a threshing floor, or straw, or hay on fire, that village shall hand that man over, if not,
that village shall pay what that man would have to pay"168.
The criminal law part of Dushan's Code, in view of the estate character of Dushan's
Serbia, has systematically carried out the difference between the delicts done by the
members of the privileged estates and the dependent population. For the same delict,
pronounced to the members of the plrivileged estates was milder penalty, while that to
the members of the dependent estate was more stiff. For example, Artcile 55 of Dushan's
Code regulates as follows: "And if a lord, or a member of gentry, swears at sebar, he
shall pay hundred perpers; if a villein swears at a lord or at a member of gentry, he shall

163

See: Aristotle, Nicomachean Ethics, p. 96.


Ibid., p. 30. "So it is generally said in such cases,even though the name itself is not suitable, like words
"gain" for that who injures and "loss" for the wounded; but when the suffered is being weighted, it is said loss
for one and gain for another. Therefore, that equal is the middle between the more and the less, while loss and
gain are more or less contrary; more good is less evil for the gain, while loss is opposition to that; that equal is
the middle between them, which is said to be righteous" (op.cit., pp. 95-96).
165
See: Dushan's Code of 1349 and 1354, translated and published by Nikola Radoji, p. 116.
166
Ibid., p. 90.
167
Ibid., p. 132.
168
Ibid., p. 117.
164

322

M. POPOVI

pay hundred perpers and be scorched"169. Dushan's Code makes a difference between the
lords and gentry in pronouncing justice for the same delicts. Thus, for example, for the
criminal act of offence, curse, Article 50 stipulates: "A lord who swears at or disgraces a
member of gentry, shall pay hunder perpers, and if a member of gentry swears at a lord,
he shall pay hunderd perpers and be beaten with sticks"170. Therefore, the principle of
equality, middle, equivalency, criminal justice is the same for the members of the same
layer, but different for the members of different layers of the same estate, particularly for
the members of the privileged and subordinated estates.
Most of the criminal law provisions of Dushan's Code were taken over from the
Byzantine legislature. Often, penalties were severe, closely related to the corporal
crippling and tortures. Hence, ceratain parts of Dushan's Code deviate from the criminal
justice. Thus, for example, Article 97 of Dushan's Code regulates: "He who is found to
have pulled out the beard of a lord or a good man, shall have both hands cut off"171.
CONCLUSION
Dushan's legislature, first and foremost Dushan's code, special attention to which I
have devoted here, that magnificent codification of the Serbian medieval law, also turned
out to be suitable for study from the philosophical point of view, first of all from that
axiological, from the justice standpoint, as a central law value.
Investigation of Dushan's Code, according to Plato's paradigm, has enabled me to
come out with a new thesis on Dushan's estate monarchy, as timocracy (timarchy), as the
least perverted form of reign with reference to Plato's perfectly righteous state. The truth
is that historians, all of them, long before me had found out that the military function of
the Serbian medieval state under Dushan was the principal one and that, because of that,
a privileged position both in economic and other fields was provided for the secular
lords, as a military estate, headed by the ruler, as a supreme military commander. The
historians, however, have not estimated Dushan's estate monarchy from the perfect and
perverted states point of view, i.e. from the axiological standpoint. Also, I have tried to
philosophically shed light on the facts conscientiously collected by the historians and to
show rationality in Dushan's legislature, particularly in Dushan's Code.
Investigation of Dushan's Code, according to Aristotle's paradigm, has enabled me to
come out with a new thesis on the situational justice, as a special form of ideological
justice. Aristotle's general justice, understood as dependence, is represented in Dushan's
Code to a high degree. The situational justice is, however, particularly demonstarted
through the distributive justice. This form of Aristotle's particular justice, which is
applied in distributing honours and goods based on merit, i.e. according to the rank,
position, is also represented in Dushan's Code and consistently carried out. As for the
judiciary or criminal justice, as subgroups of the corrective or synalagmatic justice, it is
evident that, in its pronouncing, there are deviations from Aristotle's middle, relative
equivalency, although there are examples, as I have shown, of its consistent application.
169

Ibid., p. 105.
Ibid., p. 103.
171
Ibid., p. 116.
170

Justice and Dushan's Legislature

323

In view of the time, which is middle of the 14th century, when universal codification
of the Serbian medieval law was carried out, I can conclude that higher form of justice
could neither have been achieved.
Added to the masterpieces of the Serbian medieval architecture, fresco painting,
national literature, may freely be Dushan's Code as well, as an expression of the powerful
spirit of the Serbian people. As I have already said at the beginning of this discussion, the
depth and dignity of Dushan's Code have been radiating through centuries and will do
that over the centuries to come.

PRAVDA I DUANOVO ZAKONODAVSTVO


Milijan Popovi
Navrilo se 650 godina od donoenja Duanovog Zakonika, zavrnog dela univerzalne
kodifikacije prava srednjovekovne Srbije, koja zajedno sa Skraenom Sintagmom Matije Vlastara i
tzv. Justinijanovim zakonom ini Duanovo zakonodavstvo.
Duanovo zakonodavstvo, a pre svega Duanov zakonik, propitivano je sa stanovita
aksiolokog, po Platonovoj i Aristotelovoj paradigmi. Takav pristup omoguio je da se utvrdi
umnost u Duanovom zakonodavstvu, umesto uvrivanja istorijske pojavnosti, to rade istoriari.
Duanova staleka monarhija bila je timokratija (timarhija), a to znai oblik drave koji
namanje odstupa od Platonove savreno pravedne drave. Svetovna vlastela, kao vojni stale,
zajedno sa vladarem, vrhovnim vojnim zapovednikom, vrila je glavnu funkciju, vojnu, u srpskoj
srenjovekovnoj dravi, a svetenstvo religijsku, kulturnu, prosvetnu i socijalnu. Otuda su to bili
privilegovani stalei. Prema principu poloajne pravde, s obzirom na svoje zasluge u dravi,
privilegovani stalei su imali pravo svojine na zemlji (dominium directum), a vladar i pravo
vrhovne svojine na zemlji (dominium eminens), tzv. slobodnu batinu, a i brojne druge povlastice u
vanekonomskoj sferi. Zavisno stanovnitvo, pak, s obzirom da njihova delatnost, iako nuna, nije
bila direktno povezana sa glavnom, vojnom funkcijom, imalo je pravo uivanja na zemlji
(dominium utile), tzv. potinjenu batinu, a za uzvrat brojne dabine i terete.
Isto tako, u Duanovom zakonodavstvu, a pre svega Duanovom Zakoniku, prisutna je
Aristotelova opta pravda, shvaena kao zakonitost, izriito formulisana na vie mesta, a posebno
u l. 171. i 172. Kako je Duanov Zakonik sadravao najvie odredbe javnopravnog karaktera, u
njemu je, u visokom stepenu, zastupljena distributivna pravda, koja se ispoljava u raspodeli asti i
dobara, srazmerno zasluzi. Postojao je i jedan poseban oblik distributivne pravde, sa izrazito
socijalnom funkcijom. Naime, Duanov Zakonik vodi rauna o siromanim, ubogim, bolesnim,
oslobaa ih raznih tereta, a namee obaveze crkvi i sudovima da ih pomau. Najzad, Duanov
Zakonik poznaje i Aristotelovu sudsku ili krivinu pravdu, kao oblik korektivne ili sinalagmatike
pravde, koja se ispoljava u uspostvaljanju sredine izmeu dobra i zla, odnosno ekvivalentnosti, to
ini sud. Ovaj posebni oblik pravde, meutim, nije na dosledan nain sproveden.
Po svojoj dubini i umnosti, Duanovo zakonodavstvo, a pre svega Duanov Zakonik, je primer
velianstvene srednjovekovne pravne kodifikacije.
Kljune rei:

Platonova pravda, poloajna pravda, opta pravda, distributivna pravda,


sudska pravda, staleka monarhija, timokratija.

You might also like