Introduction To Ethics
Introduction To Ethics
Our modern concepts of ethics have been derived from religions, philosophies and culture. They are of
importance in debates on topics like abortion, human rights, medicine and professional conduct.
What is the difference between ethics and morality?
There is a fairly subtle difference between ethics and morality. Morals define personal character (and
are therefore effectively something we are born with), while ethics form a social system in which
morals are applied. In other words, ethics point to standards or codes of behaviour expected by the
group or culture to which the individual belongs. Over many years, these have developed into systems
of law, medical ethics, business ethics, protocols of war etc. A very simple form of ethics is the idea of
a taboo. Taboos are forms of behaviour which societies generally find repellant and therefore refrain
from. These very often change over history as societies develop.
Are there universal moral rules?
One of the big questions in moral philosophy is whether or not there are unchanging universal moral
rules that apply in all cultures and at all times. Moral absolutists believe the answer is yes, while moral
relativists believe the answer is no.
Moral absolutism
Some people think there are universal rules that apply to everyone. This sort of thinking is called
moral absolutism. Moral absolutism argues that there are some moral rules that are always true, that
these rules can be discovered and that these rules apply to everyone.
In thinking of this kind, immoral acts - acts that break these moral rules - are said to be wrong in
themselves, regardless of the circumstances or the consequences of those acts.
Moral absolutism takes a universal view of humanity - there is one set of rules for everyone - which
enables the drafting of universal rules - such as the United Nations Universal Declaration of Human
Rights.
Religious views of ethics tend to be absolutist.
For example, in 2007 Pope Benedict XVI set out the absolutist position of the Catholic
Church as follows:
"Where God is absent - God with the human face of Jesus Christ - these
[moral] values fail to show themselves with their full force: nor does a
consensus arise concerning them.
I do not mean that nonbelievers cannot live a lofty and exemplary morality; I
am only saying that a society in which God is absent will not find the
necessary consensus on moral values or the strength to live according to the
model of these values".
Many of us feel that the consequences of an act or the circumstances surrounding it are
relevant to whether that act is good or bad
Moral relativism
Moral relativists say that if you look at different cultures or different periods in history you'll find that
they have different moral rules. Therefore it makes sense to say that "good" refers to the things that a
particular group of people approve of.
Moral relativists therefore dispute the idea that there are some objective and discoverable 'superrules' that all cultures ought to obey. They believe that relativism respects the diversity of human
societies and responds to the different circumstances surrounding human acts.
Many people disagree with moral relativism:
Many of us feel that moral rules have more to them than the general agreement of a group of
people - that morality is more than just a form of etiquette
Many of us think we can be good without conforming to all the rules of society
Moral relativism has a problem with arguing against the majority view: if most people in a
society agree with particular rules, that's the end of the matter. Many of the improvements in
the world have come about because people opposed the prevailing ethical view - moral
relativists are forced to regard such people as behaving "badly"
Moral relativism doesn't provide any way to deal with moral differences between societies
Approaches to ethics
Philosophers nowadays tend to divide ethical theories into three areas: meta-ethics, normative ethics
and applied ethics.
Meta-ethics deals with the nature of moral judgment. It looks at the origins and meaning of
ethical principles.
Normative ethics is concerned with the content of moral judgments and the criteria for what is
right or wrong.
Applied ethics looks at controversial real-life situations such as war, animal rights and capital
punishment
If a group believes that a particular activity is "wrong" it can then use morality as the justification for
attacking those who practice that activity.
When people do this, they often see those who they regard as immoral as in some way less human or
deserving of respect than themselves; sometimes with tragic consequences.
Good people as well as good actions
Ethics is not only about the morality of particular course of action, but it's also about the goodness of
individuals and what it means to live a good life.
Virtue Ethics is particularly concerned with the moral character of human beings.
If a person did this properly they would be led to the right conclusion.
But now even philosophers are less sure that it's possible to devise a satisfactory and complete theory
of ethics - at least not one that leads to conclusions.
Modern thinkers often teach that ethics leads people not to conclusions but to 'decisions'.
In this view, the role of ethics is limited to clarifying 'what's at stake' in particular ethical problems.
Philosophy can help identify the range of ethical methods, conversations and value systems that can
be applied to a particular problem. But after these things have been made clear, each person must
make their own individual decision as to what to do, and then react appropriately to the
consequences.
Ethical realists think that human beings discover ethical truths that already have an
independent existence.
The problem for ethical realists is that people follow many different ethical codes and moral beliefs. So
if there are real ethical truths out there (wherever!) then human beings don't seem to be very good at
discovering them.
One form of ethical realism teaches that ethical properties exist independently of human beings, and
that ethical statements give knowledge about the objective world.
To put it another way; the ethical properties of the world and the things in it exist and remain the
same, regardless of what people think or feel - or whether people think or feel about them at all.
Religion
political power
Intuitionism
Intuitionists think that good and bad are real objective properties that can't be broken down into
component parts. Something is good because it's good; its goodness doesn't need justifying or
proving.
Intuitionists think that goodness or badness can be detected by adults - they say that human beings
have an intuitive moral sense that enables them to detect real moral truths. They think that basic
moral truths of what is good and bad are self-evident to a person who directs their mind towards moral
issues.
So good things are the things that a sensible person realises are good if they spend some time
pondering the subject.
For the intuitionist therefore:
Consequentialism
This is the ethical theory that most non-religious people think they use every day. It bases morality on
the consequences of human actions and not on the actions themselves.
Consequentialism teaches that people should do whatever produces the greatest amount of good
consequences.
One famous way of putting this is 'the greatest good for the greatest number of people'.
The most common forms of consequentialism are the various versions of utilitarianism, which favour
actions that produce the greatest amount of happiness.
Despite its obvious common-sense appeal, consequentialism turns out to be a complicated theory,
and doesn't provide a complete solution to all ethical problems.
Two problems with consequentialism are:
it can lead to the conclusion that some quite dreadful acts are good
Virtue ethics
Virtue ethics look at virtue or moral character, rather than at ethical duties and rules, or the
consequences of actions - indeed some philosophers of this school deny that there can be such things
as universal ethical rules.
Virtue ethics is particularly concerned with the way individuals live their lives, and less concerned in
assessing particular actions.
It develops the idea of good actions by looking at the way virtuous people express their inner
goodness in the things that they do.
To put it very simply, virtue ethics teaches that an action is right if and only if it is an action that a
virtuous person would do in the same circumstances, and that a virtuous person is someone who has
a particularly good character.
Situation ethics
Situation ethics rejects prescriptive rules and argues that individual ethical decisions should be made
according to the unique situation.
Rather than following rules the decision maker should follow a desire to seek the best for the people
involved. There are no moral rules or rights - each case is unique and deserves a unique solution.
In ethics we are dealing with a plurality of truths. It'll be worth questioning the basis there might be for
ethical truth across cultures. What are good reasons for holding our moral beliefs? Pay close attention
to the words used to express moral viewpoints; we know that in the language or war, 'one man's
terrorist is another man's freedom fighter', and in the above case, 'one man's cannibalistic murderer is
another man's hero with superior survival instincts.'
Perhaps the challenge in TOK ethics is to look for what moral knowledge cultures might have in
common. Even the notion of right and wrong is shared across cultures, even if the standards to which
this approximates, differs. The idea of shared values is embodied in the idea of The Universal
Declaration of Human Rights (1948).
So to conclude, tolerance of other people's views is a fundamental principle but it does not follow that
all moral views are of equal value. Freedom of speech and the right to express your own view is
essential, but there may be some moral views that are not as sound as others. The task of ethics is to
examine the grounds on which we hold our moral beliefs. How do we decide about the case above;
killing a person as a means to an end is objectionable, but the instinct to survive in extreme conditions
might demand we re-think our moral paradigms? It's for you to decide.
For more top tips for Theory of knowledge visit Elvira Vian's Theory of Knowledge student
Article Source: http://EzineArticles.com/?expert=Elvira_Vian
This is subjectivism
This is emotivism
This is prescriptivism
Moral realism
Moral realism is based on the idea that there are real objective moral facts or truths in the universe.
Moral statements provide factual information about those truths.
Subjectivism
Subjectivism teaches that moral judgments are nothing more than statements of a person's feelings or
attitudes, and that ethical statements do not contain factual truths about goodness or badness.
In more detail: subjectivists say that moral statements are statements about the feelings, attitudes
and emotions that that particular person or group has about a particular issue.
If a person says something is good or bad they are telling us about the positive or negative feelings
that they have about that something.
So if someone says 'murder is wrong' they are telling us that they disapprove of murder.
These statements are true if the person does hold the appropriate attitude or have the appropriate
feelings. They are false if the person doesn't.
Emotivism
Emotivism is the view that moral claims are no more than expressions of approval or disapproval.
This sounds like subjectivism, but in emotivism a moral statement doesn't provide information about
the speaker's feelings about the topic but expresses those feelings.
When an emotivist says "murder is wrong" it's like saying "down with murder" or "murder, yecch!" or
just saying "murder" while pulling a horrified face, or making a thumbs-down gesture at the same time
as saying "murder is wrong".
So when someone makes a moral judgment they show their feelings about something. Some theorists
also suggest that in expressing a feeling the person gives an instruction to others about how to act
towards the subject matter.
Prescriptivism