Goodman Nelson Score Sketch Script
Goodman Nelson Score Sketch Script
Df :
..
.. '''1
.... :: .. 'ri'
nn* hAne- 0 eta"
.. .. ..
..
.. ."" .. t
.. .."
r
F· .. :",
.. ..
..
It.<<irr -au+' trttuf fie
.,'" I t ' f"
. .. ..
..
f'" .....
.. .. ..
. ""
.. ..
.. ..
- -_., ,.- _ .... _. __ .. ,,,. ~ ------ .- ., ---_. --
--------- .. - .. --- .. "r·------·-·--· .--.--.----.- .... --.--- " .. ----- .. _ .... -- - .... --- ...
!i O" .. qAr·tU( ~ tf ~
. ....If... .. f ..
... ~ L __ ..
lA.~~t: ~ Ao-. T ~~o{ • S~ 6r" lC)lb
f
."
f _I
F' : -
..
v
SCORE, SKETCH, AND SCRIPT
You see no experiment can be repeated exactly. There will always be something ditierent .... What it comes to when you say you repeat an experiment is that you repeat alI the features of an experiment which a theory determines are relevant. In other words you repeat the experiment as an example of the theory.
Sir George Thomson '"
1. Score
A score is a character in a notational system. Even in musical notation not every character is a score, but I count as a score every character that may have compliants. This excludes purely syncategorematic characters, for example, without requiring of a score either that it be a complete composition or that it be actually nonvacant. I have broadened the application of "score" to embrace characters of the sort described in any notational system,' not merely in musical notation. Similarly, I often call the compliants of such characters performances where these compliants are not by ordinary usage performed or even events at all; and
Reverse
* In "Some Thoughts on Scientific Method", Lecture of May 2, 1963, printed in Boston Studies in the Philosophy of Science, vol. II (New York, Humanities Press, 1965), p, 85.
1 Not, be it observed, "in any notational scheme". The usage here adopted counts on \y characters of notationa I svstems as scores.
Page of manuscript, late eleventh century. Fol, 127 v. from Lat. 7211, Bibliotheque Nationale, Paris.
177
SCORE, SKETCH, AND SCRIPT
MUSIC
I often call the compliance-classes works, even when these classes are such-s-e.g., fortuitous aggregates of natural objects-as not to be works in any usual sense. All this I think may help to keep before us both the cardinal example of music and the more general principles illustrated.
A score, we found, defines a work but is a peculiar and privileged definition, without competitors. A class is uniquely determined by a score, as by an ordinary definition; but a score, unlike an ordinary definition, is also uniquely determined by each member of that class. Given the notational system and a performance of a score, the score is recoverable. Identity of work and of score is retained in any series of steps, each of them either from compliant performance to score-inscription, or from scoreinscription to compliant performance, or from scoreinscription to true copy. This is ensured by the fact, and only by the fact, that the language in which a score is written must be notational-must satisfy the five stated requirements. No inherent partitioning of the subject-matter is presumed; and performances of a work may vary widely and in many respects.
Redundancy, as noted earlier, is a common and minor violation of notationality. The net effect is that in a chain of the sort described, the score-inscriptions may not all be true copies of one another; yet all will be semantically equivalent-all performances will be of the same work. Work-preservation but not score-preservatioi is ensured; and insofar as work-preservation is paramount, and scorepreservation incidental, redundancy is tolerable.
None of our usual natural languages is a notational system. Such discursive languages meet the two syntactic re-
quirements but are. exempt from the three semantic requirements. Accordingly, a definition or set of coextensive definitions is seldom uniquely determined by a member of the class defined. And as we have seen, ambiguity is not always to blame; a wheelbarrow belongs to many different compliance-classes of object-English--complies, that is, with many extensionally diverse descriptions, such as "wooden object", "wheeled vehicle", etc. In such a language there is no such thing as the definition, or set of equivalent definitions, that the given object satisfies. But in a notational system, or even a system that misses notationality only through redundancy, all scores for a given performance are coextensive-have all the same performances as compliants.
2. Music
So far, I have been discussing matters of general theory without examining closely any of the presumably notational systems actually used in the arts. Standard musical notation offers a familiar and at the same time a remarkable case. It is at once complex, serviceable, and-like Arabic numerical notation-common to the users of many different verbal languages. No alternative has gained any currency; and apparently no other culture, such as the Chinese or Indian, has developed any comparably effective musical notation over the centuries. The variety and vitality of recent rebellions against it testify to the authority it has acquired.f
% I do not say to its merits, aesthetic or otherwise; see the d.iscunion of this point later in this section.
178
V,l
V,2
179
SCORE, SKETCH, AND SCRIPT
MUSIC
8 See the Irontispiece to this chapter. According to Carl Parrish, The Notation 01 Medieval Music (New York, W. W. Norton & Co., Ine., 1957), p. 9, this system "is called diastematic from the Greek word for 'interval'. In this writing neurnes are carefully 'heighted', that I!, placed at various distances from an imaginary line representing a given pitch, according to their relationship to that line. Certain schools of neurne notation display this feature even in their earliest manuscripts .... About the end of the tenth century the imaginary line about which diastematic neumes were placed became a real one. At first it was a dry line scratched on the parchment, an idea probably suggested by the use of the guidelines on which the text was written".
strument. When the lines and the spaces between them become characters of the system, with placement of a syllable or note-sign serving only to pick out one of these characters, elements of a genuine notation emerge. However, I am primarily concerned here not with origins or development but with how fully the language of musical scores qualifies as a truly notational system.
That the syntactic requirements are in general met is quite clear. A note-mark may, indeed, be so placed that we are in doubt about whether it belongs to one notecharacter or another, but in no case does it belong to both. Ostensible note-marks do not count as inscriptions in the system unless and until they are determined to belong to one character rather than to any other. Most characters of a musical score, whether numerals or letters or neither, _are._syntacti.cally_disjpi!1_U~.m:l Qiffe!"enti§l:~<!: The symbol scheme is thus substantially notational, and the language of scores truly a language. But is this language a notational system? Does it satisfy the semantic requirements?
If we consider piano scores alone, the language is highly redundant since, for example, the same sound-events comply with the characters for c-sharp, d-tlat, e-triple-flat, bdouble-sharp, and so on 4; but redundancy, as we have seen, is not altogether fatal. A more crucial question arises when we consider scores for other instruments as well. In a violin score the characters for c-sharp and d-flat have no
Ordinary musical notation has sometimes been thought to owe its origin to the introduction of keyboard instruments, with their separate keys and spaced tones; but the question just when either a true notation or a true keyboard instrument emerged is so elusive that the hypothesis hardly admits of any conclusive historical investigation. And the hypothesis is antecedently implausible; musical notation no more needed to wait upon invention of the clavichord than alphabetical notation needed to wait upon invention of the typewriter. Development of a notational scheme or system does not depend upon an intrinsic segregation of marks or objects into disjoint and differentiated sets, but is often achieved in the face of virtual continuity in both realms.
In some early mediaeval musical manuscripts, marks _~ere _place.d.:_l.t_ig_h~LQLlow~.LQY&L~yJla bles.or __ WQLds. __ of.a. song to indicate pitch," Only later did horizontal lines come to be added. At first these lines may have functioned as mere guides for judging absolute position, like the graduation-marks on a thermometer taken as an analog in-
~ I oversimplify here by ignoring features other the;> pitch, but the central point is unaffected. The redundancy noted above will call for further consideration in another connection.
180
V,2
V,2
181
SCORE, SKETCH, AND SCRIPT
MUSIC
compliants in common," Now if two characters thus have some compliants jointly (in piano scores) and others severally, the two compliance-classes properly intersect, flagrantly violating the requirement of semantic disjointness. What this account misses, though, is that since every performance is on one instrument or another, each of the two characters can be considered a vacant atomic character that combines with different specifications of instrument to form different prime characters. The compliance-classes of the two resultant prime characters occurring in piano scores are identical; the compliance-classes of the two resultant prime characters occurring in violin scores are disjoint. Neither pair nor the pair of atomic vacant characters nor the set of all six characters violates the rule of semantic disjointness by more than the redundancy mentioned.
If we suppose the series of whole note, half-note, quarter-note, eighth-note, etc., to be continued without end, the semantic requirement of finite differentiation will be violated. For then by tying note-signs together we can construct characters for notes differing in duration by less than any given fraction of a beat. Hence no sounding of a note could be determined to comply with at most one character. Now of Course in any given score or corpus of
scores, the number of note-signs, and of Rags on any of them, is finite. But there must furthermore be a tacit or express limit on the number of flags permitted by the system at all; otherwise recovery of score from performance will not be even theoretically possible, identity of work from performance to performance will not be ensured, and the primary purpose of a notational system will not be served. Theoretically, any limit would do. Tradition seems to set it for the present at five flags-the 1/128 note.
The main corpus of peculiarly musical characters of the system thus appears on the whole to meet the semantic as well as the syntactic requirements for a notation. The same cannot be said for all the numerical and alphabetical characters that also occur in scores.
First, some compositions are written with a 'figured bass' or 'continuo', allowing performers certain options. Now so long as such scores determine comparatively broad but still mutually disjoint classes of performances," they cause no trouble; what counts is not specificity but separateness. But a system that permits alternative use of figured-bass and specific notation, without rigidly prescribing the choice in every case, materially violates the conditions upon notational systems; for the complianceclasses of some of its characters are properly included in the compliance-classes of other, more general characters. Two score-inscriptions, one in figured-bass and the other
5 This may be disputed. I am told that a tone of, say, 333 vibrations per second is accepted for either character. But we may regard such a tone either as actually compliant with both characters or (like the missing of one note) as merely within tolerable limits of deviation in pmctice. For purposes of illustrating a general point, I choose the latter interpretation here. A more relational notation is still compatible with notationafiry,
6 The question whether these compliance-classes are in fact disjoint can be answered only by careful examination of the notation in use and some delicate decisions concerning its interpretation.
182
V,2
V,2
183
SCORE, SKETCH, AND SCRIPT
MUSIC
in specific notation, even though they have some common compliant performance, will not thereby be semantically equivalent; and two performances complying with the former may severally comply with two specific scores that have no compliant in common. The comprehensive Ianguage of musical scores, insofar as it offers free choice between figured-bass and specific notation, is thus not truly notational. Rather, it comprises two notational subsystems; and the one in use must be designated and adhered to if identification of work from performance to performance is to be ensured.
Much the same can be said concerning the free cadenza.
The performer, again, is given wide scope; and scores providing for free cadenzas have compliance-classes that properly include those of other scores with their solo passages all specified note by note. Unless there is a way of determining in every case whether a solo passage is to be fully specified or indicated as a free cadenza, we must again recognize that the language of musical scores is not purely notational but divides into notational subsystems.
Trouble of a different sort arises from the verbal notation used for the tempo of a . movement. That the words come from ordinary object-language does not of itself matter. "Notational" does not imply "nonverbal"; and not every selection of characters, along with their complianceclasses, from a discursive language violates the conditions for notationality. What matters is whether the borrowed vocabulary meets the semantic requirements. Now just what is the vocabulary of tempo? It contains not only the more common terms like "allegro", "andante", and "ada-
gio", but indefinitely many others like the following, taken from a few programs of chamber music 7: presto, allegro vivace, allegro assai, allegro spiritoso, allegro molto, allegro non troppo, aI/egTo moderato, poco alIegretto, allegretto quasi-minuet to, minuetto, minuetto can un poco di moto, rondo alIa Polacca, andantino mosso, andantino grazioso, fantasia, alfetuoso e sostenuto, moderato e amabile. Apparently almost any words may be used to indicate pace and mood. Even if unambiguity were miraculously preserved, semantic disjointness would not be. And since a tempo may be prescribed as fast, or as slow, or as between fast and slow, or as between fast and between-fast-andslow, and so on without limit, semantic differentiation goes by the board, too.
Thus the verbal language of tempos is not notational.
The tempo words cannot be integral parts of a score insofar as the score serves the function of identifying a work from performance to performance. No departure from the indicated tempo disqualifies a performance as an instance -however wretched-of the work defined by the score. For these tempo specifications cannot be accounted integral parts of the defining score, but are rather auxiliary directions whose observance or nonobservance affects the quality of a performance but not the identity of the work. On the other hand, metronomic specifications of tempo do, under obvious restrictions and under a system univer-
7 Chosen cesually from programs of works played at the Marlboro Music Festival, Marlboro. Vermont, during six weeks in the summer of 1961.
184
V,2
V,2
185
SCORE, SKETCH, AND SCRIPT
MUSIC
sally requiring them, qualify as notational and may be taken as belonging to the score as such.
I have been able to discuss here, rather sketchily, only a few salient samples of relevant questions concerning the standard language of musical scores. The results suggest, however, that it comes as near to meeting the theoretical requirements for notationality as might reasonably be expected of any traditional system in constant actual use, and
that ~the e~cisi.~~s .~.~~ _ r~~~_~~~~ _~~.:_~.:.~._to._c~~_re.~t_~n~_il1~_ "-fractl6ns--are rather plain and local. After all, one hardly
expects chemical purity outside the laboratory.
Since complete compliance with the score is the only requirement for a genuine instance of a work, the most miserable performance without actual mistakes does count as such an instance, while the most brilliant performance with a single wrong note does not. Could we not bring our theoretical vocabulary into better agreement with common practice and common sense by allowing some limited degree of deviation in performances admitted as instances of a work? The practicing musician or composer usually bristles at the idea that a performance with one wrong note is not a performance of the given work at ali; and ordinary usage surely sanctions overlooking a few wrong notes. But this is one of those cases where ordinary usage gets us quickly into trouble. The innocent-seeming principle that performances differing by just one note are instances of the same work risks the consequence-in view of the transitivity of identity-that all performances whatsoever are of the same work. If we allow the least devia-
tion, all assurance of work-preservation and scorepreservation is lost; for by a series of one-note errors of omission, addition, and modification, we can go all the way from Beethoven's Fifth Symphony to Three Blind Mice, Thus while a score may leave unspecified many features of a performance, and allow for considerable variation in others within prescribed limits, fuU compliance with the specifications given is categorically required. This is not to
_saY~!I!!!_!h~,~J.ti~e_I!~je~._that_<iictate our t_e~h~ical discourse need govern our everyday speech. I am no more recommending that in ordinary discourse we refuse to say that a pianist who misses a note has performed a Chopin Polonaise than that we refuse to call a whale a fish, the earth spherical, or a grayish-pink human white.
The overwhelming monopoly long held by standard musical notation has inevitably inspired rebellion and alternative proposals. Composers complain variously that scores in this notation prescribe too few features or too many or the wrong ones, or prescribe the right ones too precisely or not precisely enough. Revolution here as elsewhere may aim atmore or at less or at different control of the means of production.
One simple system devised by John Cage is roughly as follows (see Figure 11): dots, for single sounds, are placed within a rectangle; across the rectangle, at varying angles and perhaps intersecting, run five straight lines for (severally) frequency, duration, timbre, amplitude, and su~ce~sian. The significant factors determining the sounds indicated by a dot are the perpendicular distances from the
186
V,2
V,2
187
SCORE, SKETCH, AND SCRIPT
MUSIC
BB
compliance-classes of a notational system may be of any size so long as they are disjoint and differentiated. Under the proposed system there are no disjoint and differentiated characters or compliance-classes, no notation, no language, no scores.
The objection may be raised that the lack of syntactic differentiation here hardly matters if we have the original drawing and photographic means of reproducing it within any desired or consequential degree of accuracy. But however small the inaccuracy of reproduction, a chain of successive reproductions of reproductions can result in departing to any degree from the original. True enough, we can detect significant deviation by direct comparison with the original (if it is available); yet for two significantly different originals there may be a third (or a copy) that does not differ significantly from either. To arrive at a notation here calls not only for a limit upon significant deviation but also for a means of ensuring disjointness of characters.
Now I am by no means pronouncing upon whether adoption of a system like that described might nevertheless be a good idea. I am neither qualified nor called upon to make such a judgment. I am simply pointing out that much more is involved than a mere shift from one notational system to another. Nor am I quibbling about the proper
U .,' U U and "work"
use of such words as notation", score, .
That matters little more than the proper use of a fork.
-Whar-does-matteristrratthe system-in question furnishes no means of identifying a work from performance to performance or even of a character from mark to mark. Nothing can be determined to be a true copy of Cage's
Figure 11
dot to these lines." This system is not notational; for without some stipulation of minimal significant units of angle and distance, syntactic differentiation is wanting. So long as no limit is set upon the smallness of the difference in position that makes a difference in character, no measurement can ever determine that any mark belongs to one character rather than to any number of others. Similarly, under this system, no measurement can ever determine that a performance complies with one mark rather than others. Furthermore, depending upon just how the symbols are interpreted, syntactic and semantic disjointness may be lacking. The point is not that a work is less rigidly prescribed
__ ~haI!.Jll::_iU__tandrug __ ~I;;Qf_e_; _iQf_J:he__chacacteL~classes_and-the _
IISee Concert for Piano and Orchestra, Solo lor Piano (New York, Henmar Press, Inc., 1960), p. 53, figure BB. The figure, which has been redrawn, is reproduced here by permission of the publisher.
188
V,2
V,2
189
SCORE, SKETCH, AND SCRIPT
MUSIC
autograph diagram or to be a performance of it. There are only copies after and performances aite.r that unique object as there are only drawings and paintings after a sketch. The same, of course, may be said of the mediaeval manuscript shown in the frontispiece to this chapter; sometimes revolution is retrogression.
An extreme spirit of laissez faire has led some composers to use systems that restrict only slightly the performer's freedom to play what and as he pleases. Such latitude is not incompatible with notationality; even a system with only two characters, one having as compliants all piano performances beginning with a middle c, and the other having as compliants all other performances, would be notational-though for this system there could be only two different works. But, of course, systems with characters having wide ranges of application often lack semantic disjointness.
At the opposite extreme, some composers of electronic music, with continuous sound-sources and means of activation, and with the human performer dispensable in favor of mechanical devices, seek to eliminate all latitude in performance and achieve 'exact control'," But except where
mere counting is involved, absolutely precise prescription cannot be accomplished by any notational system; differentiation requires gaps that destroy continuity. With a decimal system, for example, absolute precision would require writing out each specification endlessly; stopping at any finite number of decimal places results in some inaccuracy, however slight, that could accumulate in a long enough chain to any amount. For exact control, the symbol system would have to be both syntactically and semantically dense-an analog or graphic system; then any imprecision would arise from mechanical or human errors or limitations rather than from the symbol system. But then, also, we have no notation or scores, and ironically the demand for absolute and inflexible control results in purely autographic works.
Many of the symbol systems developed by modern composers have been described, illustrated, and classified by Erhardt Karkoschka.l" His classification, differently motivated from ours, recognizes four basic types of system:
(1) Precise Notation (Priizise Notation )-where, for ex-
ample, every note is named.
(2) Range Notation (Rahmenotation)-where, for example, only the limits of ranges of notes are set.
(3) Suggestive Notation (Hinweisende Notation)-where at most relations of notes, or approximate limits of ranges, are specified.
(4) Musical Graphics.
9 Roger Sessions, in a passage just preceding the paragraph from which the quotation heading Chapter IV is taken, writes that electronic media make possible "the exact control of all musical elements ..•• Every moment of music not only can hut must be the result of the minutest calculation, and the composer for the first time has the ~hole world of sound at his disposal"; then he proceeds to question the musical importance of this approach. Peter Yates, in "The Proof of the Notation", Arts and Architecture, vol, 82 (1966), p. 36, points out that "Even a performance by electronic means will vary with the equipment and acoustics".
)0 In Da, Schriltsbild der Neuen Musik (Celle, Herman Moeck, 1966), pp. 19if. My discussion of this searching work is brief and inadequate.
190
V,2
V,2
191
SCORE, SKETCH, AND SCRIPT
SKETCH
Obviously, a system of either of the first two kinds mayor may not qualify as notational in my terminology. Systems of the third kind seem in general to be non-notational; they include, for example, the usual verbal tempo descriptions. But a system prescribing only relations between notes-such as that one is twice as loud or an octave below the preceding note-seems also to belong to the third class and could be notational. The system used for
--Grego-riancnarif--maii--nave---beerl--of--fhis--sorE -df liiSlirst~
three classes, Karkoschka writes (p. 80): "A work falls in the three spheres of precise notation, range notation, and suggestive notation if it has the usual coordinate system of space and time as basis, is more sign than sketch, and is essentially linear." The fourth class, musical graphics, apparently consists mainly of analog systems, lacking both syntactic and semantic articulation-that is, of nonnotational, nonlinguistic systems that provide diagrams or sketches rather than scores or descriptions.
3. Sketch
neither case can anything be determined to belong to or to comply with at most one character. Thus, whereas a true score picks out a class of performances that are the equal and only instances of a musical work, a sketch does not determine a class of objects that are the equal and only instances of a work of painting. Unlike the score, the sketch does not define a work, in the strong sense of "define" explained earlier, but rather is one.
Nowthisrs nottodenyrhat a notational system might be established such that sketches belong to its characters. Obviously sketches and also paintings can be sorted into disjoint and differentiated classes in any of various ways; and any of a multitude of correlations can be set up. But quite as obviously, to have two realms that can be so sorted and correlated is not yet to have a system. Only when custom or express stipulation actually effects or selects a classification of each realm and a correlation of the two do we have a system. Such a selection has already been made in the case of standard musical notation, but not in the case of sketches. No pictorial respects are distinguished as those in which a sketch must match another to be its equivalent, or a painting match a sketch to be an instance of what the sketch defines. And no magnitude of difference in any respect is set as the threshhold of significance. Differences of all kinds and degrees, measurable or not, are on equal footing. Hence no classes of sketches are picked out as the characters, and no classes of pictures as the compliance-classes, of a notational system.
In short, the sketch-as a sketch--differs from the score
Because a painter's sketch, fike a composer's score, may be used as a working guide, the crucial difference in their status might go unnoticed. The sketch, unlike the score, is not in a language Of notation at all, but in a system without either syntactic or semantic differentiation. And while the Cage system described takes certain relationships of dot to line as the only pertinent ones, none among the pictorial properties of a sketch can be dismissed as irrelevant. But in
192
V,3
V,3
193
SCORE, SKETCH, AND SCRIPT
PAINTING
not in functioning as a character in a language of a different kind but in not functioning as a character in a language at a11,l1 The notational language of musical scores has no parallel in a language (notational or not) of sketches,
the size of the compliance-dasses of a notational system. And the uniqueness of instance in painting is irrelevant here since exactly the same question about the possibility of a notational system arises for etching, and is to be answered in the same way. If impressions are assigned numerals according to the plate printed from, the 'complianceclass of a numeral will usually have many members. Indeed, nothing precludes taking each plate itself as the unique inscription of a character having its impressions as its compliants. Hence for painting and etching alike, notational languages are readily devised.
Yet, clearly, this straight-faced answer to the literal question asked misses the main point. For the question of realtnteresthere i-s whether by means of a flotational system the work of painting or etching can be freed of dependence upon a particular author or upon a place or date or means of production. Is it theoretically possible to write a score so defining a work of painting or etching that objects produced by others, before or since the usually designated original or originals, and by other means (than, e.g., the 'original' plate) may comply with the score and qualify as equal instances of the work? In short, could institution of a notational system transform painting or etching from an autographic into an allographic art?
Some reasons that have been given for a negative answer are plainly beside the point. That a visual work is more complex and subtle than a musical performance wouldeven if true-not matter. For a score need not-indeed cannot-specify all aspects of the compliants nor even every degree of difference in any aspect; a score, as in
4. Painting
That we have ready at hand no notational system for painting does not settle the question whether such a system is possible. Taken at its face value, the question can be answered with an unhesitating but trivial yes. For examples of such notational languages are easily constructed. A library-like decimal system assigning a numeral to each .paintlng.acccrding lo--time.and .place __ of production-would meet all five requirements. Far afield is the objection that no one can tell by inspection, without further information, whether a given painting complies with a given numeral; for likewise no one can tell by inspection, without further information, whether a given performance complies with a musical score. One has to be able to interpret the score as one has to be able to interpret the numeral; and to know how to interpret a character is to know what complies with it.
The compliance-classes for the language just described will indeed be unit-classes, so that identification of a work from instance to instance will always be from sale instance to same sale instance, but there are no requirements upon
11 Of course, nothing prevents B given mark from functioning es an if. crtption in a notation (or in several different notations) andeho as II sketch in II nonhnguistic system (or in Bevera. such system,).
194
V,4
V,4
195
SCORE, SKETCH, AND SCRIPT
PAINTING
figured-bass or free-cadenza notation, may be summary in the extreme. Nor does the difficulty of making perfect reproductions of a painting have anything to do with confinement of the work to the unique original.I2 The performances of the most specific score are by no means exact duplicates of one another, but vary widely and in many ways. A moderately good copy and the original painting resemble each other more closely than do performances of a Bach suite by Piatigorsky and Casals,
Yet there are constraints. Although a notational system may pick out any set of disjoint and finitely differentiated classes in any realm as compliance-classes, not every compliance-class of every such system counts as a work. Standard musical notation might be reinterpreted so that its compliance-classes cut wildly across the standard ones or even contain no musical performances at all, Or a notational system might classify pictures according to size or shape. But in none of these cases does a compliance-class any more constitute a work than the animals in a zoo form a species, or the performances of a musical composition make up a society. Whether the compliance-classes for a system are works (or societies) depends partly upon their relationship to the classes accounted works (or societies) in antecedent practice.
Special care must be taken here. While it would be quite
wrong to suppose that a class becomes a work by being assigned a character in a notational system, it would also be quite wrong to suppose that no class is a work unless it has been antecedently considered so. On the one hand, the antecedent classification stands as license and touchstone for a notational system; only in reference to this classification can there be a charge of material error or a claim of material correctness. On the other hand, the antecedent classification is normally partial and provisional. It submits only sample classes, each only by samples. Adoption of a notational language thus effects a double projection: from the samples of the several classes to the complete classes, and from the sample classes to the complete classification of the field of reference. This involves a choice among alternatives; and some actual departures from the antecedent classification may be made for the sake of better systematization. In sum, the problem of developing a notational system for an art like music amounted to the problem of arriving at a real definition of the notion of a musical
work.
Where a pertinent antecedent classification is lacking or
is flouted, a notational language effects only an arbitrary, nominal definition of "work", as if it were a word newly coined. With no prototype, or no recognition of one, there are no material grounds for choosing one systematization rather than any other. But in the case of painting, a work is antecedently identified with (the unit-class of) an individual picture; and in the case of etching, with the class of impressions printed from an individual plate. Now
12 Widespread acceptance 01 this easy and inapt explanation has inhibited efforts toward real understanding of the matter. Philosophers of art are not immune from the error; see, for example, Joseph Margolis, "The Identity of a Work of Art", Mind, vol. 68 (1959), p. 50.
196
V,4
V,4
197
SCORE, SKETCH, AND SCRIPT
SCRIPT
the question is whether by application of a notational system works of painting or etching could legitimately be identified with quite different classes. This would call not just for such minor adjustments as occur in any systematization but for a drastic overhaul that would lump together in each compliance-class many antecedently different works. A notational system effecting such a reclassification may of course be applied at will; but scores in it will not constitute real definitions of works of painting. To repudiate the antecedent classification is to disenable the only authority competent to issue the needed license.
Thus the answer to the significant question about a notational system for painting is no. We can devise a notational system that will provide, for works of painting and etching, real definitions that depend upon history of production. We can devise a notational system that will provide purely arbitrary nominal definitions that do not depend upon history of production. But we cannot devise a notational system that will provide, for such works, definitions that are both real (consonant with antecedent practice) and independent of history of production.
In sum, an established art becomes allographic only when the classification of objects or events into works is legitimately projected from an antecedent classification and is fully defined, independently of history of production, in terms of a notational system. Both authority and means are required; a suitable antecedent classification provides the one, a suitable notational system the other. Without the means, the authority is unexercised; without the authority, the means are footless.
5. Script
A script, unlike a sketch, is a character in a notational scheme and in a language but, unlike a score, is not in a notational system. The syntactic but not all the semantic requirements are met. "Script" here is thus not confined to cursive inscriptions or to the work of playwrights and film writers. In general, the characters of natural and of most technical languages are scripts; for even if ambiguity is avoided, the compliance-classes of such a language are seldom either disjoint or differentiated from one another.
While most scripts are verbal, notationality obviously does not turn upon the look of marks. We do not arrive at a notational system if we substitute a numeral for each word of English.13 And we do not sacrifice notationality -although we surely jettison practicality-if we translate standard musical notation into a sublanguage of English in such a way that the vocabulary of admitted words meets our five requirements.
One might suppose that scripts but not scores can assert or denote. But we have already seen that means of effecting assertion (or question or command) can be added to or subtracted from a system without affecting notational-
13 Lexicographical order might be taken as the basis for assigning numerals to words. But if we want to assign a numeral to every strin/i of letters, and we place no limit on the length of a string, lexicographical ordering becomes astoundingly complex. However, numerals may be assigned to all such strings on the basis of the different and very simple ordering that begins with lexicographical ordering of all one-letter strings, proceeds to lexicographical ordering of all twoletter strings, and so on. See IV, note 17.
198
V,4
v,s
199
SCORE, SKETCH, AND SCRIPT
PROJECTIBILITY, SYNONYMY, ANALYTICITY
ity; and the idea that scores do not denote seems no better founded. Offhand, indeed, the relation between a term and what it denotes appears quite different from that between a score and its performances or between a letter and its utterances; but no very clear principle seems to underlie this distinction. The criteria that distinguish notational systems from other languages are in terms of interrelationships among compliance-classes, and provide no good grounds for refusing to say that a character in a language of either sort denotes what complies with it.H
Even less can be said for the notion that while we need' only know how to recognize a performance of a musical score or an utterance of a phonetic score, we have to understand a script. In both cases, we have to know how to determine what complies with the character. Where a language has few prime characters and fairly simple principles of compliance, so that confident and almost automatic use is acquired rather easily, we tend to regard the language as an instrument we operate. Where the prime characters are many and the principles of compliance are complex, so that interpretation of a character often calls for some deliberation, we tend to speak of having to understand the language. But this difference in complexity, besides being a matter of degree, does not at all coincide with
the distinction between notational systems and other languages. For a notational system may have a denumerable infinity of prime characters and an intricate compliance'relation, while a discursive language may have only two characters-say the words "red" and "square", with red things and square things as their compliants.
A script, then, differs from a score not in being verbal or declarative or denotational or in requiring special understanding, but simply in being a character in a language that is either ambiguous or lacks semantic disjointness or differentiation. But this prosaic distinction is more consequential than might appear, both in ways already observed and in its bearing upon some currently touchy philosophical questions.
6. Projectibility, Synonymy, Analyticity
H This is not to say that everything a symbol refers to complies with it; exemplification, though a mode of reference, does not constitute compliance. Also we 'shal! see below (section 7) that the utterances and inscriptions of a language may alternatively, and often happily, be construed as equally instances of visual-auditory characters.
To learn and use any language _is to resolve problems of projection. On the basis of sample inscriptions of a character we must decide whether other marks, as they appear, belong to that character; and on the basis of sample cornpliants of a character, we must decide whether other objects comply. Notational and discursive languages are alike in this respect.
With discursive languages, further and major projective decisions have to be made. Even after all questions about what marks belong to what characters and about what objects belong to what compliance-classes have been set, tied, still an object often complies with several characters.
200
v,s
V,6
201
SCORE, SKETCH, AND SCRIPT
PRO]ECTIBILITY, SYNONYMY, ANALYTICITY
In object-English, for example, no object or set of objects complies with just one predicate. All green objects examined to date comply with the character "green object", but all comply equally with "green object examined to date or kangaroo", and with indefinitely many other predicates. Virtually any class that contains all green objects examined to date is the compliance-class of some expression in this language. More generally, the objects in any given selection comply with some English description that has as its other compIiants any other given objects. Thus projection from given cases calls for a choice among countless alternatives; and the making of such choices pervades all learning.!"
Yet no such questions arise when we are using a nota-tionaL.system. Here nothing- is a sample of more than. one compliance-class; nothing complies with two characters that are not coextensive. So no choice remains except perhaps, where redundancy is permitted, between coextensive labels; projection even from single sample to complianceclass is uniquely determined. What has happened, in effect, is that the decisions . have already been taken in adopting the system. We saw earlier that selection and
application of a notational system resolves problems of I projection on two levels: from partial to complete compliance-classes, and from partial to complete set of compliance-classes. Hence so long as we use that system, we are free of the major problems of projectibility.
15 What constitutes the grounds for choice here is a moot question. Scientists and metaphysicians are wont to posit an ontological difference between 'natural kinds' and other classes. Philosophers often hold that members of a favored class share some real attribute or essence, or bear some absolute resemblance to each other. I think the distinction depends rather upon linguistic habit. For a detailed discussion of the problem of projectibility, see FFF.
Of course, part of a performance no more determines the rest than does part of an object. Hearing the first notes of a composition no more tells us what follows than seeing part of an object tells us what lies beyond our view. The difference is that under a notational system one complete performance (whether of a single prime character or of the entire score of a symphony) uniquely determines character and compliance-class, while under a discursive language one complete object or event complying with a
_ character does. __ not . uniquely determine character or
compliance-class.
Furthermore a notational system, unlike a discursive language, is accordingly untroubled by any distinction in nobility among different ways of classifying an object. An object cannot be assigned by one character of the system to a natural or genuine kind and by another to a random or artificial collection. All labels for an object have the same compliance-class. We cannot, in standard musical notation for example, specify merely that a note is a quarternote regardless of pitch or merely that it is a middle c regardless of duration. We have no label for all quarternotes or for all middle e's; detached note-signs and empty staff Jines must be taken as vacant characters if notationality is to be preserved. All the properties of a given object
202
V,6
V,6
203
SCORE, SKETCH, AND SCRIPT
PROJECTIBILITY, SYNONYMY, ANALYTICITY
that are specifiable in a given notational system are thus coextensive.
The distinction between real and nominal defining still stands, as is illustrated by the difference between writing a score for a work already extant in performance and composing a new work. Once the language is given, a score or class of coextensive scores is in the first case uniquely determined by a performance, and a class of performances is in the second case uniquely determined by a score. But in both cases, all scores for a performance assign it to the same compliance-class: nothing is a performance of more than a single work. Where two works are performed in succession the resultant event, though it contains performances of each of the two, is itself a performance of neither but of the conjoint score.
That all scores for a performance are coextensive does not imply that all are synonymous. Two coextensive characters, CI and Ct. are not synonymous unless every two parallel compounds of them are also coextensive. That is, if replacement of Cl or C2 by the other in some compound character kl yields a character k2 with an extension different from that of k" then CI and C2 mayan good grounds be said to differ in rneaning.t" Furthermore, where two terms thus differ in meaning, even coextensive parallel compounds of them may be considered, derivatively, to differ in meaning. We noticed earlier that a c-sharp-sign and a d-flat-sign (equal in indicated duration, etc.) as they occur in piano scores have the same compliance-class of sounds, but that
since the effect of adding the natural-sign to these characters is to negate the sharp-sign and the flat-sign alike, the compliance-class for the c-sharp-natural-sign H consists of c-sounds and is disjoint from the compliance-class, consisting of d-sounds, for the d-fiat-natural-sign. Thus the c.. sharp-sign and the d-flat-sign, even though coextensive, are not synonymous; and neither are two scores, even if coextensive, that are parallel compounds of these characters.'!
16 The criterion of difference in meaning here employed is that set forth in my papers "On Likeneas of Meaning" and "On Some Dif-
ferences About Meaning" (cited in 1, note 19). The primary extension of a character consist. of what that character denotes: a .econdat'Y extension consists of what some compound of that character denotes. Two characters differ in meaning if they differ in primary extension or in any of their parallel secondary extensions. As applied to natural languages, where there is great freedom in generating compounds, this criterion tends to give the result that every two terms differ in meaning. No such result follow. for more restricted languages; and indeed for these the criterion may need to be strengthened by providing farther that characters differ in meaning if they are parallel compounds of terms that differ either in primary or in parallel secondary extension.
11 The charactsrs here in question comprise a note-sign, a sharp-sign or flat-sign (perhaps from the signatura), and a natural-sign that neutralizes the "harp-sign or fiat-sign. The order of precedence of the note-sign and the sharp-sign of flat-sign makes no difference; but a natural-sign cancels al! and only the sharp-signs or flat-signs that precede it and are (immediately or remotely) associated with the note-sign. To modify a c-double-sharp to a c-sharp, we must suffix a natura l-sign and then another sharp-sign, 90 that the unabbreviated result is a c-sharp-sharp·natura.l.sharp-sign.
IS All never-performed SCOres have the same (i.e., no) performanceJ as compliant s. They are scores for 'different works' in the oblique sense t hat pictures of unicorns and pictures of centaurs are pictures of different things. In neither case is there a difference in primary extension. The score for Jones's never-performed Symphony #9 and the score for his never-performed Piano Concerto #3 are strictly
204
V,6
V,6
205
SCORE, SKETCH, AND SCRIPT
LITERARY ARTS
Wherever there are coextensive nonsynonymous characters, a question may arise concerning principles of preference among them in any given context. Although "rational animal" and "featherless biped" be coextensive, still "All men are rational animals" is said-upon rather obscure grounds-to be analytic, and "All men are featherless bipeds" to be synthetic. How do matters stand in a system that is notational except for containing some coextensive characters? Musicians tell us that in a traditional piano score the usual rules of composition unequivocally decide whether a c-sharp-sign or a d-flat-sign should occur. Although no difference in performance can result, the wrong choice seems to violate a rule of grammatical etiquette comparable to that governing, say, the use in English of the prefixes "un" and "in". Indeed, we might say that using a c-sharp-sign where a d-flat-sign belongs is like saying that such a choice is untolera ble (or inbeara hie).
A more substantive consideration might be found in the relation of a work to its siblings for other instruments. As we have seen, specification of instrument is an integral part of any true score in standard musical notation; and a piano work and the violin version of it, for example, count strictly as different works. Nevertheless, certain violin performances rather than others are accepted as performances of the violin version of the piano work. Let us sup-
pos~ that fnr a given piano work 'the violin performances to recognized have a c-sharp and not a d-8at at a given place. The score [or the violin version of the piano work must then have at that place a c-sharp-sign and not a d-Ratsign. This would provide grounds for choosing the c-sharpsign in the piano score itself; the piano work might be said to have the c-sharp analytically in that in versions of the work for other instruments, where the c-sharp-sign and the d-Rat-sign are not coextensive. a c-sharp is mandatory.
How close such a criterion comes to the usual notion of analyticity is hard to say, since that notion is so hopelessly confused. But musical notation seems to offer so much less opportunity than does English for befuddlement over analyticity that some philosophers might do well to stop writing and start composing.
7~ Literary Arts
The text of a poem or novel or biography is a character in a notational scheme, As a phonetic character, with utterances as compliants, it belongs to an approximately notational systern.!" As a character with objects as cornpliants. it belongs to a discursive language.
Since in the latter case the compliance-classes are not disjoint or differentiated, texts are not scores but scripts. If cornp liance-cl asses of texts constituted works, then in some cases whether an object belongs to a given work
just the jones-Symphony-#9-score and the Jones-Piano-Concerto#3-score. Replacement of a character in the Jones-Symphony-#9- score will result in the Jones-Symphony-#9-score only if the replaced and replacing characters are coextensive and furthermore, in the way explained above, synonymous.
tll't'h ". "II
e appro,nmatlon WI not be very close in English. with ils wealth
of homonyms, inconstancies, etc .. but may be fairly close in a language like Spanish.
206
V,6
V,7
207
LITERARY ARTS
SCORE, SKETCH, AND SCRIPT
would be theoretically indeterminable, and in some cas, an object would be an instance of several works. But obv ously works of literature are not compliance-classes texts. The Civil War is not literature; and two histories 0 it are different works.
Nor can the work of literature be identified as the clas of utterances compliant with the text taken as a phoneti character. For even though the text be a true score, wit an exclusive disjoint and differentiated compliance-cia . an utterance obviously has no better title to be considered a~ instance of the work than does an inscription . of the
I
text. Utterances are not the end-products as are perform-
-ances-in .. music.Moreover, the- utterances themselves might equally well be considered either as coextensive with inscriptions of 'the text or as belonging to a conversephonetic language and having the inscriptions as compliants. Or since compliance is not always asymmetrical, utterances and inscriptions could be considered as having each other as their compliants. Or we might take written and spoken English say, as separate and parallel languages. A character of the on~ consists of inscriptions, a character of the other consists of utterances, while "character of English" can be taken either way if no restrictions are imposed by the context. But perhaps the simplest course is to consider a character of English to have utterances and inscriptions alike as members. This merely extends in a convenient and appropriate way the practice of counting widely varying marks as members of a single character. Syntactic disjointness--required of a notational scheme and hence of any language, not merely of a notational system-
will have to be preserved by refusing to accept any utterance as belonging to two different characters. Just as among certain matching letter-inscriptions some belong to the first letter of the alphabet while some belong to the fourth, so among utterances consisting of a hard-g-sound followed by a long-a-sound followed by a t-sound some will belong to the same character as inscriptions of "gate" while some will belong to the same character as inscriptions of "gait".
A literary work. then, is not the compliance-class of a text but the text or script itself. All and only inscriptions and utterances of the text are instances of the work; and identification of the work from instance to instance is ensured by the fact that the text is a character in a notational sc-neme--inavocabularyof syntactically disjoint and differentiated symbols. Even replacement of a character in a text by another synonymous character (if any can be found in a discursive language) yields a different work. Yet the work is the text not as an isolated class of marks and utterances but as a character in a language. The same class as a character in another language is another work. and a translation of a work is not an instance of that work. Both identity 'ot language and syntactic identity within the language are necessary conditions for identity of a literary work.
Obviously I am not concerned with what distinguishes some scripts as 'truly literary' works. Nevertheless, equating a poem with its text may arouse some protest, on the ground that the more immediate or intrinsic properties of classes of inscriptions and utterances hardly coincide with the aesthetically important properties of the poem. But in
V,7
209
208
V,7
DANCE
SCORE, SKETCH, AND SCRIPT
the first place, -d~fining literary works no more calls for setting forth all their significant aesthetic properties than defining metals calls lor setting forth all their significant chemical properties. In the second place, immediacy is a suspect notion and aesthetic relevance a subtle one; and no end of confusion has arisen from association of the two. To identify the literary work with a script is not to isolate and dessicate it but to recognize it as a denotative and expressive symbol that reaches beyond itself along all sorts of short and long referential paths.
We have seen that a musical score is in a notation and defines a work; that a sketch or picture is not in a notation but is itself a work; and that a literary script is both in a notation and is itself a work. Thus in the different arts a work is differently localized. In painting, the work is an individual object; and in etching, a class of objects. In music, the work is the class of performances compliant with a character. In 1iterature, the work is the character itself. And in calligraphy. we may add, the work is an individual inscription.i"
In the drama, as in music, the work is a compliance-class of performances. The text of a play, however, is a composite of score and script. The dialogue is in a virtually notational system, with utterances as its compliants. This part of the text is a score; and performances compliant with it
constitute the work. The stage directions, descriptions of scenery, etc., are scripts in a language that meets none of the semantic requirements for notationality; and a performance does not uniquely determine such a script or class of coextensive scripts. Given a performance, the dialogue can be univocally transcribed: different correct ways of writing it down will have exactly the same performances as compliants. But this is not true of the rest of the text. A given setting, for example, may comply with extensionaUy divergent descriptions; and its compliance with some descriptions may be theoretically undecidable. The parts of the text other than the dialogue count not as integral parts of the defining score but as supplementary instructions. In the case of a novel consisting partly or even entirely of dialogue, the text is the work; but the same text taken as the text for a play is or contains the score for a work. The script for a silent film is neither the cinematic work no!" a score for it but, though used in producing the film, is otherwise as loosely related to the work as is a verbal description of a painting to the painting itself.
8. Dance
~IJ The much' discussed question whether 8 work of art is III symbol thUJ , .. em, to me particularly fruitless. Not only may a work. depentling upon the art. be an object or 8 class Of. o~ie~ts or a. ch.ra~,ter in a language or an inscription. bul whichever It lS It may .n varlOu, ways symbolize other things_
The possibility of a notation for the dance was one of the initial questions that led to our study of notational systems. Because the dan~e is visual like painting, which has no notation, and yet transient and temporal like music, which has a highly developed standard notation. the answer is not altogether obvious; and ill-grounded negatives
··-V,7
.... v,s.
211
SCORE, SKETCH, AND SCRIPT
and irresponsible affirmatives have been put forth about equally often.
I
The ill-grounded negatives rest on the argument that
the dance, as a visual and mobile art involving the infi~ . nitely subtle and varied expressions and three-dimensional motions of one or more highly complex organisms, is fat too complicated to he captured by any notation. But, of course, a score need not capture all the subtlety and complexity of a performance. That would be hopeless even in the comparatively simpler art of music, and would always be pointless. The function of a score is to specify the essential properties a performance must have to belong to the work; the stipulations ace only of certain aspects and only within certain degrees. All other variations are permitted; and the differences among performances of the same work, even in music, are enormous.
The irresponsible affirmative answers consist of pointing out that a notation can be devised for almost anything. This, .of course, is irrelevant The significant issue is whether in terms of notational language we can provide real definitions that will identify a dance in its several performances. independently of any particular history of production.
For such real definitions to be possible there must, as we have seen, be an antecedent classification of performances into works that is similarly independent of history of production. This classification need not be neat or complete but must serve as a foil, a scaffolding, a springboard, for the development of a full and systematic classification.
212
v,s
DANCE
That the requisite antecedent classification exists for the dance seems clear. Prior to any notation, we make reasonably consistent judgments as to whether performances by different people are instances of the same dance. No theoretical barrier stands in the way of developing a suitable notational system.
Practical feasibility is another matter, not directly in question here. The antecedent classification is so rough and tentative that the decisions to be made are many, intricate, and consequential. And inadvertent violation of one of the syntactic or semantic requirements can easily result in a non-notational language or a system that is no language at all. Bold and intelligent systematization is called (or, aIong with a good deal of care.
Among notations that have been proposed for the dance, the one called Lebenoietion 21 after the inventor, Rudolf . Laban, seems deservedly to have gained most recognition.
An impressive scheme of analysis and description, it refutes the common belief that continuous complex motion
21 Laban was working on the matter in Vienna as early as the 1920's. He published Choreographie (J ena, Eugen Diederichs, 1926); Eiioct, with F. C. Lawrence (London, MacDonald & Evans, Ltd., 1947); and Principles 01 Dance and Movement Notation (London, MacDonald & Evans, Ltd., 1956). A convenient and weH-illustrated expcsrtion by Ann Hutchinson is available in II paperback book, Lebanotetion (Norfolk, Conn., New Directions, 1961), which is cited in the next three footnotes. One of the competing systems has been proposed by Rudolf and Joan Benesh in An Introduction to Dance Notation (London, Adam & Charles Black, Ltd., 1956). I leave it as an exercise for the reader to compare the Laban and Benesh systems in the light of the principles set forth in the present book.
v.s
213
SCORE, SKETCH, AND SCRIPT
DANCE
is too recalcitrant a subject-matter for notational articulation, and discredits the dogma that successful systematic description depends in general upon some inherent amenability-some native structural neatness-in what is described. Indeed, the development of Laban's language offers us an elaborate and intriguing example of the process that has come to be called "concept formation ",
How far, though, does the system meet the theoretical - requirements for a notational language? I can answer only tentatively, from an inadequate knowledge of the system.
.That.fhe.characters aresyntactically-disiointseems-clear. --Satisfaction of the requirements of finite differentiation is less easily ascertained; but Laban avoids a good many pitfalls here. For example, one naturally looks for a violation in the directional indications, since if every different angle of a line stands for a different direction, neither the syntactic nor the semantic requirement of differentiation is fulfilJed. But in Labanotation, direction of facing is indicated by a "direction pin" in any of eight positions disposed at equal intervals around the full horizontal circle (Figure 12);
and a direction halfway between any two proximate directions among these eight is indicated by combining the signs for the two (e.g., as in Figure 13).
Fjgure 13
-This-devlce-adinits oCIle) further iteration to indicate directions between two proximate directions among the sixteen. Elsewhere in the system, differentiation is often achieved just as decisively as here. One is alerted for trouble by such a statement as: "The relative length of the direction symbol shows its time value"; but here, as in music, time is divided into beats, and the least difference in duration provided for in the language is presumably the same as in standard musical notation.~~
Like standard musical notation, Labanotation provides for more and less specific scoring, and so violates the condition of semantic disjointness, The ad lib signs and the explicit license to describe in detail or leave open certain
Figure 12
22 Or less. The least duration indicated by any of the characters actually presented or mentioned in Lebenotetion (p. 52) is onesixteenth of a beat, probably because at even the slowest normal tempo, that is the shortest time in which a dancer can be expected to execute a distinct and recognizable unit of movement. But so long as a limit is set, just where does not matter.
214
v,s
v.s
215
SCORE, SKETCH, AND SCRIPT
DANCE
aspects of a movement 2~ have much the same effect as do the free-cadenza and figured-bass notations in music. The result is that identity of a work will not be preserved in every chain of alternating steps between scores and performances. The flexibility offered may be welcomed by the choreographer or composer, and does not affect scoreto-performance steps; but it leaves the performance-toscore steps insufficiently determined until the specificity of the scoring is stipulated. Labanotation as a whole is a discursive language comprising several notational subsystems; and in some cases, a class of performances may be a work relative to one but not another of these notational systems.
So far, I have been considering only the basic vocabulary. Some of the other symbolism introduced cannot be embraced in any notational system. A prime example is the use of words or pictures to indicate physical objects involved in the dance.P' If object-words in general are ad-
rnitted, then semantic disjcintness and differentiation are sacrificed and we have a discursive language. If objectsketches in general are admitted, then syntactic differentiation goes by the board, too, and we do not even have a language. One remedy would be to restrict the admitted words or pictures very severely in appropriate ways. Another, suggested earlier for tempo-words in music and stage directions in the drama, would be to treat these characters not as integral parts of a score at all but as supplementary and nondefinitive. Whether this is fitting depends upon whether (as seems fair enough) a performance employing different objects or even none is an instance of the same dance, just as a performance of Hamlet in modern dress and without scenery or accessories is an instance of the same play.
All in all, Labanotation passes the theoretical tests very well-about as well as does ordinary musical notation, and perhaps as well as is compatible with practicality. I am not saying that we have here a good or effective notational system for the dance, that the decisions embodied in it are sound or happy or consistent. Such an appraisal by a layman would be impertinent and worthless. By extensive use, the language may be found unsatisfactory or become traditional enough to acquire authority. If this or another language becomes standard enough, its underlying analysis of movement into factors and particles will prevail; arbitrary decisions will blossom into absolute truth, and expedient units for discourse ripen into the ultimate components of reality-awaiting revolution.
.Laban.ccnceived.his system as a notation not merely for
23 For use of the lid lib signs, see Labanotldion, pp. 88, 187. On permitted varrance in specifidty of scoring, see e.g., pp. 59, 262. In such passages we find, I think, the significance of the introductory statement: "Labanotation allow! for any degree of spedficity" (p. 6). Read as meaning that the system allows for specification to within any given degree of precision whatsoever, this statement would imply lack of differentiation.
Incidentally, Labanotation seems to be redundant, although whether alternat:ive symbols are actually coextensive is not always clear from the exposition (e.g., see p. 144). We have seen that coextensive characters in music sometimes differ in meaning through entedng into parallel compounds that differ in extension; so far I have not discovered any analogue of this in Labanotation.
-2t- UiblihofiitiOil; pp.179C.l1:l1~"·-------------------- -
216
v.s
v,s
217
SCORE, SKETCH, AND SCRIPT
ARCHITECTURE
dance but for human movement in general, and went on to develop and supplement the system as a means for analyzing and classifying all human physical activities. The need for some such system is especially apparent, for example, in industrial engineering and in psychological experimentation. Whether the experimenter or the subject repeats his behavior on a second occasion depends upon the criteria of identity of behavior that are applied; and the problem of formulating such criteria is the problem of developing a notational system. As for nonhuman movement, a zoologist has recently proposed an entertaining and illuminating method of codifying the various gaits of horses.25
Careful drawing to scale is merely for convenience and elegance; a rough and distorted version, with the same letters and numerals, qualifies as a true copy of the most precisely drafted blueprint, prescribes the constitutive properties as rigorously, and has the same buildings as compliants. In the second place, while the numerals as characters in the unlimited set of fractional numerals are scripts, the numerals admissible in architectural plans are tacitly restricted--e.g., so that measurements are to be given only, say, to the nearest thirty-second of an inch. So long as any such restriction is in force, the admitted part of numerical language does not, like the whole, violate the condition of finite differentiation, but qualifies as notational. Thus, although a drawing often counts as a sketch, and a measurement in numerals as a script, the particular selection of drawing and numerals in an architectural plan counts as a digital diagram and as a score.
Architectural plans, like musical scores, may sometimes define works as broader than we usually take them. For the architect's specifications of materials and construction (whether written out separately or on the plans) can no more be considered integral parts of a score than can the composer's verbal specifications of tempo. An architect is free to stipulate that the material of a foundation be stone, or that it be granite, or that it be Rockport seam-faced granite. Given the building, we cannot tell which of these nesting terms occurs in the specifications. The class of buildings picked out by the plans-plus-specifications is narTower than that defined by the plans alone; but the plansplus-specifications make up a script, not a score. Thus the
9. Architecture
The architect's papers are a curious mixture. The specifications are written in ordinary discursive verbal and numerical language. The renderings made to convey the appearance of the finished building are sketches. But what of the plans?
Because a plan is a drawing, with lines and angles subject to continuous variation, the first guess would be that it is technically a sketch. But on the plan are measurements in words and figures. This suggests that we have here a combination of sketch and script. But I think this again is wrong. In the first place, the drawing is used only to indicate the relative location of elements and measurements.
25 See Milton Hildebrand, "Symmetrical Gaits of Hones", Science, vol. 150 (1965), pp. 701-708.
218
V,9
V,9
219
SCORE, SKETCH, AND SCRIPT
ARCHITECTURE
question whether two buildings are instances of the same work, relative to the architect's total language, is an indeterminate one, Relative to the notational language of plans, it is determinate; but the work is then identified with a more comprehensive class than is customary, However, exact conformity between definition and ordinary practice is never required or to be expected.
We must not be misled by the fact that the complianceclass of a set of plans happens so often to consist of but one.building..or by-the preeminent .interest or valuethat-a given instance of an architectural work may have; or by the emphasis sometimes laid upon immediate supervision, by the architect, of the process of construction. Many a composition is played only once; certain performances of other pieces have exceptional importance; and a building or performance executed under the direction of the designer or composer, while a more personal product and perhaps much better (or much worse) than another building or performance from the same plans or score, is not therefore a more authentic or original instance of the work.
Nevertheless, the work of architecture is not always as surely disengaged from a particular building as is a work of music from a particular performance. The end-product of architecture, unlike that of music, is not ephemeral; and the notational language was developed in response rather to the need for participation of many hands in construction. The language thus has weaker. warrant for, and meets more resistance in, overriding the primordial autographic stage of the art. Plainly enough, all houses complying with
the plans for Smith-Jones Split-Level # 17 are equally instances of that architectural work. But in the case of an earlier architectural tribute to womanhood, the Taj Mahal, we may bridle at considering another building from the same plans and even on the same site to be an instance of the same work rather than a copy. We are not as comfortable about identifying an architectural work with a design rather than a building as we are about identifying a musical work with a composition rather than a performance. In
-that architecture- has a reasonably appropriate nQt~tional system and that some of its works are unmistakably allographic, the art is allographic, But insofar as its notational language has not yet acquired full authority to divorce identity of work in all cases from particular production, architecture is a mixed and transitional case.
In the present chapter I have been applying, chiefly to symbol systems in the arts, principles developed in Chapter IV in response to questions raised in Chapter III. The reader will already have discerned that these principles have some bearing upon problems left unresolved in the first two chapters. I now turn to those problems again and to other unfinished business.
220
V,9
221
----~.----