Pragmatic Aspects of Meaning II: Speech Acts, Conversational Implicature
Pragmatic Aspects of Meaning II: Speech Acts, Conversational Implicature
Speech Acts
What kinds of things do speakers do by uttering sentences? Speakers perform SPEECH ACTS.
Austin (1962) says that when a speaker utters a sentence, s/he may perform three types of acts: locutionary act, illocutionary act and perlocutionary act.
Locutionary act: an act of uttering a sentence with a certain sense and reference, which is roughly equivalent to meaning in the traditional sense. (1) The nal exam will be difcult.
The locutionary act performed in uttering a declarative sentence can be thought of as the act of stating, placing the proposition in question in the common ground of some discourse.
1
Performative Utterances
A performative utterance does not simply convey a message, but performs some action or initiates a state that the content of the declarative describes. That is, the primary meaning of a performative utterance seems to be coming from the illocutionary force associated with it. (3) a. We nd the defendant guilty as charged. b. I bid three clubs. c. I promise to split any lottery winnings with you. d. Youre red. e. You may have dessert tonight. f. Gentlemen are requested to wear jackets and ties to dinner.
Performative utterances do not make statements, unlike ordinary declaratives. Rather, by uttering (3b), the speaker is making a bid and by uttering (3c), the speaker is making a promise.
4
It doesnt make sense to say that performative utterances are true or false. What is special about them is that the utterance itself is what makes the circumstances t the words. That is, the utterance of sentence S brings into existence the very facts that S describes.
While performative utterances cannot be said to be true or false, they can be said to be felicitous or infelicitous. Austin notes that certain conventions called felicity conditions regulate the use of performative utterances. If felicity conditions governing the use of a certain form fail to be satised, then the use of the form may misre. For instance, one of the felicity conditions for uttering We nd the defendant guilty as charged is that the speaker has the authority to issue a verdict.
5
Performative Hypothesis
Performative hypothesis: all sentences are performative utterances at some abstract level. (4) I performative verb you that S
The verbs that specify the illocutionary acts being performed is called PERFORMATIVE VERBS: e.g., promise, warn, threat, declare, ask, order, request, predict, etc. (5) a. Ill send you an email next week. I promise to you that Ill send you an email next week. b. The nal exam will be difcult. I warn you that the nal exam will be difcult. c. Send me an email next week. I request to you that you send me an email next week.
7
More on why we dont want illocutionary force to be part of literal linguistic meaning
A sentence can be associated with several different illocutionary forces, depending on the discourse context. If illocutionary forces were a matter of linguistic meaning, then we would have to say that sentences are in general ambiguous. But then what would be the source of this ambiguity? The fact that an utterance can express different illocutionary forces is a matter of assumptions and attitudes of the speaker toward the propositional content expressed by the utterance.
More on why we dont want illocutionary force to be part of literal linguistic meaning (cont.)
A single utterance can express two different illocutionary forces at the same time. (8) I will send you an email next week.
By uttering (8), the speaker can report a decision, and at the same time make a promise. Generally, for a single utterance of an ambiguous expression, speakers convey only one of the linguistically assigned meanings. (9) a. John is sitting by the bank. b. John saw a man with a binoculars.
10
More on why we dont want illocutionary force to be part of literal linguistic meaning (cont.)
There are many different ways to accomplish an illocutionary aim. The sentences in (10) can all be used to make a request to the hearer to bring some water. (10) a. b. c. d. Bring me a glass of water. I would like to drink some water. Can I have some water? I am really thirsty.
We dont want to say that they are synonymous just because they have the same illocutionary force. How can speakers use sentences to express various types of illocutionary forces other than the canonical sentential force they are associated with? How can speakers so successfully use language to convey more than what the overtly expressed words say?
11
Implicature
An utterance of sentence S has p as its implicature just in case in uttering S, the speaker invites the hearer to infer that the speaker is making a commitment to p. Conventional implicature: Implications on the basis of the conventional meanings of the words occurring in a sentence. (11) a. John is English, but he is cowardly. b. John is English, and he is cowardly. c. Johns being cowardly is somehow surprising in light of his being English.
Truth-conditionally, (11a-11b) have the same meaning. But only (11a) implies something along the lines of (11c). Conversational implicature: Implications derived on the basis of conversational principles and assumptions, relying on more than the linguistic meaning of words in a sentence. We will mainly focus on conversational implicatures in this section.
12
To implement this principle, rational speakers choose what to say in light of the following MAXIMS: (13) a. Relation: Be relevant. b. Quantity: Be only as informative as required for current conversational purposes. c. Quality: Say only what you believe to be true and adequately supported. d. Manner: Be perspicuous. That is, be brief and orderly and avoid obscurity and ambiguity.
13
Grice is saying that language users assume that the speakers are following these maxims to articulate a conversational strategy for cooperatively conveying information. Thus, hearers will assume that speakers are following these maxims, and will interpret what speakers say, under this assumption. This will allow hearers to infer things beyond what is actually said, deriving a certain conversational implicature.
14
(14a) entails (14c), but conversationally implicates (14b). The hearer will assume that the speaker of (14a) is following the conversational maxims. In particular, the maxim of quantity says that the speaker should be informative enough. So, the hearer will deduce that if the speaker knew that John had more than one car, he would have said so. Also, according to the maxim of quality, the hearer will assume that the speaker knows what he is talking about. So, the hearer will deduce that the speaker has the correct information as to how many cars John has. Through this kind of calculation, the hearer will infer (14b).
15
Implicatures are defeasible/cancelable. Sometimes, the context (or the speaker himself) may provide a new information that effects the calculation of a conversational implicature, canceling it. (15) a. John has a car. b. John has a car. Perhaps, even two. (16) a. Mary got married and got pregnant. b. Mary got married and got pregnant, but not in that order.
16
These examples show that although different linguistic forms can express the same literal content, they dont always result in the same implicatures. The exact form in which that content is expressed is often a signicant factor in deriving a certain implicature.
17
Scalar Implicature
Certain group of words are related with each other with respect to a scale. (20) a. every > some b. excellent > good > ok The meaning expressed by the weaker member of the scale is consistent with the meaning expressed by the stronger member. However, if a speaker utters a sentence using the weaker member of the scale, the implication is that the stronger member of the scale does not hold. (21) a. Some students did very well on the exam. b. Not every student did very well on the exam. Some students did not do very well on the exam. (22) a. This paper is good. b. This paper is not excellent.
18
Cancelability (23) (24) Some of the students did very well on the exam. Perhaps all. This paper will certainly be good. And it may well be excellent.
19
With the help of Gricean maxims, we can argue that semantically either...or is unambiguously inclusive, and that sometimes, it gives rise to exclusive interpretation as an implicature.
Calculation In general, in restaurants, a customer orders one dish per meal. And appealing to maxim of quantity, if John had ordered both steak and sh, the speaker would have said so, using an expression more informative than or, perhaps and. But since s/he did not use and, s/he must be in no position to to do so. Hence, the implicature that John ordered only one dish arises.
20
(27)
If either...or is ambiguous, then negation of either...or should also be ambiguous. Under the inclusive meaning: a sentence with negation of either...or is true iff both of the disjuncts are false. Under the exclusive meaning: a sentence with negation of either...or is true if (i) both of the disjuncts are false; or (ii) both of the disjuncts are true.
21
Is either...or ambiguous between exclusive and inclusive meaning? (Semantic Argument) (cont.)
Metalinguistic negation Some negative sentences appear to be supporting evidence for positing that either...or also has exclusive meaning semantically. (28) a. John didnt order either steak or sh for lunch. b. John didnt order EITHER steak or sh for lunch. He ordered both.
But negation in (28b) is not a regular negation that negates the proposition. It is a METALINGUISTIC NEGATION that attacks the word either and implies that the use of either is incorrect. More examples of metalinguistic negation: (29) a. That novel isnt GOOD; its absolutely superb. b. She didnt get SOME of the questions right; she answered every single one correctly. c. John doesnt LIKE that woman; he loves her.
22
Is either...or ambiguous between exclusive and inclusive meaning? (Semantic Argument) (cont.)
It is not the case that ... (30) a. b. It is not the case that John ordered either steak or sh. # It is not the case that John ordered either steak or sh. He ordered both steak and sh.
neither...nor A negative version of either...or is neither...nor. If either...or is ambiguous, then we should expect neither...nor to be ambiguous as well. But, neither...nor is only interpretable as negating the inclusive meaning of either...or. (31) a. b. John ordered neither steak nor sh. # John ordered neither steak nor sh. He ordered both steak and sh.
23
Sometimes, maxims are apparently outed by the speaker, and yet the hearer still assumes that the cooperative principle is in play, and tries to infer what the speaker intends to convey on this basis.
Flouting the maxim of quantity and maxim of relevance (32) In a letter of recommendation for a student applying for a graduate school a. John has a nice smile and has great handwriting. b. John is not a smart student. The letter writer is intentionally being not very informative and providing irrelevant information as to the quality of John as a potential graduate school candidate. The letter writer must know this, and therefore s/he must be trying to indicate that there is nothing good to say about John.
24
Flouting the maxim of quality (34) a. Queen Victoria was made of iron. b. Queen Victoria was hard, resilient, and non-exible.
Flouting the maxim of manner (35) a. Miss Singer produced a series of sounds corresponding closely to the score of an aria. b. Miss Singer sang an aria (and wasnt very good).
QUESTION: People lie and succeed all the time, violating the maxim of quality. Does this mean that the maxim of quality is incorrect? How can we reconcile the maxim of quality and the fact that people lie?
25