0% found this document useful (0 votes)
144 views17 pages

Sufficiency Strategy

One alleged weapon against unsustainable environmental impact is for the wealthy to consume less. This sufficiency strategy is to complement the efficiency strategy of lowering ratios of resource inputs to economic outputs. This strategy moreover addresses only the rich, raising questions of its theoretical maximum efficacy.
Copyright
© Attribution Non-Commercial (BY-NC)
We take content rights seriously. If you suspect this is your content, claim it here.
Available Formats
Download as PDF, TXT or read online on Scribd
0% found this document useful (0 votes)
144 views17 pages

Sufficiency Strategy

One alleged weapon against unsustainable environmental impact is for the wealthy to consume less. This sufficiency strategy is to complement the efficiency strategy of lowering ratios of resource inputs to economic outputs. This strategy moreover addresses only the rich, raising questions of its theoretical maximum efficacy.
Copyright
© Attribution Non-Commercial (BY-NC)
We take content rights seriously. If you suspect this is your content, claim it here.
Available Formats
Download as PDF, TXT or read online on Scribd
You are on page 1/ 17

EC O LO GIC A L E CO N O M ICS 6 4 ( 2 00 8 ) 7 7 0 7 86

a v a i l a b l e a t w w w. s c i e n c e d i r e c t . c o m

w w w. e l s e v i e r. c o m / l o c a t e / e c o l e c o n

ANALYSIS

The sufficiency strategy: Would rich-world frugality lower environmental impact?


Blake Alcott
Gretenweg 4, 8038 Zrich, Switzerland

AR TIC LE I N FO
Article history: Received 22 April 2006 Received in revised form 26 February 2007 Accepted 30 April 2007 Available online 12 June 2007 Keywords: I = PAT Resource consumption Sufficiency rebound Efficiency Ethics Quotas

ABS TR ACT
One alleged weapon against unsustainable environmental impact is for the wealthy to consume less. This sufficiency strategy is to complement the efficiency strategy of lowering ratios of resource inputs to economic outputs; the former would reduce the affluence factor in I = PAT, the latter the technology factor. That the latter strategy suffers from a consumption rebound is widely recognized. This paper identifies a similar rebound when the affluence factor is autonomously lowered: The lower initial demand lowers prices, which in turn stimulates new demand by others. The strategy moreover addresses only the rich, raising questions of its theoretical maximum efficacy. Its proponents usually conflate frugality with the NorthSouth dichotomy and intragenerational with intergenerational equity. Moreover, there are difficulties with the supporting arguments that frugality is good for ones own sake as well as for the environment, and that the rich should lead the way to living more lightly. Personal behaviour change is furthermore not a substitute for international political efforts. Finally, since all changes in right-side factors of the I = PAT equation change other right-side factors, such indirect attacks on impact should be abandoned in favor of supply and emissions quotas. 2007 Elsevier B.V. All rights reserved.

1.

Introduction

The institutions [of a steady-state economy]seek to inducea change toward resource-saving technology and patterns of living, and to a greater reliance on solar energy and renewable resources. Herman Daly (1974, p.18) In the I = PAT equation the causes of environmental impact are population, affluence, and technology. Environmental strategies here denotes groups of policies to lower resource consumption

and emissions,1 and are classified under these three headings. While population strategies are seldom discussed, much attention shines on the T factor, specifically the technological efficiency strategy meant to raise the ratio of affluence to the environmental goods used up in the economic process through technology per se as well as measures such as environmental bookkeeping, life cycle analysis, mandated capital efficiency, renewable resources, recycling, legal standards, taxes, and consumption efficiency. More broadly, the T factor is an ornery variable including

Tel.: +41 44 481 27 36. E-mail address: [email protected].

1 I define consumption as using up (German Verbrauch) rather than use (Gebrauch) i.e. as taking with or destruction following Boulding (194950; 1992, 117, 129; also Princen, 1999, 355) and conjecture that pollution is reducible to consumption of goods such as clean air or water.

0921-8009/$ - see front matter 2007 Elsevier B.V. All rights reserved. doi:10.1016/j.ecolecon.2007.04.015

EC O L O G IC A L E C O N O M IC S 6 4 ( 2 0 08 ) 77 0 7 86

771

production-process efficiency, input/emissions ratios, degrees of emissions toxicity, risk, and institutions. Affluence is consumption (depletion) or emissions (pollution) per person; the sufficiency strategy attacks this affluence (A) factor, seeking to lower per capita resource consumption in hopes of thereby lowering total or aggregate consumption or impact (I). Of course, humanism demands restricting this strategy to those who are consuming at least enough for their health, reproduction, longevity and education. Lowering the affluence of the poor would after all mean more sickness, death, and armed conflict. The strategy thus envisions cuts in material and energy consumption within the affluent target group that are large enough to reduce total impact even if (hopefully) the poor consume more. In this it is thus distinct from the strategy to lower MIPS (Material Input Per unit of Service) (Hinterberger et al., 1996). MIPS computations assume that the denominator (whether expressed as monetary GDP, services, utility, or material consumption) remains constant or rises while the numerators of resource inputs are minimised, whereas sufficiency intends a lower output, a smaller denominator, lower global demand. The factor four blueprint doubling affluence while halving impact similarly foresees no doing without (Von Weizscker et al., 1997; Schmidt-Bleeck, 1994; Grubb, 1990).2 One analysis illustrating the application of I = PAT and setting the stage for the sufficiency strategy is that of Ekins, which computes how much technological improvement is needed if 1) sustainability requires halving impact, and 2) population will double and affluence quadruple by 2040 T would have to decrease 93% (1991, 250; Goodland and Daly, 1992, 131). The obvious difficulty of this leads Ekins to place hope in frugality: The environmental crisis, the crisis of unsustainability, must be laid squarely at the door of northern industrial consumer lifestyles and their imitations now in nearly all the countries of the Third World. (249; [see my] Section 4.1) Rather than appeal to ethical duty he envisions the double benefit of less impact as well as, since money doesnt buy happiness, a better family life and better health without stress and pollution. (253; Section 4.3) In Section 2 I define and describe the strategy. Section 3 shows that like the efficiency strategy it triggers a consumption rebound: Whereas inputoutput efficiency constitutes an income effect and can lower prices of material-energy inputs, lighter lifestyles of the wealthy constitute an autonomous demand reduction that lowers prices. In both cases new demand emerges, in the case of sufficiency that of new or marginal consumers who take up the slack left by the previous consumers environmentally motivated frugality. This rebound is plausible if there is latent demand and if supply functions are relatively price inelastic. Section 4 identifies four questionable strands in arguments for the strategy: the NorthSouth dichotomy, intragenerational ethics, selfish reasons for sufficiency, and emphasis on personal rather than political behaviour. Section 5 discusses 1) some concepts necessary for quantification of strategy goals and
2

possibilities; 2) the costliness of co-ordinating changes in the independent variables on the right side of I = PAT; and 3) quotas as opposed to taxes.

2.

The sufficiency strategy

Although the plan to lower impact by consuming less consists mainly of exhortation, and seldom of legal restrictions on consumption,3 I nevertheless call this body of thought a strategy, both because a sizeable advocacy literature exists and because, however weak the means of achieving it presently are, the goal of humanity's living materially more modestly is a clear and, for many, appealing vision. First I define the strategy, then describe it in the form of a literature survey.

2.1.

Definition

Starting with what it is not, the strategy is distinct from the correction of policies or institutions that make us consume more than we would like: e.g., settlement and zoning policies and poor public transportation bless us with unwanted hours behind the steering wheel (Rpke, 1999; Sanne, 2002). It is also not the correction of externalities and market failures that favour consumption by rendering natural resources too cheap; i.e., it has nothing to do with welfare economics optimality. Finally, it is not the same as consumption efficiency, by which is meant behaviour that achieves a given level of utility with less (energy) input: e.g., boiling only the amount of water needed for the cup of coffee, switching off unneeded lights, or carpooling. (Hannon, 1975; Etzioni, 1998, 630; Prettenthaler and Steininger, 1999; Princen et al., 2002, 67; Nrgard, 2006, 96) Sufficiency, in contrast, means doing without the cup of coffee, getting by with dimmer lighting, and not taking the car. That is, assuming that environmental concern is left out of the utility function, sufficiency implies lower utility or welfare. (Section 4.3) Two concepts are needed to define sufficiency behaviour. First, it presupposes purchasing power: Those who are to alter their behaviour towards less consumption must be able to consume. Their purchasing power either remains unused or is itself reduced through working and earning less. The second concept is environmental motivation: We all limit consumption at some point, for many reasons. I am however confining the definition to the costs of non-consumption that are voluntarily traded for the benefits of believing one is relieving human pressure on planetary resources and thus benefiting other (present or future) humans or other species.

2.2.

Literature survey

Using the method of ostensive definition, several quotations from the literature advocating sufficiency follow. One paradigmatic statement is, The North should stabilize its rate of
3

It is thus incorrect to conflate the efficiency and sufficiency strategies, as when the MIPS strategy is called a naturehuman model of doing without or when factor four or factor ten strategies are characterised as being maximally sufficient at the existence minimum (quoted by Luks, 2000, 61).

Even the neglected population strategy often goes beyond education and propaganda to subsidise sterilisations, birth control technology, and abortions, or proscribe one-child families. During wars many societies ration (Simms, 2005), but today we are merely encouraged to live more lightly.

772

EC O LO GIC A L E CO N O M ICS 6 4 ( 2 00 8 ) 7 7 0 7 86

resource consumption to free resources for the South and to free up ecological space [by] reducing Northern throughput growth and decreasing Northern consumerism; we must both adjust... consumption patterns and reduce the environmental impact of each unit of consumption... (Goodland and Daly, 1992, 131, 142; Section 4.1) This argument is partly from intragenerational equity: Less consumerism... in the North could be invested in much-needed poverty alleviation and growth in the South (133; Section 4.2). As an argument from environmental quality it is moreover implicitly intergenerational: If the rich North would at least stabilize its resource consumption, global resource destruction and waste will fall. The call is for remolding consumers preferences and steering wants in the direction of environmentally benign activities and for less consumption by rich countries, whose material well-being can sustain halting or even reversing throughput growth (Goodland et al., 1992, xii, xv). Elsewhere the same authors observe that OECD overconsumers cause both intragenerational inequality and our global hurtling away from environmental sustainability, attesting the wasteful and destructive practices being pursued by Northern consumption and pollution patterns and noting in support of the sufficient lifestyle that affluence and overconsumption do not increase welfare (1996, 1005, 1015, 1009; Section 4). Sufficiency is thus a concept which needs dissemination and which they define as doing more with less4 and emphasizing quality and non-material satisfactions. (1009) Their question is: [C]an humans lower their per capita impact (mainly in OECD countries) at a rate sufficiently high to counterbalance their explosive increases in population (mainly in low-income countries)? (1011) Daily and Ehrlich similarly advocate the de-development of the overdeveloped countries, that is, controlling runaway consumption in order to reduce the physical throughput of their economies (1996, 1000). In I = PAT terms, Princen holds that Consumption or, more precisely, overconsumption, ranks with population and technology as a major driver of global environmental change (1999, 348). After decades of research into production, overall human or economic activity, equity, technology, or population, he urges a comprehensive research agenda on consumption and environment (349, 352). He envisions peoples choices not to purchase or to seek less consumptive, less material-intensive means of satisfying a need, and where needs cannot be met non-materially, this can be done less impact-intensively (354). He relies on a conventional concept of normal or background consumption and goes on to identify harmful ways of material provisioning, variously termed excessive or maladaptive consumption, problematic consumption, or the overconsumption harmful to our species and the misconsumption harmful to the individual. He diagnoses the inability of individuals to meet their needs in a given social context (356358) and pleas for lower consumption by us Northerners and Southern elites who can indeed change to embrace thrift, frugality, and selfreliance (360, 361). Rpke's starting point is likewise that growing consumption in the North contributes substantially to environ4

mental problems, and considerations about the need to change lifestyles are popping up in official publications (1999, 401). Consumption patterns must change, through mainfold concrete measures (417418), toward less environmental intensity. However, this move towards labour-intensive goods and services: theatre and music performances, courses in new skills, lectures on interesting topics, art objects, high quality clothes and houses made as handicrafts, child care, and massage treatments is not likely to take place, and therefore there is no way around consumption reduction (401402). However, this environmentally and distributionally motivated desire to halt the forces behind ever growing consumption is hard to fulfill due to causes lying in the domains of economics, socio-economic institutions, sociopsychology, history, and socio-technology (402, 416). Like others including Schor (1992, 1999a, 1999b; Veblen, 1899, 111) she attests the prima facie reasonableness of gaining free time through consuming and working less (403), concluding that while voluntary curtailment of consumption in the rich countries is first of all an ethical issue, we should avoid too much moralizing (416417). Building on both Rpke and Agenda 21, Sanne identifies reduc[ing] consumption in rich countries as a condition for sustainable development. This turns the searchlight on the consumer as the principal lever of change (2002, 273; Section 4.4). Household consumption in industrial societies like the UK must decline and the fact that consumption comes in packages calls for an analysis of activities and aggregate consumption as it is realized in lifestyles (274). The predicament of overconsumption can only be overcome if the values behind present lifestyles change; the green claim in this spirit is that we should combine the trend towards higher efficiency with a sense of sufficiency the ethical question of living lightly (275). Not just as consumers, but also as citizens in the political process (275), we are subject to economic, cultural, and socialstructural forces driving consumption (276, 284). He then advocates several institutional and lifestyle measures to further sustainable consumption and liberate consuming agents locked-in by... circumstances (282286). A similar analysis by Spangenberg and Lorek sees households making a difference and uses the concept of consumption clusters to compute low-impact affluence in the interests of eco-sufficiency (2002, 134, 139). Further recent works zeroing in on consumptions negative environmental5 impact are Rosenblatt (1999) and Princen et al. (2002). Earlier, Jevons endorsed the sufficiency strategy to save coal (1865, 138), and Scitovsky's analysis of addictive status consumption in our joyless economy touched on environmental problems (1976, 144, 283284), as did that of Leiss (1976, 9899, 139). But the ecological critique of consumption began in earnest with Meadows et al. (1972), Schumacher (1973) and Daly (1973) and has been continued by Johnson (1985), Durning
5 Other literature on the social, ethical, aesthetic, and psychological, rather than environmental, costs of consumption includes Rae (1834), Mackenzie (1892), Smart (1892), Veblen (1899), Galbraith (1958a), Baudrillard (1970), Linder (1970), Hirsch (1976), Douglas and Isherwood (1979/96), Mason (1981), Frank (1985, 1999), McCracken (1988), Schor (1992), Fine and Leopold (1993), Cross (1993, 2000), Ramstad (1998), Waller and Robertson (1998), Kasser (2002), and Brekke et al. (2003).

In contrast, I classify this within the efficiency strategy.

EC O L O G IC A L E C O N O M IC S 6 4 ( 2 0 08 ) 77 0 7 86

773

(1992), Hinchliffe (1995), Lintott (1998), Duchin (1998), and Jackson and Marks (1999). Ways of manipulating people into consuming less are dealt with by Cook and Berrenberg (1981), Ornstein and Ehrlich (1989), Meadows et al. (1992), Gardner and Stern (1996), Siebenhner (2000), Brown and Cameron (2000), and Ekins (2004). However, there is no better statement of both the efficiency and the sufficiency questions than the early one of Galbraith (1958b). In the days when environmental protection was called conservation, he wrote that our gargantuan and growing appetite has become the point of departure for all discussions of the resource problem. [W]e have been busily assessing reserves of various resources and measuring the rate of depletion against the rate of discovery. We have become concerned with the efficiency of methods of recovery. [T]he high rate of resource use has stirred interest in the technology of resource use and substitution. [I]nzvestment ininnovation may well substitute, at more or less constant rates, for investment in orthodox discovery and recovery. This means, in less formidable language, that if a country puts enough of its resources into researching new materials or new sources of materials, it may never be short of the old ones. (9091) He was one of the first to move beyond efficiency to sufficiency: If we are concerned about our great appetite for materials, it is plausible to seek to increase the supply, to decrease waste, to make better use of the stocks that are available, and to develop substitutes. But what of the appetite itself? Surely this is the ultimate source of the problem. If it continues its geometric course, will it not one day have to be restrained? Yet in the literature of the resource problem this is the forbidden question. (92) Presaging present challenges to consumer behavior and moves away from exclusively working on production efficiency, he notes that for instance the President's Materials Policy Commission began its report by stating its conviction that economic growth was important and, in degree, sacrosanct. First, we share the belief of the American people in the principle of Growth. (It is instructive to note the commissions use of a capital G. A certain divinity is associated with the word.) Growth in this context means an increasing output of consumers goods and an increase in the plant by which they are supplied. Having started with this renunciation, the commission was scarcely in a position to look critically at consumption in relation to the resource problem, and it did not (93). His pioneering critique of high consumptions low correlation with satisfaction concludes that if conservation is an issue, then we have no honest and logical course but to measure the means for restraining use against the means for insuring a continuing sufficiency of supply and taking the appropriate action. There is no justification for ruling consumption levels out of the calculation (98).

3.

The sufficiency rebound

This section seeks to render plausible the most important weakness of the sufficiency strategy, namely that its effectiveness is reduced by a rebound effect. To explain the sufficiency rebound stemming from autonomous frugal behaviour, it is necessary to describe the rebound concept in terms of its original domain, namely (energy) efficiency. This detour is justified moreover because the sufficiency literature often welcomes greater technological energy efficiency (T) but regards it as insufficient to lower impact, thus giving rise, in the first place, to the complementary sufficiency strategy (A). Using basic economic concepts familiar from the efficiency rebound literature, the assertion is that due to ensuing price drops, frugal behavior causes new consumption by others.

3.1.

The efficiency rebound

While sufficiency means lowering A on the right side of I = PAT, efficiency would lower T, not in point of toxics or risk, but rather of material and energy inputs per unit of production. This technological ratio measures for instance the amount of energy put into a lumen, a tonkilometre, a heated cubic metre of air, or tonne of steel, as well to material inputs like metals, stone, glass, and plastics (all with their own energy costs), and lower ratios constitute technological efficiency increases.6 The belief that these relieve environmental pressure is too widespread to need documentation. However, the efficiency strategy has an Achilles heel first elaborated by Jevons (1865, Chs. VIIXII) and known as the backfire problem or simply as Jevons Paradox (Giampietro and Mayumi, 1998, 2425; Alcott, 2005). Khazzoom's modern formulation of the problem assumed positive price elasticity of demand and observed that ...changes in [household] appliance efficiency have a price content[;] with increased productivity comes a decline in the effective price of commodities, and... in the face of lower effective prices, demand does not remain stagnant... but tends to increase (1980, 22, 23; Brookes, 1978). Holding the number of consumed units constant then multiplying by the lower inputoutput ratio achieved by new technology per unit yields the theoretical quantity engineering savings (Binswanger, 2001, 122). Rebound is then the percentage of this savings not realized due to income and price effects. If for example more efficient motors mean that a given number of driven kilometers is newly possible at less expense, this is the same as increased income or purchasing power which can then be spent on further energy inputs even with no lowering of energy's relative price. New demand for energy can also stem from the relative fall in energy's price when demand drops initially following the input-efficiency increase. In terms of production functions, if a unit of energy can produce more, energy's new relative power
T also includes 1) organizational efficiencies like economies of scale, Taylorite factory-floor rationality and transportation infrastructures; 2) institutional ones like property rules, honesty, security, and trade; and 3) further cultural ones (Swaney, 1991; Durham, 1992). No one claims that increasing these efficiencies lowers resource consumption; indeed, they are seen to contribute unequivocally to economic growth.
6

774

EC O LO GIC A L E CO N O M ICS 6 4 ( 2 00 8 ) 7 7 0 7 86

or attractiveness results in substitution effects (Brookes, 1990; Saunders, 1992). Binswanger sums up the effects of efficiency gains: Because the equipment becomes more energy efficient, the cost per unit of product or service that is produced with this equipment falls which, in turn, increases the demand for the product or the service (2001, 120; Howarth, 1997; Birol and Keppler, 2000).7 The demand-stimulating effects of the more efficient use of any kind of input was identified by many classical economists including Say, who attributed greater overall wealth to the more productive use of power (energy): But whence is derived thislarger supply of wealth, that nobody pays for? From the increased command acquired by human intelligence over the productive powers and agents presented gratuitously by nature. A power before known and available is directed with superior skill and effect, as in the case of every improvement in mechanism, whereby human or animal power is assisted or expanded. (1803, 101; 295; Malthus, 1820, 49, 5356; Rae, 1834, 29, 166, 171, 261262; Mill, 1848, 133134, 751) In terms of costs of production rather than income effects, Domar similarly noted that [A] rapid growth of [Kendrick's] Index [Total Factor Productivity] in any industry reduces the prices of its output, and thus stimulates sales (1962, 605; Hotelling, 1931, 137). Estimates of the size of efficiency rebound vary wildly from nearly zero (Lovins, 1988) to insignificant (Grubb, 1990; Von Weizscker et al., 1997; Howarth, 1997; Greening et al., 2000; Schipper and Grubb, 2000; 4CMR, 2006) to greater than 100%, when it is called backfire (Brookes, 1990, 2000; Greenhalgh, 1990; Giampietro and Mayumi, 2000; Rudin, 2000; Dahmus and Gutowski, 2005; Hanley et al., 2006; Herring, 2006). As rebound approaches 100%, both the effectiveness and cost-effectiveness of the strategy sink; if backfire pertains, the efficiency strategy is even environmentally counterproductive.8 Analogously, heated 19th-century debates concerning labour efficiency eventually led to a consensus that backfire indeed obtains: So-called productivity increases do not in the long run cause unemployment. (Say, 1820; Malthus, 1820, 281, 287; Mill, 1848, 756757; Jevons, 1865, 140; Sraffa, 1951, lviilx; Greenberg, 1990; Alcott, 2005, 1617) A further, similar rebound or feedback effect is identified by Kaufmann, in what is perhaps a fatal challenge to the entire concept of the material intensity of a good, service, or expenditure: When labour or capital are substituted for energy, these also have energy costs, which offsets some fraction of the direct energy savings and reduces the amount of energy saved by priceinduced microeconomic substitution. (1992, 49) Wages, for instance, are used to demand material and energy.

3.2.

Efficiency is not enough

Sanne bolsters his argument that consumption per capita among the affluent must be lowered by agreeing with Jevons: Higher efficiency due to technological improvement may create a rebound effect: saving energy or natural resources per unit of production results in lower costs which encourage increased consumption. In the end, a growing volume of activity will offset the initial gain, like futile attempts to catch ones own tail. (2002, 275) It follows that if the environmental efficiency strategy is thus only weakly effective, or even counter-effective, the sufficiency strategy recommends itself all the more (assuming it is to some degree effective). Yet even many who attest the efficiency strategy's effectiveness regard it as insufficient for lowering impact to a sustainable level. In Ekins' view, for instance, The energy performance of technology can be affected by regulation or, for example, minimum standards, but it is not clear that this will be sufficient to achieve the large cuts in carbon emissions that are necessary without complementing changes in personal behavior in both market and non-market choices (2004, 1897). Smil likewise, echoing Galbraith (1958b), advocates going beyond higher efficiency to include changing attitudes regarding the material consumption and the stewardship of the biosphere (2003, 332, 368). For Princen A productive efficiency is an undeniably, unassailably good thing, but we have too long focused on that agenda to the neglect of the consumption problem (1999, 360 361).9 Schor's (2005, 310312) disaffection with the efficiency strategy includes the observation that technological solutions are popular because they promise a free lunch and because they are apolitical [Section 5.2]; intelligent design and technological innovation shall bring us (in the curt formula of Factor Four) double the prosperity for half the resources. Her main problem with technological approaches, though, is that they fail to address increases in the scale of production and consumption, sometimes even arguing that such increases are not unsustainable, if enough natural-capital-saving technical change occurs;[but] increases in scale have outpaced technological improvements. Note that Jevons' backfire theory predicts this scale increase; technology can save natural capital only per unit of output, not overall.10 Schor goes on to adopt the Veblenian position that in addition to the impact of rising incomecompetitive consumption or luxury fever (Frank, 1999) increases consumption
9 Also Sachs, 1988; Lovins, 1988, 158; Schmidt-Bleeck, 1994, 189; Daly, 1996, 219222; Goodland and Daly, 1996, 1009; Gardner and Stern, 1996, 253; Bogun, 1997, 212; Von Weizscker et al., 1997, xvi, 244, 258, 292295; Carley and Spapens, 1998, 51, 108; Rpke, 1999, 416417; Sanne, 2000, 2002, 275; Siebenhner, 2000, 19; Princen et al., 2002; Robinson, 2004, 379; Jackson, 2005, 20. 10 The technical progress of neo-classical growth theory is in large part greater efficiency in the use of material/energy as well as labour inputs. (Solow, 1957; 1970, 3338) However, since this school of thought defines growth in monetary or utility terms, rather than biophysical ones, it does not necessarily support Jevons' position.

7 Also special issues of Energy Policy (28 (6/7) 2000) and Energy & Environment (11 (5) 2000). 8 See further Cipolla, 1962, 49, 99; Pimentel et al. 1973, 1994; Schurr, 1982, 5; Rosenberg, 1982, 75 and 1994, 166167; Saunders, 1992, 2000; Clapp, 1994, 161171; Giampietro and Mayumi, 1998, 2024; Wirl, 1997, 1932, 41, 112, 197; Berkout et al., 2000, 426; Roy, 2000, 433; Moezzi, 2000, 524, 528; Sieferle, 2001; Smil, 2003, 6881; Luks, 2005, 5052.

EC O L O G IC A L E C O N O M IC S 6 4 ( 2 0 08 ) 77 0 7 86

775

(2005, 310). However, if consumption indeed ends up higher than it would have been without energy efficiency increases, the conclusion is mistaken that technological change is a necessary, but not sufficient condition for achieving sustainability (310). A correct conclusion is that the less efficate the efficiency strategy proves to be and especially if technological efficiency is part of the problem due to rebounds greater than unity the more necessary are the further strategies of sufficiency, consumption efficiency, population limits, energy taxes, or quotas. Further writers warn of backfire. Rpke for instance writes: Obviously, the environmental benefits of a change in consumption practices in one area can easily be counterbalanced by increased consumption in other areas, if overall growth is not limited [Sections 4.2 and 4.3]. For instance, a successful policy to reduce private motoring would imply the saving not only of energy, but of money [the income effect], which could be converted into extended weekends by plane to interesting places entailing increased energy consumption... (1999, 401) Reijnders similarly attests that improvements in technology may be counterbalanced by increases in affluence and/or population, but then contradictorily asks whether improvement of technology is sufficient to lower impact to a sustainable level (1998, 17).

3.3.

The sufficiency rebound

The position that efficiency is not enough for sustainability thus makes sense only if the efficiency rebound is less than 100%, i.e., only if efficiency does not contribute to physical macroeconomic growth. This subsection claims, however, that the sufficiency strategy likewise suffers in point of efficacy: In constituting a drop in demand, it initially lowers prices, and this in turn raises others demand, so that in the

end some of what was saved through non-consumption is consumed after all merely by others. Analogous to the engineering savings theoretically achievable through technical change, the environmentally motivated drop in consumption is here called sufficiency savings and is likewise only theoretical; marginal consumers (Inhaber, 1997, xii; Wirl, 1997, 32) take up the slack left by the newly frugal people who have left the market. The analysis in this subsection holds for consumption of raw materials (metals, energy); whether it applies equally well to other consumption items such as food, water, or clothing is an open question. The description of the sufficiency rebound in terms of price and income changes is simpler than that of the efficiency rebound. The chain of economic events here under discussion starts with an autonomous reduction in demand for or consumption of natural resources. In economic terms it amounts to a change in consumers' tastes wherein they exchange, on average, some materially-derived utility for the emotional or ethical utility of reducing their own pressure on the environment. Instead of thinking in terms of small increments, imagine an overnight behavioural change: Moved by the desire to ease up on the environment OECD consumers decide to buy, say, 20% less fossil fuel than before. This sufficiency shift initially leaves 20% of their purchasing power unused; because these ex-consumers, ceteris paribus, work less, at this point in the dynamic demand is destroyed. The sufficiency rebound then amounts to a passive, rather than intentional, transfer of purchasing power to marginal consumers. The mechanism at work is that of price reductions of goods, services, and energy inputs themselves. Fig. 1 shows, in terms of classical economics' laws of supply and demand, the results of a leftward sufficiency shift in the OECD demand function from D0 OECD to D1 OECD. The graph shows Q0 WORLD (= Q0 OECD + Q0 OTHER) and P0 (World price) given by the intersection of S with D0 WORLD (itself the sum of D0 OECD and D0 OTHER). Holding both World supply function and price constant, then the sufficiency lurch, entailing as it does a

Fig. 1 Fossil fuel demand OECD, non-OECD and World.

776

EC O LO GIC A L E CO N O M ICS 6 4 ( 2 00 8 ) 7 7 0 7 86

leftward shift from D0 WORLD to D1 world, yields the theoretical quantities Q1 WORLD and Q1 OECD, both of which are less than the original Q0 quantities. That is, the sufficiency shift in the OECD demand function is such that by definition QOECD = a reduction or (theoretical) sufficiency savings of 20% of Q0 OECD: Prices fall and non-OECD (Other) demand rises; to what height depends on non-OECD price elasticities of demand; technology and S are held constant. The imagined overnight demand reduction by OECD consumers shifts the world demand function of which it is a part from D0 WORLD to D1 WORLD. The intersection of S and D1 WORLD yields the new lower price P1. For non-OECD countries (DOTHER), the new, lower price (P1) yields Q2 OTHER which is greater than Q0 OTHER. Part of the resource savings realized by the OECD consumers is thus taken back or wiped out by the classical economic behavior of others. At this price OECD countries consume Q2 OECD. (Note that there is no Q1 OTHER because there was no shift in Other's demand function. Note further that at (the lower) price P1, D1 OECD would yield some increase in consumption, namely Q2 OECD minus Q1 OECD; but we have assumed this away: regardless of price, OECD consumers consume 20% less than before.) Total consumption Q2 WORLD (given by the intersection of D1 WORLD and S) now results from the 20% reduction in consumption of the OECD countries plus the increase in consumption of other countries. The sufficiency rebound is Q2 OTHER minus Q0 OTHER. The theoretical quantity sufficiency savings (Q0 OECD minus Q1 OECD) is exactly the same as the theoretical quantity Q0 WORLD minus Q1 WORLD. The overall effect, or real savings (Q0 WORLD minus Q2 WORLD), is smaller: Worldwide real savings must be lower than the savings initially achieved by a successful sufficiency strategy. Wackernagel and Rees attest this same rebound in terms of nations as consumer units (and without mentioning price changes): Indeed the very integration of the global economy mitigates against any individual country adopting the ecological alternative: the marginal global benefits resulting from one nation's restraint would quickly be dissipated by non-cooperating countries, all of which have open access to the ecosphere (1997, 22). In conclusion, insofar as the sufficiency strategy expects consumption to remain at the level reached by subtracting the OECD frugality alone (sufficiency savings) it is unrealistic.

Fig. 2 Possible new equilibrium. But how could one measure sufficiency rebound? Assuming that the sufficiency behavior itself were measurable the previous section simply assumed a 20% reduction in consumption [Section 5.1] what would be the magnitudes of more demand and/or less supply of fossil fuels worldwide? Quantification would have to estimate the initial price fall and the slopes of the respective supply and demand functions, predicting the new equilibrium. Fig. 2 shows extreme cases of low and high sufficiency rebound, its size being some function of the ratio of the two elasticities (see also Larsen and Nesbakken, 1997). Keep in mind that the appropriate scope or scale of empirical studies must be the world economy, not any individual country or group of countries such as the OECD.11 First, how would producers react? Although estimates of the price elasticity of supply vary widely, much opinion holds that rents and profits in the fossil fuel sector are large enough to tolerate a considerable price fall (Katzner, 1987, 555; Wirl, 1991, 242; 1994, 79; Shim and Siegel, 1995, 322; Noreng, 2002, 910, 14; Salameh, 2003, 1090; Horn, 2004, 269, 271, 275; but see Kaufmann and Cleveland, 2001; Noreng, 2002, 89; Smil, 2003, 87) Second, is a historical worldwide demand curve feasible? Research is found for instance in Smil's analysis of total consumption of electricity and fossil fuels over long periods, showing rising quantities alongside (despite?) falling relative energy prices in terms of purchasing power (2003, 610, 8284, 149153; also Schurr and Netschert, 1960, 156; Cleveland et al., 1984, 896; Cleveland and Kaufmann, 2003, 486). Variability in elasticity estimates seems to depend on scale of study and economies studied. Also relevant is the cause of the price decline in our case a sufficiency shift as opposed to technological efficiency increases, quantity of remaining reserves, or political (e.g. OPEC) decisions.12

3.4.

Empirical measurement

Whether any net worldwide real savings results i.e. how close Q2 WORLD is to Q0 WORLD depends on many things, but the necessary and sufficient conditions for the rebound itself are only 1) any amount of latent demand by marginal consumers and 2) any amount of supplier profit (any upward-sloping supply function). That is, price elasticities must merely be nonzero. When the utility curve of anyone is such that a purchase happens at the incrementally lower price, and the profit situation of any producer is such that supply continues at this price, the level of consumption cannot remain at the level computed by subtracting the foregone consumption of newly frugal people, but must rebound.

11 Market globalisation and the global nature of depletion and emissions damage lessen the usefulness of country studies. (Saint-Paul, 1995; Brown et al., 1998, 114; Cleveland and Ruth, 1998, 4445; Dahlstrm and Ekins, 2006) In the efficiency-rebound literature this is often acknowledged (Grubb, 1990, 195, 235; Greenhalgh, 1990, 298; Hinchliffe, 1995, 94; Howarth, 1997, 4; Greene et al., 1999, 28; Roy, 2000, 433; Greening et al., 2000, 392; Saunders, 2000, 439; Binswanger, 2001, 124; Rhee and Chung, 2006). 12 Also Harris, 1984, 40; Krautkraemer, 1998; Cleveland and Kaufmann, 2003. Most literature unfortunately starts with price rises like those of the mid-1970s.

EC O L O G IC A L E C O N O M IC S 6 4 ( 2 0 08 ) 77 0 7 86

777

3.5.

Backfire?

Is a sufficiency rebound greater than unity possible? Some writers mention the possibility that, per unit of affluence at the margin, the consumption of the poor could be more environmentally damaging that of the rich. (Khazzoom, 1980, 26; Goodland and Daly, 1996, 1013; Schipper, 2000, 353; Binswanger, 2001, 126; Shi, 2003, 32, 3839). A bus ride in Colombia might burn more fuel per kilometer than one in Switzerland, or eschewing the North/South imagery a museum visit might use up fewer resources than a hungrier person's eating a meal. In terms of Environmental Kuznets Curves,13 the sufficiency shift might move the world economy to a position where consumption rises more steeply over against income. Deciding whether the strategy is efficate or counterproductive thus entails testing for the theoretical conditions for a sufficiency backfire, using worldwide data. However, Section 3 has merely attempted to enrich the discussion with the concept of the sufficiency rebound, whose existence is a certainty. While efficiency rebound is conceptually established and increasingly corrected for (4CMR, 2006; Allan et al., 2006), post-frugality rebound is as yet unacknowledged. Discussions concern motivations for frugality, psychological and social barriers to it, how to sell the idea, and how to garner the same number of consumer satisfaction units in spite of it but now we should examine interdependencies within the affluence (A) factor itself the necessary rise in the affluence of marginal consumers.

the developed countriesthat currently determines the general direction of the global political economy and that constitutes the source of potential future disasters for the entire human population. (1976, 98, 99) He quotes Paul Ehrlich: The most serious population growth occurs among the affluent whites of the USA, and their analogues in Western Europe, the Soviet Union, and Japan. These people are the prime looters and polluters of our planet. (139) North is here surrogate for rich, and since for ethical reasons the strategy aims only at the rich, the target becomes, as expressed by Sanne, Northern consumption as overconsumption and unsustainable or the Western consumption pattern (2002, 282, 274). Daly and Goodland similarly write that because rich countries consume more per capita, we must look at consumption patterns in the North (1996, 1015). Rpke, incidentally avoiding the mistake of arguing in per capita terms, writes that the growing consumption of the North constitutes an important part of global environmental problems (1999, 399, 401). The implicit syllogism is that the rich consume more than the poor; the rich are (predominantly) in the North; therefore Northern consumption must be lowered (also UNCED, 1993, Ch. 4; Hinterberger et al., 1996, 85; Homburg and Matthies, 1998, 121; Kasser, 2002, 92). However, openness between economies means that sufficiency-induced lower prices are known everywhere. Goods, services, fossil fuels, and people cross borders increasingly unhindered. Marginal consumers taking up the slack are wherever there is purchasing power. Higher demand in recent years from developing economies supports this view. Yet the relevant metric for environmental impact is only the total amount of depleted resources or ambient amounts of emissions: Nature does not care which countries pollute, or what per capita pollution is. Because of the universal nature of world trade, the concept of carrying capacity is difficult to apply to a nation or region. (Bartlett, 1994, 26) We should thus follow Princen in adding southern elites and the rich in developing countries to the rough concept of Northern (1999, 360), or Myers in writing neutrally of affluent communities (1997, 53; Spangenberg and Lorek, 2002, 127). For the economics of global consumption and pollution the terms Western, Northern, and even developed are largely gratuitous, as recognized by both Ayres (2000) and Opschoor (2000) in questioning the value of computing national or regional ecological footprints, and the simpler taxonomy of relatively rich and relatively poor is preferable. One strategy framed accordingly in worldwide terms is that of contraction and convergence, whose premise is that the atmosphere is a limited global commons and that Anything less than a global deal cannot solve climate change (Simms, 2005, 167, 173); while rich people have a moral ecological debt taking more than their fair share there will always be the problem of uncontrollable greenhouse gas emissions from free-riding countries. (173) Poor free-riders can also ruin the deal, and it is not sufficient for the rich to consume less; rather, everybody must be democratically mutually coerced. While emissions do not carry source labels, politics may require that rich nations reduce first. (Goodland and Daly,

4.

Weaknesses in argumentation

Section 3 showed that the strategy cannot be effective to the full extent of the original sufficiency savings. Yet since it remains possible that the strategy is to some degree effective, i.e., that rebound is lower than 100% of sufficiency savings, the next four sections explore weaknesses either in the arguments for the strategy, or in estimates of the attainability of the initial, voluntary change in behaviour towards frugality.

4.1.

North and South

Most expositions of the sufficiency strategy conflate the categories of rich and poor with those of North and South or developed vs. developing countries. As Leiss paradigmatically wrote, The one-third of the human population in the industrially developed nations currently uses 90% of the available resources; it is the exponential increase of their demands, not those of the human population as a whole, which is the real and immediate cause of the emerging global crisis. It is the unforgivable squandering of resources in

The vertical axis (dependent variable) of such curves must be in absolute rather than per capita units (Opschoor, 1995; De Bruyn and Opschoor, 1997; Luzzati and Orsini, in press).

13

778

EC O LO GIC A L E CO N O M ICS 6 4 ( 2 00 8 ) 7 7 0 7 86

1996, 1009) But this is not equivalent to the common claim that rich nations must morally take the lead towards sufficiency. (UNCED, 1992, Ch. 4) A country that involuntarily lives sufficiently cannot be expected to adopt the role of a follower, just as it is unproven that the poor emulate the rich in overconsumption. The paternalism and the donning of the hair shirt implicit in this concept of leadership do not support the case for sufficiency.

fulfilled for intragenerational ethical behavior. But a personal shift to frugality guarantees neither less impact, nor more present equality, nor more intergenerational equality. Moreover, even explicit transfers fall short of sustainable impact to the extent that either higher population results, or the consumption patterns of the poorer recipients are somehow environmentally more detrimental than those of the previous consumers. (Siebenhner, 2000, 19; Section 3.5). Brown and Cameron similarly make an important conceptual distinction between prosocial values and proenvironmental values: Individuals may be prosocial (altruistic and cooperative) but not proenvironmental (value sustainability of environmental resources). It is possible, however, that a well-developed pro-environmental position must include prosocial values involving: (1) altruistic motivations to sacrifice personal gain by limiting resource consumption in order to promote environmental integrity; and (2) cooperative orientations to use only one's fair share of resources and to act in ways to ensure that others are allowed their fair share. In effect, prosocial values may be necessary, but not sufficient conditions for guaranteeing proenvironmental values. (2000, 3839) One way of acting on proenvironmental values, that of frugal personal behavior, is in any case weakened by the sufficiency rebound. The other two goals above more equal distribution towards future humans and less impact on non-human nature thus require further conditions. The view that justice implies sustainability (Pearce, 1987, 13) is true only if justice is meant intergenerationally. Put otherwise, a perfectly just present distribution of resources is consistent with crassly unsustainable consumption of resources as well as crass disregard for future people. Intratemporal equality, at a too-large scale of the economy, can amount to unjust intertemporal material standards of living. And again, the sufficiency rebound weakens any connection between avoided consumption on anybody's part and sustainability. Pearce is right, though, that leaving all future generations a quantity and quality of resources necessary for life is more or less the same as respecting biophysical constraints in the present. Judged both by motivation and consequences, one type of ethically good transfer from rich to poor is the purchase of emissions certificates held by poorer countries in Kyoto schemes. But since the latter can and do buy fossil fuels with the proceeds,14 such transfers in the name of equity do not ipso facto reduce impact. Thus it is true that Wasteful consumption in rich countries must be reduced to allow for needed growth in poor countries, but it does not follow that more equitable and efficient patterns of energy use close the gap between rich and poor and reduce environmental damage compared with that which will result if current trends continue. (Ehrlich, 2000, 322) Intragenerational equity and the
14 Because the emissions of most poor countries are not capped, the Delhi version of the Kyoto agreement undoubtedly results in higher consumption in the remaining nations, a step for equality but not one for lowering impact.

4.2.

Sufficiency is morally good

Yet not only could voluntary Northern frugality under certain conditions result in a rich, overconsuming South. Even when rich is not equated with North, the common claim that the rich are responsible for negative impact is ambiguous, as when Spangenberg and Lorek write that there is a consensus that particular responsibility for the level, composition and impact of consumption rests with this class of affluent consumers (2002, 128): Responsible means both causally efficacious and morally culpable. (also Siebenhner, 2001, 23) In the first, causal or non-normative sense that the rich are consuming the lion s share, the claim is tautological. The concepts of marginal consumers and sufficiency rebound in Section 3 imply furthermore that the affluent are easily replaced by the slightly less affluent, who would then in their turn assume this responsibility ad infinitum. In the ethical rather than biophysical sense, on the other hand, the claim that the rich should consume less is straightforward and arguable as a moral assertion (also Goodland and Daly, 1996, 1009). Both for traditionally ethical reasons of human equity and on the newer ethical grounds of environmental concern, Smil too writes that shaping the future energy use in the affluent world is primarily a moral issue.... (2003, 370), while Greenhalgh sardonically observes that The fear of environmental damage... has introduced an ethical or moral dimension into the argument [over continued economic growth]. Excessive or wasteful consumption and associated pollution which it causes is sinful; frugality is a virtue (1990, 293). The exact bearing of the moral goodness of frugality on the fight to lower impact, however, is not clear. Let us distinguish three ethical goals: 1) intragenerational equality or justice, especially alleviation of poverty; 2) intergenerational justice; and 3) the preservation and health of non-human species and the biosphere in general. Let us further distinguish the ethical motivation for frugality from its consequences. Judged according to motivation, voluntary frugality is on all three counts good. But unless eschewed consumption is accompanied by an explicit transfer of purchasing power either to present poorer people or in general to future people does the envisioned good consequence of greater intra- or intergenerational equality actually happen. (Pearce, 1987) Without this explicit transfer, the beneficiary of the income effect could be an affluent neighbour who heats his swimming pool more often. As Robinson notes (albeit concerning efficiency rather than sufficiency), it is easy to imagine cases where the gains from such approaches are appropriated disproportionately by those who already are well-off (2004, 379) When combined with a gift to a poorer person conditions are at least

EC O L O G IC A L E C O N O M IC S 6 4 ( 2 0 08 ) 77 0 7 86

779

level of impact are two separate things. Perhaps for such reasons Princen writes, If the problem is one of inequity, no analytic advantage is gained by calling it consumption. Adding the environment and calling the problem consumption only muddles the longstanding debates of North and South, haves and have-nots, rich and poor, powerful and powerless, to include environmental inequities. (1999, 352) Or as Pearce says, the design of an economy such that it maximizes some measure of social (human) welfare but subject to biophysical constraints will assist in, but will not be sufficient for, attainment of the notion of extended justice. (1987, 10) In other words, a sustainable human economy could be presently unjust as well as indifferent to non-human nature. For Goodland and Daly poverty reduction will require considerable economic growth, as well as development, in developing countries. But global environmental constraints are real, and more growth for the South must be balanced by negative throughput growth [sic.] for the North if environmental sustainability is to be achieved. (1996, 1004). But since this balancing could leave impact unaffected, this conflates ethical goals with sustainability. Lower A and T among the rich is necessary but not sufficient for lower-impact-cumjustice, and even large-scale transfers to the poorer countries (1004) do not suffice because, again, sustainability and intragenerational equity (1005) are not the same. The sufficiency strategy does not suffice to solve conflicts between the humanist goal of present-day material equality and that of sustainable (eternally reproducible) impact.

friendships, opportunities for creativity and the quality of our family relationships. This means that with better awareness of what really gives us a sense of well-being, by ignoring the adverts, we could actually consume less and be happier. (Simms, 2005, 187) Simms backs his case up with evidence from World War II Britain, where both legal and voluntary frugality left people fitter (155164). While pointing out the personal, selfish advantages of riding one's bike, or the aesthetic beauty of natural landscape, or the disadvantages of breathing dirty street air are useful parts of the story, there are some difficulties with this argument. First, the jury is still out concerning this hypothesis that, above a certain level, greater affluence does not mean greater happiness: Much luxury consumption fulfills deep psychological desires, e.g. for prestige, thus contributing to happiness. Second, even if the thesis is somehow true, evolutionary forces may interfere with our doing what we rationally see as our own good; the everyday examples of overeating and unrequited love suffice for illustration. Evolutionary forces seeking status or display or conspicuous consumption may indeed be virtually ineradicable; and the bad consequence for the environmental sufficiency strategy is that since the purported benefits of such prestige consumption are relative to others' consumption, the sky is the limit (see Veblen, 1899; Ornstein and Ehrlich, 1989; Konrad, 1990; Low and Heinen, 1993; Morrison, 1999; Frank, 1999; Jackson, 2002; Alcott, 2004). Third, the argument maintains that the great majority of human beings has for centuries or millenia acted to its own detriment a strong claim based on no discernable theory that challenges evolutionary theory at its roots. On this view materialistic, overconsuming behaviour is not selfish after all, but rather anti-selfish and pathological also. Again, from the vantage of human ethology, this claim that we systematically act in certain ways even though costs outweigh benefits bears the burden of proof. Alternatively, one must claim for instance that those with economic and political power force us, in their own interest and perhaps subtly through advertising, etc., to overconsume (Galbraith, 1958a; Packard, 1959; 1960). Some authors recognise that they owe us an explanation of why, judged on these apparently simple, selfish criteria, we choose to live so stupidly (Schor, 1999a,b, 138; Frank, 1999, 7; Cross, 1993, 2000). Others offer selfish reasons for frugality apparently without this awareness (Mirrlees, 1991, 64; Ekins, 1991, 253, Princen, 1999, 357; Kasser, 2002). At the least, sufficiency strategists who enlist this argument for environmental ends must 1) offer a more careful rendering of the hoary concept of human welfare than hitherto, and 2) explain overconsumption.

4.3.

Two birds with one stone

Many arguments for living lightly, downshifting and shrinking one's environmental footprint appeal not to ethics or environmentalism but to one's own good. Riding a bicycle is not only environmentally friendly but healthy; working and spending less, eating less, and in general possessing less leaves us with more free time, less noise, less stress, less body weight and less local pollution. In the early 1960s I eavesdropped on the discussions of business executives dropping out of the rat-race; in the late 1960s everybody acquired this wisdom, captured by Etzioni's diagnostic term for the costs of a high-consumption lifestyle affluenza (1998, 626). Insights from this line of thought, appealing to one's selfish interests, are mobilized in socially marketing the sufficiency strategy; two birds can be brought down with one stone. The knowledge that material wealth doesnt buy happiness is as old as the hills (De Botton, 2000, 5672, 9799; Easterlin, 1973; Hirsch, 1976; Argyle, 1987; Diener et al., 1993; Kasser, 2002; but see Veenhoven, 1991) From Thoreau on, environmentally concerned writers have regarded this argument as an ally in pursuing environmental goals recently Boulding (194950, 1966), Linder (1970), Scitovsky (1976), Schor (1992), Durning (1992), Goodland and Daly (1996), Orr (1999), Princen et al. (2002), Sanne (2002) and Jackson (2005). In bolstering an argument for rationing, one author argues: Research shows that people's happiness rises along with conventional wealth only up to the point that our needs for basics like adequate warmth, food, clothing, and shelter are met. After that our well-being depends on other things like

4.4.

The political vs. the personal

The sufficiency strategy is most often conceived as a sum of individual behavioural changes. The view of Meadows et al. is representative: People who care about other people thereby contribute to staying within the limits; they advocate fifty simple things you can do to save the planet such as to buy an energy-efficient car [and] recycle your bottles and cans

780

EC O LO GIC A L E CO N O M ICS 6 4 ( 2 00 8 ) 7 7 0 7 86

perhaps at the cost of some speed, time and effort (1992, 218 19; Durning, 1992; Orr, 1999; Green Media, 2007; Union of Concerned Scientists, 2007). To the extent that the personal is local, the slogan Think globally, act locally captures this philosophy. British politician Gordon Brown similarly asserts the necessity that decisions made by national governments must be matched by individual actions. We all have a responsibility to do what we can to tackle environmental degradation. So I believe what we do as a community nationally and internationally must be matched by a new sense of personal responsibility. (2006, 2) This regards the personal and the political as equally valuable, but I hope to have shown that personal behavioural change is at most a necessary condition for sustainability and that it is thus questionable whether it adds significantly much to decisions made by national governments. The position of this paper, that personal responsibility resulting in changed consumption behaviour is not an alternative to collective measures, is seemingly shared by Sanne (2002). He clearly distinguishes between the consumer and the citizen and advocates collective, non-personal measures like halting (or reducing) production volumes as radical greens propose... (285), just as we as citizens already force ourselves to pay taxes, go to school, and obey traffic lights and public smoking bans (275, 281 [but see 273]; Sagoff, 1988). Indeed, the income tax is a good example of such mutually agreed-upon mutual coercion: No one argues that we should want to pay them, but we politically agree to i.e., provided everybody else must. Worldwide reduction of affluence, to be achieved by world citizens, thus requires a philosophy of Think globally, act globally. Only prescribed caps leaving no room for freeriders or marginal consumers to take up slack are not subject to an affluence rebound (also Ornstein and Ehrlich, 1989; De Young, 1993; Stern et al., 1995; Milbraith, 1995; Gardner and Stern, 1996; Siebenhner, 2000). In spite of these reservations, however, there is truth in the sufficiency strategy's insight that one can say of any person who newly lives lightly, One down, 6,499,999,999 to go.

criterion that only the rich shall cut consumption. But definitions of rich and sufficient are needed in order to quantify both the number of people targeted by the strategy as well as how much per person counts as over-consumption. Indeed, without some criterion based on the traditional distinction between needs as opposed to mere wants, no consumption is less necessary or justified than any other, and the sufficiency appeal simply targets those who may feel altruistic. That is, the whole concept of sufficiency would lose meaning. To better define and measure this building block of the strategy design, a rich literature is available: In addition to the classical economists and the 19th-century socialist tradition of Owen and Ruskin, as well as Maslow (1943), Baudrillard (1970), and Kasser (2002), writers who have pursued this in the economics tradition are Hobson (1929), Max-Neef (1995), or Jackson and Marks (1999). For overviews see McAdams (1992) and Brekke et al. (2003, 30, 38). Common ostensive definitions of dispensable or at least negotiable consumption include that of meat, cosmetics, air travel, large houses, and SUVs, and it is not difficult to calculate amounts of joule inputs, or emissions, per unit of these physical outputs. Alternatively, computations could be monetary, in terms of purchasing-power-parity; perhaps corrected by a material-intensity co-efficient. As is required of any global environmental strategy, this calculated amount of maximum possible sufficiency savings would then have to be measured against a level of impact deemed to be the maximum consistent with sustainability e.g., perhaps 450 ppm for CO2 (Wackernagel and Rees, 1997; Hinterberger et al., 1996, 8488). It is beyond the limits of both my knowledge and this paper to cite any rigorous research quantifying sufficiency savings (before price changes and rebound). But at the least it seems mistaken to talk merely of curbing the demand of humanity (Wackernagel and Silverstein, 2000, 394). Quantifications of sustainable consumption, yielding some maximum per capita affluence at a given population, could however challenge our humanistic belief that large numbers of people can live not only healthily but comfortably. Only such an honest comparison of quantified sufficient consumption with quantified sustainable consumption can help us to judge whether hopes for this winwin situation between ecology and economy are justified. Gordon Brown for instance claims: We can and should demonstrate that economic growth, social justice and environmental care can and must advance together. For years no international concensus has been possible that recognises how our global duty of stewardship to the environment can be discharged while delivering economic and social progress. (2006) However, political acceptability aside, all environmental strategies must face the empirical possibility and emotional dilemma that some combination of population and affluence would have to be lowered to intragenerationally unacceptable levels if justice toward future humans and other species is to be achieved.

5.

Discussion

Three further questions to be briefly discussed are: 1) What amount of depletion-and emission-reduction is possible and/ or expected by those who urge greater frugality? 2) What can be said more generally about the advisability of strategies aiming indirectly at impact by altering population, affluence, and technological factors as opposed to strategies, like the Kyoto Protocol, that aim directly at impact? 3) Finally, how are consumption taxes to be classified?

5.1.

Quantification

Sections 3.4 and 3.5 raised questions on measuring rebound; different ones arise concerning measurement of the theoretical sufficiency savings itself, of which rebound is a percentage. As established earlier, these are limited by the ethical

5.2.

Right-side vs. left-side strategies

The I = PAT identity, implying as it does that changes in affluence or technology directly change impact, holds only aggregately

EC O L O G IC A L E C O N O M IC S 6 4 ( 2 0 08 ) 77 0 7 86

781

as a static description of the environmental state of the world. However, any change in population, affluence, or technology changes the other two factors: Agricultural technology allows a larger population, higher affluence can lower (or raise) the birth rate, high consumption (P A) makes us use more efficient technologies, etc. Bartlett for instance writes, Reductions in the rates of consumption of resources and reductions in the rates of production or pollution can shift the carrying capacity in the direction of sustaining a larger population. When resources are used more efficiently, the consequence often is that the saved resources are not put aside for the use of future generations, but instead are used immediately to encourage and support larger populations. (1994, 21, 23; Jevons, 1865, 9, 196, 200, 457, Ch. X; Cipolla, 1962, 4953, 9495, 105; Giampietro, 1994; Daly, 1996, 220; Smil, 2003, 55) Due to these interdependencies we must therefore abandon I = PAT and write I = f(P,A,T). Moreover, Section 3.3 showed shifts of demand among consumer groups within the affluence term A. That is, the sufficiency rebound is described by A1 = f(A2): A value-induced reduction in the affluence of person 1 enables the affluence of person 2 to rise, and the sufficiency savings does not necessarily ever get over to the left side of the equation to lower impact. Direct or left-side strategies do exist, exemplified by the UNFCCC attempt to set global greenhouse-gas emissions caps within which country caps are politically allocated, leaving each political unit to decide on the most desirable and/or economically efficient mixture of population, affluence, and technological measures. Once the exo-market country caps have drawn the Plimsoll line of each economy, then adjustments in the right-side factors follow with little further detailed regulation, perhaps through tradable rations. (Fawcett, 2004, 10771078; Ophuls, 1977; Pearce, 1987, 17; Daly, 1991, 42; Rpke, 1999, 401) On the other hand, in the absence of overall caps on the system right-side strategies must depend on and integrate flanking or complementary strategies regarding the other rightside factors. Perhaps it is possible to compute a super-strategy of simultaneous and co-ordinated changes between and within all three factors, effectively lowering I. But as with all environmental strategies, the costs of design, administration, transaction and implementation must be scrutinized in order to measure costeffectiveness.15 The intuition here is that direct measures by definition effective are likely to show the better cost-effectiveness ratio than indirect ones, in line with Daly's suggestion that throughput [be] controlled at its input (depletion) rather than at the pollution end because physical control is easier at the point of lower entropy (1974, 20).16
The project of balancing life-cycle efficiency, renewable energy, green taxes, sufficiency, and population control has been criticized as tinkering and social engineering (Sachs, 1988; Rudin, 2000). But it does provide us with lessons of how to maximize welfare once limits are politically set. 16 Analogously, within smaller political units, it is infrastructure limitation which most cost-effectively lowers impact: Road traffic can be controlled by laws limiting parking spaces and air traffic by airport runway capacity.
15

5.3.

Taxes

Taxes, for instance on fossil fuels, in effect force us to increase technological and consumption efficiency as well as lower our personal sufficiency standards. In common with other rightside measures, however, these resource or depletion taxes only contingently lower impact. Again, when we react by making production more efficient or consumption more sufficient, prices (including the tax) fall and some of the effect is taken back (Pearce, 1987, 14). Eco-taxes would accordingly have to be periodically raised. Moreover, when the government refunds the revenue or spends it itself, a tax rebound results because demand is thereby generated for, among other things, the taxed fossil fuels. Hannon, therefore, while discussing the possible energy savings of large consumption shifts, writes that the amount of net energy savings might be small because of the respending effect. In any event, there is a limit to the savings that can be realized by such lifestyle changes which preserve the national income (1975, 100). The concept of the sufficiency rebound shows that such limits to savings also exist when the changes do not preserve the national income. Wackernagel and Rees accordingly maintain that the environment can afford cost-saving energy efficiencyonly if efficiency gains are taxed away or otherwise removed from further economic circulation (1997, 20; Greene, 1992, 118; Binswanger, 2001, 131). The purchasing power newly in the hands of government, or restored to citizens through refunds or lowering other taxes, would somehow have to be destroyed or perhaps invested in renewable resources.17 For these reasons Hannon prefers left-side measures: Another method that would conserve energy, and that is more fundamental than taxation, would be energy rationing through the use of coupons (1975, 101). This subsection merely suggests that such tax rebound problems be formally integrated not only into the double-dividend debate but into environmental policy generally to date seldom the case (e.g. Goodstein, 2003; Parry and Williams, 2004; Sterner and Isaksson, 2006).

6.

Conclusions

The environmental sufficiency strategy of greater consumer frugality has become popular in ecological economics, its attractiveness increasing along with awareness that not much can be done to stem population growth and that energyefficiency measures are either not enough or, due to backfire, part of the problem. Concerning the strategy's feasibility, effectiveness, and common rationale, several conclusions can be drawn. The consequences of the strategy's frugality demand shift price reduction and the ensuing consumption rebound are not yet part of mainstream discussion. Contrary to what is implied by the strategy's advocates, the frugality shift cannot achieve a one-to-one reduction in

17 One reviewer made the neglected point that higher fossil fuel prices increase the pressure on biomass, e.g. forests.

782

EC O LO GIC A L E CO N O M ICS 6 4 ( 2 00 8 ) 7 7 0 7 86

world aggregate consumption or impact: Poorer marginal consumers increase their consumption. The size of the sufficiency rebound is an open question. The concepts of North and South are not relevant to the consumption discussion. Even if the voluntary material consumption cuts by the rich would effect some lowering of total world consumption, changing human behaviour through argument and exhortation is exceedingly difficult. While our moral concern for present others is stronger than that for future others, this intragenerational equity is in no way incompatible with non-sustainable impact. Since savings effected by any one country or individual can be (more than) compensated by other countries and individuals, the relevant scale of any strategy is the world. No single strategy to change any given right-side factor in I = f(P,A,T) guarantees any effect on impact whatsoever. Right-side strategies in combination are conceptually complicated and perhaps more costly than explicitly political left-side strategies directly lowering impact. Research emphasis should be shifted towards measures to directly lower impact both in terms of depletion and emissions.

at the border between our needs and our (mere) wants, and to our inborn desire for justice. Neither addresses the taboo of population size. Both strategies distract us from the insight that nature limits us.

Acknowledgments
I thank Barbara Brndli, Len Brookes, Bas Girod, Tim Jackson, John Lintott, Cecilia Roa, Steve Stretton and the anonymous reviewers.

REFERENCES
Alcott, Blake, 2004. John Rae and Thorstein Veblen. Journal of Economic Issues 38 (3), 765786. Alcott, Blake, 2005. Jevons' paradox. Ecological Economics 54 (1), 921. Allan, Grant, Nick, Hanley, Peter, G., McGregor, J., Kim, Swayles, Karen, Turner, 2006. The macroeconomic rebound effect and the UK economy. Final Report to Defra. www.defra.gov.uk/ environment/energy/research. Argyle, Michael, 1987. The Psychology of Happiness. Routledge, London. Ayres, Robert U., 2000. Commentary on the utility of the ecological footprint concept. Ecological Economics 32, 347349. Bartlett, Albert A., 1994. Reflections on sustainability, population growth, and the environment. Population and Environment 16 (1), 535. Baudrillard, Jean, 1970 (1988). La Socit de Consommation (The Consumption Society: Myths and Structures). Gallimard, Paris (Sage, London). Berkout, Peter H.G., Muskens, Jos.C., Velthuijsen, Jan W., 2000. Defining the rebound effect. Energy Policy 28 (6/7), 425432. Binswanger, Mathias, 2001. Technological progress and sustainable development: what about the rebound effect? Ecological Economics 36 (1), 119132. Birol, Fatih, Keppler, Jan Horst, 2000. Prices, technological development and the rebound effect. Energy Policy 28 (6/7), 457469. Bogun, Roland, 1977. Lebensstilforschung und Umweltschutz. In: Karl-Werner, Brand (Ed.), Nachhaltige Entwicklung. Vs Verlag fr Sozialwissenschaften. Wiesbaden. Boulding, Kenneth, 194950. Income or welfare. The Review of Economic Studies, vol. XVII, pp. 7786. Boulding, Kenneth, 1966/1973. The economics of the coming spaceship earth. In: Daly, Herman E. (Ed.), Toward a Steady-State Economy. W.H. Freeman, San Francisco. Boulding, Kenneth, 1992. Towards a New Economics. Elgar, Aldershot, U.K. Brekke, Kjell Arne, Howarth, Richard B., Nyborg, Karine, 2003. Status-seeking and material affluence: evaluating the Hirsch hypothesis. Ecological Economics 45, 2939. Brookes, Leonard, 1978. Energy policy, the energy price fallacy and the role of nuclear energy in the UK. Energy Policy 6 (1), 94106. Brookes, Leonard, 1990. The greenhouse effect: the fallacies in the energy efficiency solution. Energy Policy 18 (2), 199201. Brookes, Leonard, 2000. Energy efficiency fallacies revisited. Energy Policy 28 (6/7), 355366. Brown, Gordon, 2006. The Independent Nr 6,087. London. 20 April. Brown, Lester et al., 1998. State of the World. Worldwatch/ Earthscan, London. Brown, Paul M., Cameron, Linda D., 2000. What can be done to reduce overconsumption? Ecological Economics 32, 2741. Carley, Michael, Spapens, Philippe, 1998. Sharing the World: Sustainable Living and Global Equity in the 21st Century. Earthscan, London.

Lower consumption may have advantages on the individual, community, or regional level. There is for instance some truth in the view of Diogenes that happiness and quantity of consumption do not necessarily rise proportionally. Living lightly can offer not only less stress and more free time but also the personal boon of a better sense of integrity, fulfilling the Kantian criterion that ones acts should be possible universally (worldwide). Locally it could mean cleaner air, less acid rain, less noise, less garbage, and more free space. And in the form of explicit, guaranteed shifts of purchasing power to poorer people it would enable others to eat better or to buy goods such as petrol and cars. However, given global markets and marginal consumers, one persons doing without enables another to do with: In the near run the former consumption of a newly sufficient person can get fully replaced. And given the extent of poverty and the temptations of luxury and prestige consumption, this near run is likely to be longer than the time horizon required for a relevant strategy to stem climate change and the loss of vital species and natural resources. Efficiency and sufficiency strategies both offer relatively painless solutions to non-sustainability.18 The former is praised by negawatt advocates not only as a free lunch, but one you are paid to eat. The latter appears to many of its addressees tolerable switching off a few lights, riding a bike, or eating less meat, and here, too, a lunch you are paid to eat comes in the form of various health and happiness benefits. Supply-side or other impact-side strategies, on the other hand, are hard. They confront us with the neglected question of the carrying capacity of the planet. But strictly following sustainability logic by capping extraction and/or emissions cost what it may collides with our hopes and humanism. Efficiency deals with the how, the material and social technology, of our wealth-making; sufficiency speaks to us
18 The business community welcomes efficiency (but not sufficiency) research.

EC O L O G IC A L E C O N O M IC S 6 4 ( 2 0 08 ) 77 0 7 86

783

Cipolla, Carlo M., 1962/1966. The Economic History of World Population. Penguin, Harmondsworth, U.K. Clapp, Brian William, 1994. An Environmental History of Britain Since the Industrial Revolution. Longman, London. Cleveland, Cutler J., Costanza, Robert, Hall, Charles A.S., Kaufmann, Robert, 1984. Energy and the U.S. economy: a biophysical perspective. Science 225, 890897. Cleveland, Cutler, Kaufmann, Robert, 2003. Oil supply and oil politics: dj vu all over again. Energy Policy 31 (6), 485489. Cleveland, Cutler, Ruth, Matthias, 1998. Indicators of dematerialization and the materials intensity of use. Journal of Industrial Ecology 2 (3), 1550. Cook, Stuart W., Berrenberg, Joy L., 1981. Approaches to encouraging conservation behavior: a review and conceptual framework. Journal of Social Issues 37 (2), 73107. Cross, Gary, 1993. The Making of Consumer Culture. Routledge, London. Cross, Gary, 2000. An All-Consuming Century. Columbia U. Press, New York. Dahlstrm, Kristina, Ekins, Paul, 2006. Combining economic and environmental dimensions: value chain analysis of UK iron and steel flows, vol. 58 (3), pp. 507519. Dahmus, Jeffrey B., Gutowski, Timothy G., 2005. Efficiency and production: historical trends for seven industrial sectors. Working Paper U.S. Society for Ecological Economics Conference, July 2005, Tacoma, Washington. jdahmus@mit. edu and [email protected]. Daily, Gretchen, Ehrlich, Paul, 1996. Socioeconomic equity, sustainability, and earth's carrying capacity. Ecological Applications 6 (4), 9911001. Daly, Herman E., 1973. The steady-state economy: toward a political economy of biophysical equilibrium and moral growth. In: Daly, Herman E. (Ed.), Toward a Steady-State Economy. W.H. Freeman, San Francisco. Daly, Herman E., 1974. The economics of the steady state. American Economic Review 64 (2), 1521. Daly, Herman E., 1991. Elements of environmental macroeconomics. In: Costanza, Robert (Ed.), Ecological Economics: The Science and Management of Sustainability. Columbia U. Press, New York. Daly, Herman E., 1996. Beyond Growth. Beacon, Boston. De Botton, Alain, 2000. The Consolations of Philosophy. Penguin, Harmondsworth, U.K. De Bruyn, Sander, Opschoor, John B., 1997. Developments in the 1throughputincome relationship: theoretical and empirical observations. Ecological Economics 20 (3), 255268. De Young, R., 1993. Changing behavior and making it stick: the conceptualization and management of conservation behavior. Environmental Behavior 25, 851864. Diener, Ed., Sandvik, Ed., Seidlitz, Larry, Diener, Marissa, 1993. The relationship between income and subjective well-being: relative or absolute? Social Indicators Research 28, 195223. Domar, Evsey, 1962. On total productivity and all that. Journal of Political Economy 70, 597608 (Dec.). Douglas, Mary, Isherwood, Baron, 1979/96. The World of Goods: Toward an Anthropology of Consumption. Routledge, London. Duchin, Faye (Ed.), 1998. Structural Economics: Measuring Change in Technology, Lifestyles, and the Environment. Island, Washington, D.C. Durham, D.F., 1992. Cultural carrying capacity: I = PACT. Focus 2 (3), 58. Durning, Alan Thein, 1992. How Much Is Enough? Earthscan, London. Easterlin, Richard A., 1973. Does money buy happiness? The Public Interest, vol. 30, pp. 110. Winter. Ehrlich, Paul, 2000. Human Natures: Genes, Cultures, and the Human Prospect. Island, Washington. Ekins, Paul, 1991. The sustainable consumer society: a contradiction in terms? International Environmental Affairs 3, 243257.

Ekins, Paul, 2004. Step changes for decarbonising the energy system: research needs for renewables, energy efficiency and nuclear power. Energy Policy 32 (17), 18911904. Etzioni, Amitai, 1998. Voluntary simplicity: characterization, select psychological implications, and societal consequences. Journal of Economic Psychology 19, 619643. Fawcett, Tina, 2004. Carbon rationing and personal energy use. Energy and the Environment 15 (6), 10671083. Fine, Ben, Leopold, Ellen, 1993. The World of Consumption. Routledge, London. Frank, Robert H., 1985. Choosing the Right Pond: Human Behavior and the Quest for Status. Oxford U. Press, New York. Frank, Robert H., 1999. Luxury Fever: Why Money Fails to Satisfy in and Era of Excess. Free Press, New York. Galbraith, John Kenneth, 1958a. The Affluent Society. Houghton Mifflin, New York. Galbraith, John Kenneth, 1958b. How much should a country consume? In: Henry, Jarrett (Ed.), Perspectives on Conservation. Resources for the Future/Johns Hopkins, Baltimore, USA. Gardner, Gerald T., Stern, Paul C., 1996. Environmental Problems and Human Behavior. Allyn and Bacon, Boston. Giampietro, Mario, 1994. Sustainability and technological development in agriculture. Bio-Sciences 44 (19), 677689. Giampietro, Mario, Mayumi, Kozo, 1998. Another view of development, ecological degradation, and NorthSouth trade. Review of Social Economy 56 (1), 2036. Giampietro, Mario, Mayumi, Kozo, 2000. Multiple-scale integrated assessments of social metabolism: integrating biophysical and economic representations across scales. Population and Environment 22 (2), 155210. Goodland, Robert, Daly, Herman E., Serafy, Salah El (Eds.), 1992. Population, Technology, and Lifestyle: The Transition to Sustainability. Island, Washington, D.C. Goodland, Robert, Daly, Herman E., 1992. Ten reasons why Northern income growth is not the solution to Southern poverty. In: Goodland, Robert, Daly, Herman E., Serafy, Salah El (Eds.), Population, Technology, and Lifestyle: The Transition to Sustainability. Island, Washington, D.C. Goodland, Robert, Daly, Herman E., 1996. Environmental sustainability: universal and non-negotiable. Ecological Applications 6 (4), 10021017. Goodstein, Eban, 2003. The death of the Pigovian tax? Policy implications from the double-dividend debate. Land Economics 79 (3), 402414. Green Media, 2007. www.greenconsumerguide.com. Greenberg, Dolores, 1990. Energy, power, and perceptions of social change. American Historical Review 95 (3), 693714. Greene, David L., Kahn, James, Gibson, Robert C., 1999. Fuel economy rebound effect for U.S. household vehicles. Energy Journal 20 (3), 132. Greenhalgh, Geoffrey, 1990. Energy conservation policies. Energy Policy 18 (4), 293299. Greening, Lorna A., Greene, David L., Difiglio, Carmen, 2000. Energy efficiency and consumption the rebound effect a survey. Energy Policy 28 (6/7), 389401. Grubb, Michael, 1990. Energy Policies and the Greenhouse Effect, vol. 1. Dartmouth Publishing Co., Aldershot U.K. Hanley, Nick P.G., McGregor, J.K. Swales, Turner, K.R., 2006. The impact of a stimulus to energy efficiency on the economy and the environment: a regional computable general equilibrium analysis. Renewable Energy 31, 161171. Hannon, Bruce, 1975. Energy conservation and the consumer. Science 189. Harris, Deverle P., 1984. Mineral Resources Appraisal: Mineral Endowment, Resources, and Potential Supply: Concepts, Methods, and Cases. Clarendon Press, Oxford. Herring, Horace., 2006. Energy efficiency a critical view. Energy 31, 1020.

784

EC O LO GIC A L E CO N O M ICS 6 4 ( 2 00 8 ) 7 7 0 7 86

Hinchliffe, S., 1995. Missing culture: energy efficiency and lost causes. Energy Policy 23 (1), 9395. Hinterberger, Friedrich, Luks, Fred, Stewen, Marcus, 1996. kologische Wirtschaftspolitik: Zwischen kodiktatur und Umweltkatastrophe. Birkhuser Verlag, Berlin, Basel, Boston. Hirsch, Fred, 1976. Social Limits to Growth. Harvard U. Press, Cambridge, Mass. Hobson, John Atkinson., 1929. Wealth and Life: A Study in Values. Macmillan, London. Homburg, Andreas, Matthies, Ellen, 1998. Umweltpsychologie: Umweltkrise, Gesellschaft und Individuum. Juventa, Weinheim. Horn, Manfred, 2004. OPEC's optimal crude oil price. Energy Policy 32 (2), 269280. Hotelling, Harold, 1931. The economics of exhaustible resources. Journal of Political Economy 39 (2), 137175. Howarth, Richard B., 1997. Energy efficiency and economic growth. Contemporary Economic Policy XV (4), 19. Inhaber, Herbert, 1997. Why Conservation Fails. Quorum, Westport, Connecticut, USA. Jackson, Tim, 2002. Evolutionary psychology in ecological economics: consilience, consumption, and contentment. Ecological Economics 41, 289303. Jackson, Tim, 2005. Live better by consuming less? Is there a double dividend in sustainable consumption? Journal of Industrial Ecology 9 (12), 1936. Jackson, Tim, Marks, N., 1999. Consumption, sustainable welfare and human needs with reference to UK expenditure patterns 195494. Ecological Economics 28, 42142. Jevons, William Stanley, 1865/1965. The Coal Question: An Inquiry Concerning the Progress of the Nation, and the Probable Exhaustion of our Coal-mines. 3rd edition 1905, Ed. A.W. Flux. Augustus M. Kelley, New York. Johnson, Warren, 1985. The Future Is Not What It Used to Be. Dodd, Mead, New York. Kasser, Tim, 2002. The High Price of Materialism. Bradford/MIT, Cambridge, Mass. Katzner, Donald W., 1987. Supply functions. In: Eatwell, John, Milgate, Murray, Newman, Peter (Eds.), The New Palgrave: A Dictionary of Economics. Macmillan, London. Kaufmann, Robert, 1992. A biophysical analysis of the energy/real GDP ratio: implications for substitution and technical change. Ecological Economics 6, 3556. Kaufmann, Robert, Cleveland, Cutler, 2001. Oil production in the lower 48 states: economic, geological, and institutional determinants. Energy Journal 22, 2749. Khazzoom, J. Daniel, 1980. Economic implications of mandated efficiency in standards for household appliances. Energy Journal 1 (4), 2140. Konrad, Kai, 1990. Statusprferenzen: Soziobiologische Ursachen, Statuswettrsten und seine Besteuerung. Kyklos 43, 249. Krautkraemer, Jeffrey A., 1998. Nonrenewable resource scarcity. Journal of Economic Literature 36 (4), 0652107. Larsen, Bodil Merethe, Nesbakken, Runa, 1997. Norwegian emissions of CO2 19871994: a study of some effects of the CO2 tax. Environmental & Resource Economics 9, 275290. Leiss, William, 1976. The Limits to Satisfaction: An Essay on the Problems of Needs and Commodities. U. of Toronto Press, Toronto. Linder, Stefan B., 1970. The Harried Consumer. Columbia U. Press, New York. Lintott, John, 1998. Beyond the economics of more: the place of consumption in ecological economics. Ecological Economics 25, 239248. Lovins, Amory B., 1988. Energy saving from more efficient appliances: another view. Energy Journal 9 (2), 155162. Low, Bobbi S., Heinen, Joel T., 1993. Population, resources, and environment: implications of human behavioral ecology for conservation. Population and Environment 15 (1), 742.

Luks, Fred, 2000. Postmoderne Umweltpolitik? Sustainable Development, Steady-State und die Entmachtung der konomik. Metropolis Verlag, Marburg. Luks, Fred, 2005. Innovation und Nachhaltigkeit. Jahrbuch kologische konomie Band 4. Metropolis Verlag, Marburg. Luzzati, Tomasso, and Marco Orsini, forthcoming. McAdams, Richard H., 1992. Relative preferences. The Yale Law Journal 102 (1), 1104. McCracken, Grant, 1988. Culture and Consumption. U. of Indiana Press, Bloomington. Mackenzie, J.S., 1892. The relation of ethics to economics. Report to the British Association for the Advancement of Science, Paper read on Saturday, August 6, pp. 837838. Malthus, Robert Thomas, [1820]/1836. Principles of Political Economy, 2nd Ed. Eds. Wrigley and Souden 1986, Pickering, London. Maslow, Abraham, 1943. A theory of human motivation. Psychological Review 50, 370396. Mason, Roger S., 1981. Conspicuous Consumption: A Study of Exceptional Consumer Behavior. St. Martin's, New York. Max-Neef, Manfred, 1995. Economic growth and quality of life a threshold hypothesis. Ecological Economics 15, 115118. Meadows, Donella H., Meadows, Dennis L., Randers, Jrgen, Behrens III, William W., 1972. The Limits to Growth. Earth Island, London. Meadows, Donella H., Meadows, Dennis L., Randers, Jrgen, 1992. Beyond the Limits. Earthscan, London. Milbraith, L.W., 1995. Psychological, cultural, and informational barriers to sustainability. Journal of Social Issues 51, 101120. Mill, John Stuart, 1848/1965. Principles of Political Economy. Ed. J.M. Robson, U. of Toronto Press and Routledge, Kegan Paul, London. Mirrlees, James A., 1991. The economic uses of Utilitarianism. In: Sen, Amartya, Williams, B. (Eds.), Utilitarianism and Beyond. Cambridge U. Press, Cambridge. Moezzi, Mithra, 2000. Decoupling energy efficiency from energy conservation. Energy and the Environment 11 (5), 521537. Morrison, Reg, 1999. The Spirit in the Gene. Cornell U. Press, Ithica, N.Y. Myers, Norman, 1997. Consumption: challenge to sustainable development? Science 276, 5357. Noreng, ystein, 2002. Crude Power: Politics and the Oil Market. I.B. Tauris, London. Nrgard, Jrgen S., 2006. Consumer efficiency in conflict with economic growth. Ecological Economics 57 (1), 1529. Ophuls, William, 1977. Ecology and the Politics of Scarcity: Prologue to a Political Theory of the Steady State. W.H. Freeman, San Francisco. Opschoor, Hans, 1995. Ecospace and the fall and rise of throughput intensity. Ecological Economics 15 (2), 137140. Opschoor, Hans, 2000. The ecological footprint: measuring rod or metaphor? Ecological Economics 32, 363365. Ornstein, Robert, Ehrlich, Paul, 1989. New World New Mind. Doubleday, New York. Orr, David W., 1999. The ecology of giving and consuming. In: Rosenblatt, Roger (Ed.), Consuming Desires: Consumption, Culture, and the Pursuit of Happiness. Island, Washington. Packard, Vance, 1959/60. The Status Seekers. Longmans, London. Packard, Vance, 1960. The Waste Makers. David McKay, New York. Parry, Ian, Williams, Roberton, 2004. The death of the Pigovian tax: Comment. Land Economics 80 (4), 575581. Pearce, David, 1987. Foundations of an ecological economics. Ecological Modelling 38, 918. Prettenthaler, Franz E., Steininger, Karl W., 1999. From ownership to service use lifestyle: the potential of car sharing. Ecological Economics 28, 443453. Princen, Thomas, 1999. Consumption and environment: some conceptual issues. Ecological Economics 31, 347363.

EC O L O G IC A L E C O N O M IC S 6 4 ( 2 0 08 ) 77 0 7 86

785

Princen, Thomas, Maniates, Michael, Conca, Ken, 2002. Confronting Consumption. MIT Press, Cambridge, Mass. Rae, John, 1834. Statement of Some New Principles on the Subject of Political Economy, Exposing the Fallacies of the System of Free Trade, and of Some Other Doctrines Maintained in the Wealth of Nations. Hilliard, Gray, and Co., Boston. Reprint (facsimile) 1964, Augustus M. Kelley, New York. Ramstad, Yngve, 1998. Veblen's propensity for emulation: is it pass? In: Brown, Doug (Ed.), Thorstein Veblen in the Twenty-First Century: A Commemoration of The Theory of the Leisure Class (18991999). Edward Elgar, Cheltenham, U.K. Reijnders, Lucas, 1998. The factor X debate: setting targets for eco-efficiency. Journal of Industrial Ecology 2 (1), 1322. Rhee, Hae-Chun, Chung, Hyun-Sik, 2006. Change in CO2 emission and its transmissions between Korea and Japan using international inputoutput analysis. Ecological Economics 58 (4), 788800. Robinson, John, 2004. Squaring the circle? Some thoughts on the idea of sustainable development. Ecological Economics 48 (4), 369384. Rpke, Inge, 1999. The dynamics of willingness to consume. Ecological Economics 28 (3), 99420. Rosenberg, Nathan, 1982. Inside the Black Box: Technology and Economics. Cambridge U. Press, Cambridge. Rosenberg, Nathan, 1994. Exploring the Black Box: Technology, Economics, and History. Cambridge U. Press, Cambridge. Rosenblatt, Roger (Ed.), 1999. Introduction to Consuming Desires: Consumption, Culture, and the Pursuit of Happiness. Island, Washington, D.C. Roy, Joyashree, 2000. The rebound effect: some empirical evidence from India. Energy Policy 28 (6/7), 433438. Rudin, Andrew, 2000. Let's stop wasting energy on efficiency programs energy conservation as a noble goal. Energy and the Environment 11 (5), 539551. Sachs, Wolfgang, 1988. The gospel of global efficiency. ifda (International Foundation for Development Alternatives) dossier 68, 3339. Sagoff, Mark, 1988. The Economy of the Earth. Cambridge U. Press, Cambridge. Saint-Paul, Gilles, 1995. Discussion. In: Golding, Ian, Winters, L. Alan (Eds.), The Economics of Sustainable Development. Cambridge U. Press, Cambridge. Salameh, Mamdouh, 2003. Quest for Middle East oil: the U.S. versus the Asia-Pacific region. Energy Policy 31 (11), 10851091. Sanne, Christer, 2000. Dealing with environmental savings in a dynamical economy how to stop chasing your tail in the pursuit of sustainability. Energy Policy 28 (6/7), 487495. Sanne, Christer, 2002. Willing consumers or locked in? Policies for a sustainable consumption. Ecological Economics 42, 273287. Saunders, Harry D., 1992. The KhazzoomBrookes postulate and neoclassical growth. Energy Journal 13 (4), 131148. Saunders, Harry D., 2000. A view from the macro side: rebound, backfire and KhazzoomBrookes. Energy Policy 28 (6/7), 439449. Say, Jean-Baptiste, [1803]/1836. A Treatise on Political Economy. Intro by Munir Quddus and Salim Rashid. Transaction, New Brunswick, New Jersey and London. Say, Jean-Baptiste, 1820. Lettres a M. Malthus Sur Diffrns Sujets dconomie Politique. Chez Bossange. Paris. Schipper, Lee, 2000. On the rebound: the interaction of energy efficiency, energy use and economic activity (Editorial). Energy Policy 28 (6/7), 351353. Schipper, Lee, Grubb, Michael, 2000. On the rebound? Feedbacks between energy intensities and energy uses in IEA countries. Energy Policy 28 (6/7), 367388. Schmidt-Bleeck, Friedrich., 1994. Wieviel Umwelt braucht der Mensch? MIPS Das Mass fr kologisches Wirtschaften. Birkhuser, Berlin. Schor, Juliet, 1992. The Overworked American: The Unexpected Decline of Leisure. Basic Books, New York.

Schor, Juliet, 1999a. The Overspent American: Upscaling, Downshifting, and the New Consumer. Basic Books, New York. Schor, Juliet, 1999b. What's wrong with consumer society? Competitive spending and the New Consumerism. In: Rosenblatt, Roger (Ed.), Consuming Desires: Consumption, Culture, and the Pursuit of Happiness. Island, Washington. Schor, Juliet, 2005. Prices and quantities: unsustainable consumption and the global economy. Ecological Economics 55 (3), 309320. Schumacher, Ernst Friedrich, 1973/1999. Small Is Beautiful. Hartley and Marks, Point Roberts, Washington, U.S.A. Schurr, Sam H., 1982. Energy efficiency and productive efficiency: some thoughts based on American experience. Energy Journal 3 (3), 314. Schurr, Sam., Netschert, Bruce C., 1960. Energy and the American Economy 18501975. Johns Hopkins, Baltimore. Scitovsky, Tibor, 1976. The Joyless Economy. Oxford U. Press, New York. Shi, Anqing, 2003. The impact of population pressure on global carbon dioxide emissions, 19751996: evidence from pooled cross-country data. Ecological Economics 44, 2942. Shim, Jae K., Siegel, Joel G., 1995. Dictionary of Economics. John Wiley, New York. Siebenhner, Bernd, 2000. Homo sustinens towards a new conception of humans for the science of sustainability. Ecological Economics 32, 1525. Sieferle, Rolf Peter, 2001. The Subterranean Forest. White Horse Press, Cambridge. Simms, Andrew, 2005. Ecological Debt: The Health of the Planet and the Wealth of Nations. Pluto, London. Smart, William, 1892. The effects of consumption of wealth on distribution. Report of the British Association for the Advancement of Science, pp. 840841. Paper read on Saturday, August 6. Smil, Vaclav, 2003. Energy at the Crossroads: Global Perspectives and Uncertainties. MIT Press, Cambridge, Mass. Solow, Robert A., 1957. Technological change and the aggregate production function. Review of Economics and Statistics 39, 312320. Solow, Robert M., 1970. Growth Theory: An Exposition. Clarenden Press, Oxford. Spangenberg, Joachim, Lorek, Sylvia, 2002. Environmentally sustainable household consumption: from aggregate environmental pressures to priority fields of action. Ecological Economics 43, 127140. Sraffa, Piero, 1951. Introduction to David Ricardo, [1817]/1820, On the Principles of Political Economy and Taxation. Cambridge U. Press, Cambridge. Stern, Paul C., Dietz, Thomas, Guagnano, G.A., 1995. The new ecological paradigm in social psychological context. Environmental Behavior 27, 441461. Sterner, Thomas, Isaksson, Lena Hglund, 2006. Refunded emission payments theory, distribution of costs, and Swedish experience of NOx abatement. Ecological Economics 57 (1), 93106. Swaney, James A., 1991. Julian Simon vs. the Ehrlichs. Journal of Economic Issues 25, 499509. UNCED, 1992. Framework convention on climate change. HeinOnline31 International Legal Materials, pp. 849873. http://unfccc.int. UNCED, 1993. Changing Consumption Patterns/Agenda 21. UN Department of Public Information. Union of Concerned Scientists, 2007. www.ucsusa.org/publications/ greentips. Veblen, Thorstein, 1899/1998. The Theory of the Leisure Class. Prometheus Books, Amherst, N.Y. Veenhoven, Ruut, 1991. Is happiness relative? Social Indicators Research 24, 134.

786

EC O LO GIC A L E CO N O M ICS 6 4 ( 2 00 8 ) 7 7 0 7 86

Von Weizscker, Ernst, Lovins, Amory B., Lovins, L. Hunter, 1997. Factor Four: Doubling Wealth Halving Resource Use. Earthscan, London. Wackernagel, Mathis, Rees, William, 1997. Perpetual and structural barriers to investing in natural capital: economics from an ecological footprint perspective. Ecological Economics 20 (3), 3 24. Wackernagel, Mathis, Silverstein, Judith, 2000. Big things first: focusing on the scale imperative with the ecological footprint. Ecological Economics 32, 391394. Waller, William, Robertson, Linda, 1998. The politics of consumption and desire. In: Brown, Doug (Ed.), Thorstein Veblen in the Twenty-first Century. Elgar, Cheltenham, U.K.

Wirl, Franz, 1991. Energy demand and consumption price expectations. Resources and Energy 13, 241262. Wirl, Franz, 1997. The Economics of Conservation Programs. Kluwer Academic, Boston. 4CMR (Cambridge Centre for Climate Change Mitigation Research), 2006. The macro-economic rebound effect and the UK economy. Final Report to Defra, vol. 18. May, www.defra.gov.uk/ environment/energy/research.

You might also like