Electronic Journal of Combinatorial Number Theory
Electronic Journal of Combinatorial Number Theory
TLn
w(T).
See Figure 1 for an illustration of the case n = 3.
For our second combinatorial interpretation, we will need another sequence of polynomials
closely related to the {n}. Dene n using recursion (1) but with the initial conditions
0 = 2 and 1 = s. If s = t = 1 then n is the nth Lucas number. A combinatorial
interpretation for these polynomials is obtained via another type of tiling. In a circular
tiling of the 1n rectangle, the edges labeled 0 and and n are identied so that it is possible
to have a domino crossing this edge and covering the rst and last squares. Such a domino,
if it exists, will be called the circular domino of the tiling. Let C
n
be the set of circular
tilings of a 1 n rectangle. So L
n
C
n
is the subset of all circular tilings with no circular
domino. For example, C
3
consists of the tilings in L
3
displayed previously together with
r r r
.
Now for n 1 we have
n =
TCn
w(T). (3)
Indeed, to show that the sum satises (1) rst note that we already have a weight-preserving
bijection for the linear tilings involved. And if T C
n
has a circular edge, then removal of
the tile covering square n1 will take care of the remainder. In order to make (3) also hold
for C
0
, we give the empty tiling of the 1 0 box weight w() = 2. Bear in mind that
INTEGERS: ELECTRONIC JOURNAL OF COMBINATORIAL NUMBER THEORY x (200x), #Axx 4
considered as an element of L
0
still has w() = 1. Context will always make it clear which
weight we are using.
We start with two recursions for the Lucas polynomials. These are well known for Lucas
sequences; see [4, p. 38, Identity 73] for (4) and [4, p. 46, Identity 94] or [11, p. 201, Equation
49] for (5). Also, the proofs in the integer case generalize to variable s and t without diculty.
But we will provide a demonstration for completeness and to emphasize the simplicity of the
combinatorics involved.
Lemma 2.1. For m 1 and n 0 we have
{m + n} = {n + 1} {m} + t {m1} {n} . (4)
For m, n 0 we have
{m + n} =
n
2
{m} +
m
2
{n} . (5)
Proof.For the rst identity, the left-hand side is the generating function for T L
m+n1
.
The second and rst terms on the right correspond to those tilings which do or do not have a
domino crossing the edge labeled n, respectively. To illustrate, if m = n = 2 then the tilings
in Figure 1 are counted by {m + n}. The rst two tilings do not have a domino crossing the
edge labeled 2 and so are counted by {n + 1} {m}. The edge of the third tiling does cross
that edge and is counted by t {m1} {n}.
Multiply the second equation by 2 and consider two copies of L
m+n1
. In each tiling
in the rst copy distinguish the edge labeled m 1, and do the same for the edge labeled
m in the second copy. The set of tilings in both copies where a domino does not cross the
distinguished edge accounts for the terms corresponding to linear pairs in n {m}+m {n}.
If a domino crosses the distinguished edge m1 in a tiling T, then consider the restriction
T
of T to the rst m squares as a circular tiling by shifting it so that the domino between
squares m1 and m becomes the circular edge. Also let T
, T
= (5, 4, 2, 2).
A linear tiling of is a covering of its Ferrers diagram with disjoint dominos and monomi-
nos obtained by linearly tiling each
i
. The set of such tilings is denoted L
. Note that if
mn then T L
n
which is the set of all tilings in L
n
which
do not begin with a monomino. This is equivalent to beginning with a domino if n 2,
and for n < 2 yields L
0
= {} and L
1
= . We dene L
then
it has weight w(T) = s
6
t
7
. But as an element of C
it has w(T) = 4s
6
t
7
. As usual,
context will clarify which weight to use. We are now in a position to state and prove our
INTEGERS: ELECTRONIC JOURNAL OF COMBINATORIAL NUMBER THEORY x (200x), #Axx 6
two combinatorial interpretations for the lucanomials. The rst has the nice property that
it is multiplicity free. The second is pleasing because it displays the natural symmetry of
_
m+n
m
_
.
Theorem 3.1. For m, n 0 we have
_
m + n
m
_
=
mn
TL
w(T), (6)
and
2
m+n
_
m + n
m
_
=
mn
TC
w(T). (7)
Proof.We will show that the right-hand side of (6) satises the rst recursion in Proposi-
tion 2.2 as the initial conditions are easy to verify. Given mn there are two cases. If
1
= n then the generating function for tilings of the rst row of is {n + 1}, and
_
m+n1
m1
_
counts the ways to ll the rest of the rectangle. If
1
< n then
1
= m. The generating
function for L
m
is t {m1} and
_
m+n1
n1
_
takes care of the rest.
Proving that both sides of (7) is similar using the fact that if we let f(m, n) = 2
m+n
_
m+n
m
_
then, by the second recursion in Proposition 2.2, we have f(m, n) = nf(m 1, n) +
mf(m, n 1). This completes the proof. 2
We end by noting that it would be interesting to nd analogues for
_
n
k
_
of various
known identities for ordinary binomial coecients. It might then be possible to use the
previous theorem to provide combinatorial proofs. One approach would be to apply algebraic
manipulations to the corresponding results for q-binomial coecients
_
n
k
q
. For example, this
method was used in [9] to give an analog of the Chu-Vandermonde summation for s = ,
t = 1. For general s and t it is easy to see that
_
n
k
_
= y
k(nk)
_
n
k
_
x/y
where
x =
s +
s
2
+ 4t
2
and y =
s
s
2
+ 4t
2
.
Unfortunately, this approach tends to introduce algebraic functions of s and t for which a
combinatorial interpretation is unclear.
References
[1] Andrews, G. E. The theory of partitions. Cambridge Mathematical Library. Cam-
bridge University Press, Cambridge, 1998. Reprint of the 1976 original.
INTEGERS: ELECTRONIC JOURNAL OF COMBINATORIAL NUMBER THEORY x (200x), #Axx 7
[2] Benjamin, A. T., and Plott, S. S. A combinatorial approach to Fibonomial
coecients. Fibonacci Quart. 46/47, 1 (2008/09), 79.
[3] Benjamin, A. T., and Plott, S. S. A combinatorial approach to Fibonomial
coecients: errata. Fibonacci Quart. 48, 3 (2010), 276.
[4] Benjamin, A. T., and Quinn, J. J. Proofs that really count, vol. 27 of The Dolciani
Mathematical Expositions. Mathematical Association of America, Washington, DC,
2003. The art of combinatorial proof.
[5] Bousquet-M elou, M., and Eriksson, K. Lecture hall partitions. Ramanujan J.
1, 1 (1997), 101111.
[6] Bousquet-M elou, M., and Eriksson, K. Lecture hall partitions II. Ramanujan
J. 1, 2 (1997), 165185.
[7] Bousquet-M elou, M., and Eriksson, K. A renement of the lecture hall theorem.
J. Combin. Theory. Ser. A 86, 1 (1999), 6384.
[8] Gessel, I., and Viennot, G. Binomial determinants, paths, and hook length for-
mulae. Adv. in Math. 58, 3 (1985), 300321.
[9] Loehr, N., and Savage, C. Generalizing the combinatorics of binomial coecients
via -nomials. Integers, to appear.
[10] Lucas, E. Theorie des Fonctions Numeriques Simplement Periodiques. Amer. J. Math.
1, 2 (1878), 184196.
[11] Lucas, E. Theorie des Fonctions Numeriques Simplement Periodiques. [Continued].
Amer. J. Math. 1, 3 (1878), 197240.
[12] Lucas, E. Theorie des Fonctions Numeriques Simplement Periodiques. Amer. J. Math.
1, 4 (1878), 289321.