Skolem's Paradox: 1. The Löwenheim-Skolem Theorem
Skolem's Paradox: 1. The Löwenheim-Skolem Theorem
Skolems paradox
In this essay, I shall do three things. First I will give a proof sketch of one of the LwenheimSkolem theorems, which says that any first-order set of sentences which is satisfiable has a model with a denumerably infinite domain. The next portion of the essay is then devoted to presenting Putnams model-theoretic argument which purports to show that a particular metaphysically realist position is incoherent. In short, by employing the Lwenheim-Skolem theorem Putnam argues that any such realist will be unable fix the intended interpretation of his theory of the world. Putnam thinks this realist consequently owes us an account of how his words are able to refer to their intended referents without postulating magical in another word, non-naturalistic powers. The last section of the essay discusses three replies to Putnams argument. The first two meet the argument head on, trying avoiding its conclusion, whilst the third reply merely tries to suggest that the very formulation of the argument is problematic. I argue that the two first ones fail but suggest that the last one may have more potential as an effective response to Putnams argument.
1 of 6
25-01-2014
be maximal consistent. Now we construct a model for *, which at the same time is a model for because is a subset of *. The model is an interpretation I which is an ordered pair, (D,V), consisting of a domain and a valuation function. As regards the domain, let every individual constant occurring in a sentence have itself as its extension. For the valuation function, assign predicates extensions as follows. Any predicate Fn of degree n is assigned a set of ordered n-tuples of individual constants drawn from the domain such that an ordered ntuple (a1,a2,,an) is a member of the set just in case the sentence Fna1,a2,,an is a member of *. It can be shown that such an interpretation I indeed is a model for * in the sense that any sentence is true in I iff is a member of *. Since is a subset of * the interpretation I is also a model for . Since this holds for arbitrary set of sentences , we can conclude that any set of first-order sentences has a model with a denumerable domain. Q.E.D.
2 of 6
25-01-2014
M stand for the same relations as they did in M and that the domain of M is a subset of the domain of M; the only difference is the cardinality of the domains over which the quantifier variables range. An important consequence drawn from this is that the membershiprelation of set theory can retain its meaning inside formal set theory and the LST will still apply. Putnams intended opponent is a metaphysical realist who claims that we grasp the notions of set-theory without postulating Platonistic powers of mind. In particular, such an opponent is committed to a correspondence theory of truth and thinks that truth is theory-independent. The commitment to the correspondence theory of truth is reflected in the semantics given for first-order logic. Our first-order formalization of set theory provides theoretical constraints on the permissible interpretations of our set-theoretic vocabulary: they make the meanings of set-theoretic notions as determinate as they possibly could be from the point of view of a formal language. The first part of Putnams argument can now be put as follows: P1. LST shows that first-order ZFC has non-intended models P2. If P1, theoretical constraints on ZFC fail to pick out an intended interpretation P3. Thus, theoretical constraints on ZFC fail to pick out an intended interpretation Putnam furthermore envisages his opponent having a formalized theory of total science providing operational constraints on the permissible interpretations of our set-theoretic vocabulary. This is to be understood, say, as the measurement of the magnitudes of various rational space-time points added to our first-order theory with the use of predicates and individual constants. This will result in adding at most denumerable infinitely many space-time points and denumerable infinitely many predicates. So the new theory is the union of ZFC and this formalized theory of total science call it ZFC+. To anticipate the response that our use of language fixes the intended interpretation of our theory, let us once again add denumerably many predicates for properties and individual constants for objects in our language; add all the axioms reflecting the truths expressed by our language and we get the theory ZFC++. This is the just more theory maneuver: any additional constraints on the permissible interpretations of our words are treated as yet more theory. The argument then continues as follows. P4. By applying the strengthened LST to our newly obtained theory ZFC++, we can conclude that ZFC++ has non-intended models where the meaning of the non-logical vocabulary remains the same in the sense described above P5. ZFC++ fails to pick out its intended interpretation
3 of 6
25-01-2014
Next, Putnam presses a number of questions. One particular question which is problematic for the metaphysical realist and is directly related to Skolems paradox is the following: if our firstorder formalization ZFC++ fails to fix its intended interpretation in the sense that there are other interpretations which provide a model for ZFC++, what then fixes it? Our grasp of ZFC++ must at the very least consist in being able to assign every expression of its language a unique reference. If our theory is not capable of doing this even whilst respecting every theoretical constraint and operational constraint, even whilst respecting the meaning of nonlogical expressions, what then enables us to grasp the meanings of our words?
4 of 6
25-01-2014
Wittgensteins own solution that grasping some rules is not a matter of giving an interpretation of the rule but following, or obeying, the rule. For Wittgenstein, our shared human natures are ultimately what enable us to do so. Wright similarly appeals to our subconscious patterns of rationality and making judgment. Apart from being rather obscure, such a reply seems to avoid the just more theory maneuver. Yet it doesnt deal with the problem effectively. The response acknowledges that our language fails to determine reference and then desperately reaches for something else in this case human psychology to fix reference. Not only would it be a fortuitous coincidence that human psychology managed to fix reference, it would also be inexplicable. As Putnam himself says, if our use of words is not up to the task of fixing the referents of these words, thinking that something else is simply doesnt help us. A third reply to Putnams argument tries not so much to argue that Putnams argument is incorrect but aims to show that the dialectical position between Putnam and the metaphysical realist is a philosophical stalemate. Note that by applying the LST to absolutely everything, the model-theoretic argument undermines its own talk of an intended interpretation and other notions used in the metalanguage to formulate Skolems paradox they are simply not available to us because they are incoherent. If we really are in the philosophical predicament Putnam thinks were in, every attempt to formulate the problem posed by the model-theoretic argument is impossible because accepting it implies that its very formulation is incoherent. So if Putnam accuses the metaphysical realist of postulating magical powers that determine reference whilst remaining a naturalist, the realist can only reply: tu quoque. What about the fact that there are other views in philosophy of mathematics verificationism and Platonism which arent threatened by the argument can we formulate the problem from their viewpoint, so to speak? I do not think so. If verificationism or Platonism is a correct view of philosophy of mathematics, and metaphysics more generally, then there is no problem to talk about in the first place. Similarly, one cannot accept the metaphysical realist position for the sake of argument and then refute it by reductio ad absurdum: accepting the very position means no reductio can be formulated coherently.
4. Concluding remarks
The above reply to Putnams argument is apt to seem suspicious: doesnt it imply that the refutation of any philosophical view will lapse into incoherence? No. The special feature of Putnams argument, if the reply is correct, is that it embodies a meaning-theoretical skepticism so radical that it is self-refuting. Similarly, no-one can coherently assert, for example, I dont believe anything or Everything I say is false. While this does answer Putnams argument in
5 of 6
25-01-2014
one sense, it is also unsatisfactory in another sense. The conclusion of the reply is not that there is no problem for the metaphysical realist that would be a philosophical victory and not a stalemate. Here, the conclusion must be that we cannot continue: every attempt to say something about the alleged problem is self-refuting if we accept that the problem really is a problem. The situation is that of a stalemate, not merely a draw, in the sense that we would like to be able to say something more but literally cannot do so. Where that leaves us is an interesting question, though it will have to wait for another time.
6 of 6