0% found this document useful (0 votes)
49 views15 pages

Advocacy Coalitions and The Practice of Policy Analysis

This document discusses how different models of the policymaking process influence perspectives on the role of policy analysis. It outlines three models: 1) The progressive model views policy analysis as objective expertise that informs neutral, rational decisions. 2) The interest group model sees policy shaped through negotiation between organized interests, with analysis informing advocacy. 3) The ideological conflict model recognizes that policy decisions often symbolize ideological conflicts beyond material interests. The advocacy coalition framework provides a synthesis by conceptualizing policy change as a long-term conflict between coalitions with different beliefs, perspectives that can inform legitimate roles for policy analysis.

Uploaded by

rousseau24755609
Copyright
© © All Rights Reserved
We take content rights seriously. If you suspect this is your content, claim it here.
Available Formats
Download as PDF, TXT or read online on Scribd
0% found this document useful (0 votes)
49 views15 pages

Advocacy Coalitions and The Practice of Policy Analysis

This document discusses how different models of the policymaking process influence perspectives on the role of policy analysis. It outlines three models: 1) The progressive model views policy analysis as objective expertise that informs neutral, rational decisions. 2) The interest group model sees policy shaped through negotiation between organized interests, with analysis informing advocacy. 3) The ideological conflict model recognizes that policy decisions often symbolize ideological conflicts beyond material interests. The advocacy coalition framework provides a synthesis by conceptualizing policy change as a long-term conflict between coalitions with different beliefs, perspectives that can inform legitimate roles for policy analysis.

Uploaded by

rousseau24755609
Copyright
© © All Rights Reserved
We take content rights seriously. If you suspect this is your content, claim it here.
Available Formats
Download as PDF, TXT or read online on Scribd
You are on page 1/ 15

Pol i cy Sci ences 2 1 : 2 6 3 - - 2 7 7 ( 1988)

9 Kl uwer Ac a de mi c Publ i sher s, Dor dr e c ht - - Pr i nt ed in t he Ne t he r l a nds


Advocacy coalitions and the practice of policy analysis
H. THEODORE HEI NTZ, Jr. l AND HANK C. JENKINS-SMITH 2
Office of Policy Analysis, Department of the Interior, Washington, DC; "- University of New
Mexico, Albuquerque, New Mexico
Sabatier and Jenkins-Smith (above) have presented a framework for de-
scribing the processes by which public policies change over time, and Heintz
and Weyant (above) have provided an array of case studies illustrating and
elaborating those processes. This article will focus explicitly on the manner in
which the advocacy coalition framework bears on the practice of policy anal-
ysis, both from t he perspective of the manager of analytical resources, and
from the perspective of the practicing policy analyst.
1. Issues in the practice of policy analysis
For mor e than a decade there has been an extensive debat e over both the
desirability and efficacy of public policy analysis. (See, e.g., Rein and White
1977a.) On the one hand are scholars who claim that analysis has had very
little effect because it has been used primarily for partisan political purposes.
For example, Horowitz (1970) argues that analysis has become mere a politi-
cal tool used to justify preconceived policy decisions, while Rein and White
(1977-B) claim that analysis has proved to be impotent as a device with
which to correct or improve public policy. Ot her critics cont end that policy
analysis serves merely to bury political debate under spurious complexity, or
to mask political interest under the guise of objective neutrality (Banfield
1980). On the ot her hand, defenders have rejoined that policy analysis can
and does provide an essential means to assess and balance competing claims
for increasingly scarce public resources, (Moore 1980) and that analysis does
lead to a gradual ' enlightenment' effect over time (Weiss 1977). 1 What is
interesting about this debate is that all sides are able to point to cases that
bear out their claims. In some instances, then, each of the positions seems to
have validity.
These conflicting views are a mainfestiation of the lack of consensus about
the role of policy analysis, a lack that has serious implications for the social
legitimacy of policy analysis, for expectations about its influence in policy
making, and for its practical conduct. Such conflicts reflect beliefs in funda-
264
mentally different models of the policy making process, models which, as
Nelson has shown, have deep historical roots (Nelson 1987).
Viewed in its broadest sense, the advocacy coalition framework seems to
provide a conceptual synthesis to these conflicting models. Such a synthesis
can shed light on some of the critiques of the social and political legitimacy of
policy analysis. It can also provide practical insights useful in its conduct.
This article will briefly describe the fundamental models that underly con-
flicting views of policy analysis. It will then suggest ways in which the policy
change framework can synthesize these models. Finally, it will discuss the
implications of such a synthesis regarding the socially legitimate roles of pol-
icy analysis, its management and the styles and tactics best suited to these
roles.
2 . P o l i c y a na l y s i s i n di f f e r i ng mo d e l s o f t h e pol i t i c al p r o c e s s
Nelson' s (1987) recent characterization of three views of the roles of econo-
mists in policy making provides a convenient summary of the conflicting
models of the political process that are at the root of conflicts over the role of
policy analysis. Nelson sees the three models as ( 1) t he progressive model,
(2) the interest group competition model, and ( 3) t he ideological conflict
model. Each of these models can be used to characterize a set of beliefs
about the role of policy analysis.
The progressive model
The Progressive model is based on the fundament al concept of separating the
subjective, value-oriented political policy making function from the objec-
tive, neutral scientific function (Wilson 1887.) Furt hermore, the progressives
hoped that the rationality of scientific management would gradually displace
much of the irrationality they perceived in the process of government. While
the progressive movement did not forsee the devel opment of policy analysis,
the devel opment of analysis was a logical outgrowth of the progressive move-
ment' s effort to introduce science and rationality into government.
In this model, the policy analyst is the neutral expert, objectively evalu-
ating the impacts of various options so that the most efficient can be identi-
fied. Typically the application of this model would call for the policy analyst
to identify a set of options for achieving politically det ermi ned goals, to study
their economi c and ot her impacts, and to report the results to the decision
maker in his organization. The decision maker would review the analysis,
consider ot her information on the political values involved, and render his
decision. The policy analyst would t hen assist the administrator to identify
the most efficient way to implement the decision. The separation of political
265
conflict from scientific analysis and management is achieved by regarding the
decision maker as the primary user of the policy analysis and by assuming
that the decision, once made, would be i mpl ement ed without furt her political
involvement. In this model, policy analysts are taught to operat e primarily in
a scientific research and report writing mode.
The interest group model
By the mid-point of the twentieth century, events had substantially eroded
the intellectual basis for the progressive expectation that science and ration-
ality could supplant much of the perceived irrationality of the governmental
process. Political scientists began to focus on t he ways in which competing
interest groups influenced policy to serve their material ends. In this model,
policy developed through a continual, incremental process in which organ-
ized interests negotiated for favorable treatment through legislative, executive
and judicial processes and through implementation as well as policy making.
Policy makers in executive agencies were expected to represent the interests
and views of the primary constituents served by the agency. Policy analysis
was seen in this model as providing the information which interest groups
and policy makers used to advocate their positions, a role often criticized by
believers in the progressive model.
Efforts to expand the role of policy analysis in the 1960s led to efforts to
synthesize the progressive and interest group models. Notable in these efforts
was Charles Schultze who presided over the Bureau of the Budget during
efforts to install policy analysis as a major component of the Planning, Pro-
gramming and Budgeting Systems (PPBS) in the civilian agencies of the fed-
eral government (Schultze 1968). Schultze rejected the progressive separa-
tion of politics and expertise, but retained the rationalist concept of policy
analysis as a means of clarifying objectives and making evident the trade-offs
inherent in allocating scarce resources. While the policy process was seen as
largely incremental and political, the role of the analyst was to provide infor-
mation on the efficiency of the various choices confronting decision makers
at each decision point. The policy analyst would thus become an ' efficiency
partisan' (Schultze 1968: 95), thus retaining the efficiency orientation of the
progressive ideal while merging it with the acceptance of advocacy inherent
in the interest group model. Furt hermore, the analytical tools to be used were
based on the broader concepts of economi c efficiency drawn from welfare
economics rather than the scientific management concepts of the progressive
era that were mor e narrowly focused on the efficient delivery of government
services. This model does not provide for the analyst to advocate interest
ot her than efficiency, however, thus retaining the concept that analysts were
to stand apart from the partisan or special interest politics.
266
The i deol ogi cal conf l i ct mo d e l
As Nel son points out, modern political scientists have now come to recog-
nize not only that the progressive hope of restricting subjective political con-
flict to a narrow set of decisions had failed to be realized, but also that many
observations of the behavior of political systems are difficult to explain whol-
ly on the basis of interest group behavior. Attention has therefore focused on
the role of ideology in political processes. Public policy decisions, it ap-
peared, were often influenced by deepl y held beliefs about the way the world
should be made to work. Decisions seemed often to be regarded as symbols
of the ascendency of an ideology rather than merely as instruments for
achieving material consequences.
Nel son suggests that since an ideology is "a basic way of thinking about
social issues [that] rests on fundamental assumptions and values that involve
some elements of faith," economists (and by extension policy analysts) have
an ideology. In this model the policy analyst is not merely an advocate for
efficiency among competing special interests, but a proponent of an ideology,
one that emphasizes rationality and efficiency and a decentralized system of
social organization (the competitive market) that relies upon the workings of
material incentives and self interest. Ot her ideologies emphasize such values
as fairness in the distribution of i ncome and wealth, the primacy of the
natural environment over man-made goods and services, or systems of cen-
tralized social organization that rely on planning and regulation. Thus, ideo-
logical issues are inescapable in the application of efficiency oriented analysis
of public policy issues. The policy analyst, wittingly or not, often becomes an
advocate for efficiency.
Synt hesi s
One of the purposes of the conceptual framework of policy change and
learning present ed in the Sabatier and Jenkins-Smith articles (above) has
been to characterize long term policy change in a manner that synthesizes
these three models. It does so through its focus on the relationship bet ween
the context of analysis and the kind of role analysis is likely to play on the
political process. The three model s can be synthesized using three key ele-
ments in the policy change framework, including (1) the focus on interaction
bet ween Opposing advocacy coalitions, (2) the analysis of factors explaining
policy change, and (3) the explication of belief systems of opposi ng coali-
tions.
The framework' s focus on interaction bet ween opposi ng coalitions incor-
porat es many of the elements put foreward by theorists of the interest group
school and carried over into the study of ideological conflict. This interaction
includes competition for control of resources and coalitions' efforts to gain
implementation of favorable policies. Interaction takes place through many
267
of the political and governmental processes identified by interest group the-
ories as the mechanisms of negotiation, bargaining and compromise. The
interaction between coalitions is continual and typically leads to incremental
policy changes. This interaction is also the process for working out subjective
political values in the progressive model or ideological conflicts in the ideo-
logical model.
The framework is focused on factors that can explain how policy changes
occur within a particular policy subsystem. Such factors include forces and
events external to the subsystem such as general economi c conditions and
electoral outcomes. But mor e importantly, the framework offers the possibil-
ity of explaining the evolution of policy as the result of policy ori ent ed learn-
ing in which analytical debat e is a key process. In such debate, the results of
policy analysis can provide the primary substantive arguments and analysts
may directly or indirectly play the role of advocates for their coalition's posi-
tion. Within the framework, the nature and extent of policy ori ent ed learning
are to be explained by reference to characteristics of the policy context.
These include the analytical tractability of key issues, the nature of the forum
in which the debat e occurs, and the level and intensity of conflict over beliefs.
The explication of coalitions' belief systems as a way of characterizing pol-
icy debat e is an important synthesis of aspects of political systems that have
often been treated as separate, or even incompatible, in the progressive, in-
terest group and ideological models. A belief system incorporates ideology in
its core beliefs about the causal relationships that affect material interests in
its secondary aspect. Thus the debate between opposed coalitions is moti-
vated by, and conduct ed in terms of, ideology, material interests and informa-
tion on causes of the probl em and consequences of policy options. The belief
systems concept thus allows explicit recognition that these three elements
are, in general, combi ned in most policy debates while t he proportions of the
mixture and its effects on policy change differ across subsystems and policy
issues.
The synthesis of the progressive, interest group and ideological models
achieved by the policy change framework has significant implications for the
issue of the legitimacy of the role of policy analysis in a representative politi-
cal system. Critics of policy analysis have charged that policy analysis con-
tributes to a drift toward centralized, technocratic control (Ellul 1964: 258- -
259). Others have argued that policy analysis serves to distort the expression
of individual political preferences by subsuming them into a narrow benefit-
cost framework (Kelman 1981). 2 The policy change framework makes clear
that analysis rarely speaks with a single voice, and even more rarely deter-
mines the out come of a policy debate. Cont rary to the fears of its critics,
users and providers of analysis have proliferated among interests groups and
public agencies, increasing the range and number of policy preferences that
268
are bol st ered by analysis (Leman 1982). Only in rare policy contexts - - those
characterized by highly analytically tractable issues subject to low levels of
conflict in a ' professionalized' forum - - will analysis be likely to cont ri but e to
centralized, technocratic control.
The policy change framework also suggests that analysis is rarely likely to
foist a distorted picture of public preferences ont o decision makers. As not ed
above, analysis tends to be mobilized by all active interests in the subsystem.
The framework makes clear that, on major policy debates, advocacy analysis
will persist over an ext ended peri od of time - - up to a decade or more. Thus,
should policy analysis bias public expression, t hose slighted can anticipate
subsequent analytical fora in which to press for redress.
As a final point regarding the legitimacy of policy analysis, the framework
indicates that analyses can stimulate genuine learning among policy sub-
system members. At worst, analysis stimulates intra-coalition learning, an
elaboration of the secondary aspect related to an advocacy coalition' s policy
core. At its best policy analysis stimulates cross-coalition learning, leading to
modification of the policy core of one or more advocacy coalitions. In recent
years this process has been clearly evident in the airline and trucking deregu-
lation issues (Derthick and Quirk 1985).
The advocacy role of policy analysis in the democrat i c policy making proc-
ess has similarities to the advocacy role of attorneys in the judicial process
and, indeed, to the advocacy role of scientists in debating opposi ng theories.
Such advocates abide by a set of rules appropri at e to their endeavors, rules of
evidence, relevance and logic by which opponent s can criticize and judge
each proposition. When policy analysis is used to advocate positions in the
policy process, similar rules structure the debate. The policy change frame-
work provides a way to det ermi ne the nature of such rules by examining the
content of the debate. It also provides the potential for understanding how
the context of the debat e effects the role of policy analysis and ot her factors
in leading to policy oriented learning and policy change. We now t ur n to an
examination of the context of policy debat e and its implications for the prac-
tice of policy analysis.
3. Pol i cy analysis in cont ext
What are the implications of the framework for the practice of policy anal-
ysis? In broad terms, the hypot heses drawn from the framework can be used
to depict those regions of the policy context that are hostile or hospitable to
the effective use of policy analysis in policy change. The relevant variables
underlying the policy context, as not ed in the first two articles of this
volume, are (1) the intensity of conflict over the political issue as derived
from the level of conflict bet ween belief systems of competing subsystem
269
coalitions, (2) the analytical tractability of the issue, and (3) the nature of the
forum in which the analytical debat e takes place. These variables in combina-
tion provide the context in which analysts attempt to shape the dimensions and
weights of the analytical policy space, as described in Jenkins-Smith (above).
Within subsystems, policy learning can take place within and/ or across
advocacy coalitions. In the former case, a given coalition elaborates upon the
causal connections and relations within its belief system, or perhaps finds
more persuasive ways to defend its policy core and secondary aspect. In the
case of cross-coalition learning, however, one or bot h coalitions add to or
modi fy their policy cores or secondary aspects in response to the analytical
debate. Thus while bot h kinds of learning involve adjustment of belief sys-
tems, intra-coalition learning primarily involves reinforcement or elaboration
of preexisting beliefs, while cross-coalition leafing involves genuine alteration
of beliefs. An important aspect of cross-coalition learning is the change in
beliefs of peopl e who were not coalition members. Strong arguments can
convince the undeci ded to support a coalition' s policy, perhaps even to join
and cont ri but e resources.
To the extent that the policy context enhances prospect s for cross-coali-
tion learning, then, the context can be t ermed hospitible to policy analysis. A
hostile context, on the ot her hand, will inhibit cross-coalition learning,
although it may instead foster intra-coalition learning. What then are the fac-
tors that lead to hostile or hospitable context for the application of policy
analysis?
Given the hypothesis devel oped in Sabatier (above), policy analysis can be
expected to generate cross coalition learning under conditions in which:
1. conflict between subsyst em coalitions is moderate. Moder at e conflict typi-
cally stems from conflict bet ween the policy core of one coalition and the
secondary aspect of another. The result is conflict sufficient to result in the
allocation of analytical resources, but conflict moderat e enough to permit
bot h coalitions t o cont empl at e change in their belief systems.
2. the pol i cy pr obl em at issue ranks fairly high on the di mensi on o f analytical
tractability. Thus when the issue under debat e has well devel oped theory,
is well conceptualized and operationalized, and adequat e data exists, the
probability that analysis will contribute to cross-coalition learning is
increased. Issues that are relatively new are tractable if these analytical
tools can be devel oped in a reasonable period, or carried over from a
related policy issue area. As a general rule, we would expect analytical
tractability to be highest among natural resource issues, and lowest in such
social issues as welfare and health care.
3. the f or um in whi ch the pol i cy debate is conduct ed approxi mat es the 'profes-
si onal i zed' f orum. Thus when the participants of the debat e share a com-
mon analytical background, such that common bases for assessing the
270
validity of analytical claims exists, analysis has a bet t er chance to effect
cross-coalition learning. A professionalized forum also provides some
assurance of an undeci ded audience that will apply the same rules and
criteria in judging the analysis and arguments made by the opposi ng coali-
tions. Thus the hospitality of the policy context will be affected by factors
that det ermi ne who participates in the forum.
Of course, there will also be combinations of characteristics of the policy
context that severely inhibit the ability of policy analysis to foster cross-coali-
tion learning. In some (but not all) respects, these are the converse of the con-
ditions leading to hospitable contexts not ed above. They include the follow-
ing:
1. either intense conflict or the absence of conflict across advocacy coalitions
within the policy subsystem. When intense conflict exists, considerable
analytical resources may be commi t t ed to the political fray, but neither
coalition is likely to evidence much willingness to modi fy its belief system.
On the ot her hand, where conflict is absent or insignificant, it is unlikely
that either coalition will commit sufficient analytical resources to effect
any possible learning.
2. the policy issue under consideration is highly analytically intractable. If
Sabatier' s hypot heses 8 is correct, most analytical debat es concerning
social policy - - wherein the objects of the analysis are themselves advo-
cates in the debat e - - will be subject to a hostile policy context.
3. the issue is addressed in an open political forum. In ot her words, the partic-
ipants in the political debat e are highly het erogeneous in their training and
in their bases for acceptance of analytical claims.
Thus the framework of policy learning provides us with extreme points, indi-
cative of those policy contexts that are most hostile and most hospitable to
cross-coalition learning. Of course we woul d expect many policy contexts to
fall somepl ace bet ween these extremes, perhaps with moder at e conflict com-
bined with a relatively intractable analytical issue. A degree of pessimism
may be in order, however, in light of the fact that professionalized fora are
relatively rare in the Ameri can political system. 3
Even when the policy context is hostile to prospect s for cross-coalition
learning, analysis may result in policy change. In the case of high levels of
conflict, wherein advocacy coalitions in the subsyst em rigidly adhere to the
existing belief system, repeat ed attempts to ignore or refute compelling ana-
lytical criticisms results in the loss of analytical credibility. The loss of analyti-
cal credibility forces the coalition to expend more scarce political resources
in support of translation of its belief system into policy via ot her avenues - -
such as lobbying (see Hypot hesi s 5, Sabatier, above). In the extreme, a con-
vincing and sustained analytical assualt on the belief system of the dominant
coalition within a subsystem - - like the extensive body of research pr oduced
271
in the t obacco policy subsystem indicating that significant health probl ems
result from the use of t obacco product s - - can result in a loss of support from
the system-wide governing coalition, in turn resulting in forced changed from
outside the subsystem. Although coalition members may not change their
beliefs, previously undeci ded participants may become convinced and lend
support to the opposi ng coalition to bring about policy change.
The devel opment of the policy change framework provides an opport uni t y
to examine in detail a variety of cases having different policy contexts
and different analysis roles. This volume presents only a few of the possibili-
ties, giving preliminary indications of the usefulness of the framework. Of
particular interest to practicing policy analysts are questions about the selec-
tion of policy issues as targets of analysis and the relationship of the style or
role of the analyst to the policy context.
4 . M a n a g e r i a l i m p l i c a t i o n s : a l l o c a t i n g a n a l y t i c a l r e s o u r c e s
Given the effect of the policy context on the role that analysis can be expect-
ed to play, how can (usually scarce) analytical resources be allocated in a
manner that enhances prospect s for cross-coalition learning? In answering
such a question, one must remember that analysts must respond to their pol-
icy making clients, usually officials in agencies or organized interest groups: it
is the client, after all, who has political legitimacy and authority (Foster
1980). Policy analysts usually have a weaker claim to represent the beliefs of
a policy coalition, except perhaps in professionalized fora devot ed to anal-
ysis.
Because analysis must be responsive to the client's needs, the overall allo-
cation of analytical resources frequently must take into account objectives
ot her than maximizing cross-coalition learning. Like it or not, analysis will
sometimes be called upon to delay decisions ('paralysis by analysis') or to
legitimize a preconcei ved policy position of the client (Marver 1979). In
essence, the range of free choice of over which analytical tasks to undert ake
can vary significantly (Jenkins-Smith, 1982). Acknowledging that such
demands may need to be met to ' pay one' s dues' within an organization, there
is often some degree of discretion over selection of issues and allocation of
analytical resources. What guides for allocation of analytical resources can be
discerned from the policy change framework?
Managers of policy analysis are faced with a variety of choices as they par-
ticipate in an ext ended analytical debate. They must deci de which issues or
beliefs to analyze, whet her to focus primarily on the beliefs of their own coa-
lition that are under attack by the opposi t i on or to focus on the beliefs of the
opposi ng coalition. The framework suggests that managers should, in part
272
identify opport uni t i es in hospitable policy contexts, and in part try to manip-
ulate the policy context to make it more amenable to analysis. In the former
case, managers will select t hose issues for which the context is characterized
by moderat e conflict, a relatively tractable subject matter, and a forum in
which participants can be expected to evidence a modi cum of agreement
over the bases for assessing analytical claims. Cases scoring high on all those
factors will be rare, however, so the task will ordinarily be one of eliminating
the ' hopeless cases' where analysis is most likely to be ineffectual. Where the
discretion of the broker permits such screening, the benefits could be sub-
stantial: the release of analytical resources, including staff time and the cost of
consultants, woul d permit a concentration of effort on issues where analysis
is more likely to make a genuine contribution.
The possible contribution of analysis is not always obvious. In some cases,
the policy context can be manipulated by judicious tailoring of the analytical
issue. For example, an issue of importance, like natural gas deregulation, may
be subject to very high levels of conflict (Rep. John Dingel, chairman of the
House Energy Committee, was quot ed in the press as saying full deregulation
of natural gas would be achieved over "my dead body"), but some important
sub-issues (like the ' old gas' supply response issue) of the debat e may be less
exposed to the political cross-fire. Furthermore, tailoring analysis may permit
focus on an aspect of the larger policy issue that is relatively tractable. This is
precisely the manner in which analysis was depl oyed in the 1983 natural gas
deregulation debates, recount ed in Jenkins-Smith (above), with the result
that all participants in the debat e adjusted their belief systems to account for
the benefits of increased supply under deregulation.
Anot her conceivable mechanism for manipulating the policy context - -
one that is less likely to be under the control of the policy manager - - is the
selection of the policy forum. Usually the forum will be established in ac-
cordance with the distribution of authority over the policy issue in question.
Where the broker might be able to influence the forum will be in cases where
a client - - e.g., a Cabinet level secretary - - has the power to convene a forum,
invite participants and set the agenda. In the end, of course, issues will be
debat ed in many fora, only some of which can be structured to facilitate pol-
icy oriented learning.
The optimal choice in selection of an analytical forum will be based in part
on how persuasive the analysis is, and on the sponsoring coalition' s political
resources. If the analysis is compelling, the manager should attempt to steer
the issue into a professionalized forum, perhaps by soliciting highly respect ed
bodi es like the National Academy of Sciences to sponsor studies and/ or con-
ferences on the issue. If the analysis is less compelling, but the coalition has
abundant political resources, the manager is more likely to meet with success
by routing the issue to an open political forum, like the U.S. Congress.
273
Whatever the strategy, the manager should realize that changing the core
beliefs of opposing advocacy coalitions will take a considerable period of
time. But it can happen, as illustrated by the airline deregulation (Derthick
and Qui rk 1985) and tobacco regulation (Fritschler 1983) cases. On the
ot her hand, when the debat e is focused on secondary aspects, as illustrated
by the gas deregulation case recount ed above in Jenkins-Smith, results can be
expected to be evident much mor e quickly.
5. Implications for the individual analyst
The policy framework also provides important insights for individual ana-
lysts. First and foremost, it is a mistake to view policy analysis as a discrete
act in which a probl em is analyzed, options reviewed, and advice given.
Viewed in isolation from the interactions of advocacy coalitions within policy
subsystems, ' success' and 'failure' of analysis are too often seen as wholly
contingent on the technical perfection of its content, and on whet her policy
makers accept or reject its conclusions. Such a view fails to recognize that
analysis is mor e often one part of an extended, many-sided exchange about
how issues should be perceived, and what policy options meri t consideration
by policy elites. Such a view may also fail to recognize that what counts as the
success of a particular analysis is at least partly contingent on the prevailing
policy context: to expect scrupulously objective, technically precise analysis
to make dent in a highly conflictual, intractable policy debat e is to invite dis-
appoi nt ment and frustration. 5 On the ot her hand, to write a partial, even
adversarial, analysis that makes the case for an important but neglected pol-
icy perspective can be a significant corrective when t he debat e is conduct ed
in a closed and/ or politicized forum.
Mor e broadly, the framework sheds light on the question of the appro-
priate professional role for the policy analyst in democrat i c politics. A survey
of the literature reveals that three domi nant roles for policy analysis are of-
fered as appropriate guides for professional behavior. (For a summary of that
literature, see Jenkins-Smith 1982.) The objective technician, operating in the
progressive mode, holds the primary objective to be provision of neutral,
objective and comprehensive analysis - - and then to retire from the field. 6
Advocacy is not t he game. The primary professional value is analytical integ-
rity. The issue advocate, on the ot her hand, does not object to joining the
political fray, and will use analysis to pursue some concept i on of the ' good
society.' It is probably the case that most issue advocates, by dint of training
in t he fundamentals of policy analysis, are advocates for economi c efficiency.
Alternatively, the client's advocate uses analysis to make the best case for his
political client's preferred option. For this analyst, it is the client who has
274
political legitimacy - - not the analyst - - and t he analyst is obliged to sub-
ordinate values derived from a personal view of t he good society or technical
integrity to service for t he client (Foster 1980). Often, of course, such advo-
cates come to share their client's beliefs, either through self-selection or
socialization within the coalition.
The framework suggests that each of these roles has legitimacy, strengths
in particular kinds of policy contexts, and fatal weaknesses in others. The
objective technician may do well with regard to a low conflict issue debat ed
in a professionalized forum, but would be utterly at sea in an analytical brawl
over a high conflict-intractable issue in an open forum. Furt hermore, the
advocate styles of analysis may be appropriate for analytical debates in which
analytical conflict is sufficient to assure that all relevant viewpoints are repre-
sented, but they may actually undermi ne the credibility of analysis when
employed in contexts of less (or uneven) conflict. Thus there is an inescap-
able and uncomfort abl e tension here: none of the styles of analysis seems
adequate in and of itself, and yet, applied indiscriminately, the various styles
of analysis could well undermi ne one another.
Of course, tailoring analytical practice to context would not be easy. Diffi-
culty may arise over determination of which context actually exists; the bulk
of the analytical contexts fall somewhere between extremes on dimensions of
analytical conflict, tractability, and types of fora. Different analysts could thus
quite conceivably perceive these factors differently, and therefore adopt and
apply incompatible styles of analysis in the same debate. Alternatively, the
context may change as the analytical debate wears on, forcing periodic
assessment of which style of analysis is appropriate. It is nonetheless highly
likely that most analysts could, particularly in extreme cases, discern the
major characteristics of the analytical forum. Furt hermore, as illustrated in
the case studies present ed in Jenkins-Smith (above), analysts do as a mat t er
of course modify their perceptions of the policy context through experience
and adjust their styles of analysis accordingly. 7 The probl em is to det ermi ne
what the appropriate style would be in a given context.
On the basis of the framework of policy learning, we offer a tentative reso-
lution to the problem. The three styles of analysis appear to best correspond
with three extremes in the policy context. The resolution calls for an explicit
adoption of a combi nat i on of styles of analysis, flexibly adapted to the policy
context. In a context in which the issue draws little analytical conflict, when
the forum is closed or not widely visible and approximates a professionalized
forum, participants should t end toward the objective technician style. Be-
cause of low levels of conflict, participants cannot count on the interests of
those aggrieved to readily correct for analysis that neglects or overempha-
sizes particular dimensions of value or beliefs. Furt hermore, the closed or
low-profile forum may serve to screen participants who may otherwise have
275
added important dimensions and interests to the debate. The objective tech-
nicians' penchant for comprehensive neutral analysis, though unlikely to be
fully realized in practice, will serve to increase the likelihood that the most
important factors are included.
Sometimes, however, the closed or low-visibility forum will already have a
distinctive pat t ern of expressed interests represent ed in analysis; analysis may
reflect the existence of ' client politics' (Wilson, 1980), in which a small group
of directly affected beneficiaries of a policy have incentives to join the debat e
while the larger, mor e diffuse population of those bearing the costs of the
policy do not. In this context, objective analysis using the general concepts of
applied welfare economics could be expected to produce information con-
flicting with the positions of particular interests. If efficiency-oriented anal-
ysis is to be present ed in such instances, an issue advocate role is hard to
escape. Stressing t he cos t s of a special interest policy to t he broader popula-
tion, especially within a coalition in which the special interest has substantial
power, requires a mor e assertive advocate style, but may entail some risks.
The issue advocate role may be appropriate as well in high conflict debates
waged in open, politicized fora. In those instances, a variety of interests to the
debate can be expect ed to be well represent ed by analysis. Because this mul-
tiplicity of interests is mobilized, each hammeri ng home its own grievances,
rights and expectations, the prudent analyst could well assume the role of
partisan efficiency advocate without concern that the structure of values
represented to policy elites is unduly distorted.
The practicability of the role of the partisan efficiency advocate will often
be contingent, of course, on the analyst working for an uncommi t t ed (or like-
minded) client. Because the latter cannot be count ed on in high conflict pol-
icy issues, analysts empl oyed by a client intensely commi t t ed to a particular
policy out come will be pressed to adopt the role of client's advocate. For high
conflict issues debat ed in open fora, such a result is not as bad as critics have
suggested. The t endency of the analytic contribution to such policy contexts
to be pluralistic in charact er would serve to ameliorate advocacy for any par-
ticular partisan or position in the aggregate analysis produced. It is well for
the analyst to remember, too, that the publicly elected or appointed policy
maker has at least an indirect legitimacy in the positions taken by virtue of
representative electoral politics. Finally, service of the client's interests, con-
sonant with the prevailing analytical tractability of the issue at hand, may be
necessary in order to maintain the client's sympathetic ear on ot her issues.
For these reasons, t he prudent analyst may on occasion assume the role of
the client's advocate.
Demands for service of the client's interest may become unreasonable,
however. In particular, the demand that analysis be shaded in the client's in-
terest to a degree that departs from the prevailing analytical consensus on the
276
questi on cannot be met in good consci ence. In those instances, shoul d the
exercise of voi ce not modi fy the demand, the analyst may be compel l ed to
empl oy exit. 8
The appropriate application of the range of styles of analysis - - knowi ng
when each is appropriate and what are their limits - - woul d require consi der-
able judgment on the part of the analyst. Nonet hel ess, the pol i cy change
framework suggests that a flexible combi nati on of styles of analysis is both
legitimate and practical. It is appropriate for the role of pol i cy analysis to
evol ve by adapting to the characteristics of various pol i cy contexts. In some
contexts a detached, objective scientific role is appropriate while in others
advocacy is called for. Experi enced and perceptive pol i cy analysts, using the
advocacy coal i ti on framework, should be able to adapt their analyses and
their style to the pol i cy context and thus contribute more effectively to the
injection of shared knowl edge into the pol i cy making process.
Not e s
1. To be sure, there are many uses of policy analysis - - some of which are overtly political
uses designed to legitimize preconceived policy positions. Furt hermore, clients may seek
out analysts who will agree with the policy maker' s policy perspective (often called ' hired
guns') to assure ' compatability' of analysis and the client' s policy position. Marver (1979)
provides a provocat i ve list of the full range of ' functions' of analysis. Nonetheless such uses
are typically percei ved as abuses of analysis, and if widely employed will undermine the
credibility of all analysis.
2. For an extensive discussion of these criticisms of policy analysis, see Jenkins-Smith (1985),
Chapters 3 and 7.
3. Professionalized fora may be more common in Eur opean political systems. See, for exam-
ple, Brickman' s (1984) discussion of the differences bet ween patterns of formulation of
toxic waste policy in the Uni t ed States and in Eur opean countries.
4. See Frischler (1983). Anot her case of analysis leading to forced change from outside the
policy subsystem concerns airline regulatory policy, See Derthick and Quirk (1985).
5. Arnol d Meltsner quotes an analyst frustrated by the recept i on of his work at the U.S. Office
of Economi c Opport uni t y ( OEO) as saying: "That' s what drove me out of OEO; the
leadership simply didn' t understand the role of evaluation" (Meltsner 1976: 23).
6. See Meltsner (1980) for a description of the technician model of analysis. Al so see Jenkins-
Smith (1982) for a devel opment of the ' objective technician' style of analysis, that typifies
the dominant paradigm in policy analysis.
7. In the Alaskan oil export case, it was a f t e r confronting advocacy for the maritime interests
on the part of Mar Ad analysts that the DOE analyst raised more uncertain issues that
would tug the analysis results back in the ot her direction. And in the Strategic Pet rol eum
Reserve case, it was a f t e r repeated experience with OMB analysts doggedly pursuing ana-
lytical results that would show a large SPR to be unjustified that analysts from DOE dug in
their heels and extracted a concession that permitted them to use their own, i mproved ana-
lytical approach.
See Wei mer and Vining (1986), Chapt er 2, for a very useful way of understanding the ethi-
cal dilemmas confronted by a policy analyst whose client demands analysis in support of a
preconceived policy position.
8.
277
References
Banfield, Edward, 'Policy Sciences as Metaphysical Madness.' Bureaucrats, Policy Analysts,
Statesmen: Who Leads! Edited by Robert Goldwin, Washington DC: American Enterprise
Institute, 1980.
Brickman, Ronald. 'Science and the Politics of Toxic Chemical Regulation: U.S. and European
Contrasts,' Science, Technology, and Human Values, Vol. 9, No. 1, (Winter 1984), 39--50.
Derthick, Martha, and Quirk, Paul. The Politics of Deregulation Washington, DC: Brookings
Institute, 1985,
Ellul, Jacques. The TechnologicalSociety. New York, NY: Vintage Books, 1964.
Foster, John L. 'An Advocate Role Model for Policy Analysis,' Policy Studies Journal, Vol. 8,
No. 6 (Summer 1980), 958--964.
Fritschler, A. Lee. Smoking and Politics. 3rd Ed. Englewood Cliffs, N J: Prentice-Hall, 1983.
Horowitz, Irving. 'Social Science Mandarins: Policymaking as a Political Formula,' Policy Sci-
ences, Vol. 1 (1970), 339--360.
Jenkins-Smith, Hank. Politics and Policy Analysis: Efficiency and Democratic Norms in Tension.
Rochester, NY: University of Rochester, Ph.D. dissertation, 1985.
Jenkins-Smith, Hank. 'Professional Roles for Policy Analysts: A Critical Assessment,' Journal
of Policy Analysis and Management, Vol. 2, No. 1, (Fall 1982), 88--100.
Kelman, Steven. 'Cost-Benefit Analysis: An Ethical Critique,' Regulation, 5(1) (Jan/Feb) 1981,
34--42.
Leman, Christopher. Some Benefits and Costs of the Proliferation of Analysis in Natural Re-
source Budgeting. Discussion Paper D-101. Washington, DC: Resources for the Future,
December 1982.
Marver, James. Consultants Can Help: The Use of Outside Experts in the U.S. Office of Child
Development. Lexington, MA: Lexington Books, 1979.
Melisner, Arnold. Policy Analysts in the Bureaucracy. Berkeley, CA: University of California
Press, 1976.
Moore, Mark. 'Statesmanship in a World of Particular Substantive Choices.' Bureaucrats, Policy
Analysts, Statesmen: Who Leads? Edited by Robert Goldwin. Washington, DC: American
Enterprise Institute, 1980.
Nelson, Robert. ' The Economics Profession and the Making of Public Policy." Journal of Eco-
nomic Literature, Vol. 25 (March 1987), 42--84.
Rein, Martin, and White, Sheldon. 'Policy Research: Beliefs and Doubt,' Policy Analysis, Vol. 3,
No. 2, (Spring 1977), 239--271.
Rein, Martin, and White, Sheldon. ' Can Policy Research Help Policy?' The Public Interest, Vol.
49, (Fall 1977), 119--136.
Schultze, Charles. The Politics and Economics of Public Spending. Washington, DC: Brookings
Institute, 1968.
Weimer, David, and Vining, Aidan. Policy Analysis: Introduction to an Emerging Profession.
Draft manuscript, 1986.
Weiss, Carol. 'Research for Policy's Sake: The Enlightenment Function of Social Research,' Pol-
icy Analysis, Vol. 3, No. 4, (Fall 1977), 531--545.
Wilson, James Q. Politics of Regulation. New York, NY: Basic Books, 1980.
Wilson, Woodrow. ' The Study of Administration.' Political Science Quarterly, (June 1887),
197--222.

You might also like