Eastern APA Paper
Eastern APA Paper
Abstract:
Political philosophy presents a static conception of childhood as a state of lack, a
condition where intellectual, physical, and more capacities are undeveloped. This view,
referred to by David Kennedy as the deficit view of childhood, is problematic because it
systematically disparages certain universal features of humanity dependency and
growth and incorrectly characterizes them as features of childhood only. Thus, there is
a strict separation between childhood and adulthood because adults are characterized as
fully autonomous agents that have reached the end of their moral and cognitive
development. I argue that this view is mistaken, and limits both the developmental
abilities of adults and ongoing moral development within an organized state. I propose
that we view dependency as a human condition. By doing so, children and adults form
the kind of relationship with one another that encourages the growth and development of
our moral sense in both childhood and adulthood.
Most philosophers believe that childhood is a distinct, universal feature of life for
human beings. 1 So, it is surprising to discover that the concept of childhood in
philosophical thought has not been adequately developed, especially within political
philosophy. This is problematic because political theories have been heavily shaped by
underlying assumptions about childhood assumptions about their intellectual and moral
capacities that determine a childs place within an organized state. These underlying
assumptions have neglected the cultural and social attitudes toward children that Philippe
Aris identifies in his Centuries of Childhood.
Aris presents a compelling account of the metamorphosis of the Western
conception of childhood from the early medieval period through modernity, arguing that
1
Kennedy, David. The Well of Being: Childhood, Subjectivity, and Education. Albany: State
University of New York, 2006. Print. P. 8.
the evolving understanding of childhood has depended upon advances in hygiene and
medicine, the development of Christianity, and shifting views of publicity and privacy in
daily life.2 Although Aris concludes that the concept of childhood has remained in flux,
political philosophy has primarily presented a static conception of childhood as a state of
lack that is, as a state of incomplete development that must be guided to an approved
end-state.3 This deficit view of childhood, as David Kennedy refers to it, not only informs
a limiting conception of childhood, but also a limiting conception of moral development
within an organized state. The deficit view of childhood maintains a strict adult-child
dichotomy, defining adulthood as an end-stage of physical, cognitive, and moral
development, and defining childhood as a series of incomplete developmental stages on
the way to adulthood.4 Thus, the deficit view of childhood supposes that adults possess,
among other capacities, a fully developed moral sense. In turn, the deficit view of
childhood must also be committed to the view that the state, comprised of and legitimized
by adults, condones an end-point for the moral development of its citizens.
In this paper I argue that the deficit view of childhood is unsound because it
systematically disparages certain universal features of humanity dependency and
growth and incorrectly characterizes them as features of childhood only. This mistaken
approach renders the relationship between the concepts of childhood and adulthood
nonexistent, insisting on a sharp distinction between the two concepts. If instead these
universal features are viewed positively and characterized as belonging to the experiences
2
Aris, Philippe. Centuries of Childhood: A Social History of Family Life. New York: Alfred A.
Knopf, 1962. Print.
3
Arneil, Barbara. Becoming versus being: a critical analysis of the child in liberal theory, in
The Moral and Political Status of Children. Archard, David, and Colin M. Macleod (ed.).
Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2002. Print. P. 70.
4
See Kennedy, Chapter 1.
of children and adults alike, the renewed relationship between the concepts of childhood
and adulthood benefits an organized state by encouraging the moral development of its
citizens beyond childhood.
By doing so, children and adults form the kind of relationship with one another that
encourages the growth and development of our moral sense in both childhood and
adulthood.
dispositions of women, slaves, and animals they are all driven by more natural
desires and needs, and hence, they all lack the rational capacity for political decisionmaking.5
Aristotle similarly categorizes children as appetitive as being lead by their
desires for pleasure only. Likewise, he also compares them to women, slaves, and
animals, claiming that each group has an underdeveloped (or completely absent) capacity
5
for deliberation.6 Thus, for Plato and Aristotle, children were thought to be deficient
when compared to adults they lack the fully developed moral and cognitive rationality
of adulthood that both philosophers judged so integral to decision-making, citizenship,
and personhood. This view of childhood, referred to by David Kennedy as the deficit
view of childhood, supposes that adulthood represents an end to certain incapacities of
childhood be they cognitive, psychological, physical, moral, legal, etc. in such a way
that it is as if the child is overcoming a deficit condition, something they must rid
themselves of.7 The deficit view of childhood also appears in various forms within the
writing of Augustine, Kant, Hegel, and then more prominently in early-modern and
contemporary liberal views of the state, as childhood education and moral training
became a dominant feature of political philosophy.8
In his Confessions, Augustine describes children not as pure and untainted, but as
naturally marred with original sin.9 This characterization of deficiency in childhood was
a move away from traditional views of the child as naturally pure, and provided
motivation for emphasizing a system of education aimed at the moral development of the
youth. For Augustine, children were inherently flawed, wicked, and naturally sinful;
their only hope for attaining moral purity was to be rid of this original sin through
rigorous moral training.10 Thus, Augustine described children as lacking some capability
or characteristic of adulthood, namely, a moral education. His focus on education was
influential not just to his contemporaries, but also to Jean-Jacques Rousseau.
6
Rousseaus conception of
11
Duschinsky, R. "Augustine, Rousseau, and the Idea of Childhood." Heythrop Journal Quarterly Review of Philosophy and Theology. 54.1 (2013): 77-88. Print.
12
It should be noted that for most of these philosophers, including Rousseau, there was a focus on
male childhood and male moral and cognitive development. The development of female
children, like the potential of female adults, was limited to reproductive labor. See: Scholz, Sally
J. "That All Children Should Be Free: Beauvoir, Rousseau, and Childhood." Hypatia. 25.2
(2010): 394-411. Print.
13
Riley, Patrick, and Jennifer Welchman. "Rousseau, Dewey, and Democracy." In A Companion
to the Philosophy of Education. Curren, Randall R. (ed.). Malden, MA: Blackwell, 2003. 94-112.
P. 102.
14
Duschinsky, p. 83.
15
Rousseau, Jean-Jacques, Christopher Kelly, and Allan D. Bloom. Emile, Or, on Education:
Includes Emile and Sophie, Or, the Solitaries. Hanover, N.H: University Press Of New England,
2009. Print.
childhood, then, continues the adherence to the deficit view of childhood within political
thought.
See: Scholz, Sally J. "That All Children Should Be Free: Beauvoir, Rousseau, and Childhood."
Hypatia. 25.2 (2010): 394-411. Print.
17
See: Arneil, p. 88. A more thorough discussion of the universal features of childhood will be
discussed in the next section.
18
Tamar Schapiro acutely makes this point. Employing a Kantian framework, Schapiro argues
that childhood should be thought of as 1) a condition of undeveloped agency, and 2) a temporary
deviation from the norm of adulthood. She concludes that we ought to regard the predicament of
childhood as on obstacle to morality, and that it is the job of adults to do whatever is in our power
to help children work themselves out of childhood. See: Schapiro, Tamar. "What Is a
Child?" Ethics. 109, no. 4 (1999): 715-738.
19
Duschinsky, p. 79.
to become more independent, emphasizing the deficiency of dependency that, for liberal
political theories, remains a fixture of childhood.20 Barbara Arneil argues that Lockes
theory of education is also fundamentally tied to this cause, as childhood education is a
central focus of his political theory.21 Locke writes that children will remain dependent
upon their parents, who are responsible for their childs education, until they mature and
fully develop the capacities that they lack as children.22 Once they have overcome their
deficiency, they can be recognized as citizens as autonomous members of the state.
The emphasis on the proper upbringing of children towards an autonomous, yet
civically minded, adults is present in contemporary political works such as John Rawls A
Theory Of Justice. However, Rawls is somewhat skeptical of this program of education
(though he nevertheless endorses it). He worries that the type of attitudes that must be
instilled in children so that they develop the right moral sense can only be successfully
imparted when the proper conditions are met.23 His skepticism leads a general worry for
liberal theory that many children will not have the kind of developmental upbringing that,
despite the institutionalization of education, instills in them the combination of autonomy
and the right kind of moral sentiments as adults.24 Arneil uses this general worry about
the moral status of adults, and its ramifications for the rights of children under a liberal
20
This concept of childhood is also found in Hegels Elements of the Philosophy of Right.
Therein, Hegels express purpose for the family and the civil elements of school are to instill
independence in children, who are to leave their temporary state of dependency to become
independent citizens of the state. See: Hegel, Georg W. F, Allen W. Wood, and H B. Nisbet.
Elements of the Philosophy of Right. Cambridge, England: Cambridge University Press, 1991.
Print.
21
Arneil, p. 72.
22
Locke, John, and J W. Gough. The Second Treatise of Civil Government: And a Letter
Concerning Toleration. Oxford: B. Blackwell, 1946. Print. Ch. 6, 58.
23
These conditions are heavily dependent upon the role of parenting. See: Rawls, John. A Theory
of Justice. Cambridge, Mass: Belknap Press, 2005. pp. 459-467
24
Coleman, Joe. Answering Susan: Liberalism, Civic Education, and the Status of Younger
Persons, in The Moral and Political Status of Children. Archard, David, and Colin M. Macleod
(ed.). Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2002. Print. pp. 170-173.
state, to motivate an argument for adopting the ethics of care as a better framework for
conceptualizing the relationship between child and adult and, consequently, the kind of
relationship that parents should have with their children.25 Before fully discussing her
view, I will turn more thoroughly to David Kennedys analysis of the adult-child
dichotomy and John Deweys account of dependency, as I believe they provide the right
conceptual foundation for engaging with, and building upon, Arneils account.
implicitly in the universality of childhood; that there is some distinct class of human
beings who are not quite persons (in the robust sense described in the previous section),
yet not quite non-persons either.26 However, when children are described as lacking
particular capacities synonymous with adulthood (namely, maturity, rationality, and
autonomy), the nature of the child is not being described; rather, the relation between the
adult and the child is being described.27
25
Arneil, p. 88.
Kennedy, p. 8.
27
Kennedy claims that there is no such thing as a child apart from and adult to observe,
categorize, and classify it as lacking properties distinct form the adult. See: Kennedy, p. 3.
26
Kennedys position follows that of John Dewey, who claims in Democracy and
Education that our tendency to equate immaturity with lack and growth or development
as something that paves the way from immaturity to maturity is attributable to viewing
childhood comparatively instead of intrinsically. 28
28
31
Kennedy, p. 63.
Ibid. p. 70.
33
Dewey, p. 48.
32
10
Arneils argument and its shortcomings, I will use Kennedys proposal for a renewed
approach to education to extend her account beyond childhood.
See: Ginsburg, Herbert, and Sylvia Opper. Piaget's Theory of Intellectual Development.
Englewood Cliffs, N.J.: Prentice-Hall, 1979.
35
Kennedy, pp. 22-25.
36
Arneil, p. 74.
11
because they lack the rationality to consent to being a part of a political community.37
Thus, children are seemingly born without rights, and they neither possess rights, nor are
they entitled to any claims within their own society, throughout childhood.38 Lastly,
Arneil argues that the conception of the state suffers by holding children in this particular
non-citizen status, for it creates an antagonistic relationship between the state and the
families within it.
In response to these issues, Arneil argues that we need to stop viewing the child as
a becomming and instead as a being that is, as the child is now, and not in relation
to a future self.39 This means recognizing that there are certain universal features of
childhood, and that these universal features are not deficiencies. The first universal
characteristic of childhood is growth. Just as Dewey sees growth as an ability, Arneil
understands growth as a non-limiting (i.e. not definitively ending) process that
encompasses social, emotional, and intellectual development.40 Thus, growth is a process
of development that yields positive results (the expansion of our knowledge and
experience), and is not strictly limited to ones childhood years. A second universal
characteristic of childhood is dependency and its correlating need for care part of being
a child is to be dependent upon others, necessitating care from adults.
However,
37
This is the associational element of liberal theory. See Rawls, pp. 467-472.
Though the focus of this paper is not on childrens rights, the question of what rights children
have, or may potentially have, will surely be affected to alternative views of childhood and
alternative views of the relationship between childhood and adulthood. For some in-depth
discussions of childrens rights (and, relatedly, parental rights), see: Narayan, Uma, and Julia J.
Aaron. Having and Raising Children: Unconventional Families, Hard Choices, and the Social
Good. University Park, Penn: Pennsylvania State University Press, 1999; and Matthews, Gareth
B. The Philosophy of Childhood. Cambridge, Mass: Harvard University Press, 1994 (especially
chapter 6); and Eekelaar, John. The emergence of children's rights. Oxford Journal of Legal
Studies, 6 (2) (1986):161-182.
39
Arneil, p. 88.
40
Ibid. p. 88.
38
12
dependency here is not viewed as a deficit; instead, it is viewed as a motivating factor for
incorporating the ethic of care into liberal political thought.
Part of recognizing
dependency means recognizing that the success of parental care is dependent upon a
wider social structure that supports the robust notion of growth that Arneil has in mind,
and that social structure, Arneil argues, can only arise through an ethics of care.41
Arneils conception of childhood as being provides a justification for why the
ethics of care is so important for liberal thought: it gives an explicit directive to the state
as a social structure to ensure that children are properly cared for. However, the limited
focus of Arneils account how care should be implemented to best serve the growth of
children does not challenge the notion of adulthood as the end of maturation. Although
Arneil expands the notion of growth beyond childhood, she does not relate the
importance of growth in adulthood to the cultural change that will be necessary to
perpetuate a focus on care in an organized state. While I agree that a reconceptualization
of childhood that leads to improved care for children is indeed a step in the right direction
for liberal theory, I believe we can gain much more from this conceptual evolution if we
also take into account what changes the concept of adulthood will undergo when growth
is seen as an essential part of adulthood as well.
Ibid. p. 88.
13
Kennedy, p. 14.
14
A dialogical form of education would ensure that the prevailing ideology [of
adulthood] is challenged by new information, which leads to social and cultural
transformation.43 By taking a different stance toward childhood, we come to value the
features of childhood that were once thought to be deficient and incorporate those
features into our cultural norms, which in turn affect the beliefs, institutions, and
behaviors of adults.
Ibid. p. 14.
Ibid. p. 73.
15
45
See: Gilligan, Carol. In a Different Voice: Psychological Theory and Women's Development.
Cambridge, Mass: Harvard University Press, 1982. Print; and Tronto, Joan C. Moral Boundaries:
A Political Argument for an Ethic of Care. New York: Routledge, 1993. Print.
46
Dewey, p. 54.
16
5. Concluding Remarks
The strict adult-child distinction that has remained a constant fixture in political
philosophy has not only hindered the development of a more robust concept of
childhood; it has placed undue restrictions on moral development period. This is due, in
part, to the emphasis on the development of autonomy that appears in liberal thought
especially. By reconceptualizing the universal features of childhood dependency and
growth as positive and universally human features, childhood is no longer a deficient
condition.
17