Comparing Modernities
Comparing Modernities
International Comparative
Social Studies
Editorial Board
Duane Alwin, Ann Arbor, USA
Wil Arts, Tilburg, The Netherlands
Mattei Dogan, Paris, France
S.N. Eisenstadt, Jerusalem, Israel
Johan Galtung, Versonnex, France
Linda Hantrais, Lougborough, UK
Jim Kluegel, Urbana-Champaign, USA
Chan Kwok Bun, Hongkong, China
Frank Lechner, Atlanta, USA
Ron Lesthaeghe, Brussels, Belgium
Ola Listhaug, Trondheim, Norway
Rubin Patterson, Toledo, USA
Eugene Roosens, Leuven, Belgium
Masamichi Sasaki, Tokyo, Japan
Saskia Sassen, New York, USA
John Rundell, Melbourne, Australia
Livy Visano, Toronto, Canada
Bernd Wegener, Berlin, Germany
Jock Young, London, UK
VOLUME 10
60
chapter two
Shmuel N. Eisenstadt
Comparing
Modernities
Pluralism versus Homogenity
Essays in Homage to Shmuel N. Eisenstadt
Edited by
BRILL
LEIDEN BOSTON
2005041989
ISSN 15684474
ISBN 90 04 14407 2
Copyright 2005 by Koninklijke Brill NV, Leiden, The Netherlands.
Koninklijke Brill NV incorporates the imprints Brill Academic
Publishers, Martinus Nijho Publishers and VSP.
All rights reserved. No part of this publication may be reproduced, translated,
stored in a retrieval system, or transmitted in any form or by any means,
electronic, mechanical, photocopying, recording or otherwise, without prior
written permission from the publisher.
Authorization to photocopy items for internal or personal use is granted by Brill
provided that the appropriate fees are paid directly to The Copyright Clearance
Center, 222 Rosewood Drive, Suite 910, Danvers, MA 01923, USA.
Fees are subject to change.
printed in the netherlands
CONTENTS
Preface ........................................................................................
ix
xi
31
57
83
4. The exception that proves the rule? Rome in the Axial Age .......... 125
W.G. Runciman
5. Civil Society: Some remarks on the career of a concept .................. 141
Jrgen Kocka
6. Challenges of modernity in an age of globalization ........................ 149
T.K. Oommen
7. The dark side of modernity: Tension relief, splitting, and Grace .... 171
Jerey C. Alexander
vi
contents
II. MODERNITY AND PLURALISM
183
191
205
223
229
245
261
287
309
327
339
365
contents
vii
395
413
443
461
483
501
515
527
545
553
581
viii
contents
VI. EPILOGUE: MODERNITY AS PROGRAM
605
635
Appendix
The trail of a scholar ....................................................................
A scholarly portrait ........................................................................
Donald N. Levine
657
662
Bibliography ..............................................................................
Index of Persons ........................................................................
Index of Subjects ......................................................................
671
707
713
PREFACE
preface
and Brill Academic Publishers. As an introduction to the topics discussed in the all-following, it is our privilege to introduce rst the
contribution of Shmuel N. Eisenstadt.
The Editors
xii
xiii
pline and his openness to the world and its challenges. We wish him
many more years of intellectual creativeness, health, prosperity and
deserved satisfaction with a work so important for others.
Piotr Sztompka
President of the International Sociological Association
xiv
xv
xvi
xvii
xviii
xix
xx
xxi
xxii
English language social science journals across the world. And it lists
94 monographs and edited books including translations into Hebrew,
German, Spanish, Italian, Portuguese, Japanese and Korean. Their
subjects range from classical sociological questions of structural
dierentiation and stratication to classical anthropological preoccupations like age sets among the plains Indians in north America.
They include the absorption of immigrants in Israel, the generalisation
of trust and patron-client relationships in Latin America, patterns of
social change in India, Japanese civilisation in comparative perspective, charisma and institution building, the dilemmas of development
in post-colonial societies, youth culture in Israel, the reconguration
of the political in modern protest movements, the reconstruction of
tradition in post-traditional societies, the modernity of religious
fundamentalist movements, the deconsolidation of contemporary
democracies and the dynamics of revolutionary change, to mention
only a few of the topics which bear witness to the extraordinary
range of his scholarly interests. He brings a wealth of historical
and empirical material to bear on these issues moving eortlessly
from the macro level to the micro level, linking social structure and
cultural traditions with collective action by diverse groups of actors.
Not everything he has written may be equally persuasive, but even
when one disagrees with him one learns more than from most
scholars.
Prof. Eisenstadt is no stylist. What his prose lacks in elegance, it
makes up for in clarity and the coherence of the argument. One
always reads him with prot, but listening to his lectures is a special pleasure. I do not know if it is years of teaching experience, or
just a natural gift, which enable him to deliver a public lecture without even a set of notes, let alone a manuscript. Never rambling,
timed to the minute, these well-structured oral presentations, in which
he never loses the thread of his complex argument, could go into
print without any alterations. His lectures have the informality of a
personal conversation with him and bear some testimony to his
delightful sense of humour of which there is no trace in his writings.
But they would not qualify as Eisenstadt lite. However brief his talks,
or informal the setting in which they are delivered, they are full of
stimulating ideas. Remarkable is the eortless ease with which he
links the large picture to little details drawn from a vast variety of
sources. So lightly does he wear his learning that even audiences
with a limited acquaintance of the enormous range of secondary
xxiii
INTRODUCTION:
CIVILIZATION, PLURALISM AND UNIFORMITY
Eliezer Ben-Rafael and Yitzhak Sternberg
Anthropologist Clyde Kluckhohn expressed years ago the truism that
every man is in certain respects like all other men; like some other
men; like no other man (see Hannerz, 1996: 39). Two major sociological issues relate to this sentence, namely the appropriate unit of
socio-historical analysis and the question of pluralism versus uniformity in society; these issues are at the center of this volume. More
specically, it deals with the tensions and dilemmas that in nearly
every contemporary society oppose pluralism and homogeneity. Unlike the widest part of the literature that discusses this area of
questions, the present frame of discussion is civilizational analysis and
it looks at essential aspects of civilizations in order to approach it.
To avoid confusion, the concept of civilization is to be distinguished
from culture. This distinction developed in Germany where scholars
included in the notion of civilization technological, material and organizational aspects of the social reality which tend to spread in society
and beyond. In the same perspective, culture, on the other hand,
was viewed as designating deeper spiritual and aesthetic aspects of
social life and personality that are particular to specic societies and
groups (see Elias, 1994). According to this distinction, dierent social
groups can absorb given aspects pertaining to a same civilization
reaching them from external or internal foci, and at the same time
share dierent cultures. Hence, change in civilization does not necessarily imply corresponding change in culture, and civilization and
culture do not necessarily develop at the same pace. In addition, it
is also widely acknowledged that impacts of civilization may stand
in contradiction with desirata of culture. This theme was already
asserted by Wilhelm Mommsen in the middle of the 19th century,
when he said that it is humanitys duty today to see that civilization does not destroy culture, nor technology the human being (see
Braudel, 1994: 56). This theme, even if the explicit terminology
was not used, also appeared in Karl Marxs notion of alienation
and Max Webers typology of rationality and its iron cage metaphor.
An attitude that has also been exemplied in writings of scholars
from the Frankfurt School (Horkheimer and Adorno, 1972). In
other words, the distinction between civilization and culture enables
a critique on civilization on behalf of culture.
At the heart of these outlooks resides the fact that civilization and
culture are both mainly concerned with choices of criteria of social
action and perspectives on social life. Civilization and culture, it is
true, are turned toward dierent items pertaining to dierent areas
of activity and reections. Yet, these areas are not completely
separate from each other and may overlap to a varying extent: the
use of technologies and the organization of consumption behavior,
for instance, as rstly determined by civilizational perspectives are
not alien to aesthetic or moral considerations that form the core of
cultural preoccupations. Moreover, civilization and culture may also
compete with each other with respect to the relative emphases individuals and groups set on the dierent relevant areas of action or
reection. Hence, the relations of civilization and culture are fraught
with tensions and dilemmas. Furthermore, such tensions and contradictions can still be aggravated when individuals, groups, parties
or organizations stand for opposed outlooks drawing in dierent
manners from civilizational or cultural codes.
It remains that contrary to the particularism of cultures, civilization is bound to world-historical processes (see Arnason, 2001;
Eisenstadt, 2001a), constitute long-term developments involving selfconstraints coming up to transformations in human behaviorwhat
Elias (1994) means by the notion of civilizing process. As such
they raise a spectrum of unavoidable analytical and moral questions.
According to Emile Durkheim, for example, a man is a man only
to the degree that he is civilized (see Arnason, 1988: 89). Sigmund
Freud expressed a similar view when remarking that the word
civilization describes the whole sum of the achievements and the
regulations which distinguish our lives from those of our animal
ancestors. (Freud, 1961: 36). This notion is connected, among
others, to the problmatique implied by the theme of the noble
savage, and opens a fundamental debate about the universal, nay
even universalistic, nature of social development.
At the same time, civilizations also refer to distinct sociocultural
spaces that include diverse units such as states and societies. Hence,
civilizational analysis usually deals with units of larger dimensions
introduction
and longer duration than the single societies that they encompass
(Arnason, 2001: 1910) and it is under this angle that Arnold Toynbee
(1965) considered civilization as the central unit for socio-historical
analysis. At this very point, however, this notion of civilization questions its relation to religion that, as it happens, also consists of a set
of codes that mostly run across the borders of individual societies.
According to Shmuel N. Eisenstadt although in the history of human
kind civilizations and religions were very closely interwovenat the
same time many religions have been only a part of the component
or not necessarily the most central component of civilizations
(Eisenstadt, 1992b: 1; see also Kroeber, 1963). Yet, as argued by
Fernand Braudel, religion can be seen as one of the most important traits of civilizations. According to him, Christianity is an essential reality in western life: it even marks atheists, whether they know
it or not. Ethical rules, attitudes to life and death, the concept of
work, the value of eort, the role of women and childrenthese
may seem to have nothing to do with Christian feeling: yet all derive
from it nevertheless (Braudel, 1994: 23). Braudel also suggests that
the long historical continuity of civilizations should be part of their
denition. Civilization is in fact the longest story of all says Braudel
(1994: 34). For Durkheim and Mauss ([1913] 1971: 811) a civilization constitutes a kind of moral milieu encompassing a certain
number of nations, each national culture being only a particular
form of the whole. Moreover, according to Carroll Quigley (1979)
only a culture that has some instruments of expansion can become
a civilization. This large-scale dimension of civilization makes it a
family of societies distinct from other such familiesto use the
words of Marcel Mauss. It is under this angle and at the level of
world history that one may also speak of civilization as carrying a
form of particularism (see also Arieli, 1992; Braudel, 1980; Febvre,
1973; Kroeber and Kluckhohn, 1952; Nelson, 1981b).
In this broad context, the concept of civilization implies a pluralistic calling that stems from both the plurality of civilizations and
plurality within civilizations. A plurality-condition that may add up to,
and combine with, additional factors of pluralism, like the character
of dominant and dominated groups (Toynbee, 1965) or diverse
distinctions between core and periphery (Quigley, 1979). In all
respects, what is at stake is the extent that dierencesthat is,
pluralismare tolerated at the cost of the common perspectives and
uniformity carried primarily by civilizational codes.
introduction
are another ingredient that one often nds behind the groups mobilization on behalf of its recognition as a distinct and respectable
entity. On the other hand, changes of values and perspectives among
members are also inevitable as they insert themselves in society,
are exposed to predominant patterns of behavior and convictions,
and undergo a degree of acculturation. Acculturation may even lead
to assimilation when individuals accede to higher-status positions and
are tempted by distancing themselves from their group of origin in
order to better integrate new milieus.
Such processes, however, are by no means unrelated to the viewpoint characterizing the societal center that may either encourage or
on the contrary hamper processes leading to homogeneity. In this
latter case, it is that which supports, from the above, the retention, nay even institutionalization, of pluralism regarding at least,
some of the groups in presence. This stance of the stronger party
of the scene is the primary factor in laying down the rules of the
game. On the ground of its representation of societys historical and
cultural personalityand of course, under the inuence of the interests of those who support its policies, this party may combine, in
dierent possible manners, universal valuessuch as freedom or
equalitywith particularistic outlooks, and specify in varying terms
rules of the pluralism-homogeneity dilemma, such as the exclusiveness or accessibility of membership; regulations ofeconomic, political,
or otherparticipatory rights; or entitlements to prominent positions
(see Almond and Verba, 1963; Znaniecki, 1973). These rules where
the imprint of civilization as well as culture can be revealed, manifest basic attitudes toward social divisions and, among other expressions, articulate fundamental orientations toward pluralism that may
vary over time and space (Grillo, 1989).
Unifying orientations perceive a setting where dierences are secondary and doomed to disappear. This type of orientation may accept
new members who are dierent, only on condition that they are
willing to conform. It encourages a complete integration of newcomers but with no tolerance for the public manifestation of their
particularisms. In contrast, pluralistic orientations recognize the social,
cultural, and linguistic dierences that exist in society. Permissive of
dierences, it is ready to institutionalize them as enduring features
of the social order. At its limit, these orientations can be segregationist
and refuse to leave to individual groups the choice between the retention of singularity or assimilation. Unifying and pluralistic orientations,
however, are by no means mutually exclusive, and we may well conceive of a society where the center insists on unication and assimilation vis--vis some groups, but on pluralism vis--vis others.
This rough characterization is enough, we think, to evince how
far pluralism versus homogeneity can constitute a central axis of
debate in society. An assessment that, to be sure, cannot but remind
what we know about many contemporary societies, and more precisely, contemporary societies which participate to the modern civilization where universalistic claims and exigencies and particularistic
demands and struggles often constitute an endemic constituent of the
social order.
Have not, it must be emphasized time and again, to come up to
this point, societies had a long way to go through civilizational development. It is this parcours that is discussed in the rst section of this
volume.
The historical trajectory
Looking at historical civilizations or using the civilizational perspective, we have said, is fruitful for analyzing macro-historical continuities.
However, it can also be productive for understanding major historical or cultural ruptures and breakthroughs (see Arnason, 2001).
Thus, for example, Eisenstadt employs this civilizational perspective
in order to depict what seems to him as two major turning-points in
the history of mankind, namely the discontinuities relating to the
axial age and the modern age. It is argued that these major historical ruptures were materialized by civilizations. Eisenstadts chapter
which opens the rst section of this volume denes what modernity
as a civilization means, and further chapters delve into its historical
trajectory.
Eisenstadt, who forged the notion of multiple modernities to
account for the diversity of forms that modernity can assume in
dierent settings, discusses the analytical links of the notion of civilization to modernity, pointing out, more particularly, the tensions
with which their interaction is fraught. In modernity, says Eisenstadt,
the premises of the social order are not taken for granted, as people are freed from permanent authority or tradition. Society and the
human experience are interpreted on the basis of a belief in autono-
introduction
introduction
10
project and modern life. The empirical actuality of these transformations substantiates the reality of multiple modernities which, in
turn, account for the multiplicity of globality. Colonialism, the rst
phase of globalization, ascertained new conceptual dichotomiesthe
primitive versus the modern, the Orient versus the Occident and the
New World versus the Old. Globalization then also implied cultural
homogenization of urban populationsfrom the nuclearization of
the family to parliamentarism, although (and this is the pluralization
dimension), consumption styles and institutional structures pertaining
to national legacies often retain an inuence that is antagonistic to
modernization. Conict may ensue between revivalist traditionalist
reactions and the hegemonizing tendencies of modernization. It is
then the case that globalization intensies the clash between traditional communitarianism and modernization, even though their
unavoidable cross-breeding also nourishes a creative hybridism of
innovative patterns that are neither traditional nor modern.
The lack of systematic order that is the outcome of these transformations as well as the awareness of basic diculties that characterize our era bring Alexander to insist on an additional aspect that
can be followed up to axiality. This aspect is directly bound to the
question of mundane-transcendental tensions which is important for
the further development toward modernity. According to him, the
dark spot in Axial Age theory is that it rests on the assumption that
human beings tolerate the tension without backing away, ignoring
Webers warning of evasions from the demands of this-worldly asceticismwhat Fromm called escapes from freedom. Freedom might
be too hard to support and Weber could see escapes from it in militarism and the enlisting after dangerous demagogues. Such patterns,
according to Weber, illustrate the diculty for individuals to remain
adepts of moral universalism. Unable to bear the anxiety entailed
by autonomy, egos may tend to split the world and to project the
causes of anxiety onto otherswhich is discussed by sociologists under
the title of social closure. This is further expressed in the fact that
every collectivity creates an inside and outside, which Durkheim
conceptualized as pure and impure. This problem that is bound to
antagonisms and transgressions can be seen as intrinsically pertaining to modernity. Even fragmentation that is so evident in contemporary social life, Alexander contends, is fuelled by the energetic
obsessions of this-worldly asceticism and by the drive to escape from
introduction
11
12
introduction
13
14
introduction
15
concept of axiality and the delving into the complexities of nationalism, researchers have come to reappraise religions role in the
emergence of the age of modernity. In fact, some aspects of the particularism of given versions of modernity are now related to the open
or latent inuence of religious codes conveyed by, and from within,
major civilizational aspectsincluding the patterns taken on by the
pluralism-versus-homogeneity dilemma.
Schluchter starts this section by focusing on Webers analysis of
ancient Judaism, one of the most important progeny of the axial
age. Weber contrasts Jews with Indian pariahs by speaking of a
voluntary, not imposed, ghetto existence; while, moreover, the Indian
performs caste duties with the prospect of promotion in a better
future life, Jews see themselves now as elected and understand
ritual exclusion as a manifestation of inner morality. An ethics of
conviction leading to an ethics of law brings Judaism to dene its
God as a personal transcendent creator. It was a crucial turning
point in Middle-Eastern and Western development because it supported religious rationalization in combination with prophecy. While
theocracy achieved supremacy, hand in hand with fossilization, the
Jesus movement, at rst an internal Jewish movement for renewal,
achieved independence before the Pauline mission granted it a worldhistorical signicance. Christianity, says Weber, was an urge towards
universalization as the hour of conception of Occidental citizenship.
This kind of analysis sees religious developmentslike that from
Judaism to Christianitynot as obstacles to the evolution of modernity, but rather as preconditions for this development. Tiryakian continues this discussion by turning to thirteenth-century Occitan-speaking
Southern France. This area was then an urban, commercial and
quite wealthy region, characterized by a social hierarchy that was
less rigid than the feudal North, greater political participation of local
notables, and a relatively liberal spirit. Catholicism was predominant
but religious pluralism was strong as well. A center of Catharism
and its Albigensian sect which stood for dualist transcendental visions
and rejected monotheism, challenged the established Church. The
Albigensians were led by spiritual leaders while among the other new
movements advocating the return to the original ideals of the church,
one noted the importance of the Waldensians who preached
voluntary poverty. The Franciscans also preached similar values, but
remained attached to the Church. It is the Albigensian Crusade organized by the papacy that crushed the heretics by reviving the
16
Inquisition. This was the end of Occitan pluralism, but from a comparative civilizational perspective, the episode hints that only the
repression of heresy prevented modernity from emerging centuries
before it did.
This analysis suggests that the enemy of modernity was not religion as such but rather intolerant religious policies and institutional
set-ups. Focusing on the Islamicate political culture in the medieval
age, Arjomand emphasizes a convergent tendency in the development
of Islamicate political culture. He points out the mutual accommodation of the Sharia and Greek and Perso-Indian sources. This
encounter introduced a dualism of political and religious power in
the normative order. Works on ethics and statecraft dominated the
political thought of the Ottoman, Safavid and Mogul empires. Aristotles
Politics and equivalent works were missing however, as were many
key Aristotelian concepts. They penetrated the Islamic world only
in the wake of modern constitutionalism in the nineteenth and twentieth centuries, and as the panacea of rulers and patrimonial-state
bureaucracies. This represented a missed opportunity to refashion
the political science of previous centuries in a democratic direction.
Failures of the Westernized state machinery, says the author, then
stirred up velleities to reassert the Islamic world view and reinstate
the Sharia in public life. The result was the reinvention of an Islamic
political tradition with no resemblance to the historical synthesis of
former centuries. Twentieth-century dispossessed traditional intellectuals formulated an Islamic counter-myth of their own against the
modernized state, obliterating the theory of the two powers on the
basis of an increasingly reied historical memory which decried
the menace of Islams suocation by Western cultural invasion. This
invented tradition blurs today the understanding of the prospects for
democracy in the contemporary Muslim world.
Focusing on today European society, Hervieu-Lgers analysis leads
to assessments that are not foreign to Tiryakians and Arjomands
concerns. She discusses religions relation to the shaping of social
reality from the viewpoint of contemporary Western Europe. Never,
she says, has denominational religion become eroded as much as at
the present time. The decline is steep, both in practice and traditional beliefs whereas one witnesses widespread individual do-it-yourself constructions of beliefs. Yet all European societies still carry the
marks of their particular and specic religious rootseven though
they are today extremely secularized. Up to now, major institu-
introduction
17
tions everywhere widely function by implicit reference to past religious models, while symbolic structures are still impregnated by them.
This is so, even though dissociation has taken place between politics and religion and the latter has been gradually pushed back into
the private sphere. What is new these days throughout a good part
of Europe, however, is that groups of newcomers who never shared
the original legacies of the veteran population weaken the reference
to Christian civilization. A cultural-religious pluralization has taken
place that is asserting a strong presence of Islam. This creates new
diculties on the road to integration that are widely accounted for
by both the political culture of Europes countries, and the varieties
of Islam brought by newcomers. The phenomena of internal cultural pluralization on the one hand and external cultural globalization on the other hand contribute simultaneously to the erosion, and
the partial and paradoxical recreation, of dierent religious civilizations in Europe. It is in this context that the pluralism-versus-homogeneity dilemma now requires new kinds of reference to religion.
The undeniable relation between religion, policies and societal
structures related to modernity and modernization is then presented
by Connos analysis of Eastern Orthodoxy. This Church has always
been a politicized ecclesiastical organization where, at least in the
Oriental-Empire version, the emperor was the head of the Church,
making it a part of the State structure. This state of aairs represented endemic tensions as by its very theogony, the Church aspired
to supremacy over the State. These tensions actually hindered the
Churchs drive toward hegemony over the State and facilitated its
submission. The Church never revolted against the State, despite its
autonomy and expansionism in the outside where it consisted of a
confederation of independent national churches united by common
dogma and regular ecumenical councils. This structural decentralization was bound to the use of local languages in liturgies, which
brought the Church closer to the people and separated the various
national churches from each other. This trend blurred the distinction
between church, state and nation.
To be sure, this particular form of relations between Church and
State is not alien to the versions of modernity witnessed in Russia
and Slavic Europe, on the one hand, and the Balkan countries,
on the other. We think here of both the institutional-structural
development of modernity in these areas and the relation of religion
to nationalism. Ben-Rafael focuses more particularly on this latter issue.
18
introduction
19
20
introduction
21
22
introduction
23
24
late 1990s, both democracy and the new economic policies were discredited. Though most citizens still support democracy, their trust
in the new system is decreasing, engendering institutional fragility,
as several countries on the continent went through economic disarray.
Democracy, it is true, still persists despite eventual outbreaks of
violence but security concerns are now expressed in tendencies to
seclusion along class and ethnic lines. Urban spaces become privatized, with groups refraining from entering each others neighborhoods. Accountability of the state and its institutions has eroded, and
while elections are being held, disenchantment with politicians is profound. Politicians have in fact revived clientelism and populism.
Seemingly, and according to the singularity of its own context and
basic orientations, Latin America is one more example of the importance of original codications of the social order in the unfolding of
social pluralism and group confrontations.
Martinelli brings us back to Europe by discussing the formation of
identity on this continent which, in recent decades, is undergoing
far-reaching transformation. His contention is that the basic elements
of the European culture make up a code that, although dierently
declined in geo-historical contingencies, identies a European-specic
character. Its central core is the opposing-complimentary relation of
rationalism and individualism. Another element is the nation-state
where the nation represents collective primordial goals, and the state
organized rationality. Democracy is still another component, and so
is the relation to Christianity which distinguishes the temporal from
the sacred. As a whole, these elementsloaded with inner contradictionsare not equally pervasive everywhere but are all relevant
to the making of European identity. This is not to deny that European
history has also been the source of aggressions and crimes, and in
this respect, contemporary European identity is necessarily an object
of reexive reassertion that must be built around a morally defensible project concerned with a multicultural future.
Epilogue: Modernity as program
The practice of pluralism in the context of civilizational diversity
explains how we can look at contemporary societies and at their
development, in a manner that leaves room for convergence across
civilizational spaces. Boudon proposes here an idea that sets in rela-
introduction
25
26
introduction
27
PART ONE
CHAPTER ONE
32
shmuel n. eisenstadt
II. In this analysis I shall follow James D. Faubions recent exposition of Webers conception of modernity:
Weber nds the existential threshold of modernity in a certain deconstruction: of what he speaks of as the ethical postulate that the world
is a God-ordained, and hence somehow a meaningfully and ethically
oriented cosmos.
What he assertswhat in any event might be extrapolated from his
assertionsis that the threshold of modernity has its epiphany precisely as the legitimacy of the postulate of a divinely preordained and
fated cosmos has its decline; that modernity emerges, that one or
another modernity can emerge, only as the legitimacy of the postulated cosmos ceases to be taken for granted and beyond reproach.
Countermoderns reject that reproach, believe in spite of it . . . One can
extract two theses: whatever else they may be, modernities in all their
variety are responses to the same existential problematic. The second:
whatever else they may be, modernities in all their variety are precisely those responses that leave the problematic in question intact,
that formulate visions of life and practice neither beyond, nor in denial
of it but rather within it, even in deference to it . . .2
Thus, the core of this program was rst that the premises and
legitimation of the social, ontological and political orders were no
longer taken for granted; second, that concomitantly there developed
within this program a very intensive reexivity around the basic ontological premises as well as around the bases of social and political
order of authority of societya reexivity which was shared even
by the most radical critics of this program, who in principle denied
the legitimacy of these premises. The second core of this program
was the quest for the emancipation of man from fetters of external authority or tradition, and the closely related naturalization
of the cosmos, man and society.
It is because of the fact that all the responses to the breakdown
of the traditional order leave the problematic intact, the reexivity
which developed in the program of modernity went beyond that
which crystallized in the Axial Civilizations. This reexivity focused
not only on the possibility of dierent interpretations of the transcendental visions and basic ontological conceptions prevalent in a
society or societies, but came to question the very givenness of such
33
3
4
34
shmuel n. eisenstadt
5
6
35
Eisenstadt, 1999b.
36
shmuel n. eisenstadt
guided by the various attempts to reconstitute the markers of certainty in the political arena grounded in utopian visionsvisions promulgated by various social activists, above all by the major social
movements that developed as an inherent component of the modern
political process.
Out of the combination of the transformation of the incorporation of symbols and demands of protest into the central symbolic
repertoire of society, and of the recognition of the legitimacy of multiple interests and of visions of social order, the continuous restructuring of center-periphery relations and of the reconstitution of the
realm of the political has become a central component of political
process and dynamics in modern societies. The various processes of
structural change and dislocation which took place continually in
modern societies as a result of the development of capitalism, of economic changes, urbanization, changes in the process of communication, and of the new political formations have led in modern
societies not only to the promulgation by dierent groups of various
concrete grievances and demands, but also to a growing quest for
participation in the broader social and political order and in the
central arenas thereofindeed in the reconstitution thereof.
These demands for participation in the center were closely
connected with the crystallization of the basic characteristics of the
modern political processesthe common denominator of which has
been the openness thereof. While these characteristics are naturally
most visible in open, democratic or pluralistic regimes, they are also
inherent in autocratic and totalitarian regimes even if the latter
attempt to regulate and control them in such a way as seemingly to
close them. The rst of these aspects of the political process in
modern societies, attesting to such openness, has been the emergence
of a new type of political class or classesand of new types of
political activistsa non-ascriptive class, the recruitment to which
was in principle, if not in fact, open to everybody. The second is
the continual attempts of that class or those classes and activists
to mobilize political support through open public contestations. The
third is the fact that such attempts at the mobilization of such support and governance are closely related to the promulgation of
dierent policies and their implementation. Fourth are the very strong
tendenciesunparalleled in any other regimes, with the possible, but
very partial, exception of some of the city-states of antiquityof
37
38
shmuel n. eisenstadt
39
40
shmuel n. eisenstadt
The basic antinomies of modernity constituted a radical transformation of those inherent in Axial civilizationsnamely, rst, those
focused on the awareness of a great range of possibilities of transcendental visions and of the range of ways of their possible implementation; second, on the tension between reason and revelation or
faith (or their equivalents in the non-monotheistic Axial civilizations);
and third, on the problmatique of the desirability of attempts at full
institutionalization of these visions in their pristine form.
The transformation of these antinomies and tensions in the cultural program of modernity focused rst on the evaluation of major
dimensions of human experience, and especially on the place of
reason in the construction of nature, of human society and human
history; and on the concomitant possible problem of the bases of
true morality and autonomy; second, or the tension between reexivity
and active construction of nature and society; third, between totalizing and pluralistic approaches to human life and the constitution
of society; and fourth, between control and autonomy, or discipline
and freedom.
The rst major tension that developed within the cultural program
of modernity was that with respect to the primacy or relative importance of dierent dimensions of human existence. This antinomy
focused on the evaluation of the relative importance, indeed predominance of reason as against the emotional and aesthetic dimension of human existence, often equated especially in the romantic
literature with various vital forces often seen as epitomizing the autonomy of human will, as well as with so-called primordial components
in the construction of collective identities. The emphasis on the emotional or expressivist dimension of human experience which could
nd its embodiment in the authenticity of community, while often
oriented against universalizing of perception of reason in the Enlightenment, yet shared with it the strong emphasis on the autonomy of
human will and activity inherent in the cultural program of modernity. Closely related were tensions between dierent conceptions of
the bases of human morality, especially whether such morality can
be based on or grounded in universal principles based above all in
reason, in instrumental rationality or in multiple rationalities; and/or
in multiple concrete experiences and traditions of dierent human
communities.
The second tension that developed within the cultural program of
modernity was that between dierent conceptions of human auto-
41
42
shmuel n. eisenstadt
identied as the major message of the Enlightenment and which subsumed value-rationality (Wertrationalitt) or substantive rationality under
instrumental rationality (Zweckrationalitt) in its technocratic mode or
under a totalizing moralistic utopian vision. In some cases, as for
instance in the Communist ideology, there may develop some combination of both the technocratic and the moralistic utopian visions
under one totalistic canopy. Concomitant tension between totalizing,
absolutizing as against more pluralistic tendencies developed also in
the denition of other dimensions of human experienceespecially
the emotional ones.
In all institutional arenas and arenas of cultural creativity there
developed tensions between emphasis on discipline with strong emphasis on guidance and regulation of the individual, as against autonomy and self-expression; between strong emphasis on clearly
structured, strict totalizing conceptions of man and relatively sharp
boundaries between dierent spheres of life and, on the other hand,
more multifaceted and open ones.
It was indeed this tensionbetween the view which accepts the
existence of dierent values, commitments and dierent rationalities;
of pluralistic multifaceted visions and practices as against the view
which conates such dierent values and rationalities in totalistic
ways, with strong tendencies to their absolutizationthat has been,
especially when combined with the other tensions, probably the most
critical from the point of view of the development of the dierent
cultural and institutional patterns of modernity, and of the possible
destructive potentialities thereof.
All these tensions, especially the one between the totalizing and
more pluralistic conceptions of constitution of human society, history
and nature and of the place of human agency in these constructions; between some type of an overarching logocentric, usually
some grand narrative and between a more pluralistic conception
of meaning of life and of the good society, and of constitution of
society, between emphases on dierent dimensions of human existence, between control and autonomy have existed from the very
beginning of the promulgation of the cultural program of modernity; and between the universalistic components of cultural program
of modernity and the traditions of the respective societies in which
it was institutionalized and they constituted continual components in
the continual far-reaching changes in the development of this program throughout modern history.
43
shmuel n. eisenstadt
44
13
14
Sombart, 1976.
Hartz, 1964.
45
of the great Axial civilizations and also the last to date. The crystallization of dierent modernities in the Americasa fact to which
Weber was very sensitive in his analysis of the North American (U.S.)
experienceattests that even within the broad framework of Western
civilizationhowever denedthere developed not just one but multiple cultural programs and institutional patterns of modernity.15 This
was of course even more so with respect to the institutional orders
that developed beyond the West.
VIII. One of the most interesting illustrations of the crystallization
of such distinct programs of modernity beyond the West is Japan.16
Japan provides indeed one of the most interesting case-studies, not
only from the point of view of the comparative study of modern
societies, but also from the more general point of view of the analytical and empirical distinctions between the structural and organizational, and the cultural dimensions of human activity in terms of
the pattern variables.
While in purely structural-organizational terms, modern Japanese
society developed strong achievement and universalistic criteria, yet
these criteria went together with a very strong immanentist orientation/setting and were embedded in the particularistic social setting
a combination which crystallized already in the Meiji restoration and
state.
The Japanese program of modernity ushered in by the Meiji
Restoration was rooted in the non-Axial, immanentist ontologies, and
it guided the crystallization of the Meiji state and later on the development of modern Japanese society, and shaped to some extent at
least the specic characteristics of the major institutional formations
of modern Japan. These formations were not grounded in the conceptions of principled, metaphysical individualism or in a principled
confrontation between state and society as two distinct ontological
entities. One of the most important such characteristics was the strong
tendency to the conation of the national community, of the state
and of society. Such conation has had several repercussions on the
structuring of the ground rules of the political arena, the most important of which have been the development, rst of a weak concept
15
16
shmuel n. eisenstadt
46
Ibid.
47
48
shmuel n. eisenstadt
18
49
19
Eisenstadt, Kahane and Shulman (eds.), 1984; Eisenstadt and Hartman, 1997,
pp. 2755; Hensen, 1999.
50
shmuel n. eisenstadt
systems or frameworks in the wake of military political and economic expansion were not of course by themselves new in the history
of mankind, especially in the history of the great civilizations. What
was new in the modern era was rst that the great technological
advances and the dynamics of modern economic and political forces
made this expansionthe changes and developments attendant on
them and their impact on the societies to which it expandedfar
more intensive. The expansion of modern civilization which took
place rst in Europe and then beyond it continually combined economic, political, and ideological aspects and forces, and its impact
on the societies to which it expanded was much more extensive and
intensive alike than in most historical cases. Accordingly the expansion of modernity evinced in comparison with other civilizations some
very distinct characteristics.
All of these frameworks were multi-centered and heterogeneous,
each generating its own dynamics, continual changes in constant
relation to the others. The interrelations among them have never
been static or unchanging, and the dynamics of these international
frameworks or settings gave rise to continuous changes in various
modern societies.
But it is only in conjunction with the specic cultural programs
of modernity as it crystallized rst in Europe and then expanded to
become continually interpreted throughout the world that the dynamics of these expansions and of the multiple worldwide systems can
be understood. The combination of military, political and economic
expansion with ideological vision rooted in distinct cultural programs
was not, of course, in itself new in the history of mankind. It has
indeed been characteristic of all Great Religions, of the Axial Civilizations,to some extent of the Jewish one, above all of the Christian,
Islamic or Confucian and to some extent also of the Buddhist ones.
It was also characteristic of the Hellenistic and Roman Empires. But
the cultural program of modernity, as it crystallized rst in Western
Europe from around the seventeenth century was characterized by
specic ideological features which entailed some very distinct institutional implications, which are of crucial importance for the understanding of the dynamics of modernity and its expansion. Of crucial
importance in this context is the fact that its basic modernity
crystallized out of the dynamics of Western and European Christian
civilization and societies and that the expansion of modernity entailed
its continual impingement on other great civilizations, among them
51
52
shmuel n. eisenstadt
elitesespecially their autonomy as against being embedded in various particularistic groups, the ontological visions promulgated by
them, and the relations between such elites and between them and
the broader onethat were of crucial importance.
A reassessment of the relations between structural and cultural dimensions
of modernity
XII. This basic fact that modernity did not develop in a uniform
way but in multiple, continually changing patternsmanifest in
dierent types of national and revolutionary states, and later on in
the contemporary era in multiple new patterns, calls for a close reexamination of some of the assumptions of the classical theories of
modernization, especially of the relations between the structural, institutional and cultural dimensions of modernity.
In the classical theories of modernization of 50s and 60s of the
twentieth century, it was the trend to continual structural dierentiation
and the concomitant development of distinct institutional arenas
the economic, the political, the cultural and the likethat were
often seen as the major institutional core of modernity.
There can be no doubt that processes of structural dierentiation
so strongly emphasized by many of the classics of sociologySpencer,
Durkheim, and later on in the classical theories of modernization of
the 50s and 60s of the twentieth century, constitute a basic component of the modern developments. It is, of course, true that the
concrete institutional context of the crystallization and development
of modernitythat of the initial phase of the development of capitalism, rst mercantile then industrial capitalism, and of their continual expansion involved continually increasing structural dierentiation
and the development of the attendant potentialities, to follow Karl
Deutschs nomenclature, for growing social mobilization.20
The crystallization of the cultural program of modernity, of the
distinct mode of interpretation of the world and of the attempts to
institutionalize it in new patterns, was indeed closely connected historically with the distinct structural-institutional dimensions of modern societiesabove all with the decomposition of olderpreviously
20
53
54
shmuel n. eisenstadt
or totalitarian ones and the dierent components of the modern cultural program.
The same is even more true with respect to the relation between
the cultural and structural dimensions of modernity. A very strong
even if implicitassumption of the studies of modernization was that
the cultural dimensions or aspects of modernizationthe basic cultural premises of Western modernityare inherently and necessarily
interwoven with the structural ones, became highly questionable. The
actual developments in these societies have gone far beyond the
homogenizing and hegemonic dimensions of the original cultural program of modernity. While the dierent dimensions of the original
Western project have indeed constituted the crucial startingand
continual referencefor the processes that developed among dierent
societies throughout the world, yet those processes did not simply
copy, as it were, the Western patterns.
XIII. Each of these dimensions or aspects of modernity, of modern
societiesthe structural, the institutional and the cultural onesare
analytically distinct, and they come together in dierent ways in
dierent historical constellations coalescing in dierent ways in dierent
historical contexts. Moreover, in one historical casethat of Tokugawa
Japanthere developed many institutional, especially economic formations which could have perhaps led to modern market capitalist
economy, without a concomitant development of a distinct cultural
program of modernity (Randall Collins);21 and it was only under the
impact of the West that such a programindeed of a very distinct
typedeveloped.
These dierent modes of modern institutional order were greatly
inuenced among other factors by the dierent ways in which the
basic civilizational premises of modernity were interpreted within
those societiesor in other words, these modes were greatly inuenced
by the dierent interpretations of the central core of modernityof
the cultural program of modernity, very often constituting in each
society foci of contestation.
It is through the interweaving of such distinct institutional constellations with the dierent dimensions or components of the new
mode of interpretation of the world, of the cultural program of
21
55
22
Giddens and Held, 1982; Schumpeter, 1991; Furet, 1982; Furet and Ozouf,
1989; Joas, 1996, pp. 1327.
56
shmuel n. eisenstadt
CHAPTER TWO
1
2
58
johann p. arnason
on the two latter themes; but the discussion will then shift to a recent
interpretation which exemplies the broader context of historical and
sociological reection, as well as the specic issues of axiality and
its long-term-transformative logic.
The problem of the Axial Agemore precisely: the question
whether we should speak of it as a distinctive and formative historical periodcan now, as a result of scholarly work in several interrelated elds, be posed with greater precision than in the rst stages
of the debate. The chronological setting can only be dened in broad
and exible terms: some earlier writers placed particular emphasis
on the sixth century bce, but it now seems clear that comparative
analyses of the Axial Age must deal with several centuries around
the middle of the last millennium bce.3 During this period, there
was undeniablyto quote an author who takes a skeptical view of
traditional approachesa certain cumulation4 of innovative changes
to the cultural traditions of major civilizational centres, from Ancient
Greece to Ancient China. Even this minimalist version of the axial
thesis calls for some qualications. Growing knowledge of early civilizations has brought to light trends and episodes that pregured the
more decisive (or at least conventionally acknowledged) achievements
of the Axial Age. So far, however, this line of research is very unequally developed, and it seems unlikely that a balanced picture
will ever be possible. Among the crucial cases, the Egyptian tradition is better known than its Mesopotamian counterpart; but the
available evidence would still seem to allow for further progress on
the latter side. As for the archaic backgrounds to Indian and Chinese
transformations, the record is more elusive, the attempts at reconstruction more speculative and the prospects for further work more
limited. But given the nature of the sources, the Chinese experience
seems somewhat more accessible than the Indian one.5 Finally, there
are historical borderline cases that may never be settled: in particular, it is still an open question whether the beginning of the
Zoroastrian tradition should be ranked among the most momentous
3
For otherwise very dierent examples of emphasis on the sixth century BCE,
see Burckhardt, 1978 (rst published posthumously in 1905), who refers (p. 8) to a
religious movement of the sixth century BC, from China to Ionia; and Nehru,
1936.
4
Assmann, 2000, p. 291.
5
For a recent interpretation of the Chinese evidence, see Pines, 2002.
59
archaic innovations or included in the Axial Age. There is no consensus on the chronology, but growing support for a date in the
early last millennium bce (at least among some scholars) may have
strengthened the latter view.
To sum up, the chronological demarcation of the Axial Age is
bound to be uid and contested, even more so in some cases than
others, and more work on its prehistory is likely to raise new questions about its claims to exceptional signicance. But if we accept
that there are stillon balancegood reasons to regard the period
in question as a prima facie challenging problem for comparative history, the next step is to consider the specic meaning and long-term
logic of the changes that seem to have taken place in dierent but
similarly formative settings. All interpretations of the Axial Age have
centred on cultural (more specically religious or intellectual) breakthroughs of such epoch-making dimensions that they could not nd
adequate expression in any simultaneous structural changes. Without
entering into the debate between rival theories, a provisional phenomenological view would suggest that axial transformations aect
the position and the possible role of cultural patterns within the
social-historical world. New cultural orientations lend themselves to
more varied social uses: they provide social frameworks for justication
on one side and protest on the other, as well as for more detached
forms of intellectual life. These innovations presuppose new and
more complex ways of articulating the world, whether the primary
cultural impetus to that shift comes from religion or philosophy, or
from a mode of thought that cuts across conventional distinctions
between them. Changes to the relationship between culture and
society are reected on the level of social structures: most obviously,
intellectuals as a social group can play a more important role, both
directly and through interaction with a broader eld of social forces.
Finally, the earliest modern attempts to re-envision the Axial Age
made much of exemplary individualsprophets and thinkerswho
for the rst time appeared as creators of meaning in history. But
although the images of charismatic founders cannot be dismissed out
of hand, we must nowon the basis of better insight into the mechanisms of tradition-buildingallow for retrospective individualization.
The question of substantive parallels or anities between the various transformations isas will be seena very dicult and still
hotly debated one. But even the most cautious view of the evidence
will, at this stage, admit the striking fact of roughly simultaneous
johann p. arnason
60
61
Ibid., p. 115.
62
johann p. arnason
63
Axial Age and its legacies faces another set of problems. The historiographical division of labour has, on the whole, not favoured systematic study of the interconnections between ideas and institutions.
As for the dierent civilizational complexes in question, scholarly
work on their respective dynamics and trajectories is very unequally
developed. Last but not least, the original formulations of the whole
problematic were one-sidedly and inevitably Eurocentric, and although
signicant steps have been taken to correct this bias, there is no
denying the need for more sustained work from non-European perspectives. This is an uphill task, and the persistence of Eurocentrism
is not the only obstacle to progress. For all these reasons, interpretations of the Axial Ageseen as a formative phase of world historymust translate into long-term research programmes, open to
adjustment and revision of basic assumptions. But in that context,
strong hypotheses with a speculative thrustprospecting a eld to
be further explored by comparative historycan be useful: they may
sensitize us to dimensions and implications that would otherwise go
unnoticed. Rearmations of speculative views might even help to
avert the danger of fragmentation into case studies without a connecting project.
Gauchets interpretation of the Axial Age
With the problematic of ideas and institutions, the focus of the discussion shifts towards historical sociology. Eisenstadts work on the
Axial Age and its civilizational paradigms is the rst systematic formulation of that perspective. More precisely, it translates ideas originally developed within the philosophy of history into the language
of historical sociology and integrates them into a theoretical framework for the comparative analysis of civilizations. Eisenstadts model
links the cultural logic of world-views to the dynamics of institutional
formations, the strategic action of political and cultural elites, and
the transformative eects of social conict. This reorientation of the
debate represents a decisive and denitive achievement, even if the
more specic claims attached to it can be questioned; it seems clear
that both the transformations of world-views and the new direction
of social change were more diverse than Eisenstadt was at rst inclined
to think, but these issuesand others related to themcan be discussed within the general historical-sociological framework. They are,
64
johann p. arnason
8
For a more detailed discussion, see Eisenstadts Concluding statement in
Arnason et al., Axial Civilizations and World History, and the last section of my article in the same book.
65
66
johann p. arnason
10
Gauchets main works are as follows: Le dsenchantement du monde, 1987 (English
translation: The Disenchantment of the World ); La rvolution des droits humains, 1989; La
rvolution des pouvoirs, 1996; La dmocratie contre elle-mme, 2001; La condition historique,
2003.
11
I follow English usage in referring to primitive religions. But it should be
noted that Gauchet has strong reservations about the term primitive. It suggests
that we are dealing with religions or societies closer to the natural origins of humanity. In his view, this is an illusion.
12
Gauchet, 1997, p. 9.
67
core13 of religion is more fully present and more adequately embodied in primitive forms than in the historical ones. This stronger
emphasis reects a more fundamental underlying dierence. Gauchet
equates primitive religion with radical dispossession, where the
foundation was considered to be wholly other.14 Such an understanding is not totally alien to the Elementary Forms, but certainly not
fully translatable into Durkheims language. It presupposes a vision
of history and a phenomenology of the human condition, neither of
which is easily adapted to classical sociology.
For Gauchet, it is an anthropological fact of the most fundamental
kind that humanity entered history (at least the history that we can
know) by denying its capacity to create history.15 This initial self
suppression of human creativity is, as he argues, an intelligible but
not predetermined response to the ambiguous human experience of
time: our perception is divided between an always already there,
which reduces us to nothing, and a yet to be realized, which throws
us into the wide open space of action. On the one hand, we always
arrive on the scene after things have been determined, so we have
no grasp of them and have no choice but to comply with their rules
in order to become part of and lose ourselves in them. On the other
hand, we nd ourselves thrown into the world as originating beings
for whom there is no before, which is why we are beings of action
who cannot avoid changing ourselves and our surroundings, even
when we try desperately not to, as we have done for the greatest
part of our history.16
The socio-cultural regime conforms to the rst aspect of this experience and strives to minimize. The second is a choice, in roughly
the same sense that Marcel Mauss used to describe civilizational
alternatives: it is contingent in the sense that no causal chain can
explain its logic, but it is based on pre-given possibilities and develops them into a coherent pattern. Its dening feature is the acceptance of absolute dependence on a mythical past. The socio-cultural
order, embedded in a cosmic one, appears as a creation of ancestors who accomplished their work in another time, and whose legacy
13
14
15
16
Ibid.,
Ibid.,
Ibid.,
Ibid.,
p.
p.
p.
p.
9.
23.
15.
11.
johann p. arnason
68
17
18
Ibid., p. 13.
Ibid., p. 33.
69
19
20
21
Ibid., p. 37.
Ibid., p. 39.
Ibid., p. 40.
johann p. arnason
70
the ultimate unication of the world under the authority of the most
powerful, is latent in the narrower form of domination.22 This is
the rst encounter with the promises and challenges of universality,
and it has the potential to transform the whole range of human relationships, identities and beliefs.
Hierarchy and subversion, power and subjectivity, conquest and
universality: in all three respects, the early state thus appears as a
motor of momentous and potentially divergent changes. It simultaneously rearms and undermines a cultural model of social order.
Gauchet develops this argument in very general terms, without
reference to particular cases. Moreover, his strong emphasis on the
problematic of statehood as such and on it relevance to pre-literate
polities (such as the African states) tends to obscure the specic importance of early civilizations. It is worth pausing to consider the implications of the model for the historical examples most closely related
to our topic: the civilizations of the Ancient Near East. In light of
Gauchets analysis, they would seem to represent creative and elaborate compromises, resilient but certainly not crisis-proof, between
archaic visions of order and innovations generated through their
implementation in an altered context. Episodes of signicant but contained or abortive change might be understood as expressions of the
underlying tensions. The very brief breakthrough of monotheism in
Ancient Egypt is a case in point. It is less clear whether there was
any comparable upset to the Mesopotamian tradition, but the Epic
of Gilgamesh reects an early concern with the human predicament
in a theocentric world; this exploration of ultimate limits and faultiness was preserved as a literary monument, not as a source of interpretive variations. At another level, the tension between early state
particularism and the aspirations to universal rule is most evident in
the history of Assyria, the rst city-state that became a regional
empire.
Gauchets line of argument is thus easily extended to more concrete cases. But the main topic to be discussed here is its bearing
on the Axial Age. The latter is dened very broadly: Gauchet refers
to the enormous groundswell, which over several centuries (from
approximately 800 to 200 bc) swept from Persia to China, from
22
Ibid., p. 41.
71
23
24
Ibid., p. 44.
Ibid., p. 44.
johann p. arnason
72
during the spiritual upsurge of the axial age.25 The anity with
Jasperss interpretation is obvious, and it is further underlined by
remarks on the principle of individuality as another invention of the
Axial Age: in the double sense of creative individuals opening up
new horizons and the mobilizing appeal to individuality as inwardness. A more distinctive view emerges when Gauchet sums up the
meaning of the Axial Age as a metamorphosis of otherness.26
This metamorphosis responds to prior changes in the relationship
between religion and society, but at the same time, it opens up alternative possibilities of further innovations. The decisive step is a shift
from temporal to ontological otherness: the alignment of sacred
authority with political power had broken through the original
barrier between a foundational past and a derivative present. When
the axial breakthrough brings the implications of divine intervention
and involvement in history to the surface, the otherness that has lost
its mythical meaning is rearmed at the level of being. Gauchet
reserves the term transcendence for this new articulation of the
religious division between the visible and the invisible, which can
also be seen as a reunication of two dimensions that were initially
separate, the original and the actual, the inaugural institution and the
actually present forces of the invisible.27 Although the early state
had striven to preserve essential parts of an older religious imaginary,
the new role of a sacral transforming agent was in the long run
unsustainable without a redenition of ultimate authorizing forces.
But Gauchet rejects the idea that the turn to transcendence could
be explained in terms of a search for legitimization. Rather, the
radical transformation of the social world triggers a corresponding
but neither instant nor unambiguousrestructuring of the religious
universe. The separation of the here-below from the beyond makes
it possible to glorify and justify power in new ways, but it also opens
up a whole new dimension of reection, questioning and imagination that can never be brought under complete control. There is, in
other words, a general shift towards a new logic of religious life and
thought, going far beyond the institutional interconnections of religion and politics. At its most radical, the reorientation can lead to
the constitution of a realm of faith, as distinct from the realm of
25
26
27
Ibid., p. 44.
Ibid., p. 46.
Ibid., p. 52.
73
28
29
Ibid., p. 47.
Ibid., p. 48.
johann p. arnason
74
30
Ibid., p. 147.
75
Critical reections
Gauchets detailed analysis of Christianitythe religion of incarnation and interpretationand its key role in laying the foundations
for the modern world is beyond the scope of this paper. The focus is
on his interpretation of the Axial Age; to conclude, I will reconsider
its main points and single out some major strengths and weaknesses.
The discussion should begin with the emergence of the state. There
are good reasons (and Gauchet has summed them up very convincingly) to regard the state as the most momentous innovation and
the most radical transforming agent among the forces and phenomena
commonly taken to mark the origins of civilization. Gauchet is also
right to insist on the ambiguous implications of this transition to a
new form of social life. The subordination of society to a separate
power centre is accompanied by an upgrading of human agency on
the part of the rulers. At the same time, the transformative ramications
of the new order are minimized by attaching it to pre-existing sacred
foundations. It is at least a plausible hypothesis that the tensions thus
built into the stateas a power structure and a symbolic constellationtranslate into long-term dynamics. Our perceptions of the Axial
Age are bound to change when these aspects of its prehistory are
given their due. In particular, we cannot see the intellectual and religious transformations in question as breaks with a previously undisturbed continuity. Early states and their cultural elites already faced
the task of balancing or reconciling continuity and discontinuity. The
cultures of the Axial Age had to re-open that question, and even if
we have some reservations about Gauchets account of the relationship between philosophy and religion, we can accept that the
creative eorts and achievements were not all on the side of discontinuity: they also included rearticulations of inherited traditions
in new contexts. Varying mixtures of these two trends left their mark
on the cultural legacies of the Axial Age. To stress this pervasive
but unequally developed ambiguity is, of course, to cast doubt on
constructions that subsume the new beginnings of the Axial Age
under a uniform and unequivocal logic; and by the same token, it
becomes more dicult to shift from the idea of the Axial Age as
a historical period to an analytical model or a typology of axial
civilizations.
In short, Gauchets analysis of the background to the Axial Age
has some obvious merits. But there is a rub: his reconstruction of
76
johann p. arnason
the cultural logic inherent in early statehood takes an uncompromisingly universalist turn and seems to disregard the evidence of
diversity. More specically, Gauchet stresses the sacral aspect of the
state and treats it as an invariant factor; there is no discussion of
divergent trends or alternative forms. The main point at issue is the
relationship between kingship and priesthood. It would be thoroughly
misleading to interpret it as a matter of secular and sacred power,
interdependent but also prone to rivalry: both sides are actively
involved in and structurally dependent on the relocation of the sacred
into history. But the dierence reects the underlying problematic
of the shift. The tensions are not wholly deected to the level of
long-term processes; they nd a more direct expression in two faces
of power, both embedded in sacral contexts, but not in the same
fashion.
The dierence between kingship and priesthood, as well as the
dierent ways in which it is dened and institutionalized, could therefore be taken as starting-points for more comparative approaches to
early states. This diversifying factor also highlights the contingent
character of key developments (not that Gauchet denies contingency,
but his strong emphasis on dominant dynamics tends to limits its
importance). Max Weber alluded to this in a brief aside, but did
not take it further: he suggested that Indian and Chinese traditions
might exemplify the lasting consequences of early and accidental
shifts in the balance between royal and priestly power. A brief look
at a broader range of cases may bring the problem into clearer focus.
Among early civilizations, Ancient Egypt stands out as the extreme
example of not merely sacred, but divine kingship. But even this
exceptionally long-lived and self-contained power structure had to
cope with tensions between kings and priests, and the brief but spectacular turn to monotheism would seem to have been an ambitious
rulers response to that problem, The origins of the Mesopotamian
political tradition are still a matter of debate, but even if the idea
of an early temple-state has to be toned down, it seems clear that
the power of the temples always set limits to the scope and status
of kingship, and that this institutional pattern was linked to a selflimiting symbolism of kingship: contrary to Egypt, the king could
not claim divine status (an abortive move in that direction under
the rst Mesopotamian empire had no noteworthy eects).
The Egyptian and Mesopotamian models of kingship were associated with dierent types of statehood: Egypt emerged into history
77
78
johann p. arnason
kings two bodies: the mortal exterior and the sacred essence). An
earlier variant of sacred rulership, more distant from the two main
centres and much less denable on the basis of available evidence,
had emerged in Minoan Crete; it is interesting both in its own right
and as a predecessor to Mycenaean and post-Mycenaean Greece. In
short, even a brief glance at the spectrum of archaic civilizations
in the most innovative and multi-central regionshows the range of
diversity compatible with the shared pattern of sacral statehood. The
problems posed by the entanglement of the gods in history, to
paraphrase Gauchets formulation, are reected in historical dynamics and managed (rather than solved) in ways that translate into
divergent developmental paths. If the transformations of the Axial
Age are see in light of this eventful prehistory, rather than against
the background of a supposedly uniform archaic world, some traditional views will have to be reconsidered. Gauchets notion of a
permanent containment, neutralizing the religious problematic of the
state from its beginnings to the onset of the Archaic Age, ismutatis
mutandisopen to the same objection as the interpretations that
posit an untroubled discontinuity of pre-axial world-views: it does
not do justice to the historicity of early civilizations.
But if we set out to contextualize the Axial Age, the long-term
perspective discussed above must be linked to a more specic historical conjuncture. A few centuries before the Axial Age (around
the twelfth century bce), the Near East and its Mediterranean margins experienced a massive upheaval which historians now know as
the crisis of the late Bronze Age. While the relationship between
external and internal factors (attacks from the periphery and decomposing power structures) is very unclear and disputed, the outcome
is easier to describe: some major cultural and political centres were
destroyed, those that survived were seriously weakened, and in the
long run, the crisis seems to have prompted a shift towards more
community-related forms of statehood. In this de-centred and destructured world, there was more scope for innovative developments
in peripheral contexts, and the most momentous changes of that
kind occurred in the two places that became primary sources of
Western axiality, Ancient Greece and Ancient Israel. If we compare
the elusive but unmistakably signicant Near Eastern episode to
events in other regions that were to undergo major transformations
in the Axial Age, we rst encounter a case of the contingent parallelism that often provides an anchor for comparative inquiry. At
79
roughly the same time (the turn of the twelfth and eleventh centuries bce), the Shang kingdomlater included in the list of Chinas
ruling dynastieswas conquered by a peripheral and previously subordinate state; the victors went on to found the Zhou dynasty. Up
to that point, there is a Chinese parallel to the crisis of the late
Bronze Age. It is less clear whether the underlying structural factors
are comparablehistorians do not seem to have discussed this at
great length. But in contrast to the Near East, the result seems to
have been a very constructive takeover of the centre by the periphery. The new Zhou rulers built on Shang foundations and added
new elements; the combination had a very lasting and formative
impact on the later trajectory of Chinese history. As for the other
major axial site east of Iran, the Indian case is very dierent from
both China and the Near East, and it is much harder to construct
a coherent picture. An early, distinctive andat its most mature
very far-ung civilization collapsed long before the crises of the late
Bronze Age, and it was not until much later that invaders from
Inner Eurasia set Indian history on a new course (the idea that an
Aryan invasion destroyed the Indus civilization has been completely
abandoned). The discontinuity between the whole archaic phase and
the prelude to the Axial Age is much more marked than elsewhere.
The two sides of the historical contexttraditions and conjuncturesare intertwined, and the connection is best understood in
relation to the problematic of sacred rulership and its metamorphoses. The Near Eastern crisis resulted in what Jean-Pierre Vernant
called a crisis of sovereignty, most acutely felt on the periphery.
Vernants analyses show how important this aspect of post-Mycenaean
Greece was for the formation of the polis and the new direction taken
by Greek thought. Jan Assmanns interpretation of Ancient Israel
also suggests a crisis of sovereignty, but with a very dierent outcome: sovereignty is transferred from the king to a lawgiving god.
In more general terms, the shared background to Greek and Jewish
axiality was a regional setback to sacred kingship and a corresponding
opening of perspectives that could be articulated in dierent ways
in dierent settings. In China, the transition from Shang to Zhou
does not seem to have involved a crisis of sovereignty; rather, the
conquering elite redened sovereignty in a way that preserved the
essentials of sacred kingship but translated its core idea into a new
language that lent itself to further rationalization. The notion of a
mandate from heaven goes back to the beginning of Zhou rule, and
80
johann p. arnason
32
81
tive horizons. Whether it leads to an armation of ontological transcendence, in the more specic sense of a distinction between ultimate
and mundane realities, is another question. It did so, most clearly
and momentously, in the case of the Jewish turn towards monotheism. But it could also nd expression in an attempt to reintegrate a
fragmented world, and to draw on correspondingly reworked older
traditions for this purpose. This was the dominant trend in China.
As suggested above, the historical-sociological analysis of the Axial
Age must allow for dierentiations of that kind. But here we must
abstain from further discussion of details.
CHAPTER THREE
84
bjrn wittrock
questions of meaning in history, namely those that we may associate with classical historicism, with modern speech-act theory, and
with postmodernist radical constructivism. I shall briey indicate
where I believe some implications of an historical sociology in the
tradition of S.N. Eisenstadt hold particular promise in this respect.
The cultural constitution of modernity
Both social scientists and social historians have tended to cast the
constitution of modernity in terms of dual, interlinked, transformations
in socio-economic and political practices. Terms such the industrial revolution and the democratic revolution and are just two
examples of this type of conceptualisation which ranges from functionalist ways of theorising to Weberian and Marxian ones. What
they have in common is a disregard for the fact that the formation
of modernity also involved a profound change in the nature of discursive practices. These discursive transformations were not mere
ideological epiphenomena. Rather, deep-seated epistemic and ontological ruptures; redenitions opened up new horizons of expectations and hopes. These shifts made possible or, more literally,
conceivable, if only as projects and imaginations, new institutional
practices.
The works of Reinhart Koselleck have played a pioneering role
in enabling accounts that emphasis that the formation of modernity
can not be reduced to the processes of transformation in political
and economic practices that are referred to by terms such as the
to use, once again, Parsons terminologythe democratic revolution and the industrial revolution. Instead it has to be located
within the context of a deep epistemic and cultural shift as well. For
Koselleck, contrary to Parsons and a number of earlier scholars, the
French revolution per se is a symptom rather than a cause of the
arrival of new expectations and new imaginations of temporality, of
the sense of co-temporality of the non-co-temporal, die Gleichzeitigkeit
des Ungleichzeitigen. In the new era the simultaneous existence of
phenomena, that in an earlier era would have appeared so dierent
as to be conceivable only at historical points separated by vast
expanses in time, is a prominent feature (Koselleck 1985: 88 ). In
this sense the French revolution did not oer anything substantially
new but entailed an acceleration, a Beschleunigung, of the passage of
85
historical time so as to engender precisely this new sense of co-temporality of historical dierence. One may add that Kosellecks analysis of the European revolutions of 1848/49 emphasizes that the
distinguishing innovative feature of them was not their substantive
nature but rather their almost instantaneous spatial diusion across
most of Europe (Koselleck 1989).
In recent years one may, apart from the many contributions by
conceptual historians proper, also speak of something of a school of
new historical sociologists, such Johann Arnason, Johan Heilbron,
Hans Joas, and Peter Wagner, who trace historical interactions of
ideational and macro-institutional transformations far beyond what
has been customary among proponents of historical institutionalism
in the social sciences. They and others have also explored the extent
to which the rise of the social sciences themselves must be cast in
terms of the fundamental transformation of European societies that
the formation of modernity entailed. In the late eighteenth and early
nineteenth centuries natural philosophy gradually gave way to a range
of natural science disciplines. Analogously, moral philosophy was
slowly transformed into a range of separate discourses. In the course
of the nineteenth century these discourses came to distinguish themselves both from natural science and from literary discourse and
came to label themselves social sciences. In this process of an epistemic sea change, historical reasoning, which had formed a central
component of moral philosophy, came to form a discursive realm
of its own, separate from philosophy and separate from the social
sciences.1
One shift in intellectual and cultural transformation in this period
pertains precisely to the concepts of society and history and to the
new awareness of the structural and constraining nature of societal
life. Pierre Manent has put forward the notion that society is a
postrevolutionary discovery. True enough, and as is convincingly
demonstrated by Keith Baker, the term society undergoes a long
conceptual development in the French context in the course of the
seventeenth and eighteenth centurieswith a dramatic increase in
the utilisation of the term in the mid-eighteenth century. It is also
true that, in his critique of Louis Dumonts analysis of Western
1
See, e.g., Heilbron (1995), Heilbron, Magnusson and Wittrock (1998), but also
Brian (1994), Fox, Porter and Wokler (1995), Lepenies (1988), and Wokler (1987).
86
bjrn wittrock
Johan Heilbron has pursued an inquiry into the constitution of individual interests (Heilbron 1995). In the course of the seventeenth
and eighteenth centuries, such interests were conceived as amenable
to the constraints of various notions of sociability. In particular, given
a human condition short of true religious virtue, was there a prospect
for a human existence beyond the borders of a Leviathan-like imposition of absolute order that would involve socially acceptable outcomes of the pursuit of the self-interests of human beings? Such
inquiries were pursued in various ways in the dierent parts of Europe
throughout the late seventeenth and the eighteenth centuries. However,
Heilbron and many others today agree that, even if there is a long
process of gestation of the modern concept of society, the unique
event of revolutionary upheaval requires that discursive controversy
and political practice become joined in the formation of a distinctly
modern era. Pierre Manent has elaborated a similar argument: The
Revolution oered the original spectacle of a political change of
unheard-of scope, yet having no stable political eects, of a political
upheaval impossible to settle, of an interminable and indeterminate
event (Manent 1994, 82).
This description of the Revolution as an irreversible and interminable process of fundamental change was formulated, as pointed
out by Hans-Ulrich Wehler, perhaps most clearly by one of the most
well known thinkers of the nineteenth century, Alexis de Tocqueville.
In his memoirs, Souvenirs, written in the summer of 1850, he describes
the revolution as one long upheaval that our fathers have seen the
beginning of and which, in all likelihood, we shall not see the end
of. Everything that remained of the old regime was destroyed forever (Tocqueville 1964, 30).
87
88
bjrn wittrock
89
90
bjrn wittrock
91
Europe, the wave of demand associated with these ideas, what Parsons
referred to as the Democratic Revolution, was a constant feature of
political life from the late 18th to the mid 20th century when they
were nally victorious across the board. In political terms it had
entailed the gradual limitation of constitutional monarchical regimes
and their eventual replacement by some form of parliamentary
democracy.
In the private sphere, there were parallel developments which basically entailed that age-old demands that princely rulers abstain from
acts of arbitrary intervention and violence be superseded by demands
that there be a legal-rational basis for all actions of government.
Thus ocial acts are legitimate only if they are based on legal rules
that are transparent and allow for consequences of actions to be predictable. Such transparency and predictability can become a reality
only if the nature of political order accepts the rule of law as a basic
principle rather than the volition of the princely ruler as its basic
principle of operation. Such demands not only for legal protection
but also for the universal application of legal order had long traditions in somebut by no means allEuropean countries. At the
turn of the 18th century, however, they were voiced with increasing
intensity. Furthermore their urgency was reinforced by the demands
of new commercial and industrial activities.
New public spheres also emerged outside of courts, academies and
salons, outside of the control and purview of royally sanction and
control. Whether in scholarly, political or artistic life, fora are created that are based on the idea that public discourse should not be
subject to persecution or censorship but rather be able to express
an opinion on all aspects of political and public life. One may say
that they were premised on the legitimate articulation of a discourse
not only about but addressed to and critical of the ocial power of
the state.
In what sense do these dierent institutional projects constitute a
societal form that we may associate with the notion of modernity?
Clearly it would be misleading to suggest that these projects became
universally realised in the European context at the time of their intellectual conception. Nothing could be further from the truth. Instead
the new institutional projects remained embattled and highly controversial in practical aairs in Europe throughout the following
century and a half. Even in Western Europe, a modern political order
in terms of truly universal surage did not become a full institutional
92
bjrn wittrock
reality until the end of the Second World War. Despite these facts,
however, it is still possible to speak in a meaningful way of modernity and its institutional projects as a societal reality in a specic
sense of the word, namely as a new set of promissory notes. These
promissory notes, formulated and promulgated and even partially
implemented, if for brief periods of time, at the turn of the 18th
century, came to have global relevance. At their core were notions
of self-reexivity, agency and historical consciousness. These institutional projects became the object of continuous discursive and institutional battles. However, they could never again be exorcised from
the attention of such battles in the European context.
The Vienna Congress and the Holy Alliance was a comprehensive eort to unthink the consequences of the French Revolution
and to restore the Old Regime and make Europe safe for tradition.
It became almost immediately clear that this program was an unrealisable one. Even the political thought of the pro-resurrection forces
in France found it impossible to return to the intellectual landscape
of pre-Revolutionary France.
The new institutional projects, whether they were adopted or, as
was initially often enough the case, rejected, became inevitable reference points on a truly global scale. The history of European dominance and colonialism in the nineteenth and early twentieth centuries
is largely the history of gross violations of promissory notes of the
institutional projects of modernity. The twentieth century includes
histories of horrors of war and of not only traditionally authoritarian
regimes but also state terrorism on a vast scale. These experiences
indicate that a purely structural analysis of modernity is insucient.
The institutional structures of modernity were and are by their own
inhabitants interpretedand this is true not only of the victims but
also of some of the perpetrators of some of the worst massacres
in terms of normative commitments and entailments and would
remain inexplicable if the outside observer refused to pay attention
to this fact.
It is also this feature that makes it possible to talk about modernity without unduly imposing a rigid and misleading institutional
gridlock on an unwieldy and complex historical reality. Thus modernity is not equivalent with universal acclaim of a small set of philosophical principles or the endorsement and implementation of a few
crucial institutional projects. This also means that modernity can
possibly best be delineated in terms of a conjunction, with global
93
94
bjrn wittrock
these phenomena may have to do not just with the violence exercised by themthis seems to be little but another instance of the
kind of ruthless violence, performed without any qualms, with which
the twentieth century is repletebut rather the inkling of a fundamental challenge to precisely the cultural and cosmological presuppositions of modernity.
The conjunction of new epistemic and ontological presuppositions
and the range of institutional proposals put forth on the basis of
these presuppositions constitutewhat, in another context (Wittrock
2000), I have calledpromissory notes. Such promissory notes
form focal points for long-term processes of contestation and interpretation. In the course of such processes, they may travel in time
and space far beyond the imaginations and expectations of any of
the progenitors of the original shift. They entail a range of possible
societal states of aairs that were previouslyand literallynot conceivable but that can thereafter not be made, as it were, unthought.2
Discursive and cosmological shifts are not ideological reections;
they are necessary, but not sucient, for the constitution of new
institutional practices.
The notion of promissory notes alsoand as I have indicated
above argued at some extent in another context (Wittrock 2001)
provides a way to make sense of what is sometimes called cultural
trauma.3 This latter notion has been used to interpret experiences
of deep violations of human dignity. I believe the simplest, and perhaps the only, way to make the concept analytically meaningful outside of the realm of psychology is to limit its use to instances where
a fundamental and irreversible breach occurs of promissory notes
that have become constitutive of key practices. Such a breach means
that conceptually necessary assumptions inherent in the practice itself
are violated. In this sense such violations do not merely encroach
upon the integrity, or indeed the lives, of human beings, but bereave
them of the means to interpret and articulate their experiences of
those violations.
If a large group of citizens of a country, as occurred in countless
instances in the course of the twentieth century, are suddenly treated
95
by the authorities and by their neighbours not as citizens or compatriots but as enemies whose only redemption is death, then conceptually necessary components of citizenship have simply disappeared.
Similar violations may, incidentally, also occur in person-to-person
relationships. A child, who is molested by her or his own parent,
has not just been grossly violated but is bereft of a crucial experiential horizon by the parent taking away irreversibly from the child
a conceptually necessary component of the relationship between
parent and child.
If I am right, however, an analysis of cultural traumas presupposes an understanding of institutional practices. It presupposes an
understanding of the way in which promissory notes have become
constitutive of these practices. In particular for a theoretically and
historically orientated social science it is necessary to rethink the
formation of the key institutions of modernity and to understand the
outlines of the cultural constitution of modernity and not to shortcircuit such an analysis by way of going straight to a structuralinstitutional account.
A purely structural account will not be able to reect critically
upon its own foundations and will not be able to lend itself to a
comparative and historical analysis that is not just a conceptual imposition of the experiences of a particular region of the world. This, I
believe, is equally true whether the particular version of such a structural-institutional account is Parsonian, Weberian or, indeed, Marxian.
An analysis of the varieties of modernity in the contemporary world
must be culturally sensitive and open up for a dialogue across dierent
historical and civilisational legacies. The constitution of modernity
involved a process emanating at the North-Western edge of the
Eurasian hemisphere but with repercussions that came to have global
extension. In its core this process involved not just institutional changes
but new conceptualisations of the fundamental dimensions of human
existence. In this respect, the new understanding of the formation
of modernity that we may associate with contributions by conceptual historians also raises the question of the specic nature of modernity relative to other processes of deep-seated cultural crystallization
in global history.
96
bjrn wittrock
Modernity in global context
During the late eighteenth and early nineteenth centuries, the type
of critical historical reection on the European political experience
relative to that of other parts of the world, and in particular that of
East Asia and China and which was most closely associated with
Voltaire, but echoed also in Kants critique of European imposition
and in his appreciating comments on Chinese society, gradually disappeared. In its place came rst a distinctly Europe-centred conception of world history with Hegels lectures on the philosophy of
history as an emblematic expression. Later history emerged as an
academic discipline with its focus on the European experience of
the formation of a range of nation states.4 In its formative stage in
the early nineteenth century, in the foundational works of Ranke, the
main theme was the shaping of Europe through the conuence of
the cultural traditions of Latin and Germanic peoples. Later most
European historians would narrow their focus further and write
narratives about the trajectories of individual nations. Sometimes
these studies, as in majestic works at turn of the nineteenth century
by Meinecke and Hintze, had a strong comparative perspective;
sometimes their orientation was limited to the achievements of one
particular nation.
In the late nineteenth century, at a period in time when European
global pre-eminence was at its peak, history largely came to be a
scholarly exercise that served as a discursive parallel to the formation or reform of European nation states. The new investigations of
social conditions and the back side of processes of industrialisation,
urbanisation and modernisation were to become institutionally embedded, if in a slow and uneven process, in the research-orientated universities and other new higher education institutions.5 They formed
an analogous parallel to the eorts of those nation states to cope
with the social question. Thus the relationship of the new social
sciences to an historical conception, other than that, which took the
life of a given nation state as its starting point, could not be but a
4
The argument about that the formation of modernity entailed that a universalistic commimtent inherent in the Enlightenment was abandoned has in recent
years been pursued perhaps most vigoursly by Robert Wokler, e.g. in Wokler (1998).
5
Wittrock and Wagner (1992) and (1996). See also Rothblatt and Wittrock (1993).
97
The argument in this section is largley based on a long-term research programme with results published in Wagner et al. (1991); Wagner (1999); Wittrock
(1999); Wittrock and Wagner (1992) and (1996). An analogous line of argumentation is pursued in Wallerstein et al. (1996). For a discussion of the role of universities in this process see Rothblatt and Wittrock (1993).
7
This also entailed that an alernative, more historical, interpretation as propounded e.g. by Reinhard Bendix came to play a less prominent role as did Bendix
own magnum opus, Kings or People (1978).
98
bjrn wittrock
the scholarly promise of a social science that brings in a comparative and critical account of world history.
However, these potentials were certainly not the ones that became
predominant or were realised when social science nally became
institutionalised across the board in the 1950s and 1960s. Rather
this occurred in the particularly ahistorical form of social science
that had long been predominant in the United States and that became
transposed abroad after the Second World War, linked to the notion
of the so-called behavioural revolution. These eorts were often promoted within the framework of the new international social sciences
associations that had been established with links to unesco and other
forms of international scientic collaboration, shaped by the United
States.8 Thus social science not only became less historical than it
had tended to be in most parts of Europe at the turn of the century. It also became shaped by the fact that social science disciplines,
and most notably so perhaps political science and sociology, in their
theoretical core came to reect the pre-eminent position of the United
States in the post-Second World War world.
Nowhere is this more obvious than in the curtailed form of theorising about world history that came to be known as modernisation theory. This type of theorising was explicitly premised on a view
of world history cast in terms of a set of dichotomies between the
traditional and the modern, the Western and the non-western, the
rural and the urban, the stagnant and the dynamic. Implicitly it
tended to be premised on a view of the world in which the particular experiences of one country, notably the United States, was taken
as the yardstick against which the achievements and failures of other
countries were measured.
Thus even if social science, in its own long-standing self-conception, remained a discourse of modernity, these presuppositions tended
to entail a social science that was reticent to theorise either world
history at large and even those upheavals that came to constitute
the particular Western trajectory. Thus the particular Western trajectory to modernity tended to be assumed rather than examined.
Furthermore, the relationship of a European trajectory to global historical developments tended to be ignored or simply dismissed. These
8
For an overview of these developments see Wagner et al. (1990) and Wagner
(1999).
99
100
bjrn wittrock
For a set of contributions to this debate see e.g. Engelstad and Kalleberg (1999).
101
11
This is the case already in his early standard work, originally published in
1967 with later editions (McNeill, 1999) but also in his shorter essays, e.g. McNeill
(2000). Hodgsons posthumous collection of essays (Hodgson, 1993) is a monument
to this kind of thinking about global history.
12
Subramanyam (1997) and (1998); Bentley e.g. (1993) and (1998). For an overview
of the treatment of global history, which served as the rst major theme at the
recent 19th international congress of historical sciences, see OBrien (2000).
102
bjrn wittrock
and in some case all but forgotten, traditions in social thought and
historical scholarship, but that seem exceptionally promising in such
a wider perspective. One such important existing tradition of great
relevance to a reconstructive research programme in social theory
and global history is the one that is often associated with a work of
Karl Jaspers. In the book, Vom Urspung und Ziel der Geschichte
(published in 1949; English translation, The Origin and Goal of
History, in 1953), he expressed the idea that our understanding of
history, indeed the very origin of history, is related to the emergence
and institutionalisation of forms of critical reexivity. Needless to say,
it is, to some extent, an arbitrary decision whether that moment is
associated by the most basic human activities in the form of the
emergence of language itself or with some other form of human
articulation. Jaspers argued that the emergence and institutionalisation of critical reexivity is associated with the emergence of forms
of thought that clearly transcend activities associated with the daily
lives and needs of human beings. Thus it has to be possible to identify the expression of forms of thinking that involve an explicit formulation of ideas about human life beyond the constraints of existence
as it looks at a specic time and place.
In other words, Jaspers believed that the distinctive feature in the
emergence of human history, as opposed to the evolution of the
human species, is the manifestation of a specic capacity. This was
the capacity of human beings to reect upon and to give expression
to an image of the world as having the potential of being dierent
from what it was perceived to be here and now. The emergence of
such images of the world, based on critical reection, marked, in
Jaspers classical formulation (1949), the transition from Mythos to
Logos, a breakthrough in critical reexivity and, indeed, the emergence of history in the sense of the epoch in human existence characterised by a reexive, historical consciousness.13 He termed this
period the axial age. In temporal terms he located it to the centuries around the middle of the rst millennium bce.
13
In fact, Jaspers notion was not altoghether dierent from the one Hegel proposed in his lectures on the philosphy of history, although in Hegels case the ascription, as in the case of Iran, and denialas in his statement that India does not
have a historyof such a capacity was heavily imbued with an empirical bias that
cannot but be called Eurocentric.
103
The idea of the axial age, as outlined by Karl Jaspers, had the
character of a bold idea briey sketched. The same is true of analogous formulations by Alfred Weber and Eric Voegelin. In the 1970s
this idea was taken up the Harvard sinologist Benjamin Schwartz
and a group of prominent scholars, including Peter Brown, Louis
Dumont, Eric Weil and Robert Darnton, in a special issue of the
journal Daedalus, devoted to the theme Wisdom, Revelation, and
Doubt: Perspectives on The rst Millennium bc. The idea was
explored later and elaborated by S.N. Eisenstadt who, with Wolfgang
Schluchter as the other principal investigator, made it the focus of
a sustained research programme. In collaboration with a large number of historians and linguists Eisenstadt extended the analysis considerably and systematically related it to recent advances in historical
scholarship.
For all its remaining openness, this theoryor rather this hypothesisof the axial age is to date the most ambitious and encompassing one that outlines the key features of a rst global cultural
crystallisation. It has, without achieving universal acclaim but also
without being convincingly refuted, been the subject of two decades
of intense scholarly debate, involving ancient historians, historians of
religion and philosophy, and linguists.14 My own ambition in this
essay is to advance an understanding of the notion of axiality that
makes it possible to relate it to some of the key problems in present-day historically orientated scholarship on major transformations
of societies and, indeed, civilisational legacies. As already indicated,
I am convinced that a purely structural and institutional analysis is
grossly inadequate for this purpose.
The concept of the axial age encompasses deep-seated intellectual
and cosmological shifts that occurred in dierent forms but with
striking, if relative, simultaneity, across the Eurasian hemisphere.
These shifts were manifested in such dierent forms as the thought
of Confucius and, two centuries later, Mencius in China, Buddha in
India, the Hebrew prophetical movement and the classical age in
Greek philosophy. Neither in the early formulations of Japers, nor
in the more recent ones by scholars, collaborating with S.N. Eisenstadt,
14
Among these publications the following ones may be specially mentioned, viz
Eisenstadt (1982), (1986c), (1987a), and (1992c, d and e), (1996b), and (1999a), as
well as Eisenstadt et al. (2001) and Schluchter (1996).
104
bjrn wittrock
has there been an entirely successful eort to relate these cosmological shifts to other types of human activities. Maybe the most
important direction in future research directions is to spell out the
links between the set of intellectual and cosmological breakthroughs,
that the concept of the axial age in a limited sense of the word
denotes, and sea-changing institutional transformations.
These are rstly the formation of the great world religions. This
transformation is a consequence of the Axial Age but not an immediate and direct one. It only manifests itself in the form of a series
of cultural encounters with ensuing articulations that synthesise cosmological elements from dierent and previously distinct civilisational
traditions. Furthermore, the hemispheric-wide diusion of these articulations in the form of world religions is in practical terms premised
on a second transformation of the widest consequence, namely the
emergence of a number of imperial political orders across the Eurasian
hemisphere. This development, thirdly, also makes possible the consolidation of hemispheric-wide trade routes over land linking the Far
West and the Far East. Thus the establishment of, what 19th century historians came to call, the Silk Route was stimulated by the
meeting of Sinic and Hellenistic cultures in Central Asia, and the
concomitant Western extension of control by the Han empire. Fourthly,
there also occurs, in direct conjunction with the last two transformations, a path-breaking change in the institutionalisation of warfare and military organisation. In this process, the role of the Iranian
imperial polities of the Parthians and Sassanians plays the foremost
role.
The concept of the axial age in a wider sense encompasses also
these macro-institutional transformations. In other words, a profound
cultural crystallisationthe dimensions of which refer to the imagination and representation of human existenceinvolved not just a
process of cultural reconguration. It also meant the formation of
culturally entrenched structuring principles for macro institutions.
Such a conceptualisation of the axial age stands in a striking relationship of analogy in analytical terms to accounts of the formation
of modernity. More precisely this is valid for such accounts that
emphasise that the formation of modernity can not be reduced to
the processes of transformation in political and economic practices
that are referred to by terms such as theto use Parsons terminologythe democratic revolution and the industrial revolution.
Instead it has to be located within the context of a deep epistemic
105
15
E.g. Foucault (1966); Koselleck (1979), (1985), (1986), (1987a), (1987b) and
(2002); Heilbron 1995, Heilbron et al. (1998).
106
bjrn wittrock
107
beliefs and practices. They also entailed the potentials for new interpretative contestations. Thereby, of course, the stage was set not only
for the articulation and diusion of orthodoxy but also for heterodox challenges.
This, I maintain, is the core of the meaning of the Axial Age in
its original formulation, and it is this core that has subsequently been
elaborated in various ways. My understanding is that it is important
to see that any particular articulation of a position on any of these
existential dimensions will inevitably involve some assumptions that
are contextually bound and culturally specic. It would for instance
to my mind be illegitimate to tie the meaning of the Axial Age to
an insistence on the occurrence of some specic cosmology, say one
premised on notions of transcendence as opposed to immanence, or
on some specic account of the dramatic increase in historical consciousness that we associate with the Axial Age.
What is not culturally specic is the idea that the Axial Age is a
period of deep change in the fundamental dimensions of human
existencereexivity, historicity and agentiality. This change, furthermore,
exhibits great variations in dierent parts of Eurasia, but it universally entails increasing reexivity, historicality and agentiality.
The change is broadly cotemporaneous across vast regions of the
Old World. The Axial Age is then an epoch, but not the only one,
of a profound cultural crystallisation that aects these inevitable existential dimensions in some of the high cultures across Eurasia. These
shifts entail the consolidation or the emergence of a set of dierent
cosmologies and make possible a set of dierent institutional paths
of development of lasting importance.
For all contestations about historical accounts, a delimitation of
the notion of the Axial Age in this way provides not only a fruitful
starting point for the study of global history and for an understanding
of its relevance to the social and human sciences at large. It is, I
claim, the only possibility of giving the notion of the Axial Age a
meaning that does not entail an unjustiable teleology and some
form of cultural imposition.
The axial age and the origin of history
One problematic question, and one, which Arnason deals with at some
length, is that of the relationship of political and societal formations
108
bjrn wittrock
109
context of meaning and familiarity. The emergence of the world religions is also part of this problematique.
The more the Axial Age breakthrough is described in terms of
an epochal rupture, the more the relevance of earlier intellectual and
institutional traditions is de-emphasised. As a consequence historical
and civilisational analysis will be less concerned with the specicity
of individual traditions and more with the extent to which a given
civilisation has or has not achieved an axial breakthrough. This
question is directly related to the question of the relationship between
the axial age as a cultural and cosmological shift on the one hand
and institutional transformations of religious and political practices
on the other.
The axial age and the world religions
A key question is the relationship between the Axial Age and the
emergence and diusion of the great world religions. The idea of
such a relationship has been at the core of much reasoning concerning the Axial Age hypothesis. Again, it seems undeniable that
the intellectual and ontological shift, described in terms of a breakthrough, has important links to deep-seated shifts in religious practices. It is however also clear that the exact of such links in many
cases is open to quite dierent interpretations.
Maybe one can say that the articulation and diusion of Mahayana
Buddhism occurred in a complex process of demarcation and synthesis of Indic and later, in artistic and perhaps also in ideational
terms, of Hellenistic traditions, as they existed in Bactria, parts of
Central Asia but also south of the Hindu Kush. Perhaps Christianity
may be described as a kind of secondary breakthrough in the form
of a synthesis of shifts in Hebrew and Greek Axial transformations.
Maybe even Islam can be seen as a distant echo of the early Axial
transformations, if occurring a millennium later. However, neither
Mahayana Buddhism, nor Christianity emerges as widely diused
world religions until maybe the 4th to 6th centuries. It is only
then that they become closely linked to imperial political orders in
the Mediterranean region and in China respectively.
Their subsequent wider diusion across the North-Western and
North-Eastern peripheries of the hemisphere is even more removed
from the original Axial Age breakthrough. In both cases it means
110
bjrn wittrock
that their religious practices become transmuted and intimately interwoven with distinctly non-Axial traditions, whether in the form of
the nature-orientated pre-Christian religions of the Celtic and Nordic
peoples of Europe or the nature-orientated pre-Buddhist religious
practices in Korea and Japan.
In all these cases, however, world religions have some sources that
are related to Axial transformations. However, the further developments of the religions, in terms of processes of standardisation,
codication and routinisation, involve at least as much of processes
that tended to stie the reexivity, the sense of historical contingency
and agential openness that were inherent in the axial transformations.
The Axial Age and the political order of empires
In most interpretations of the Axial Age, a relationship is discerned
between the Axial Age as a shift in cosmology and ontology and the
emergence of imperial-like political orders on the other. This raises
three questions that concern rstly the imagined nature of axial- and
pre-axial age political orders, secondly the continuities of such orders
and, thirdly, the consequences of the axial breakthrough for political
orders.
As to the rst question, clearly, as argued by Arnason, Jaspers
characterisation of pre-Axial political orders in terms of small states
and cities is not tenable. It is for instance simply not reasonable to
characterise the pre-axial Chinese empires of Western and Eastern
Zhou in these terms. There is no reason to deny the obvious fact
that many pre-axial political entities exhibit features of an imperial
order. This relates directly to the second question about continuities.
Again, it seems clear that we discern continuities between pre-axial
and axial political orders in dierent civilisations. Indeed, the political transformations that were possibly stimulated by the axial breakthrough may well be thought of as eort to preserve or resurrect
features of an idealised political order of the past. Again, as already
indicated, China, but also Iran, provides examples of precisely this.
Thirdly, maybe the most important question from the point of view
of the Axial Age hypothesis concerns the consequences of this axial
breakthrough for the emergence of imperial political orders. Basically
the problem here is that while such links may be hypothesised in
individual cases, the nature of any kind of causation is tenuous at
111
best. At the Western edge of the Eurasian landmass, the rise of the
Roman Empire may be coterminous with events that may be associated
with axial transformations. However, it would be unreasonable to
describe this empire as in any way itself expressing a commitment
to an axial age cosmology. On the contrary, emerging empires may
rather be seen to entail processes of the stiing of the vivid contestation and critique involved in the original axial transformations.
Conversely, the Han Empire is maybe the clearest example of a
relationship between imperial order and philosophical reection associated with the Axial Age breakthrough. This philosophical reection,
whether in the form expressed by Confucius or Mo or the one later
associated with Mencius, occurs against the background of coterminous political upheavals and may more accurately be seen in the
light of eorts to preserve features associated with an earlier imperial tradition than with any kind of cosmological reection on a
chasm between a mundane and transcendental sphere, more accurately as a kind of moral and political philosophy, with a stronger
emphasis on the human mind than on transcendental-religious discourse. To some extent, and in a completely, dierent political and
societal context, much the same may holds true for Greek philosophy in the same period where a pragmatic attitude and a focus on
the life of a polis was often the self-evident starting point for philosophical reection and debate, not a purported chasm between
transcendental and mundane spheres.
Analogously, the Maurya Empire during the reign of Ashoka, and
the Achaemenid Empire, may perhaps be depicted as political
manifestations of axial transformation of Buddhism in India and of
an axially transformed Ahura Mazda worship in Iran. In the Indian
case, though, this rather immediate link is of relatively short duration. The Iranian case, as the Chinese, is of a more long-standing
nature but one where the cosmology involved is of a radically dierent
nature than the one posited in some earlier pronouncement of the
thesis of the Axial Age in terms mainly of a dichotomy between a
transcendental and a mundane sphere.
These observations lead to two conclusions. Firstly they underline
the relevance of the delimitation of the concept of the Axial Age
made previously and formulated in a way that focuses on deep-seated
redenitions in key existential dimension without elevating the outcome in any given civilisational context to the status of being the
sole standard of the achievement of axiality.
112
bjrn wittrock
Secondly, they bring out the need to spell out links between shifts
in these dimensionsmanifested in new forms of basic conceptualisations and cosmologiesand institutional transformations in terms
not of one single form of axial transformation but in terms of a set
of dierent paths of axiality. This is the task to which we now turn.
Overcoming teleology
Jaspers rejected teleological reasoning. His formulation of the thesis
of the Axial Age also marked an eort to overcome the idea of
European cultural pre-eminence. It is clear however that much of
the discussion around the Axial Age has been haunted by an implicit
teleology, not completely unlike the one that has characterised much
of the discussion of modernity and modernisation. Even if the
Eurocentrism of earlier historiographyand historiosophy16has been
absent from virtually all formulations of the idea of the Axial Age,
many of them have been unable to avoid an implicit teleology. This
has been so in two respects:
Firstly, some formulations have focuses on just one specic form
of ontological transformation in the basic dimensions of human existence that I have chosen to delineate in terms of increasing reexivity
and sense of the temporal location of human beings and their agential possibility. This particular form of transformation then tends to
be depicted as more genuinely axial than another one and indicative of the achievement of a true axial breakthrough. One typical
example of such a conceptualisation is one that claims that a dening
characteristic of axiality is the positing of a cosmological chasm
between a transcendental and a mundane sphere.
This is a view that I do not share. My own view is that the
dening characteristic is an increasing reexivity of human beings
and their ability to overcome the bounds of a perceived inevitability of given conditions in temporal and social orderings. What particular cosmology this gives rise, e.g. one cast in terms of transcendence
or immanence, is a mater of context and contingency. Therefore I
propose an analysis that brings out dierent varieties of axial trans-
16
For an interesting discussion on these aspects see Assmann, 1992, 330340.
See also Koselleck (1986). I have spelt out my own view in Wittrock (2003).
113
114
bjrn wittrock
none of which should be given either empirical or normative preferred status. The contributions to this volume provide rich empirical evidence about these dierent paths. In the present context, I
shall only outline their dierences by the briefest indication. The
paths are:
Firstly, there is the development in the Near East whereby, in
a complex process of inuence and juxtaposition, the Mosaic
distinction (to use Jan Assmans terminology) between true and false
in religion and, as a consequence, a distinction between religion and
politics, is being drawn not, despite several preparatory steps, in
Ancient Egypt but in Ancient Israel. Eventually this distinction, in
the prophetic age and in second temple Judaism gives rise to a
path of development that may perhaps be termed transcendentalinterpretative.
One signicant element is a process of textual inscription and standardisation but also of interpretative contestation and the interplay
between carriers of orthodoxy and heterodoxy. The participants in
these contestations exhibit a remarkably independence relative to
political power. Sometimes this reects a withdrawal from it. However,
more often their activities impinge upon the world of rulership, sometimes explicitly, sometimes inadvertently, sometimes as heterodox
dissent or even rebellion, sometimes as support for established power.
Secondly, there is a related path, fundamentally inuenced by
Near Eastern developments, but in key respects distinctly dierent.
It is a tradition that gradually emerges in the Greek world and that
may be termed a philosophical-political path of development. It
involves contestation and deliberation that exhibit intense concern
about human potentials and action, about the location of human
beings in history and constant reection on the human condition.
However, in this case, a clear distinction between a transcendental and a mundane sphere, something absolutely central to the transcendental-interpretative tradition, is relatively insignicant. Nor can
one speak of a standardised religious cosmology inscribed in codied
texts. Instead contestation is dialogical, if often textually transmitted,
and has a philosophical and largely pragmatic character with the
political and moral life of a given community, a polis, as an inevitable
reference point. The key protagonists in these contestations act in a
context that is characterized by a previously unknown combination
of intellectual independence, institutional autonomy and political
engagement.
115
116
bjrn wittrock
117
bjrn wittrock
118
CulturalCosmological Focus
Ancient Israel
transcendentalinterpretative
philosophicalpolitical
universalinclusive
pluralisticsemantic
dualisticagential
Greece
China
India
Iran
Relation to
Political Power
strong
independence
strong
independence
weak
independence
strong
dependence
strong
dependence
Ethno-linguistic Force
autonomous
weakly
ecumenical
strongly
ecumenical
weakly
ecumenical
Ethno-transcendence
cum linguistic
pluralism
119
120
bjrn wittrock
centurieswhat in another context I have term the period of Ecumenical Renaissanceand the formation of modernity, should also be
examined in comparative terms.
Here neither a purely structural account, nor one that just highlights the contingency of language, is of much help. It is also here
that both the historical phenomenology of Karl Jaspers and the
civilizational analysis of S.N. Eisenstadt raise important questions
beyond those that most historical sociologists and speech-act theorists
nd interesting or indeed legitimate. Thus beyond speech acts proper
and beyond both linguistic conventions and social structural conditions, there are unavoidable dilemmas posed by our very existence
as reecting human beings. One inevitable fact is the nite nature
of our physical existence but equally inevitable is the need to adopt
some kind of position relative to a few basic phenomenological dimensions. These dimensions, inherent in our existence as human beings,
pertain to the nitude of our own existence, to universal anthropological necessities of drawing boundaries between the inside and outside of a community and of recognising the temporal and social
location of our own existence relative to that of others.17
An articulation of the phenomenology of reexive human existence is inherent in the human condition. Our very capacity to reect
upon our own situation entails the inevitability of a boundary between
the world and ourselves; the world is no longer a seamless web from
which we cannot even reectively distance ourselves. This, of course,
is what Jaspers saw as the origin of history in the sense not of biological reproduction but of the self-reexivity of humankind. Reexivity
entails the unavoidability of some boundary between inside and outside, no matter where this boundary is drawn and how it is constructed. Our realisation of the nitude of our own existence entails
a reection on our temporal and historical location. These types of
reexivity and our realisation of the existence of orderings in relations between oneself and other human beings entail the potential
of concepts of changing states of the world, of what social scientists
today would call agentiality.
Here two statements of caution are necessary. Firstly, the recognition of these phenomenological dimensions does not entail any single specic theory of historical meaning. It is compatible both with
17
121
18
122
bjrn wittrock
certainly part of the Axial Age, and Daoism, which was not, and,
in the Western provinces bordering Central Asia, to some extent
also, Nestorian Christianity and Zoroastrianism.
Christianity as a distinctly axial synthesis of Jewish and Hellenistic
beliefs and practices came, eventually came to exemplify the rst
pattern of development within the ecumene of Latin Christendom;
it was only in the Northern- and Easternmost peripheries of Europe,
where the conversion to Christianity came even later than the arrival
of Buddhism to Japan, that strong non-axial elements survived long
after formal Christianisation.
In South Asia, the emergence of Buddhism marks a moment of
axiality and a demarcation against Vedic religion. However, it is precisely in reaction against this challenge that there occurs an articulation of Vedic religion. Much later, in the 8th to 10th centuries ad,
what may then be termed Hinduism goes through another stage of
a articulation, this time in conscious demarcation against Islam as a
religion and cultural system that could not easily as Buddhism and
largely also early Christianity be assimilated into the Indic world.
Thus the Indic world of Vedic religion may have been distinctly
non-axial. However, even Vedic religion could not avoid an engagement with the cultural systems that grew out of the early axial transformations. Thus axial transformations came to impinge upon and
inuence cultures and societies across Eurasia, whether or not there
was a rejection or an embrace of some of the specic paths of axiality discussed in the previous section.
Fundamental redenitions along the dimensions of reexive consciousness, of historicity and agentialityto use once again the language of social theoryare what characterize periods of deep-seated
cultural crystallization, be they the Axial Age in the analysis of Alfred
and Max Weber, Karl Jaspers and S.N. Eisenstadt or be they the
formative moment of a new era in late eighteenth century Europe
in the analysis of Reinhart Koselleck, the conceptual historians and
the new historical sociologists. These dimensions are no mere cumbersome ontological addition to conceptual history. It is existentially
unavoidable for us as reecting human beings to relate to them.
However, precisely for that reason, they are also analytically necessary presuppositions for a historical phenomenology that is able to
engage with conceptual change in global history.
Ultimately, the cultural crystallizations that constitute formative
moments in global history involve an institutional articulation and
123
interpretation of the human condition, of what it means to conceptualise the nitude of our own existence in a world premised on
assumptions of the potentially innite malleability of the world upon
which and into which our actions impinge and what human existence
may mean in such a world.
CHAPTER FOUR
1
2
126
w.g. runciman
in the attitudes and behaviour of both its rulers and their critics
including not least the intransigent members of monastic communities of the kind so important in the history of Christianity.3 Why did
it not happen before? Two stereotypical answers immediately suggest
themselves, the Durkheimian and the Marxist. But neither will do.
From a Durkheimian view, Roman religion was so paradigmatic an
example of a societys worship of itself that the collective consciousness
of the Roman people excluded any possibility of tension between
the mundane and transcendental. From a Marxist view, the Roman
ruling class was so rmly in control of the means of production that
it was able to suppress any alternative ideology to which its exploitation of the rest of Roman society might give rise. But although the
connection between Roman religion and Roman politics was always
exceptionally close, they were never identical; and although the
Roman ruling class was always ready to manipulate Roman religion
to its advantage, there is at the same time ample evidence which
shows its members acting from authentically religious motives (of
piety or superstition, as you please). In comparative sociology, the
question why not? is often as dicult to answer as the question
why?; and it is particularly so in this case because so many of the
conditions which might be expected to give rise, in Roman as in
the other civilizations, to a similar Axial Age revolution were visibly
present in some form and to some degree.
First of all, it would be mistaken to suppose that Roman culture
drew no distinction between this world and some other one. Cynical,
philistine, and avaricious as many members of its elite may have
been, they seldom questioned the existence of non-human agencies
of some kind or other to whose inuence human beings were, or
could be, subject. When Marcus Aurelius (Meditations XII.38) said
that we know the gods exist because we experience their power, he
was enunciating what was a virtual truism even to the many Romans
who did not share his own philosophical interests or outlook. Prayers,
sacrices, haruspication, incantation, spells, and curse-tablets (dexiones)
invoking unseen powers were facts of everyday Roman life. As Cicero
remarks at the opening of his dialogue On the Nature of the Gods, there
is no subject on which there is more disagreement among the docti
and indocti alike. But disagreement of the kind in which that dia-
127
128
w.g. runciman
with the Christians, invite active persecution. But such groups and
movements were generally left to themselves unless or until reasons
of state dictated otherwise. Philosophers, preachers, oneiromancers,
mystagogues, and magi (of whom Jesus could be seen as just another
one) moved freely about the Roman Empire and addressed whatever audiences were prepared to listen to them. However strongly
and from whatever self-interested motives the Roman elite upheld
traditional Roman religion, potential competitors were always present.
Fourth, despite the weight of both literary and archaeological evidence for the public and political character of Roman religion, there
is evidence also for the signicance of personal and private religious
beliefs and values in the lives not only of a wealthy neurotic like
Aelius Aristides4 whose obsessive self-description survives in literary
form but of the many humble Romans whose votive oerings and
funerary inscriptions were in no sense part of the self-worship of the
Roman state. The notion of personal salvation is amply documented
in the evidence for the appeal of the mystery cults, notably Mithraism,5
into which initiation was on oer in the two centuries before the
conversion of Constantine. It was not, to be sure, salvation in the
Christian sense, but it did involve the explicit idea of the possibility
of detachment from the mundane experience of the worshipper and
a transcendental communication with some higher being.
Fifth, the seriousness with which the Romans took omens, portents,
prodigies, apparitions, and the prophetic implications of dreams
testies not only to the universal human hope of nding ways of
predicting the future but also to an uneasy wish to ascertain the attitudes and requirements of the supra-human agencies capable of
inuencing their destiny and that of the Roman state itself. A fear
that supra-human agencies to whom prayer and sacrices are oered
may be oended or displeased is explicit in the Roman cultural tradition, however shamelessly it might on occasion be manipulated for
political ends. There were always sceptics and scoers ready to deride
the idea that the wicked are punished for their wickedness either in
this world or the next, but there was also a plentiful supply of anecdotes whose moral is that they are. Whatever the intellectual merit
4
5
129
130
w.g. runciman
8
9
131
or at most a transference from one set of members of the dominant stratum to another supplemented by some upward individual
mobility by provincials into the ranks of the senatorial nobility.10
Nor, in any case, is it as if a close overlap between politics and
religion automatically inhibits the emergence of tension between the
mundane and transcendental orders. On the contrary, as the example
of Islam was later to show, it can directly give rise to it. In the
empire created by the Prophet and his early successors as rulers,
political and religious authority were even less distinguishable than
in Rome. But unlike the Roman jurists, the jurists of the Islamic
ulemate, through their diering interpretations of the Quran, the
sayings of the Prophet, and the Sharia, provided would-be rebels
and usurpers with ideological justications which they eloquently and
vigorously deployed. It was an empire which was as quintessential
a case of expansion by conquest as the Roman Empire had been.
But where the would-be usurpers who challenged the rulers of the
Roman Empire were simply seeking to replace the incumbents of
existing roles by themselves, the would-be usurpers of power in the
world of Islam, however they might behave if and when they succeeded, laid claim to legitimacy as the true heirs of the Prophets
mission which the existing rulers had betrayed.
Nor is it enough simply to point to the conservatism amounting
on occasion to self-conscious archaism of the Roman elite. The legitimacy of rulers can be as readily challenged when they depart from
a standard of conduct set in a mythical past as when they fail to
live up to the utopian ideals of a projected future. Indeed, the literary sources are full of complaints about the decline and disappearance of the virtues characteristic of the earlier days of the Republic
when its exemplary leaders were supposedly frugal, ascetic, selfdisciplined, austere, and impervious to the temptations and trappings
of riches. But the criticisms voiced of the decadence and corruption
of their successors never carried personal disapproval into serious
questioning of the system which had placed them in power. Again,
the unrestrained degree of Romes enrichment by conquest might
have been expected to generate an ideological movement aiming to
return the institutions of the state to their earlier and purer forms
and functions. But there is none. So what is it that is unique to the
10
132
w.g. runciman
Roman case which might explain the absence of anything approaching an Axial Age revolution as Eisenstadt denes one?
III. Once the question is put in that form, one answer immediately
suggest itself. If there is a single feature of Roman civilization which
distinguishes it from any and all others it is Roman lawa unique
combination of culturally selected beliefs and values and socially
selected roles and institutions whose pervasive inuence extends from
the XII Tables of the mid-5th century bce and the early days of
the Republic to the late Empire and the codications of Justinian.
But if that indeed furnishes the right answer to the why not?
question, why should it be so? Systems of law can be of very dierent
kinds and can evolve in very dierent ways. From a Weberian perspective, rational-legal legitimacy stands in contrast not only to charismatic but to traditional legitimacy. But the legitimacy which Roman
law gave to magistrates and emperors was, in practice, a unique
combination of the resolutely traditional with the pedantically rational-legal. Could it, therefore, be that combination which in itself created an ideological and political environment within which an Axial
Age revolution would never occur?
Anyone not a specialist in Roman studies who oers to comment
on Roman law is aware of venturing into a eld to which successive
generations of specialists have devoted lifetimes of scholarship. But
nobody who does venture into it can fail to be struck not only by
extent to which legal and political roles were occupied by the same
people but by the unquestioned appeal to ancestral customthe mos
maiorumas the criterion of legitimacy for successive legal decisions.
It is not enough just to repeat the platitude that law is inherently
conservative, since the XII Tables had, as emphasized by Weber,
much of the character of what he called aisymnetic lawlaw, that
is, which is the active creation of a lawgiver in whom authority has
been vested because of a recognized need to bring about change by
which political stability can be secured. But right through the Republic
and the Principate, the system as it existed is consistently and even
fervently justied by the wisdom of the maiores from whom the senatorial patres have inherited it and by the length of time for which
it has been upheld.
It is perhaps unwise to draw too heavily on Cicero simply because
so many of his writings survive. But it is remarkable that when, in
his enforced retirement from active politics, he set himself to write
133
two dialogues of his own based on Platos Republic and Laws, his
ideal republic turns out to be nothing other than the Roman state
and his ideal laws those of the kind of state already agreed to be
best, i.e. Rome. Similarly, when Tacitus (Annals XIV.423), in his
account of the Senates ferocious but traditional (vetere ex more) reaction to the murder of the prefect Pedanius Secundus, reports the
eminent Gaius Cassius Longinus as saying that he has never doubted
that on any issue what had been olim provisum was melius and rectius
and change always for the worse (in deterius), there is no reason to
suppose that Longinus was not reecting an attitude common among
his peers. The jurists are explicit that it is improper to challenge the
rationes for things that are a maioribus constituta, and that where there
is no law to which reference can be made directly custom (consuetudo)
is the appropriate guide. There is nowhere in the texts (so far as I
am aware) any elaboration of what could be called a philosophy of
law or of the notion of a legal right: for Buckland, The conception
of a right is so familiar to us as to seem obvious. But it represents
a feat of abstraction which the Romans never thoroughly achieved.11
Anachronistic laws were allowed simply to lapse rather than be formally abolished. Cases were argued not by reference to entitlements
in principle that individual persons might have but to the procedures available to redress the wrongs they might be held to have
suered. It would be an exaggeration to say that no distinction is
drawn between the letter and the spirit of the law, since ius may
not guarantee aequitas. But aequitas is not justice as fairness to all so
much as the procedural proprieties without which the application of
the law may wrongly discriminate against an aggrieved litigants
deserving case.
IV. Roman law cannot, however, be seriously discussed in the present context without reference to Roman religion. At the time when
the XII Tables were enacted, there was no very clear distinction
between religious and legal rules. The shadowy leges regiae which preceded them seem to have been at least as much ius divinum as ius
civile. The practices dening the roles of the members of the College
of pontices are an inextricable mixture of the sacred and the secular, and (if Livy is to be trusted) the pontices were for a long period
11
134
w.g. runciman
the repositories of secret formulae and the authorities for the religious-cum-legal procedures which ordinary citizens were to follow
in such matters as the burial of the dead or the maintenance of
familial sacra in households with no male heir. They had, moreover,
a power to interpret the XII Tables which, in the words of Buckland,
was in eect a power to alter the law,12 and they were responsible both for controlling the calendar and for keeping an annual
record of public events. They were credited (according to Valerius
Maximus) by the maiores with the scientia by which ceremonial should
be regulated. They held oce for life, and were drawn from the
leading families of the day. They might therefore be expected to
have constituted the beginnings of a distinctive group or stratum
with theocratic aspirations and the authority to pursue them. But no
such development took place. Although the norms and practices of
Roman religion were regularly adapted to changes in both their
domestic and their foreign environment, they never changed in such
a way as to bring them into conict with the presuppositions underlying the ius civile and the entitlement of political oce-holders to
apply it as they did. The divisive conicts were not about doctrine
but about control of the priestly colleges. Roman law, as Weber
categorically put it, evolved without any theological input whatever
(Der theologische Einschlag fehlt der romischen Rechtsentwicklung vllig).13 If
there had been an appeal to the supernatural in the XII Tables,
there was no trace of it left in the simplied legis actio.14 Priests never
became, or even looked like becoming, the carriers of transcendental standards by which the conduct of the business of the state might
have been publicly criticized or the authority of magistrates (and in
due course emperors) seriously questioned.
The same was true of the Roman jurists. They were neither an
organized group of teachers, pupils, and successors promoting a distinctive doctrine of rights and duties, nor a set of detached intellectuals testing the rationale for the legal system as such. They were
unpaid but prestigious advisers who gave legal opinions (responsa),
instructed advocates on the conduct of particular cases, and helped
in the preparation of documents. They disputed with one another,
12
13
14
Op. cit.: 2.
Weber (1956): 466.
Jolowicz and Nicholas (1972): 179.
135
but the rival schools or sects referred to in our sources were not
divided by religious or any other principles but at most by a greater
or lesser readiness to depart from strict adherence to traditional
authority. They gave no formal teaching. Their writings were perhaps more systematic, particularly in the later period, than Weber
gives them credit for (he calls them meist mssig rational geordnete
Sammlungen von einzelnen Rechtssprchen).15 But nothing that they wrote
could possibly be construed as subversive or even seriously critical
of the system about whose interpretation and application they recorded
their views. So far from being potential carriers of ideas of some
transcendental order, they were, whatever their intellectual talents,
untted by training, inclination, and interest alike for anything other
than the application of traditional legal concepts and procedures to
the circumstances and needs of those to whom they gave their advice.
None of this necessarily prevented a group of like-minded members of the Roman elite from formulating a critical attitude of their
own which might at least have raised the possibility of a challenge
to the dominant orthodoxy in the name of a transcendental standard of some kind. But once again, that is precisely the direction in
which their intellectual interests never did take them. Although
not restricted purely to rhetoric, history, and natural science, their
speculations were philosophical only in a form which not only avoided
the issue of political legitimacy altogether but left both traditional
law and traditional religion institutionally in place. Whatever Ciceros
own views about the Epicurean, Stoic, and Academic arguments
deployed by his three protagonists in the De Natura Deorum, no more
radical conclusion can be drawn from it than that there are serious
grounds for scepticism about the inuence allegedly exercised by the
gods in human aairs; if, as some scholars including Momigliano16
have argued, this implies that Cicero was now paying no more than
lip service to the traditional values of the Roman religious tradition,
that is still a very long way from championing an alternative system
of values with which they should be replaced. The Stoicism brought
to Rome by Crates and Panaetius and later expounded by Seneca
clearly had some impact on the higher echelons of Roman society,
but exercise of the virtues which Stoicism sought to inculcate was
15
16
136
w.g. runciman
17
137
early 3rd century bce when a pontifex maximus (and a plebeian one
at that) was also consul; and that occurred shortly after the civile ius,
which in Livys words (IX.46.5) had hitherto been repositum in
penetralibus ponticum, was rst made public. It was not that the successive holders of political powerrst, the senatorial oligarchs of
the Republic and then the emperors and their favoured appointees
kept both law and religion under their direct control as part of an
undierentiated, all-embracing authority. As the codication of the
XII Tables and the establishment of the priestly colleges already
demonstrate, Roman society was not a traditional one of the kind
in which law and religion remain embedded in such a way that
the distinction cannot be meaningfully drawn. But whereas the law
became increasingly disembedded from religion, religion never became
disembedded from politics to anything approaching the same degree.
This did not make either law or religion any less serious an activity to those who practised them. The members of the Roman elite
devoted large amounts of time, energy, and money to both. In both,
however, they were preoccupied much less with doctrine than with
practice. Numerous commentators have been struck by the Romans
obsessional concern with accuracy of performance of the details of
their traditional rituals and the superuity of priestly zeal which
Warde Fowler thought best illustrated by that strange list of forms
of invocation called Indigitamenta.18 But, as it has aptly been put by
Linder and Scheid, the Romans concern was not with croyance but
with savoir, and not with savoir-penser but with savoir-faire.19 In the
commerce rituel between men and gods, it was critically important to
avoid maladresse: gods were not thought to care about the purity of
heart of their devotees so much as about aronts for which the whole
community, not merely the oending individual, might be punished.
To be sure, insistence on accurate performance of ritual is abundantly documented across the ethnographic and historical record
both in religion and in law. The proceedings must follow the prescribed sequence, due dates must be adhered to, the parties must
be correctly addressed, and the traditional formulae are not to be
varied without good cause. But what is missing in the Roman case
is the articulation of any principled case for serious reform, even to
18
19
w.g. runciman
138
the limited extent of asking whether the concern with mere accuracy of performance might not have become excessive. Change was
always permissible, particularly in the modications to both legal and
religious ritual which inevitably followed the transition from republic to autocracy: the extensive fragments of inscriptions which survive from the cult centre of the Arval Brethren illustrate this without
the need to rely on literary testimony alone. But the legitimacy of
imperial, as previously of senatorial, decision-making was taken for
granted.
Once lawmakers were no longer priests, but priests were always
politicians, no systact could easily form, if at all, within the structure of Roman society whose constituent roles might have carried
the novel ideas by which the preoccupation with procedure at the
expense of principle might have been challenged. In comparative
sociology, it is often the overlap between roles which is more important than the relative economic, ideological, or political power which
attaches to them, and Rome oers a particularly striking example.
The only potential carriers of ideas which might have initiated an
Axial Age revolution were outsiders such as Jews or Greeks. But
whatever the interest shown by members of the Roman elite in
Judaism as well as in Greek philosophy, literature, and rhetoric, no
Jew or Greek occupied an institutional role from within which
political dissent might have been inuentially articulated. In the
Roman economy, outsiders (including freedmen as well as provincials) played an essential part. But neither in law nor in religion
were outsiders ever in a position to change the presuppositions which
underlay the decisions taken by the holders of power. Even if Roman
culture oered some limited ideological space within which the invocation of a transcendental standard might have been both horizontally and vertically transmitted from preachers to acolytes, Roman
society oered no institutional space for a prophetic would-be leader
of a reformation movement of the kind which in later empires set
out to purge the power-holders and submit them to ancient and
universal virtues.20
VI. It remains to relate the argument of this chapter to the theoretical perspective from within which it has been advanced. If Rome
20
139
21
w.g. runciman
140
22
23
Runciman (forthcoming).
MacMullen (1981): 101.
CHAPTER FIVE
142
jrgen kocka
civil society
143
144
jrgen kocka
2
For details and references see Kocka, 2000, pp. 1420. For the conference
The languages of civil societyEurope and beyond at the European University
Institute in Florence, 68 Nov. 2003, three reports on the history of the concept
were prepared (as part of the EU-sponsored network Towards a European Civil
Society with the Social Science Research Centre Berlin as its speaker institution)
by Peter Hallberg and Bjrn Wittrock (Uppsala); by Shin Jong-Hwa, Jean Terrier
and Peter Wagner (Florence); and by Jody Jensen and Ferenc Miszlivetz (Szombathely).
They will be published. A basic survey: Riedel, 1975, pp. 719800, esp. 73267
(749 Hume, 751 Mendelssohn, 75759 Kant). Gramsci, 1975, pp. 751f., 800f., 1028.
On this: Bobbio, 1988, pp. 7399; Arato, 1981, pp. 2347; Geremek, 1991, pp. 264
273; Keane, 1998, pp. 1231; Trentmann, 2003, pp. 38.
civil society
145
146
jrgen kocka
related tobut distinguished fromgovernment (or the state), business (or the market) and the private sphere; a social space in which
civil society understood as a specic type of social action dominates.
Understood as a core element of a project not yet fullled, civil
society preserves part of its utopian thrust, by which it is dened
due to its Enlightenment heritage. This is where the descriptiveanalytical concept becomes most clearly normative.
Denition is always partly a matter of decision, too, and there are
many dierent shades of opinion. Some authors abstain from a clear
denition, preferring to stress the historical uidity, the openness and
the paradoxes of civil society.3 But intellectually, this is not satisfactory and opens the door both to misunderstandings and a certain
degree of essayistic arbitrariness.
Some authors like John Keane tend to see large corporations and
other economic institutions as major parts or actors of civil society.4
In contrast I have stressed the dierence between the logic of the
market and the logic of civil society. It is interesting to note that
Ferguson already dierentiated between commercial relation (on the
market) and communicative relation (in civil society).5 But it may be
appropriate to concede that while businesses primarily act according
to the logic of the market, they can, under specic circumstances,
be actors in civil societies as wellwith both roles interconnected.
Some scholars think that we should see family as part of civil
society.6 The relation between family and civil society is underresearched. While families as spaces of privacy should not be seen
as belonging to civil society, certain types of familiese.g. European
bourgeois families of the nineteenth centuryperformed functions
and provided opportunities which enabled and strengthened civil
society. In this sense the family could become part of civil society.7
And there are those who dene civil society in a more formalistic
way, by seeing non-state and non-prot voluntary associations with
or without political ambitions and functions as the dening element
civil society
147
CHAPTER SIX
150
t.k. oommen
151
152
t.k. oommen
153
eties created a convergence between them. This means one can and
perhaps one should distinguish between the compartmental modernity of socialist systems and the fully edged modernity of capitalist systems. Which is to say, structural dierentiation is not the
only not even the most critical marker of modernity. This renders
structural dierentiation as a source of modernity incomplete and
inecient as it can account for only certain dimensions of modernity (cf. Luhmann 1982). This brings me to rationalization as a
source of modernity.
Rationalization is a process bound up with disenchantment of the
world, its demystication. Accordingly, unforeseeable forces no longer
interfere in social aairs, it is argued. The good is dened less and
less in relation to God, but more and more in relation to functioning society. In this rendition of modernity, reason and reality are
isomorphic. Understandably, the rationalization process results in
increasing t between means and ends, it is believed. Science and
technology, rather than religion or magic, becomes crucial. In this
vein of thinking, capitalism is the embodiment of rationality and
modern capitalism has its essence in rationality (Weber 1947).
The essential features of rationality of modern capitalism are the
calculability furthered by market place, the purely instrumental orientation of action, a highly technical system of book-keeping and
the bureaucratic organisation of rms. Traditional aective constraints
wane or vanish as a social world wherein social actors are increasingly,
if not exclusively, guided by their instrumental interests emerging.
The project of rationality assumes that the individual can gradually
evolve and ultimately become autonomous guided by his interests,
in an intelligible world. Perfection through reason is the guiding principle; and hence god is a dispensable entity; but rationalization of
the world pre-supposes the depersonalization of social relations.
However, the fact that functioning modern societies are visited
by irrationality, superstition and sentiments is widely acknowledged
and recorded which points to the impossibility of a completely rational and hence modern society of this version. The hatred which thrives
across religious, linguistic and racial groups and the animosity which
prevails across even secular ideological communities in the modern
world are not founded in rationality. In fact, human beings are more
rationalizers rather than rational. This points to the limits of the
modernity which can be unleashed through the axis of rationality.
154
t.k. oommen
155
156
t.k. oommen
157
All the four classical thinkers recognized the discontents of modernity. Durkheim recognized increasing individuation, Weber warned
about depersonalization, Marx alerted about alienation and Simmel
noted the loss of intrinsic worth. Through these processes the community is sentenced to death by modernity, individualism is celebrated and a homogeneity based on similarity in behaviour, attitudes
and values emerge which has no organic base, but is merely aggregative. That is social actors are apparently similar viewed in terms of
their life style but actually they are dierent in terms of their deeper
values. This explains why individuals and groups who share the same
life styles enter into persisting conicts based on race, religion or
language. Recall the conicts in Bosnia, Rwanda, Sri Lanka, Ireland
or Kashmir.
Part of the problem here arises from the monistic conceptualization of modernity as a movement from multiple traditions to singular modernity. Western epistemological dualism and displacement
syndrome is at the core of this mode of conceptualization. It is an
either-or paradigm which juxtaposes mind and matter, emperor and
pope, church and state, sacred and secular. The fact is that this
mode of conceptualization cannot grapple with the evolving empirical reality even of the West. Co-existence of religious, racial and
linguistic diversities along with dierent secular ideologies has become
an empirical fact which sits uneasily with the tradition versus modernity paradigm. Further, the ongoing process of transformation also
indicates the existence of multiple modernities. It seems to be correct
to think of dierent versions of democracy, capitalism, socialism, secularism and technologies. If so, plurality of modernity is a fact.
In Europe, modernitys source was endogenousthe internal
dynamic of societysurfacing through a series of revolutionsthe
conicts between aristocracy and clergy, the revolt of economic categories against clergy and aristocracy, and the proletarian revolution
which targeted the bourgeoisie. The trajectory of modernity diers
in other part of the world. For example, in South Asia, to begin
with the source of modernity was colonialism. But the modernizing
impact of colonialism was segmental: the lites exposed to higher
education and secular ideology were the agency through which modernization impacted. Gradually the consequences started seeping
down. The vertical transmission of the consequences of modernity
started gradually enveloping the lower sections of society in South
Asia. The promise of equality and justice in a modern polity which
158
t.k. oommen
159
160
t.k. oommen
161
important of these were the value of individualism and the institution of private property. In turn they gave birth to democracy,
monogamous marriage and nuclear family. The introduction of
modern communication, transportation and technology gradually led
to the shrinkage of time and space, the basic pre-requisites of
globalization.
The second phase of globalization was couched in terms of the
modernization project. Broadly speaking three revolutions produced
three worlds. The rst revolution to occur was the bourgeoisie revolution, which produced the First World with its anchorage in Western
Europe. The values and institutions which colonialism sought to
spread were the products of this revolution. The proletarian revolution followed and produced the Second World. This revolution questioned some of the values (e.g. individualism) and institutions (e.g.
private property, multiparty democracy) of the First World. The leading value produced by the proletarian revolution was modern collectivism; it advocated one-party democracy and collectivization of
property. Inspired by the values and institutions of the rst and the
second worlds, the colonial revolution triggered o producing the
Third World. The rst and the second worlds started the contestation for the Third World and the Cold War phase, the period of
capitalist and socialist modernities, emerged.
If colonialism produced three dichotomies, Cold War produced a
trichotomy of the three worlds (Worsley 1984). In this rendition the
Third World was characterised as the world of tradition, illiteracy,
irrationality, under-development and over-population. It needs to be
modernized. For this, modern (that is, European) knowledge is to be
imbibed, western technology should be introduced, secular-values
ought to be internalized and population should be controlled. Most
of all, the persisting traditional collectivism of the Third World
should be replaced by western individualism to sustain multi-party
democracy.
Unlike the Third World, the Second World was modern but its
modernity was dierent from the modernity of the First World. The
Second World was technologically sophisticated and secular. But it
was politically authoritarian; it did not provide any space for civil
society and the market was subservient to state. Indeed it produced
a state-centric system which rolled the state, market and civil society
into one entity. If the central thrust of the First World modernity
was dierentiation, the ethos of the Second World modernity was
162
t.k. oommen
163
both to the compression of the world and intensication of consciousness of the world as a whole (Giddens 1990; Robertson 1992).
To accomplish globalization, this should apply equally to all the
inhabitants of the erstwhile three worlds. In turn this implies reciprocity between them and ow of ideas across them. But in reality
the process of globalization as it occurs is quite at variance from this.
The chief instrument of globalization is the Structural Adjustment
Programme (SAP) and it is enunciated and operated by the Brettonwoods institutionsthe World Bank, International Monetary Fund,
World Trade Organisation etc. on behalf of the erstwhile First World,
particularly some of its constituents. As is well known SAP has several
aspects: Minimalization of state, dismantling of developmental bureaucracy, de-legitimation of the concept of welfare state, promotion of
free trade, privatization of the economy, institutionalization of multiparty democracy, observance of Human Rights. Admittedly, this is
a mixed baggage. While the last two dimensions have acquired nearuniversal acclaim and recognition this cannot be said of other aspects.
The most widely contested dimensions of SAP are the disproportionate
importance it accords to market and the near marginalisation of
state.
It is very important to recall here that those who are subjected
to the pressures of SAP are mainly the democratic incapables of
the colonial erathe primitives and orientalsand the democratic
mists of the Cold War erathose from the former socialist states.
Thus viewed, globalization is the third incarnation of the civilizing
mission, the rst two being colonialism and modernization. With this
understanding of the conceptual history of globalization which situates the changing cognitions about the world let us look at the more
direct manifestation of its social impact, the intention being to avoid
the decits of modernity in the ongoing process of globalization.
III. Globalization, as other izations, has both negative and positive consequences as I have noted above. In what follows I shall
identify four inter-related and interacting processeshomogenization,
pluralization, traditionalization and hybridizationin terms of their
positive and negative social impact and through that the challenges
posed by modernity to globalization.
The revolution in transport and communication did bring about
a certain degree of homogenization in cultural patterns and institutional
arrangements right from the time of colonialism. While modernization
164
t.k. oommen
165
Not only that. Several of the old patterns in food, dress and music
persists with vehemence; cultural revivals are indeed common in contemporary world. This partial change and partial persistence gives
birth to what I have designated as pluralisation.
I have already hinted above the possibility of pluralisation in the
institutional realm. Witness the arrangements of marriage that exists
today from simple temporary co-habitation without any legal or moral
binding to highly committed and life-long marriages. Similarly,
families range from ephemeral dwelling units of couples to long
term cohabitation of a wide circle of kin. Even as private property
and parliamentary democracy are endorsed in form, their content
varies across societies. The democratic pattern varies from two-party
systems to multiparty coalitions. Property forms vary from exclusive
private ownership, to joint-stock companies to co-operatives and collective enterprises. Even in the case of technology, the distinction
between simple (traditional), intermediate and advanced (complex)
technologies is not merely conceptual but is of robust empirical possibility (Oommen 1992: 1319). That is, pluralization is a fact of
contemporary social reality.
I must add a caveat here. It is not my point that globalization
causes pluralization. But I want to suggest that because of the processes
of accretion and retention pluralization comes about as globalization
proceeds. That is, globalization cannot be and indeed should not be
homogenizing in its tenor, the central tendency of modernization.
Pluralism does not reject a cultural item or an institutional device
based on the locale of its origin, because it recognizes and respects
other cultures. But generally speaking the non-west accepts many
more of the western cultural items and west reluctantly takes to
things non-western. Globalization which should imply ow of goods
and ideas in multiple directions actually results in their ow in one
direction, from the west to the non-west, from the centre to the
periphery and hence hegemonizing in its tenor and orientation. One
of the challenges of globalization is to reject this unilinearity and
consciously move towards reciprocity.
The hegemonizing tendency of modernization gives birth to a loss
of meaning and an erosion of identity to the non-West. This leads
to the revivalist syndrome, the resurrection of roots, a search for
identity, a process of traditionalisation. However this tendency is not
conned to the non-west. Americanization is resisted even by
Europeans, particularly the French. Dierent nations even as they
166
t.k. oommen
167
The clashes between great traditions transmit their tension vertically leading to conicts at the level of local communities. These
manifest in a million mutinies between religious, linguistic and tribal
communities as well as racial and caste groups. The clashes between
these little traditions are based on the specicities of their situations
whether they occur in Ireland, Bosnia, Basque Land, Kashmir,
Burundi or Los Angeles. These are not clash of civilizations as such
but are their local expressions which have a bearing at the macro
level. Further, these local clashes feed on each other because of
globalization, through the agency of communication, particularly
electronic media.
It is not my intention to suggest that globalization only intensies
the clashes between little traditions, it can also and often it does
prompt communitarianism. The mass media often instills in their
audience sympathy and concern for the victims of dierent types of
disasters. Humanitarian work and charity result from this. Thus
globalization does produce fellow feeling, fraternity and altruism.
There is another aspect of communitarianism that merits reference.
Modernitys emphasis on homogenization tends to destroy the
specicities of local communities. Therefore, people soon discover
the decits of modernityanonymity, impersonality and bureaucratization. These render them rudderless creatures and they often
yearn for the return of the community. New associations of friendshipclubs, eating jaunts, entertainments, picnics, excursions, tours
and the likecome into vogue. Neighbourhood associations and
other voluntary associations get established to meet instrumental and
expressive needs. There occurs a resurrection of localism as a reaction
to globalism resulting in the return of community (see Etzioni 1993).
The cross-breeding of the traditional and the modern, the local
and the global, gives birth to hybridity. Hybridisation creates new cultural elements and social patterns which are neither traditional nor
modern, neither local nor global. Hybridization is dierent from pluralization in that it is neither co-existence nor elaboration. It is an
eort to innovate, to break out of cultural and social dead ends. It
is a product of the mutation syndrome. It is simultaneous engagement
with both tradition and modernity and local and global (cf. Pieterse
1994: 16184). This is evident in contemporary institutional arrangements and consumption patterns.
If in the traditional societies living in joint family was the norm,
in the modern society nuclear family came to be accepted as the
168
t.k. oommen
standard. But it was realized that nuclear family with its aggressive
individualism neglects not only the aged, the imbecile and the physically
handicapped but even the normal child. An appreciation of eastern
family ethic gradually developed in the West. Inter-family arrangements
to look after children intermittently are gradually emerging (e.g., in
Scandinavian countries) instead of vigorously pursuing the professionalization of mother role, the refrain of modernity. Acute sexual
division of labour which prevailed in the wake of modernization is
gradually being replaced by sharing of domestic chores by husband
and wife (Hochschild 1989). The possibility of lodging the aged parents in houses and ats proximate to those of adult children is being
explored instead of their being dumped into Old Age Homes, which
are invariably run with a commercial motive. In all these institutional arrangements of the Global Age one sees mutation of the traditional and the modern.
The mutation between the local and the global too lead to hybridization as is evident in music, art forms or food items. Vegetarian hamburger, Indian rap music, European Curry, Japanese Pasta, and
numerous other examples suggest the relentless march of hybridization. And yet, it ought to be noted that there is a hierarchy here.
Generally speaking the cultural elements from the auent and dominant nations dominate over the cultural elements from weak, small
and/or dominated nations. There is an unfortunate tendency to
value positively everything from the dominant or groupsbe they
political institutions, economic organisations, family patterns, or eating
habits and stigmatization of those from dominated ones. Nullication
of this tendency is an important challenge before globalization.
IV. The four processeshomogenization, pluralization, traditionalization and hybridizationthat I have referred to above are resultants of the revolutions in transport and communication leading to
ideational, spatial, social and cultural mobilities. Precisely because
globalization contribute to the acceleration of these processes it is
extremely unlikely that the world will become one socially and culturally. True, a commonly shared social and cultural layer is emerging and getting universal endorsement. But even as this layer is likely
to be similar in its form, it is likely to be dierent in its contents in
dierent locales. To wit Indian democracy, the biggest in the world
functions dierently from the American, the most successful. Italian
Catholicism is conservative as compared with the Brazilian one
169
CHAPTER SEVEN
172
jeffrey c. alexander
173
modern age has produced turmoil and strife, not amelioration and
equilibrium.
But history has provided an opportunity to overcome this ambiguous legacy of the Axial age, in order to make it good. The
Puritans of old, under the yoke of modern abstraction, created capitalism and bourgeois democracy. Bearing the same cultural and
organizational burden, the new PuritansMarxists, Leninists, or
Maoistswould create communism and workers democracy. Revolution
is this-worldly asceticism in our own time.4 Yet, the result is a just
order; the deracinating promise of bourgeois modernity will nally
be fullled in the next historical time.
The third response to the question posed is No, modernity, tout
court, simply is not a good thing. The abstraction that men are bound
to live with is fundamentally other, and unbearable for that reason.
It sets up tensions that tear man away from himself. The passions
of human nature cannot be corrected or civilized through abstract
morality, the hypocrisies of which man must be fundamentally in
rebellion against.5 Modernity unleashes, not enlightenment, but an
even darker dark age. It cannot be saved through disciplined revolution, which would only make it worse. It must be discarded.
Some of these critics have argued that an alternative to modernity
can be found by just saying No, by taking the route of other-worldly
or this-worldly mysticism.6 Others have insisted that modernity must
be destroyed by violence of a right-wing, not left-wing, form.7 Both
kinds of critics agree that the new world must set aside the tensions
of the axial age. Unity must be restored. Depending on which path
to restoration is chosen, there will be concreteness, not abstraction
release, not disciplinefusion, not divisionplay, not work. Only if
abstract morality and inner-worldly discipline are set aside can humans
lead a truly human life.8
4
Eistenstadt, 1978.
Nietzsche, 1956 [1872, 1887].
6
Roszack, 1969.
7
On the role that desire for transcendence played in radical right wing ideology, see Nolte, 1966.
8
In simplifying so as to make its polemical point, this paragraph points once
again to the self-circumscribed framework of this paper, which considers the history of modern society and thought entirely from within the framework of rationalization theory in its classical and modern from. A fuller treatment of the no
reaction against modernity, for example, would have to explore romanticism. The
5
174
jeffrey c. alexander
aesthetic, cognitive, and moral development of romanticism forms the key counterpoint to rationalized modernity. Emerging in late eighteenth and early nineteenth
century literature, music, art, and philosophyfor one of the best general accounts
of this movement, see, e.g., Abrams, (1953)romanticism did not necessarily take
an antidemocratic or anti-Enlightenment form. As Seidman (1983) pointed out,
while Romanticism often opposed hyper or distorted rationalization, it did not
oppose rationality in a broader sense, which would include such themes as expressive individualism, authenticity, creativity, and reciprocity. For this broader argument, see Taylor, (1989).
9
Furet, 1999.
10
Eisenstadt, (1982): 294314. Alexander, (1992): 8594.
175
11
Weber, (1927).
Walzer, 1965; Eisenstadt, 1999a.
13
Eisenstadt, 1987.
14
These quintessentially modern feelings are captured by such terms as ontological anxietyrst employed, in a psychoanalytic version of existentialism, by
Lang (1966) and later by Giddens (1984)and psychological man, which Philip
Rie (1968) developed. The structural status of such anxieties explains why psychotherapy can make a claim to have been the most important and inuential cultural invention of the twentieth century, and why so much contemporary popular
literature is devoted to self-help guides for the perplexed and restless.
15
Eisenstadt, 1995a.
16
Freud, 1961 [1930].
12
176
jeffrey c. alexander
I would phrase the question this way. Does the separated ideal
that is posited by the Weberian tradition remain whole and transcendent in the manner that liberal social theory suggests?
Transcendent. The ability to tie the Axial age breakthrough to human
progress, to the institutionalization of principled ethics and democratic reform, rests on the assumption that human beings can tolerate
the tension without inching or backing away. Perhaps this assumption, and this ability, seems obvious enough, but Max Weber himself
expressed doubts.
In Religious Rejections of the World and their Directions, Weber
outlined dierent kinds of ights from the demands of this-worldly
asceticism.17 Each of these eorts undermined the capacity of ethical judgment to exercise compelling moral demands. They undermined dualism, and they provided expressive outlets for symbolic
process that took a mystical form. Weber speaks of aestheticism, of
art for arts sake, which is closely connected to the Nietzschean
rejection of the good for the beautiful and to his attack on the sustainability of modern moral claims. Weber also speaks of eroticism,
demands for impulse release, and romantic love, whether the love
of another or of divine representatives of god.
Weber presents here a range of forces that undermine discipline
and autonomy and tempt moderns into bad faith. They are, in
Fromms words, escapes from freedom.18 There is in the mind of
every modern person the conviction that freedom might be too hard,
too unkind, and too intrinsically fullling. There is some evidence
in Webers writings that he sees this need to escape not merely as
a micro problem, or an incidental one, but as a systemic and dangerous macro-social strain. He speaks, for example, of militarism and
various forms of popular enthusiasm as providing ights from asceticism that are positively sanctioned by society.19 It is this strain in his
theorizing that explains Webers attention to plebiscitarian democracy,
17
Weber, (1946). For a broader discussion of Weber from this point of view,
and a systematic comparison to Sartres dialectic of freedom in Being and Nothingness,
see Alexander, 1988: 185206. In the background to this discussion is Mitzmans
(1970) compelling and original, if also awed interpretive.
18
Erich Fromm, (1941)Fromms work should be seen as part of the dialogue
about the dialectics of rationalization; he was a connected to the Frankfurt school
and a Freudian analyst, as well.
19
For a recent and penetrating study that applies this perspective to contemporary American life, see Gibson, 1994.
177
20
For this framing of the early American experience, see Morgan, (1958) and,
most generally and powerfully, the various works by Perry Miller (1956, 1965, 1967).
One of the great intellectual historians of American history, Millers reections about
grace, salvation, social rationalization, and psychological release form an extraordinary counterpart to Webers sociology. There has even emerged a left-Millerism
that constructs violence less as a deviant than as a deeply institutionalized search
for grace, e.g., Slotkin, (1973) and Gibson, loc. cit. Edward Tiryakian took o from
this Miller tradition in American Studies in his thoughtful and imaginative discussion of the dilemmas of modernity (cite).
21
Both because of the American nations Puritan-Protestant religious core, and
because of the vast inuence of Perry Millers historical framing, the escape from
this-worldly tension and the paths this escape have taken can be seen as a constant
theme in the non-Marxist criticisms that American thinkers have leveled against
themselves and their nation. See, e.g., Riesman (1950), Cherry, (1970), Slater, (1970),
Bellah, (1975) and Bellah et al., (1985).
22
Alexander, 2003.
178
jeffrey c. alexander
23
Freud, (1936).
Dahrendorf, (1959); Erikson, (1966); Parkin, (1979); Brubaker, (2002); Lamont,
(1982); Giesen, (1998).
25
Alexander, (1988); Alexander and Smith, 2004.
26
Batailles, (1985); Caillois, (1959); Douglas, (1966); Drag Kings at the Totem
24
179
PART TWO
CHAPTER EIGHT
This quote could very well have been attributed to a Zionist discoursing on Israel as a Jewish state. However, the idea that a Zionist
could have spoken these words is dispelled once we turn to the continuation of the quote expressed by Eliot which reads:
reasons of race and religion combine to make any large number of
free-thinking Jews undesirable.
184
zvi werblowsky
pluralism, which is (perhaps) unobjectionable, and intensive pluralism, which is only possible within strict limitations. From the latter
perspective, pluralism is, at best, a euphemism for a millet system.
Having said that, I reassure that there is no immediate danger of a
coalition of free-thinking Jews and Palestinian Arabs undermining
the character of the State of Israel, nor, for that matter, is there a
coalition of free-thinking Copts and Muslims threatening the character of Egypt.
There are many kinds of pluralism e.g., external tolerance or even
armation of plural identities vs. the internal intolerance required
to safeguard collective identityor at least a certain conception of
it (as Socrates realized in Athens). These in turn relate to, and are
dened by, a variety of pluralities (ethnicity, historical consciousness, language, religion). Should and can plural entities, rather than
clash and compete for hegemony, co-exist and possibly even enrich
one another (whatever that may mean) without the dissolution of
their individuality which continues to be considered a major value?
Should minority cultures and population-groups (aboriginal tribes,
local dialects, religious sects ancient and modern) be treated as endangered species to be preserved at all cost? In due course we shall
single out religion for closer examination, as its sacrality renders
it a particularly potent identity-marker as well as a test-case for
the theoretical and practical applications of pluralism.
Understandably enough, and almost logically rather than paradoxically, it is precisely the age of globalization that is also the age
of urgent concern with pluralism. The galloping processes unleashed
by the accelerating speed of technical innovation, of which transportation and the near-instantaneous transfer of information are
merely some of the more conspicuous examples, has led to a globalization of economic, political and cultural systems; the origin of
which is in the West and in western hegemony. But there is a
dierence between the endogenous development of western modernity and its reception and absorption, both imitative and ambivalent elsewhere. This also accounts for the initial misconception,
abandoned long ago, that modernization equals non-plural, uniform
westernization. Some forty years or so ago Eisenstadt already told
us to look in the various societies and cultures for the possibility of
the development of parameters of modernity diering from the ones
developed in Europe and not dened by a uniform set of charac-
185
teristics or indices and irreversibly moving in the same xed direction. Since then the expression multiple modernities (a truly pluralistic concept!) has become the commonly used word referring to
a series of processes with a common core, generating similar problems to which, however, dierent responses have been and are being
given.
Of the innumerable examples with which I could illustrate my
present argument I shall choose the one to which Eisenstadt has
devoted a monumental study: Japanthe one civilization which
Huntington did not quite know how to classify since it does not
prima facie belong to his China-Islam axis. Japan, as Eisenstadt has
shown in great detail, is a prime example of an old home-truth
which in the Latin middle-ages was rendered quidquid recipitur ad
modum recipientis recipitur. Whatever is received, it is received (we
might also say absorbed) according to the mode of the recipient.
The Jewish philosophers and kabbalists translated hakol ke hamekabbelim. My present tzen (advance eastwarda term used
already in ancient texts for the spread of Buddhism from China and
Korea to Japan) is concerned not so much with modernization as
with another exemplary aspect of the experience of, and reaction to,
massive hegemony on the part of a civilization conscious of its identity, not to say uniqueness. This experience is, of course, not limited to the East. Every group absorbs inuences from outside which
aect and transform it and which, in the process of such adoption,
are themselves adapted and transformed in accordance with what is
supposed to be the receivers basic character. Some would use the
terms culture and civilization to distinguish between the two levels.
(Huntington uses the two terms interchangeably). The Meiji separation of Shinto and Buddhism (shinbutsu bunri) was, as we all know,
an expression not of religious intolerance but of ideologized Nihonism.
Ruthless as it was, the crusade was rather humane. There simply
were too many Buddhists in Japan who could not all be massacred
like the Albigenses in Catholic France, or expelled like the Jews in
Catholic Spain, or persecuted and crucied like Christians in Tokugawa
Japan. If globalisation is associated in the contemporary mind with
the U.S. and symbolized by McDonalds then it may be useful to
remind ourselves that in the pre-global universe of the Japanese the
dominating hegemon, culturally more than economically, was China.
Hence not only the Chinese importation called Buddhism but also
186
zvi werblowsky
the Japanese-Confucian (viz. neo-Confucian) symbiosis was repudiated by the School of National Learning and their predecessors as
a foreign corruption of the true Japanese spirit, the yamato damashii.
National Learning (kokugaku) meant authentic Japanese learning
(wagaku). Kangaku (Chinese Learning) could easily be cast in the
role of the main whipping boy and source of all evil as long as
China was politically and culturally dominant. Chinas dramatic
decline and the equally dramatic rise of western inuence, yogaku
(western learning and culture) took the place of kangaku as the
villain of the piece. These ambivalences, of course, are not specically
Japanese. Especially since the 19th century non-western civilizations
(including orthodox Judaism) keep repeating their answer to the Clash
of Civilizations with more or less the same favourite formula: western technology (including nuclear weaponry for Gandhis India)
yes, by all means; western civilizationno! The earlier Japanese
slogan wakonkansai (Japanese spirit and Chinese knowledge) has
now been replaced by wakonyosai (Japanese spirit and western
technology). Theoretically one might interpret this attitude as a
charter for pluralism which, in a global age, should lead to civilizational two-way trac instead of confrontation, were it not for the
shadow of hegemonic dominance blackening the horizon.
Pluralism, as I have said before, implies an existing plurality.
Rapprochement of pluralities requires that each side be sure of its
identity and be unafraid of losing it. Cultural plurality means that
every group has its own denitions of narrower or wider identities
and homogeneities, and of their relation (congruence or dierence)
to other identities. This is a very complex aair and not simply a
matter of inventing (I have deliberately chosen this ambiguous
word because of its original meaning which is nding, discovering) some allegedly trans-cultural and supra-particular common
denominator of valuesfor example the U.N. Bill of Rightsor, in
the case of religions, implying a vague reference to some ultimate
spiritual realityfor example, the by now almost traditional jamborees of world-religions, especially of world religions for peace
or for interfaith dialogue or whatever. Whether held in Assisi (which
is certainly more appealing than the Vatican) or on Mount Hiei.
Every culture has to inventthat is both discover and construct
the nature, character, dynamics and limitations of the pluralisms that
it can advocate or endure.
187
Of the factors and elements constituting the identities of the candidates for rapprochement I want to mention, by way of example,
only a few of the better known in order to illustrate how their specic
weight varies from one case to another: historical memory, language,
religion. Religion can function as a major identity-marker also when
initially absorbed from outside but then so thoroughly internalized
as to become an essential part of a groups self-denition. Catholic
Poland, Buddhist Thailand, Sinhalese Sri Lanka and Muslim Malaysia
are cases in point. A conict that is known by religious labels is not
necessarily a religious conict. In Ireland both sides speak the same
language (not Irish!) and the murderous conict in which Catholics
and Protestants are locked is not about the doctrine of the Eucharist
or the status of the Holy Virgin. In Belgium both sides are Catholic
and the conict therefore ostensibly polarizes around language. The
India/Pakistan case cannot, of course, be compared to either Ireland
or Belgium. Often sets of binary opposites coalesce; Canada could
serve as an example. The main sanctuary of France is not the cathedral of Reims or Chartres, not even the Panthon or the Arc de
Triomphe, but the Acadmie Franaise. Switzerland has added a
fourth idiom to its list of national languages and apparently nobody
feels this to be a threat to his Swiss identity. India had good reason
to fear that the imposition of one national language might be
perceived as a particularist hegemonic act jeopardizing a wider
national identity. I am not speaking here of the unique sacrality
inherent in the Hebrew language or, for that matter, in the kotodama of Japanese which makes them dierent from all other languages. When several elements coincide in an identity-marker the
conict can become explosive: Cyprus (Greek/Christian v. Turkish/
Muslim), Sri Lanka (Sinhalese/Buddhist v. Tamili/Hindu) and Israel
Palestinians are alarming examples. The ethnic component is increasingly and indeed frighteningly in the ascendant. Is the state the only
guarantor or even source of unity? I am asking the question not so
much philosophically with a view to William James A Pluralistic
Universe as to Carl Schmitts Staatsethik und pluralistischer Staat.
Basques probably do not object to membership in the European
Union, but they want to do so as Basques and not as Spaniards. A
President of the French Republic exclaimed, nota bene as guest of
the Canadian Government, vive le Qubec libre. There is no
record of his ever having exclaimed, when in France, vive la Corsique
188
zvi werblowsky
libre. Globalization is one of the biggest of the currently fashionable big words. One of its oddest manifestations is the multiplication of nation-states in which ethnicity determines geography. Here
is pluralism with a vengeance! The U.N. currently has close to 200
member-statesmost of which share a not unfounded fear of the
hegemony called globalization, though all of them indulge in their
own particular agendas of hegemonic practice.
Let me return, in conclusion, to my earlier, perhaps unduly sarcastic, remarks about the popular jamborees of world-religions and
say a word in praise of religion, especially the so-called universalistic religions and even more especially the bible-derived monotheistic religions. A few weeks ago (2324 September 2003) such a jamboree
took place in Kazakhstan, signicantly titled The Congress of World
and Traditional National Religions. Traditional National (to avoid
the apparently more pejorative tribal) Religions are therefore as
respectable as the universalistic so-called World Religions which,
of course, are traditional too. That is probably why pluralism in
Kazakhstan stopped short of the less traditional so-called new religions. In any case religions and their gods are pluralizable, regionizable, tribalizable, nationalizable. Monotheism is not. The view that
the plurality of manifestations of the cultural phenomenon usually
subsumed under the term religion is ultimately a matter of variations on a common theme may be a perfectly legitimate ideological
position or even theological corollary of the structure of certain religious systems but it is surely incompatible with others. What now?
Should we be satised with distinctions such as aggressive vs. peaceful universalism (e.g., regarding missionary activity), or theoretical vs.
practical intolerance, or perhaps retreat behind a relativism that looks
at all claims to validity revise to: looks at the validity of all claims
whether absolute validity or relative validities or combinations of
bothas a plurality of cultural and religious language-games. This,
of course, would merely be a post-modern version of the jolly old
common denominator game. The study of contemporary religion
is fascinating not least because it seeks to comprehend how religious
cultures, each with its particular and specic claim to validity,
struggle, each in its own way, to invent i.e., to discover, construct
and dene on their own terms, the nature, character, dynamics, theological legitimations as well as immanent limitations of the inescapable
demands of pluralism in a global world. The common denomina-
189
tor, at least for some of them, would thus be their openness to what
might be called the pluralist imperative. To the ancient teaser can
tolerance tolerate intolerance? we can now add the question how
much plurality can pluralism bear?
CHAPTER NINE
MULTICULTURALISM REVISITED
Han Entzinger
Cultural diversity and the state
Sociologists and political scientists have long been fascinated by the
way in which public authorities, the state, come to terms with pluriformity. The concept of the modern nation-state nds its roots in
the social contract: the idea that the confrontation of diverging individual and group interests in a society should be regulated by means
of political institutions that acquire their legitimization through democratic decision-making. The genesis of this phenomenon has been
wonderfully described and analyzed in what I think is one of the
jewels of Shmuel Eisenstadts monumental work over the past half
centurythe book Paradoxes of Democracy (Eisenstadt 1999b). It is a
short textalmost an essaybut one that very well reects his profound knowledge and his rich experience in these matters.
One of the main reasons why in the Western world the modern
nation-state was able to develop the way it did, was the sucient
degree of cultural and political homogeneity among individuals and
groups who were part of it. The idea that everyoneor virtually
everyonebelonged to the same nation provided a sense of togetherness and a collective identity, which became stronger than the
divisive forces that equally existed. As the institutions of the nationstates expanded, largely through improved communications and the
development and spreading of educational and social policies, the
sense of togetherness was further reinforced. Those states that included
more than one pre-existing natione.g. Belgium, Switzerland, Canada,
Spainhave more or less successfully learnt how to cope with their
dierences. They usually do so through forms of institutional devolution. Besides, over the years, most modern nation-states have also
come to terms with religion and its potentially divisive power in societies that are not homogeneous in that respect. As Shmuel Eisenstadt
stated, bringing the City of God into the city of man almost by
192
han entzinger
denition excludes pluralism. It is that tension that the modern nationstate has been able to overcome, at least seemingly.
Much more recently, the modern nation-state has again been confronted with a potentially divisive phenomenon, which is immigration. It should be stated right away that immigration is not new to
all democratic societies in the world. In certain cases it is even part
of the national ideology. National identity has been constructed
and shaped around immigration in countries such as the USA,
Canada and Australia. However, that does not imply that immigration is unproblematic in those countries. Immigration not only disrupts the existing social, economic and political order, but it also
forces societies to reconstitute their collective identitiesan issue
recently back in the forefront of the social sciences. Nation-states
always look somewhat like gated communities: they are weary of
newcomers, even though they know very well that their future may
depend on them. This weariness is particularly acute when newcomers look dierent and behave dierently, as newcomers often do.
Their initial response is one of exclusion, rather than of inclusion.
Countries that have much more recently been confronted with immigration, particularly those in Western Europeand increasingly also
those in Central Europetend to be even more weary of its consequences. The basic question here is how liberal democratic societies that formally acknowledge cultural pluriformity, actually handle
the increase in pluriformity thatalmost by denitioncomes along
with immigration.
Of course, in our Western societies people are free to organize
themselves on the basis of common interests, and in the majority of
cases this also applies to immigrants. A more pluriform society is
also likely to produce a more pluriform civil society and a more pluriform market. That is not our primary interest here. The idea is
how the state itself comes to terms with plurality, or with multiculturalism, as it is often referred to in the context of immigration. On
the basis of the comparative work carried out by many of our
colleagues and myself on a considerable number of immigration countries in the Western world, it is possible to develop a continuum that
reects the degree of institutionalization of dierence that results
from immigration. On this continuum I distinguish ve positions,
which I shall briey describe.
1. The neutral state, which treats all its citizens in the same way
and considers culture to be a private aair. The Jacobin French tra-
multiculturalism revisited
193
194
han entzinger
1
Interestingly, the much-condemned system of apartheid in pre-1994 South Africa
had the same roots as pillarisation: the basically Calvinist idea that communities
who share the same cultural background should be self-governing in as many elds
as possible (sovereignty in ones own circle). The big dierence, however, was
that under apartheid a hierarchy of communities existed: some had more rights and
entitlements than others.
multiculturalism revisited
195
196
han entzinger
The ve positions I have just described are far from static. That
is, the positions may remain unchanged, but countries and their policies tend to move along the continuum. Approaches may change as
immigration changes, as governments change, as the economy and
the employment situation change, et cetera. The initial choice of a
country upon its rst confrontation with immigration often tells us
more about that country than about its immigrants. Thus, it is understandable that France opted for the culture is a private aair
approach, while the Netherlands preferred institutionalized multiculturalism. In order to be eective in defending their interests, immigrants should familiarize themselves as much as possible with the
habits of the country where they live and get organized in accordance with the pattern commonly used in that country. In his comparative study on lobbying practices of the Moroccan community in
four dierent European cities, Hassan Bousetta found that in each
case Moroccans were more eective as they adapted themselves
better to local circumstances (Bousetta 2001).
On the whole, it is interesting to observe that the further one goes
North in Europe, the more traces one nds of institutionalized multiculturalism. This is not always because it is the traditional way of
dealing with diversity, as is the case in the Netherlands. The fact
that the North European countries have a particularly strong public sector may equally be of importance. A strong public sector almost
seems an imperative for state supported multiculturalism. Surprisingly,
therefore, institutionalized multiculturalism seems to ourish better
in a welfare state, where opportunities for public intervention tend
to be stronger than in societies where more is being left to private
initiative or the market.
Exploring the limits of multiculturalism
In recent years we have witnessed considerable changes in the way
many countries in Europe are dealing with immigration and its longterm eects. Frances recent struggles with the headscarves indicate
that that country cannot totally ignore the relevance of cultural
dierence, although its traditional ideology points in a dierent direction. The presence of almost ve million Muslims in that country,
the signicant transformations in the banlieues of Paris and other large
cities, simply require certain forms of recognition and acceptance of
multiculturalism revisited
197
198
han entzinger
multiculturalism revisited
199
200
han entzinger
the need for acceptance and change. This situation may legitimize
the country of origin in its eorts to exercise political and other
inuences on its diaspora citizens. Of course, in todays globalizing
world we are getting increasingly familiar with transnationalism, a
phenomenon that has become quite popular in certain academic
circles (Portes et al. 1999; Vertovec & Cohen 1999; Faist 2000).
Migrants can indeed identify and have contacts with more than one
country at a time. However, an almost complete avoidance of contacts with the receiving society, as is the case for certain immigrants
in Europe, forces that society to reconsider its diversity policies.
4. A fourth reason why institutionalized multiculturalism has been
losing ground is its growing complexity as immigration continues and
becomes more diverse, and as the number of immigrant communities grows. It may be feasible to set up arrangements of the types
discussed earlier for four or ve communities, but it becomes much
more complex if their numbers increase further. Besides, many groups
are too small and too much dispersed to create a sound basis for
own institutional provisions. This is a strong conceptual dierence
with classical Dutch pillarisationas described by Lijphart (1975)
where the various groups needed one another in order to reach compromises and to create majorities. At the national level, todays
immigrant communities simply are too small for that, and therefore
not suciently relevant. Only in larger metropolitan areas with substantial immigrant or ethnic minority populations, in Europe and
elsewhere, can we observe that ethnicity or immigrant status continues to play a role in the forging of alliances and in local policymaking. This phenomenon was rst analyzed and described for New
York City by Nathan Glazer and Daniel Moynihan in their classical Beyond the Melting Pot (Glazer & Moynihan 1963).
5. Perhaps the most important objection against institutionalized
multiculturalism is that it insuciently accounts for shifts that take
place in immigrants cultural orientation. Every social anthropologist knows
that identities are dynamic, dened as they are by the surrounding
conditions. This is even more so for migrant identities. There is overwhelming research evidence that migrants identities and their orientations change as time goes by. For those who are familiar with
one of Shmuel Eisenstadts earliest works The Absorption of Immigrants,
this is not new (Eisenstadt 1954). In that work, still a classic in
migration studies, he analyzed the sequence of the adaptation process
of newcomers to Israel, in which he found a number of regularities.
multiculturalism revisited
201
202
han entzinger
adapt to its basic values, particularly those that are not codied in
legislation. To what extent can this approach be reconciled with freedom of religion, and also with other freedoms and rights to which
anyone, including migrants, is entitled in a liberal society?
My personal viewpoint of this is that any society, including immigrant societies, must require from its members a certain degree of
identication with a common core. But, in the footsteps of Habermas
and Parekh, I shall not go any further than advocating a sucient
degree of what the former calls Verfassungpatriottismus (constitutional
patriotism), and the latter calls civic assimilation. (Habermas 1995;
Parekh 2000). Newcomers may be required to identify unconditionally with the public sector and its institutions, even though these are
not totally unchangeable. Newcomers may be forced to comply with
the demands of these institutions, among which the law has a very
prominent place. Otherwise, they must be free to preserve their own
heritage and their own ties and connections, if they wish to do so.
At most, the public authorities may have a facilitating role in these
matters.
This approach leaves more room for individual and group dierences
in the private sphere than in the public sphere. Of course, this will
produce social and cultural tensions and clashes of the types described,
inter alia, by Carens (2000). However, the essence of a liberal-democratic system is that it must give room to divergent ideas and divergent behavior up to the point where these actively seek to overthrow
the system. This is by no means always the case in situations of cultural pluriformity. Flexibility and a great capacity for absorption have
always been dominant characteristics of our Western, strongly individualist cultures.
To illustrate this last point I once more quote some of the results
of our survey of Rotterdam youngsters (Phalet et al. 2000; Entzinger
2003a). It is remarkable how strongly both native and immigrant
youngsters are aware of dierences between the public and the private spheres, and of the fact that dierent attitudes may prevail in
each of these. In the public sphere 80 per cent of the Moroccans
and 75 per cent of the Turks were convinced that integration should
be the rule. They showed themselves willing to adapt to the rules
of Dutch society, basically on the condition that the Dutch would
accept them as fellow-citizens. By contrast, in the private sphere this
readiness to adapt was only expressed by 35 per cent of the Moroccans
and 32 per cent of the Turks. The Dutch control group, asked about
multiculturalism revisited
203
204
han entzinger
CHAPTER TEN
206
dominique schnapper
207
208
dominique schnapper
209
210
dominique schnapper
The abstraction and rationality of citizenship cannot, alone, organize democratic society. On its own, the civic principle is not sucient
to allow individuals to live togetherindividuals who need to share
a culture, values and emotions in order to make a society. Democratic
societies cannot only be civic. They are also inevitably and simultaneously ethnic (in the sense of a shared history, be it real or
invented, a shared culture and a common project) and civic
(Schnapper 1994). The specicity of a society organized according
to the principle of citizenship as opposed to other modes of political organization is that the values and institutions of citizenship must,
in the nal analysis, prevail over ethnic or religious particularism,
and over domestic and clan-like solidarities.
Furthermore, the French Revolution demonstrated insuciency of
Reason in regards to the organization of social life. The revolutionaries opposed to the pre-modern world a Reason which was
neither rational nor controlled, but just as zealous as the religious
zeal it was supposed to surpass. The People and the Homeland took
the place of God as objects of identication which, from then on,
were seen as spontaneous. The zeal of individuals in the name of
Reason was no less zealous than their ethnic-religious identications.
In addition, passions are neither necessarily exclusive nor condemnable. It is inevitable and perhaps even desirable to develop
holistic values when they do not contradict common values. As Louis
Dumont argued, the art of politics also involves bending the law,
or rather adding to it secondary elements, which if applied without
limitation, would contradict the original spirit of the law (Dumont
1991: 270). And as Todorov has also pointed out: Demanding equal
legal rights for all does not in any way imply a renunciation of a
hierarchy of values; cherishing the autonomy and freedom of individuals does not oblige us to reject all sense of solidarity (Todorov,
1989: 436).
Should we therefore conclude that the eects of citizenship on the
dierent forms of social life are limited because of the limits of human
rationality, and that the rise of ethnic, religious or ethnic-religious
forms that we are observing today reect the insuciency of rationality in its attempt to respond to the need for shared emotion and
explanation of individual and collective misfortunes which the premodern ethnic-religious world provided?
This interpretation is based on the notion that only rationality can
211
212
dominique schnapper
Without taking this analysis to its logical conclusion, one can argue
that the utopian nature of the society of citizens, allied with the
Promethean project of mastering the natural world through scientic
and technical progress, explains the refusal of all limits which characterizes democracy today. Ill just briey give some examples: the
refusal of limits in the denition of the political body, and as regards
the material and moral well-being of individuals, reticence regarding
the acceptance of a limit to the age of procreation, reticence regarding
the acceptance of adversity, old age and deatheverything which
conditions the human condition.
The dynamic of democracy rst of all exercised its inuence on
the denition of the political body. As we know, after having declared
the universality of the citizen, the revolutionaries of 1791 in France
then proceeded to exclude a whole series of categories of the
population from active citizenship. The poor, indigenous peoples
of the colonies, women, and young people only possessed the rights
of passive citizens. The history of universal surage reveals the
potentially universal vocation of citizenship. Indeed, the above categories of the population were gradually accorded citizenship rights
in the name of the universal values of the Revolution: the poor, and
the indigenous peoples in 1848, women in 1944, young people aged
between 18 and 21 and the newly naturalized in 1974. It was in
the name of universal principles that the colonized peoples demanded
the citizenship rights that the colonizers had declared, but then
reserved for themselves alone. There is an internal dynamic within
democracy, which tends, in accordance with its own values, to enlarge
the political body.
Today, when it would seem that universal surage has been established, three great debates are raging as to the legal limits that still
aect the denition of the political body. The rst of these debates
concerns children. At what age do they really become full citizens?
Up until what age is it legitimate not to accord children the right
to vote, although they are subject to the constraints of the political
order? Some argue that the vote should be accorded at 16 years of
age, or even earlier, as soon as they are obliged to exercise a certain amount of responsibility, be it civil, penal or nancial. The
second area of debate is expressed through the theories of those who
argue in favor of citizenship rights based on residence. According to
those in favor of residence-based citizenship, the exclusion of nonnationals from strictly political practice (the right to vote and to be
213
elected), whilst they already benet from equal economic and social
rights, contradicts democratic values, since through their very presence
or residence, foreign nationals are an integral part of the national
society. In other words, imposing nationality as the pre-requisite for
citizenship is regarded as illegitimate. It is argued that citizenship
rights should be automatically granted to all those residing on the
national territory, and some even argue that citizenship rights should
be accorded to those who are illegally resident. Finally, at the instigation of international activists who defend the political rights of
animals, a third debate is developing around the Great Ape project.
This debate, although somewhat absent in France, is very active in
the Anglophone world. These thinkers argue that it is in keeping
with democratic values, that the Great Apes (orangutans, chimpanzees,
gorillas), which share most of their genetic capital with humans and,
like humans, are subject to the consequences of political decisions
in the human societies in which they live, should be accorded political
rights. These thinkers adopt similar positions to the advocates of
deep ecology who argue in favor of according rights to the natural
world. The debates around these theories illustrate the weakening of
the frontier between human beings, dened by their freedom and
responsibility, and animalsa barrier established by Christian tradition and humanist thought. This push to extend the limits of the
political body continues to develop, thus demonstrating the force of
the democratic dynamic. A book which was recently translated into
many European languages over the last few yearsthus revealing
the vast interest in the questiongives us another almost caricaturelike example. The book is entitled Towards a General Democracy: Direct,
Economic, Ecological and Social Democracy. Indeed, the title is explicit; it
is in favor of what we can call total democracy, a democracy that
knows no limits or bounds.1
The contemporary development of social rights in particular reects
the democratic ambition to guarantee concrete equality for all. The
development of the welfare state, which was fully established at the
end of the Second World War in liberal Europe is the instrument
of social rights. The term welfare state should not be limited to
its strict or classic sense, that is, implying the protection of individuals against disease, old age, family dependency, unemployment, nor
214
dominique schnapper
2
This phenomenon concerns all European countries, but it is the most developed and theorized in France.
215
and social criteria. Hence successive Town Policies have been adopted
over the past twenty years in order to: (1) re-dynamise the poorest
neighborhoods, where the population of foreign origin makes up the
majority of inhabitants, and (2) encourage the integration of these
inhabitants. In the same vein, there is the Education Action Zone
policy (ZEP), involving the accordance of greater funds to schools
in these neighborhoodsa measure which would be described as a
multicultural policy in other countries. In all cases, it is a question
of trying to dene new categories of the population who continue
to be dened in social or geographical termsbut which crudely
correspond to ethnicised categories due to the spatial concentration
of these populationsand allowing them to benet from the transfer of a part of the collective resources, so as to re-establish or
guarantee concrete equality for all.
This is the reason why the welfare state decit is not solely linked
to the economic and nancial crisis. Rather, it is a structural decit.
By denition, the need for security, well-being and equality are
indenite and self-perpetuating as societies transform. Individuals
demands become more and more pressing as they are given satisfaction. This phenomenon is illustrated by the new professions that
are constantly being invented in order to respond to growing demands
and which go as far as to include domestic pets, who have now
become the objects of medical care. The welfare state feeds dissatisfaction because the response to demands is always delayed and
the resources are by denition limited, unlike the unlimited number
of demands.
This desire to guarantee real equalityto use the classic Marxist
opposition between formal and real freedom and equalityhas
the eect of particularizing the states actions. The state decides
which new categories of the population are to benet from a new,
specially designed policy. In the face of the ever-growing demands,
the state responds by ever-more specic measures in order to guarantee more security, more well-being for individuals and greater
equality for all. As a result, state intervention increases and becomes
increasingly specic, and so entrenched that it is not easily reversed.
A section of society becomes welfar-ised, or providential; that is,
it becomes linked to the intervention of the welfare state and its
inevitable bureaucratization.
A nal illustration of the refusal of limits as regards the human
condition: the cult of the body, sporting success, youth and health,
216
dominique schnapper
Upon arrival in the West, the Soviet writer, Boukovski, argued that what he
had before him was an adolescent society searching to accumulate contradictory
advantages.
217
218
dominique schnapper
219
have economic, cultural and social resources, i.e., for those who actually have an ability to create ties out of individualism. We should
not forget that strong institutions protect the most vulnerable and
the weakest members of society.
These spontaneous and immediate references to beliefs and historical collectivities challenge the institutions of the community of
citizens. As a result of its own internal dynamic, democratic aspiration runs the risk of undermining its own legitimacy. By increasingly
recognizing ethnic-religious particularisms in the public space, by
legitimating the outbreak of spontaneous emotion at the expense of
institutional control, by challenging the political and religious institutions inherited from the past, democratic practice weakens common
institutions and the control they once exercised over human zeal and
emotion. The civic is a principle of inclusion, even if in reality, it
inevitably has its limits. On the other hand, ethnic-religious belonging
is a principle of exclusion, even if it can in reality be corrected and
amended. The very principle of the society of citizens implies a
society which is open to all those who are able to participate in
political life. A society which is organized around the principle of
citizenship is, by denition, more open to others than communities
which are dened in religious, cultural or historical terms. All national
organizations envisage the foreign nationals right to gain access to
the political community, as long as a certain number of conditions
xed by the state are respected. It is possible to obtain French, Swiss
or German nationality through naturalization, even if the conditions
imposed on the candidate dier in each case. On the contrary, one
belongs to the Corsican people by birth; one does not become
Corsican. Moreover, if Corsica were to become a sovereign nation,
it would not be able to envisage the legal and administrative means
by which certain individuals would be able to obtain Corsican nationality. Rabbis render entry into the Jewish community as it is dened
by religious tradition, dicult. However, the state of Israel has admitted as Israeli citizens, a large number of individuals who are not
Jewish, or who would not be recognized as Jewish by rabbinical
courts.
To what extent is it feasible to institutionally recognize specic
identities without calling into question the shared public domain
where, within a given nation-state, individuals who identify with particular historical communities, can live together thanks to the rules
of citizenship? To what extent can historical or religious multicul-
220
dominique schnapper
221
CHAPTER ELEVEN
224
ralf dahrendorf
225
and much violent conictto come to terms with its minorities and
today Arthur Schlesinger is not the only one to note the disuniting
of America. Switzerland is perhaps an example, but one may well
doubt whether it can be described as a nation-state. Israel is in some
ways an example, but only within the common assumptions of the
varied Jewish communities gathered in this country.
Sometimes I feel that the only real example of a truly heterogeneous liberal community is London whose nearly ten million citizens are as varied as one can imagine. But in London too we nd
one feature which I believe is almost generally characteristic of pluralist arrangements: In the public sphere London is a successful
community of many cultures; but the nearer one gets to the personal sphere, the more separate its cultural communities remain.
Jewish Finchley and Bangladeshi Tower Hamlets, West Indian Brixton
and Indian pockets in many places are clearly recognizable and
unmistakably dierent from each other. There is a plural input into
the common sphere, but at the same time a plurality of separate
cultural spheres.
In the 1960s, some of us fought a losing battle against the slogan, separate but equal. We thought that this was not enough.
Equality was only the beginning of a process which we thought would
end up with total intermixture, e pluribus unum in an almost biological
sense. Today, after the experience of armative action and race riots
in European cities and numerous small and not so small clashes of
civilizations, one is tempted to say that separate but equal is in
many cases the best we can hope for. Pluralism will not mean a
blending of cultures but a clearly delineated toleration of dierences
as long as certain common public rules are accepted. Pluralism fails
to create unity. Above all it fails to create a sense of belonging which
is so important for people. It is one of those abstract ideals which
engage the heads but not the hearts of people.
The consequences of such pluralism without integration are quite
serious. The rules of public life are barely sucient to hold communities together. The groups involved are themselves not static
either in numbers or in aspirations. Demography plays a part:
Catholics, or Palestinians, or immigrantsit is saidhave more
children and will soon try to dominate the rest by the sheer weight
of their numbers. The result is conict, hidden at rst, then occasionally explosive, and potentially leading to deep cleavages bordering
on divisive civil wars. Where this is not the case, the demand for
226
ralf dahrendorf
227
interests of the plurality. And how about the two men holding hands?
Yes, they should be allowed to do so, but must they do it while
walking down a road, that is in public? Is it not one necessary condition of an eective pluralist society that some of the diversity is
displayed only in private?
Above all: what exactly holds a society for which freedom is precious and which therefore accepts plurality in the preferences of its
members together? How does it avoid self-destruction by the gradual
slide from pluralism to anomy? How does it dene the boundaries
within which plurality becomes fruitful without closing itself o from
the unceasing exploration of new horizons?
Shmuel Einsenstadts analyses are sustained by an impressive developmental optimism. For him, the imagination of societies is virtually
unlimited. If problems such as those of pluralism arise, something
new will be invented, and this will still be a version of modernity.
In all societies these attempts at interpreting modernity are continually changing under the impact of changing historical forces,
giving rise to new movements that will come, in time, to reinterpret
yet again the meaning of modernity. There are truly multiple
modernities including de-Westernised ones which are not only
viable but acceptable.
If this sweeping view of comparative civilizations leaves the Westerner
a little breathless, and one remains nearer home in ones analysis of
the contradictions of modernity, the key question remains unresolved:
How can we avoid the two risks of pluralism, that of tenuous verzuiling,
of separateness without centre, and that of total uidity, of a world
in which anything goes? This is where the distinction between
pluralistic and totalistic modernities ceases to be helpful, because
it fails to enable us to answer the question of the basis of solidarity
in pluralistic societies. A set of dominant values and concomitant
institutions is needed to make diversity fruitful and avoid the twin
risks of anarchy and anomy.
This is of course an old subject, and historical societies have found
a number of answers to the issue. In the case of the United States
what Tocqueville identied as civic religion had and continues to
have a strong binding force. In the case of Britain, the much-maligned
class system served to uphold a sense of dominant values by which
all tended to abide. The same may also be true for countries like
Sweden, though there it is less agrantly based on social class. All
these historical ligatures however have been under pressure for some
228
ralf dahrendorf
time. The result has been a sense of confusion and dissolution, and
coupled with it, a growing readiness to embrace totalising substitutes
for the loss of benign sources of solidarity. Versions of fundamentalism have often taken the place of traditional linkages.
Liberal alternatives are not easy to nd. Jrgen Habermas has
long advocated what he calls (with a term borrowed from the conservative publicist Dolf Sternberger) constitutional patriotism as a
source of solidarity in pluralist societies. Unless this assumes some
of the features of a civic religion, as it used to in the United States,
it seems a strangely abstract project. This is even more the case if
one follows the more recent attempt by Habermas and others to
apply such sentiments to Europe, the European Union. Some of the
exaggerated hopes of intellectuals in the so-called European constitutionit is in fact merely a treaty between stateshave to do with
the search for an identity which creates a sense of solidarity. In the
light of day however this is a very long way away if it is ever to be
a realistic prospect.
My own preferences are of a more traditional kind. When John
Stuart Mill talked about nationality as a denition of the political
space within which a hundred owers can blossom, he had in mind
sets of values associated with what we loosely call countries. To be
sure, it is hard to contradict Eisenstadt and others when they point
out that the nation-state has lost some of its charm and much of its
power in an age of globalization; but it is still there, and it is still
the most eective space for the liberal order to ourish. Larger spaces
of action are diuse and removed from checks and balances, and
smaller ones have a built-in totalizing tendency.
Beyond the nation-state, I would be more reluctant than Shmuel
Eisenstadt to allow Western values to be submerged in an ocean of
multiple modernities. De-Westernization is more often than not deliberalization. The enlightened belief in the responsible use of reason, and the institutions which go with the acceptance of the basic
uncertainty of the human condition, are quite a good guide to a
world in which pluralism is contained without totalising risks. It may
not be enough to return to Kant and further to Hume, but it is a
good beginning.
CHAPTER TWELVE
230
alain touraine
we are not unaware of the fact that other societies have used concepts of another sort, in particular political ones, to do the same
task. The rst centuries of modernity were dominated by the use of
political categories and the main elds of analysis were the formation of absolute monarchiesafter that of the city-statesthen the
appearance of nation-states, rst in the Netherlands and in Great
Britain, then later in the British colonies in America when they
gained their independence, and above all in France at the time of
the Revolution. All these political changes have been of major importance. For a long time, our vision of society was shaped on the basis
of political terms and analyses. And since our representation of social
life has not always been social, why should we not wonder today
if this social vision is not beginning to disappear or even whether
it has not already been replaced by another vision? But before making
a judgment about the disappearance of this social representation of
society, we ought to specify the content of this vision. It is primarily dened by recourse to the idea of society, which is not merely
a means of describing a concrete entitywe talk about English society in 1900but also a principle for evaluating Good and Evil, as
a principle of denition of values, norms and forms of authority:
anything which reinforces society, its integration, its capacity to act
upon itself and also to adapt to necessary changes, is good; anything
which undermines this integration, increases its internal conicts and
renders most social relations unmanageable, is bad. This concept of
society is based on notions of institutions and socialization: institutions give legal shape to the treatment of a number of important
social functions and are also responsible for enforcing respect for
established norms. The word socialization has been used to speak
of all forms of education, which implied that the aims of education,
at school or in the family, were eectively to train citizens and
workers. This is an indication of the extent to which the idea of
society has really been the keystone of the whole social representation of social life.
The concept of society is so strong that good sociologists attempt
to restrict its applications rather than to extend them. It is indeed
tempting to consider that all the aspects of a concrete society,
historically and geographically dened, form a system, fullling positive or negative functions for society. In fact, many sociologists have
recalled, quite correctly, that phenomena which were very dierent
in kind, and had little relation to one another, could be juxtaposed
231
in the same space and time. Marxist sociology has pushed the idea
of society to the extreme by giving an unlimited power of explanation to the idea of capitalism, dened in terms of social relationships
of production, class domination and the subordination of all aspects
of social life to the domination of prot and its beneciaries. We
are still living, in part at least, in a period of post-Marxism in which
we are oered key principles of explanation which are social in
nature and eectively account for a great variety of observable phenomena. The most important example of this post-Marxism today
is provided by radical, particularly American, feminism, of which the
most outstanding analyses endeavor to show that all the categories
concerning women and sexual behavior have been constructed to
provide monopoly to heterosexual relations in which women are
dominated.
The only powerful enemy of the idea of society has been that of
rationalization, that is to say, the triumph of reason. Today, like
yesterday, many defend the idea that human beings act, both individually and collectively, in function of the rational pursuit of their
interests and that social organization calls on increasing rationality
which can be seen both in the use of new technologies and in the
capacity to forecast consumer behavior. But this sort of vision, which
has many practical applications, cannot be easily applied to the population and social organization as a whole. A great deal is said about
the irrationality of the working classes, the bureaucratic routine and
the lack of long-term perspectives for small entrepreneurs or farmers to explain the non-rational aspects of a society. These limits of
a rationalist vision are so powerful that sociology, based on the idea
of society, has always been critical of its optimism and the simplistic nature of this elementary form of utilitarianism. The inadequacies so frequently mentioned of a purely economistic representation
of social behavior have led most sociologists to prefer analyses loaded
with subjective meanings and references to norms and values. This
social representation of society, which corresponds to what we call
sociology or, at least, classical sociology, cannot be identied with a
political position. Nor is it enough to oppose conservatives to radicals or communitarians to liberals.
Firstly, because terms of this sort always have a very restricted
geographical sphere of application: whoever seems a moderate in
Buenos Aires is considered a radical in Boston and a conservative
in Berlin. In fact, by far the majority of sociologists lie within a
232
alain touraine
233
234
alain touraine
culture leaves little possibility to those who wish to impose their point
of view. At the level of personal life, this desocialization often takes
the form of frequent breaks in occupational life which, for many,
consists of a haphazard series of temporary jobs, part-time contracts
or unemployment.
How can we dene ourselves as social actors when our main concern has become to defend ourselves, and our loved ones, against
the misfortunes, crises and catastrophes which can hit us unavoidably
without warning? In fact, the forces which seem to command the
world today can no longer be dened in social terms. The best example is that of money, and in particular of the market; the second is
war, including the monopoly of information and forecasting. The
world which we refer to as social, of which we were attempting to
understand the norms and the procedures, as much to criticize as
to adopt them, seems to be drifting and even disintegrating, torn
between money and war. We could call societies today post-social,
meaning they no longer have internal control over themselves. One
could, for example, imagine speaking about Israel in these terms, a
country founded on a set of collective goals and development projects, a capacity for the integration of newcomers, with scientic
amenities of the highest level and which is dragged by the weight
of war towards situations, conicts and policies which are very far
from the still recent model of construction of the State of Israel.
This remark is even more appropriate for the Palestinians whose
national construction is still in the making and marked by the violence done to them. The eorts to construct a Palestinian society
seem to be constantly overwhelmed and destroyed by being dragged
into war and by the desire of some to ght to the death. When all
that is destroyed, the sphere of sociology, like that of social life, quite
simply disappears. At a much less dramatic level, how can we fail
to see in many parts of the world, the disappearance of what can
be called an economic system? In many countries, domestic production represents a very small percentage of national income. The
main components are the money sent back by emigrants, foreign
subsidies, smuggling and tracking in arms and in drugs. Only
recently the idea that a country could be dened without reference
to its production, its forms of labor and its social relationships of
production, corresponds to real cases. The situation has changed
rapidly and we may indeed ask whether rises in productivity and
the possibility of obtaining a high standard of living in return for a
235
limited number of hours of labor would not give more decisive importance to the market and to war than to production and distribution.
In other words, are post-social societies not dominated by violence?
It is however impossible for us to wholly indulge in this type
of vision of the planet at the beginning of the century and the
millennium, for while the forces of death and speculation are powerful, it is not true that the lives of human beings, even those who
live in the worst conditions, can be reduced to the domination exercised by non-controllable forces. Politics have not disappeared, quite
the contrary. In contrast with the rst image which we have just
evoked, it is the extension of the public space which is the easiest
to see. The public sphere formed at the time of the bourgeoisie, particularly in the eighteenth century, was overtaken in the nineteenth
century by the elections and by information and education processes
which involved an increasingly large proportion and nally by far
the majority of the population. Today, we live in a society which
we refer to, quite correctly, as a society of mass communication, and
behind the parties and trade unions which are in decline, associations and NGOs have sprung up, forming what we call rather strangely
civil society, whereas it is in fact a question of a new level, much
broader than the previous ones, of political life. We are all concerned by what is going on in the whole world, from events in our
private lives to the catastrophes and hopes which deeply aect the
population as a whole. Thus political and social facts are visible
everywhere in such a way as to constantly occupy our attention.
However, the world of information and communication remains
relatively external to each of us; that is to say, we do not perceive
our world, our environment and our own existence in political and
social terms. These terms are present in the world of television which,
it is true, has an important place in our lives, but we participate in
it as consumers. Television does not construct our world; it distributes images to us that most of us accept willingly but only in so far
as we do not feel involved. We receive the programs; we do not
create them and if we choose them in function of our demands for
a specic type of consumption, we do not exercise, or at least not
directly, an inuence on the programs.
Should we then content ourselves with this dual image of our postsocial world: the alliance of money and power on one hand; and,
on the other hand, the ubiquitous presence of mass communication
which constructs a world of entertainment around us, but which in
236
alain touraine
no way provides us with a mode of construction of our own experience, since the programs from which we have to choose have no
direct reference to our personal life?
Finally, the third component of our experience: the private sphere,
which can also be known as beliefs, culture, passions and anything
which is primarily dened by its non-social content. This world of
private beliefs is not determined in social terms any more than is
the world of the market, of war or of the mass media. In the private sphere, individuals are no longer confronted with anything other
than themselves and their lives can no longer be expressed in any
other terms than those of their experience, which is the denition
of private life. This denition is both weak and strong. It is strong
because the private sphere not only resists by defending itself against
the most brutal forces, but because it occupies all the space which
used to be that of social statuses and roles. But, once again, is it
possible to conceive of a construction of the social sphere on the
basis of the private sphere? Or must we accept in its entirety the
conclusion already envisaged: the complete disappearance of the personal subject, both social and political or even religious, that is to
say, of any principle of organization and representation of social life
or, if we can use this expression, of any subject for itself?
It is impossible to accept this type of conclusion, particularly for
those who have studied collective action and conscience. We must
therefore endeavor to pierce the mystery of private sphere, to nd
there something other than the gaze of self upon itself. There are,
in the private sphere, requirements which are produced by political
or social pressures. The appeal to private life, to a subject oriented
toward itself, is not an expression of weakness but of strength, not
of ight but of positive initiative. What each individual seeks in his
private life is not the trace of past social or political life, which has
been erased; it is the means for a fragmented subject to resist all
the forms of domination and all the languages which have become
restrictive and meaningless. Because we no longer nd any support
around us for the required reconstruction of the sphere of community life, we appeal to what does seem to us essential to defend: pure
interiority, concern for oneself, resorting to all forms of behavior
which bring us back to ourselves, instead of distancing us even further.
We nd similar approaches in all the previous models of struggle
against dependency: the appeal to the nation against the king, to
workers against the employer, etc. An active attitude which implies
237
our hope in our possibility to limit the hold of the external world
on us and, inversely, our capacity to construct, in the outside world,
bases of support, forces of organization and communication, institutions and training methods, which reinforce the free subject. This
theme can be easily developed: the subject is the central reference
by which we resist the environment and construct a mode of
evaluation and judgment capable of guiding our behavior.
But we must waste no time in considering this a libertarian form
of protest, like that of a solitary individual clinging to a raft in the
middle of a storm. If there were no other possible images of liberty
and liberation, we would have to lose hope and give ourselves up
to the waves which, sooner or later, would swallow us up. Luckily,
these romantic images do not give an accurate account of our
situation and real activities. Concern for oneself can be based on
what best resists all forms of social domination and all processes of
disintegration.
In the rst instance, reason. The appeal to reason is primarily a
universalist approach. In opposition to money and war, reason,
whether applied to science, law, economics, administration or to
public works, provides an essential element of what is known as
modernity. The belief in rational thought is associated with the idea
of universalthat is, individualrights set above all other social
attributes. A central expression of this respect of individual rights is
the universalist principle of citizenship as opposed to all forms of
religious, political or other communities. Some may wish to add that
rationality implies distribution of resources and in particular rules
for the production and circulation of goods, services and capital
determined by it. But this sort of sentence is fraught with possible
misunderstandings; it is better to leave it aside. It is impossible to
state that freedom of trade ensures the best distribution of resources,
when this is refuted every day by observable facts. On the other
hand, any system of production has to seek a high level of rationality, even if this level is not best reached by the absence of any
social or political control of the economy. This bringing together of
the recognition of individual rights and the universalism of reason
has founded modernity. The 1789 Declaration of Rights states that
everybody, whatever their origin, opinions and interests, had the
same rights.
Maybe this analysis gives the impression of taking a step backwards
from a social and even political denition of social organization,
238
alain touraine
based uniquely on natural law, perhaps even on a religious conception of human experience. This impression is not false. To leave
behind a pure social vision of social life, we have to base ourselves on universalist principles; we do this with increasing frequency
and insistence by referring to human rights to better condemn
totalitarian and authoritarian regimes. But this only takes us half way
and we have to round o this reference to the Enlightenment by an
approach which is not in opposition to it but which gives it a content and therefore a very dierent meaning from its own. The appeal
to human rights has long since descended from its metaphysical
pedestal.
In past centuries, in some parts of the world at least, we have
seen natural law becomes civil and political rights. This was proclaimed most explicitly by the Declaration of the Rights of Man and
of the Citizen. But very rapidly, this call for civil rights which
corresponded to a political vision of society, was bypassed and replaced
by major battles for the conquest of social rights and in particular
the right to work, which were developed as from the end of the
nineteenth century, in the rst instance in Germany and in Great
Britain. And now the decline of the social representation of social
life confronts us with the need to defend the right of each individual to defend his or her culture, that is to act according to both
their personal projects and the heritage they have received, especially
from their family and by virtue of their awareness of belonging to
a cultural, religious and linguistic community. It is possible and necessary to go further still by invoking the right to live and to choose
ones sexuality to begin with, and then ones personality as a whole,
shaped both in the family environment and by real-life experience.
The result is that we are getting closer and closer to the theme of
private life as an extreme form of individualism. We demand recognition in all aspects of our personal life. The old idea that the liberty of the individual is best ensured by participation in social life
and its institutions is replaced by the completely opposite idea
namely that the liberty of the individual is only ensured by his
liberationat least in partfrom social roles and attributes. We no
longer believe in the creation of a wise and rational society; on the
contrary, we accept more negative images of society as a terrain
where violence is never controlled.
But it is dicult to be precise about exactly where there is continuity or discontinuity between the universalism of the Enlightenment
239
240
alain touraine
241
242
alain touraine
243
244
alain touraine
is very dierent from the slow but regular advance towards equality
to which so many thinkers have referred in the past. It is true that
we must salute womens victories and support their eorts towards
equality which could result, as many feminists have indicated, in the
gradual elimination of the categories of sex and gender, since in
many professional activities and other areas, it would not matter
whether one dealt with a woman or a man. But the position which
I have just taken is dierent in kind. It is no longer a question of
a gradual disappearance of inequality and consequently of the advance
towards a unisex society, but on the contrary of the reversal, not
from a masculine cultural model to a feminine cultural model, but
from masculine domination to an outdistancing by and for women
of the polarization and ranking which have characterized masculine
society. This remark is conrmed by the fact that the pairs of opposites which have played such a central role over the past centuries
social thought are attacked and demolished. On all sides, the separation between body and mind, intelligence and sensibility, the interior and the exterior, private and public life, war and peace, are
destroyed or transgressed. Everywhere, we see the reconstruction of
a reintegrated, reunied notion, beyond a polarized view of social
life, but quite opposed at the same time to the completely destructured
image of a post-modern society. Thus what seemed to us in the rst
instance to be the decline of the social representation of collective
life can now be re-interpreted as the birth of a post-social, cultural
model of representation and action. This post-social model has nothing to do with post-modernity, but, on the contrary, it forces us to
raise the issue of hypermodernity, because it is in this new model
of representation and action that the self-transforming action of society appears to be the strongest and above all with the least intermediaries. The political model, like the social model, led to the
creation of objects of knowledge and action dened in an almost
natural manner, especially since Auguste Comte, with the result
that political or sociological theories were often tempted to free themselves from a historical analysis to lead into a general theory of systems. This general approach which has nurtured and sustained social
thought brilliantly for so long is now on the way out. The creative
capacity, instead of grappling with outside objects, has turned inwards
to become an end in itself and to better resist both economic and
military forces and communitarian ideology.
CHAPTER THIRTEEN
246
bernhard giesen
248
bernhard giesen
250
bernhard giesen
252
bernhard giesen
Tragically failing heroism
254
bernhard giesen
give them back their names, their faces and their place within the
community.
During the last century the gure of the victim has gained in
attraction as a symbolic representation of individual and collective
identity (Giesen 2004). A well-known case is that of Benjamin
Wilkomirski who claimed to have escaped the Vilna Ghetto as a
child and to suer from a trauma of victimization. After much public acclaim for his autobiography, critics discovered that it was pure
imagination and ction. The suering of the past seems increasingly
to provide an attractive reference for the imagination of collective
identity: the victim replaces the hero as a gure of heightened
subjectivity.
Conicts and debates about public recognition of a groups claim
to victimhood are, certainly, driven by hidden interests. Big money
is at stake; self-appointed advocates of victims stage their cause in
public arenas and require compensation. But revealing these interests does not answer the question why these claims are publicly
recognized, why people visit monuments remembering the victims of
the past, why, today, serious intellectual debates about collective identity focus more on victims than on heroes?
Explanations of this remarkable phenomenon cannot ignore the
level of structure and culture. The collective identity of victims is,
of course, a retrospective one: it is not our own suering here and
now, but the suering of the past, the suering of others that is
turned into an identity of the present. As individuals, African Americans
and Jewish Americans today can hardly claim to be victims, but they
can claim the collective identity of a group whose members have
been victimized in the past. The gure of the victim seems to gain
salience as a pattern of collective identity when the surviving individual victims are disappearing (Giesen 2004). There is also another
structural reason for the increasing focus on victims. In identifying
with the victims of the past we retroactively avoid the position of
the bystander, the uninvolved third-party who ignored the suering
and failed to intervene (Hilberg 1992). When we identify with victims and remember their suering, we reverse their depersonalization; we give them back their names, their faces, and their place
within the community. A hidden and haunting awareness of the dangers of objectication in modern social systems might foster this
retroactive recognition of personhood. What has been treated as an
object is invested with the qualities of a subject again (Bauman 1989).
256
bernhard giesen
258
bernhard giesen
transmitted from generation to generation. Furthermore, the JudeoChristian tradition is a paradigm case of an axial-age culture: the
mundane history is contrasted sharply with the impersonal principles of the transcendental realm, politics and moral are opposites
(Eisenstadt 1996a). Taken together, these cultural codes crystallize in
the gure of the innocent individual who charismatizes himself by
assuming the guilt of the collectivity he represents. In a way the
German chancellor Willy Brandt performed Christomimesis when he
kneeled down and humiliated himself ritually in order to save his
people (Giesen 2004).
In contrast, the non-axial-age Japanese culture can hardly conceive of the community as guilty. Individual persons can be wrong
and guilty, but the Japanese nation is seen as primordially sacred:
the Tenno himself is divine and there is no way of appealing to
higher principles for criticizing the representation of the sacred
(Eisenstadt 1986c). It has been noted before that Japan is a paradigm case of a culture of shame that can be contrasted to the Western
culture of guilt (Benedict 1946). For reasons that are dierent but
equally fundamental, Turkey bans and persecutes any open admittance of a national responsibility for the Genocide on the Armenians.
It was Kemal Atatrk and his followers who planed and executed
the mass-murder committed on Armenians because they were considered to be a threat for the ethnic purity of the Turkish nation
state (Bayraktar/Seibel 2004). Thus genocide lies under the foundation stone of modern Turkey. But since there was no defeat that
forced a conversion of heroes into perpetrators (as in the case of
Germany) the Turkish authorities can continue to revere Atatrk as
the founding hero and ignore his responsibility for the genocide.
The Japanese and Turkish cases testify not only to the importance
of comparative analysis of cultures ( Japan is indeed Gods special
gift to comparative sociology as Eisenstadt constantly underlines) but
they also show the shifting imaginations of liminal gures. Like other
symbolic representations of collective identity they too are cultural
constructions determined by a certain temporal and social perspective.
With history passing and social boundaries being crossed triumphant
heroes can be converted into perpetrators, tragically failing heroes
can be interpreted as victims, and we discover that among the nation
of victims there were also collaborators, and that among the nation
of perpetrators there were also tragic heroes and victims.
PART THREE
CHAPTER FOURTEEN
1
In the Agrarian Conditions, Weber analyzes the capitalism of antiquity as a
system and relates it to ancient forms of state organization. He does not take an
interest in religions and their consequences on economic attitudes. In the Replies,
262
wolfgang schluchter
are not taken as testimony that the writer was not working on
the religious history of ancient Judaism, there is plenty of evidence
that actually it was only after 1910 that, in connection with Max
Webers now awakened interest in Asian religions, he was also more
specically examining the history of Israelite-Jewish religion. This eventually came to fruition with his study Ancient Judaism, that from
the start encompassed the whole spectrum from ancient Israel to
early Christianity.2
I shall deal with my theme in four steps: I shall start by saying
something about the major projects, which were complementary, though
not executed simultaneously, on which Max Weber was working from
1910 until his death, and which both remained unnished. These
were his Grundriss article, known under the title Economy and
Society, and the Gesammelte Aufstze zur Religionssoziologie: comparative studies on the economic ethics of worldor rather cultural
religions (1). 3 There follow reections on the unconventional
combination of comparative and developmental viewpoints which
underlies his reconstitution of major processes in religious history (2).
I shall then show that he takes the creations of the Old Testament,
the Bible of the Jews, as the turning pointone might even say
the point of departurefor one of these great processes in religious
history, the development of the Israelite-Jewish-Christian and Islamic
religions (3). Finally, I shall consider whether it is tenable to designate the ancient Jews as a pariah people which, from the forcible
internment4 onwards, that is to say, from the Babylonian exile until
the fall of the second Temple, voluntarily brought itself into this
situation. Max Webers formula on the subject: from a political to
a confessional community.
his concern is the defence of the original thesis of the study on Protestantism. Weber
does indicate in various places that he intends to extend his investigations forward
and backward, and indeed in his nal reply to the critiques of the Protestant Ethic
of 1910 there is even mention of a projected return to ancient Christianity, though
not to ancient Judaism. Cf. Weber, 1982, p. 322.
2
This choice of title is far from self-explanatory, and signals a special approach
to the topic.
3
The title does indeed specify world religions, but Weber says expressly that
Judaism is not a world religion, but rather a cultural religion. For the distinctions
between the concepts of cultural, world and redemptive religions, see Schluchter,
1988, here vol. 2, pp. 24.
4
Weber, 1920, p. 4 (hereafter: RS III). Weber even goes so far as to assert that
voluntary ghetto life had existed long before forcible internment.
263
5
This quotation is taken from the Preface to the publication of the 1st part
of the Grundri der Sozialkonomik, dated 2nd June 1914. The Preface is written
by Max Weber. The choice of words material economic cultural sociology certainly seems strange. Material is indeed comprehensible in this context, as Weber
was trying in his Grundriss article to disregard the relationship of economics to the
particular elements of cultural content, among which he mentions literature, art,
science etc. (MWG I/221, p. 114). What economic cultural sociology may be,
however, is less clear. It must either be an analysis of culture from an economic
standpoint, or else a sociology of culture. This remarkable conceptual denition
could, though, be the expression of Webers intention of emphasizing the importance of each side of the causal relationship to both his theoretical and historical
ponderings, that is to say the economic conditioning of culture as much as the
cultural conditioning of the economy. More will be said on this later. This would
then lead to an economic sociology of literature, an economic sociology of art, etc.
However this may be, possible candidates for this material economic cultural sociology, apart from studies in the sociology of music, which already existed at this
stage, include the essays in the economic ethics of world religions. As the footnote
of 1915 in the Archiv shows, these were obviously alluded to with the rest.
On the Preface and other documents relevant to reconstructing the history of
the emergence of the major projects, see the compilation of Johannes Winckelmann,
1986, here, p. 165, and for an overall view, Wolfgang Schluchter, 2000, pp. 179.
264
wolfgang schluchter
6
Max Weber starts the publication of the essays in ancient Judaism in October
1917 with a footnote that deserves attention, clarifying his further plans: The following presentation (of ancient Judaism, W.S.) is published here omitting the discussion of the Egyptian, Babylonian and Persian conditions. In a future collection
and revised publication (for China, provided with source references and revised), in
combination with other earlier essays, some of them unpublished, the missing part
will be inserted. Cf. Archiv fr Sozialwissenschaft und Sozialpolitik, Volume 44
(1917/1918), p. 52. As Weber never got as far as to ancient Judaism when compiling the Gesammelte Aufstze zur Religionssoziologie, the omitted discussion of
the Egyptian, Babylonian and Persian conditions still remained unpublished, possibly unwritten. Nevertheless, comparative references to these conditions occur repeatedly in the study itself.
7
Archiv fr Sozialwissenschaft und Sozialpolitik Band 41 (1916), p. 1. Weber
used this expression again in the Gesammelte Aufstze zur Religionssoziologie. He
simply changed two years ago to two years before. Cf. Max Weber, Gesammelte
1920, (hereafter RS I) und MWGI/19, p. 83. Where an edition of Max Weber
Gesamtausgabe is available, quotations are also referenced to this.
8
On this subject, see also the editorial report of Hans G. Kippenberg in MWG
I/223, pp. 89f.
265
9
This is not quite true, as Weber got out the manuscript at least once more,
to use it as the basis for a lecture at the University of Vienna in the summer term
of 1918. This was a sort of probationary term that he had insisted on, to see
whether he could accept the invitation to succeed Eugen von Philippovich. Weber
then declined this oer. See also MWG, I/17, p. 12.
10
RS I, p. 15.
266
wolfgang schluchter
11
In this connection, cf. in particular MWG I/222, p. 114. This passage is
especially important in clarifying the original objectives of the Grundriss article.
Weber expressly emphasizes that what matters to him is a general analysis, taking
the particular only by way of examples. He intended to discuss only the general
forms of structure of human communities. And further: The content-related directions of community action are only taken into consideration insofar as they generate forms of structure which are specic in nature and at the same time economically
relevant. The limit thus dened is no doubt extremely uid, but invariably means
that only a few highly universal varieties of community are examined. In what
follows, this is done rst only with regard to general characteristics, where-asas
we shall seeit will only be possible to discuss their forms of development with
some degree of precision at a later stage, in connection with the category of
domination.
267
12
13
268
wolfgang schluchter
14
In the essay on objectivity, it is stated: If we decide to give the name of cultural sciences to such disciplines as observe the processes of human life from the
point of view of their cultural signicance, then social science in our sense is included
in this category. Cf. Max Weber, WL, p. 165. In his lectures at the turn of the
century, Weber was already terming economics a social science.
15
Ibid., p. 166.
16
Ibid., p. 170.
17
Ibid., p. 166. In this connection, it should not be forgotten that the purpose
of Webers essay, in addition to the aims of the new Archiv fr Sozialwissenschaft
269
also wrote a study that was specically based, not on the economic
conditioning of religious manifestation, but on the religious conditioning of economic manifestations, examining phenomena which
specically do not fall within the compass of an economic viewpoint,
even if, in the context of an economic approach, a distinction is
made between economic, economically conditioned and economically
relevant.18 For economically relevant phenomena are rst and foremost non-economic in nature. And for this reason, Weber is primarily concerned in this study to employ a conceptual-methodical
apparatus which departs from that of socio-economics, and to present a causal attribution which, in a complicated manner, links hopes
of salvation and their religious signicance with economic attitudes.
Here he also intended to show how ideas can operate in history,
specically as factors of conditioning and not always as factors conditioned, as postulated, for example, by historical materialism as
the common denominator in a causal explanation of historical reality.19
But even if we abstain from such a Weltanschauung and content
und Sozialpolitik, was to emphasize continuity with its predecessor, the Archiv fr
soziale Gesetzgebung und Statistik. The latter, however, had treated the topics that
it dealt with as socio-economic matters, right from the start. Ibid., p. 161.
18
This Weber did, as is known, in his essay on objectivity, though here he was
to extend the scope of the socio-economic approach beyond the bounds of the permissible. Cf. ibid., p. 162. It immediately becomes clear that this approach in particular is not sucient to encompass the religious conditioning of such economic
manifestations as the spirit of modern capitalism, since for this purpose, to employ
a subsequent formulation, seen from the economic viewpoint, the other side of the
causal relationship is important. Also, in his distinction between the economic, the
economically conditioned and the economically relevant, strictly interpreted, Weber
does not speak at all of a socio-economic approach, and thus of the specic viewpoint of the analysis, but only of socio-economic problems. In my view, it is therefore erroneous, to dene Webers approach in 1904 and thereafter as socio-economic.
In reality, even the study on ascetic Protestantism denitely does not t this designation. For the processes of daily life, no less than the historic events of high
politics, collective and mass manifestations as much as the unique acts of statesmen or individual literary and artistic achievements are simultaneously inuenced
by [material interests, W.S.],economically conditioned. On the other hand, the
totality of all the manifestations and conditions of life of a given historical culture
exert an inuence on the form of material needs, the way in which they are satised,
the formation of material interest groups and the type of their power resources and
thence on the type of process of economic developmentit becomes economically relevant. WL, p. 163. It is also true that the distinction between the economic, the economically conditioned and the economically relevant can be transferred
in an analogous way to all value spheres and life orders, and to all the regulations
and powers of society. Thus cultural manifestations may be religious, religiously
conditioned or religiously relevant.
19
Ibid., p. 166.
270
wolfgang schluchter
20
Ibid., p. 167.
Cf. in this connection WL, pp. 166f. It was not by chance that Weber, in a
letter to Rickert, described his procedure in the Protestantism study as a kind of
spiritual construction of modern economics.
21
271
wolfgang schluchter
272
26
Ibid., p. 12.
273
plemented in 1920 and now enriched with the almost entirely new
essay on the Protestant sectsand the studies on the economic ethics
of world religions. This can also be detected with very little diculty
from the Table of Contents, authorized by himself, of the rst
volume of the Gesammelte Aufstze zur Religionssoziologie. According to
this, the Preliminary Remarks written in 1919/1920 applies to all
the essays, i.e. including the revised version of the Protestant Ethic
and the essay on the Protestant Sects; the Introduction and
Intermediate Reection, on the other hand, apply only to the
Economic Ethics of World Religions, notwithstanding the fact that
all previously published texts were revised. Indeed, the conceptual
apparatus that had been developed since 1904/1905 is used throughout; in the essay The Protestant Ethic and the Spirit of Capitalism
spirit now without quotation marks, this is especially true of the
insertions, which, as elsewhere, are the primary constituent of the
revision. (See Appendix C).27
The primary function of comparisons is to identify peculiarities,
not to explain them.28 Furthermore, they serve to construct sociological concepts. As the construction of concepts is not central to
the essays on the economic ethics of world religions, the principal
use of comparisons here is to determine the specic characteristics
of occidental cultural manifestations. As the above quotation shows,
Weber wishes to pursue Asiatic cultural manifestations only insofar
as it is necessary to nd points of comparison with the occidental
development still to be analysed. We could rephrase this: In this
way, the dierence characteristic of occidental development compared with Asian developments will be identied. Once this has been
done, it will be known what crucial turning points await clarication.
With respect to religious history, it is not only the turning point
related to ascetic Protestantism. More relevant are the turning points
that arose before and after. The subsequent phenomenon that Weber
wanted to examine was the Counter-Reformation. For the preceding
turning points, Weber gives the decisive indication in the revised
27
274
wolfgang schluchter
29
275
34
276
wolfgang schluchter
value-related ideal types. These are heuristic means for causal attribution. At issue is always a particular developmental history whose
reconstruction requires three steps: identication (What is the dening
characteristic of a cultural manifestation?), causal attribution (How
did this manifestation arise?) and prioritization (What weight can be
attributed to one causal factor in relation to other causal factors?).38
The rst question can only be answered by means of comparisons,
the second and third only by counterfactual arguments using the categories of objective possibility and adequate causation, as Weber
develops them with reference to von Kries and Radbruch.39 Here
he rightly stresses that the problem of prioritization in historical
processesthe key to judging between adequate causescan mostly
not be settled, or in any case only with diculty. When all this is
borne in mind, it becomes easy to understand why he included the
following remark into his plan for the Gesammelte Aufstze zur Religionssoziologie in 1919: The issue everywhere is how to handle the question of what is the foundation of the economic and social dening
characteristic of the Occident, how it arose and, in particular, how it
stands in relation to the development of the religious ethic.40
Thus in his historical investigations, Weber describes the religious
developmental history of cultures without becoming entangled in the
coils of classical evolutionism. His studies on the logic and methodology of the social sciences as cultural sciences aim to separate two
pairs of questions: the question of the relevance of a phenomenon
from that of its validity, and the question of development from that
of progress. For both these distinctions, it was Heinrich Rickert who
had laid the logical groundwork. A prerequisite for the rst separation is to be able to distinguish between theoretical value relatedness and practical evaluation; the second demands the capacity to
38
The proposition that a consequence can have more than one cause is a commonplace that should not be ascribed to Max Weber. Some Weber interpreters see
this realization as his greatest achievement. If this were so, it would hardly be
worth giving him any attention today. He did indeed have most sophisticated concepts of causality and attribution. To understand this, one need only read his remarks
on objective possibility and adequate causation in the consideration of historical
causality, in which, admittedly, he did not achieve absolute clarity. See also WL,
pp. 266290.
39
In this connection see WL, pp. 271277.
40
News bulletin, 11.
277
41
wolfgang schluchter
278
42
43
RS III, p. 5.
Ibid., p. 6.
279
Weber takes his unconventional comparison between Indian religion and Judaism even further: thus he contrasts the Brahmins with
the Levites, who represent disparate professional groups versed in
ritual and the law. But he also contrasts Yahweh with Brahman (and
the Tao), the thought of a personal, transcendent creator God with
that of an uncreated, immanent and eternal order, which leads to
dierent conceptions of transcendence.
But the hypothesis of voluntary ghetto existence and the resulting
status of a pariah people is the primary aim of this comparison. I
shall return to this hypothesis in the last part of my exposition. Before
we come to that, it is more important to note that after his comparative introductory section, Weber changes over to developmental
history. He is concerned with the religious creations, which in the
end are decreed by that religious ethic of rational innerworldly conduct: the oldest collection, the Book of the Covenant, and the
Decalogue, which can today be dated to about 1000 to 800 BC; the
Law of Deuteronomy, which presents a programme of reform for
the period during and after the Exile, which probably originated
about 550 to 500, and the most recent collection, the sacred law
and priests codex, which are dated to about 500 to 400 BC. But
what fascinated Weber above all was the prophetic books, especially
Isaiah (including Deutero- and Trito-Isaiah), Jeremiah, Ezekiel and
Amos44and not forgetting the book of Job. But in the prophetic
books, he saw the foundations of a sublimation based on an ethic
of conviction, of the material put together in the collections, which
leads to an ethic of law only.45
44
This arrangement in the canon does not correspond to the supposed historical sequence. After this comes rst Amos (c. 780 to 750), then Isaiah (c. 740 to
700), then Jeremiah (c. 625 to 595), last Ezekiel (c. 600 to 570), who is already a
prophet of the period of Exile. Deutero-Isaiah, the second Isaiah (Isa. 4055), was
already seen as a book in its own right and, as a later interpolation in the Book
of Isaiah, dates its origin to the end of the period of Exile. Weber broadly adheres
to these crude datings. Nevertheless, he does speak of the pre-Exile prophets from
Amos to Jeremiah and Ezekiel. Ibid., p. 281.
45
The Torah numbered 613 rules, 248 commands and 365 prohibitions. To
Webers mind, this normative material forms the foundation of the prophecy. In
his view, these rules from the pre-Exile teaching of the Torah, the Levite Torah,
constitute the content of the Jewish ethic (ibid., pp. 250f.), though this did not deviate strikingly from the religious ethics of other peoples. Only with the prophecy did
it become stamped with its specic characteristics: the central religious conviction
that lies behind it. Ibid., p. 333.
280
wolfgang schluchter
281
47
48
282
wolfgang schluchter
49
283
the lax Jewry of the Diaspora; Jewish and Gentile Christians argue
about the role of circumcision, and even of the Jewish ritual prescriptions in general. One gains the impression of a conict-laden
religious pluralism within Jewry and on its periphery, not to mention the conicts with Greek and Roman tradition in which both
Jews and Christians are becoming entangled.51 Weber himself speaks
of a profusion of cults, schools, sects and orders of every kind
characterizing not only Asia, but also the ancient Occident, a religious pluralism restrained only by reasons of state, where it did
nally meet an inexible limit.52 In the fragment on the Pharisees,
Weber again underlines this religious diversity.53 None of this tallies
with the picture of cultural and social rigidity. What led Weber, so
knowledgeable about Antiquity, to this perception?54
We might rst answer: this perception arises as a back-projection
of mediaeval conditions on to antiquity (the ghetto), and a postReformation concept (confessional community) is inappropriately
applied. Yet in my view, this too is only half the truth. There is a
more profound reason for the (mis-)construction. Weber paints a
background against which the Pauline mission stands out in a clear
light. He sees this as an act of liberation of world-historical signicance.
It was this above all that preserved the creations of the Old Testament
for early Christianity as it freed itself from the imposition of Jewish
modes of thought. For, as Weber puts it: Among the most important spiritual achievements of the Pauline mission was that it kept
this holy book of the Jews alive to become a holy book of the
Christian religion; at the same time, it eliminated all those ethical
features taught in it, which specically anchored the Jews ritually in
their characteristic state of a pariah people, as no longer obligatory,
having been annulled by the Christian saviour.55 Without this
51
Belief in the Resurrection and in an eschatological renewal of the world, which
dominated early Christianity and the apocalyptic tendencies in Jewry, were foreign
to Greek thought. Concerning the dispute that arose from this during Pauls stay
in Athens, Acts 17, 16.
52
RS II, p. 364 (MWG I/20, p. 527).
53
On this subject, see the essays in Schluchter, 1985.
54
Of course, this picture is not complete invention. Because of its laws, which
were diverse from all people and bound up with its separation, anti-Judaism was
already existent in antiquity, going hand in hand with acts of violence against the
scattered Jewish communities. An example of this can be seen in Esther 315.
55
RS III, p. 6f. But it should not be forgotten that the opposition between
universalism and particularism was among the fundamental tensions present in
284
wolfgang schluchter
post-exile Jewry, and that there were denite tendencies, not least under Hellenistic
inuence, towards a world-religious understanding of Jewry, including proselytism.
Weber was fully aware of this, but consideredprobably with justicethat the
opposing trend was the stronger. The peak period for the world-religious orientation
seems to have been during the second century BC, at the time of the re-establishment
of the temple cult in Jerusalem by Judas Maccabaeus and the regaining of political
freedom, though the latter only lasted a short time and was not liberating either.
( Jerusalem was to fall under Roman rule in 69 BC). It was a period in which a
vigorous Diaspora Jewry also developed.
56
Ibid.
285
57
Ibid., p. 220.
CHAPTER FIFTEEN
Preface
Shmuel Eisenstadt is undoubtedly one of the great navigators of
modern social science, one who has taken some clues from an earlier
explorer of modernity, Max Weber, and gone on various expeditions
charting the ocean of modernity and its civilizations. He has steered
safely past the Scylla of marxism and the Charybdis of functionalism to map out the course of the civilization of modernity, and has
recently presented us with various results of his epic saga (Eisenstadt
2003). If we consider that out of his nearly 700 publications in 7
decades, several hundred are comparative and historical, with the
problematic of modernization and modernity, including their disruptive and dark side, as core concerns, and if we consider that he
has circumnavigated the worlds of axial age and non-axial age
civilizations (1986c), from Israel (1992b), to India (2003a), to Japan
(1996b), to the Americas (2001b), and many others along the way,
well, then, in one sense, what we are left to oer him is commentary, rather than new continents and seas that he hasnt mapped.1
My commentary for this occasion springs from Eisenstadts essay
on the Origins of the West (2003a: 578611). We need not spend
1
Willfried Spohn oers an important commentary in making the case that
Eisenstadts treatment of comparative civilizational analysis represents one of the
most forceful heterodox conceptualizations in contemporary macro-sociological
theory, (Spohn 2001: 499).
288
edward a. tiryakian
2
Weber and Marx may be said to share the same view on the medieval period
through the prism of Enlightenment historiography, as exemplied by Voltaire (in
his inuential The Age of Louis XIV). A contrasting view is that of Saint-Simon
who took the medieval period as a prototype of an organic period of Western
civilization, marked by the meshing of structural conditions and dominant ideology.
3
The date 1203 does not have any particular signicance. I use it as a marker
for the setting of the civilization of modernity in the European South, shortly before
the terrible wave of religio-political repression marked by the onset of the crusade in 1209.
289
290
edward a. tiryakian
of the clergy but also, in the gure of Roger Bacon, the early promotion of experimental study and empirical knowledge based on
observation. Walsh went on to show the creativity of the century in
literature and the arts (Dante and Cimabue as innovators) in law
and jurisprudence, in innovative social services (the establishment of
hospitals), in the advancement of women (Walsh 1912: 331), and
not least in the beginnings of modern commerce (the Hanseatic
League, for instance), linking countries in trade as an alternative to
endemic warfare.5
Briey, this historical perspective is a portrayal of an early and
unsurpassed high point of a Euro-Christian civilization, one that provided a model of an integrated civilization of modernity not only
for traditional Catholicism but also for some sociological gures like
Saint-Simons organic period of social organization and Sorokins
concept of idealistic integration is the cyclical aspect of Western
civilization.
What I term the minimalist view on the 13th Century is provided in one of the least remembered writings of sociologist George
Homans. Unlike his later attempts at theory construction, ultimately
privileging psychological reductionism of social phenomena into their
elementary forms of operant conditioning, his rst major work is
grounded in archival research on village society in 13th Century
England (Homans 1960). Homans sought to reconstruct from records
a whole social order, a sort of the social organization of everyday
social life; and it is apparent from his discussion that he was motivated to carry out this research much the same way that anthropologists (at least at the time of publication) sought to in a monograph
the depiction of the total social order of a society. Homanss English
Villagers is synchronic, not diachronic, and the historical setting is
in the deep recess of the background. The cultural, religious dimension of village life gets some attention as part of an orderly social
system, but not in terms of any signicant basis of orthodoxy/
heterodoxy.6 What is noted by (young) Homans that makes the 13th
Century an ingress worth noting is that it is with that century that
Hansa did more than almost any other institution in northern Europe to establish the reign of Law, (Walsh: 424).
6
Quite dierent, as will be noted in the next section, is the depiction of French
14th Century village life by Annales historian Le Roy Ladurie, drawn from the
context of heterodox and orthodox confrontations.
291
7
Although beyond the scope of Cohns discussion, it may be said that the
Reformation is a period of clashing interpretations of Christian fundamentalism. In
more general terms, in all great religious traditions there are critical moments when
segments claim for themselves orthodoxy and brand other segments as heterodox.
292
edward a. tiryakian
293
294
edward a. tiryakian
9
This book . . . takes the position that . . . the century between A.D. 1250 and
1350 constituted a . . . critical turning point in world history, (Abu-Lughod 1989:
12).
295
Dutch to take over in the new European approach to trade-cumplunder that caused a basic transformation in the world system
(1989: 361).
Abu-Lughod has added an important corrective to truncated EuroWhiggish perspectives on modernity, so to speak, that tell a success story from the 16th Century to the recent modern. But her
story-telling leaves out or minimizes some ingredients. First, although
the focus of Before European Hegemony is on urban centers as
strategic to international trade, she dismisses cursorily rather than
discusses Max Webers pregnant discussion of the distinctness of
Western cities in the development of a capitalist civilization (Weber
1978). For Weber, the Western city, especially that of Northern
Europe, was a unique locus of legal emancipation from seigniorial
authority, which would make possible free labor.10 And besides this
contribution to political economy, Weber also in his discussion of
the medieval city pointed to the cultural import of Christianity in
destroying the religious signicance of clan ties, unlike Islamic cities
of the caliphate which, according to him, never overcame the divisiveness of Arab tribal and clan ties, (1978: 1244). Most of AbuLughods rather meager discussion of Weberunderstandably since
her major stimulus is world-system analysisis aimed at negating
the cultural claims in his comparative religious studies. These argued
that the Wirtschaftethik of the religions of China, India and Islam
provided a hostile environment for the development of modern
capitalism in the form of merchant-accumulators and industrial developers. The latter actors, she posits somewhat enigmatically, were
very much present in the thirteenth-century world; what they lacked
were free resources, (1989: 364).
The cultural aspect of civilization is thus residual in both the major
historical accounts of modernity (or pre-modernity) provided by
Braudel and Abu-Lughod. An important corrective to this is the
suggestive programmatic essay of Wittrock (2001), which has much
more anity with the Eisenstadt paradigm, if we may call it that.
Also arguing like Abu-Lughod for reconsidering the formation of
modernity in the medieval period, Wittrock underscores its central
10
The urban citizenry therefore usurped the right to dissolve the bonds of
seigneurial domination; this was the greatin fact, the revolutionaryinnovation
which dierentiated the medieval Occidental cities from all others, (1978: 1239,
emphasis Webers).
296
edward a. tiryakian
11
What seems more important to his perspective is the challenge to political
arrangements institutionalized in the Axial Age period by new political forces (in
the form of new nomadic incursions, largely from Central Asia). These challenges
produced or stimulated new cultural visions and solutions that paved the way for
new institutions, such as, in the case of the West, the university as an autonomous
center of new cognitive understandings and as a center for the training of elites.
297
12
Regarding China and its cultural renaissance in the Song period in the form
of Neo-Confucianism as a cultural synthesis, see Tu Weiming (2000: 196f.) and
Hsu (2001: 445).
13
Curiously, though Wittrock makes no mention of him, the suggestion for such
an emphasis on the 13th Century was proposed by Nelson thirty years ago in discussing intercivilizational encounters and the civilizational breakthrough in the West
in the moralities of thought and in the logics of decision which open out the possibility of creative advance in the direction of wider universalities of discourse and
participation in the conrmation of improved rationales (1981a: 99). Nelson went
on to discuss in terms of dierential utilization of intercivilizational encounters during this second Axial Shift period of the 12th and 13th Centuries how this provided the West with a new point of departure for the great searching of the
Western spirit (1981a: ibid.). By contrast, if we join Arjomand to this point, an
Islamic medieval breakthrough faltered due to a gap in the reception of Aristotle,
specically the fact that Aristotles Politics, which Thomas Aquinas used and which
had far-ung consequences in the development of Western consitutionalism, was
not translated into Arabic as were other of Aristotles writings (Arjomand 2003b:
4548). For a broader analytical and comparative treatment of multiple modernities, see Eisenstadt (2000b) and the entire issue of Ddalus in which Arjomands
essay appears.
298
edward a. tiryakian
14
Occitan as a Romance language with variants was the language of the troubadours and is still spoken today throughout the area, shading into Catalan. It had
an enduring literary renaissance in the 19th Century with the Flibrige group of
poets and writers headed by Mistral. In the 1960s and 1970s a new radical region-
299
alist impulse made itself felt seeking for Occitania cultural if not political autonomy from Paris (see Lafont 1973).
15
For a detailed look at everyday life in a typical Languedoc town, Montaillou,
see the masterful study of LeRoy Ladurie based on ocial 14th Century transcripts
of an Inquisitor (Ladurie 1978). A map in the appendix of this essay shows the
location of Montaillou.
16
It might be noted that Nelli (1968: 18386) discusses many interesting points
of overlap between the Kabbala and the doctrines of the heterodox sect that I focus
on, the Cathars. It would suggest there were many points of contact between
religious and intellectual leaders of the two communities.
300
edward a. tiryakian
17
I will use the name that has stuck, Cathars (from the Greek kataros, pure),
although it might be more proper to use in its place the designation goodmen
(bonhommes) which their neighbors and fellow men in terms of approbation and
to dierentiate them from other non-Catholic sects, such as the Vaudois (Waldensians,
followers of Peter Waldo of Lyon), and the less numerous Beguines (Duvernoy 1994).
For detailed materials on the beliefs, rituals, and organizational structures of the
Cathar religion and its societal setting, see Duvernoy (1976).
301
administer the rite of adult baptism by the Spirit, the consolamentum, and thirdly, the rite for the moribund, the convenenza, of
critical importance for the salvation of the soul. All the believers
viewed the creation of the material world, nature and matter, as the
work of the Evil God, while the Good or hidden God was the God
of the Spirit, which in humans is held captive as the soul by the
body.
Essentially, the Cathar religion appears as a simplied form of
Christianity, in beliefs, rituals and organizational structure, from that
of the orthodox Church of Rome. The clergy of the Cathars seemed
on the whole better educated, more conversant with Scriptures, than
a good number of priests, many of whom practiced concubinage and
beneted from the practice of tithing (Ladurie 1978: 30626). The
parfaits won the respect and esteem of all the social strata, from
commoners to nobility and even had the tacit support of the reigning
ruler of Languedoc, the Count of Toulouse. By 1200 or so, Catharism
seemed poised to provide the Midi with a new religious foundation
for its social order, one whose transcendental vision was more consonant with the Occitan civilization than was the vision of Catholicism.
It was for the latter an immense challenge which it answered in
several ways. First, the latter half of the 12th and beginning of the
13th Centuries was not only a period of new wealth and urban opulence (generated by the multiplication of trade and commerce with
the East, as discussed by Abu-Lughod). But it was also a period
where auence bred a reaction of asceticism in the form of grassroots movements of voluntary pauperism as a return to the ideals
of the primitive Christian church.18 Two such movements stand out.
In the case of Peter Waldo and his followers, drawn from auent
urban circles, the ideal of poverty meant that one should venture
forth to preach and lead the evangelical life, even if this meant
deance of the established hierarchical church. As a sect the
Waldensians had a theology practically identical to that of orthodox Christianity, but had no ordained priest and recognized no
bishops much less the Pope. Yet it had much support where it spread,
18
To some extent, the American Peace Corps under President Kennedy, which
sent thousands of middle-class college-educated students to Third World countries,
seems like an echo of the impetus of Peter of Waldo to go out to the countryside
and identify with the poor.
302
edward a. tiryakian
especially among the lower urban and rural strata, since the preaching
of the Waldensians was done in the vernacular, not in Latin, and
they refused to pay indulgences; since the Waldensians, like the
Cathars, did not believe in purgatory.19
The dual challenge for orthodoxy of the appeal of voluntary pauperism, especially in the rapid spread of the Waldensians, and of
addressing the problem of a lax ocial clergy which enjoyed a material life that contradicted the ideals of the primitive church was
answered by the other great movement of voluntary pauperism, that
launched by Francis of Assisi. Living an exemplary life of asceticism
outside the monastery, the Franciscan order (which provided the
impetus for the Mendicant orders in Western Christianity) became
a signicant movement to counter the Cathars, by engaging in disputes with the parfaits and becoming an alternative presence in urban
areas.
Orthodoxy also countered the heterodox challenge by seeking capable intellectuals who could argue the true faith with heretics:
this was found in the presence of a newly formed order founded by
Dominic Guzman at the turn of the 13th Century. The Dominican
order was recognized by the Pope and its members excelled in
preaching, being sent to counter the preaching of the heretics.
Unfortunately for the Languedoc as a whole, moral persuasion
did not remain the sole strategy of the orthodox to counter the threat
of heterodoxy. In an age when costly crusades to regain lost territory in the Holy Land had met with uneven success, holding on to
if not regaining the spiritual territory of the Languedoc became a
primary concern for the new prelate of the Church of Rome, Innocent
III. He called for a crusade against the heretics; since these were
Christians, the crusade that took the name of The Albigensian
Crusade (Cathars were particularly numerous in the city of Albi)
was the only of the crusades of the 13th Century directed not at
Islam in the Holy Land but at a Christian sect inside Europe. And
it was not just a holy war to extirpate religious error but also
rapidly became a war of military conquest, of the North and its
allies against the South. The conquest did not take place overnight,
for there was strong military resistance against the invaders by the
19
For major treatment of Waldensians and Cathars, see Thouzellier (1969) and
Duvernoy (1994).
303
20
For an extensive discussion of the prolonged ghting and the ultimate destruction of the last Cathar strongholds in the Pyrenees, see Bordonove (1991).
304
edward a. tiryakian
21
For an important set of papers regarding this historiography see Historiographie
du catharisme, Cahiers de Fanjeaux, no. 14 (Toulouse: E. Privat 1979).
305
rejected the Old Testament, but still, there are some intriguing
common denominators. These will have to wait another occasion to
be drawn out, perhaps an international conference to celebrate a
centennial anniversary.
IV. From a comparative civilizational perspective of modernity, the
13th Century oers a rich laboratory of investigation. Perhaps the
key question underlying a research program that might follow in
the wake of Bjrn Wittrocks call for a new global history noted earlier is something like this: why did not a civilization of modernity
emerge and become institutionalized a thousand years ago? There
was unprecedented contacts and encounters between the major centers of the Eurasian land mass and a case can be made for each
the Christian West, the Islamic Middle East, the Hindu South Asia
and the Confucian East Asiahaving a material and cultural
eorescence. Yet, the promise of a civilization of modernity did not
actualize, and if anything, a fragmentation seemed to take place, not
only between themselves but even, to some extent, within themselves.
The materials discussed in this essay do not address this broad
comparative query, but for the case of the West, it suggests that the
repression of heresy, and in particular, the brutal repression of
Catharism was a critical turning point. On the one hand, from
the point of view of orthodoxy, the challenge of dissent that could
undermine the unity of church and state by undermining the legitimacy of both was successfully met, at least for three centuries. On
the other hand, there was a price paid for ontological security,
not only the price paid by the thousands of heretics who were
burned at the stake and the greater numbers who perished in solitary connement. The price paid was also more than the unlawful
conscation of property from families accused of heresy or of
assisting heretics. The price paid was the setting up an institution
which became a veritable state within a state, ultimately responsible only to the Pope, and which could even attack clerical dissent
going as high as Cardinals as being heretical.
It may not be too dicult for readers to discern a certain tie-in
of this with Norman Cohns already mentioned study of 13th Century
chiliastic thought and its legacy for the fanaticisms of the 20th. The
Gestapo, the KGB, the stasi and other agencies of state control of
the 20th Century sought in their turn to extirpate dissidents and
heretics using tactics of interrogation and torture, short of burning
306
edward a. tiryakian
at the stake, not altogether dierent from that of the Inquisition and
its secular arm. This could readily be seen as a Jacobin tendency
of modernity, an orientation of bringing about homogeneity of beliefs
and behavior, not by persuasion which is one political option, but
by coercion, which is an alternate political option.
The demise of Nazi Germany and the collapse of Soviet communism seemed to have paved the way for a continuation if not
extension of a civilization of modernity marked by a commitment
to technological progress, political democratization, and the freer circulation of goods and services world wide, while at the same time
allowing for cultural dierences and a new appreciation and respect
for others. Francis Fukuyamas noted essay (1992) at the beginning
of the last decade was, tacitly, a vision of a new onset of such a
civilization of modernity, a rekindling of the vision of the Enlightenment. Carried to its full extent as a new pax Romana guaranteed
by American hegemony, this vision might accommodate a new
era of multiple modernities within an overarching civilization of
modernity.
September 11th has been a rude awakening from this vision. In
the context of this paper what is most troubling is that the response
of the country that has been so much of an epicenter of modernity
in the 20th Century may in fact be taking a sharp turn away from
the moral, normative aspects of modernity and returning to the
regressive, coercive ways that orthodoxy came to deal with heterodoxy in the 13th Century. The war on terrorism is, in one obvious
sense, unfortunately perhaps, a dichotomized clash of civilizations
(Huntington 1996), of radical anti-modern Islam against modern
civilization. But there is a more disturbing way of looking at it,
beyond a sterile barbarism versus civilization prism.
I will not dwell on the irony that the perceived architects of 9/11
terrorism view the United States as a Satanic force not only because
of its support for Israel but also, and perhaps more profoundly,
because it is corruptive of traditional morality and domestic values,
and that this is precisely why the present American administration
and its conservative supporters hold liberals in askance. Structurally,
the fundamentalisms involved are isomorphic.
What is ominous are not the measures for external protection so
much as those for internal protection. The latter are of two sorts.
One is protection from dissent and public debate by a climate of
invoking the war on terrorism as a defense of the country, its peo-
307
ple and its values; hence, public criticism is muted in the spirit of
patriotism. Second are much more tangible measures and practices
designed to achieve homogeneous conformity, of the domestic population and of overseas allies. Within the United States, the USA
Patriot Act22 and amended provisions of the 1978 Foreign Intelligence
Surveillance Act have not only greatly increased the surveillance,
searches and data gathering powers of the federal government, beyond
traditional constitutional safeguards, but also set up secret courts
where detainees are kept indenitely without benet of counsel. How
dierent is the lot of the hundreds of detainees at Guantnamo Bay
and those of other inmates at American and British detention camps,
subjected to violent and coercive interrogation, including beatings,
withholding of pain medication, sleep deprivation, and loud noise
intended to be disorientating, with the recalcitrant ones rendered
for questioning to foreign countries (Dworkin 2003: 37), from what
Lea says about the detainees of the Inquisition:
The Inquisition shrouded itself in the awful mystery of secrecy until
afar sentence had been awarded and it was ready so impress the multitude with the fearful solemnities of the auto de f. Unless proclamation were to be made for an absentee, the citation of a suspected
heretic was made in secret (Lea 1969: 159).
Just as the accused and convicted heretic had no appeal in the 13th
Century to customary courts, only to the Pope, so also in the military tribunals set up for terrorists hearsay evidence and involuntary
confessions are admissible and there is no appeal except to the
secretary of defense and the president (Dworkin 2003: 37). Quite
forcefully, Dworkin, among others, points to the grave danger of civil
liberties in the American administrations policies of dealing with
terrorists, including American citizens accused of terrorism. Not only
has the Patriot Act been extended in its purview to investigate and
prosecute more ordinary crimes but also there is strong temptation for this to be seen as having a duration beyond the emergency
situation of 9/11 to something lasting at least a generation, just as
the Inquisition became institutionalized into a permanent organization
that lasted into the 19th Century. Thus, there is need to heed the
22
Formally, the Uniting and Strengthening America by Providing Appropriate
Tool Required to Intercept and Obstruct Terrorism Act of 2001, signed into law
on 26 October 2001.
308
edward a. tiryakian
warning that the governments anti-terrorist policies may be an irreversible step to a new and much less liberal state, (Dworkin: 38).
The issue that Dworkin raises is that the American administrations policies regarding terrorists or alleged terrorists, even if technically legal in a national emergency, are of concern to more than
Americans. If these policies violate peoples fundamental human
rightsrights at the foundation of the international moral order
that nations must respect even when under threat (Dworkin: 37)
then these policies are wrong and immoral.
In the 13th Century, human rights had not entered into the consciousness of civilization. The civilization of modernity has accepted
this as a normative cornerstone. But we have already seen tragic
examples in the last century of societies that had identied with the
civilization of modernity breaking o from it and developing Jacobin
enforcement of homogeneity. Terrorism today, like heresy a thousand years ago, is a threat to the social order of modernity. But the
response may itself lead to a reactionary breakdown with far-reaching
unfortunate consequences.
CHAPTER SIXTEEN
1
Such commitment should not turn us into apologists of old or new nations and
cultures and result in any kind of feel-good soft-ware support for international diplomacy. In other words, civilizational analysis and explanation of multiple modernities must remain distinct from politically correct cultural relativism and apologetic
pan-modernism or pan-rationalism.
310
sad arjomand
Eisenstadt, civilizational analysis and Islam
What we might call the Weberian paradigm for civilizational analysis focused on the impact of world religions on social action and
social organization. Culturally, the impact was through the motivation of social action generally by ethos of the world religions, and
more particularly by their economic, political and social ethics
(dietary, sexual, domestic regulations and rules for ritual purity).
Webers conception of rationalization related this ethical regulation
of the life system to the worldview of the respective world religion
through the requirement of meaningful consistency (Sinnzuzamenhang).
Sociologically, the impact of the world religions was transmitted
through the social strata or classes that constituted their respective
social bearers or carriers (Trger). Here, too, the notion of rationalization as a developmental pattern links the institution-building of the
formative periods to the religious solutions to the problem of the
meaning of human life through the ideal interests of these bearers
of the world religions and their meaningfully consistent reconciliation to material conditions and historical contingencies. (Arjomand
2004)
Eisenstadts comparative civilizational analysis makes more explicit
and amplies the sociological dimension of Webers paradigm. On
the one hand, he oers a more pluralistic picture of civilizational
dynamics by highlighting Webers analysis of the transformative impact
of heterodoxies within the world religions. (Eisenstadt 2003a, 1: 1719)
Tension among contending interpretations and their respective bearers within the same world religion and civilization is stressed by distinguishing orthodoxy and its ocial representatives from heterodoxies
of unocial challengers who oer contesting interpretations of the
central values of the tradition and create movements of cultural and
political protest. On the other hand, he emphasizes the degree of
autonomy of the elites representing orthodoxy in relation to the ruler
and political power as a determinant of the strength of their civilizational impact.2 According to Eisenstadt, whether Buddhism,
Confucianism or Islam remain conned to the religious sphere or
2
I have similarly treated the degree of the autonomy of the Shi`ite hierocracy
from the patrimonial state in dierent periods as a key determinant of their impact
cultural impact on Iran. (Arjomand 1984)
311
have a broader impact in a civilization largely depends on their autonomy from the rulers. This explains the dierent civilizational impact
of Confucianism and Buddhism in Japan as compared to China and
Thailand, and of Islam in sub-Saharan Africa and Southeast Asia
as compared to the Middle East and North Africa. (Eisenstadt 1993b)
In a major work inspired by Webers idea of the world religions
as the core of civilizations, Marshall Hodgson (1974) argued that
Islamic law facilitated great social mobility but not institutional development. The Shari`a ignored public law and state action, and left
too little room for initiative to the Caliph in theory. Consequently,
social activism tended to take the form of revivalist movements outside the framework of the state and of governmental institutions.
Eisenstadt has put forward a model of the inner dynamics of Islamic
civilization centered on constant tension between an Islamic primordial utopiathe ideal of the Golden Age of pristine Islamand
the historical reality of patrimonial Sultanism, coexisting with autonomous public sphere dominated by the religious elite, the ulema,
as the guardians of the Shari'a and orthodoxy. He points to a very
interesting decoupling . . . between the makeup of the public sphere
and access to the decision-making of the ruler. The de facto separation of religious authority and rulership, entailing this decoupling
of a vibrant public sphere, autonomous from the . . . realm of rulership is in fact the distinctive feature of the Islamicate in contrast
to the Western civilization, where the participation in the public
sphere was linked to political decision-making. (Eisenstadt 2002a:
153) Drawing on Hodgson and on Ibn Khalduns depiction of the
cycle of the rise and fall of puritanical Muslim dynasties, as interpreted by the late Ernest Gellner, Eisenstadt further constructs a
model of oscillation between military patrimonial regimes with limited pluralism, on the one hand, and intolerant proto-fundamentalist
and Jacobin fundamentalist ones, on the other. (Eisenstadt 2002)
The tension between the orthodoxy and heterodoxies is incorporated
into this model. Cook (1999: 276) argued persuasively that there is
a striking mist between Webers conception of sect, derived from
Christianity, and the intensely political character of religious schism
in Medieval Islam. Eisenstadt similarly approaches heterodoxy
under sectarianism and political dynamics. (Eisenstadt 2003a, 1:
42129)
Eisenstadts model of the religio-political dynamics of the Islamicate civilization is appealing for its simplicity, for discarding the
312
sad arjomand
313
314
sad arjomand
great Persian poet, Sa'di of Shiraz (d. 1291), who wrote the most
moving elegy on the demise of the last 'Abbasid Caliph, in fact
accompanied the Mongol conqueror in the fateful siege of Baghdad
in 1258.
The encounter with the Greek civilization was, however, of much
greater axial signicance for Christianity and Islam. The transmission
of Greek scientic and philosophical texts through Arabic and of the
Muslim medical treatises to Europe in the Middle Ages is indisputable. As is generally known, the major civilizational encounter
between Western Christendom and the Islamicate civilization resulted
in the transmission of Greek philosophy and sciences as well as mathematics and medicine as developed in the Muslim world. The importation of institutions has not been proven, however. George Makdisi
(1981) has argued that the institutions of higher learning also
traveled from the Muslim world to the West as a part of this civilizational encounter. But there is little evidence for the inuence of
the fully developed madrasas on the nascent European universities in
the thirteenth century. Makdisis argument for the inuence of the
mosque-khn model on the Inns of Court as the rst English law
colleges set up in London in the twelfth century by the Knights
Templar returning from the Holy Land, cannot be accepted as the
alleged model rests on a misreading of the textual source. (Mottahedeh
1997) Inspired by Makdisi, Monica Gaudiosi (1988) claims the law
of waqf as a source of the English law of trust or use, and argues
that the 1264 statutes of the House of Scholars of Merton, the deed
of trust that set up the rst Oxford College, can be analyzed as a
waqf instrument. (Gaudiosi 1988: 1250) But she can only show
generic similarities between the deeds of trust and waqf rather than
giving any direct proof of borrowing. It is true that the inuence of
the trusts founder was as great as that of a waqf endowment. Walter
de Merton names members of his own family as the primary
beneciaries. Hugh of Balsham, the Bishop of Ely, founded the rst
Cambridge College, Peterhouse, in 1284 pro utilitate rei publice. It was,
however, explicitly modeled on Merton and reserved the appointment of the master and conrmation of fellows for the Bishop.
(Leedham-Green 1996: 2122) Merton College was soon incorporated by a subsequent deed of 1274, however, and it was not the
unincorporated Inns of Court or Peterhouse but, as we have seen,
the corporations of masters and/or scholars of Paris or Bologna that
315
316
sad arjomand
The reception of the Greek political science was a part of the translation of Greek philosophy and medicine into Arabic a century later,
and was developed into the discipline of practical philosophy or
political science (Arjomand 2001). Rather than focusing on the
caliphate and the sacred law (shari'a), the typical conception of
political order found in the Persian literature of the medieval period
on statecraft and the political ethic was that of a world order constituted by the two powers of prophecy (nobovvat) and monarchy
(saltanat). From the end of the twelfth century onward, this idea of
the two powers constitutive of order was developed into a type of
political theory that is called Islamic royalism in this essay. Islamic
royalism came to represent the constitutional organization of Muslim
polities after the Mongol overthrow of the Abbasid caliphate. (Arjomand
2003a)
Before comparing the Greco-Islamic synthesis I have called Islamic
royalism as expressed by Tusi with the Greco-Christian synthesis
exemplied by his contemporary Aquinas as the point of divergence
of Western and Islamicate political thought, let me briey consider
the failure of a somewhat dierent synthesis of the Shi'ite and Sunni
political theories that excluded the Greek elements and minimized
the Perso-Indian ones. I refer to the constitutional reforms of the
late 'Abbasid caliph, al-Nsir li-Din Allh (11801225), who sought
instead to integrate the Shi'ite Sects and Su Orders into an expansive Islamic orthodoxy under the Caliphate.
The grand civilizational synthesis and its failure
An irreversible bifurcation of supreme authority into Caliphate and
Sultanate (monarchy) began with the Buyid (Arabized as Buwayhid)
seizure of power in Baghdad in the mid-10th century ce, and lasted
for a little over three centuries to the mid-13th Century (1258, to
be precise). The Caliphate and monarchy were dierent concepts
and drew on two dierent political theories. Monarchy was the older
Near Eastern concept, and the imperial (post-Medina) conception of
the Caliphate was elaborated with increasing reference to it. (AlAzmeh 1997) I have argued that a theory of the two powers had
been in the making since the 'Abbasid revolution: the ethico-legal
order grew around the idea of the Shari'a, independently and at the
same time as the conception of the political order as monarchy
317
318
sad arjomand
4
To make good this claim as the heir to the heritage of Prophecy (mirth alnubuwwa), Caliph al-Nsir published and widely disseminate a collection of the
Prophetic Traditions he considered authentic. (Hartmann 1975: 21632)
319
320
sad arjomand
secular conception of royal authority that can partly account for the
remarkable accommodation of religious diversity and tolerance of
heterodoxy in these Muslim empires. Islamic royalism, however, did
not foster democracy, as did the Thomist synthesis of the Greek
political science and the Christian religion.
Dierential reception of Aristotles political ideas
Thomas Aquinas was an exact contemporary of Nasir al-Din Tusi;
they both died in 1274. They were both closely associated with the
institutions of higher learning. Aquinas was a professor of theology
at the University of Paris in the formative era of European universities, and sides with its secular masters in including Aristotle in the
syllabus. Tusi was the supervisors of the religious endowments and
madrasas of the Il-Khnid (Iranian Mongol) empire, and made a serious attempt to capture the madrasas for the teaching of philosophy.
The Roman law of corporations enabled the European universities
to claim that legal status and use it autonomy to make the reception of Aristotle denitive. The law of waqf which was the legal basis
of the madrasas did not have a similar concept of corporation, and
Tusis promotion of philosophy was reversed within a generation as
it lacked a permanent legal foundation. The graduates of European
universities acted as eective bearers of political Aristotelianism in
the long and uneven path to representative government and democratization in Western Europe. Despite his failure to reorient the
teaching in the madrasas, Tusis political ethics was taught there as
practical philosophy in the early modern period. It remained marginal, however, and was not integrated in to the main disciplines of
Islamic law and jurisprudence.
Elsewhere, I have covered the initial reception of the Greek political
science in the tenth and eleventh centuries and argued that the
rational legitimation of religion is the philosophical theory was a
potential challenge to the traditional legitimacy of the shar'i order.
This made a clash between Islam and Greek philosophy, including
political theory, inevitable, and a rejectionist civilizational response
by the pious traditionalists gathered momentum and eventually
displaced philosophy to the margin of institutionalized learning. In
the course of a long and complex Kulturkampf, the rejectionist response
was formulated by the jurists who proposed to revive the institution
321
322
sad arjomand
323
5
The fact that the Islamic reaction was so late in coming should cast doubt on
Hu s (1993) attribution of the failure to develop modern science to medieval Islamic
ethos, which was in fact less hostile to science than the medieval Christian ethos.
324
sad arjomand
deceptive as the development of political thought in the two civilizations had followed a sharply divergent path.
The unavailability of Politics in the Muslim world meant continued
unawareness of many key Aristotelian political concepts that became
available to Aquinas and others in the thirteenth century and shaped
Western political thought, such as the commonwealth (res publica) and
the rule of law (government by laws and not men), with the citizen
being the ruler and the ruled at the same time (Aquinas 1965:
13839). These ideas penetrated the Islamicate world as the implicit
conceptual substratum of modern constitutionalism in the nineteenth
and twentieth centuries. Only much later did modern translations of
Politics appear, and then as something of an antiquarian text in
the history of philosophy. The real thrust of modernization in the
debilitated early nineteenth century Muslim empires, the Ottoman
and Iran, did not come from the strata with an interest in political
science but from the rulers and the servants of the patrimonial state.
The latters interest in the rationalization and defensive modernization
of armies and bureaucracies gave them no incentive to uncover the
Aristotelian substratum of modern constitutional law or to refashion
Tusis political science in a democratic direction.
Francis Robinson (1999: 241) ingeniously develops the idea that
by taking Webers understanding of developmental history of world
religions and his typology of religious rationalism, we can make sense
of the fact that failures of the Westernized state machinery has often
been accompanied by a reassertion of Islamic world view and a reinstatement of the Shari'a in public life. The result has been an ideologically concocted reinvention of the Islamic political tradition that
bears no resemblance to the historical synthesis analyzed in this essay.
The modernization of the Ottoman (later Tunisian, Egyptian and
Turkish) and Iranian states dispossessed the ulema as an elite by
taking over or eliminating many of their social and judiciary functions.
In the twentieth century, the dispossessed traditional or organic
intellectuals of Muslim societies formulate an Islamic counter-myth
of their own against the idol of the modernized state. The political
edge of this alternative Islamic social myth became increasingly
sharpened as the century was drawing to a close. The late-twentieth-century political Islam obliterated the theory of the two powers
from an increasingly reied and holistic historical memory, and discovered a hero in Ibn Taymiyya, whose apprehension of the abovementioned triple threat matches their fear of suocation by the
325
Western cultural invasion. Ibn Taymiyyas monistic idea of Shari'abased policy was simplied still further into a vehemently rejectionist
anti-Western myth of the Islamic State with the primary function
of the execution of the divine law. Thus has the Islamic political
tradition been reinvented in our time. Needless to say, this invented
tradition requires elaborate separate treatment, but without understanding their divergence from the historical tradition, we cannot
assess the prospects for democracy in the contemporary Muslim
world.
CHAPTER SEVENTEEN
328
danile hervieu-lger
329
330
danile hervieu-lger
331
332
danile hervieu-lger
333
334
danile hervieu-lger
the systems of truth, which itself derives, at least in part, from the
de-occidentalization inherent in the globalized age of modernity.
The European model: a second look at a singular conguration
of religious modernity
But the prospect revealed by S. Eisenstadt does more than merely
invite us to identify the plurality of the cultural and institutional
congurations that are progressively brought into play on the basis
of, and by ambivalent reference to, the original occidental programme
of modernity. In my view, it oers an equally persuasive invitation
to explore the internal dynamics of the dierentiation and homogenization that produce the continual denitions and redenitions of
the programme itself. Within the constraints of this presentation, I
shall make no attempt to set out all the theoretical and methodological implications of the latter proposition. But I would like to
give a brief illustration of its scope, by taking a fresh look, in this
light, at a few of the elements in the description of the singular
conguration of European religious modernity.
Europeans are further removed than mostas I remarked earlierfrom the gure of the practising believer, receiving his religious identity from the community to which he has belonged since
birth and in which he obeys the prescriptions of observance laid
down by the institution responsible for the transmission of the faith.
I myself have adopted two descriptive gures to exemplify the mobility of the individual paths that characterize the European religious
scene. The rst is that of the pilgrim, following his personal spiritual path, stage by stage. The second is that of the convert, who
chooses the line of belief in which he feels at home.2 These descriptive gures are not valid exclusively in the European area, but it is
in Europe that they best designate the movement towards religious
individualization that disorganizes the classical forms of religious
adherence and dissemination. This process of subjectivization of
religion constitutes the culminating point of the long history of its
gradual relegation to the sphere of the private. Historically, indeed,
Europe (with processes that diered according to nation) was the
335
Gauchet (1998).
336
danile hervieu-lger
the dual and indivisible struggle against despotism on the one hand
and religion on the other that was crystallized in the revolutionary
experience.4
For a more profound analysis of the dierences in the civilizational workings of religion in Europe, we would have to distinguish
other relevant dierentiations within these Catholic and Protestant
sub-groups. Thus, within the broadly Protestant part of Europe,
the English, German and Scandinavian perceptions of the Enlightenment, themselves rooted in dierent constructions of Protestantism,
generated political cultures, conceptions of the relation between the
State and the citizen, and notions of sovereignty and representation,
that are far from homogeneous. Now every society in Europe today
still bears the marks of the religious roots that are specic to it. In
a country like France, where the historical work of laicization went
particularly deep and the objective and subjective loss of religion can
be particularly clearly illustrated, the phenomenon of catholic encoding
of culture, institutions and mentalities remains extraordinarily signicant.
We are all Catholics, Sartre declares in Being and Nothingness. This
formula is noteworthy in its emphasis on the mirror that the laity
hold up to the gure of the Roman church whose direct hold over
society and the individual it had laboured to break. More broadly,
the whole programme of the major institutionsschools, hospitals,
justice, the University, etc.was established, and functioned for a
long period, by reference (rendered implicit, of course) to the Catholic
model.5 It is impossible to comprehend the manner of expression in
public debate of numerous questions which have strictly nothing to
do with religion (from the quality of food to ethical regulation of
science, from the management of hierarchical relationships in business
to the future of rural society, from the expectations that society has
of the State to practices in social activism) without gauging this
Catholic impregnation of culture. But this function of symboliccultural encoding operates in a completely dierent way, though with
equal force, in every country in Europe, from Scandinavia to Great
Britain, from Germany to Belgium or the Netherlands, in Italy or
Ireland. In every country in Europe, the style of political life, the
content of public debate on social and ethical problems, the denition
of the areas of responsibility of the State and the individual, con4
5
Bouretz (2000).
Dubet (2003).
337
338
danile hervieu-lger
countries, it is also clear that the road to integration of these populations diers considerably, as a function partly of the political culture
of each country, and partly of the special character of each of the
varieties of Islam concerned (Pakistani, North African or Turkish, in
the three cases in point). The dierent ways of dealing with a question
such as the wearing of the veil in school is a good illustration of the
fact that Islam has become a reality which simultaneously unites and
divides the dierent European countries.
The same dialectic of proximity and distance comes into play with
regard to the phenomena of cultural globalization in which Europe
is involved as much as all the rest of the planet. On the one hand,
the spread of a homogenized media culture, the accelerated development of the circulation of goods, people and ideas, the homogenization of modes of consumption and the generalized subjection of
exchangesincluding exchange of symbolsto the mechanisms of
the free market, tend to erode the cultural idiosyncrasies, especially
religious, of European societies. On the other hand, the dynamics
of this very cultural homogenization engender reactions which may
favour the revival of these same cultural idiosyncrasies and bring
back to the surface national political and symbolic issues relating to
religious matters which might have been thought completely obsolete. While it may be imagined that the growing hegemony of NorthAmerican culture and values may arouse in opposition the assertion
of a European culture armed with its own references and values, we
must also reect that it tends to generate the formation of reactive
identities which, even within Europe, nourish strengthened areas of
competition which may be inseparably denominational and national.
The ght to defend the cultural exception certainly nds nourishment
in the soil that supports the religious worlds that cohabit in Europe,
but these religious worlds, which are themselves dierentiated, may
bring to it elements of content that are in plain contradiction.
The phenomena of internal cultural pluralization on one hand
and external cultural globalization on the other hand have the potential to contribute simultaneously to the erosion and the partial and
paradoxical recreation of dierent religious civilizations in Europe.
It is this dual trend that permanently denes and redenes the singularity of a European religious modernity. It is through this movement also that the place of European modernity is dened and
redened in the constellation of those multiple modernities that
Shmuel Eisenstadt has taught us to consider.
CHAPTER EIGHTEEN
340
michael confino
many of the entities involved; and, on the other hand, specic ones,
peculiar to each and every church and nation. Both types will be
touched upon albeit with dierent degrees of emphasis. The paper
is divided into two parts, with the rst devoted to an overview of
some salient features of the church-state problematic in Eastern
Orthodoxy; and the second to an examination of church-state relations mainly in Muscovy and Russia, and occasionally in the Orthodox
countries in the Balkans.
Church and state: the view from the East
It should be noted from the outset that during long periods of time
Eastern Orthodoxy was a very politicized ecclesiastical organization.
Georges Florovksy observes that it was essentially a social religion,
and Pedro Ramet writes that it had from the beginning a social
and political concern.1 This characteristic will be kept in mind in
the present enquiry, with regard to the three main features examined in the rst part of the paper, for their role in the shaping of
church-state relations in Eastern Orthodox Christendom in Europe:
the legacy of the past, the inuence of some basic tenets of its creed,
and its structural makeup.
The weight of the past
The Byzantine Empire lasted almost 1200 years and outlived most
of the other great empires. The inuence of its civilization expanded
from Russia to Ethiopia, through the Caucasus, the Balkans and the
eastern Mediterranean regions. Peoples owe to Byzantium their literacy
and literature (Bulgaria, Russia, Serbia), others the beginning of their
art and architecture (Romania, Georgia), and manytheir Christianity,
including the specic Eastern Orthodox turn of the perennial question of church and state.2
1
Florovsky, 1974, quoted in Pedro Ramet, 1988 p. 3. For some comprehensive
and interpretative works see French, 1951; Schmemann, 1963; Pelikan, 1974; Ware,
1995; Binns, 2002.
2
The literature is immense; for some relevant general works and monographs,
old and new, see: Runciman, 1933; Ostrogorsky, 1940; Angelov, 1946; Every 1947);
341
Constantines conversion to Christianity was of the utmost importance not only for the fate of the church, but also for the theology
of an empire, forin the accepted religious beliefhe was converted
directly by God, rather than by ordinary men. This fact sanctioned
implicitly his power both in the church and in the empire and
represented one of the most lasting and solid basis of the emperors
position in the church. The early Eastern Church enjoyed the protection of the Roman emperors who, after conversion to Christianity,
transferred their capital to Constantinople. In the Eastern Roman
Empire, the emperor was head of the church, and the church was
part of the state structure. Emperor Justinian (527565) held that
there existed a relationship of harmony between secular and ecclesiastical authorities. To this should be added the principle of symphonia (rst formulated in 535 in Justinians sixth Novella,) which
became a fundamental Orthodox tenet. In practice the harmony
implied that the emperors took part in the internal life and activity
of the church and at times even in the formulation of cannon law
and the appointment of bishops. In this situation it was in the order
of things that the state would use its power in order to support the
decisions of the church and secure their implementation on its
territory. The concomitant result of this relationship was that the
church used the secular power of the state in order to implement
what it considered religious orthodoxy and to ght schismatics and
heretics. In any case, it has been pointed out that for Byzantine
theorists it was axiomatic that the church could not survive without
protection of the state (a view which requires qualication, as we
will see below); in this view, later on, when Byzantium began to
decline, the church became even more dependent on secular authority
for physical protection and nancial assistance.3
Thus we may say that this relationship, so to speak, spared Byzantium and the Eastern Church a War of Investiture, but although
Berkhof, 1947; Brehier, 1949; Barker, 1957; Browning, 1980; Alexander, 1985;
Hussey, 1957; idem, 1990; Whittow, 1995; Treadgold 1997; Herrin, 2001.
3
See Richard Pipes, 1974, ch. 9, pp. 221245. This succinct and brilliant chapter is a critical analysis of the Orthodox Churchs role and history; it oers insightful interpretations and raises questions open to debate. I have addressed here some
of them as formulated in this treatment; see also Brehier, 1969, pp. 430506; Hussey,
1957, pp. 8599.
342
michael confino
4
On this issue the noted historian Michael Karpovich holds a dierent view:
At any rate, neither in Byzantium nor in Russia did the Church as a whole ever
exhibit either a strong tendency to assert the supremacy of the spiritual power over
the secular, or such a tenacity in defending itself against the encroachments of
the State as were characteristic of the Roman Catholic Church in the West
(M. Karpovich, 1944, p. 13.)
343
5
A notable exception in this respect was king Otto I, a Protestant and Bavarian
prince, who, ruled in Greece from 1832 to 1862. He had the church submitted to
the civil authority, interfered in its internal aairs, and made it for all practical
purposes an agency of the state, very much alike the Bavarian Protestant church
after the 1818 Constitution. Deposited in 1862 folowing a military revolt, he was
succeeded in 1863 by George I, a Danish prince.
6
Most of the works listed above in note 1 devote chapters or sections to the
relations between Byzantium and the Roman Catholic west; for two recent monographs and documents dealing with shorter periods see Davids 1995; Ciggaar 1996;
for a brief summary and selected examples of these relations, see also 1967, ch. 4
(The Legacy of Dead Empires), pp. 5069; the sack of Constantinople in 1204
by the crusaders of the Fourth Crusade is a well known historical episode, and does
not need a detailed description here.
344
michael confino
345
10
See Toynbee, 1948, pp. 164183. Here is, in Toynbees words, a short summary of his thesis: What are [Byzantines] society salient features? Two stand out
above the rest: the conviction (mentioned already) that Byzantium is always right,
and the institution of the totalitarian state. Subsequently, when the state succeeded
to transform the church into a department of the medieval East Roman state, it
reduced the church ipso facto to a position that made it totalitarian too. And nally
(exculpating in fact Lenin, Stalin, and even Ezhov, at the tune of Cest la faute
a Byzance), this is the heritage which Byzantium bequeathed to Russia from St
Vladimir to the Bolsheviks.
11
11 Kazhdan, 1989, pp. 2634; he writes: . . . we can call the Byzantine empire
a totalitarian state. And it was the only totalitarian state of the European Middle
Ages. As such, Byzantium gives us material to observe a totalitarian state over a
long period and to analyse its liabilities and assets, its roots and mechanism. (p. 32).
The four elucidations are: 1. Kievan (Rus) temporal society absorbed very little of
Byzantium in terms of political thought and practice, weaponry, etc.; 2. As for
Muscovy, Only in the fteenth century when Russian grand princes began to
build up their centralised monarchy did they discover their Byzantine ancestry;
Russia did not inherit Byzantine totalitarianism but used the model for their [sic]
political ends (p. 34); 3. Countries like Bulgaria, Serbia, and Romania, that were
in direct contact with Byzantium, did not develop a tendency to totalitarianism; 4.
On the other hand, totalitarian governments could be traced in various European
countries whose contacts with Byzantium were very slight, such as Spain and France
from the fteenth century onwards (p. 34).
346
michael confino
over state, and required the implementation of all the rights and
prerogatives attached to this status. But this state of aairs didnt
last long. The militant stand of the papacy and the gradual strengthening of the secular power led inevitably to acute and endless conicts,
during which the secular rulers interfered in church aairs and in
the nomination of popes, and above all arrogated to themselves
the investiture of clerics and the distribution of spiritual oces.
Sucient to read the list of wrongdoings which Pope Gregory VII
( 10731085)famous for bringing emperor Henry IV to Canossa
attributed to the brachium seculare to see the extent of the churchs
submission and its manipulation by emperors, kings, princelets, dukes,
and lesser notables. Gregory VII issued indeed his dictatus papae on
papal world dominance, but the subsequent history of the papacy,
with its popes and antipopes, scandals and nepotism, embezzlement
and luxury, futile dethronments and contested excommunications,
bears witness that the church didnt enjoy a status of supremacy (nor
of spiritual leadership) over the secular rule. After all, the Reformation
came, at least in part, as a result and as a remedy to this deplorable
situation.
Thus, in spite of conventional wisdom, it seems that in many
respects till the beginning of the early modern times (about the sixteenth century or so), the western church cannot be advantageously
compared to Eastern Orthodoxy, including the cardinal issue of
church-state relations. In any case no substantial dichotomy or
fundamental contrasts can be observed in this regard between the
western and the eastern churches. How things evolved in this respect
during the subsequent periods is a weighty question which deserves
serious treatment in its own right.
Doctrinal inuences on church-state relations
The tenet postulating the supremacy of church over state was rarely
implemented, not only because of unfavorable political constellations
and the overwhelming strength of the secular power, but also because
of inner tensions within Eastern Orthodox theology and worldview,
tensions which hindered the drive toward hegemony of the church
(at least till the late Middle Ages) and facilitated its submission to
the state. It has been said also that in Eastern Orthodoxy another
strong inhibiting factor of the drive to hegemony has been its propen-
347
12
348
michael confino
13
In the case of the Bulgarians, this represented an ironic and unwelcome twist
of history. In the 860s, when the Bulgarians decided to convert to Christianity, they
chose Byzantium over Rome as their mentor (after a erce competition between
the two). One of the main reasons for this decision was that the Byzantines did
not insist on the use of Greek in the liturgy, while the Roman Church required
Latin. In fact, two clerics, Cyril and Methodius, had already invented a cyrillic
alphabet for the translation of holy books and prayers from Greek into Old Slavonic.
14
See Ramet, 1988, pp. 78.
15
It has been often observed that anti-Semitism was extremely weak and inconsequential in Bulgaria. I can venture here from personal experience (being born
and raised there) a hypothetical proposition that for Bulgarians anti-Hellenism served
as a substitute for antiSemitism (you may have to hate somebody, but not everybody). Negative stereotypes of the Greek were similar to those attributed to the
Jew in other countries, such as Greece and Romania for instance. From elementary school onward, kids were bred (before and after the 1930s) with intense
anti-Greek feelings and representations. Textbooks, in rst grade and up, told as a
rule the story of Emperor Basil 11 Bulgaroktonos (Bulgaroubietz: Slayer of Bulgarians), who, after the battle of the Belassitsa (Balathista) Mountain on 29 July
1014, had over 14,000 Bulgarian war prisoners blinded leaving a one-eyed man to
every hundred to lead them back to tsar Samuel, who died of the shock. The story
was illustrated with drawings of endless columns of hapless blinded soldiers heading home in vast and gloomy plains.
16
Engelstein, 2001, p. 141.
349
350
michael confino
17
For a recent examination of this topic see Walters, 2002, pp. 358364; see
also Ramet, pp. 319.
18
Meerson, p. 33.
351
his view: Attachment to the heavenly king, [and] the act of communion in sacraments.18
This structural decentralization contributed to promote the right
of the Orthodox churchs national branches to use the local language in liturgies and theological writings. This practice brought
the church closer to the people, and had the twofold eect of
strengthening the bonds within the community of believers, and also
separating the various national churches from each other. In this
respect the Orthodox church seems to be closer to the Protestant
congregations; and although it has been often asserted that it had
nothing corresponding to Latin to give its members a sense of
oneness transcending national boundaries, such positive eect is highly
dubious considering the fact that in the Catholic church only the
hierarchy understood Latin, while the mass of the believers did not,
and one wonders what kind of oneness this gap could generate.
(And has this oneness ever prevented bloody wars between western
nations whose peoples attended mass ociated in Latin?) In fact,
as John Meyendor has convincingly argued, instead of being a
weakness, part of the inner strength of the Orthodox church was its
traditional theology, transmitted to the laity through the medium of
the vernacular liturgy.19
Historical events and circumstances, not less than theological tenets
and ecclesiastical policies in Eastern Europe, South-Eastern Europe,
and the Middle East during the centuries, resulted in that the main
trend of Orthodox Christianity was centrifugal, away from the ecumenical and towards the regional and the national. And this trend,
in turn, has tended to blur the distinction between church, state and
nation, which means also, by the same token, that it has tended to
strengthen the bond between the church, the state, and the nation.
This was so in Russia, and to an even greater extent in the Orthodox
churches in the Balkans.20
19
See Meyendor, 1982. To illustrate this point I may add the following example. Recently a guest of mine, an Italian Catholic, attended mass in the church of
Abu Gosh, an Arab village near Jerusalem; as usual mass was conducted in Arabic.
When leaving the church, my guest had this comment: It was very strange and
perplexing. I imagine that during the centuries this must have been the feeling of
millions of western Catholics when mass was read in Latin.
20
Pipes, 1976, p. 224.
352
michael confino
Russian Orthodoxy: traditions, old and new21
21
There is a vast literature on Russian Orthodoxy (exegesis, theology, catechetics, canon law, church history, monasticism, etc.). It is richer on pre-Petrine Russia
than on the imperial period. In terms of ecclesiastical publications the Soviet regime
is a hiatus during which appeared either anti-religious propaganda or (after the late
1930s) nothing at all. At that time the center of activity moved to the west (mainly
to France) where emigres scholars and theologians, and non-Russian specialists
published from the 1920s original and valuable studies. In Russia a renewed interest in these subjects is apparent in the 1990s (on this trend see Freeze, 2001, pp.
269278). For some general works see: Dvornik, 1926; Florovskii, 1937; Fedotov,
1946; Taube, 1947; Seraphim, 1952; Kartashev, 1959; Talberg, 1959; Smolitsch,
1964; Billington, 1968; Pascal 1976; and the works cited in note 1 above.
353
22
Karpovich, 1978, pp. 1213. On this and other important topics, there are
valuable informations and interpretations in the following collections of articles:
Nichols and Stavrou eds., 1978; Le Christianisme russe. Entre millenarisme dhier
et soif spirituelle daujourdhui, a special issue of Cahiers du monde russe et sovihique, 1988; Hosking, 1991; Batalden, 1993; Kivelson and Greene, 2003.
23
Karpovich concurs to this assessment: And yet, in reality, almost from the
outset the Church became a subordinate member of the alliance, with the State
rmly retaining full measure of control (Church and State, p. 3).
24
Marc Szeftel, 1978, p. 128 (emphasis added); see also Bushkovitch, 1992; Baron
and Kollman, 1997.
354
michael confino
25
Karpovich thinks that patriarch Nikon attempted to advance in Russia the
medieval Western doctrine of the supremacy of the spiritual over the secular
power . . . (Church and State, p. 14). This view is open to debate, and is not
endorsed in this paper. Kliuchevskiis psychological portrait of Nikon remains a
classic piece of historical analysis, and worth to be read again despite the one
hundred years and more since it was published (see Kliuchevskii, 1957, vol. 3, pp.
298313. Aristeides Papadakis follows Karpovichs view and holds that Nikon sought
to break the Byzantine past by setting the church above the state, and he denes
the patriarch as a Russian Hildebrand. (Papadakis, 1988, p. 54).
26
For an exhaustive and still useful treatment see Kapterev, 1909. This conict
should not be confused with Nikons attempts at liturgical reforms which led to the
great schism in 1666; in his magisterial work (1959), Pierre Pascal gives a brilliant
analysis not only of the religious schism (raskol) generated by them, but also valuable information on the church and state issue at that time and the personalities
involved.
355
27
This was the case, for instance, during the reign of the rst Romanov, when
patriarch Filaret (16191633) was the virtual co-regent with tsar Mikhail, and was
ocially recognized as such. It should be said, though, that in addition to his skill
and prestige, Filaret owed his elevated position to the fact that he was the tsars
father.
28
Karpovichs interpretation is dierent, and he sees Peters ecclesiastical reform
as less revolutionary that it might seem at rst glance. It was a consummation of
a long historical process rather than a sudden break with the past (Church and
State, p. 15). In this respect he follows the grand interpretation of Vasilii Kliuchevskii
who held that Peters reforms were a continuation of trends and changes that began
in the second half of the seventeenth century; in his view Peters innovations consisted less in the substance of things, than in the harsh and brutal means he used
to implement the reforms.
29
For a good treatment of this subject see Cracraft, 1971.
30
Muller, 1972.
356
michael confino
its twelve members, appointed by the tsar, were drawn from the
ranks of the higher hierarchy, including the monastic clergy. Its main
functions were dened as the preservation of the uncorrupted
doctrine of Orthodox Christianity and proper norms for the conduct of church services, the combating of heresy and schism, the
verication of reports concerning miracles and saints, the extirpation
of superstition, the supervision of preaching, the choice of worthy
hierarchs (bishops, archbishops, and metropolitans), the supervision
of ecclesiastical schools, the censorship of ecclesiastical books, and
several others.31 The Holy Synod was under the supervision of an
Over-procurator (ober-prokuror), always a layman, who acted as the
sovereigns eye; he had for all practical purposes the status of a
cabinet minister,32 and although formally not a member of the
Synod, he became the actual head of the church administration
(the ocial and statutory title held by the tsar was not Head of
the Church, but Supreme Judge). The Synod employed an array
of ocials to carry out its ecclesiastical, administrative, and policelike functions.33 This synodal system of church governance was adopted
also, after their emancipation from Ottoman rule in the nineteenth
century, by Greece, and later on by Bulgaria.
Although the Russian Orthodox church, not unlike those in the
west, never succeeded to become the supreme power in the realm
(a status it didnt aspire to anyway), it had, until 1721, as mentioned
above, its autonomous administration, headed by ecclesiastical dignitaries (rst the metropolitans of all the Russians, then the patriarchs, and nally the keeper and administrator of the patriarchal
see) who recognized no secular authority except that of the Crown.
The tsars interfered at times in ecclesiastical aairs, but there was
some truth in Feofan Prokopovichs view that the Church continued
to remain a state within a state. If this was also the perception of
the tsar, then the reform was intended to bring it to an end with
the creation of the Holy Synod in 1721. And although in purely
religious matters the Holy Synod was to exercise the full rights and
power of the patriarch, this signied also the incorporation of the
31
357
Church within the framework of the state administration. This curtailment of the churchs autonomy had at least one positive result;
in the view of Gregory Freeze, an authority on Russian ecclesiastical history, this link between the church and the state structure was
instrumental in creating an improvement in the church administrative functions. It allowed also the Holy Synod to exercise a more
eective control over the various ranks of the clergy, and to enhance
the training of the priests.34 On the other hand, Freeze questions the
notion of the church incorporation within the state, and considers
that the church preserved until 1917 its special status as an institution
parallel to, not inside, the state apparatus. Moreover, he holds also
that, Set apart structurally and organizationally from the state, the
Synod retained considerable operational autonomy and, especially,
the capacity to defend ecclesiastical interests, to function more like
an interest group than a mere department of the state bureaucracy.35
This is certainly correct, but it does not invalidate the fact of the
churchs incorporation in the state structure. As is well known, in
bureaucratic organizations, and particularly in state bureaucracies,
various departments (ministries, agencies, bureaus, etc.) achieve various
degrees of relative independence and autonomy from the central
government or from superior authorities. (And this is so even in the
most centralized and authoritarian regimes.) In Russia, the case of
some provincial Governors (for example Mikhail Speranskii in Siberia,
General C.P. Kaufman in Central Asia), who took great liberties
in fullling their task and acted almost as Vice-Roys or Roman
proconsuls, is well known. Thus, in real life, the Synod was part of
the state bureaucracy, and at the same time held a considerable
degree of autonomy thanks also to the spiritual aura attached to its
eld of competence.
The Holy Synod continued to function as a ministry of ecclesiastical
aairs until the fall of the monarchy in 1917, when the patriarch
ate was restored. Tikhon, the rst patriarch, was elected in 1918;
after his death in 1925, the Soviet Government, like Peter the Great,
abolished de facto the patriarch ate and did not let an ecclesiastical
assembly to convene in order to elect a successor.36 Later on, by an
34
35
36
358
michael confino
37
The tting expression secular religion in reference to marxism and twentiethcentury communism was coined in the 1930s by Raymond Aron, a credit almos never
given to him.
38
Verkhovskoi, 1916; the other works have already been quoted above.
39
Freeze, 1985.
40
Since Nikon Russia has no church. She has a state religion. From that point
to [establishing] a religion of the State there is just one step. The religion of the
359
State was established by the government which succeeded the Empire in 1917.
Pierre Pascal, Avvakum et les debuts du raskol, p. 574; quoted in Agursky, 1988,
p. 493. Strangely enough, recent research has conned to oblivion both Pascal and
Agursky in spite of their authoritative works in Russian religious history; alternatively, when ndings and ideas of theirs are used, no credit is given them and no
attribution of authorship. One such example is the above mentioned article of
Agursky: post-Soviet historiography in Russia and in the west discovered (and
presented as innovations) religious aspects in the bolshevik project, and religious
motivations in Stalins bent to monolithic ideology, contracted, as it were, during
his seminarian years. None of these cases mentions Agurskys (let alone Boris
Souvarines) pioneering works in this eld. For the new Stalinologists, Souvarine,
author of the rst major book on Stalin and stalinism (1935), remains taboo as in
the Soviet times.
360
michael confino
41
Toynbee, 1948 see above n. 10. As another example illustrating the weakness
of the Byzantine heritage thesis one may turn to the often cited theory of Moscow,
the Third Rome. In fact, this theory was not identical with Byzantine universalism. The messianic and nationalistic elements with which it was tainted had little
to do with Byzantine tradition, and were not part of a Byzantine heritage.
361
42
A similar case can be seen in the Greek Constitution of 1833 which made
Orthodoxy an extension of the state. Papadakis writes that this settlement, authored
by king Otto I and the German Protestant Georg von Maurer, was fundamentally
Protestant and Western, alien to Byzantine tradition of church-state relations. It was
[. . .] inspired largely by the modern secular state rather than by any Byzantine
pattern (Papadakis, 1988, p. 51.)
43
Szeftel, 1978, p. 130; see also Karpovich, 1978, p. 16.
362
michael confino
In Russia, by the middle of the eighteenth century, this led to what Viktor
Zhivov has called the cultural synthesis of absolutism, which included religious
and secular forms of expression; see Zhivov, 1996, pp. 368369; see also Nichols,
1978, pp. 6789.
45
Szeftel, 1978, p. 136. This support was of paramount importance after the
secularization of the church landholdings (and the serfs attached to them) by Catherine
II in 1764; this act deprived the church of its main source of income.
46
Freeze, 1985, p. 88.
363
47
CHAPTER NINETEEN
366
eliezer ben-rafael
war. In all these, religion was the ally of nationalism and, with the
rise of latter, left strong prints on its further evolution. Religion itself
might undergo politicization and play a role of its own within the
politysanctifying the nation-state through messianic politics, for
instancewhile nationalism itself may tend to become a political
religion.
All in all, nationalisms draw on the religious background of the
population, even where the nationalists reject it personally. Nationalism,
says Anthony Smith (1991; 1998), emerges on religious foundations
and is infused with their motives, though in each society, it may mix
sacred and worldly notions in a dierent manner and with dierent
consequences. Nationalism raises new concepts of collective identity
that transform traditions and religion but rarely turns its back on
them. It draws symbols from the warehouse of traditional symbols
and alters their meanings, but still uses them to indicate an allegiance to a past that is both idealized and criticized. Idealized because
it asserts a collective historical destiny, and criticized on behalf of
new civic values (Schama, 1989; Tamir, 1993).
This perspective throws light on Jewish nationalism, since the religion-people link has always been a primary code of Judaism; this
anity of Zionism to values of traditional Judaism has been noted
(Katz, 1960; Avineri, 1981; Eisenstadt, 1992b). What has not yet
been considered is how, more precisely, religious value contents were
transformed to become ingredients of the national identity, and what
specic consequences this process entails for the new society. The
more intriguing of these issuesas nationalismhas here eectively
created a new society, not only thanks to references to religious
axioms but through confrontation with religious forces. Moreover,
the reliance of national identity on religious contents, it appears here,
does not necessarily follow one path only, and this may account for
tensions and conicts that may then constitute new endemic features
of the public scene.
It is against this background that we focus here on the question
of collective identityas widely understood in the literature (LeviStrauss, 1961; Giddens, 1991; Taylor, 1998). We see by denition
(Ben-Rafael, online 2001), a collective identity as necessarily implying
three facets associated with dierent basic principles or dilemmas
between principlesin Levi-Straussian terminology, one would speak
of deep structures (Levi-Strauss, 1958). The rst asks how people
describe their link to the collective and their obligations to it; that
367
368
eliezer ben-rafael
369
tianity (Ragussis, 1995); while Jews were admitted into the French
army, the Dreyfus aair sparked a wave of anti-Semitism.1 Above
all else, the transformation of the Jews was spurred by their internal dilemmas, which were cast in a new light by Europes national,
democratic and industrial revolutions. Post-traditional outlooks regarded
the basic issuesthe deep structures of Jewish identityas questions
that could be given new answers which would ultimately construct
the space of modern Jewish identities.
A rst question related to the concept of the Jewish People, and
asked whether it could still indicate a collective whose denition was
primarily religious, or whether it should now be seen as a community in the social, cultural, and even ethical sense. In other words,
did the term still refer to an actual collective whose existence in the
modern world needed no justication beyond the mere fact of its
being a collective entity? A second question, related to the concept
of the God and Torah of Israel, i.e. the singularity of the collective
in the traditional identity, is how could the singularity of Jews be
indicated in the new secular reality? In reaction to the previous religious attitude, growing numbers began to wonder whether Judaism
might not better be seen as a culture, a collection of symbols and
a history. A third question concerned the concept of the Land
of Israel, the response of traditional Judaism to the place of the
collective which denes any other place as Galut, that is, exile. In
the traditional view, the Land of Israel is an actual geographical
location to which the Jews will return at the time of redemption.
It was now asked whether this was in fact the homeland of the Jews,
or whether it could be treated as a metaphor with moral, cultural,
or ideological meaning. The traditional answers of Judaism were only
the lot of a minority, the Orthodox (Urbach, 1971). Numerous other
answers to these three questions can be found in the plethora of
new forms of Judaism (Ben-Rafael, 2002)from Jewish enlightenment and Reform Judaism to the Bund and territorialism. Among
all these, ZionismJewish nationalismwould soon take the lead
among those dierent forms of Judaism.
1
In the early 1890s, it was discovered that someone in the French army was
spying for the Germans. The generals chose to place the blame on Alfred Dreyfus,
a Jewish ocer. Tried and found guilty, Dreyfus was exiled to Devils Island. As a
result of tireless eorts on the part of his family and well-known writers and public
gures, Dreyfus won a retrial in which his name was cleared.
370
eliezer ben-rafael
Zionists identity transformation
2
The most notable institutional arrangements in this context is the Law of Return
which stipulates that Jewsand this notion refers here to the child of a Jewish
mother or an individual who has converted to Judaismare allowed to immigrate,
acquire Israeli nationality and benet from special aid for integration.
371
to Jewish redemption alone, or according to its termthe normalization of the Jewish people. Seemingly conscious of this shortcoming, the Zionists have long tried to give universal meaning to
their image of the Jewish future by stressing its connection to some
universally utopian conceptsuch as with the notion of Socialist
Zionism. In other words, they tended to present Zionism as oering
an example of a social utopia for the world at large. By doing so,
they denied the principle of caste, foregoing any aspirations that
conicted with the demands of secular society, with which Zionism
also associated itself. The price they paid, of course, was exposing
Zionism to the criticism of proponents of the caste model, who saw
it as a form of collective assimilation into the non-Jewish world.
The Zionist leadersDavid Ben-Gurion, Moshe Sharett, Berl Katznelson, Zalman Shazar and othersresponded to the critics by claiming
that Zionism endeavored to build an enlightened society in the
Land of Israel, where the Chosen People would be a light unto
the nations. In their opinion, that was what the normalization of
the Jewish people meant (Gorny, 1990). By taking up this challenge
to combine a modern secular ideology with a uniquely Jewish inspiration and orientation, the Zionists hoped to present an ideological
alternative to the view of the Jewish nation as the carrier of the
promise of messianic redemption. The notion of exemplary society
(hevra le-mofet) which this aspiration conveyed included the republican
principle of cultural unity (mizug galuyot or fusion of exiles) that should
direct the engineering of the ingathering of the exiles (kibbutz galuyot).
The intention was not only to welcome Jews from all over the world,
but to create a new national Israeli culture as well, whose exemplary
character would be determined by its dedicationin a secular spirit
to the ethics of Judaism, socialism and liberalism.
A crucial element in achieving this objective was the revival of
Hebrew as a spoken language and its adoption as the legitimate
national tongue. Essentially, the successful creation of a spoken language from classical Hebrew3 was due to the fact that in the collective memory of Jews almost everywhere, Hebrew was the original
Jewish tongue and the language of Scriptures. The Zionists in Israel
This was greatly facilitated by the work of the secular writers of the Jewish
Enlightenment movement that developed in nineteenth-century Central and Eastern
Europe a rst wave of modern Hebrew literature and journalism.
372
eliezer ben-rafael
4
Obviously, the initiators of this linguistic revolutionthe pioneers of the rst
decades of the twentieth centuryactually had to invent its lexis and syntax to
meet the demands of a new time and place, and thereby, to expose it to a plethora
of inuences, bringing it closer in nature to European languages, as well as to
Yiddish and Arabic.
5
This is the only case in history in which a new language, not native to any of
its speakers, successfully became the language of a group which already shared a
common tongue.
373
desire for linguistic and cultural unication did not only contribute
to the unity of the new society but also to further divisions therein.
In fact, the same models that sought to produce unity promoted new
distinctions. The very call for unication indeed implied recognition
of the special status of those portrayed as the worthy role models
the generation of pioneers. Furthermore, as in any immigrant society where newcomers are striving to put down new roots, here too
being native became a source of social prestige. It is the children
of immigrants who fulll their parents lofty ambitions and ensure
the success of their endeavors. In the case of Israel, the native-born
also carried the bulk of the security burden and the armed struggle
that developed with the Arab environment from quite the earliest
stages, reinforcing their image as the salt of the earth. In addition, the sons and daughters of the pioneers were also highly conscious of being the children of people who had adopted a new
national Jewish identity, and of themselves representing a new kind
of Jew who had never known life in the Diaspora. The fact that
they were also a minority group for a long time, within a population of where the majority was made of immigrants, added to their
luster. As an elite which prided itself on this status, they created
their own symbols, the most conspicuous of which was a typically
nonchalant use of Hebrew that could be acquired only by being
born within the language, that is, in the country (Katriel, 1986).6
This inuence was linked to the Zionists self-image as the antithesis
of Diaspora Jewry that in their eyes bore the signs of dependence.
Quite a few of the sons and daughters of the pioneers displayed
a similar attitude to the Diaspora Jews who settled in the country,
seeing in them people who continued to bear the stigma of the
Diaspora. In contrast, they saw themselves the essence of Israeliness
that sprouted from the new form of life in the country. For a long
6
A no-nonsense languagea laconic style of speech which abhorred euphemisms
and high language in generalthis Hebrew underscored the connection to the
Middle East by incorporating numerous Arabic words, and encouraged a blunt,
casual, and natural way of speaking. By doing so, it expressed repugnance for
verbosity, protocol, formality, and sophistry, all traits attributed to Diaspora Jews
(Rubinstein, 1977). The sabra activities of hiking the length and breadth of Israel,
belonging to a youth movement, spending time on a kibbutz, and serving in the
army produced new words that were unfamiliar to those who didnt belong
(Shamir, 1970).
374
eliezer ben-rafael
time, entry into this elite was not easy, for those who had arrived
in Israel as youngsters but were not born here, those who had left
the ultra-Orthodox community but were still close to forms of religiosity, or Yemenites who had been in the country for many years
but remained attached to community values.
That culture has, however, undergone profound change over the
decades. The collectivistic approach that prevailed prior to the establishment of the state and in the rst years of statehood has been
replaced by a much more individualistic model following demographic, economic and political developments. The tatist ideology
that gained in strength during the 1950s and 1960s stressed the need
to move from utopia to nation-building. Pioneer was redened to
relate to anyone who contributed to the state: not only farmers
and settlers as in the past, but also professionals, public functionaries,
and business people. The country born out of war and strongly
aicted by security concerns reserved a place of honor for the armed
forces, and now placed great stock on a military career. Mass immigration which tripled the population within a few years brought to
the country a broad array of cultural groups that diused new perspectives and perceptions. Thus a new social order came into being.
In this new social reality, numerous myths were shattered, among
them the superiority of physical labor, which had been central to
the pioneering ethos. Now higher education and professionalism were
also considered legitimate pursuits. At the same time, immigration
and wars resulted in a constant strengthening of Israels relations
with the Jewish world, now viewed as the countrys natural partners,
in contrast to the anti-diaspora mood in vogue among Zionists years
before.
These economic, social, and cultural processes also had an impact
on the drastic change that overtook the leading forces of society.
Along with a constantly growing middle class came features of Western
consumer society while the 1948-generation (the generation of the
War of Independence) had become bureaucrats, nanciers, politicians, and businessmen. As this elite came to be dened in terms of
achievements, the meritocracy adopted a more formal standard language. The disdain for foreign languages disappeared as international communication gained in importance. English became virtually
a second language at all levels of education, professional life, and
business, and uency in English was now a status symbol.
Even in this context, some signiers of native culture persist today
375
7
This is expressed in Fundamental Laws regulating the work of institutions and
warranting individual freedoms.
376
eliezer ben-rafael
8
They consisted of Mitnagdim from Lithuania who adhered to Jewish classical
holy learning, and members of major Hassidic movements which emphasize the
value of spontaneous and emotional religious experiences. The Hassidim are themselves divided into dierent groups led by charismatic leaders.
377
9
Hence, Yeshiva students require exemptions from the army and large families
request special housing assistance.
378
eliezer ben-rafael
379
380
eliezer ben-rafael
10
As Yemenite Jews saw it, it was their faithfulness to this Judaism throughout
the generations that had brought them to the Holy Land by Divine Will. According
to this traditionalist Zionism, religious fervor in the Diaspora had been as important as the eorts of the pioneers who set down the basis of the Jewish State.
11
In fact, the last of the Yemenite Jews to immigrate to Israel, who arrived in
the 1990s, could barely recognize themselves in their Israeli cousins, and several
asked to return to Yemen.
381
12
As Weingrod (1990) demonstrates, the hilulaa festive visit to the tomb of an
individual considered a sainthas been gaining in popularity. Another example
of this phenomenon is the Moroccan Mimouna, the holiday of bread that follows
Passover, which gradually became so established that it now has the nature of a
public holiday for all edot. In addition, the religious practices of the dierent communities are often preserved in the many synagogues constructed for a specic eda.
382
eliezer ben-rafael
In a very similar manner to the elitism of the Ashkenazi ultraOrthodox as well of the national-religious, here too the motivation
behind the partys eorts reveal an ambition to ultimately dene an
all-Israel calling. In this case, this self-appointed mission is revealed
in the systematic replacement of Mizrahi by the term Sephardic
in the movements rhetoric. This latter term generally denotes a relatively small cohort of descendents of the Jews of Spain. Yet, it is
Yossef s contention that the Sephardic culture that predominated in
the yeshivot in the Land of Israel for hundreds of years, constitutes
the variety of Judaism which is the only one that can be truly considered to belong to the Holy Land. This legacy should therefore
be adopted by all Israeli Jews in the area of public, let alone national,
cult and rites. Since, moreover, the Judaism practiced by Mizrahi
communities is assumedly closer than that of the Ashkenazim to the
Sephardic legacy, this endows the Mizrahim with a calling of Israelwide signicance, namely, bringing Israels religious culture back to
its true legacy. In this spirit, Shas is working to introduce new
forms of prayer and ritual into those Mizrahi synagogues that are
willing to do its bidding (Leon, 2003), which, admittedly, is demanding
considerable sacrices from these communitiesi.e. setting aside their
own traditional rituals and texts.
Religious cleavages, Russians and Israeli Jewishnesses
In sum, the relation of nationalism and religion in the case of the
Jews has brought about a variety of cleavages. One cleavage revolves
around the role of Talmudic law in the codication of the social
order; a second, around the link of religious beliefs to national policies, and a third, around the competition of legacies in areas where
the religious rite applies. In all cases, it is spoken of actors moved
by a kind of mission who aspire to gain inuence over the center without making do with the widening of their space of freedom,
outside centers control.
The context of the evolving of these cleavages, which by no means
simplies the problmatiques that these cleavages represent, is the allegiance of Israeli Jews in generalincluding the non-observantto
traditional symbols. Surveys indicate that the majority of Israeli Jews
by no means disassociate themselves from the sources of Judaism.
Many of those who do not hesitate to describe themselves as secular
383
384
eliezer ben-rafael
13
385
14
This model nds diculties among Moslem Arabs as well, as illustrated by
the example of the Muslim population of France itself.
386
eliezer ben-rafael
387
15
In 1951, Ratosh founded the Young Hebrews Center whose organ, Alef,
lobbied for a constitution that would dictate total separation between religion and
state and annul the established connection between the Jews and Israel (Gorny,
1990).
388
eliezer ben-rafael
been felt mainly since the early 1980sare not critical of Diaspora
Jewry, but of Israeli Jews themselves, who dene the country as a
Jewish state and not the state of all its citizenswhich should
include non-Jews on equal footing with Jews. This camp focuses on
the Israeli-Palestinian conict, placing the blame for the hostility on
Israel and Zionism, and more importantly with respect to this analysis, it advocates eliminating the reference to Judaism as the basis of
national identity (Furstenberg, 1995) contending, in the spirit of nave
materialism (Orr, 1994), that, as a religious belief, Judaism is doomed
to disappearjust as all other religions will presumably disappear
in the wake of the advance of science and secular culture. In this,
both Canaanites and post-Zionists agree to assert a common velleity to detach the country from any religious allegiance and to request,
on this basis, its de-Zionization. The Israeli nation, they contend,
should be based on territory and be socially and culturally pluralistic.
The Jews in Israel belong to the Israeli nation in the same way that
those who reside elsewhere belong to other nations (Agassi, 1990;
Agassi, Buber-Agassi, and Brant, 1991). Anti-nationalists, whether
Canaanite or post-Zionist, see Jewish nationalism emptied from its
substance as soon as it is detached from the contributions of religion, and this detachment is necessarily bound to dissolve Jewish
nationalism. Hence, in addition to the quarrels between the religious
and the non-observant that the relation of religion to nationalism
brings about here, one more ground of dissension concerns the
question of the validity itself of a nationalism that eectively responds
armatively to the accusation of maintaining links to religion (see
also Silberstein, 1996).
In one way or another, these critical approaches which denounce
these links in the contemporary Israeli reality are not without reminding the two-three generations of Jewish intellectuals and militants
who, at the turn of the previous century joined radical causes like
revolutionary socialism and communism, and did not care to sacrice
their anity to Judaism on behalf of an utopia where Jewishness
like any particularismwould necessarily lose any social, political or
cultural raison dtre.
For the time being, and as far as the overwhelming majority of
Israels Jews are concerned, crucial importance is widely attached to
the Jewish identity which, more often than not (among observant
and non-observant alike) mixes religious ingredients with nationalism.
Israeli Jews are not ready to reduce Judaism to either religion or
389
390
eliezer ben-rafael
16
According to Talmudic law, even a converted individual remains a Jew but
this law has been overshadowed by the ancestral custom of considering the conversion of Jews to other faiths as loss.
17
In Israel itself the Orthodox holds a monopoly over conversion for mere
political reasons, but individuals who have been converted to Judaism by liberal
rites are accepted as such upon immigration, by the Israeli legislation.
18
As a rule, liberal conversion insists more than the Orthodox rite does on social
allegiance than on religious rigor.
391
of nationalism. Hence, while the non-observant insist on the secularization of traditional symbols and tend to emphasize general and
universalistic values, other forces remain more straightforwardly faithful to versions of nationalism that are closer to original religious contents. These forces become breeding-grounds for cleavages and political
confrontations that mark the evolving of the setting. As a rule, in
the very context of the specic relation of religion and nationalism
in this case, religious forces tend to present themselves as a special
elite, i.e. as authorized guardians of religious interests assumedly
of general crucial importancethe role of Talmudic law in the
social order, the relation of religious commands to national policies
or the predominance of given legacies over others in public cult.
(6) The Jewish case of nationalism also shows that the link to religion, in a majority-minority setting, excludes the eventuality of mutual
assimilation of the two camps. This denies the validity here of a
republican model which would ignore the particularism of both the
majority and the minority. It is rather a pluralistic model, in a vein
reminiscent of the UK, that should be of relevance in the attempt
to reconcile the ambitions of a dominant group to determine the
collectives overall personality and its obligations to respect the rights
of the minoritys full democratic participation through the proliferation of compensatory rights and privileges.
(7) Last but not least, we also learn from the Israeli-Jewish case
how far a society grounded in a nationalism which draws values and
symbols from religious traditions may be prone to intellectual and
academic debates about the very validity of its national ideologies,
on the ground of the eventual total detachment of protagonists from
religious values per se.
All in all, the Zionists reliance on religious motives was certainly a
contributory factor to their success but it also widely accounts for
the development of the cleavages that have wracked it ever since.
To be sure, as a modern society, Israel also experiences other conicts,
and especially class quarrelsin fact, it rates among the highest
among the nations of the world in the number of labor disputes and
strikes. Yet in spite of its eventual acuity, this dimension remains
secondary in national politics, where two other parameters clearly
dominate. The rst is the right-left cleavage which refers here mainly
to hawkish versus dovish attitudes toward Israels conict with the
392
eliezer ben-rafael
PART FOUR
CHAPTER TWENTY
396
david shulman
2
I want to thank Velcheru Narayana Rao for illuminating discussions of all the
Telugu works mentioned in this essay.
3
Narayana Rao, Shulman and Subrahmanyam 2001.
4
Narayana Rao, Shulman and Subrahmanyam 1992.
5
See Shulman, in press.
6
Narayana Rao 1996.
397
thought of as the modern age, and that it evolves mostly organically, from within, without being dependent on sustained contact
with external, especially Western, forces. Thus Apparao is, in a way,
the culminating voice in a long series of innovative poets and thinkers
hence, perhaps, the remarkable resonance and impact of his work.
Kalinga
There is also a more specic background to the Kanyasulkam and the
Vizianagaram cultural production of which it was a part. The city,
some 50 kilometres north of todays large port-city of Visakhapatnam,
very close to the coast, is situated in the heart of the region sometimes known as southern Kalinga. It is a setting of remarkable physical beautya fertile, rice-growing plain bounded by the sea to the
east and the high hills of the Eastern Ghats to the west. Vizianagaram
District is mostly Telugu speaking, but culturally this area is perfectly continuous with the Oriya-speaking northern Kalinga (presentday Orissa) and marked o by many conspicuous diagnostic features
from deltaic Andhra to the south. Historically, too, Kalinga, in both
its segments, has its own particular integrity. There is, for example,
a pronounced tribal element, evident both in the formation of the
major ritual systems (such as the Jagannatha temple at Puri) and in
the political domain. Tribal kingdoms and city-states, Hinduized
in various degrees, still exist in the uplands; they have profoundly
inuenced the development of all the little kingdoms on the coastal
plains, including Vizianagaram. If we go further back in time, we
can see traces of the ourishing proto-Mahayana Buddhist civilization that once saturated Kalinga with stupas, monasteries, and schools.
These Buddhist communities were eventually replaced by Brahminical
institutionsalso of a distinctive typebut a vital substratum of
diverse heterodox traditions survived here right up to the present
day. A particular variety of Tantric Yoga developed in Kalinga and
continues to generate living lineages of teaching. We can see something of it in Laksmidharas famous sixteenth-century commentary
on the Saundarya-lahari; and there is a strong local tradition that
Santarama, the author of the foundational text of Tantric Yoga, the
Hatha-yoga-pradipika, came from Kumili, just north of Vizianagaram
(the original home of the Pusapati dynasty that concerns us here).
Whether or not this tradition is historical, there is unquestionably a
398
david shulman
7
Kanyasulkam 5.4. The Mukhalinga-ksetra-mahatmyamu oers another perspective on this layer of the tradition (see below).
8
See Eisenstadt 1999.
9
See Pusapati rajulayokka purvottaram, 1; discussion by Berkemer 1993: 252.
10
According to the Ranga-raya caritramu of Dittakavi Narayanakavi (1.115),
Madhava Varma came to this region together with a Mughal adventurer called
Sher Muhammad Khan; for his services, Madhava Varma was rewarded with the
Vizianagaram kingdom. See Narayana Rao, Shulman and Subrahmanyam 2001: 63.
11
Pusapati rajalayokka purvottaram, 4.
399
succeeded in dominating its rivals and drawing them into an emergent scal and military system operating from the new capital of
Vizianagaramfounded in the second decade of the eighteenth century (according to tradition, on Vijaya Dasami, in the autumn
Navaratri festival, in the Vijaya year 17131714).
Several traditions speak of the founding of this aptly named city
of victory (more properly transliterated Vijaya-nagaram; I retain the
old Anglo-Indian spelling in order to dierentiate it from the wellknown imperial state far to the south in the western Deccan). The
site was, not surprisingly, chosen for security considerations: large
hills protected it to the east and north; to the west was the village
of Devulapalli; the fort-palace was constructed on the edge of a lake
fed by mountain rivulets.12 Originally, there was nothing here but
wilderness and a small village called Rega; the area was full of tigers
and subject to predatory raids by Muslims (mlecchulu). Still, after the
founding of the fort by the rst real royal gure, Peda Vijaya Rama
Raja, the entire Pusapati clan, with its women and children, marched
there from Kumile in four days.13 Some say that Peda Vijaya Rama
Raja rst discovered the site on a hunting expedition; to his amazement, his hunting dogs were savagely attacked there by the rabbits
they were hunting. The king asked a Muslim saint, Denkha Shah
Wali Baba, who was meditating in the shade of a tree, about the
meaning of this strange reversal. Denkha Shah said: Kumili will be
ruined. Build a new fort here. Heroic manliness ( paurusam) is in the
soil. So Vijaya Rama Raja moved his kingdom to Vizianagaram and
built the rst, mud-walled fort. An oral account collected by Georg
Berkemer insists that the founders of the forttwo royal brothers14
deliberately ignored the Muslim saints directions for building the
fort nearby, instead constructing it precisely on the spot where the
hunting dogs were attacked by a (single) hare; as a result, the new
state lost its chance to conquer the entire world.15 Denka Shahs
tomb is situated today about halfway between the royal fort and the
Square Shrine (sadur gudi) of the dynastys tutelary goddess, Paiditalli
another golden lady.
12
Ibid., 910.
Ibid.
14
This seems to be a memory of the historic rivalry between the brothers Peda
Sitaramaraju and Peda Vijaya Rama Raju.
15
Berkemer 1993: 275.
13
400
david shulman
16
Don Handelman and I are preparing a monograph on the cult of Paidi Talli
at Vizianagaram and the socio-political universe in which it is enacted.
17
Thus an early king, Raghunatha, a Vaisnava, is said to have given two or
three agraharams to Brahmins: Pusapati rajulayokka purvottaram, 3.
18
See detailed discussion in Narayana Rao, Shulman and Subrahmanyam 2001.
401
402
david shulman
to the late kings sister, Riva Rani. At his early death in 1915, aged
53, he left behind several unpublished works including another seminal but unnished play, Bilhaniyam, an extensive diary of many years
(still unknown in its original Telugu), and a comprehensive history
of Kalinga. His house, just around the corner from the palace-fort
in Vizianagaram, is today a public library and national monument.22
These bare facts tell us little of his achievement. Throughout the
twentieth century, Andhra modernists claimed him as their main
precursor (together with Kandukuri Viresalingam, who was active
further south, in Rajahmundry); but for the most part, they misunderstood the subtle awareness that he sought to express. His agenda
coincided only rather supercially with the meliorist social vision of
the reformers. As Velcheru Narayana Rao has written, His program
was to clear the path so that a modern Telugu prose could emerge,
and to modernize Telugu sensibilities with a new kind of poetry
a sort of cultural revolution, to create the basis for the emergence
of a new class of people who would have both the cultural condence
to assimilate alien inuences without being defensive, and who would
also possess the intellectual strength to retain what was valuable in
their past.23 To this end, Apparao fashioned almost single-handedly
a Telugu prose based on vernacular speech instead of the somewhat
articial language of the panditsthough he was familiar with the
robust prose of the karnam historians who preceded him. No attempt
to come to terms with his work can ignore this intensely controversial linguistic and stylistic break-through, which goes well beyond
the realm of language per se. The characters Apparao puts on stage
speak a rich, colloquial, highly individualized Telugu; each of them
is a strong subjective presence giving voice to a personal experience
of the world. Nothing like this had ever been seen before in Telugu;
some would argue that a century later this precise, symphonic, oral
eloquence has yet to be imitated or successfully extended. On this
level alone, Apparao is modern through and through.
As its name implies, Brides for Sale thematizes one of the classic
reformist targets in late nineteenth-century Andhra: the practice of
22
A vast secondary bibliography exists in Telugu on Apparao. Noteworthy is the
incisive biographical study in Russian by Petrunicheva 1985. See, rst, Narayana
Rao 2003: 28187.
23
Ibid., 284.
403
marrying o young girls, for sizable fees, to older men, often widowers. The usual result was a life of misery for the young bride,
inevitably widowed at a young age. Apparaos royal patron at
Vizianagaram, Ananda Gajapati, an active modernist in many ways,
initiated legislationthe Kanyasulkam Billin the Madras Legislative
Council with the aim of prohibiting such marriages; this initiative
was not approved. In the program advocated by the Andhra reformists,
proscribing the sale of young brides was only half the struggle; the
other side of it was enabling widow remarriage. Both these issues
gure prominently in Apparaos play.
The plot, to summarize very baldly the extraordinary profusion
of witty dialogue and melodramatic events, revolves around the desire
of an elderly Brahmin villager, Lubdhavadhanlu (Greedy Scholar),
to buy as his new bride the young daughter, Subbi, of another
Brahmin, Agnihotravadhanlu. The latter is more than willing to go
through with the deal, but the girls mother is staunchly opposed; she
induces her brother, Karataka Sastri, to stop the match by a ruse
in hard bargaining, he sells Agnihotravadhanlu another bride, who
is none other than Karataka Sastris own (male) disciple, disguised
as a girl. The complicated masquerade requires deft manipulation
by the plays true heroine, the world-wise courtesan Madhuravani, who
brings her most recent lover, Ramappantalu, into play as a middleman. After the wedding is duly performed, the eager bridegroom
soon realizes the catastrophe he has brought upon himself; and when
the new bride disappears, Lubdhavadhanlu nds himself in danger of being charged with murder. Interwoven with the main plot
is the somewhat disingenuous love of Girisam, a man about town
with half-baked education in English and an innite resourcefulness
in advancing his selsh interests, for the young widow Buccamma,
Agnihotravadhanlus other daughter. A supporting cast of lawyers,
policemen, a village priest-magician, corrupt ascetic, astrologer, and
servants, lls in the contours of this varied and, in a certain sense,
realistic social universe.
Elements of the plot, and the sophisticated parodic impulse working
through it, have medieval sourcesfor example, in the tenth-century
Sanskrit drama by Rajasekhara, the Viddha-salabhanjika, which was
well known in Andhra. We could also trace a clear line of succession
from the sixteenth-century Telugu novels by Pingali Suranna, mentioned above. But the development of the plot is, in a way, less crucial than the particular tone or tones Apparao has established. Here
404
david shulman
24
V. Narayana Rao is preparing a complete study to be published with his translation of the text.
25
Italics marks the verbatim insertion of English terms into the Telugu text.
405
Venkatesam: You stole a pack of tobacco from the Bhuktas. Wont god be
angry with you for your sin?
Girisam: See, when I was young, my unclewho was a rebrand like your
fathertwisted my earlobes and made me read Upanisads. In one of
those Upanisadsdamn it, I forget the namea student asks questions
and a teacher answers them. You are the student and I am the teacher
just like in that Upanisad. If someone records your questions and my
answers on a palm leaf, it will be a sacred textafter a couple of hundred years it will be known as Tobaccopanisad. Whats so sinful about
stealing tobacco? You just smoke it away, right? Moreover, its good for
the world to steal tobacco from those idiots who inhale snu.
Venkatesam: Hows that good for the world?
Girisam: Ill tell you how. If you smoke cigars, the smoke goes to the sky
like steam from a locomotive and turns into clouds that rain. If you
inhale snu, the sky gets dry from that pungent smell. Only your nose
drips a few drops, making your clothes dirty. So we should, by all means,
steal all the tobacco from those who inhale snu and smoke it all as
cigars. If God, however, says: Sir, Girisam-garu, you did commit a sin
and you have to honor hell with your presence, I will give him a lecture and confuse him.
Venkatesam: Whats your lecture going to be on? Im curious.
Girisam: What will that be? O Almighty God, did you create me to be
independent of you or dependent on you? If I am created to be independent of you, I did what I did and who are you to ask? If you trouble
me with your questions, I will organize a National Congress in Heaven.
Or, if I am created to be dependent on you, you are the one to take
responsibility for my sins and you will be the one to be punished.
Therefore, you go to Hell yourself. If you give me power over Heaven
in your absencefor just six hoursI will x a few mistakes in your
creation.
Venkatesam: What are those mistakes, sir?
Girisam: Serious mistakes. You yourself will agree. Is it not a mistake to
create a stupid person like your teacher in the high school?
Venkatesam: Yes, it is a mistake.
Girisam: Making a beautiful young girl like your sister a widowis it a mistake or not?
Venkatesam: Surely a mistake.
Girisam: There are a million more like this. And how much of Gods creation is wasteful? For instance, how many seas are there?
Venkatesam: Seven.
Girisam: Seven senseless seas. After creating a sea of milk, why do you need
a sea of curds and a sea of claried butter? This is pleonismredundancy. Now, another stupid mistake: God dumped this totally useless
salt-water sea in our neighborhood and placed seas of milk, curds, claried
butter, and sugar-cane juice in places impossible for anybody to reach.
If God hands over his power to me for one year, I will bring the ocean
of milk to Bhimunipatnam, the ocean of fresh water to Visakhapatnam,
406
david shulman
and the sea of sugar-cane juice to Kalingapatnam. I will make the entire
Eastern Ghats a tobacco forest. When I give this lecture, you know what
God will say? He will say, This man is impossible to defeat. [. . .] Then
God will ask his angels to take me on a horse cart, show me around
heaven and let me choose the best house in the place. I will tell them
that I want my favorite student Venkatesam to live with me. They they
will bring you on an airplane. We will live happily ever after. Enough
religious instruction for today.26
26
407
28
408
david shulman
Girisam [to Buccamma]: You are still protected by your parents. No man
can approach you. But your parents wont live forever. Once they are
gone, you, too, will be independent. Who knows how your mind will
work then? Once you stray from the straight path, you will regret not
marrying Girisam the proper way. You will think: If only I had married
him, I would have children and wealth and all happiness. Where will
I be then? In heaven, waiting for you. After this wedding, Venkatesam
and I will return to the city. I will long for you and give up food and
sleep. How long can anyone live without food and sleep? I will keep
thinking of you and spend many sleepless nights. Then one day in the
middle of the night, Ill be sitting in an easy chair, in front of me there
will be an electric lamp and a life-size mirror and I will look at myself
in the mirror and I will say to myself: This handsome face, these wide
eyes, this charming mustacheall these are of no use. What good are
they, when my Buccamma doesnt want them? In despair I will open
the drawer and pick up the double-barreled pistol, aim it at my heart
and shoot myself.
Buccamma: Dont, dont do that. If you say such things, Ill cry.
Girisam: Immediately the gods will send their sky-chariot and take me to
heaven. Will I be happy even in heaven? No. The gods beauty queen
Rambha will come bedecked with jewelry and will fall all over me, cooing, My sweet Girisam, I have never seen a more handsome man than
you. Come, give me a kiss. And I will say to her: Go away, I am
anti-nautch.29
29
30
409
410
david shulman
31
411
ripe Scholar as Your Highness, but he has ventured to seek your Highnesss indulgence, as he deems it the highest honour and his greatest ambition to be permitted
to dedicate the fruits of his intellect, poor though in merit, to a Prince with whom
knowledge is an absorbing passion and whose appreciative encouragement of letters,
has attracted to his court literary stars of the rst magnitude and inaugurated a
brilliant epoch in the history of Telugu literature.
33
Narayana Rao, Shulman and Subrahmanyam 1992.
412
david shulman
34
Mukhalingesvara-ksetra-mahatmyamu 3 (pp. 5357). I am indebted to Velcheru
Narayana Rao for making this text accessible to me.
CHAPTER TWENTY-ONE
IS ISRAEL WESTERN?
Sammy Smooha
Israel is Western in its self and international image. It is also considered Western in social science writings though not always explicitly.
Some scholars see Israel as an exceptional case, and many do not
openly declare it as Western, but few question its deviation from to
the Western model. Troubled by lingering doubts about this stock
view of Israel, I will examine the degree to which Israel qualies as
Western and attempt to uncover the forces that expedite and inhibit
its Westernization.
A better understanding of Israeli society is the main but not the
sole purpose of this study. The Israeli case can shed some light on
the necessary conceptual distinction between Western, modern and
developed, on possible non-Western trajectories of modernization
and globalization, and on the question whether the post-Communist
states that joined the European Union in May 2004 are indeed
Western.
Distinguishing Western
A distinction must be made between modern, developed and
Western. To become modern means to abandon old traditions
and practices and to replace them with new patterns. The essence
of modernization is the capacity, desire and legitimacy to change
and to adopt novel norms and habits. The process of modernization is pervasive in all contemporary societies.
While most societies are modern in the basic sense of being nontraditional and change-oriented, only a minority of them are developed. Developed countries are high in human and economic
development and capital. They have advanced market economies
and democratic political systems. The United Nations (UNDP 2003)
and World Bank (2003) gather and publish data on various indicators
414
sammy smooha
is israel western?
415
sammy smooha
416
5.
6.
7.
8.
9.
10.
A post-industrial economy.
Separation of military from society.
A liberal or consociational type of political democracy.
Separation between state and religion.
A civic-territorial form of nationalism.
An individualistic and bourgeois way of life.
For a list of indicators of Westernization, see Lauristin 1997: 30. With regard
to individualism as the core value in Western culture, see Triandis 1995.
2
The comparative sociological literature does not identify the Western model
as a distinct social type. Other terms are usually used, including developed, postindustrial, advanced industrial, capitalist and core. See, for example, Lenski 1994
and Hopkins et al. 1996.
3
These studies include Eisenstadt 1985, Horowitz and Lissak 1989, Shar and
Peled 2002, Kimmerling 2001, and Barnett 1996.
4
Divided Ireland is an exception in this area as in some other spheres, the most
important of which is the continued central role of religion in state and public life.
is israel western?
417
cure and internationally unrecognized boundaries, and controls extensive territory beyond the Green Line. Its borders are in dispute, both
internally and internationally. There is a sharp discrepancy in Israel
between state borders demarcated by control and frontiers delimited by sovereignty (Kimmerling 1989).
Israel further fails the related test of clear-cut societal boundaries
that distinguish Western societies. Israel controls over 10 million
people in the area of Mandatory Palestine, but over a third of them
are non-citizen Palestinian Arabs, subject to some form of military
rule. It also has about a quarter of a million foreign workers whose
stay in the country is neither permanent nor temporary. Israel declares
itself the homeland of the Jewish people and extends the automatic
right of immigration and citizenship to any Jew or to any person
closely related to a Jew. This makes 9 million Diaspora Jews and
an additional 34 million persons related to them eligible for immigration and instant citizenship and accords them a certain right of
hold over Israeli society. While 1,025,000 Arabs are citizens of Israel,
their societal membership is not considered full in a society that
denes itself as Jewish. Besides, the Israeli law is applied to a quarter
of a million Jewish settlers in the West Bank and Gaza but not to
the Palestinians there. Horowitz and Lissak (1989) see these ambiguous
territorial and social boundaries as a distinguishing feature of Israeli
society, thereby indirectly conceding the un-Western character of
Israel.
Image, orientation, ties and membership
Israel clearly passes the test of Western image, orientation and ties,
and even membership in the West as much as possible.
Image. Israel projects the image of a Western state. Israels political
and intellectual elites claim that the state is indeed Western in its
culture, economy, political democracy and way of life. The West
and the international community in general reciprocate by viewing
Israel as part of the West.
Orientation. Israel has a strong orientation to the West. When Israelis
think of their conduct and achievements, they always refer to the
West. Public leaders, intellectuals, journalists, judges, scientists, academicians, sportsmen, entertainers and other leading gures evaluate
Israels and Israelis performance by Western standards. In Israel,
418
sammy smooha
the general statement this is the way it is done in the world means
this is the way it is done in the West.
Israels powerful attraction to the West should not be taken for
granted because there are several good reasons for Israel to shy away
from the West. Zionism, Israels founding and main ideology, lacks
a clear goal to make Israel Western. Among all branches of Zionism,
as well as among the Jewish elites and the Jewish majority, there is
consensus that Israel should be Jewish, democratic and modern; however, none of these three objectives requires Westernization. In addition to Hebrew, Jewishness may refer to Orthodox Judaism, Jewish
heritage, or anything created by Jews, but it does not necessarily
imply the adoption of Western ways and values. The founders of
Zionism and Israel undertook to cast a new Jew and a new Jewish
society that would be unique and exemplary, but by no means clones
of a Western mold.5
The Jews have another strong reason to be reserved about the
West. It is under Western Christianity that they were accused of
killing Jesus, treated as a pariah people and subjected to centuriesold, virulent hatred, persecutions, pogroms and anti-Semitism. It is
in the West, and as recent as the past generation, that the hatred of
the Jews climaxed in unprecedented proportions: a systematic scheme
to exterminate the Jewish people by Nazi Germany, a Holocaust
that the Western powers did little to stop.
Another possible reason that Israel might be reluctant to be Western
is related to its geo-political location. Since it is located in the Middle
East and interested in living in peace with the Arab world, Israel
may feel a need to be integrated into this region in order to be
accepted by the surrounding peoples and countries. By becoming
Western, Israel reveals its alien nature and its objection to Middle
Eastern patterns, which reinforce Arab antagonism.
Despite these potential substantial objections, Israels actual pull
to the West is staggering. Of the Jews polled in a representative public opinion survey, conducted in March 1995 (TSC 1995), 47.9%
wished Israel to be most similar to the United States and Canada;
34.8% to Belgium, France and the Netherlands; leaving insignicant
proportions attracted either to Italy, Spain and Greece (3.4%), and
5
For a succinct presentation of Zionism and its continued relevance, see BarOn 1993.
is israel western?
419
to Jordan, Egypt and Morocco (2.4%) (11.6% did not answer). When
further asked to choose where Israel should be integrated in terms
of culture and way of life, 73.9% preferred Europe and America,
compared to only 9.8% who favored the Middle East (11.0% rejected
both, and 5.3% did not know). In another survey taken in September
2003, 78.0% of the Jews favored Israels integration into the Western
world rather than into the Arab and Moslem states in the region,
and in the area of culture 68.3% preferred Israel to integrate into
Europe-America rather than the Middle East.6
Several key reasons apparently underlie Israelis staunch disposition
toward the West. In their eyes, the contemporary West constitutes
success, richness, abundant opportunity, power, progress, freedom,
protection of individual rights, a sense of morality and advanced science and technology. Western countries dominate the world economy,
politics and media and are at the forefront of cutting-edge developments. Since Israeli Jews identify themselves with all these values
and assets, they want to be Western. They explicitly adopt Western
standards in various areas of life and judge their practices and accomplishments accordingly. They are driven by excellence and take the
successful West as a model of emulation.
Israels rm Western commitment also stems from the substantial
assistance it receives from the West. Many believe that Israel could
not have been created and would not have survived without Western
backing. Israel lives on political, military, economic and moral support
from the West.
The Western composition of the Jewish Diaspora also pulls Israel
to the West. Seven out of the 9 million non-Israeli Jews live in the
West: 5.3 million in the United States and about one million in
Western Europe (mostly in France, the United Kingdom and Germany)
and the rest in other parts of Europe. But the hearts of the two
million Diaspora Jews who reside outside the West (mostly in the
Commonwealth of Independent States and Latin America) lie in the
West, and they would move to the West if forced out and if admitted
to the West. Zionist and Jewish, Israel maintains ties with and receives
ample help from Western Jewry. A non-Western orientation on the
6
This survey was conducted by the author as part of the project of index of
Arab-Jewish relations. It was based on telephone interviews with 700 Jews who constituted a representative sample of the adult Jewish population in Israel. Sampling
error is 3.5%. The eldwork was carried out by Dahaf Research Institute.
420
sammy smooha
part of Israel may adversely aect the status of the Jews in the West
and harm Israel-Diaspora relations.
The founders and leaders of Israel spoke with admiration about
the West and with contempt about the East. The idea of the Jewish
state, set forth by Herzl, the founder of Zionism, was reminiscent of
bourgeois Austria at the turn of the twentieth century. Jabotinsky,
the leader of right-wing Zionism, and Ben-Gurion, the leader of
labor Zionism and the founder of the State of Israel, expressed a
denite desire to make the new Jewish state European and warned
against the cultural danger posed by the Jewish immigrants from
Arab countries.7
Ties. Israel does not only meet the criterion of being imagined as
Western and oriented to the West but also satises the requirement
of rm and ramied ties with the West. Israel passes this test very
well. Indeed most of Israels current military, commercial, scientic,
technological, cultural, tourist and sports relations are with the West.
In world politics, Israel is part of the Western bloc. It maintains
very close relations with the United States and good ties with Western
Europe. The United States acts as a political protector, defending
Israel in the United Nations and other international forums. It is no
small matter that during the 1980s and 1990s Israel enjoyed onethird of total United States foreign aid, and it is still one of the highest per capita foreign aid recipients. Israels special standing in the
United States also stems from the strategic activity of the Jewish
community in domestic American politics. Thanks to their concentration in urban centers and key states, strong political consciousness
and activity, contributions to campaigns and access to the mass
media, American Jews are able to master political clout that is disproportional to their meager numbers (less than 2% of the population).
Israels perceived and actual ability to inuence decision-making in
the United States, directly or through American Jewry, is an asset
that attracts other countries to Israel in hope that it would intercede
on their behalf with the United States.
Israel is part of the Western global security system. Its military
capability and the threats to its survival are taken into account by
7
For a sample of quotations from Zionist leaders in this regard, see Smooha
1978: 8789.
is israel western?
421
the Wests defense strategy. The West is committed to Israels survival and counts on its strength for its own defense. For this reason,
Israel can be considered a de facto ally of the West. Israels military technology and tactics are Western. Many Israeli-made weapons
have essential American components and hence their sale is restricted,
requiring the prior approval of the United States. Israel contributes
to the West by testing and upgrading some of the Western weapons.
It also shares in Western intelligence-gathering and in the ght against
terrorism.
The Israeli economy is equally tied to the West, and the bulk of
Israels trade is with the West. In 2002, Israeli imports totaled 33.1
billion US dollars, of which 72.8% came from Europe, North America,
Australia and New Zealand; exports amounted to 29.3 billion US
dollars, of which 74.4% went to these Western destinations (CBS 2003:
Table 16.5). A formal treaty provides for duty-free trade between
Israel and the United States although Israel continues to impose sales
tax and VAT on American goods as a source of revenue and as a
means of protecting Israeli products. Yet Israel is bound by the joint
agreement to gradually reduce these taxes.
Israels cooperation with the West in the area of science and technology is remarkable. Most Israeli scientists are at least partly trained
in the West. They are integrated into the Western scientic networks
and communities and take part in Western research and development
projects.
Israelis are frequent travelers. Although they reach almost every
corner of the globe, most travel to the West, especially to Western
Europe and the United States.8 The only exception to this rule are
the young backpackers, who prefer to go, following their discharge
from the army, to South America or to the Far East, mainly for
budgetary reasons.
Membership. Due to its geographical location in Asia, Israellike
Australia and New Zealand which are located in Oceaniais not
and is not expected to be a member of Western international organizations, especially the Western bloc in the UN, NATO and the
In 1999, 2.3 million trips abroad by Israelis were reported, of which 53.6% to
Europe, 21.9% to United States and Oceania, 12.8% to Asia, 1.8% to Africa and
9.9% were unknown (CBS 2003: Table 23.5).
422
sammy smooha
EU. It does however maintain close and special ties with them. For
years Israel has waged a failing struggle to join the Western bloc in
the UN because it is denied membership in the Asian bloc and as a
result deprived of representation in certain UN committees and organizations. On the other hand, Israel is not interested in becoming a
NATO member or an ocial US ally, in order not to be limited
in its national security policies and military actions.
Israel is an associate member of the EU, enjoying a favored status
that makes it easier and cheaper for her to trade with Europe (Monin
2003). It is also earmarked to join the new Wider Europe program
of the EU. Full membership in the EU is not a goal that the Jewish
state is seeking, because it may reduce its sovereignty. The EU is
based on the principle of free movement of goods, capital and people.
Most importantly, Israels immigration policy of admitting Jews only
will be annulled. As an EU member and a holy land, Israel may
be ooded by millions of Moslem and Christian immigrants from
Europe. The Palestinian right of return can also indirectly be fullled
through European citizenship.
Israel is a full member of many European organizations. It is a
member of the Council of Europe, a part of EU scientic and
research organs, and a participant in European sports and songs
contests.
It is the vision of Israeli elites to end the Israeli-Arab conict in
order to exit from the Middle East and accede to the Western world.
The conict ties Israel to the region, disrupts its globalization and
inhibits its integration into the West.
Demography
Being a modern and developed society, Israel is basically similar to
the West in demography. To illustrate, in 2001 life expectancy for
men was 76.1 years and for women 80.9 years, and infant mortality
rate per 1,000 live births was 5.1, putting Israel on a par with OECD
and Western states (CBS 2003: Table 28.2).
Israels divergence from the West in socio-demographic characteristics is rather striking, however. Most signicant is the total fertility rate of 2.89 in 2002 (CBS 2003: Table 3.12) that places Israel
much higher than the West which is marked by negative replacement rates. Israels annual population growth, which consists of both
natural increase and immigration, was 1.9% in 2002 (CBS 2003:
is israel western?
423
9
For an analysis of demographic trends in Israel in a comparative context, see
Goldscheider, 2002, and Della Pergola 2004.
10
In 2003 the Knesset enacted a temporary law denying a right to Israeli citizenship to Palestinian Arabs on the West Bank and Gaza who marry Israeli Arab
citizens. The ocial grounds for this human right violation are the use of marriage
as a means for fullling a right of return to Israel and the involvement of some
naturalized Palestinians in terrorism.
424
sammy smooha
11
Germany is quite similar to Israel in its law of return, extending admission
for settlement, automatic citizenship and support to ethnic Germans. The German
law of return is, however, restrictive when compared to the unrestrictive Israeli law.
It does not give a right of return to Germans who voluntarily left Germany (for
instance, millions of German descendants who live in the West are not entitled to
return). Quotas are also imposed on the number of ethnic Germans who return
annually. For similarities between Israel and Germany on immigration policies, see
Levy and Weiss 2002.
is israel western?
425
for the provision of equal rights and opportunities to the Arab national
minority.
Although Israels demographic divergence from the West has
declined over the years, it has remained substantial.
Research & development and higher education
Advanced industrial societies invest considerably both in research
and development and in higher education. Both are necessary to
maintain and to develop the economy and the high level of services.
Educational standards are rising continuously because of the increasing use of sophisticated computers, communications, automated
processes and technological machinery. The excellence of higher education and attendance rates provide the main key in these societies
for adequate functioning, economic growth and quality of life.
Israel does well in research and development and is at a par with
the advanced West. In 2001, it spent 4.8% of its GDP on civilian
research and development, a very high percentage that puts it at the
very top of countries in the world (CBS 2003: Table 28.14).12 It is
very high and rst in the world on various indicators of information and communications technologies (ICT) and in the registration
of patents (CBS 2003: Table 28.15 and Table 26.8). Israeli scientists publish about 1% of all publications that appear in refereed
scientic journals all over the world in the natural sciences, medicine and technology (Council for Higher Education 1994: 54). On
the index of scientic publications per capita, Israel ranks sixteenth.
Israel also compares well in expenditure on education and higher
education. In 2000, Israel spent 8.2% of its GDP on education (the
OECD average was 5.9%) and 12,508 dollars per college or university student, higher than most OECD countries (CBS 2003: Table
28.13).
Israel underwent a near revolution in the system of higher education in the 1990s. The number of students rose from 76,000 in
1990 to 180,229 (not counting the 36,710 students studying in the
Open University) in 2002, of whom 65.2% were in universities,
12
In 2001 Israels expenditure per capita on research and development was 1,029
dollars (in terms of purchasing power parities) which was 122.7 points compared
to the 100 US baseline points and 23 higher than the OECD rates (CBS 2003:
Table 28.14).
426
sammy smooha
is israel western?
427
428
sammy smooha
is israel western?
429
extended period. Men are not given an option to substitute civil for
military service. Military service is regarded as a cornerstone of civic
status and persons who do not fulll their army dutyArabs, ultraOrthodox Jews, the disabled and evadersare frowned upon and
considered not full Israelis. The military experience is part of being
an Israeli, a quite unique Israeli situation.
Israel diers from the West in having its military central not only
to individual and family life but also to society at large. The military
is a cardinal institution in Israeli society. Seen as a guarantor of
national survival, it commands a lions share of state resources and
9% of the GNP. National security considerations and concerns pervade all Israeli spheres of life. Decisions about layouts of infrastructures, such as highways, include heavy security components. The
relatively large number of children per family is also inuenced by
the high-risk attributed to soldiering in Israel. Free Jewish immigration to Israel is not only fulllment of an ideological Zionist mission
but also a coveted addition to the national ghting capability. A
major obstacle to gender equality is the edge accorded to men for
their military service and combat duties.
The question of militarism poses a critical issue. Some scholars
deny the existence of militarism in Israeli society (Lissak 2001). They
claim that the military, its ethos and commanders, have not grown
out of proportion despite the constant state of belligerency. But even
from a functionalistic-structuralistic perspective, militarism is necessary
for a society that has had to survive in a hostile environment for
over a hundred years. People should be socialized and believe that
the military can solve problems, including territorial-political disputes
like the Jewish-Palestinian conict. Over the years, as both soldiers
and civilians, the Jews have developed an iron wall mentality that
helps them ght the Arabs and makes them insensitive to the Arabs
(Lustick 1996). This is the kind of cultural or civilian militarism that
many Israeli Jews internalize (Kimmerling 1993; Ben-Eliezer 1998;
Levy 2003).
While the military in the West has, over time, become professional,
removed from society and geared to peacetime, the Israeli military
has maintained symbiotic relations with Israeli culture, politics and
society and has been fashioned for protracted violent conict.
sammy smooha
430
Democracy
Israel prides itself in being the only genuine democracy in the Middle
East, and indeed it maintains a good democratic record. The elites
and general public show a strong commitment to democracy. All
citizens enjoy all types of rights: human rights like dignity and privacy, social rights like social and welfare services, civil rights like
freedom of speech and association, and political rights like the right
to vote and to stand for public oce. The judiciary is impartial and
independent. The Supreme Court is liberal and active in checking
governmental actions. The press is free and highly critical of the
government. The army is under civilian control and does not unduly
inuence political decision-making. While still enjoying a fair amount
of freedom of action, especially in dealing with non-citizen Palestinians,
the secret services are steadily being brought under public scrutiny.
The political parties play an active role, have elected governing bodies
and most of them hold primaries for their heads and parliamentary
candidates. Parliamentary and municipal elections are fair and held
regularly. The civil service and the governing elite are not corrupt.
Israeli democracy has survived deep divisions and wars since 1948
without any severe crisis or breakdown.
These features make Israel a resilient democracy, but not necessarily
a rst-rate democracy. According to the Freedom House 2003 world
surveys of independent countries, Israel scored 1 (rst on a 17
rating) on political rights and 3 on civil rights, and was classied as
a free country (Freedom House 2003). In 2003 Israel Democracy
Institute launched the Auditing Israeli Democracy project for comparing Israeli democracy with 35 Western and non-Western democracies and for monitoring its quality over time. The fundamental
assumption of the project is that the political system in Israel is a
Western democracy. The comprehensive evaluation uses 31 objective indicators as well as public survey attitudes toward democracy.
Since the authors refrain from ranking the countries on an overall
index of quality of democracy, they nd Israel uctuating on the
various indicators and failing to meet high standards:
In comparison with democracies elsewhere in the world, Israels situation ought to arouse concern among proponents of democracy. Although
its relative position in the institutional aspect is good, in general, even
this aspect is not without its problems: voter turnout is decreasing, and
belief in the integrity of government has diminished somewhat. Israels
is israel western?
431
The quality of Israeli democracy is worse than this reserved assessment. Israel does not have a constitution or an equivalent of a constitution, and as a result the rights of individuals and minorities are
subject to restrictions. In 1992, the Knesset passed two laws: Basic
Law: Freedom of Occupation and Basic Law: Human Dignity and
Freedom. Although they are each entitled basic law, both were
enacted by a simple majority, and they lack a binding constitutional
authority (Gavison, 1998). Yet the Supreme Court takes advantage
of them in buttressing its judicial activism for broadening the limits
of democratic rights and freedoms.15
Israel is also situated in a permanent state of war. During the
War of Independence in 1948, the government declared a state of
emergency that has never been lifted. Consequently, the government
and the military possess sweeping legal powers, including administrative detention, declaration of curfews, closure of areas, land
conscation, use of military courts against civilians and censorships
and banning of books and the press. These excessive powers are
used to legislate parts of the budget law and to deter and to restrict
minorities and dissidents (Hofnung 1996; Barzilai 2003).
Furthermore, Israel declares itself as both democratic and Jewish.
Along with equal rights for all, Jewish dominance is institutionalized
and Jews are accorded special status. Israels language, holidays, days
of rest, times of remembrance, emblems, symbols and heroes are all
Jewish. Through the Law of Return and immigration policy, the
15
The leader of this undertaking is the President of the Supreme Court, Aharon
Barak. See Barak 1992.
432
sammy smooha
is israel western?
433
16
These fundamental deciencies of Israeli democracy, especially its built-in
inequalities and exclusions, prompt some scholars to argue that Israel is not democracy
at all. See, for instance, Ghanem, Rouhana and Yiftachel 1999.
434
sammy smooha
Religion
The West is by and large secular. The wars between state and religion were fought during the modern era and ended, in the last century, in de jure or de facto separation of church from state. In
consequence, religion is squeezed into the free market to compete
with other institutions for attention, support and money.
In this respect Israel is denitely non-Western. No war has as yet
been waged between state and religion, and the conict is pushed
to the backburner. The population is divided into religious communities and everyone is registered by the Ministry of the Interior into
a single religious category. The ocial religious communities are
entrusted with a monopoly over marriage, divorce, custody of children,
burial and, in the Jewish case, also with the crucial denition of
who is a Jew. The state lavishly funds religious services, synagogues,
religious schools, yeshivas (Talmudic colleges) and a plethora of other
religious associations and activities. It exempts scores of thousands
of yeshiva students from military service and provides them with
tuition and subsistence allowances. The state recognizes and empowers
only Orthodox and ultra-Orthodox Judaism, ignoring Conservative
and Reform Judaism. Public transportation does not run on the
Sabbath and Jewish holidays. The public schools and mass media
are infused with many religious symbols and contents.
This integration of religion and state generates considerable tension among Israeli Jews. To mention just the most serious hardships,
Jewish women are clearly discriminated against in secular Western
terms (some of them are not allowed to marry or are left deserted:
they are neither permitted to serve as religious judges nor as witnesses in rabbinical courts). The ospring of mixed-marriage couples
encounter the hurdles of ambiguous status. Many people are denied
the right to marry because there is no provision in the Israeli law
for inter-faith and civil marriage. Conservative and Reform Rabbis
are neither recognized nor authorized by the state to fulll ocial
religious functions, such as ociating at marriages. Unlike Judaism
in the West, that stresses its universalistic, humanistic and moralistic aspects in an open, competitive environment, the monopolistic
Orthodox and ultra-Orthodox Judaism in Israel is excessively ritualistic, politicized, nationalistic and ethnocentric (Liebman 1993;
Liebman and Cohen 1990).
The central place of religion in state and public life in Israel and
is israel western?
435
17
For a discussion of the dierent types of nationalism and presentation of Zionism
in comparative perspective, see Smith 1992b and 1995.
436
sammy smooha
unication, and by multiculturalism, Jewish and Palestinian nationalism still run high in Israel. National identities, interests and commitments are still paramount, deeply dividing Jews and Arabs within
Israel and in the region.
In Israel, contribution to the public good is still an ever-present,
major demand; while in the West individual concerns are pivotal.
Israelis are expected to take the national interest into consideration,
not just to cater to their private careers and kin. They are supposed
to make personal sacrices for society, to volunteer for various tasks,
to ght and to die if necessary for the country, to pay high taxes
and to feel guilty when emigrating from the country. Israeli Jews
are also expected to feel a close anity and strong emotional solidarity with millions of Diaspora Jews and to welcome and help new
immigrants, though in fact many feel indierence, even a conict of
interests vis--vis non-Israeli Jews and newcomers. Israeli Jews are
constantly mobilized for national projects, such as the settlement of
the Negev, the Galilee, and even the controversial Golan Heights
and the West Bank and Gaza Strip.
The long-term trend points, nevertheless, to a decline in Jewish
nationalism in Israel. Private aairs are increasingly gaining priority
and legitimacy. This is well reected in the spread of the Freier syndrome (the opposite of the pioneer), according to which the Israeli
will not do anything without getting a fair reward for it and will
not let others or the state take advantage of oneself (Roniger and
Faige 1992). Israelis are becoming more and more bourgeois in their
mentality and conduct. Despite this general trend of change of Israeli
society, individualism as a value and a behavior has to compete hard
with collectivistic and communitarian orientations (Roniger 1999)
and nationalism runs high and at a signicantly higher level than in
the West (Don-Yehiya and Susser 1999).
Way of life
The Israeli way of life is still not Western although it is increasingly
becoming so. There is a continuous trend toward the embourgeoisement of Israeli Jews, bringing them closer to Westerners.18 This
18
is israel western?
437
Israeli drift toward the West is incomplete, though, and remains far
from eroding the special Israeli way of thinking and behaving.
Israelis resemble other Westerners in their modern way of life. In
2002, 92% of them lived in towns and urban localities (CBS 2003:
Table 2.12) as compared to under 80% of the populations in highincome countries (World Bank 2003). Israeli Jews come closest to
Westerners in the set of values known as the Protestant ethic. They
share with Westerners the belief in the ability to control ones life
and destiny and in hard work, the drive for achievement and excellence, tough competition, a positive orientation toward change and
innovation, setting a high amount of income for saving and wealth
accumulation, a high regard for science and technology, a wide exposure to media, an emphasis on information gathering and learning
and a strong consumerism and materialism. Israeli Jews also increasingly adopt Western leisure pursuits. The young are engaged in pop
music, disco dancing, movie going, television watching and Internet
usage, much like other Western youth. Compared to Westerners,
however, Israeli youth and adults have remained remarkable in their
high rate of book reading, intensive domestic and international tourism,
and a high incidence of beach-going and sun-bathing (Katz et al.
1999).
In some key areas, Israelis dier appreciably from Westerners.
Social relations are still strongly marked by spontaneity, warmth,
personal and non-technical contacts, neighborliness and a sense of
community. These patterns stand in contrast to the alienation and
impersonality that characterize social relations in the West. Israeli
manners are also peculiar. Israelis are known for their directness,
chutzpah, use of rst names, roughness, informal but fashionable
dress, assertiveness, aggressiveness, impoliteness, frequent invasion of
privacy, inattentiveness, interrupting speaking manner and inconsiderate driving. Improvisation is also a common Israeli trait. Israelis
tend not to plan ahead in detail, but leave a wide margin for improvising. They believe in their ability to cope with contingencies and
embarrassing situations.19
19
An exploratory study of software development in Israel reveals the commando
syndrome of Israeli developers. To quote: Clarifying the meaning of the term
commando in the Israeli mind may be best done with a list of terms closely associated with it in the Israeli culture: imaginative, unconstrained, informal, quick,
438
sammy smooha
small-scale, exible, resourceful, front line, hard work, dicult, self-reliant, aggressive,
lack of sense for order and administration, specialized, intensively trained, eective,
action-oriented, trouble shooting, elitist, arrogant, improvisational, reactive,
Commando properties are very useful in product development and focused software problem solving but are less so for long-term business strategy, marketing planning, patient attention to customer needs, or the immersion in dierent cultures to
understand subtleties (Ariav and Goodman 1994: 21).
is israel western?
439
shaped and managed Israeli society from its inception. While these
East European Jews may have been Western in orientation, they
have been preoccupied with concerns incompatible with Western
patterns.
Another key factor is the fusion of ethnicity, religion and nationality
in historical and contemporary Judaism that has precluded the emergence of a new Israeli civic nation grounded in a common territory
and shared citizenship. Despite being a modern, secular and revolutionary national movement, Zionism accepted this peculiar nature
of Jewry because of its East European roots.20
Israel is a relatively new entity that emerged in the mid-twentieth century. It lacks the centuries-long history of Western civilization. Like immigrants and descendants of immigrants to Western
countries, Jews who come to Israel endure rapid change; in Israel,
however, change takes the form of modernization, not Westernization,
because no Western model has been in existence for the immigrants
to follow. With the passage of time, though, Israel may gradually
lose its peculiarities and converge with the West.
The Israeli-Arab conict, which has been part and parcel of Israeli
society from its inception, is a primary factor forestalling its full
Westernization. The implications of this conict are evident in many
areas. To mention just a few, the dispute with the Arab world feeds
the Arab economic boycott of Israel, severely limits investments by
multi-national corporations and deters the government from shifting
fully to pro-market policies because of fear of social dislocations.
National security considerations and survival threats dictate a policy
of Jewish immigration at all costs, maximal mobilization of society,
collectivistic orientation, cohesion and other clearly non-Western
patterns.
Some of these historical impediments combine with other current
obstacles that block Israels way to the West. Zionism still constitutes a powerful force containing Israeli Westernization. It is a nonWestern form of ethnic nationalism which is central in the lives of
Israeli Jews. As such, it magnies the particularistic forces of Jewish
20
Sternhell (1998) analyzes the far-reaching implications of the East European
origins of Zionism for Israeli society. He shows that the project of Zionism was
ethnic nation-building rather than forming a just, socialist society. Shapiro (1977)
also traces the low-rate and formal nature of Israeli democracy to its East-European
origins.
440
sammy smooha
21
Ram (2003) calls this Israeli stream neo-Zionism and argues that it has
become dominant since Rabins assassination.
is israel western?
441
accepted standard denition, but it is possible to identify the institutional characteristics common to Western societies.
A detailed application of the Western model shows that Israel
qualies only partly. Israel is Western in self-image, orientation and
ties, science and technology, higher education, market economy, procedural democracy and Protestant ethic. But it is not Western in the
absence of permanent borders, blurred criteria of membership in
society, high natural increase, centrality of family, focal position of
the military, state intervention in the economy, not-high standard of
living, strong role of religion in public life, lack of robustness of the
law, weaknesses of democracy and salience of ethno-nationalism. The
main causes for Israels failure to become Western are the nonWestern origin of the founding fathers and charter group, the entangling unity of ethnicity, religion and nationality in Jewry, the East
European roots of Zionism, and the need of total mobilization for
surviving in a hostile environment. These inhibiting forces continue
to slow down the ongoing process of Westernization that Israel has
been going through as a result of steady democratization, accelerated
globalization and painful transition to the peace (non-belligerency)
era. Israel in the 2000s is much more Western than it was in the
1950s and 1960s, and it is constantly Westernizing in many areas
of life. Israelis are becoming increasingly more individualistic, materialistic and bourgeois, adopting more openly and fully the positive
and negative traits of the West. Israels Western image, desire to
extricate itself from the Middle East and to integrate into the West
are potent forces that draw it closer to the West.
The Israeli case-study demonstrates that the Western model is not
readily exportable, globalization can occur without Westernization
and the claim of the post-Communist European states for being
Western should be scrutinized. The examination of the Israeli case
rejects the thesis that globalization necessarily leads to homogenization of and convergence between societies all over the world and to
their recasting into the hegemonic, capitalist, Western mold. The
non-Western origin and experience of the Jewish population, the
short-span of Israels development, the protracted Israeli-Arab conict
and the ethnic nature of Zionism are powerful and historically specic
factors discouraging Westernization. Israel responds to the forces of
globalization and close ties with the West by combining emulation
of certain Western patterns with new ways and syntheses.
Semi-Western Israel makes it clear that there are non-Western
442
sammy smooha
alternatives of development and modernization and that globalization leaves much diversity and localism in the world today. What is
true of Israel may hold true for Japan, China and South Korea in
the Far East and for some post-Communist states in Central-Eastern
Europe.22 A study of the transition of Estonia, for instance, conceives
of its re-independence in terms of return to the Western world,
namely, that Estonia was Western during the inter-War period, was
forcibly annexed to the Soviet-Eastern civilization in 1940, and it
has made its way back to the Western civilization after its liberation
in 1991 (Lauristin and Vihalemm 1997). Although Estonia, like Israel,
meets certain Western criteria, it fails other standards, as evidenced
in its ethnonationalism, the appropriation of the state by its ethnicEstonian majority and the denial of citizenship to most of its Russianspeaking residents (Linz and Stepan 1996). The accession of Estonia
to the EU in 2004, along with nine other countries, would accelerate
its Westernization but it would not necessarily make it suciently
Western. The Israeli case shows that despite globalization, international images and wishful thinking, societal change takes various trajectories and molds, and that there are alternatives to Westernization.
22
For a discussion of the limits of homogenization resulting from globalization,
see Barber 1995, Warde 1994, and Eisenstadt 2003a.
CHAPTER TWENTY-TWO
444
gerard delanty
445
446
gerard delanty
447
448
gerard delanty
449
450
gerard delanty
451
1
See for example Gaonkar (2001), Taylor (1999), Eisenstadt (2000b, 2003a),
Pieterse (2004), Dirlik (2003), Therborn (2003), Featherstone et al. (1995).
452
gerard delanty
specically dened by a mode of cultural translation in which culture is itself a mode of translation. Modernity might be seen as a
condition in which the form of culture is one of translation. The
encounter of self and other, local with the global, past and present
takes multiple forms, determined largely by the forms of cultural
translation inuenced by civilizational patterns and historical interactions and conicts. This suggests an isomorphic view of modernity; that is, an approach that stresses common features amongst
diverse elds. It needs to be said that the suggestion of uniformity
in it is neither an homogenizing nor a harmonious one: it is a social
isomorphism of structurations, mechanisms, translations and processes
rather than a condition that is simply either heterogeneous or homogeneous. In other words, it is a uniformity only in socio-cognitive
structures, forms of consciousness, legitimation processes and certain
kinds of practices and rationalities; in sum, particular modes of translation. Modernity entails common ways of doing things, certain universalistic values such as democracy; but uniformity does not extend
beyond these levels since the global is appropriated, or translated,
dierently by the local. This is an attempt to explain how modernity emerges in dierent places, at dierent times, and in dierent
societal forms without recourse to either an inexplicable notion of
heterogeneity or an over-deterministic notion of homogenization. The
multiple crystallizations of modernity cannot be explained monocausally by reference to a homogenizing and linear evolutionary
process of modernization to which all societies adapt. It is neither a
question of convergences nor of divergences, but one of the diusion
of a culture of translation by dierent societies by social actors. The
argument, then, is that modernity derives from the fact that social
actors all over the world are increasingly dening themselves by
reference to global culture. But in doing so, they are not all saying
the same things; andto make this more complicatedglobal culture
is not constant but evolving, since translations are never static, for
people continuously reinterpret their situation in light of their ongoing encounter with others. The proposal I am making, then, is to
see globalizationas a process that intensies connections, enhances
possibilities for cultural translations and deepens the consciousness
of globalityas the principal motor of modernity.
Integral to the project of modernity is a culture of translation.
What we are witnessing today is the completion of the transformative
project of modernity whose origins go back to the axial age (Eisenstadt,
453
2
See the growing literature on civil society in non-western societies and especially in Isalmic societies, Eickelman and Salvatore (2002), Hann and Dunn (1996),
Kamali (2001), Chambers and Kymlicka (2002), Hoexter et al. (2002).
3
We also have every reason to be sketpical of false notions of relativism (see
Cook, 1999).
454
gerard delanty
today and is nothing more than the fact of intensied interconnections resulting from accelerated social transformation, new possibilities for cultural translation and diminishing boundaries between
the dierent parts of the world. Global modernity can be examined
by reference to such processes of cultural translation such as crossfertilization and societal interpenetration, dynamics of dierentiation
and integration, producing convergent or divergent patterns. Its diverse
forms are varied and shaped by what ever responses localization
generates. This connection of the local and global has been much
discussed by authors such as Appadurai (1996), Hannerz (1996),
Friedman (1994), Robertson (1992) and Tomlinson (2000) and does
not need to be repeated here other than to stress that globalization,
which entails agency, is articulated in local contexts, leading dierent
kinds and degrees of indigenization, creolization, vernacularization,
hybridization, cosmopolitanism, transnationalism. Viewed in this way,
modernity is globally inclined but is neither universal nor western.
Modernity is not universalistic; it does not rest on a universal moral
or cultural foundation; as a tendentially global dynamic and consciousness, it is as much an agent of localization/particularization as
universalism. Yet, on the other hand, it intensies the longing for
universalistic ideas and frameworks, while making their realization
dicult, if not impossible.
Global modernity does not yet exist as what Niklas Luhmann has
called a world society, but only as a set of diverse trends (Luhmann,
1990). However, what we can say is that global modernity is the
primary form of modernity today, for modernity is no longer dened
by reference to premodern civilizations or traditions untouched by
any dimension of modernity. Modernity has had an impact on virtually every part of the world, including indigenous societies, which
have been transformed by the impact of world culture and have to
reinterpret their own culture in this light. The self-transformative
impetus of modernityin capitalism, in science, in state formation
and democratization, in technology, in communications, in collective
identities and cultural patternshas been multilinear and uneven,
but it has had its impact on almost every corner of the world and
has led to a modernity that is no longer specic to any nation, society
or culture. The advent of a now more fully globalized modernity
has in fact allowed many parts of the world, societies and groups to
reconstruct themselves in the image of modernity.
In sum, I am arguing that what is often called multiple moder-
455
456
gerard delanty
457
458
gerard delanty
459
460
gerard delanty
CHAPTER TWENTY-THREE
CENTER-PERIPHERY, CREOLIZATION
AND COSMOPOLITANISM
Ulf Hannerz
The idea of multiple modernities presumes that the
best way to understand the contemporary cultural
worldindeed to explain the history of modernity
is to see it as a story of continual constitution and
reconstitution of a multiplicity of cultural programs.
Eisenstadt (2000b: 2)
The conversation with anthropologists began, one might note, when Eisenstadt
was a postdoctoral scholar at the London School of Economics, in 194748 (Eisenstadt
2003a: 12).
462
ulf hannerz
2
I cannot refrain from noting here, too, that it was Shmuel Eisenstadt who at
one time, noting my travel habits, persuaded me that I should get an airline bonus
card.
3
I draw here partially on Hannerz (2001).
463
464
ulf hannerz
465
466
ulf hannerz
467
468
ulf hannerz
town built in the colonial era around a new railroad junction. I had
actually intended to do a study focusing on local social organization,
but then the eld experience itself gradually drew my attention in
another direction. Some of my new acquaintances in the town would
pull my sleeve and suggest that they and I ought to get into an
import-export business together; they had lots of ideas about desirable goods to import from overseas (but fewer ideas, it seemed, about
what to export). Or that they would propose that I take a promising
young nephew of theirs along when I would return to Europe, to
put him into my university where he would get a good education
and from which he could come back to Nigeria as a rich and powerful
manwhat had quickly become known in West African English as
a beento. Obviously these were people whose horizons did not
coincide with local town limits. Rather, their imagined worlds were
in large part overseas, constructed from ideas about credentialed
knowledge as well as material opulence.6
Most strikingly, moreover, there was in my eld that young urban
culture which was quite basically and dramatically a result of the
intricate and shifting blending of West African, European and by
now North American cultures as well. From within Nigeria, and
from just about every corner of it, people of a great many ethnic
groups had arrived in the town, to nd their places in its life. Even
as they brought some parts of their traditions along, however, there
were also the meanings and messages from further away. Music emanating from the loudspeakers of the small record stores switched back
and forth between American televangelist gospel, Afro-American soul
music, Caribbean reggae and Nigerian popular music genres such
as highlife and juju. And since Nigeria had oil and was at least for
some time a quite prosperous country, over the rusting zinc roofs
of the one-storey or two-storey houses, one could now see new television antennae being installed.
Here I could see the growth of global interconnectedness; but as
I became more inclined to focus my attention on this, I also became
more critical of the two ways of telling the story about it which were
more routinely available in Europe and North America at the time.
One was still the early version of modernization theory; the other
6
The formulation about imagined worlds, I need hardly point out, draws inspiration from Appadurai (1991).
469
7
My use of notions of creolization is most fully elaborated in Hannerz (1987,
1996: 65.).
470
ulf hannerz
Hybridity, collage, mlange, hotchpotch, synergy, bricolage, masticate, mineralization, syncretism, transculturation, third cultures; some
of these terms were perhaps used only in passing as summary images,
others made stronger and more durable claims to analytical status.8
Some were new and others retrieved from the past, others again had
more identiable regional or thematic strongholds. At present, hybridity
seems to have become the more favored general term.
What this entire vocabulary suggests, again, is a critique of essentialist assumptions of cultural purity and timelessness, as well as of
scenarios of homogenization. If that critique has now won wide
acceptance on the academic scene (as well as in the arts, not least
due to the inuence of writers like Salman Rushdie). Meanwhile,
the central metaphors have themselves come under scrutiny. Some
would be unhappy with the biologistic avor of hybridity; and if
the rhetorical trick often seemed to be to turn past prejudices about
the social and cultural worth of impure forms upside down, it was
perhaps not always certain that the trick would succeed.
As far as terms of Creole and creolization have been concerned,
it has evidently been one complication that their particular historical roots lie in the New World societies of plantations and slavery,
and that some of the meanings and associations out of that past,
with its extensions into the present, are not carried into the more
generalized sociolinguistics from which I (and others) have drawn
the term into cultural analysis. The argument that sometimes arises
over that is of a kind which is recurrent when terms originating in
some particular cultural tradition are made to travel and become
generalizedcaste, taboo. I see the point that their meanings
may be impoverished and even corrupted when borrowed for a wider
usage, and still feel that social and cultural imagination in the world
would also be poorer if such travel were restricted.
More often, perhaps, it has been proposed that creolization or
hybridity concepts merely push essentialism one step back, implying
that what comes together are the same old kind of presumably pure
and timeless entities. That may seem at rst sight like a good argument, but I do not think it necessarily is. In linguistics, there are
many English-based Creole languages, but probably hardly anybody
471
would claim that English is historically a very pure, bounded language. There may be creolizations all the way down, or at least a
medley through history of more creolizing and relatively more integrated, homogenized forms following upon each other. It is not that
some cultures, or people, are forever mixed, and others equally forever pure. Creolization is rather a process characteristic of periods
when major cultural currents which have previously been more separate come to engage more intensely with one another, with a potential for new outcomes. We may all be moving in and out of more
noticeably creolizing phases; and as we try to understand this we
should be concerned, for one thing, with periodization.
What I thought I could see in creolist sociolinguistics (although
not so many others seem to have taken much note of this) was probably above all a stronger sociology than I found in syncretism,
hybridity or other terms of blending. Once again, it was an attempt
to combine social and cultural analysis. That sociology, of course,
at least makes my notion of creolization more specic than some of
those other terms, not simply a fancier way of saying that something
is mixed. And the notion of the open cultural continuum organized
by center-periphery linkages has a major part in this.
The understanding of creolization here, however, also contributes
to a certain renewal in the understanding of center-periphery relationships. Anthropologists have recently had little inclination to accept
the assumption of passive reception at the periphery. They are far
more likely to see an active periphery, involved in the management
of diusion from the center: the periphery accepts this, rejects that,
modies one thing, and synthesizes something else with items from
its own local cultural inventory. Creolization involves all of that.
Furthermore, anthropologists generally like to draw attention to the
multicentricity of cultureand not least, to instances of cultural
counterow, to diusion from periphery to center. In the latter case,
one might perhaps still suggest some rather unexciting caution. At
times, the enthusiasm over discoveries of counterow could lead us
to deny or disregard even quite basic asymmetries of cultural diusion.
One should try to be constantly aware of the danger of Eurocentric
culture history, but some net asymmetries seem to me undeniable
during recent centuries, involving for one thing much of whatever
is shared among modernities. This complex of asymmetries has in
itself created some of the conditions for those later cultural counterows
and crossows in space which we now nd so intriguing.
472
ulf hannerz
473
but since then Japanese popular culture has certainly had a major
global impact. Shmuel Eisenstadt sometimes describes Japan as Gods
gift to comparative sociology, in its capacity to oer early and continuous evidence that modernity can appear in other than Occidental
forms. Perhaps it is beginning to take up a similarly important place
in the study of transnational cultural process. It is true that the
Japanese have also invented the entire intellectual eld of Nihonjinron
to theorize forms of national uniqueness, but since the country
endedwas forced to endits isolation from world markets and
world culture in the mid-nineteenth century, it has been remarkably
preoccupied with its handling of the inux of culture from elsewhere.
I can hardly fail to consider as evidence of the capacity of that
metaphor to travel that a group of Japanese and Japan-based scholars
have recently referred to the age of creolization in the Pacic as
they describe post-World War II cultural processes in the JapanAmerica borderlands (Matsuda 2001). But then another analyst of
the emergent place of Japanese popular culture in the world can
persuasively argue that this, to a degree, by now also involves recentering globalization (Iwabuchi 2002). We can indeed see multiple
modernities in motion here.
Cosmopolitanism reconsidered: culture and politics
Now I turn to my third key concept. My own engagement with the
notion of cosmopolitanism began with a departmental colloquium at
an American university in the mid-1980s, where I had sketched some
of my interests in the cultural aspects of globalization, and one of
my local colleagues asked if I had given any thought to cosmopolitanism.9 Essentially, my answer had to be no, but the question
stuck in my mind as one I ought to do something about. An opportunity later presented itself with a conference in Seoul, where I presented a paper titled Cosmopolitans and Locals in World Culture.
Later on, the paper appeared in the journal Theory, Culture and Society,
in a special issue on global culture. That issue was also published
as a book, which has thus been the publication reference for my
paper (Hannerz 1990). Riding on a wave of growing interest in the
474
ulf hannerz
10
475
12
Apart from those citations which are in the original text, as some readers have
noted my references to surrender and proteanism, I might add here that they
were inspired by Wol (1974) and Lifton (1968) respectively.
13
For some of these developments in the study of cosmopolitanism see e.g. Cheah
and Robbins 1998, Beck 2000, Vertovec and Cohen 2002 and Stevenson 2003.
476
ulf hannerz
many kinds of global interconnectedness, and the increasing consciousness of this fact. Importantly, too, the Cold War, with its great
divide running through humanity, came to an end, and this appeared
to allow new possibilities in organizing power as well as responsibility. Furthermore, if the term globalization had to a remarkable
extent been appropriated to refer to the deregulation of markets and
the triumphant march of capitalism, cosmopolitanism suggested
that human beings could relate to the world not only as consumers,
or members of a labor force, but also as citizens. This could mean
that cosmopolitan ideas could indeed oer a critique of at least certain qualities of global capitalism, and involve a search for ways of
constraining it.
With time, it also turned out that the passage of the Cold War
order had not everywhere gone altogether smoothly. New wars and
other conagrations such as those of the Balkans had involved atrocities which contributed to placing human rights prominently on a
cosmopolitan agenda. Environmental changes were also seen as
matters requiring active handling at a level beyond the nation-state,
as they could not be contained within its boundaries. Risk became
a key word here; it could cover more gradually evolving dangers as
well as the threat of disasters of an apparently more sudden nature.
And as much as ever, the politics of cosmopolitanism could also
stand opposed to nationalism, nativism, and xenophobia, adversary
responses to global interconnectedness which could be reactions to
the inux of migrant labor forces as well as refugees, but sometimes
also to other social and cultural trac across borders. Eisenstadt
(e.g. 2003a: 556) notes here, as one characteristic of present times, a
continuous oscillation between cosmopolitanism and particularistic
tendencies.
Toward the end of the twentieth century and continuing into the
early years of the new millennium, many of these developments were
obviously more toward the political side of cosmopolitanism, in
thought as well as practice; but not all. In any case, while cosmopolitanism is a very old topic in social thought, it could now make
a remarkable comeback across a range of scholarly pursuits, from
political philosophers by way of social theorists to ethnographers,
from law to cultural studies. It is also clear that as a keyword in
recent debate, it has not stood alone, but has belonged in a wider
eld of arguments revolving at the same time around such other
477
keywords as multiculturalism, identity politics, diaspora, transnationalism, and civil society; even political correctness.
I am coming back now myself to a more active engagement with
ideas of cosmopolitanism for various reasons.14 One is because of a
curiosity about the current distribution of cosmopolitan orientations
in the world. In my rst paper on the topic, I obviously came rather
close to what may have been the more or less classic notion: cosmopolitanism has tended to be a privilege associated with other privileges. Perhaps that has meant that in the twentieth century it has
shifted from the aristocracy to the professions, but it still involves
education, the freedom to travel, and a certain material security.
Calhoun (2002), in the essay I cited early in this chapter, is also
among those who basically shares in such assumptions.
During the 1990s, with the renewed interest in cosmopolitanism,
there was, however, increasing questioning of that somewhat exclusive notion of its locus in society. A recurrent reference has been
James Cliords (1992: 108) notion of discrepant cosmopolitanisms,
generated through displacement and transplantation, often through
violent histories of economic, political and cultural interaction. As
Cliord was more generally concerned with the part of travel in
constituting the contemporary world, he oered little discussion of
cosmopolitanism as such, but he eectively made the point that for
a long time this has not been a world divided between haves who
move and have-nots who stay put.
Along such lines, a number of ethnographers have recently found
cosmopolitans where they have not been noted beforeand not even
always among frequent travelers. Huon Wardle (2000), drawing on
eld materials from working-class urban Jamaica, notes the enduring harshness of Caribbean living conditions and the historical and
continued openness of the region to inuences from the outside world,
and he notes the mobility and the transnational networks in which
ordinary Jamaicans are engaged. But proceeding beyond material
circumstances and practical adaptations, Wardle nds a cosmopolitan
philosophy and a shared community esthetic emerging in sociality,
out of the uncertainty and ux of life: recognizable for example in
playfulness and in narratives of adventure.
14
478
ulf hannerz
479
480
ulf hannerz
worlds, they may be more directly and deeply involved with cultural
alterities than those inhabitants of the center who, even as they travel,
may more easily encapsulate themselves in their own kinds of institutions and comfortsperhaps more expatriates than cosmopolitans.
So that assumption about where the cosmopolitans are may need to
be reconsidered. The Indian culture critic Ashis Nandy (1998: 146)
raises the issue bluntly: Europe and North America have increasingly
lost their cosmopolitanism, paradoxically because of a concept of
cosmopolitanism that considers Western culture to be by denition
universal and therefore automatically cosmopolitan. Believe it or not,
there is a cost of dominance, and that cost can sometimes be heavy.
Shifting understandings of the loci of cosmopolitanism may again
be a part of the history of multiple modernities. I am also drawn
toward scrutinizing ideas and practices of cosmopolitanism again,
however, precisely because of that two-facedness of the concept: cultural and political. What is actually the relationship between the two
clusters of meaning sharing a space in the dictionary? Are we dealing
here with an arbitrary lexical cohabitation, an (originally at least)
characteristically western confusion? In my original essay, I concentrated entirely on the cultural dimension of cosmopolitanism. Now
I wonder if there is at least some sort of elective anity between
the two. Political philosophers, who have recently been contrasting
cosmopolitanism with patriotism (or nationalism), have mostly concluded that the former may be noble, but is also thinthere is a
symbolic, experiential decit which makes it dicult to mobilize people around it.15 Is that really always so? Again, consider those two
faces. In its cultural dimension, cosmopolitanism tends to show a
happy face, enjoying new people, new intellectual and esthetic experiences, new skills, a new sense of security. Political cosmopolitanism is
often a cosmopolitanism with a worried face, trying to come to grips
with very large problems. But perhaps the one can at times be a
resource for the other. If these two senses of cosmopolitanism must
not simply be conated, the intertwining of the two may yet proceed along dierent lines and take many shapes. Why should there
not be as much scope for variation and complexity here as there
has been in the case of nationalism? It may be time for the political
philosophers of cosmopolitanism to let more ethnographers in.
15
See in particular the volume of essays by Martha Nussbaum and others (Cohen
1996).
481
And then perhaps as another reason for engaging now with cosmopolitanism, there is one more recent turn in human history. I
noted in my rst attempt at understanding cosmopolitanism that the
cosmopolitan, engaging with another culture, typically knows where
the exit is. Something that can be called home is available. If the
combination rootless cosmopolitans has been recurrent, more cosmopolitans may actually have been rooted somewhere, and making
their excursions from there. In a somewhat similar vein, it seems to
me, the well-known scholar-journalist Michael Ignatie, identifying
himself as a cosmopolitan, writes in his Blood and Belonging (1994: 9),
on late twentieth-century nationalist conicts, that cosmopolitanism
is the privilege of those who can take a secure nation state for
granted. A decade or so later, that is worth thinking about again,
whetherafter 2001any nation state, not even the strongest, may
seem quite so entirely secure. After the end of the Cold War, a
politics of cosmopolitanism seemed for a period perhaps not only
desirable, even necessary, but more than ever before possible too. It
may now have to survive in times of widespread, diuse fear; when
even a term like civilizations becomes part of battle-cries. In such
times, it is good to have scholars like Shmuel Eisenstadt, with a
respect for pluralism and a sense of being at home in the world.
CHAPTER TWENTY-FOUR
484
erik allardt
historical durability, and that have created a high degree of consensus about some basic values and cultural programs. The most
typical civilizations are the so-called historical Axial Age Civilizations,
a concept that emphasizes the integration of the religious and mundane orders, as was the case in ancient Israel, in European Christianity,
ancient Greece and China, the Islamist world, Hinduism etc. However,
a search for a uniform and generally applicable denition of the
civilization concept in the texts of Eisenstadt would be in vain. In
fact, a consistent and unequivocal civilization concept cannot be
found in his texts. This view is not here presented as criticism. On
the contrary, the lack of an unequivocal denition of the civilization
concept is, so to say, in the very nature of large-scale social phenomena. They contain so many dimensions, slightly diering qualities and, in particular, ever-changing but nevertheless related attributes,
that a denition presented once and for all would be grossly misleading. This is a methodological predicament which has been observed
only diusely in the textbooks of social science methods. As judging
from leading scholarly texts, the fruitful way to proceed in the presentations of many general sociological concepts appears to be descriptions made as accurately as possible but without the ambition to give
a nal, all-time, precisely valid and completely covering denition.
A seminal way to advance is to make the conceptual descriptions
continuously more telling and precise in future presentations. At any
rate, Eisenstadt proceeds in a very fruitful way when he avoids dogmatic and seemingly universally valid denitions.
The avoidance of universally valid denitions is related to the traditional distinction between nominal and real denitions. Nominal
denitions are agreements on the meaning and use of words, whereas
real denitions are empirical statements about the nature of the real
world. Accurate real denitions are of utmost importance in sociology,
but there is a lack of analyses about when and how real denitions
should be used. As empirical descriptions, real denitions cannot be
assumed to remain constant and unchangeable, but there are no
rules governing how much they can change until a new wording is
invented. At any rate, fruitful use of real denitions is a sign of creativity in sociology.
485
486
erik allardt
487
488
erik allardt
489
490
erik allardt
by the superiority of the market form of production over centralized
and socially oriented ways of running the economy, and, on the other
hand, by the yearning for meaning, social coherence, the fusion of
value and fact, the absorption of the individual in a supportive and
loving community, which in turn blends into the natural background.
These are the terms of reference for our problems. Anyone who simply proposes one of them and ignores or dismisses the other, has little
to tell us. That might have been possible once, but it is not so longer
(Gellner 1998, 190).
491
492
erik allardt
and aspirations. One crucial phenomenon was the weakening importance of traditional class conicts. In scholarly, conceptual presentations of the new developments, the institutional aspect of modernization
in particular was played down and relativized. A telling example is
the concept reexivity, in the way the term has been used for
instance by Ulrich Beck. For him, reexive modernization refers to
a type of society beyond simple modernity in which there is an
acknowledgment of the impossibility of knowing the unintended consequences produced by modernization . . . (Beck 1998, ch. 7, Nash
2000, 278279). Similarly, Goran Therborn presents a denition in
which while empirically traceable the proposed concept of modernity does not contain any concrete institutional references, but leaves
the latter as causes, eects and contingencies for investigation
(Machonin 2000, 150).
The emphasis on reexive modernity, in the sense of Beck, Nash,
Therbom and Machonin, comes very close to what was included in
the phrase the postmodern turn in sociology, as it was developed
by Zygmunt Bauman (2000). It implies a view of society in which
social institutions and structures are ongoing processes. Postmodern
sociology declares an interest in the study of how social phenomena
and social categories are constantly constructed, and socially dened
and interpreted. Thus the concept of reexive modernizationas
well as the phrase the postmodern turn of sociologyimplies a
vision which was already emphasized in the preceding section of this
paper. Modernity is no longer simply a tendency to overall rationalization and to the creation of rational and systematic institutional
mechanisms. Modernity implies a constant ow of interpretations of
what is considered important and valuable in social life. Cultural
and moral issues are emphasized, while established bureaucratic structures are increasingly questioned.
The terms postmodern and postindustrial are sometimes
regarded as just journalistic descriptions designated to appear mostly
in popular magazines. Yet they describe truly fundamental societal
changes. A newor at least a rejuvenated concept in social analysis
is agency. One leading precursor in introducing the concept of agency
was Alain Touraine (1984). His approach has been christened The
New Social Movement Theory (Nash 2000, 130133). Revealing analyses
of crucial tendencies in present-day advanced societies have been
presented by his students, the Danish scholar Peter Gundelach and the
Italian Alberto Melucci. Gundelach emphasizes grassroots movements
493
494
erik allardt
495
496
erik allardt
of power at the grassroots level (Adamski, Zaborowski and PelczynskaNalecz 2002, 155169). An important part of the picture is that the
strength of the movement did not last long, and that it soon became
the victim of a new grassroots process. Solidarity was the rst successful grassroots movement in the socialist countries, but a signicant
feature of the 1989 revolution was the absence, in all the countries
involved, of an organized revolutionary movement with an explicit
and systematic ideology. The revolution began at the grassroots, and
it was over almost at the same time it started.
During the 1990s there was a vast output of studies of democracy
and democratization in Central Europe. The basic query often
concerned the extent to which the Central European countries copied
or renewed Western European models of democracy and representative institutions. Many studies and conclusions speak about a partial
success. In an issue of the International Political Science Review on elections
and parliaments in East Central Europe in the early 1990s, Janos
Simon (1997, 361379) emphasized how the Central European countries succeeded in both partly copying the Western models and in
returning to their own historical traditions.
Despite dominantly positive conclusions about the tendencies to
democratic developments in the post-socialist societies, it is obvious
that the democratization process in the 1990s abounded in problems. There were a great number of analyses pointing to a lack of
stable national parties representing the interests of crucial groups in
the social structure (Rychard 1992, 167179), to an inated number
of political parties (Simon 1997, 372377), and to a lack of crystallization in the party system (Adamski 1997, 69823; Holmes 1998,
232248). It was emphasized that a reasonable degree of correspondence between the actual political attitudes of the citizens and
the support for dierent parties was lacking. A telling description
was presented by two Dutch sociologists, Gijsberts and Nieuwbeerts;
they showed that while the members of the dierent classes diered
in their views about income inequality and social security, those
dierences were not reected in their voting behavior. People in the
emerging democracies in Eastern Europe had been unable to translate their political preferences into party preferences.
There are of course also other aspects and facets of democracy
than party politics. However, as Jean Blondel (1998, 157) once
remarked in a discussion about the challenges facing liberal democracies in the twenty-rst century, it is dicult to imagine how democ-
497
racy could exist without parties. Yet as a number of political scientists from dierent countries maintain, at the beginning of the twentyrst century, party systems are facing many threats that could weaken
their role as guardians of democracy. This is, however, as much a
West European phenomenon as something characteristic of postsocialist Central Europe. According to Peter Mair (1998, 161174),
the political parties became more distant from society, on the one
hand, and more strongly linked to the government and the state, on
the other. They suered from a clear decline in their appeal to and
their distinctiveness for the citizens. A telling, although by no means
unique, example is provided by the Scandinavian countries. Some
decades ago there were often references to the Nordic model implying,
among other things, a consistent search for consensus and a playing
down of ideological dierences. The Scandinavian ve-party model
has been eroding since the 1970s. New parties such as the Greens
and populist parties on the radical right have emerged. Novel issues,
such as those related to ecology, to the power of peripheral regions,
the European Union, and to cleavages of gender and sex, lie basically
outside the traditional political divisions. In the parliamentary elections,
the new developments have resulted in higher voting volatility,
decreases in voting participation among the youngest voters in particular, and in an obvious decline of class voting (Allardt 2000,
129141). In fact, many of the facets emphasized as post-modernity
are observable. The West European societies are, in fact, as far from
the traditional West European model as are the post-socialist central
European countries. Many of the traits observable in the elections
and political life of the Central European post-socialist countries
often pointed out as doubtful from the point of view of democracy
seem to have emerged also in the West European countries.
It is signicant for the traditional conception of European modernity that the fall of the Communist regimes in the socialist countries
of Central Europe and their consecutive development has been considered as a case of modernization. It is true that some institutional
changes during this great European transformation strongly support
such a notion. There was a clear transfer to both political democracy and market economy. On the other hand, a closer look at what
happened in Europe during the nal decades of the twentieth century
also provides reasons to further scrutinize the modernization concept.
It is apparent that the processes of modernization diered among the
various post-socialist societies. Those countries that were economically
498
erik allardt
most successful were not the ones that had more political freedom.
Modernization seems to be more of a multidimensional process than
was traditionally assumed. More important still is that some of the
features resulting from the regime change in the post-socialist lands
also have tended to emerge in Western Europe, and that the former
socialist countries in East Central Europe on some counts may have
developed faster in a new direction than the traditional European
democracies have. At least for the time being, nal conclusions about
political developments in Western and in East Central Europe are
too related to political opinions in order to be accepted as scholarly
ndings. Nevertheless, it seems permissible to conclude that multiple
modernities are characteristic of todays European societies.
A concluding note: Divergent modernities
To speak about modernity is a risky business, as there is a wide
range of dierent denitions. In a lucid presentation of the key ideas
in sociology, Peter Kivisto (1998, 119152) shows that practically all
founding fathers and recent leading theoreticians have had something
to say about modernity, usually in terms of their own terminology.
Here the point of departure was Max Webers view of European
modernity as a tendency to an overall rationalization of social life,
and in particular its continuation in S.N. Eisenstadts more comprehensive and research-based conception of European modernity, with
its emphasis on multiplicity and pluralism. Institutionally, the core
of European modernity has meant an accentuation of the democratic
nation-state, the market economy, research-oriented universities and
the importance of questioning achieved knowledge. In its emphasis
on universality and reexivity Eisenstadts view has some anity with
the conceptions of Anthony Giddens who especially emphasized the
basic social processes of modernization. According to Giddens (1990,
1927) modernization has entailed what he has called distanciation from the ties to particular locales, and a weakening of the
embedment of social ties to specic locales and primary groups. Here
we have followed Eisenstadt, at least partly, in the assumptions that
research, reexivity and the questioning of knowledge are crucial in
modernization. However, regarding the points made by Giddens, this
paper advocates a dierent view. In recent decades there has emerged
an increased depreciation of the ideas about increased distanciation
499
CHAPTER TWENTY-FIVE
1
These needs, as recent social neuroscience has demonstrated, are hard-wired
in the human species (Smith and Stevens 2002).
502
donald n. levine
mandates derive from the work of elites who have produced transcendent ideals for reconstructing worldly relations, ideals that were
elaborated in what have been called the Axial civilizations (Eisenstadt
2003a, I, chs. 1, 7).
The great civilizations, consequently, have often defended and
extended their domain through gloried ethnocentric processes involving conquest, conversion, and assimilation of those outside the pale.
In Greco-Roman civilization, for example, Hellenes came to disparage
outsiders who were ignorant of Greek language and civilization,
thereby uncivil and rude. Calling them barbarians (barbaroi) disposed
the Greeks to conquer, enslave, and colonize others who were deemed
culturally inferior. This conceit continued in Roman times, as Roman
citizens justied their extensive conquests of alien peoples (barbari) in
ways that coerced them into adopting the Latin language and their
religious beliefs. In the case of European civilization this pattern
found its denouement in the missione civilatrice whereby Italian airplanes rained poisoned gas on shoeless Abyssinian peasants armed
with spears, and Nazi armies attempted to expand their notion of a
superior German culture throughout Europe.
The Greek/barbarian paradigm can be found in all other major
civilizations. Among those I shall consider here, it appears as
Hindu/mleccha, nihongo/gaijin, Christian/pagan, mumin/kar, and Chosen
People (am segulah)/gentiles ( goyyim). In what follows I shall relate
each of those dichotomies to certain core values in each civilization,
suggesting how these values have been used to justify disparagement
if not aggression against others. However, since each civilization has
evolved patently contradictory sub-traditions, they all contain elements that promote hospitability toward strangers, tolerate diversity,
and cultivate understanding and compassion, and so promote a more
inclusive orientation. Beyond that, I shall show that in the course of
the past century, three of these civilizationsIndia, Japan, and
Western Christianitygave rise to developments in which traditional
symbols were invoked in ways that heighten levels of openness and
inclusiveness dramatically. These developments represent resources
for dialogical engagement that could inspire ways of reducing clashes
among contemporary civilizations.
To adumbrate the modern transformational pattern I want to identify, let me begin with a prototype of the process, which appeared
in Greco-Roman civilization. The concept of physis (nature) formed
503
504
donald n. levine
2
They were obliged to provide literary instruction, priestly duties, and certain
magical services, and to support themselves from gifts, not by earning a salary.
Although Brahmanic status rested on birth, to become a fully accredited Brahman
a man had to study the Vedic texts, learn certain ritual practices, and acquire a
holy belt.
3
In an eort to win over Muslims who were averse to his model of barefoot,
mendicant, vegetarian asceticism, Gandhi subdued his satyagrahi persona. He also
sided with Muslims who were being murdered by Hindus. Fearing widespread civil
505
war between Hindus and Muslims, he nally encouraged the Congress Party to
accept partition. For this alleged betrayal, he was assassinated by a Hindu nationalist
soon after India became independent.
4
Success is not the criterion here. Ivan Morris (1975) suggests that the value of
makoto action may be enhanced by failure. Other aspects of makoto are described
in Gleason 1995.
506
donald n. levine
507
508
donald n. levine
better than the dierent meanings this term has acquired in Islamic
civilization. On the one hand, jihad refers to aggression against
Unbelievers through the legal, compulsory, collective eort to expand
territories ruled by Muslims. Most scholars argue that despite ambiguities about the term in the Koran, this has been the principal line
of interpretation of the doctrine in Islamic tradition. Thus, jihad was
invoked to instigate the conquest, beyond the Arabian peninsula, of
the region from Afghanistan to Spain within a century of Mohammeds
death, and later to spur Muslim invasions of such territories as India,
Anatolia, Balkans, Ethiopia, Sudan, and West Africa. More recently,
it has been dramatically revived in modern Islamic fundamentalism
by inuential gures such as Sayyid Outb, who argues that the only
way for Muslims to achieve religious purity is to establish an Islamic
state through jihad.
On the other hand, jihad has been interpreted as a struggle for
personal moral improvement, in the sense of living more closely in
accord with Islamic Law. Thus, in language that parallels Ueshibas
formulation that in his form of martial art, there are no enemies
and that the greatest victory is the victory over oneself, the 11thcentury theologian Abu Hamid al-Ghazali maintained that the soul
is an enemy which struggles with one and which must be fought,
and that this jihad against the soul constitutes the greater jihad. In
this sense of the term, it extends beyond overcoming baser instincts
to a struggle for social justice. So understood, it could be viewed as
an injunction to live peaceably with everyone, and to cooperate with
people of all faiths in a quest for social reform. This position has
been embraced by virtually all Su theologians. It accords with the
absence in Islam of any particularistic ethnic emphasis, apart from
the status of Arabic as a sacred language (Eisenstadt 1992b, 41). In
fact, in many contemporary societies until recently, including Ethiopia
and India, the norm was for public displays of solidarity between
Muslims and other religious groups.
Although some progressive Muslims wish seriously to promote and
extend the latter denition of jihad, no charismatic gure, such as a
Gandhi or a Bonhoeer, has arisen to challenge authoritatively the
contemporary drift toward an escalation of the other view.5 In the
5
This view was propounded with particular virulence by heirs to the 13C jihad
revivalist Ibn Taymiyya and his 18C disciple, Mohammed Ibn Abdul Wahhab Najdi,
from whom the fundamentalist Wahabi sect derives.
509
510
donald n. levine
511
donald n. levine
512
Benign
consequences
Exclusionary
framework
Expanded
Inclus.
concept
Creative
agents
Greco-Rom nature
rational ethics
civil/barbar
cosmopolitanism
Stoics
Indian
purity
Brahmanic
leader
pure/impure
satyagraha
Gandhi
Japanese
makoto
social order
modernization
nihon/gaijin
aikido
Ueshiba
Western
Christian
agape
domestic
pacication
believer/
pagan
Confessing
Church
Niemoeller &
Bonhoeer
Islamic
submission
pacication
ummah/kuar
greater jihad
???
Jewish
covenant
moral law
chosen/gentile
universalism
???
PART FIVE
CHAPTER TWENTY-SIX
rolland goetschell
516
Feuerwerker, 1976.
517
duties in the confederate states. Until then, however, those who profess the
Jewish faith shall retain those rights, which they have already been
granted by the several confederation states.
At the last minute, the formula in the confederate states was revised
to read in the individual confederated states.
Thus, individual states were obliged to rearm via their own
sovereign institutions. This meant that the individual states were
allowed to question the emancipation granted to the Jews, which
had been decreed by a foreign power. The Revolution of 1848, in
which the Jews took an active part, and the National Assembly of
18481849, were a result of the latter act of congress. The Constitution
of March 28, 1848, in part VI 144148, granted civil, political and
religious equality. In May, once again, after the Revolution, the Jews
were disappointed and emancipation was postponed to the Greek
Calends. During the forty years that elapsed from the Congress of
Vienna to the Revolution of 1848, the promises of Article 16 of the
Federal Act were not honored.2
Under Bismarcks rule, the Jews situation started to change. When
Germany crushed Austria in Sadowa on July 3, 1866, the road
became clear for the reorganization of Germany. With the exception
of the states of the SouthBavaria, Wurtemberg, Bade, and HesseDarmstadta Confederacy of Germany of the North was formed,
dominated by Prussia. Politically, the time was marked in the Reichstag
and the Prussian Chamber of Representatives with the emergence
of the national liberals. Bismarck was ready to grant them a measure of liberal reform compatible with his foreign policy. Thus, the
emancipation of the Jews came as part of a package of liberal reforms
included in the reshaping of laws intended for the institution of the
Reich to be implemented. The Act of Reichstag of the Germanic
Union of the North in July 3, 1869 specied: All remaining limitations of civilian and political rights derived from the dierence in
religious creed are hereby abolished. In particular, eligibility for participation in municipality and state representation and for the high
rise of public oce shall be independent of religious creed. Although
the Jews were not mentioned, a debate between Edouard Lasker and
a conservative representative opposed to the law proves that the
518
rolland goetschell
3
4
5
6
519
tic and foreign markets now began making their appearance. The
Jewish banks were based in Frankfort, Karlsruhe, Mainz and other
places. Jews also participated in the construction of the railways. The
numbers of Jewish doctors increased considerably and Jewish writers
and journalists made their rst appearance. Nevertheless, unlike in
France, the public service sector remained closed to Jews, consequentially, Jews had no access to such positions as judges, schoolteachers, and professors.7 The Prussian monarchy eventually forged
strong ties with Germany, that were signicant in constructing the
German nation-state. In creating a signicant European state in 1871,
Bismarck fullled the expectations of the liberal middle class by implementing Herrenreform. Revitalizing the monarchy and the army became
an important part of the political structure by which imperial Germany
distinguished itself from Western Europe. Preserving the monarchys
military character was connected to the idea that the state (Staatsragende
Schucht) could claim for itself, without having to justify itself by means
of the social order. The pact between the monarchy and the noble
landowners remained intact, although the ties weakened from the
late eighteenth century onward and during the later period of reform.
Consequentially, Jews were forbidden to enter the reserve ocers
corps (without exception, conrming the rule in Bavaria in 1885).
Both as a community and as individuals, Jews never crossed that
border in civil society as long as the monarchy lasted.8
Intellectual Revolution and Reformation
Emancipation also presents an intellectual aspect that was embodied,
rst and foremost, in Wissenschaft of Judentum, and then in Reformation.
With Wissenschaft of Judentum, one can say that Judaism committed
itself to modernity. In 1823, the movements program was published
in the form of a speech by Emmanuel Wolf in Zeichrift fuer die
Wissenschaft of Judentum, which bears the exact title eber of Begri einer
Wissenschaft of Judentum (On the concept of a Science of Judaism).
In that text, Wolf denes this concept and his understanding of
Judaism:
7
8
520
rolland goetschell
When it is a question of the science of Judaism, it is obvious that the
term Judaism is taken in its acceptance in its broadest sense, as the
quintessence of the set of circumstances, specic characteristics and
performances of the Jews in touch with the religion, the philosophy,
the history, the law and the literature generally, the social life and
human aairs and not just in the restricted sense of simple religion of
the Jews. [. . .] Judaism, such as represented here, as a whole (als ein
Ganzes) rests on an appropriate internal principle and is contained on
one hand in an impressive literature, but also in a particular life and
a texture of a numerous class of human being that is capable and
requires in itself and for itself (an und fr sich) a scientic treatment.
Until now it was never presented scientically in all its parts, from a
completely independent point of view. If the total content of the Judaism
owed, in itself and for itself to be the object of scientic investigation
and if Wissenschaft of Judentum must be formed, one can understand
that there is a question here of all methods. The contents of this special science are then systematic development and presentation of its
object in all its parts, in itself and for itself and not just for external
ends. Let us apply this to the Wissenschaft of Judentum:
1. Wissenschaft of Judentum understands Judaism in its fullest scope
2. It unfolds Judaism according to its concept and makes a systematic
statement of it where the particular is returned permanently with
the fundamental principle of everything.
3. It treats its object in and for its own sake, the appropriate interest,
and not for any special purpose, or denite intention.
See the special number of the review PARDES, no. 19/20, 1994.
521
10
11
12
522
rolland goetschell
13
14
Breuer, 1992.
Cohen-Albert, 1982, pp. 121141.
523
524
rolland goetschell
15
16
17
18
Isral, 1968.
Marrus, 1971.
Leyer, 1966, pp. 137170.
Lamberti, p. 11.
525
526
rolland goetschell
3. Did political emancipation precede and facilitate, or follow economic and social incorporation? In France, political emancipation preceded and facilitated economic and social incorporation.
Regarding Germany, the opposite is true.
4. Was emancipation a part of the new nationalist assertion, or part
of the liberal political movements with which the Jews were
aliated? In Germany, it was clearly the support of liberal political movements that assured the emancipation of the Jews, while
the conservatives and nationalists took all possible steps to prevent it.21 In France, emancipation was a result of the activity of
individuals more than of movements.
5. Once obtained, did emancipation proved itself long-lasting or were
there episodes of restoration that tried to question its results? In
France, Napoleons dcret infme in 1807, was a minor inuence.
In Germany, the decisions of the Congress of Vienna delayed the
emancipation of German Jews.
In both cases, modernity did not mean the disappearance of the two
communities, but rather adaptation to the appropriate conditions of
social, economic, and political life in the two countries.
21
CHAPTER TWENTY-SEVEN
528
piotr sztompka
European identity. I also claim that the revolutions of 1989 will not
be completed until such transformations of identity come to a successful
conclusion. Being invited to enter the European house does not
necessarily mean automatically feeling at home or that newcomers
will necessarily be treated as one of us by the current tenants. This
metaphor is useful for grasping the opposition of hard institutional
arrangements and soft cultural orientations. House means the architecture; home means solidarity, loyalties, attachments, trust. To
reside in the house does not necessarily mean to consider it ones
home.
Rudiments of the theory of identity
Human society is the product of a dynamic process in which society
continually reconstructs itself. Society is constantly becoming; it
is never simply being. It is a process rather than a substance
(Sztompka 1991). This process is driven by societal agency which
refers to the potential of a society to eectively transform itself. A
crucial component of societal agency is collective identity, which is
at the same time both a pre-requisite for the future collective social
practices as well as the outcome of those social practices, accumulated marks of past experiences. Collective identity must be distinguished both from personal identity and mass identity. Personal
identity is the individuals concept, self dened in terms of belonging
to a specic social group or organisation, ones status or societal role,
etc. Thus, I consider myself: a Pole, a Krakowian, a Catholic, an
academic, a male. Mass identity, on the other hand, is the sum of
specic individual identities found in a particular collectivity. As
such it is an artifact: a statistical average devoid of ontological hard
reality. It tells us only that there are a certain number of individuals with a particular type of personal identity. In contrast, collective
identity can only be produced by the exchange of meanings through,
for example, public debate, artistic expression, conversation, argument
and the media; what is sometimes referred to as the meaning
industry. It emerges in interpersonal interactions as a record of
common social experiences. It is created not so much as a result of
individual biography, but rather in the course of societal history. In
a way, collective identity can be seen as sedimentary rock built up
of layers of social practices and traditions.
529
530
piotr sztompka
531
532
piotr sztompka
533
rights, pluralism, tolerance, justice and solidarity have been mentioned. Signicantly, such an apology for common values corresponds
with the recognition of Europes rich diversity of languages, lifestyles
and customs, which are to be preserved in everyday life.
Rather more problematic is the fourth foundation of unity, the
Euro-Centric ideology claiming that Europe is the cradle of the expanding West (including the US). According to this ideology, the West
is considered synonymous with the most dynamic, developed and
progressive civilization. It assumes, somewhat in line with Spencerian
social evolutionism, that there is only one scenario for social development and only one road leading to modernity and beyond, which
all societies have to follow, as if we were all riding one giant escalator, with the more privileged people at the top, and the less fortunate down at the backward bottom. By implication Europe was
said to be entrusted with the civilizing mission of pulling up the laggards, realised by its domination across many continents. The geopolitical consequence of such a theory has been European imperial
expansion and colonialism. In 1800, thirty-ve percent of the land
was controlled by European powers. This rose to sixty-seven percent
in 1878, and nally, to eighty-four percent, in 1914. Such an absolutization of European path to modernity is presently challenged
by the notion of multiple modernities, put forward by scholars
such as Shmuel Eisenstadt, Bjorn Wittrock, Johann Arnason and
others.
In spite of all these commonalities Europe has always raised numerous boundaries, both internal and external. Internal dividing lines
have separated its core from the peripheries. There have been various
types of divisions, such as: barbaricum versus civilization; the North
(as dened by Voltaire to include Scandinavia, Baltic countries,
Poland) versus the Mediterranean South, the cradle of Europe;
Western Christendom (Catholic, Protestant) versus Byzantine culture
and Orthodox religion; the economic backyard or under developed
areas versus the developed, highly industrialized and urbanized countries; urbanized areas versus rural areas; the former centres of empires
or imperial states (Britain, France, the Netherlands) versus small
states; communist countries versus the free Europe, or in dierent
terms, Western versus Eastern Europe; EU countries versus others;
recently acceded countries versus the rest within the EU, and potentially, the two-speed future development of the EU, with the core
countries versus the rest.
534
piotr sztompka
The external boundaries of Europe have also always created resistance to other areas of the world, to other continents and civilizations. The earliest fault line separated it from the Orient. As Edward
Said puts it: The Orient is not only adjacent to Europe; it is also
the place of Europes greatest and richest and oldest colonies . . .
its cultural contestant, and one of its deepest and most recurring
images of the Other (Said 1979: 1). A more recent fault line is the
opposition toward Islam prophetically described by Samuel Huntington
as: the war of civilizations. The most recent boundary emerging
after the collapse of communism is the one erected against the US
(as the opposition against American hegemony in a no longer bipolar, globalising world). It raises the spectre of age-old anti-American
sentiments, expressed for example already in 1900 in the statement
describing Americans as: Clients of Europe which have become its
rivals (dAppolonia 2002: 177).
The East-European identity
I claim that specic historical circumstances in the Eastern part of
Europe have led to the emergence of a particular type of collective
identity, which I label as the East-European identity. After a period
of considerable economic and political success and inuence under
the Byzantine and Ottoman empires in the southern anks of the
region (the Balkans, Hungary), and under strong monarchies in the
northern part (Poland, Lithuania, the Czech lands), which lasted until
the end of the seventeenth century, the region lost its importance
faced with the birth and expansion of modern capitalism in Western
Europe. Ever since, it has retained its pervasive peripheral status
vis-a-vis Western Europe. There are many reasons for this: Firstly,
the geographical shape of the European peninsula made the Eastern
part into a kind of residual area for Europe without any obvious
geographical boundary from Asia. Secondly, the region has been
economically underdeveloped and has fallen into backwardness also
regarding its civilization and technology. This underdevelopment
resulted in a relatively large proportion of rural settlements with
relatively rare and small urban centres, and a rural population. The
region was often conquered and politically dominated by Western
powers (e.g. in the case of Polands partitions throughout the whole
nineteenth century, or the Nazi occupation in the twentieth century).
535
536
piotr sztompka
537
tory practices at employment agencies, etc. Being treated as secondrate persons always contributes to the development of a decient
self-identity. Allow me an aside: lecturing often at Western universities, both in Europe and in the US, I have always been aware of
a certain guardedness among my students and an initial suspicion
of that professor from Eastern Europe and it takes a lecture or two
to convince them that I am not a polar bear that drinks vodka.
The slow return to Europe at the level of a collective identity
started already with the birth of a democratic opposition and various
forms of contestation against the existing communist regime. The
slow erosion of the communist bloc culminated in the revolutions
of 1989, which brought about the collapse of communism. The main
aim of the revolution was to escape from the grip of Asia and move
toward Western Europe, and to nally realise old pro-Western aspirations and ambitions (Sztompka 1996). This aim is best expressed
by the concept of rectifying revolutions proposed by Jrgen Habermas
(Habermas 1990). The immediate result of the revolution was twofold: it changed the boundaries, both the tangible and the symbolic
borders separating Eastern Europe from Western Europe, and it
changed the content of the value-system with which the people had
identied.
The main symbolic boundary disappeared already with the destruction of the Berlin Wall. The metaphor of the Iron Curtain lost its
physical representation, and hence any validity in social consciousness. The free ow of persons, goods, cultural products, and massmedia began soon after. The next step was the incorporation into
Western institutions and supranational structures: World Bank, IMF,
OECD, NATO. But, the nal conrmation of a European status
came with the accession of Poland, Hungary, the Czech Republic,
Slovakia, Slovenia and the Baltic States to the European Union. A
likely prospect for the future is the elimination of the last symbolic
signs of dierence: border checkpoints and a separate currency. These
changes will hopefully take place with the incorporation of Eastern
Europe into the Schengen area and Euroland.
However, while old boundaries were being brought down, new
boundaries emerged or became strengthened. First of all, a stronger
dividing line appeared from the East, separating East and Central
Europe from the former Soviet republics. Borders were sealed o,
and visas introduced. At a symbolic level old resentments were dug
out, dormant historical enmities reawakened and the memories of
538
piotr sztompka
539
540
piotr sztompka
541
542
piotr sztompka
The new landscape of identities
The collapse of the communist bloc has had a double eect on the
collective identities of East-European societies. The rst eect we
focused on in this work was the slow fading away of the EastEuropean identity and the incorporation of East-European societies
into a wider continental European identity. But, we also saw that at
the same time new boundaries had emerged and a growing diversity was now visible within the former Soviet bloc. In this second
development we witness the reappearance and rearmation of old,
temporarily latent national, ethnic, religious and cultural dierences
and identities, which unfortunately in some cases, like in the Balkans,
or post-Soviet republics, have tragically led to destructive wars.
Although they might at rst sight appear so, both tendencies are
not necessarily contradictory. In this late modern period, identity has
become multidimensional, multilayered, dierentiated. It is produced
as a personal construction built of multiple repertoires of options.
People craft themselves, rather then receiving themselves readymade. Transnational, continental, or even global identities appear as
new additional options, but do not necessarily eliminate other identities or orientations linked to, region, nation, ethics, religion, occupation, gender, sexual preference, life styles, consumer communities,
fashion-communities, leisure-communities, etc. Multiple identities imply
the enrichment of bonds, social networks and opportunities for experience and expression.
The best way to ensure the development of a balanced and trouble-free identity is to break up the age-old unity of national (tribal,
ethnic) identities and citizenship (Miller 2000). Since the birth of the
nation-state, as a hyphenated notion, both these identities have been
unconditionally united. Attachment to the nation was considered
synonymous with loyalty and allegiance to the state, and vice versa.
This need not be the case. Citizenship, dened as the set of rights
and obligations making one a competent member of a political
community (Everson and Preuss 1995: 12), may be detached from
nationhood, as the set of allegiances to the heritage, language and
customs of ethnic community. Ones identity should no longer be
tainted with exclusion, but rather become inclusive. The emergence
of what David Held calls cosmopolitan citizenship (Held 1995) is
imminent, expedited by both institutional and ideological factors.
The institutional factor is the globalisation of politics and the various
543
CHAPTER TWENTY-EIGHT
1
2
Pandey, 1990.
See Tambiah, 1996, pp. 23, 31322 for a summary of Pandeys submissions.
546
stanley j. tambiah
3
Jarelot. The Hindu Nationalist Movement in India. op. cit.; Thomas Bloom
Hansen. The Saron Wave: Hindu Nationalism and Democracy in Modern India.
Princeton: Princeton University Press, 1992. McKean, 1966.
4
For example, Engineer, 1991.
5
Ashutosh Varshney, Ethnic Conict and Civic Life, op. cit. The cities are
Aligarh and Calicut, Hyderabad and Lucknow, and Ahmedabad and Surat.
6
Gaborieau, 1985.
hindu-muslim cleavage
547
548
stanley j. tambiah
hindu-muslim cleavage
549
10
550
stanley j. tambiah
13
hindu-muslim cleavage
551
16
See Tambiah, 1996 (op. cit., Chapter 3, The 1915 Sinhala Buddhist-Muslim
Riots in Ceylon, pp. 3681).
17
See for a review of relevant literature, Cliord Geertz, 2003.
552
stanley j. tambiah
CHAPTER TWENTY-NINE
1
Reasons of space preclude developing fully the claim that this is part of a longterm trend of global insertion and connection, which shaped a forward-looking stress
on progress and development; and, which generated its own countervailing forces,
again related to trends and ideas at the forefront of Western multiple modernities.
On this see the contributions in Roniger and Waisman 2002, especially the works
by Whitehead, Eisenstadt and Roniger.
554
luis roniger
555
level their claims over land and, at the same time, over the recognition of cultural identity. These movements of protest reject, or at
least express a sense of uneasiness with, policies which reinforce
exclusion, huge socioeconomic gaps and marginalization. The open
protest is but the tip of an iceberg of large sectors wrangling to
understand the failure to meet the dreams heralded by recent market openings. Precisely because of these struggles and in spite of what
analysts dene as politics of anti-politics, expressed in calls to get
rid of politicians (Caetano, Moulin and Yankelevich 2002), politics
remains a central arena and state institutions are still the locus of
political articulation and public life.
In the last generation authoritarianism has receded throughout
Iberoamerica. Democratic hopes and expectations spread to the entire
region in the quarter-century since the Ecuadorian and Dominican
elections of 1978 (Alcntara 2003). And yet, while democracy has
become the only game in town, we should still ask in what forms
and through which dynamics has it been installed in these societies?
In this regard, the trends are contradictory and deserve analysis.
They involve some innovative experiences institutionalizing democratic
controls at the local scene, but also various forms of neo-populism
and neo-clientelism.
In this chapter I would like to reect on the signicance of these
contemporary trends in one of the regions in which, contrastingly
to the Islamic or Chinese societies, the confrontation with Western
modernity took the form of countervailing currents derived from
within the hegemonic ideas and institutions themselves, that is, in
terms of the latters own malfunctions and disillusions. Thus, this
confrontation turned to be, in Shmuel N. Eisenstadts terms, a clash
of multiple modernities, mutually implicated and challenging one
another in terms of their unfullled visions and global iconic standing.
Disenchantment and loss of public trust
The most conspicuous element we can identify in the process of routinization of democratic institutions at this stage is the decrease in
public trust, which public opinion surveys reect.2 From the surveys
2
556
luis roniger
by Latinobarmetro for the year 2002 (published in 2003), for example, it appears that even though most of the citizens interviewed
supported democracy, preferring it over other forms of government,
the rates of support decreased since 1996 in 13 out of 17 countries
covered by the survey, with 5 nations showing a very low percentage, in the range of 37 to 45 percent. In this range of the scale in
2002 were Colombia, Brazil, El Salvador, Paraguay and Guatemala.
In 11 out of 17 countries the level of dissatisfaction and disenchantment
with the functioning of the democratic system crossed the line of the
50 percent of those surveyed between 1996 and 2002.
The parallel trend is that the level of support for authoritarianism
has increased in 8 countries between the years 1996 and 2002. This
is accompanied by a persistent increase in the popular demand for
hard-line policies against criminals. Marginal elements were also
traced, even in countries in which the population was strongly in
favor of democracy after long periods of authoritarian and military
governments, such as the Southern Cone countries.
These gures indicate a signicant lack of condence in the democratic system, despite its formal acceptance. Paraguay and Argentina
have been extreme cases, with over 90 percent of dissatisfaction in
2002. Mexico was another case of great discontent with democracy:
over 80 percent, in a country which started a process of transference
of government after a decades-long period of single-party rule, corporatism and clientelist politics. In Colombia, Brazil, Chile, Bolivia,
Peru, and Ecuador, the disenchantment with the system was around
the 60 to 80 percent of the representative samples. Citizens express
very low levels of public trust towards politicians and the ruling
class (Latinobarometro 2003).
What are the implications of such public disenchantment? It may
be assessed as an expression of failing democratic consolidation. But
it may also reect a trend found elsewhere in mature democracies,
which by denition are pluralistic and open to criticism and civilian
control. In order to evaluate the signicance of these trends, it may
be useful to take two parallel lines of analysis: one comparative and
the other longitudinal across time.
Taking the comparative lead, it is necessary to keep in mind that
in the postwar democracies of the so called trilateral countries
the USA, Europe and Japanthere has been a constant concern
with the crises of democracy, at least since the 1970s. Diverse indi-
557
cators reected a deep disappointment with representative democracy, as it was shown already in the germinal report of Crozier,
Huntington, and Watanuki (1975). The more recent work on the
deterioration of public trust by Susan Pharr and Robert Putnam
(2000) indicates that this is more than an ephemeral trend in these
democracies.
Coming back to Iberoamerica, this lead may suggest that the critical attitude of the population may be related to the fact that these
democracies managed to become established. Indeed, at least in terms
of the formal criteria advanced by Robert Dahl or Adam Przeworski,
the longevity of democracies in the region stands out. And, yet, their
citizens express low levels of public trust towards politicians and the
ruling class. So, perhaps public distrust may not necessarily be a sign
of institutional immaturity (See also Uslaner 2003).
While we can contextualize the current disappointment being
expressed toward democracy, by taking into account the high expectations in the 1980s and 1990s, we should assess whether representative democracy can be sustainable in such a context of widespread
disenchantment and loss of condence in institutions, if these come
together with a failure of democratic culture to reach down to the
entire society and with a cynical approach toward the supposedly
public commitment of political elites? I would like to suggest that is
precisely now, when representative democracy turned to be the only
game in townat least in the Westwhen in some countries coups
dtat are launched in the name of democracy and to deepen democracy, and when various forces aim to criticize it in terms of its own
rationality and unfullled vision, that we should approach analytically this crucial dimension of institutional fragility.
Institutional fragility and democratic persistence
As emphasized by Eisenstadt, every democracy is fragile (Eisenstadt
1998, 1999b; see also Bobbio 1987). The Iberoamerican systems were
especially fragile during the Cold War, when they collapsed under
mounting mass mobilizations, guerrilla and paramilitary groups, and
military takeovers.
It is well known that these trends destabilized civilian rule in the
1960s and 1970s. We should also recognize that such fragility has
been reenacted after the restoration of democracy in the current
558
luis roniger
559
this demand for harsh measures follows its own logic within the context of social deterioration and economic decline, it constitutes a
problem for the newly established democracies as far as civil and
political rights are concerned, even if the current systems have professed to condemn the use of repression as carried out by the previous de facto governments.
Pooling these cases together, violence emerges as a central concern in terms of combined institutional fragility and viability. Whether
related to the political system as in Colombia, where violence crystallized very early on fuelled by party identities, or in countries such
as Brazil, where social and criminal violence mounted in relative disconnection from the political system, violence generates a process of
amalgamation of identities. Violence cuts o the ties of shared identity between strangers, while replacing them with the illusion of
nding security and stability through the construction of an image
of the other as an enemy. This process of reconstruction of collective identities predicates exclusion and the adjournment of dialogue
(Bowman 2001, Feitlowitz 1998, Touraine 2002). In Iberoamerica
such seclusion takes place primarily along class lines and secondarily
along ethnic identities. It may trigger a dynamics of ghettoization
of identities, to use Ralf Dahrendorf s term (2003) or of spatial segregation as typical of the mega-cities but also found in rural areas,
especially in countries of continental dimensions and long-standing
regional seclusion such as Colombia (Rojas de Ferro 1998).
As violence persists, it has crucial implications for the institutional
vitality of democracy. When segregation occurs and a restrictive sense
of collective identity is forged, individuals cling to distrust and exclusion towards the members of other classes, social groups or ethnicities. This is even more pronounced if occurring together with a
deterioration of traditional norms and forms of reciprocity and its
replacement by high residential mobility, the weakening of ties of
locality and connections, the perception of authoritative gures as
arbitrary and unexpected, and the perception of the public sphere
with suspicion and lack of condence.3
560
luis roniger
561
562
luis roniger
563
4
Experiences cannot be reproduced, even in countries with similar institutional
dynamics. The local anchoring of change is crucial. In Chile the change of policy
was adopted by a highly authoritarian and repressive government. In spite of the
social price demanded, Pinochets government was able to overcome the crisis of
the early 1980s and managed to transfer its institutional model during the transition to democracy. In Argentina, in a formal democratic framework, many of the
changes were introduced by presidential decree, against a background of disarticulation of the opposition and the widespread fears of the population about the perils
of hyperination, as experienced in the late 1980s.
564
luis roniger
politics and politicians or at least some of them have to make a tremendous eort in order to stop the tendency to make politics merely instrumental and technocratic. This is an eort that in some way is meant
to fail, but on the other hand it must be done in order to generate a
certain resistance against the total technocratization. (Hoppenhayn 2000)
This has had various consequences for the provision of public services and goods. There are consequences related to state responsibility and others, which are related to the changing relationship of
the population with the political system and with the public spheres.
In a certain way, whatever occurs in one of these realms aects the
others. The idea that the state left behind the central role which it
played in the era of protectionism, aects in the rst place the states
responsibility to guarantee the quality of public goods and intervene
in cases of market failure.
These aspects are articulated in the public sphere, through expressed
condence in the institutional channels and guaranties for the regulation of services and markets, the possibility of access to public
education and healthcare, or the provision of security, running water
and pollution control as public goods. In many cases, consumers
have been unable to appeal to institutional channels when they
encountered widespread problems in their reliance on market mechanisms. For example, in Argentina in the 1990s there were numerous
incidents of gastric problems and hospitalization, the consequence of
consuming unhealthy products. In countries with normative codes
and appropriated institutional channels of appeal, like the USA or
Western Europe, such incidents would generate a judicial prosecution
and a demand for monetary compensation. In Iberoamerica, at the
most, those involved lamented the case, and in other cases neither
that would happen, it just ended with a generous smile. The institutional frameworks often failed to sustain the bond of trust between
costumer and vendor, that once disavowed, could be taken to superior instances for adjudication. If such eective protection of consumers existed, the aected party could opt to bring the claim into
relief, which beyond the specic merits of the case, would have wider
implications in terms of duciary trust. That is, the eect of repairing the damage if the case warranted it and, what is even more
important for the public sphere, an ethics of market responsibility
sustained whenever consumers realize their expectations of market
fairness have not been deceived.
Whenever this is not possible, expectations of impunity are con-
565
Once they were carried out, the gap between the expectations of
public benet and the opaque and sometimes little eective way in
which many privatizations were done created public discontent.
Every process of privatization touches upon accountability, regulation and policy results. The urgency and mode by which privatizations were sometimes carried out implied some serious faults in
the subsequent regulation of the functioning and provision of the
privatized services. Outstanding in this respect were the early privatizations in Argentina, done irrespective of procedures and creating
what many saw as conditions for corruption and scandals that reached
top government ocials, their associates and families. This also
aected the issue of equality and access to services and goods related
566
luis roniger
to the so called third-generation rights, e.g., healthcare and education. Peter Knapp and his associates, among others, have indicated the importance of these realms, stating that there is a level of
inequality beyond which the ideals of basic equal opportunities, social
equality and inclusive community are transformed into a vacuous
claim (Knapp et al. 1996: 202; see also Chalmers et al. 1997 and
Kliksberg 2000).
Dealing with these aspects of institutional performance and malfunctioning turns crucial for public trust, as it is central to the public
perception of an eective functioning of institutions and the formation of a view of the political and administrative leadership that is
committed to the collective well-being of the population in an eective
manner.
Politics and representation
Turning to the political realm we need to focus on representation and
representation, democracys sine qua non. No matter what denition
we followwhether Dahls concept of polyarchy, Lord Dahrendorf s
pacic regulation of socio-economic conicts, or Adam Przeworskis
denition of representative democracy as the system in which political
parties lose electionsthe core of democracy refers to its systemic
and normative regulation of competition for power. Its inner logic
is built upon a shared commitment not to stop the ever-renewed
competition following short-term political triumphs over adversaries.
As such, the comparative advantage of the democratic political system
vis--vis its late alternatives (namely, Fascism, Nazism, and Communism)
has been its built-in exibility for incorporating new demands and
interests by groups and political movements. One of the most basic
conditions for such perpetuation is the existence of channels of open
representation.
Studies concerning representation emphasize the aspect of formal
structure of the electoral systems, expecting representation by political parties to express social pluralism. They also conceive that the
parliamentary organs are those charged with holding a serious and
informed debate over the actual and future alternatives, as part of
policy formation process. According to these views, power-holders
are supposed to take decisions in a calibrated way, being fully informed
and able to assess information rationally, combining discrete interests
567
568
luis roniger
569
political, social and administrative articulation (Graham 1997). Clientelism involves asymmetric but mutually benecial relationships of
power and exchangea non-universalistic quid pro quo between
individuals or groups of unequal standing. It implies mediated and
selective access to resources and markets from which others are normally excluded. Perhaps it is not surprising that, under the changing
macroeconomic policies and the reality of poverty in which 200 out
of the 516 millions of habitants of the region exist, clientelism has
reappeared, despite the predictions of modernization theories, which
forecasted its decline. What is striking is the transformation of its
forms, which become intertwined with civil society and the new discourses of democratic participation and representation.
As the new social movements revolutionalize politics, establishing
alternative discursive arenas, challenging dominant practices and
achieving at the very least a measure of symbolic power, new constituencies committed to the ideal of rights emerge (Alvarez et al.
1998). This in itself does not eliminate reliance on clientelism, yet
it reshapes the terms in which relationships are expressed, as well
as the tactics employed by those using them, from favors in a patrimonial sense to public services that clienteles demand as their own
right. To quote from an analysis of this phenomenon in the Brazilian
urban landscape by Robert Gay, in Brazil and probably in other
settings as well, clientelism seems increasingly to be
a means for pursuing the delivery of collective as opposed to individual
goods. This means that political clienteles are less likely to assume the
form of loose clusters of independently negotiated dyads than organizations, communities or even whole regions that fashion relationships
or reach understandings with politicians, public ocials and administrations. In other words, contemporary clientelism exhibits both hierarchical and relational elements and elements of collective organization
and identity (Gay 1998: 14).
570
luis roniger
571
6
In the last decade Iberoamerica has moved strongly in this direction, albeit not
without conicts. Yet, the shift is strongly reected constitutionally and culturally
in many countries, from Peru to Brazil and from Bolivia to Guatemala, both in
terms of ethnic and linguistic diversity and to a lesser extent in terms of gender.
See Alvarez et al. 1998; Braig 1999.
572
luis roniger
573
There are signicant variations, not only regarding the stance toward
neo-liberal economy, as discussed above, but also in political terms.
In relatively high institutionalized polities, the styles described are
geared to the creation of what I would call a certain third tier of
democratic resonance, as identied and expressed by the leader. A
typical case is that of Joaqun Lavn, leading a populism coming
from one of the forces that supported Pinochet and who, while personalizing politics, launched policies to mobilize the young, popular,
and women populations, through a combination of old and new, that
strongly recalls Gianfranco Finis political bases of support in Italy.
In less institutionalized polities such as Ecuador or Bolivia, the
logics of neo-populism become entrenched in the perception of participatory, cum-direct democracy as the true democracy. In these
societies, substantial sectors recognize an aboriginal ascendance and
relate to images of autochthonous models of leadership and communal
574
luis roniger
575
576
luis roniger
political articulation and through protest. The second process of dualization separates the above groups, which somehow relate to the
state, and those marginal groups that live outside organized society,
beyond the formal economy and outside the control of the state, be
it positively or negatively phrased (Sznajder and Roniger 2003). In
this kind of democracy it is typical for large sectors to be sidelined,
with little autonomous access to goods and services, and lack a capacity to fully participate in the public spheres due to their marginal
placement at the margins of society, economy, and politics. In parallel, other sectors continue to have a mediated access to markets of
goods and services and to use the clientelist networks to connect to
the political system and the public administration.
And yet, there is a long tradition of parallel attempts to generate
such participatory social and political capital, mostly futile in the
past and recently crowned with success. Practices such as the electoral control in Mexico or the model of participatory budgeting
in Brazilian cities such as Porto Alegre and Belo Horizonteare
exemplary. In Brazil, following the reform of the Constitution, there
has been a process of institutional innovation based upon a tripartite structure that involved public administrators together with professionals and local delegates representing civil society, in the process
of provision of public services, tying the translation of macro policies to the daily practice of making decisions over the nature of services, their costs and the quality of their provision. In Brazil, one
could witness in the impoverished and dry hinterland of Cear, one
of the poorest settings of the Northeast, a new willingness to contribute resources to public projects, in addition to the funds delivered
from the federal and state levels, as a result of these changes in the
articulation of local participation in decision-making (eldwork,
MarchApril 2002).
According to researchers of Iberoamerica, the recent experiences
suggest an alternative to the elitist theories of democracy. According
to the elitist theories, democracy will exist wherever there will be a
fair political game of recurring competition for power, structured
through electoral decisions. The origins of such minimalist denition
focusing on the selection of political leadership and the election of
governmentcan be traced to the inter-war period in Europe, when
wide mass mobilizations disrupted the political systems of the rst
wave of democratization. Something similar occurred at the end of
Cold War, when violence on the right and the left disarticulated
577
578
luis roniger
Conclusions
Even though the work of Shmuel N. Eisenstadt has raised our awareness to the crystallization of not one but multiple models of modernity, research still tends intuitively to look for the ideal institutional
format which will be the denitive solution for the problems of
democracy. Related to this intuitive tendency, political marketing has
become fashionable, orienting the use of media strategies as political weapons for identifying preferences, orienting public opinion and
capturing votes. And yet, even if one recognizes their importance,
the emphasis on the ways we do politics cannot obviate dealing with
dierences in the workings of public institutions. In order to invigorate
democracy, political marketing and media strategies are insucient
guidelines.
The search after the ideal model has led many to think, for example, that some democracies are successful due to their electoral format, which seems to be better than others, or that the issue of
optimal representation can be formally resolved by an intelligent use
of the mass media or a referendum. We should keep in mind that
the problem of development of representative democracy cannot be
dissociated from the nourishing of shared ideas regarding the public
good, elaborated democratically in various ways in dierent societies,
and from the generation of social capital, vital for institutional transformations.
Accordingly, this work has analyzed some innovative experiences
for Iberoamerica, aiming at the institutionalization of democratic
controls in the local scene, but also the phenomena of neo-clientelism
and neo-populism. These two trends seem almost contradictory and
yet both indicate the need to address current problems in the current
workings of representative democracy and in the connection between
the public agenda and the markets.
Beyond its concrete focus, this analysis has made a claim on the
importance of rethinking the public realm in the widest possible
terms, that is, as a focus for the forging of collective identity, the
recreation of sociability and the building of a shared sense of future.
In practical terms, for democracies overloaded with poverty, unemployment and exclusion, this means that work has to be done to
improve public performance and ecacy, to promote and safeguard
public goods and, in parallel, to intensify the equation of growth,
redistribution and inclusion instead of the inverse equation of stag-
579
nation (recession or decline), widening socioeconomic gaps and exclusion. The latter is crucial in societies such as those of Iberoamerica,
overload with pressures derived from their huge socioeconomic gaps
combined with raising expectations of democratic voice and participation, which are often manipulated by populist rhetoric and clientelistic intercession.
CHAPTER THIRTY
582
alberto martinelli
2000b) or varieties of modernity, through the continuous interpretation, reinterpretation and transformation of the modern project.
European identity is also a key political issue. There is widespread
criticism that the European Union is today a limited project, since
the economic integration of Europe has not been transformed by a
parallel cultural integration into a true political union. It is argued
that a decit of cultural integration exists because the communitarian
process is based on economic rationality rather than on a feeling of
common belonging and that a shift from interest politics to identity
politics is needed. Actually, the current construction of the European
Unionas a process of building a loosely coupled, open system
through a set of supra-national, supra-state normative institutions
is made possible by a common historical heritage and by shared cultural attitudes. The formation of a united Europe developed from
the desire to put an end to centuries-long European civil wars and
from the recognition of common economic interests for the peoples
of Europe, and grew through the development of a unied European
market where persons, capitals, goods and services can move freely;
but the cultural dimension has also been, and remains, present in
the process of European integration, and a common European identity is not opposed to, but linked with, common interests.
Shared values and cultural attitudes, however, should be better
specied and strengthened in order to dene a clear and distinct
European identity. The drafting of the European constitution aims
at meeting such a need. In the debates that took place during its
drafting. the questions were raised whether the building of the
European Unionparticularly with the admission of former Eastern
European communist countriesrequires the denition and the
armation of a distinctive European identity, whether such an identity exists, which are its specic features, and how it can be fostered.
In the rst draft of the European Constitution, specic reference was
made to the tradition of the Enlightenment, but no analogous reference
was made either to Christianity or to Greek and Roman antiquity.
Subsequently the preference was to eliminate any reference to cultural
traditionsalthough well entrenched in the historical experience of
the European peoplesboth in order to avoid ideological quarrels
and to emphasize the open, multicultural nature of the new Europe.
But the question of the specic features of a distinctive European
identity is of the utmost importance and a key issue of debate in
the European public space.
583
584
alberto martinelli
One or many European identities?
585
586
alberto martinelli
587
the quest for political freedom within the community, i.e. the development of the individual together with the social world around him.
The third factor, science, is also related to liberty insofar as it is
dened as the constant eort to arrive at the heart of everything
that can be penetrated; knowledge and the love for knowledge makes
human beings free, giving them not only the external freedom achieved
through the knowledge of nature, but alsoand foremostinternal
freedom.
The quest for knowledge is a distinctive European trait since
ancient times, but it is with modernity that it acquires a new impulse
because it is freed from the subordination of knowledge to a given
religious truth or to a single political end. The incessant quest for
knowledge is the product of the critical mind, which has its roots in
the Greek philosophical ethos and develops with the Enlightenments
permanent critique of our historical era. The development of science is linked together with the driving force of capitalism and the
massive development of technology, both related in their turn to the
belief in continuous progress. European modernity is the age of
Prometheus unleashed, which corresponds to the absence of ethical
and religious limits to the technical dominion of nature. Capitalism
is a mode of production based on technical instrumentality and on
the maximization of economic rationality for successful competition
in the market.
European rationalism has manifested itself in a variety of dierent
forms, from Romanesque architecture to Renaissance painting, from
the philosophy of Descartes to the music of Bach, from the democratic man of the Enlightenment to the homo economicus of capitalism.
It can be dened lato sensu as the capacity of the human mind to
know, control and transform nature (according to a conception of
the world as an environment that can be molded to the fullling of
human needs and wants) and as the condence of human beings in
rationally pursuing their own ends and, in the nal analysis, being
the masters of their own destiny.
In its condence in the power of reason to control and transform
nature, European rationalism is the breeding ground of scientic and
geographical discoveries and technological and entrepreneurial innovations; it is related to the perception of an absence of limits (as
mentioned earlier), to that particular restlessness of the European
people, as it is portrayed in paradigmatic gures of European literature from Dantes Ulysses to Goethes Faust, and it is exemplied
588
alberto martinelli
589
590
alberto martinelli
591
rm, the nation-state and the democratic polity, the university and
the research academy.
Let us briey look at these above elements: rst, European science
and technology, i.e. a particular approach to the knowledge of physical and human reality capable of transforming nature for the fulllment
of human wants. The depth of Indian and Chinese religion and philosophy, the richness of Muslim scientic and religious thought, and the
advanced astronomic knowledge of Mesopotamia and pre-Colombian
America are a few examples which demonstrate that Western knowledge is not exceptional. What is distinctive and specic in European
culture is a greater capacity to unite abstract theory and empirical
research and, even more importantly, to link together scientic discovery, invention and technological innovation under the constant
pressure of either war or commercial competition, as well as a greater
ability to design institutions particularly suited to the formation and
diusion of knowledgefrom the Italian and French medieval universities to the seventeenth-century British scientic academies, from
the nineteenth-century German research universities to the great
research laboratories of the present. European modernity was not
simply a package of technological and organizational developments;
it was intimately linked to a political revolution, and to an equally
important transformation of the nature of scholarly and scientic
practices and institutions (Wittrock, 2000). Europe has invented and
perfected an understanding of science, which has become a global
example and role model. The main characteristics of this understanding of science, as it has developed since the Renaissance, are,
as Rudolph argues, the recognition of mathematics as the measure
of exactness in science, the unity of freedom of scientic enquiry
and scientic criticism, and the dependence of empirical knowledge
on conceptual reection (Cerutti & Rudolph, 2001b).
The second element is market-driven industrial capitalism. The
governing principle of capitalism is the constant search for the rational maximization of individual utility in order to successfully compete in the market. The ecient combination of the factors of
production in the industrial rm and the exchange of goods and services in the self-regulating market slowly expanding all over the world
are the two basic institutions of capitalist development. The industrial revolution of the eighteenth century (a most powerful process
of innovation, capital accumulation and market expansion) developed
thanks to agricultural surpluses, long-distance trade surpluses and the
592
alberto martinelli
593
594
alberto martinelli
595
596
alberto martinelli
597
598
alberto martinelli
599
European contribution in a peaceful process of cultural cross-fertilization with other cultures in the world.
An open European identity as part of the European
project of unity through diversity
So far, I have argued that the peoples of the European Union countries have common cultural roots, and both values and institutions
that have ancient origins have crystallized in the process of European
modernization, yet spreading later to the other parts of the world.
This common cultural heritage contributes to European political integration, but it cannot (and does not need to) produce a distinctive,
coherent identity which legitimizes the specicity of Europe as a single political entity in the way national cultures legitimized the formation of European nation-states, because the political building of
the European Union cannot follow the path of national building and
cannot be grounded on the opposition us versus them. Identity
and otherness are of course closely related; at least to some extent,
I identify with somebody because we both feel dierent from somebody else. As Fontana (1994) argues, in the course of their history
Europeansand more precisely those groups which were culturally
hegemonicdened a distorted identity through the deforming
glasses through which they looked at the other (the barbarian, the
heretic, the savage). But the lessons of historyreligious fundamentalism and bigotry, ideological dogmatism, nationalistic aggressivenessteach us that this negative and arrogant way of dening an
identityan identity against somebody elseand its use to build a
political entity, is no longer advisable in the world today. Besides,
in the Europe of nations it would be hardly feasible. European
identity must deny the old belief that what is dierent is potentially
hostile. For this reason European political identity cannot become a
rigid and closed set of beliefs and attitudes but must be built around
a project; it cannot be deduced from its origin, but rather from its
future. The notion of absence of limitswhich I discussed above as
typical of modern European identity (Cerutti & Rudolph, 2001b)
provides the basis for conceiving Europes present political identity
as a project in the making and in terms of its consequences.
The legitimacy of the process of European integration cannot be
deduced from a separate cultural identity, rather it is linked to the
600
alberto martinelli
601
multiple citizenship, in the process we should also foster those elements of traditional nationhood that are compatible with the multicultural supranational model. Let us consider for this purpose the
basic components of nationhood as dened by scholars of ethnicity
and nationhood (A. Smith, 1991, Tullio-Altan, 1995): ethnos, logos,
topos, ethos, and epos. We cannot rely on ethnos (that is, on ancestral
ethnic origins), since it fosters closure, exclusion and discrimination,
and runs against the core values of the EU. We cannot rely too
much on logos either; if language is taken as the basis of logos, European
citizens cannot be forced to speak a single language, since multilingualism is considered a basic requisite for the respect of dierent
cultural identities. Topos, the symbolic transguration of the space
where Europeans live, can help to some extent. There are, in fact,
distinctive common characters in European cities, buildings, squares,
and public and private spaces, but this goes together with such a
great variety of natural and human landscapes that it can be hardly
considered a strong identifying element.
We are then left with ethos and epos. We can certainly invest more
in ethos (the basic core values, vision of the world, and practical
knowledge that dene the new European identity and outline the
basic rights and responsibilities of democratic citizenship), and in
epos (the great gures and events that testify as to the common
European heritage in arts, science, and culture). Both ethos and epos
should be basic components of educational programs for the next
generations and should orient the activities of the media and various
manifestations of public discourse, in order to create a real European
public space grounded in a shared political culture, which could
orient peoples choices on matters of common concern.
Moreover, the process of union building will be helped by an
increasingly interconnected economy (favored by the euro), a homogeneous European social fabric and the growth of a European public
space. The strengthening of a common culture, I want to stress again,
should not be seen as a means for excluding others, but rather as
a necessary basis for the dialogue among civilizations.
If this project fails, it will provide support for the theory that
nation-states continue to be built only upon either a homogeneous
culture or a hegemonic culture capable of integrating immigrants
into a melting pot. If the project succeeds, the European Union can
become a model for other regions of the world to form large supra-
602
alberto martinelli
PART SIX
CHAPTER THIRTY-ONE
606
raymond boudon
607
608
raymond boudon
609
610
raymond boudon
611
economic system, with few exchanges being conducted with the outside environment. In such societies, the weakest members would be
considerably threatened if collective decisions were taken, say, on the
basis of the majority rule. Consequently, such a constitutional rule
would not be considered as legitimate. Popkins interpretation, diering
from the current interpretation of most anthropologists, recognizes
the obvious fact that the unanimity rule maximizes the power of
each individual, as shown by the fact that it has another name: the
veto right. Moreover, Popkins interpretation accounts for the fact
that in the village societies with the unanimity rule as a basic constitutional rule, decisions generally take a long time and occur in a
climate of confrontation and institutionalized conict. On the whole,
this type of study shows convincingly that the sense of all for their
individuality and singularity is characteristic of societies where solidarity is mechanical, to use Durkheims vocabulary, as of societies
with organic solidarity. Individualism meets more favorable conditions
in the latter, i.e. modern societies; but it characterizes the former
as well.
Possibly without being aware of Durkheims statement according
to which individualism would begin nowhere, Simmel (1990) considers
as evident the fact that the individualistic virus was already present
at the dawn of history. It explains the abolition, in antique Germany,
of the Wergeld, a judiciary practice which indexed the sanction on
the social rank of the victim. Once abolished, any human life had
in principle the same value. Once the abolition of the Wergeld
was introduced, it became irreversible because it represented a step
forward in the establishment of individualism. To Simmel as to
Durkheim, individualism begins nowhere, but it leads the selection
of ideas and institutions and explains that some of them are irreversibly adopted.
Such studies illustrate the powerfulness of the social sciences. Once
they follow a scientic ethos and care about scrupulously examining
data, they display their capacity of eradicating the ethnocentric representations of ordinary sociology. Durkheim, Simmel and nowadays
Popkin show that the viewaccording to which individualism (in
the sense that Durkheim takes the concept) would be exclusively
characteristic of modern societiesis the product of an ethnocentric
illusion. Popkins powerful study shows that ethnocentrism can be
strong even among professional anthropologists; many of who seem
to believe that, since the people they observe behave dierently from
612
raymond boudon
the way they behave themselves, they should be dierent. The imagery
of the fusional community where individuals would have no consciousness of their own self and would exist exclusively, so to say,
through the group, is treated by many anthropologists as going without saying, while it is a mere ethnocentric illusion. Equally ethnocentric is the representation that people would have been in the past
submitted to collective representations and values they would have
passively accepted, while in modern and postmodern societies, they
would pick up the representations and values they please. Ethnocentrism
can be historical as well as geographic, vertical as well as horizontal,
as it were. Unfortunately, studies like Popkins are too rare. A lasting
ethnocentric tendency leads on the contrary to the current view that
individualism is a cultural distinctive feature of modern western society. Like Durkheimand Adam Smith before himthe economist
of Indian origin Amartya Sen has stated that the rst value for any
individual, Indian or European, is to be able to consider himself
with respect.
The a-historical character of individualism
It is important to note immediately that the basic principle of individualism (organizing society in order to respect as much as possible the vital interests and the dignity of each) has been permanently
thwarted by all kinds of historical forces, to use Webers phrase.
Durkheim aims to stress, evidently not that the dignity of individuals has always been respected in reality, but that they have always
had the sense of their dignity and of their vital interests; that this
feeling is the ground on which the history of institutions and even
history shortly unfolds; more precisely, that the dignity of individuals
and the respect of their vital interests is the ultimate criterion of the
legitimacy of any norm or institution, whatever its level, microscopic,
societal or intermediary.
Thus, the Greek devised institutions which have been justly praised
and imitated because they aimed at being respectful of the dignity
of citizens. But they considered slavery as legitimate, for they were
convinced of its functional interest for society as a whole. Aristotle
did not conceive of a society without slaves. Montesquieu held slavery
as being against nature (contre la nature), but thought that if slavery
was abolished in the Antilles, the price of sugar would rise too much.
613
614
raymond boudon
615
616
raymond boudon
[19201921]) sketched some ideas that converge with those of Durkheim. The similarity, it seems to me, is striking.
In his Essays in the Sociology of Religion, Weber comments on a passage of St. Pauls Letter to the Galatians in which Paul reprimands
Peter. In the passage, Peter suddenly takes his leave from a group
of Gentiles because he sees Jews coming to them. In this anecdote,
Weber writes, he sees a crucial episode in the history of Western
civilization. It signals the birth moment of the idea of citizenship
in the West [Die Geburtsstunde des Brgertums im Okzident]. Peter did
not dare remain in the company of the Gentiles when the Jews
appeared, while Paul would have expected that, by remaining seated,
he would have meant that, beyond their dierences, all men are
equally worth; that they are consequently all entitled to sit at the
same table; that a legitimate political order must recognize this equal
dignity; briey, that individuals should be regarded as persons and that
a necessary condition for them to be treated as persons is that they
are treated as citizens. The realization of this idea, says Weber, was
considered from this moment as a basic objective; this objective was
bound to lead the history of the West for centuries. Where does the
strength of this idea come from? From the fact that the crucial innovation represented by the notion of citizenship that underlies the idea
of commensality, the idea that all should sit at the same table, appears
immediately as giving an expression to the idea of the intrinsic value
of any individual, with the corollary that good institutions are institutions that would be approved by all.
Individualism begins nowhere, Durkheim has written. But it
develops constantly throughout history. In the Letter to the Galatians,
individualism appears, writes Weber, as responsible for a crucial innovation which was to inspire the history of the West for centuries,
beyond doubt because it is an answer to a latent universal demand.
Weber proposes in other words a programmatist view of social evolution, if I may use this disgraceful neologism: a view that sees evolution led by programs: a familiar concept in Eisenstadts evolutionary
theory. Weber invites us to consider the history of political institutions, the history of religions or the history of morals, as guided by
a diuse program aiming at dening institutions, rules, etc. which
would most eciently respect the dignity and vital interests of all.
The invention of the notion of person is a crucial step in the realization of this program. As early as the rst century, Weber writes,
this program was advanced in a spectacular fashion thanks to the cre-
617
ation of the notion of citizenship (the word is not used by Paul, but
the notion underlies the anecdote reported by Weber).
In order to make clearer the interpretation I propose of Durkheims
and Webers intuitions, one can insist, as Weber often does, on the
analogy between the history of morals and of political philosophy
and the history of science (Boudon, 2000, Ch. 5). Science is born
from a vague program which can be dened as describing the real world
as it is. The value of this program cannot be demonstrated, for ultimate values cannot be demonstrated acceptable or not, legitimate or
not: an obvious statement well stressed by Webers famous conference on Science as Vocation. I will leave aside here the undesirable
comments, such as those of Leo Strauss (1953) and of his numerous
followers who saw in this statement the expression on Webers part
of a relativistic stance, while Weber simply meant that any theory
starts from principles which cannot be demonstrated if not by other
principles which would have to be demonstrated, and thus ad innitum.
Once this program is proposed (if one can say so, since, as individualism, the program begins nowhere), it has inspired and still inspires
a constant ow of speculations and researches.
In this conference, Weber states clearly that, not only science but
the other districts of thought, is governed by a process of rationalization: Scientic progress is beyond doubt the most important fraction of this intellectualization process to which we are submitted since
millenaries [Der wissenschaftliche Fortschritt ist ein Bruchteil, und zwar der
wichtigste Bruchteil, jenes Intellektualisierungsprozesses, dem wir seit Jahrtausenden
unterliegen] (Weber, 1995 [1919], p. 18).
Similar to the history of science, the history of morals and of political philosophy is that of the realization of a program, whose objective is to conceive institutions able to respect as far as possible the
dignity and vital interests of individuals. As the validity of the program science, the validity of such a program cannot be more demonstrated. And this program is as fuzzy as the program of science; the
notion that science should describe the world as it is is unclear; as
unclear as the notion of the dignity of the person. The validity of the
two programs cannot be demonstrated and they are equally vague.
In fact, they are even necessarily vague, one might add, since they
are dened by a regulatory idea which requires that their meaning
is made more precise. They are never completed; they guide human
action in several of its dimensions. An indirect proof of the fuzzy
character of the program described by the notion of science can be
618
raymond boudon
read in the fact that, while many works in the philosophy of science
have been devoted to identifying the demarcation criteria between
science and non-science, they were never found. The Vienna circle
tried to make veriability the criterion of science. Popper rejected it
and proposed falsiability instead. That criterion was accepted until
many objections were raised against it. Finally, a commonly accepted
view today is that there are no general criteria that would make it
possible to distinguish science from non-science.
The success of Christianity and later, in an entirely dierent conjecture, of socialism is due to the fact that the two movements may
be viewed held as major steps in the realization of the program
described by Weber and Durkheim. As Simmel (1984 [1892], 1990)
has rightly noted, the two movements, as dierent as they are in
many respects, have one point in common: they owe their inuence
to the fact that they have been perceived as advancing the individualistic program. In other words, they are thought to stress the respect
owed to each individual independently of his or her competence and
merits. In order to avoid possible misinterpretations, it should be
noted that Simmel clearly evokes the socialist movement in the state
where it was in his own time, when it had not yet gained power
anywhere.
It can be noted in the context of the Simmels association between
Christianity and socialism, that regular religions have a crucial advantage over secular ones. Given the symbolic character of their doctrine,
the former are immunized against criticism, while the latter are not,
since they claim to be scientic. This explains why Christianity
seems today to be in better health than socialism.
Before sociologists, philosophers were well aware that programs
can be proposed that include their own denition among their objectives. Thus, Hegel saw that many ideas can become clear only once
they are realized; he was also well aware that ideas can be fought
by social forces and that, nevertheless, they could survive in human
minds. However, as Popper (1945) rightly states, Hegel did not escape
the fallacy of historicism. With Max Weber, this undesirable feature
is eradicated. To him, some ideas appear irreversible because they
are the product of a rational selection; but historical forces can always
have the consequence that they are not really inscribed in the real
world. I will come back to this essential point in Webers intuition
in a moment.
If the elaboration I propose of Durkheims and Webers intuitions
619
620
raymond boudon
621
622
raymond boudon
623
624
raymond boudon
625
626
raymond boudon
627
628
raymond boudon
any laws or regulations. As an example, see the French droit au logement (literally: the right to a home). For some decades, this notion
has been part of the common language, while this so-called right is
not legally enforced. Some lawyers have proposed to call rights of the
third generation as the right to peace or the right to right, i.e. those rights
which have little chance of being ever legally enforced since it would
imply the abolition of force in national and international processes.
This stammering character of the development of new rights is
unavoidable. It conrms the characteristics of any program in the sense
where I use this concept here. The notion of the dignity of the person
is fuzzy; hence its content is unstable, and hyperbolic interpretations
of the notion are consequently unavoidable. See for instance, particularly in the USA, the hyperbolic views developed by the feminist
movement or by the movements struggling for the defense of minorities rights. Utopias are a normal component of the rationalization
processes through which new rights are identied and dened.
But it should also be noted that, at the same time, these utopias
and hyperbolic interpretations are exposed to a process of rational
selection. Obviously, this selection process does not result from a discussion between experts; it results rather from a confrontation between
actors; including public opinion, social movements, intellectuals and
lawmakers. That such rational selection processes develop currently
in a context of conict should not occult their underlying rationality.
Unfortunately, such an occultation is typical of the so-called sociological theories of conict and domination.
The inationary extension of rights which can currently be observed
is a symptom of the development of the program dened by the
notion of the respect of the person, as are many other features characteristic of contemporary societiesthe development of the right of
interference with the sovereignty of other nations (in French: droit
dingrence), or the creation of international penal tribunals. Episodes
like Pinochets arrest in the UK or the indictment of Milosevic by
an international court of justice are easily explained by the rationalization processes I have described. Their importance lies in the
fact that they illustrate the case where the rights of individuals are
perceived as having a priority with regard to the principle of national
sovereignty. The constant attempt at devising means of social control intended to minimize cases of misbehavior and at the same time
to express the utmost respect for the person of the criminal, is another
example of the action of these rationalization processes.
629
630
raymond boudon
631
law. Many anthropologists see the world as composed of a juxtaposition of singular cultures. Once it is realized that institutions should
be interpreted as deriving from the realization of a program, those
dilemmas disappear. Among the norms enforced in a given society,
some express their singularity, others are the outcome of processes
of diuse rationalization.
Finally, the evolutionary theory I propose to draw from Durkheims
and Webers intuitions is open in the sense that it does not claim that
evolution would tend toward some end. Evolution results from the
realization of programs led by a rationalization process. The cases
of ethics, law or political theory are not in principle dierent from
the case of science. Like the evolution of science, the evolution of
these other dimensions of thought is doomed to never reach an end.
Advantages of a programmatist theory of social evolution
It seems to me that the programmatist theory I propose to derive from
sketchy intuitions by Durkheim and Weber has a certain number of
distinctive features when compared to others. It insists on the importance of ideas in social evolution; on the importance of innovations;
on the unpredictable character of many ideas; on the role of contingencies; on the fact that new ideas can reect the realization of
a program; that for instance the notions of citizenship, person, rightto, belong to a widely undened program which they contributed to
deploy progressively; it insists on the fact that ideas tend to be rationally selected; that a selected idea can be realized in an indenite
number of fashions; on the fact that many norms are unaected by
these rationalization processes, because they are connected with some
values in an arbitrary fashion (as in the case of customs); on the fact
that evolutionary processes cannot be always interpreted as adaptation processes, but are often generated by innovations with no adaptation function properly; that the notion of rationalization combines
the cognitive and the instrumental dimensions of rationality.
These various features characterize the theory of social evolution
proposed by Eisenstadt (2002b). Eisenstadt uses the notion of program
explicitly and abundantly. He shows well how collective identities
are generated by programs made up of a mixture of singular and universal features, resulting from the interplay between rationalization
and singularities.
632
raymond boudon
633
CHAPTER THIRTY-TWO
636
shmuel n. eisenstadt
1
Mayer, 1976; Wilson, 1980; Portman, 1944; Gehlen, 1971; Plessner, 1966,
Diederichs, Plessner, and Augen, 1982.
637
determinants, and hence they necessarily constitute a focus of continuous change and of at least potential struggle.
The existence of some degree of such indeterminacy in patterns
of behavior and interaction is true of many other species, although
in a more limited way than among humans. But human beings are
also conscious of that indeterminacy and of the openness of their
own biological program. Such consciousness is closely related to the
consciousness, manifest in the construction of burial places, of death
and of human nitude, and it generates among human beings a core
existential anxiety and a closely related fear of chaos. This anxiety
is exacerbated by the human capacity for imagination, so brilliantly
analyzed by J.P. Sartre, i.e., by the ability to conceive of various
possibilities beyond what is given here and now,2 and in the closely
related universal predisposition to play.3 All these lead human beings
to problematize the givens of their own existence and to undertake
a quest for the construction of meaningful order as an integral part
of their self-interpretations and self-awareness, and of their selfreexivity.
Such anxiety and fear of chaos and the quest for the constitution
of a meaningful order through which that chaos can seemingly be
overcome, generate among human beings the strong predisposition
to construct a realm of the sacred, in which direct contact with the
roots of cosmic or social order is established, and which serves as a
focal point for the construction of symbolic and institutional boundaries inherent in the constitution of such an order.
It is such construction of the realm of the sacred that constitutes
the core of human charismatic activity. Such activity, oriented towards
the construction of a meaningful order, entails not only constructive
but also destructive tendencies or potentialities. Such destructive
potentialities are rooted in the fact that the constitution of such an
order cannot do away with either the indeterminacies inherent in
any pattern of continual human interaction, with the awareness or
consciousness thereofhowever dimor with the core existential
anxiety. Indeed, the very construction of such an order generates a
strong awareness of its arbitrariness and a strong ambivalence towards
it in general and towards any concrete social and cultural order in
2
3
Sartre, 1972.
Huizinga, 1970; Caillois, 1961; Brunner, Jully and Silva, 1979.
638
shmuel n. eisenstadt
4
5
6
Bateson, 1972; Taylor, 1985; Van der Lieuw, 1957, pp. 324353.
Bateson 1972; Taylor 1985; Eisenstadt, 1995b, pp. 167201; 22889; 378380.
Schneider and Smith, 1973.
639
640
shmuel n. eisenstadt
11
12
13
14
Durkheim, 1933.
Tenbruck, 1989.
Eisenstadt, 1983; Eisenstadt, 1987a.
Eisenstadt, 1983.
641
ways in which such themes are dened, combined and institutionalized that constitute the distinct characteristics of dierent collectivities. Whatever the concrete specication and combination of such
themes in any collectivity, the construction of collective identity entails
somehighly variablecombination of mostusually all ofsuch
codes or themes, and continual tension between them.
IV. The construction of collective identities is eected by various
social actors and situations, especially by various inuentials and
elites in interaction with broader social sectors. The core of this interaction is the activation of the predisposition to and search for some
such order, which is inherent, even if not fully articulated, among
all, or at least most, people. Such predispositions or propensities are
activated by dierent inuentials and actors who attempt to attain
hegemony in various settings. Of special importance are those actors
like for instance the dierent promulgators of the visions of the Great
Axial Civilizations or the bearers of the modern Great Revolutions,
or of dierent conceptions of modern statehood and nationality
who attempt to promulgate distinct visions of collective identity, and/
or distinct cultural programs. In so far as such activists nd resonance
among wider sectors of the population, they are able to institutionalize
the distinct symbols and boundaries promulgated by them, and crystallize dierent concrete collective identities and boundaries. Such actors
often compete with each other, as was the case, for instance, of the
competition between dierent religions in late antiquity.15
The competition between such activists is not purely symbolic
and the construction and promulgation of collective identities is not
a purely symbolic exerciseit is manifest not only in the symbolic depiction of the boundaries of the collectivity, but also in the
institutionalization thereof. The institutionalization of boundaries of
collectivities takes place through the interweaving of the promulgation
of such models of cosmic and social order and of the visions of distinctiveness of any collectivity, and of the attributes of similarity of
its members, appropriate to the members of these collectivities, with
the control of the production and distribution of resources, with the
regulation of power and access to such resources.
15
642
shmuel n. eisenstadt
16
17
18
643
19
Eisenstadt, 2002b.
644
shmuel n. eisenstadt
we shall focus here on the distinctive characteristics of the constitution of collectivities and of their destructive potentialities as they
developed in modern societies.
With the emergence of modernity, of modern civilization, there
emergedin close relation to the distinct cultural program of modernity and to the specic historical context of the development of the
institutional contours of modernitya new pattern of constitution of
collective identities. That constitution was characterized by some very
specic characteristics, which have greatly inuenced the entire modern
historical, social science and general discourse about collective identity,
especially of nationalism and ethnicityoften presenting them as if
they were the natural attributes or forms of collective identities, but
which have to be analyzed in the broader comparative and analytical
framework.
The cultural and political program of modernity as it developed
rst in the West, in Western and Central Europe, entailed distinct
ideological as well as institutional premises. It entailed a very distinct
shift in the conception of human agency, of its autonomy, and of
its place in the ow of time; one of the major characteristics thereof
was the loss of the markers of certainty and continual attempts and
contestation about their reinstatement. Accordingly, this program also
entailed a very distinctive mode of construction of the boundaries of
collectivities and collective identities. In some, even if certainly not
total, contrast to the situation in the Axial Civilizations, collective
identities were not taken as given or preordained by some transcendental vision and authority, or by perennial customs.
At the same time the most distinct characteristic of the construction of modern collectivities, very much in line with the general core
characteristics of modernity, was that such construction was continually
problematized in reexive ways, and constituted a focus of continual
struggles and contestations.
Those continual contestations were borne by distinct social actors
be they political activists, politically active intellectuals, and distinct
social movements, above all national or nationalistic onesoriented
to the constitution of such new collectivities. Indeed, one of the most
distinctive characteristics of the continual process of reconstruction
of modern collective identities was the centrality in this process of
special social and political activists, and above all organizations bearing
distinct visions of collective identities and ideologies, and mobilizing
wide sectors of the population. The best illustrations of the latter are
645
of course distinct social movements, especially the national or nationalistic ones, as well as the closely related promulgation of distinct
ideologies, above all national and also modern ethnic ones, of collective identity.
It was these activists and movements that were the bearers of contestations and struggles, often couched in highly ideological terms,
around the far-reaching transformation in comparison with the preceding Axial periods, of the codes of collective identity and of the
relation between them.20
The development of new, mainly secular denitionscouched in
highly ideological and absolutized termsof each component of collective identity were among the most important of such transformations of the themes of collective identity which were both attendant
on the development of modernity and rst emerged in Europe. The
key transformations of the components were the civil, primordial and
universalistic and transcendental sacred ones; the growing importance of the civil and procedural components thereof; of a continual
tension among these components; and a very strong emphasis, in
the construction and institutionalization of the collective identities,
on territorial boundaries.
Concomitantly there developed intensive tendencies toward the
establishment of a very strong connection between the construction
of the political order and that of the major encompassing collectivities, a connection that later became epitomized in the model of
the modern nation-state. The crystallization of the modern nationstate and its institutionalization entailed an emphasis on congruence
between the cultural and political identities of the territorial population; strong tendencies to attribute to the newly constructed collectivities and centers charismatic characteristics; the promulgation,
by the center, of strong symbolic and aective commitments of members of society to the center and the collectivity; and a close relationship between the center and the more primordial dimensions of
human existence as well as social life, as well as the civil and sacred
ones. In most modern societieswith the partial exception as we
shall see of Japansuch relationships did not entail denial of the
validity of the broader, civilizational orientations. Rather there developed strong tendencies for the new national collectivities to become
20
646
shmuel n. eisenstadt
21
Meyer and Jepperson, 2000, pp. 100120; Meyer, Boli and Thomas, 1987,
pp. 1238; Meyer, Boli, Thomas and Ramirez, 1997, pp. 144182.
22
Meyer and Jepperson, 2000; Meyer, Boli and Thomas, 1987, pp. 1238; Meyer,
Boli, Thomas and Ramirez, 1997.
647
relations between the central identity and the various secondary, primordial or sacred universalistic identitiesreligious, ethnic, regional
and the like.
The distinctive visions of the new modern collectivitiesabove all
indeed, of the nation-stateconcomitantly entailed the promulgation
of distinctive collective memories in which the universal, often sacred
components rooted in the universalistic components of the cultural
program of modernity and the particularistic national ones emphasizing their territorial, historical and cultural specities came together
albeit in dierent ways in dierent societies, but constituting in all
of them one of the major and continual foci of tensions and contestations.23
These dierent orientations of the overall collectivities were often
symbolized or dened in distinctive gender termswhere the state,
with its civic components, as well as with the organization of political
force was often portrayed in masculine terms, and the nation, with
strong primordial, nurturing and vitalistic components, in feminine
ones. Both these gendered symbols were usually brought together
under the canopy of the overarching nation state, yet at the same
time constituting a focus of continual tensions and of distinct, potentially competing identities.
Yet despite the strong tendency to conate, in the ideal model of
the nation-state, within state and nation there developed strong
tensions between the state with its emphasis on territoriality and
the seeming potentially universalistic notions of citizenship, on the
one hand; and nationwith its more closed denitions of membership with strong primordial components, on the other hand.
Thus paradoxically, a central aspect of the constitution of modern
collective identities, closely related to the tension between citizenship and membership of a primordial community, between state
and nation, was also the construction of a growing tendency to a
sharper delineation of the boundaries, of dierent ethnic, regional
and even religious communities, transforming the relative porousness
of former semi-ethnic territorial, linguistic or kin boundaries into
more formalized ones and with strong political orientations. Although
in principle such dierent primordial communities were to be brought
23
Meyer and Jepperson, 2000; Meyer, Boli and Thomas 1987, pp. 1238; Meyer,
Boli, Thomas and Ramirez 1997.
648
shmuel n. eisenstadt
together under the overall canopy of the nation state, in fact there
developed a potential for the continual development of a multiplicity
of such distinct collectivities with strong potential political orientations,
which needless to say varied greatly between dierent societies.
VII. In many ways, the model of the nation-state, closely related to
some of the basic ontological premises of the cultural program of
modernity, has become hegemonic in the modern international systems and frameworks that developed in conjunction with the crystallization of modern order.24 But despite its hegemonic standing, the
model of the nation-state was never as homogeneous, internally within
any single society or across dierent societies. Even in Europe, a
great variety of nation-states developed.
One of the most important aspects of that variety was the relative importance in them of the dierent codes or themes of collective identity, i.e. of the primordial and civil and sacral (religious or
secular ones) and the dierent combinations thereof. The second
aspect of that variety was the extent to which there developed totalistic
as against multifaceted visions of those basic collective identities
i.e. the extent to which the basic codes and the ways in which primordial-national, civil and universalistic orientations were interwoven
in them, and especially the extent to whichin the historical experience of those societiesnone of these dimensions is totally absolutized or set up by their respective carriers against the other dimensions
or, contrariwise, the extent to which rather multifaceted patterns of
collective identity developed instead.
Such dierent modes of construction of modern collective identities were promulgated in modern societies by many political activists
and intellectuals, and particularly the major social movements. It was
indeed one of the most distinct characteristics of the modern scene
that the construction of collective boundaries and consciousness could
also become a focus of distinct social movementsthe national or
nationalistic ones. In many modern societies, such as the UK, France,
and Sweden, the crystallization of new national collectivities and
identities of dierent types of nation-states took place. Without the
national movements playing an important role, the potentiality of
24
Meyer and Jepperson, 2000; Meyer, Boli and Thomas, 1987, pp. 1238; Meyer,
Boli, Thomas and Ramirez 1997.
649
25
Eisenstadt, 1996a.
650
shmuel n. eisenstadt
651
26
Eisenstadt, 1999a.
652
shmuel n. eisenstadt
27
28
L. Kolakowski, 1990.
Ben Kiernan, 1999, 17:93128.
653
traditional forcebut outcomes of modern reconstruction, of seemingly traditional forces in a modern way. Thus, to paraphrase
Leszek Kolakowskis (1990) felicitous and sanguine expression, modernity is indeed on endless trial.29
29
L. Kolakowski, 1990.
APPENDIX
658
appendix
appendix
659
Israeli Society. New York: Basic Books, 1967 (Also Hebrew, German and Portuguese
translations).
The Sociology of Modernization ( Japanese). Tokyo: Mizuzu Shobo, 1967.
Modernizacao e Mudanca Social. Introduction and translation by Jose Clovis Machada,
Belo Horizonte, 1968.
Ensayos sobre el cambio y la Modernizacion. Madrid, 1970.
Social Dierentiation and Stratication. Glenview: Scott, Foresman & Co., 1971 (Also
Hebrew and Japanese translations).
Tradition, Change and Modernity. New York: John Wiley & Sons, 1976. (Also German
and Italian translations).
Revolution and the Transformation of Societies. New York: Free Press, 1978. (Also Hebrew,
Portuguese, Russian and German translations).
The Transformation of Israeli Society An Essay in Interpretation. London: Weidenfeld &
Nicolson, and Boulder, Colorado: Westview, 1985.
[a] Hebrew: 1989. The Transformation of Israeli Society. Jerusalem: Magnes.
[b] German: 1987. Suhrkamp Verlag, 1992: German paperback with new
Introduction.
Comparative Sociology of Civilizations (in Japanese). Tokyo: Mariaisha. Translated by
Junichi Umezu and others, 1991.
A Dinamica das Civilizacoes. Tradicao e Modernidada. Lisbon: Edicoes Cosmos 1991.
De Transformatie van de Israelische Maatschappij. The Willem Drees Lecture, The Hague:
Sdu Uitgeverij Koninginnergracht, 1994.
European Civilization in a Comparative Perspective. Oslo: Norwegian University Press, 1987
(Also Japanese and French translations).
with A. Shachar Society, Culture and Urbanization. Beverly Hills and London: Sage
Publications, 1987.
Jewish Civilization. The Jewish Historical Experience in a Comparative Perspective. New York:
State University of New York Press, 1992 (Also Italian and enlarged Hebrew
translations).
Power, Trust and Meaning: Essays on Sociological Theory and Analysis. Chicago: University
of Chicago Press, 1995.
Japanese CivilizationA Comparative View. Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1996
(also Italian translation). (Forthcoming Japanese and Chinese translations).
Fundamentalismo e Modernidade. Portugal: Celta Editore (Portuguese), 1997.
Les Antinomies de la Moderniteles Composantes jacobines de la Modernite et du Fondamentalisme.
Paris: LArche (French), 1997.
[a] Die Antinomien der Moderne: Die Jakobinischen Grundzuge der Moderne und des
Fundamentalismus. Frankfurt am Main: Suhrkamp Verlag (German), 1997.
Modernita, Modernizzazione e Oltre. Rome: Armando Editore (Italian), 1997.
Os Regimes Democraticos: Fragilidade, Continuidade e Transformabilidade. Oeiras: Celta Editore
(Portuguese), 1998.
Paradoxes of Democracy, Fragility, Continuity and Change. Washington: The Woodrow
Wilson Press and Baltimore: The Johns Hopkins Press, 1999 (Also Italian and
Arabic translations).
[a] 2002. Paradossi Della Democrazia Versus Democrazie Illiberali, Bologna: Societa
Editrice il Mulino (Italian).
[b] 2003. Paradoxes of Democracy: Fragility, Continuity, and Change. Cairo, Egypt: El
Ahram Press (Arabic).
[c] 2004. Hebrew translation to be published by the Israel Democracy Institute.
Die Vielfalt der Moderne. Velbruck Wissenschaft, 2000.
Fundamentalism, Sectarianism and Revolutions. Cambridge University Press, 2000. (Hebrew
translation to be published in 2004.)
Democracy and Its Tortuosity: Paradoxes in Modern Democracy. Tel Aviv: Ministry of Defense
Publications (Hebrew), 2002.
660
appendix
Le Retour des Juifs dans lHistoire. Paris and Brussels: Editions Complexe (French).
Fundamentalism and Modernity, Tel Aviv: Ministry of Defense Publications (Hebrew),
2002.
Jewish Civilization: The Jewish Historical Experience in a Comparative Perspective and Its
Manifestations in Israeli Society. The Ben-Gurion Heritage Center: Ben-Gurion
University of the Negev (Hebrew), 2003.
S.N. Eisenstadt, Comparative Civilizations & Multiple Modernities2 volumes collection
of essays. Brill: Leiden-Boston, 2003.
Explorations in Jewish Historical Experience: The Civilizational Dimension. Brill: Leiden/Boston.
Changes in Israeli Society. Tel Aviv: Ministry of Defense Publications (Hebrew), 2004.
Modernity and Modernization: Collection of Essays. (in Italian), Rubettino, Italy, 2004.
Modernity and Modernization. (in Chinese), SDX Joint Publishing Company, China,
2004.
Political Theory in the Search of the Political. Soveria Mannelli, Italy (Italian).
appendix
661
A SCHOLARLY PORTRAIT
MULTIPLE OPENINGS FOR
SOCIOLOGICAL DISCOURSE
Donald N. Levine
Over the past decade or so, critics have raised questions about the
central unit of analysis in the discipline of sociology. They have done
so by questioning the viability of using the notion of society, in particular the nationally-circumscribed society, as such a foundational
unit. Some have even concluded that the age of sociology is over:
since its essential heuristic unit, the national society, is now obsolete, it is now time to discard the discipline of sociology altogether.
Thus, in his widely discussed ISA presidential letter no. 5 (1997),
Immanuel Wallerstein decried the persistence of sociological investigation of national societies on grounds that only an interdisciplinary
and evolutionary framework made sense for the social sciences. Nico
Stehr has emphatically rejected the continuing identication of
modern society with the nation-state as an obsolescent ideological
and epistemological residue of the 19th-century origins of social
science discourse (2001, 911). Martin Albrow (1997) urges us to
abandon terms like modernity altogether, arguing that while it was
appropriate to use the term Modern to designate the epoch of the
past few centuries, that epoch has now ended and we have entered
a new one, which he calls The Global Age.
Alain Touraine has for two decades been promoting the idea of
a sociology without society, by which he refers largely to the
national society. At meetings of the World Congress of Sociology in
July 2002, one of the hot ideas in circulation concerned the obsolescence of the nation-state as a central unit for sociological analysis,
and the theme of sociology without society was being taken up as
a banner behind which to secure a putative emancipation from all
previous sociology.
Long before the rise of these objections to using the trope of
society qua nation as an authoritative notion for sociological inquiry,
however, the sociological tradition included four strands of work that
transcend this analytic focus. These include the Simmelian notion of
appendix
663
664
appendix
appendix
665
On the other hand, Weber did signal a disposition to use the term
society in certain circumscribed ways. It could serve as a rough
generalization of certain kinds of conduct. When reference is made
in a sociological context to a state, a nation, . . . or to similar collectivities, what is meant is, on the contrary, only a certain kind of
development of actual or possible social actions of individual persons. What is more, he argued, these concepts of collective entities . . . have a meaning in the minds of individual persons, such that they
orient their action to them (1968, 14, emph. mine). The persons
in question include not only professionals such as judges and bureaucrats but ordinary, private individuals as well. Webers position on
this issue could thus be glossed as providing a foundation for what
has come to be thought of as a constructivist view of concepts like
the nation.
Parsons and the supranational social system
Where Simmel transcended the national society perspective by identifying forms of social interaction that could be manifested at any
level, from microscopic through international, and Weber did so by
repudiating the assumption that society referred to any sort of concrete phenomenonother than a symbolic construct in the minds of
actors, Parsons did so by subordinating the notion of society to a
more encompassing idea, that of the social system.
Initially, Parsons dened the social system as a plurality of individuals interacting in an environmentally contextualized situation, motivated to optimize gratications and related through a system of shared
symbols; he viewed society. then, as a type of social system that
meets all the essentials of long term persistence from within its own
resources (1951, 56, 19). As he developed the concept, he came to
use it with increasing exibility, to refer to systemic phenomena at
all levels, from microscopic to macroscopic. And although some of
his analyses of societies were directed at national entities like Germany
or the United States (1993; in press), in his innovative work of
the 1960s on the comparative analysis of societies, he concluded by
subordinating nations as units under what he called an overarching
system of modern societies. As early as 1971, then, Parsons had
illuminated the way to analyzing the global community in the terms
of his far-reaching systems theory.
666
appendix
appendix
667
668
appendix
appendix
669
670
appendix
BIBLIOGRAPHY
Abrams, M.H. (1953). The Mirror and the Lamp: Romantic Theory and the Critical Tradition.
New York: Oxford University Press.
Abromeit, H. (1998). Democracy in Europe: Legitimizing Politics in a Non-State Polity. New
York: Berghahn Books.
Abu-Lughod, J.L. (1989). Before European Hegemony. The World-System A.D. 12501350.
New York: Oxford University Press.
(1993). The World System in the Thirteenth Century: Dead-End or Precursor?
Washington, D.C.: American Historical Association.
Adamski, W.W. (1997). Structural Conicts Legacy as a Challenge to Systemic
Transfonnation: The Polish Case in Comparative Perspective, Sisyphus: Social
Studies X: 6982.
Adamski, W., P. Machonin, and W. Zapf (eds). (2002). Structural Change and Modernization
in Post-Socialist Societies. Hamburg: Krlimer.
Adamski, W., W. Zaborowski, and K. Pelczynska-Nalecz. (2002). The dynamics
of structural conict in the process of systemic change: Poland From 1980 to
2000, pp. 155169 in Adamski, Machonin and Zapf (eds.), Structural Change
and Modernization in Post-Socialist Societies. Hamburg: Krlimer.
Adorno, T. and M. Horkheimer. (1973 [1944]). Dialectic of Enlightenment. London:
New Left Books.
Agamben, G. (1995). Homo Sacer. Sovereign Power and Bare Life. Stanford, CA: Stanford
University Press.
Agassi, J. (1990). Bein dat la-leom: Likrat zehut leoumit israelit (Religion and nation:
toward an Israeli national identity), Tel-Aviv: Papyrus.
Agassi, J. and Brant, B. (1991). Mihou israeli? (Who is an Israeli?) Tel-Aviv: Kivunim.
Agursky, M. (1988). Laspect millenariste de la Revolution bolchevique, Cahiers du
monde russe et sovietique 29(34).
Ahrweiler, H. (1975). Lideologie politique de lEmpire byzantin. Paris: Presses universitaires de France.
Al-Azmeh, A. (1997). Muslim Kingship: Power and the Sacred in Muslim, Christian and
Pagan Polities. London: I.B. Tauris.
Albrow, M. (1996). The Global Age. Cambridge: Polity Press.
(1997). The Global Age: State and Society Beyond Modernity. Stanford: Stanford
University Press.
Alcntara Senz, M. (2003). Tras un cuarto de siglo de democracia en Amrica
Latina, pp. 519550 in Alfonso Guerra and Jos Flix Tezanos (eds.), Alternativas
para el siglo XXI. Madrid: Sistema.
Alexander, J. (2000). This Worldly Mysticism: Inner Peace and World Transformation
in the Work and Life of Charles Skip Alexander, Journal of Adult Development
7(4): 267272.
Alexander, J.C. (1988). Durkheimian Sociology: Cultural Studies. Cambridge: Cambridge
University Press.
(1992). The Fragility of Progress: An Interpretation of the Turn Toward
Meaning in Eisenstadts Later Work, Acta Sociologica 35: 8594.
(2003). The Meanings of Social Life: A Cultural Sociology. New York: Oxford
University Press.
Alexander, J.C., Eyerman, R., Giesen, B., Smelser, N., Sztompka, P. (2004). Cultural
Trauma and Collective Identity. Berkeley: University of California Press.
672
bibliography
bibliography
673
Aristotle. (1984). The Politics. Trans. Carnes Lord. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.
Arjomand, S.A. (1984). The Shadow of God and the Hidden Imam: Religion, Political
Organization and Societal Change in Shi`ite Iran from the Beginning to l890. Chicago:
The University of Chicago Press.
(2001). Perso-Indian Statecraft, Greek Political Science and the Muslim
Idea of Government, International Sociology 16(3): 46180.
(2003a). Medieval Persianate Political Thought, Studies on Persiante Societies
1: 534.
(2003b). Islam and the Path to Modernity: Toward a Historical Sociology
of the Islamicate Civilization, paper presented at the Yale Sociology Workshop,
September 25.
(2004). Rationalization, the Constitution of Meaning and Institutional
Development, pp. 247274 in C. Camic & H. Joas (eds.), The Post-Disciplinary
History of Modern Academic Disciplines. Rowman & Littleeld.
Armstrong, J.A. (1982). Nations before Nationalism. Chapel Hill, NC: University of
North Carolina.
Arnason, J.P. (1988). Social Theory and the Concept of Civilization, Thesis Eleven
20: 87105.
(2000). Communism and Modernity, Daedalus (Winter): 6190.
(2000a). Thesis Eleven: Modern Constellations, Civilizational Horizons. 61.
(2000b). Thesis Eleven: Modern Civilizations. Civilizational Horizons 62.
(2001). History of Civilizational Analysis, pp. 19091915 in Smelser, N.J.
and Baltes, P.B. (eds.), International Encyclopedia of the Social & Behevioral Sciences
(Vol. 3). Amsterdam: Elsevier.
(2003a). Civilizations in Dispute. Leiden and Boston: Brill Academic publishers.
(2003b). East and West: From Invidious Dichotomy to Incomplete
Deconstruction in G. Delanhy, E. Isin and M. Somers (eds.), Handbook of
Historical Sociology. London: Sage.
(2004). The Axial Age and its interpreters, in Johann P. Arnason, S.N.
Eisenstadt and Bjrn Wittrock (eds.), Axial Civilizations and World History. Leiden:
Brill Academic Publishers.
Arnason, J.P., Eisenstadt, S.N. & Wittrock, B. (2004). Introduction, in Johann P.
Arnason, S.N. Eisenstadt and Bjrn Wittrock (eds.), Axial Civilizations and World
History. Leiden: Brill Academic Publishers.
Asad, T. (1986). The Concept of Cultural Translation in British Social Anthropology,
in J. Cliord and G. Marcus (eds.), Writing Culture: The Poetics and Politics of
Ethnography. Berkeley: University of California Press.
Assmann, A. (1992). Einheit und Vielfalt in der Geschichte: Jaspers Begri der
Achsenzeit neu betrachtet, pp. 330340 in S.N. Eisenstadt (Hg.), Kulturen der
Achsenzeit II. Ihre institutionelle und kulturelle Dynamik. Teil 3. Buddhismus, Islam,
Altgypten, westliche Kultur. Frankfurt aM: Suhrkamp.
Assmann, A. and Frevert, U. (eds.). (1999). GeschichtsvergessenheitGeschichtsversessenheit:
vom Umgang mit deutschen Vergangenheiten nach 1945. Stuttgart: Deutsche Verlags
Anstalt.
Assmann, J. (1997). Moses the Egyptian: The memory of Egypt in Western Monotheism.
Cambridge, MA.: Harvard University Press.
(2000). Das kulturelle Gedchtnis: Schrift, Erinnerung und politisch Identitt in frhen
Hochkulturen. Mnchen: Beck.
Avineri, S. (1981). The Making of Modern Zionism: The Intellectual Origins of the Jewish
State. New York: Basic Books.
Avritzer, L. (2002). Democracy and the Public Space in Iberoamerica. Princeton: Princeton
University Press.
Azaryahu, M. (2000). McIsrael? On the Americanization of Israel, Israel Studies
5(1): 4164.
674
bibliography
bibliography
675
Bellamy R.P. (2002). Liberalism: impact on social science, in Smelser, N.J. and
Baltes, P.B. (eds.), International Encyclopedia of the Social & Behevioral Sciences.
Amsterdam: Elsevier.
Benbassa, E. (1997). Histoire des Juifs en France. Paris: Seuil.
Benda, J. et al. (1947). Lesprit europen. Neuchatel: Editions de la Boconnire.
Benedict, R. (1946). The Chrysanthemum and the Sword: Patterns of Japanese Culture. Boston:
Houghton Miin.
Bendix, R. (1978). Kings or People. Berkeley, CA: University of California Press.
Ben-Eliezer, U. (1998). The Making of Israeli Militarism. Bloomington, Indiana: Indiana
University Press.
Benhabib, S. (2002). The Claims of Culture: Equality and Diversity in the Global Era.
Princeton: Princeton University Press.
Benjamin, A. (1989). Translation and the Nature of Philosophy. London: Routledge.
Benjamin, W. (1982). The Task of the Translator. Illuminations. London: Fontana.
Ben-Rafael, E. (1982). The Emergence of Ethnicity: Cultural Groups and Social Conict in
Israel. Westport, Conn.: Greenwood Press.
(1994). Language, Identity and Social Division: The Case of Israel. Oxford: Oxford
University Press/Clarendon.
(1996). Multiculturalism in Sociological Perspective, pp. 133154 in
Baubck, R., Heller, A. and Zolberg, A. (eds.), The challenge of diversityIntegration
and Pluralism in societies of immigration. Aldershot, England: Gower/Avebury and
European Centre Vienna.
(1997). Crisis and Transformation: The Kibbutz at Centurys End. Albany, NY: SUNY.
(1997a). Critical versus non-critical Sociology: An Evaluation, Israel Studies
2(1): 174193.
(2001). Ethnicity, Sociology of in Smelser, N.J. and Baltes, P.B. (eds.),
International Encyclopedia of the Social & Behevioral Sciences. Amsterdam: Elsevier.
(2002). Jewish Identities: Fifty Intellectuals Answer Ben-Gurion. Leiden and Boston:
Brill Academic Publishers.
Ben-Rafael, E. and Sharot. S. (1991). Ethnicity, Religion and Class in Israeli Society.
Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
Ben-Rafael, E. and Brosh, H. (1995). Jews and Arabs in Israel: The cultural convergence of divergent identities, pp. 1834 in Ron Nettler (ed.), Medieval and
Modern Perspectives on Muslim-Jewish Relations. London: Harwood Academic Pubs.
Ben-Rafael, E., Olshtain, E., Geijst, I. (1996). The socio-linguistic insertion of
Russian Jews in Israel, pp. 364388 in Lewin-Espstein, N. et al. (eds.), Russian
Jews in Three ContinentsEmigration and Resettlement. London: Frank Cass.
Bentley, J.H. (1993). Old World Encounters: Cross-Cultural Contacts and Exchanges in PreModern Time. New York: Oxford University Press.
(1998). Hemispheric Integration, 5001500 C.E., Journal of World History
9(2): 237254.
Berkemer, G. (1993). Little Kingdoms in Kalinga. Ideologie, Legitimation und Politik Regionaler
Eliten. Stuttgart: Franz Steiner Verlag.
Berkhof, H. (1947). Kirche und Kaiser. Zurich.
Berman, S. (1997). Civil society and the collapse of the Weimar Republic, World
Politics 49: 401429.
Betzig, L. (1992). Roman polygyny & Roman monogamy, Ethology and Sociobiology
XIII: 30949, 35783.
Bhabha, H. (1994). The Location of Culture. London: Routledge.
Billington, J. (1968). The Icon and the Axe: An Interpretive History of Russian Culture. New
York: Knopf.
Billington, J.H. (1980). Fire in the minds of men: origins of the revolutionary Faith. New
York: Basic Books.
Binns, J. (2002). An Introduction to the Christian Orthodox Churches. Cambridge: Cambridge
University Press.
676
bibliography
Birbnbaum, P. (1992). Les Fous de la Rpiuluique, Histoire Politique des Juifs dEtat. Paris:
Fayard.
Birle, P. (1999). Convergencia entre el Sur y el Este? Sindicalismo y relaciones
laborales en Amrica del Sur y Europa centro-oriental, pp. 249265 in Peter
Hengstenberg, Karl Kohut and Gnther Maihold (eds.), Sociedad civil en Amrica
Latina: representacin de intereses y gobernabilidad. Caracas.
Bloch, M. (1992). Prey into Hunter: The Politics of Religious Experience. Cambridge:
Cambridge University Press.
Blondel, J. (1998). Introduction: The Challenge Facing Liberal Democracy and Political Parties at the Beginning of the 21 st Century, European Review 6: 156160.
Bobbio, N. (1987). The Future of Democracy. Oxford: Polity Press.
(1988). Gramsci and the Concept of Civil Society, pp. 7399 in John
Keane (ed.), Civil society and the state. New European perspectives. London: Verso.
Bonhoeer, D. (1963). The Communion of Saints: A Dogmatic Inquiry into the Sociology of
the Church. Trans. R. Gregor Smith. New York: Harper and Row.
Bordonove, G. (1991). La Tragdie Cathare. Paris: Pygmalion/Grard Watelet.
Boudon R. (1999). Les Formes lmentaires de la vie religieuse: une thorie toujours vivante, Anne sociologique 49(1): 149198.
(2000). tudes sur les sociologues classiques, II. Paris: PUF, Quadrige.
(2001). La rationalit du religieux selon Max Weber, LAnne sociologique
51(1): 950.
(2002). Dclin de la morale? Dclin des valeurs?. Paris, Puf, et Qubec, Nota
Bene, distr. Gallimard.
(2003). Raison, bonnes raisons. Paris: Puf.
Bouretz, P. (2000). La Rpublique et luniversel. Paris: Gallimard (Folio).
Bousetta, H. (2001). Immigration, Post-Immigration Politics and the Political Mobilisation of
Ethnic Minorities. A Comparative Case-Study of Moroccans in Four European Cities.
Dissertation, Katholieke Universiteti Brussel.
Bowersock, G.W. (1986). Architects of Competing Transcendental Visions in Late
Antiquity, pp. 28087 in S.N. Eisenstadt (ed.), The Origins and Diversity of Axial
Age Civilizations. Albany: State University of New York Press.
Bowman, G. (2001). The Violence in Identity, pp. 2546 in Bettina E. Schmidt
and Ingo W. Schrder (eds.), Anthropology of Violence and Conict. London: Routledge.
Brague, R. (1993). Europe, la voie romaine. Paris: ditions Critrion.
(2002). Eccentric Culture: A Theory of Western Civilization, South Bend
Indiana: St. Augustine Press.
Braig, M. (1999). Espacios femeninos y poltica o la poltica como un espacio para
mujeres, pp. 281300 in Peter Hengstenberg, Karl Kohut and Gnther Maihold
(eds.), Sociedad civil en Amrica Latina: representacin de intereses y gobernabilidad. Caracas.
Braudel, F. (1972). The Mediterranean and the Mediterranean World in the Age of Philip II.
New York: Harper & Row.
(1977). Afterthoughts on Material Civilization and Capitalism, tr. Patricia M. Ranum.
Baltimore: John Hopkins University Press.
(1980). On History. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.
(1992). Civilization and capitalism, 15th18th Century. Berkeley: University of
California Press.
(1993). Grammaire des civilisations. Paris: Flammarion.
(1994). A History of Civilizations. London: Penguin Books.
Brehier, L. (1949). Les institutions de lEmpire byzantin. Paris
Breuer, M. (1992). Modernity within tradition: the social history of orthodox Jewry in imperial Germany. Translated by E. Petuchowski. New York: Columbia University
Press.
Brian, E. (1994). La mesure de lEtat. Administrateurs et gomtres au XVIII e sicle. Paris:
Albin Michel.
bibliography
677
Brown, P. (1978). The Making of Late Antiquity. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University
Press.
(1982). Society and the Holy in Late Antiquity. London: Faber and Faber.
(1992). Power and Persuasion in Late Antiquity: Toward a Christian Empire. Madison,
WIS: University of Wisconsin.
Browning, R. (1980). The Byzantine Empire. New York.
Brubaker, R. (1992). Citizenship and Nationhood in France and Germany. Cambridge, MA:
Harvard University Press.
(1996). Nationalism Reframed. Nationalism and the National Question in the New
Europe. Cambridge, UK: Cambridge University Press.
(2002). Citizenship and Nationhood in France and Germany. Cambridge: Harvard
University Press.
(2003). The Return of Assimilation? Changing perspectives on immigration and its sequels in France, Germany and the United States, pp. 3958
in Joppke, C. and Morawska, E. (eds.), Toward Assimilation and Citizenship;
Immigration in Liberal Nation-States. London: Palgrave Macmillan.
Brubaker, R. and Cooper, F. (2000). Beyond Identity, Theory and Society 29: 147.
Brunner, J.S., S.A. Jully and K. Silva (eds.). (1979). PlayIts Role in Development and
Evolution. Harmondsworth: Penguin Books.
Buber, M. (1957). What Is To Be Done?, in Maurice Friedman (ed. and trans.),
Pointing the Way: Collected Essays. Atlantic Highlands, NJ: Humanities Press
International.
(1992). On Intersubjectivity and Cultural Creativity. Ed. S.N. Eisenstadt. Chicago:
University of Chicago Press.
Buckland, W.W. (1963). A Text-Book of Roman Law from Augustus to Justinian 3.
Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
Budde, G. (2003). Das entliche des Privaten. Die Familie als zivilgesellschaftliche
Kerninstitution, pp. 5775 in Arnd Bauerkmper and Manuel Borutta (eds.),
Die Praxis der Zivilgesellschaft. Akteure, Handeln und Strukturen im internationalen Vergleich.
Frankfurt/Main: Campus.
Budick, S. and Iser, W. (eds.). (1996). The Translatibility of Cultures. Stanford: Stanford
University Press.
Burckhardt, J. (1978). Weltgeschichtliche Betrachtungen. Stuttgart: Krner.
Burkert, W. (1983). Homo Necans: The Anthropology of Ancient Greek Sacricial Ritual and
Myth. Westport, Conn.: Greenwood Press.
(1987). Ancient Mystery Cults. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.
(1998). Creation of the Sacred: Tracks of Biology in Early Religions. Cambridge,
MA: Harvard University Press.
Bushkovitch, P. (1992). Religion and Society in Russia: The Sixteenth and Seventeenth Centuries.
New York: Oxford University Press.
Cacciari, M. (1994). Geo-losoa dellEuropa. Milano: Adelphi.
(1997). Arcipelago. Milano: Adelphi.
Caetano, G., T. Moulin and P. Yankelevich (2002). Las democracias bajo la lupa.
Luz roja en Amrica Latina, Puentes (La Plata) 7: 2025.
Caillois, R. (1959). Man and the Sacred. Glencoe, Ill: Free Press.
(1961). Man, Play and Games. New York: The Free Press.
Calhoun, C. (2002). The Class Consciousness of Frequent Travellers: Towards a
Critique of Actually Existing Cosmopolitanism, in Steven Vertovec and Robin
Cohen (eds.), Conceiving Cosmopolitanism. Oxford: Oxford University Press.
Callon, M., Law, J. and Ripp, A. (1986). Mapping the Dynamics of Science and Technology.
London: Macmillan.
Campbell, J. (1971). The Hero with a Thousand Faces. Princeton, NJ: Princeton University
Press.
Canning, J.P. (1988). Introduction: politics, institutions and ideas [c. 1150c. 1450],
678
bibliography
in J.H. Burns (ed.), The Cambridge Medieval political Thought. Cambridge University
Press.
Carens, J.H. (2000). Culture, Citizenship and Community. Oxford: Oxford University
Press.
Caruth, C. (1996). Unclaimed Experience. Trauma, Narrative and History. Baltimore,
MD/London: John Hopkins University Press.
Castoriadis, C. (1991). Philosophy, Politics, Autonomy. Oxford: Oxford University Press.
CBS. (2003). Statistical Abstract of Israel 2003. No. 54. Jerusalem: Central Bureau of
Statistics.
Cerutti, F. and E. Rudolph (eds.). (2001a), A Soul for Europe. On the Political and
Cultural Identity of Europe, vol.1. Peeters, Leuven- Sterling, Virginia.
(2001b), A Soul for Europe, vol. 2. An Essay Collection. Peeters, LeuvenSterling, Virginia.
Chalmers, D. et al. (1997). The New Politics of Inequality in Iberoamerica. Oxford University
Press.
Chambers, S. and Kymlicka, W. (eds.). (2002). Alternative Conceptions of Civil Society.
Princeton: Princeton University Press.
Champion, F. and Hervieu-Lger, D. (ed.). (1990). De lmotion en religion. Renouveaux
et traditions. Paris: Centurion.
Cheah, P. and B. Robbins (eds.). (1998). Cosmopolitics. Minneapolis: University of
Minnesota Press.
Cherry, C. (1970). Gods New Israel. Englewood Clis, N.J.: Prentice-Hall.
Ciggaar, K.N. (1996). Western Travellers to Constantinople. The West and Byzantium,
9621204: Cultural and Political Relations. Leiden: Brill.
Claess, M. (2000). Mithraism, tr. Gaden. Edinburgh: Edinburgh University Press.
Clark, T.N., M.S. Lipset and M. Rempel. (1993). The Declining Political Signicance
of Social Class, International Sociology 8: 293316.
Clark, T.N. and V. Homan-Martinot (eds.). (1998). The New Political Culture. Boulder,
Colo.: Westview.
Clarke, J.J. (1997). Oriental Enlightenment: The Encounter between Asian and Western Thought.
London: Routledge.
Cliord, J. (1992). Traveling Cultures, in Lawrence Grossberg, Cary Nelson and
Paula Treichler (eds.), Cultural Studies. New York: Routledge.
(1997). Routes: Travel and Translation in the Late Twentieth Century. Cambridge,
MA: Harvard University Press.
Cohen, J. (ed.). (1996). For Love of Country. Boston: Beacon Press.
Cohen-Albert, P. (1982). Non-Orthodox Attitudes in NinentheenCentury French
Judaism, pp. 121141 in F. Malino & P. Cohen-Albert (eds.), Essays in Modern
Jewish History. A tribute to Ben Halpern.
Cohn, N. (1961). The Pursuit of the Millennium. Revolutionary messianism in medieval and
Reformation Europe and its bearing on modern totalitarian movements. 2nd ed. New York:
Harper Torchbooks.
Colley, L. (1992). Britons: Forging the Nation, 17071837. Yale: Yale University Press.
Collins, R. (1999). Macrohistory. Essays in Sociology of the Long Run. Stanford: Stanford
University Press.
Connor, W. (1984). The National Question in Marxist-Leninist Theory and Strategy. Princeston:
Princeston University Press.
Cook, J. (1999). Morality and Cultural Dierence. Oxford: Oxford University Press.
Cook, M. (1999). Weber and Islamic Sects, in Toby E. Hu & Wolfgang Schluchter
(eds.), Weber and Islam. New Brunswick, N.J.: Transaction Publishers.
Council for Higher Education. (1994). The System of Higher Education in Israel: Trends
and Developments. Statistical Report. Jerusalem: Planning and Budget Committee.
(Hebrew).
(2003). The Planning and Budgeting Report 28/29 for 2000/2001 and 2001/2002.
bibliography
679
Cowan, J.K., M.B. Dembour and R.A. Wilson (eds.). (2001). Culture and Rights:
Anthropological Perspectives. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
Cracraft, J. (1971). The Church Reform of Peter the Great. Stanford: Stanford University
Press.
Cronin, M. (1996). Translating Ireland: Translation, Languages, Identities. Cork: Cork
University Press.
(1998). Unity in Diversity: Current Trends in Translation Studies. St. Jerome.
Crouch, C. (1999). Social Change in Western Europe. Oxford: Oxford University Press.
Crozier, M., S. Huntington and J. Watanuki. (1975a). The Crisis of Democracy. New
York: New York University Press.
(1975b). The Crisis of Cultural Essentialism, Philosophy and Social Criticism
21(4): 1536.
Curtiss, J.S. (1940). Church and State in Russia: The Last Years of the Empire, 19001917.
New York.
Daedalus (1998), Early Modernities 127(3).
(2000), Multiple Modernities 129(1).
Dahme, H.J. (1993). Georg Simmel und Gustav Schmoller: Berhrungen zwischen
Kathedersozialismus und Soziologie um 1890, Simmel Newsletter 3, No. 1
(Summer).
Dahrendorf, R. (1959). Class and Class Conict in Industrial Society. Stanford: Stanford
University Press.
(1990). Reections on the Revolution in Europe. London: Chatto and Windus.
(2003). Doubts about Pluralism. Paper for the international conference
on Comparing Modern Civilizations, in honor of S.N. Eisenstadt, organized
by the International Institute of Sociology and the Israel Academy of Sciences
and Humanties. Jerusalem, November 2003.
Danet, B. (1989). Pulling Strings: Biculturalism in Israeli Bureaucracy. Albany, NY: SUNY
Press.
DAppolonia, A.C. (2002). European Nationalism and European Union, pp.
171190 in A. Pagden (ed.), The Idea of Europe. Cambridge University Press.
Davids, A. (ed.). (1995). The Empress Theophano: Byzantium and the West at the Turn of
the First Millennium. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
Davie, G. and D. Hervieu-Lger. (1994). Identits religieuses en Europe. Paris: La
Dcouverte.
Davies, N. (1997). Europe: a History. London: Pimlico.
Delano, M. and H. Traslavina. (1989). La herencia de los Chicago Boys. Santiago:
Ornitorrinco.
Delanty, G. (1995a). Inventing Europe. Idea, Identity, Reality. London: Macmillan.
(1995b). The Limits and Possibility of a European Identity: A Critique of
(Un)Translatibility, pp. 293305 in Budick, S. and Iser, W. (eds.), The Translatibility
of Cultures. Stanford: Stanford University Press.
(1996a). The Frontier and Identities of Exclusion in European History,
History of European Ideas 22(2): 93103.
(1996b). The Resonance of Mitteleuropa: A Habsburg Myth or AntiPolitics?, Theory, Culture and Society 14(4): 93108.
(1997). Habermas and Occidental Rationalism: The Politics of Identity,
Social Learning and the Cultural Limits of Moral Universalism, Sociological
Theory 15 (3): 3059.
(1998). Social Theory and European Transformation. Is there a European
Society?, Sociological Research Online 3,1.
Delgado Gutirrez, A. (2003a). Expansin de ciudadana y construccin ciudades.
International colloquium on Bogot, sistema politico y cultura democrtica.
Bogot, 2931 July.
DellaPergola, S. (2004). Demography in Israel at the Dawn of the Twenty-First
680
bibliography
Century, pp. 2044 in Uzi Rebhun and Chaim I. Waxman (eds.), Jews in
Israel: Contemporary Social and Cultural Patterns. Hanover, NH: Brandies University
Press, published by University Press of New England.
Deutsch, K. (1963a). Social Mobilization and Political Development, pp. 582603
in Eckstein, Harry and David E. Apter, Comparative Politics: A Reader. New York:
The Free Press.
(1963b). Cracks in the Monolith: Possibilities and Patterns of Disintegration
in Totalitarian Systems, pp. 497507 in Eckstein, Harry and David E. Apter,
Comparative Politics: A Reader. New York: The Free Press.
Diederichs, E., H. Plessner, and A. Augen (eds.). 1982. Aspekte einder Philosophischen
Anthropologie. Stuttgart: Ph. Reclam.
Dingsdale, A. (2002). Mapping Modernities: Geographies of Central and Eastern Europe,
19202000. London: Routledge.
Dirlik, A. (2003). Global Modernity? Modernity in an Age of Global Capitalism,
in B. Hesse (ed.), Disaporas, Entanglements, Transruptions. London: Zed Books.
Don-Yehiya, E. and B. Susser. (1999). Democracy versus Nationalism: Israel as
an Exceptional Case. Democratic Culture 1: 921. (Hebrew).
Douglas, M. (1966). Purity and Danger. London: Penguin.
Dubet, F. (2003). Le dclin de linstitution. Paris: Seuil.
Dubiel, H. (1999). Niemand ist frei von der Geschichte. Der Nationalsozialismus in den Debatten
des deutschen Bundestages. Mnchen: Hanser.
Dumont, L. (1977). Homo HierarchicusLe Systeme des Castes et ses Implications. Paris:
Gallimard.
(1991). Lidologie allemande. Paris, Gallimard.
Durkheim, E. (1960 [1893]). De la division du travail social. Paris: Puf.
(1969). Leons de sociologie. Paris: Presses Universitaires de France.
(1933, 1964, 1984, [1893]). The Division of Labor in Society. New York: Free
Press.
Durkheim, E. and Mauss, M. (1971) [1913]. Note on the notion of Civilization,
Social Research 38(1): 808813.
Duroselle, J.B. (1990). LEurope: histoire de ses peuples. Paris: Perrin.
Duvernoy, J. (1976). Le catharisme: la religion des cathares. Toulouse: Privat.
(1994). Cathares, Vaudois et Bguins, dissidents du pays dOc. Toulouse: Privat.
Dvornik, F. (1926). Les Slaves, Byzance et Rome. Paris.
Dworkin, R. (2003). Terror & the Attack on Civil Liberties, The New York Review
of Books, November 6: 3741.
Easwaran, E. (1999). Nonviolent Soldier of Islam: Badshah Khan, a Man to Match His
Mountains. Tomales, CA: Nilgiri Press.
Eder, K. and Giesen, B. (eds.). (2001). European Citizenship between National Legacies
and Postnational Projects. Oxford: Oxford university Press.
Eickelman, D. and Salvatore, A. (2002). The Public Sphere and Muslim Societies,
Arch. Europ. Sociol. XLIII (1): 92115.
Eisenstadt, S.N. (1954). The Absorption of Immigrants. London: Routledge & Kegan Paul.
(1956). From Generation to Generation: Age Groups and Social Structure. Glencoe,
IL: The Free Press.
(1963). The Political Systems of Empires. New York: Free Press.
(1966). Modernization: Protest and Change. Englewood Clis: Prentice-Hall.
(1973). Tradition, Change, and Modernity. New York: John Wiley & Sons.
(1978). Revolution and the Transformation of Societies: A Comparative Study in
Civilizations. New York: Free Press.
(1982). The Axial Age: The Emergence of Transcendental Visions and the
Rise of Clerics, European Journal of Sociology 23(2): 294314.
(ed.). (1983). The Origins and Diversity of Axial Civilizations. Albany, NY: SUNY
Press.
bibliography
681
682
bibliography
(eds.), The Public Sphere in Muslim Societies. Albany: State University of New York
Press.
(2002b). Cultural Programs, the Construction of Collective Identity and
the Continual Reconstruction of Primordiality, pp. 3387 in Malesevic, Sinisa
and Mark Haugaard (eds.), Making Sense of Collectivity: Ethnicity, Nationalism and
Globalization. London: Pluto.
(2002c). The Civilizations of the Americas: The Crystallizations of Distinct
Modernities, Comparative Sociology 1(1): 4361.
(2002d). The First Multiple Modernities: Collective Identities, Public Spheres
and Political Order in the Americas, pp. 728 in L. Roniger and C. Waisman
(eds.), Globality and Multiple Modernities. Brighton: Sussex Academic Press.
(2003a). Comparative Civilizations and Multiple Modernities. Vols 1 and 2. Leiden:
Brill Academic Publishers.
(2003b). The Construction of Collective Identities and the Continual
Reconstruction of Primordiality and SacralitySome Analytical and Comparative
Indications, pp. 75134 in S.N. Eisenstadt, Comparative Civilizations and Multiple
Modernities. Leiden: Brill Academic Publishers.
Eisenstadt, S.N. with M. Curelaru. (1976). The Form of SociologyParadigms and Crises.
New York: John Wiley & Sons.
Eisenstadt, S.N. and Giesen, B. (1995). The Construction of Collective Identity,
European Journal of Sociology 36: 72102.
Eisenstadt, S.N. and H. Hartman. (1997) Historical Experience, Cultural Traditions,
State Formation and Political Dynamics in India and Europe, pp. 2755 in
Doornbos, Martin and Sudipta Kaviraj (eds.), Dynamics of State Formation: India
and Europe Compared. New Delhi: Sage.
Eisenstadt, S.N., R. Kahane and D. Shulman (eds.). (1984). Orthodoxy, Heterodoxy and
Dissent in India. Berlin: Mouton Publishers.
Eisenstadt, S.N., Schluchter, W. and Wittrock, B. (eds.). (2001). Public Spheres and
Collective Identities. New Brunswick, N.J.: Transaction Publishers.
Elias, N. (19781982). The Civilizing Process. New York: Urizen Books.
(1982). The Civilizing Process, 2 vols., Oxford: Basil Blackwell.
(1983). The Court Society. Oxford: Blackwell.
[1939] (1994). The Civilizing Process. Oxford: Blackwell.
Eliot, T.S. (1948). Notes Toward the Denition of Culture. London: Faber & Faber.
Emeri C. and Zylberberg, J. (eds.). (1991). Citoyennet et nationalit, perspectives en France
et au Qubec. Paris: PUF.
Engelstad, F. and Kalleberg, R. (eds.) (1999). Social Time and Social Change: Historical
Aspects in the Social Sciences. Oslo: Scandinavian University Press.
Engelstein, L. (2001). Holy Russia in Modern Times: An Essay on Orthodoxy and
Cultural Change, Past and Present 173.
Engineer, A.A. (ed.) (1991). Communal Riots in Post-Independence India. New Delhi:
Sangam.
Entzinger, H. (2003a). Les jeunes musulmans dun Rotterdam pluriculturel; une
vision maigre de la citoyennet, pp. 101110 in Michel Wieviorka (ed.),
Lavenir de lislam en France et en Europe. Paris: Balland.
(2003b). The Rise and Fall of Multiculturalism: The Case of the Netherlands,
pp. 5986 in Joppke, C. and Morawska, E. (eds.), Toward Assimilation and
Citizenship; Immigration in Liberal Nation-States. London: Palgrave Macmillan.
Erikson, K. (1966). Wayward Puritans. New York: Wiley.
Espinosa, M.E. (2003). Las siete plagas capitales. El Universal (Caracas, Venezuela),
25 July.
Etzioni, A. (1961). A Comparative Analysis of Complex Organizations. Glencoe: The Free
Press.
(1993). The Spirit of Community: The Reinvention of American Society. New York:
Touchstone.
bibliography
683
Everson, M.C. and U.K. Preuss. (1995). Concepts, Foundations and Limits of European
Citizenship. Bremen: Zentrum fr Europaische Rechtspolitik.
Every, G. (1947). The Byzantine Patriarchate, 4511204. London.
Evtuhov, C. (1991). The Church in the Russian Revolution: Arguments For and
Against Restoring the Patriarchate at the Church Council of 19171918, Slavic
Review 50(3): 497511.
Faist, T. (2000). The Volume and Dynamics of International Migration and Transnational
Social Spaces. Oxford: Clarendon.
Farago, U. (1989). The Jewish identity of Israeli youth, 19651985, Yahadut Zmanenu:
Contemporary Jewry, Jerusalem, vol. 5: 259285.
Faubion, J.D. (1993). Modern Greek Lessons. A Primer in Historical Constructivism. Princeton:
Princeton University Press.
Featherstone, M., Lash, S. and Robertson, R. (eds.). (1995). Global Modernities. London:
Sage.
Febvre, L. (1973). Civilisation: Evolution of a Word and a Group of Ideas, pp.
219257 in Febvre, L., A New Kind of History and other Essays. New York: Harper
& Row.
Fedotov, G.P. (1946). The Russian Religious Mind. Cambridge, Mass.
Feitlowitz, M. (1998). A Lexicon of Terror. Argentina and the Legacies of Torture. Oxford:
Oxford University Press.
Ferguson, A. [1767] (1995). An Essay on the History of Civil Society. Cambridge:
Cambridge University Press.
Ferguson, J. (1999). Expectations of Modernity. Berkeley: University of California Press.
Feuerwerker, D. (1976). LEmancipation des Juiifs en France, coll. Histoire de lHumanit.
Paris: Albin Michel.
Finley, M.I. (1983). Politics in the Ancient World. Cambridge: Cambridge University
Press.
Florovskii, G. (1937). Puti russkogo bogosloviia. Paris.
Florovsky, G. (1974). Christianity and Culture. Belmont, MA.: Nordland.
Fontaine Aldunate, A. (1988). Los economistas y el presidente Pinochet. Santiago: Zig-Zag.
Fontana, J. (1994). Europa ante el espejo. Barcelona: Editorial Critica.
Fotopoulos, T. (2002). Vers une dmocratie gnrale. Une dmocratie directe, conomique,
cologique et sociale. Paris: Seuil.
Foucault, M. (1965). Madness and Civilization: A History of Insanity in the Age of Reason.
New York: Pantheon Books.
(1966). Les Mots et Les Choses. Une archologie des sciences humaines. Paris:
Gallimard.
(1973). The Birth of the Clinic: An Archaeology of Medical Perception. New York:
Vintage Books.
(1975). Surveiller et Punir: Naissance de la Prison. Paris: Gallimard.
(1988). Technologies of the Self: A Seminar with Michel Foucault. Amherst: University
of Massachussetts Press.
Fowler, W.W. (1922). The Religious Experience of the Roman People from the Earliest Times
to the Age of Augustus. London: Macmillan.
Fox, C., Porter, R, and Wokler, R. (eds.). (1995). Inventing Human Science: Eighteenth
Century Domains. Berkeley, CA: University of California Press.
Frank, A.G. (1967). Capitalism and Underdevelopment in Latin America. New York: Monthly
Review Press.
Freedom House. (2003). Freedom House Country Ratings. http://www.freedomhouse.org.
Freeze, G.L. (1977). The Russian Levites: Parish Clergy in the Eighteenth Century. Cambridge,
Mass.: Harvard University Press.
(1983). The Parish Clergy in Nineteenth-Century Russia: Crisis, Reform, CounterReform. Princeton: Princeton University Press.
(1985). Handmaiden of the State? The Church in Imperial Russia Reconsidered, Journal of Ecclesiastical History 36(1).
684
bibliography
bibliography
685
686
bibliography
Gross, J.T. (2001). Neighbours: The Destruction of the Jewish Community in Jedwabne, Poland.
Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press.
Gundara J. and S. Jacobs (eds.). (1998). Interculturalism in Europe: Cultural Diversity and
Social Policy in the European Union. London: Aldershot.
Gundelach, P. (1984). Social Transformations and New Forms of Voluntary
Associations, Social Science Information 23: 10491081.
Gutmann, A. (2003). Identity in Democracy. Princeton: Princeton University Press.
Habermas, J. (1985). Der philosophische Diskurs der Moderne. Frankfurt: Suhrkamp.
(1987). The Philosophical Discourse of Modernity. Cambridge: Polity Press.
(1990). What does socialism mean today? The rectifying revolution and
the need for new thinking on the left, New Left Review, No. 183, SeptemberOctober.
(1994). Citizenship and National Identity, in Steenbergen, B. van (ed.),
The Condition of Citizenship. London: Sage.
(1995). Struggles for Recognition in the Democratic Constitutional State,
pp. 107148 in Charles Taylor & Amy Gutmann (eds.), Multiculturalism. Princeton:
Princeton University Press.
(2001). Glauben und Wissen. Frankfurt: Surhkamp.
Halbfass, W. (1988). India and Europe: An Essay in Understanding. New York: State
University of New York Press.
Hamburger, E. (1969). One Hundred Years of Emancipation, Leo Baek Year Book
XIV: 366.
Handelman, D. and D. Shulman. (1997). God Inside Out: Sivas Game of Dice. New
York: Oxford University Press.
Hanegbi, M. (2004). We Have Become Like Sodom. Jerusalem: Keter. (Hebrew).
Hann, C. and Dunn, E. (1996). Civil Society: Challenging Western Models. London:
Routledge.
Hannerz, U. (1987). The World in Creolisation, Africa 57: 546559.
(1990). Cosmopolitans and Locals in World Culture, in Mike Featherstone
(ed.), Global Culture. London: Sage.
(1992). Cultural Complexity. New York: Columbia University Press.
(1996). Transnational Connections. Culture, People, Places. London: Routledge.
(1997). Fluxos, fronteiras, hbridos: palavras-chave da antropologia transnacional, Mana (Rio de Janeiro), 3(1): 739.
(2001). Center-Periphery Relationships, in Smelser, N.J. and Baltes, P.B.
(eds.), International Encyclopedia of the Social & Behevioral Sciences (Vol. 3). Amsterdam:
Elsevier.
(Forthcoming). Cosmopolitanism, in Joan Vincent and Daniel Nugent
(eds.), Companion to the Anthropology of Politics. Oxford: Blackwell.
Hansen, T.B. (1999). The Saron Wave: Hindu Nationalism and Democracy in Modern India.
Princeton: Princeton University Press.
Harris, W.V. (1976). War and Imperialism in Republican Rome 32770 B.C. Oxford:
Clarendon Press.
Hartmann, A. (1975). an-Nsir li-Din Allh (11801225). Politik, Religion, Kultur in der
spten 'Abbsidenzeit. Berlin: Walter de Gruyter.
(1993). al-Nsir li-Din Allh, Encyclopedia of Islam, Leiden: E.J. Brill, 7:
9961003.
Hartz, L. (1964). The Founding of New Societies. New York: Brace and World.
Hayek, F. von (19731979), Law, legislation and liberty. London: Routledge and Kegan
Paul.
Heer, F. (1962) [1961]. The Medieval World. New York: Mentor/New American Library.
Heesterman, J. (1971). Kautalya and the Ancient Indian State, Wiener Zeitschrift
fuer die Kunde Sued- und Ostasiens 15: 522.
(1979). Power and Authority in Indian Tradition, pp. 6085 in R.J. Moore
(ed.), Tradition and Politics in South Asia. New Delhi: Vikas.
bibliography
687
688
bibliography
bibliography
689
690
bibliography
bibliography
691
Leibowicz, J. (1976). Iahadout, am Israel ve-medinat Israel ( Judaism, the People of Israel
and the State of Israel). Jerusalem: Schocken.
Lenski, G. (1994). Social Taxonomies: Mapping the Social Universe, Annual Review
of Sociology 20: 126.
Leon, N. (2003). Mizrakhi ultra-Orthodox. Tel-Aviv: Department of Sociology, TelAviv University, PhD thesis. (Hebrew).
Lepenies, W. (1988). Between Literature and Science: The Rise of Sociology. Cambridge:
Cambridge University Press.
Lerner, D. (1958). The Passing of Traditional Society: Modernizing the Middle East. Glencoe,
Ill.: Free Press.
Levine, D.N. (1995). Visions of the Sociological Tradition. Chicago: University of Chicago
Press.
(2004). The Continuing Challenge of Webers Theory of Rational Action,
in Charles Camic and Philip Gorski (eds.), Max Weber at the Millennium: Economy
and Society for the 21st Century. Stanford: Stanford University Press.
Levi-Strauss, C. (1958). Anthropologie Structurale. Paris: Plon.
(1961). Race et Histoire. Paris.
Levy, D. and Y. Weiss (eds.). (2002). Challenging Ethnic Citizenship: German and Israeli
Perspectives on Immigration. New York: Berghahn Books.
Levy, Jr. M.J. (1966). Modernization and Structures of Societies: A Setting for International
Aairs, Vol. I. Princeton: Princeton University Press.
Levy, S. (1996). Values and Jewishness of Israeli Youth. Jerusalem: Guttman Institute.
Levy, S., H. Levinsohn and E. Katz. (2002). A Portrait of Israeli Jewry: Beliefs, Observances,
and Values among Israeli Jews 2000. Highlights from an In-Depth Study Conducted
by the Guttman Center of the Israel Democracy Institute for the AVI CHAI
Foundation. Jerusalem: Israel Democracy Institute.
Levy, Y. (2003). The Other Army of Israel: Materialist Militarism in Israel. Tel Aviv:
Yediot Aharonot. (Hebrew).
Leyer, M.A. (1966). Great Debate on Antisemitism; Jewish Reaction to New Hostility
in Germany 18791881, Leo Baek Year Book XI: 137170.
Lichtenstein, A. (1981). The Seven Laws of Noah. New York: The Rabbi Jacob Joseph
School Press.
Liebeschutz, J.H.W. (1979). Continuity and Change in Roman Religion. Oxford: Clarendon
Press.
Liebman, C.S. (1993). Religion and Democracy in Israel, pp. 273292 in Ehud
Sprinzak and Larry Diamond (eds.), Israeli Democracy under Stress. Boulder, CO:
Lynne Rienner Publishers.
Liebman, C.S. and S.M. Cohen. (1990). Two Worlds of Judaism: Israeli and American
Experiences. New Haven, CT: Yale University Press.
Liebman, C.S. & Katz, E. (eds.). (1997). The Jewishness of Israelis: Responses to the
Guttman Report. New York: SUNY Press.
Lifton, R.J. (1968). Protean Man, Partisan Review 35(1): 1327.
Lijphart, A. (1975). The Politics of Accommodation. Pluralism and Democracy in the Netherlands.
Berkeley: University of California Press.
Linder, D.M. and J. Scheid. (1993). Quand croire cest faire: le problme de la
croyance dans la Rome ancienne, Archives de sciences sociales des religions LXXXI: 54.
Linz, J.L. and A. Stepan. (1996). Problems of Democratic Transition and Consolidation:
Southern Europe, South America and Post-Communist Europe. Baltimore, MD: Johns
Hopkins University Press.
Lipset, S.M and S. Rokkan. (1967). Cleavage Structures, Party Systems, and Voter
Alignments: An Introduction, pp. 164 in S.M. Lipset and S. Rokkan (eds), Party
Systems and Voter Alignments: Cross-National Perspectives. New York: The Free Press.
Lissak, M. (2001). The Security Ethos and the Myth of Israel as a Militaristic
Society, Democratic Culture 45: 187211. (Hebrew).
692
bibliography
Lissak, M., U. Almagor, Cohen E. (eds.). (1985). Comparative Social Dynamics: Essays
in Honor of S.N. Eisenstadt. Perseus Books.
Luhmann, N. (1982). The Dierentiation of Society. New York: Columbia University Press.
(1990). The World Society as a Social System, in Essays in Self-Reference.
New York: Columbia University Press.
Lukacs, G. (1971 [1924]). History and Class Consciousness. Cambridge: MIT Press.
Lukes, S. (1998). Foreword, in E. Gellner, Language and Solitude. Wittgenstein, Malinowski
and the Habsburg Dilemma. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
Lustick, I. (1996). To Build and to Be Built By: Israel and the Hidden Logic of
the Iron Wall, Israel Studies 1(1): 196223.
Machonin, P. (2000). Modernization Theory and the Czech Experience, pp.
103226 in L Mloch, P. Machonin and M. Sojka (eds.), Economic and Social
Change in Czech Society after 1989/an alternative view. Prague: the Karolineum Press.
Macintyre, A. (1988). Tradition and Translation, in Whose Rationaity? Which
Rationality? London: Duckworth.
MacMullen, R. (1981). Paganism in the Roman Empire. New Haven: Yale University
Press.
Mahjub, M.J. (1971/1350). Introduction to Vaez-e Kshe, Moll Hosayn, Fotovvatnmaye Soltni. Tehran: Bonyd-e Farhang-e Irn.
Mair, P. (1998). Representation and Participation in the Changing World of Politics,
European Review 6: 161174.
Makdisi, G. (1981). The Rise of Colleges; Institutions of Learning in Islam and the West.
Edinburgh: Edinburgh University Press.
(1990). Magisterium and Academic Freedom in Classical Islam and Medieval
Christianity, in N. Heer (ed.), Islamic Law and Jurisprudence. Seattle: Washington
University Press.
Manent, P. (1994) An Intellectual History of Liberalism, Princeton, N.J.: Princeton
University Press.
(1998). Modern Liberty and Its Discontents: Lanham: Rowman and Littleed
Publishers.
Marriott, M. (2003). Varna and Jati, in Gene R. Thursby and Sushil Mittal (eds.),
The Hindu World. London: Routledge.
Marrus, M.R. (1971). Les Juifs de France lpoque de lAaire Dreyfus. Paris
Marshall, T.H. (1964). Class, Citizenship and Social Development. Garden City, New
York: Doubleday.
Martinelli, A. (1998). La modernizzazione. Bari-Roma: Laterza.
(2002). Globalization, Democratic Global Governance and the European
Union, The Tocqueville Review 1.
(2003). The European and the North-American Model of Society (unpublished paper).
(forthcoming). Modernization and Globalization. Rethinking the Project of Modernity.
Sage: London.
Marx, A.W. (2003). Faith in Nation: Exclusionary Origins of Nationalism. Oxford: Oxford
University Press.
Marx, K. and F. Engels. (1988). Manifesto of the Communist Party. New Delhi: Peoples
Publishing House.
Matsuda, T. (ed.). (2001). The Age of Creolization in the Pacic. Hiroshima: Keisuisha.
Mayer, E. (1976). Evolution and the Diversity of Life. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University
Press.
Mazlish, B. (2001). Civilization in a Historical and Global Perspective, International
Sociology 16(3): 293300.
McKean, L. (1966). Divine Enterprise, Gurus and The Hindu Nationalist Movement. Chicago:
University of Chicago Press.
McNeill, W.H. (1991). The Rise of the West: A History of the Human Community. Chicago:
The University of Chicago Press.
(1999). A World History. New York: Oxford University Press.
bibliography
693
(2000). A Short History of Humanity, The New York Review of Books XLVII
(11): 911.
Meerson, M.A. (1988). The Doctrinal Foundation of Orthodoxy, in P. Ramet
(ed.), Eastern Christianity and Politics in the Twentieth Century. Durham and London:
Duke University Press.
Melucci, A. (1989). Nomads of the Present. London: Hutchinson Radius.
(1996). The Playing Self: Person and Meaning in the Planetary Society. Cambridge:
Cambridge University Press.
Mendes-Flohr, P. (1989). From Mysticism to Dialogue: Martin Bubers Transformation of
German Social Thought. Detroit, MI: Wayne State University Press.
Mendras, H. (1997). LEurope des Europens. Paris: Gallimard.
Merton, R.K. (1957). Social Theory and Social Structure. Glencoe: The Free Press.
Meyendor, J. (1982). The Byzantine Legacy in the Orthodox Church. New York: St.
Vladimirs Seminary Press.
Meyer, J.W., J. Boli and G.M. Thomas. (1987). Ontology and Rationalization in
the Western Cultural Account, pp. 1238 in G.M. Thomas, J.W. Meyer, F.O.
Ramirez and J. Boli (eds.), Institutional Structure: Constituting State, Society and the
Individual. Newbury Park: Sage Publications.
Meyer, J.W., J. Boli, G.M. Thomas and F.O. Ramirez. (1997). World Society and
the Nation State, American Journal of Sociology 103: 144182.
Meyer J.W. and R.L. Jepperson. (2000). The Actors of Modern Society: The
Cultural Construction of Social Agency, Sociological Theory 18: 100120.
Michalowski, I. (2004). An Overview on Introduction Programmes for Immigrants in Seven
European Member States. Den Haag: Adviescommissie voor Vreemdelingenzaken.
Mikkeli, H. (1998) Europe as an Idea and as an Identity. Basingstoke: Palgrave Publishers.
Miles, M.A., E.J. Feulner and M.A OGrady. (2004). 2004 Index of Economic Freedom:
Establishing the Link Between Economic Freedom and Prosperity. Washington, DC: The
Heritage Foundation. http://www.heritage.org/research/features/index/downloads.html
Miles, R. (1989). Racism. London: Routledge.
Miller, D. (2000). Citizenship and National Identity. Cambridge: Polity Press.
Miller, P. (1956). Errand into the Wilderness. Cambridge: Harvard University Press.
(1965). The Life of the Mind in America. New York: Harcourt Brace.
(1967). Natures Nation. Cambridge: Harvard University Press.
Mittleman, A.L. (1996). The Politics of Torah: The Jewish Political Tradition and the
Founding of Agudat Israel. Albany: State University of New York Press.
Mitzman, A. (1970). The Iron Cage: An Historical Interpretation of Max Weber. New York:
Knopf.
Mockus, A. and J. Corzo. (2003). Dos caras de la convivencia: cumplir acuerdos
y normas y no usar ni sufrir violencia. International colloquium on Bogot,
sistema politico y cultura democrtica. Bogot, 2931 July.
Momigliano, A. (1984). The Theological Eorts of the Roman Upper Classes in
the First Century BC, Classical Philology LXXIX: 199211.
Mongardini, C. (ed.). (2001). La nascita di una coscienza europea. Roma: Bulzoni.
Monin, N. (2003). The European Union and Israel: Present Situation 2003. Jerusalem:
Ministry of Treasury. (Hebrew).
Moore, G.E. (1903). Principia ethica. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
Morgan, E. (1958). The Puritan Dilemma. Boston: Little, Brown, and Company.
Morin, E. (1987). Penser lEurope. Paris: Gallimard.
Morris, I. (1975). The Nobility of Failure. Tragic Heroes in the History of Japan. London:
Secker and Warburg.
Mottahedeh, R.P. (1997). The Transmission of Learning: The Role of the Islamic
Northeast, pp. 6572 in N. Grandin & M. Gaborieau (eds.), MADRASA. La
Transmission du savior dans le monde musulman. Paris: Arguments.
Motzkin, G. (1992). Time and Transcendence. Dordrecht: Kluwer.
694
bibliography
bibliography
695
Ogburn, W.F. (1964). On Culture and Social Change: Selected Papers. Chicago: Chicago
University Press.
Oommen, T.K. (1992). Restructuring Development Through Technological Pluralism,
International Sociology 7(2): 13139.
(1997). Citizenship, Nationality and Ethnicity: Reconciling Competing Identities.
Cambridge: Polity Press.
(2000). Changing Modes of Conceptualizing the World: Implications for
Social Research, pp. 153170 in P.N. Mukherji (ed.), Methodology in Social
Research: Dilemmas and Perspectives. New Delhi: Sage Publications.
(2001). Multiple Modernities and the rise of New Social Movements: The
case of India, Indian Social Science Review 3(1): 116.
(2002). Pluralism, Equality and Identity: Comparative Studies. New Delhi: Oxford
University Press.
Oren, A., N. Lewin-Epstein and E. Yaar. (2003). Jewish Identity, Religious Belief
and Observance of Tradition. Research Report, pp. 95122 in Judaism as a
Culture: A Decade since Shenhar Committee. Documents for Consideration2003. Lucerne:
Posen Foundation. (Hebrew).
Oron, A. (1993). Zehout iehoudit israelit (The Jewish Israeli identity). Tel-Aviv: Sifriat
Poalim.
Orr, A. (1994). Israel: Politics, Myths and Identity Crises. London: Pluto Press.
Osterberg, D. (1988). Metasociology. An Inquiry into The Origins and Validity of Social
Thought. Oslo: Norwegian University Press.
Ostrogorsky, G. (1940). Geschichte des byzantinischen Staates. Munchen.
Oszlak, O. (2000). Interview in Buenos Aires, 5 September.
Outb, S. (1980). Milestones. Beirut: The Holy Koran Publishing House.
Pagden, A. (2002). Europe: Conceptualizing a Continent, pp. 3354 in A. Pagden
(ed.), The Idea of Europe. Cambridge University Press.
Pandey, G. (1990). The Construction of Communalism in Colonial North India. New Delhi:
Oxford University Press.
Papadakis, A. (1988). The Historical Tradition of Church-State Relations under
Orthodoxy, in P. Ramet (ed.), Eastern Christianity and Politics in the Twentieth
Century. Durham and London: Duke University Press.
Parekh, B. (2000). Rethinking Multiculturalism. Cultural Diversity and Political Theory.
Houndmills: MacMillan.
Parkin, F. (1979). Marxism and Class Theory: A Bourgeois Critique. London: Tavistock.
Parsons, T. (1951). The Social System. New York: Free Press.
(1971). The System of Modern Societies. Ingelwood Clis, N.J.: Prentice Hall.
(1993). Talcott Parsons on National Socialism. Ed. Uta Gerhardt. New York:
Aldine de Gruyter.
(In press). The American Societal Community. Paradigm Publishers.
et al. (eds.). (1962). Theories of Society. Foundations of Modern Sociological Theory,
III. Glencoe: The Free Press.
Pascal, P. (1976). Religion of the Russian People, trans. R. Williams. New York: Crestwood.
Paul, J.-P. (ed.). (1996). Europe and its Citizens. Helsinki: Edita.
Pelikan, J. (1977). The Spirit of Eastern Christendom (6001700). Chicago: University
of Chicago Press.
Pennington, K. (1988). Law, legislative authority and theories of government,
11501300, in J.H. Burns (ed.), The Cambridge Medieval political Thought. Cambridge:
Cambridge University Press.
Petrunicheva, Z.N. (1985). Gurazada Apparao. Moscow: Uzdatelstvo Nauka.
Phalet, K., C. Van Lotringen and H. Entzinger. (2000). Islam in de multiculturele
samenleving. Opvattingen van jongeren in Rotterdam. Utrecht: ERCOMER.
Pharr, S.J. and R.D. Putnam (2000a). Culture or Performance?, pp. 5273 in
S.J. Pharr and R.D. Putnam (eds.). Disaected Democracies. London: Fontana.
696
bibliography
bibliography
697
pp. 190207 in Galit Hasan-Rokem and D. Shulman (eds.), Untying the Knot:
On Riddles and Other Enigmatic Modes. New York: Oxford University Press.
(2003). Hibiscus on the Lake. Twentieth-Century Telugu Poetry from India. Madison:
University of Wisconsin Press.
Rao, N., Velcheru, D. Shulman, and S. Subrahmanyam. (1992). Symbols of Substance:
Court and State in Nayaka-Period Tamil Nadu. Delhi: Oxford University Press.
Rao, N., Velcheru, D. Shulman, and S. Subrahmanyam. (2001). Textures of Time.
Writing History in South India 16001800. Delhi: Permanent Black.
Rappaport, R.A. (1999). Ritual and Religion in the Making of Humanity. Cambridge:
Cambridge University Press.
Rattner, A. and G. Fishman. (1998). Justice for All? Jews and Arabs in the Israeli Criminal
Justice System. Westport, CT: Praeger.
Rauer, V. (2004). Geste der Schuld. Die mediale Rezeption von Willy Brandts
Kniefall in den Neunziger Jahren, in Giesen, B. and Schneider, C., Ttertrauma.
Konstanz: Univeristtsverlag Konstanz.
Rvandi, M. 'Ali b. Sulaymn. (1921). Rhat-us-sudur, M. Eqbl (ed.). Leiden: E.J.
Brill.
Redeld, R. (1957). The Primitive World and its Transformation. Ithaca, NY: Cornell.
Reese-Schaefer, W. (ed.). (1999). Identitat und Interesse. Der Diskurs der Identitatsforschung.
Opladen: Leske und Budrich.
Restrepo, G., J. Eduardo Jaramillo and L.G. Arango (eds.). Cultura, poltica y modernidad. Bogot: CES/Universidad Nacional.
Ricarz, M. (1975). Jewish Social Mobility in Germany during the Time of Emacipation (17901871), Leo Baek Year Book XX: 6977.
Ricoeur, P. (1996). Oneself as Another. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.
Riedel, M. (1975). Gesellschaft, brgerliche, pp. 719800 in Otto Brunner et al.
(eds.), Geschichtliche Grundbegrie, vol. 2. Stuttgart.
Rie, P. (1968). Psychological man, in The Triumph of the Therapeutic: Uses of Faith
after Freud. New York: Harper and Row.
Riesman, D. (1950). The Lonely Crowd. New Haven: Yale University Press.
Robertson, R. (1992). Globalization: Social Theory and Global Culture. London: Sage.
(1995). Glocalization: Time-Space and Homogeneity-Heterogeneity, pp.
2544 in Featherstone, M., Lash, S. and Robertson, R. (eds.), Global Modernities.
London: Sage.
Robinson, F. (1999). Secularization, Weber and Islam, in T.E. Hu and W.
Schluchter, Weber and Islam. New Brunswick, N.J.: Transaction Publishers.
Rojas de Ferro, M.C. (1998). Civilizacin y violencia: la lucha por la representacin
durante el siglo XIX en Colombia, pp. 217246 in Gabriel Restrepo et al.
(eds.), Cultura, poltica y modernidad. Bogot: CES/Universidad Nacional.
Rokkan, S. (1970). Citizens, Elections, Parties. Oslo: Universitetsforlaget.
(1975). Dimensions of state formation and nation-building: a possible paradigm for research on variations within Europe, in C. Tilly (ed.), The Formation
of National States in Western Europe. Princeton: Princeton University Press.
Roniger, L. (1995). Globalization as Cultural Vision, Canadian Review of Sociology
and Anthropology 32(3): 259285.
(1999). Individualism among the Jewish Public in Israel of the 1990s, pp.
110127 in A. Bishara (ed.), Between I and We: The Construction of Identities and
Israeli Idnetity. Jerusalem: The Van Leer Jerusalem Institute. (Hebrew).
(2002). Global Immersion: Iberoamerica and its Multiple Modernities, pp.
79105 in L. Roniger and C. Waisman (eds.), Globality and Multiple Modernities.
Comparative North American and Latin American Perspectives. Brighton: Sussex Academic
Press.
Roniger, L. and M. Faige. (1992). From Pioneer to Frier: The Changing Models
of Generalized Exchange in Israel, Archives Europennes de Sociology 33(2): 280307.
698
bibliography
Roniger, L. and T. Herzog. (2000). The Collective and the Public in Latin America.
Brighton: Sussex Academic Press.
Roniger, L. and M. Sznajder (eds.). (1998). Constructing Collective Identities and Shaping
Public Spheres: Latin American Paths. Brighton: Sussex Academic Press.
(1999). The Legacy of the Human-Rights Violations in the Southern Cone. Oxford:
Oxford University Press.
Roniger, L. and C. Waisman (eds.). (2002). Globality and Multiple Modernities. Comparative
North American and Latin American Perspectives. Brighton: Sussex Academic Press.
Roszack, T. (1969). The Making of a Counter-Culture: Reections on the Technocratic Society
and Its Youthful Opposition. Garden City, New Jersey: Doubleday.
Rothblatt, S. and Wittrock, B. (eds.). (1993). The European and American University Since
1800: Historical and Sociological Essays. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
Rotker, S. (ed.). (2002). Citizens of Fear. Urban Violence in Iberoamerica. New Brunswick:
Rutgers University Press.
Rubinstein, A. (1977). Lihiot am khofchi (To be a free people). Tel-Aviv: Schocken.
(1980). Mi-herzl ad gouch emounim (From Herzl to Gush Emunim). Jerusalem:
Schoken.
(1997). Mi-herzl ve-ad rabin ve-halha: mea chnot tsionout (From Herzl to Rabin
and later: 100 years of Zionism). Tel-Aviv: Schocken.
Rudrakavi, K. (1992). Nirankusopakhyanamu. Kadapa: Akasavani.
Runciman, S. (1933). The Byzantine Theocracy. London.
Runciman, W.G. (1989). A Treatise on Social Theory II: Substantive Social Theory.
Cambridge: Cambridge University Press..
(forthcoming). The Diusion of Christianity in the Third Century ad as
a Case Study in the Theory of Cultural Selection, Archives Europennes de Sociologie.
Rrup, B. (1976). German Liberalism and the Emancipation of the Jews, Leo Baek
Year Book XX: 59 68.
Russe, L.C. (1988). Entre millenarisme dhier et soif spirituelle daujourdhui. A
special issue of Cahiers du monde russe et sovietique, vol. 29 (34).
Russell, S. (1996). Jewish Identity and Civilizing Processes. Houndmills, UK: Macmillan
Press; NY: St Martins Press.
Rychard, A. 1992. Participation and Interests: Dilemma of the Emerging Social
Political Structure in Poland, pp. 167179 in W.D. Connor and P. Ploszajksi
(eds.), Escape from Socialism. The Polish Route. Warsaw: IFIS Publishers.
Sachs, W.L. (1993). The Transformation of Anglicanism: From State Church to Global
Communion. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
Sahlins, P. (1989). Boundaries: The Making of France and Spain in the Pyrenees. Berkeley:
University of California Press.
Said, E.A. (1978). Orientalism: Western Conceptions of the Orient. New York: Pantheon
Books.
(1979). Orientalism. New York: Vintage Books.
Santos, B. (1998). Participatory Budgeting in Porto Alegre: Towards a Redistributive
Justice, Politics and Society 26(4): 46151.
Sarma, A., V. Dattatreya. (1994). Vizianagaram District in the Lap of History. Vizianagaram:
Mansas.
Sartre, J.-P. (1972). Imagination: A Psychological Critique. Ann Arbor: The University
of Michigan Press.
Sassower, R. (1995). Cultural Collisions: Postmodern Technoscience. London: Routledge.
Schafer, W. (2001). Global Civilization and Local Cultures: A Crude Look at the
Whole, International Sociology 16(3): 301319.
Schama, S. (1989). Citizens. New York: Knopf.
Scheper-Hughes, N. (1992). Death without Weeping. Berkeley: University of California
Press.
Schluchter, W. (ed.). (1981). Max Webers Studien ber das antike Judentum. Frankfurt:
Suhrkamp.
bibliography
699
(ed.). (1985). Max Webers Sicht des antiken Christentums. Frankfurt: Suhrkamp.
(1988). Religion und Lebensfhrung, 2 vols. Frankfurt: Suhrkamp.
(1996). Paradoxes of Modernity: Culture and Conduct in the Theory of Max Weber.
Stanford: Stanford University Press.
(1998). Die Entstehung des modernen Rationalismus. Eine Analyse von Max Webers
Entwicklungsgeschichte des Okzidents. Frankfurt: Suhrkamp.
(2000). Individualismus, Verantwortungsethik und Vielfalt. Weilerswist: Velbrck
Wissenschaft.
Schmemann, A. (1963). The Historical Road of Eastern Orthodoxy. New York: Holt,
Rinehart and Winston.
Schmueli, A. (1980). Sheva tarbouiot Israel (The Seven cultures of Israel). Jerusalem:
Bialik Institute.
Schnapper, D. (1993). Le sens de lethnico-religieux, Archives des sciences sociales des
religions 81 ( janvier-mars): 149163.
(1994). La communaut des citoyens. Sur lide moderne de nation. Paris: Gallimard.
(1998). The Community of Citizens. On the Modern Idea of Nationality. New
Brunswick, NJ: Transaction Publishers.
(2002). La dmocratie providentielle. Essai sur lgalit contemporaine. Paris: Gallimard.
Schneider, C. (2004). Der Warschauer Kniefall. Zur Geschichte einer Charismatisierung, in Giesen, B. and Schneider, C. Ttertrauma. Konstanz: Univeristtsverlag
Konstanz.
Schneider, D.N. and R.T. Smith. (1973). Class Dierences and Sex Roles in American
Kinship and Family Structure. Englewood Clis, New Jersey: Prentice Hall.
Schumpeter, J.A. (1991). Imperialism and Social Classes. Philadelphia: Orion Editions.
Schwarz, R. (1992). Misplaced Ideas: Essays on Brazilian Culture. London: Verso.
Seidentop, L. (2000). Democracy in Europe. London: Penguin.
Seidman, S. (1983). Liberalism and the Origins of European Social Theory. Berkeley:
University of California Press.
Seraphim, M. (1952). LEglise Orthodoxe. Les dogmes, la liturgie, la vie spirituelle. Paris;
trans. J. Marty.
Shafer, B.C. (1972). Faces of Nationalism: New Realities and Old Myths. New York:
Harcourt Brace Jovanovich Inc.
Shar, G. and Y. Peled. (2002). Being Israeli: The Dynamics of Multiple Citizenship.
Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
Shamada, S. (2002). Constructions of Cultural Identity and Problems of Translation,
in Friese, H. (ed.). Identities: Time, Dierence and Boundaries. Oxford: Berg.
Shamir, M. (1970). Pirkei Alik (The stories of Alik). Tel-Aviv: Sifryat Poalim.
Shapiro, Y. (1977). Israeli Democracy. Ramat Gan: Massada. (Hebrew).
Shils, E. (1972). The Intellectuals and the Powers. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.
(1975). Primordial, Personal, Sacred and Civil Ties, pp. 111126 in
E. Shils, Center and Periphery: Essays in Macrosociology. Chicago: The University of
Chicato Press.
Shulman, D. (forthcoming). Cowherd or King: The Sanskrit Biography of Ananda
Ranga Pillai. To appear in a volume on South Asian autobiographies edited
by Stuart Blackburn.
Sigmund, P. (1993). Law and Politics, in N. Kretzman and E. Stump (eds.), The
Cambridge Companion to Aquinas. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
Silberstein, L.J. (1996). Cultural Criticism, Ideology and the Interpretation of
Zionism: Toward a Post-Zionist Discourse, pp. 325360 in Kepnes, S. (ed.),
Interpreting Judaism in a Postmodern Age. New York: New York University Press.
Simmel, G. (1984[1892]). Les Problmes de la philosophie de lhistoire. Paris: PUF. Tr.
de Die Probleme der Geschichtsphilosophie, Mnchen, Duncker & Humblot.
(1990). The Philosophy of Money (2nd edn.). London: Routledge and Kegal Paul.
Simon, J. (1997). Electoral Systems and Democracy in Central Europe 199094,
International Political Science Review 18: 361379.
700
bibliography
Singly, F. (2003). Les uns avec les autres. Quand lindividualisme cre du lien. Paris: Armand
Colin.
Slater, P. (1970). The Pursuit of Loneliness: American Culture at the Breaking Point. Boston:
Beacon.
Slotkin, R. (1973). Regeneration through Violence: The Mythology of the American Frontier,
16001860. Middletown, CT: Wesleyan University Press.
Smelser, N.J. (1998). The Rational and the Ambivalent in the Social Sciences,
American Sociological Review 63: 116.
Smith, A.D. (1991). National Identity. London: Penguin Books.
(1992a). National identity and the idea of European unity, International
Aairs 68: 5576.
(1992b). The Question of Jewish Identity, pp. 219233 in P. Medding
(ed.), A New Jewry: America since the Second World War. Oxford: Oxford University
Press.
(1995). Zionism and Diaspora Nationalism, Israel Aairs 2(2): 119.
(1998). Nationalism and Modernism. London: Routledge.
Smith, B. (1994). Classifying the Universe: The Ancient Indian Varna System and the Origins
of Caste. New York: Oxford University Press.
Smith, T. and G. Stevens. (2002). Hyperstructures and the Biology of Interpersonal
Dependence, Sociological Theory 20(1): 10630.
Smolitsch, I. (1964). Geschichte der russichen Kirche, 17001917. Leiden: Brill.
Smon-Nahum, P. (1998). La cit investie. Paris: Cerf.
Smooha, S. (1978). Israel: Pluralism and Conict. Berkeley and Los Angeles: University
of California Press.
(2002a). Types of Democracy and Modes of Conict-Management in
Ethnically Divided Societies, Nations and Nationalism 8(4): 423431.
(2002b). The Model of Ethnic Democracy: Israel as a Jewish and Democratic
State, Nations and Nationalism 8(4): 475503.
Sombart, W. (1976). Why Is There No Socialism in the United States? New York: M.E.
Sharpe.
Soudavar, A. (1996). The Saga of Abu-Sa`id Bahador Khan. The Abu-Sa`idname,
Oxford Studies in Islamic Art 12: 95218.
Spengler, O. On the Style-Patterns of Culture, pp. 13431354 in T. Parsons et
al. (eds.), Theories of Society. Glencoe, IL.: The Free Press.
Spilerman, S. (2004). The Impact of Parental Wealth on Early Living Standards
in Israel, American Journal of Sociology 110(1).
Spilerman, S. and Y. Elmelech. (2003). Israeli Attitudes about Inter Vivos Transfers,
pp. 175195 in V. Bengtson and A. Lowenstein (eds.), Global Aging and Challenges
to Families. New York: Aldine.
Spohn, W. (2001). Eisenstadt on Civilizations and Multiple Modernity, review
essay in European Journal of Social Theory 44(4): 499508.
Sprinzak, E. (1986). Every Man Whatsoever Right in His Own Eyes: Illegalism in Israeli
Society. Tel Aviv: Sifriat Poalim.
(1993). Elite Illegalism in Israel and the Question of Democracy, pp.
173198 in E. Sprinzak and L. Diamond (eds.), Israeli Democracy under Stress.
Boulder, CO: Lynne Rienner Publishers.
Stehr, N. (2001). The Fragility of Modern Societies. London: SAGE Publications.
Sternhell, Z. (1996). Neither Right nor Left: Fascist Ideology in France. Princeton, NJ:
Princeton University Press.
(1998). The Founding Myths of Israel: Nationalism, Socialism, and the Making of the
Jewish State. Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press.
Stevenson, N. (2003). Cultural Citizenship. Maidenhead: Open University Press.
Stille, A. (2003). Historians Trace an Unholy Alliance: Religion and Nationalism,
New York Times: May, 31.
bibliography
701
702
bibliography
bibliography
703
Van der Lieuw, G. (1957). Primordial Time and Final Time, pp. 324353 in
Campbell, J. (ed.), Man and Time. New York: Bollinger Foundation.
Venuti, L. (ed.). (1992). Rethinking Translation: Discourse, Subjectivity, Ideology. London:
Routledge.
(ed.). (2000). The Translation Studies Reader. London: Routledge.
Verkhovskoi, P.V. (1916). Uchrezhdenie Dukhovnoi kollegii i dukhovnoi reglament [The creation of the Ecclesiastical college and the ecclesiastical statute], 2 vols. Rostovon-Don.
Vernant, J.P. (1991). Mortals and Immortals: Collected Essays. Princeton, NJ: Princeton
University Press.
Vertovec, S. and R. Cohen (eds.). (1999). Migration, Diasporas and Transnationalism.
Cheltenham: Edward Elgar.
(eds). (2002). Conceiving Cosmopolitanism. Oxford: Oxford University Press.
Vicaire, M.H. (1979). Les Albigeois Anctres des Protestants. Assimilations
Catholiques, Cahiers de Fanjeaux 14: 2346. Historiographie du catharisme.
Toulouse: Privat.
Vijayanagaram jilla kaiphiyyatulu. Edited by S.K. Pachauri, M. Muniratnam and
J. Akkidas. Hyderabad: Andhra Pradesh Government Press, n.d.
Vujacica, V. (2001). Nationalism, Sociology of , in Smelser, N.J. and Baltes, P.B.
(eds.), International Encyclopedia of the Social & Behevioral Sciences. Amsterdam:
Elsevier.
Wachtel, A. (2001). Translation, Imperialism, and National Self-Denition in Russia,
in Gaonkar, D.P. (ed.), Alternative Modernities. Durham: Duke University Press.
Wagner, P. (1990). Sozialwissenschaften und Staat. Frankreich, Italien, Deutschland, 18901980.
Frankfurt/M: Campus.
(1994). A Sociology of Modernity: Liberty and Discipline. London: Routledge.
(1998). Fest-Stellungen. Beobachtungen zur sozialwissenschaftlichen Diskussion
ber Identitt, pp. 4472 in Assmann, A. and Friese, H. (eds.), Identitten.
Erinnerung, Geschichte, Identitt. Frankfurt am Main: Suhrkamp.
(1999). The Twentieth CenturyThe Century of the Social Sciences?,
in Kazancigil, A. and Matkinson, D. (eds.), World Social Science Report 1999.
Paris and London: UNESCO and Elsevier.
(2001). Theorizing Modernity: Inescapability and Attainability in Social Theory. London:
Sage.
(2004). Palomars questions, in J.P. Arnason, S.N. Eisenstadt and B. Wittrock
(eds.), Axial Civilizations and World History. Leiden: Brill.
Wagner, P., Weiss, C.H., Wollmann, H., and Wittrock, B. (eds.). (1990). Social Sciences
and Modern States: Theoretical Crossraods and National Experiences. Cambridge:
Cambridge University Press.
Wagner, P., Wittrock, B. and Whitley, R. (eds.). (1991). Discourses on Society: The
Shaping of the Social Science Disciplines. In memoriam Norbert Elias. Dordrecht:
Kluwer Academic Publishers.
Waisman, C. (1998). Civil Society, State Capacity, and the Conicting Logics of
Economic and Political Change, in P. Oxhorn and P. Starr (eds.), Market or
Democracy? Boulder: Lynne Rienner.
Wallerstein, I. (197479). The Modern World-System. I and II. New York: Academic
Press.
(1983). Historical Capitalism. London: Verso.
et al. (1996). Open the Social Sciences: Report of the Gulbenkian Commission on the
Restructuring of the Social Sciences. Stanford, CA: Stanford University Press.
Walsh, J.J. (1912). The Thirteenth Greatest of Centuries. 4th ed. New York: Catholic
Summer School Press.
Walters, P. (2002). Notes on Autocephaly and Phyletism, Religion, State and Society
30(4): 358364.
Walzer, M. (1965). Revolution of the Saints. Cambridge: Harvard University Press.
704
bibliography
bibliography
705
INDEX OF PERSONS
Abilea, Joseph 511
Abu-Lughod, J.L. 292296
Adamski, W. 494
Adrian (patriarch of Moscow) 355
Adriansee 594595
Advani, L.K. 548
Agursky, M. 359 n40
Albrow, Martin 662
Alcntara Senz, Manuel 567, 572
Alexander, Jerey C. 10
Alexei Mikhailovich (tsar of Russia)
354
Alfonsn, Ral 570 n5
Allardt, Erik 21
Alli, Lord Waheed 226
Apparao, Gurujada 19, 396397,
400411
Aquinas, Thomas 297 n13, 316,
320324
Aristides, Aelius 128
Aristotle 16, 224, 297 n13, 312,
320324, 503, 612, 614, 625
Arjomand, Sad 16, 296, 297 n13
Arnason, Johann P. 7, 85, 105108,
110, 312, 491, 494
Aron, Raymond 358 n37
Asad, Talal 448
Assisi, Francis of 302
Assmann, Jan 77, 79, 114, 445
Atatrk, Kemal 258
Augustus, Octavianus (Roman
emperor) 130, 136137
Aurelius, Marcus 126127, 503
Avitzer, Leonardo 577
Bacon, Francis 531
Bacon, Roger 290
Baker, Keith 8586
Balsham, Hugh of 314
Batailles, R. 178
Bauman, Zygmunt 232, 492, 560
Beard, M. 136
Beck, Ulrich 492, 560
Bellah, Robert 668
Bellamy, R.P. 633
Ben-Gurion, David 420
Ben-Rafael, Eliezer xiiixiv, 17
Bendix, Reinhard 97 n7
708
index of persons
Colley, L. 365
Collor de Mello, Fernando 570
Comte, Auguste 613, 615, 669
Conno, Michael 17
Conni, Michael 570
Constantine (Roman emperor) 140,
341
Cook, M. 311
Cooley, Charles H. 487, 531
Coulborn, Rushton 666
Crates 135
Crmieux, Adolphe 523
Crozier, M. 557
Dahl, Robert 557, 566, 577
Dahrendorf, Ralf 13, 540, 559, 566
DAndrea, ? 597598
Darmsteter, James 523
Darwin, Charles 275
Das, Venkata Rama 401
Davies, Norman 531532
Delanty, Gerard 20
Delgado, Adriana 577
Denkha Shah 399
Derenbourg, Joseph 518
Descartes, Ren 41, 223, 239
Deutsch, Karl 52
Dewey, John 172 n1, 575, 669
Dhu Nuwaas 509
Diogenes of Sinope (the Cynic) 503
Dittakavi, Narayanakavi 398 n10
Douglas, Mary 178
Dreyfus, Alfred 369 n1
Dumont, Louis 8586, 210211
Durkheim, Emile 23, 10, 25,
6567, 126, 157, 171172 n1,
178, 232, 487, 518, 527, 540,
605610, 611615, 618619, 621,
626627, 630631, 633, 639, 666,
669670
Dworkin, R. 307308
Eisenstadt, Shmuel N. ix, xixxiii, 3,
6, 25, 63, 71, 83, 103, 120, 122,
125, 132, 141, 174175, 184,
191192, 200, 205, 223224,
227228, 245, 252, 258, 287288,
292, 295297, 309312, 332, 334,
338, 344, 409, 411, 415, 443,
461462, 472473, 476, 481,
483488, 490, 498, 505, 509, 555,
557578, 606610, 616, 631,
657661, 666670
Eliade, Mircea 66
index of persons
Gibb, H.A.R. 315, 321
Giddens, A. 175 n14, 498
Giesen, Bernhard 13, 667
Gijsbert, M. 496
Glazer, Nathan 200201
Goetschell, Rolland 22
Gouldner, Alvin 475
Goyard-Fabre, S. 621
Graham, Richard 568
Gramsci, Antonio 143144, 467
Greeley, A. 205
Gregory I (the Great, pope) 345346
Gregory VII (pope) 346
Grgoire, Henri 515
Gundelach, Peter 492493
Guzman, Dominic 302
Habermas, Jrgen 202, 228, 448,
537, 575
Hall, Stuart 446
Handelman, Don 400 n16
Hannerz, Ulf 20, 473474
Hardenberg, Karl August von 516
Harris, W.V. 130
Hartz, L. 44
Havel, Vaclav 532
Hayek, F. von 606, 632
Heesterman, Jan 80, 410
Hegel, Georg Wilhelm Friedrich 96,
102 n13, 108, 143, 275, 618, 664 n1
Heidegger, Martin 93, 97
Heilbron, Johan 8586, 446
Held, David 542
Herder, Johann Gottfried von 487,
664 n1
Hervieu-Lger, Danile 16, 383
Herzl, Theodor 420
Hill, Christopher 292
Himmelstrand, Ulf 488490
Hintze, Otto 96
Hirsch, Samson Raphal 521522
Hirschman, Albert 562
Hobsbawm, E. 365
Hodgson, Marshall 6061, 101,
311313
Homans, George 290291
Hoppenhayn, Martin 563564
Horowitz, D. 417
Hu, T.E. 313, 323 n5
Hughes, E.C. 197
Hleg (Mongol Emperor) 323
Hume, David 142, 228, 624
Huntington, Samuel 2627, 150, 185,
415, 534, 557, 613
709
710
index of persons
Machonin, P. 494
Macintyre, Alisdair 445
Mackenzie, Colonel ? 398
McNeill, William 101
Magidor, Menachem xi
Maimonides, Moses 299
Mair, Peter 497
Makdisi, George 314315
Mallia, Martin 652
Manent, Pierre 8586
Mannheim, Karl 669670
Marcus Aurelius 126127
Marr, Wilhelm 524
Marshall, T.H. 627
Martinelli, Alberto 24
Marx, Karl 12, 143, 157, 171172,
288, 669
Maurer, Georg von 361 n42
Mauss, Marcel 3, 67
Meerson, Michael A. 350351
Meinecke, Friedrich 96
Melko, Matthew 666
Melucci, Alberto 492493
Mendelssohn, Moses 142
Menem, Carlos 570
Merton, Robert K. 474 n11
Merton, Walter de 314
Meyendor, John 351
Meyer, John 646
Nadeau, R. 632
Nagorski, Andrew 536
Nandy, Ashis 480
Napoleon Bonaparte 515, 526
Narayana Rao, Velcheru 396, 402,
404
Nash, Kate 493
al-Nsir li-Din Allh 316319
Nava, M. 478
Nelli, R. 299 n16
Nelson, Benjamin 297 n13, 666
Nicholas XI (tsar of Russia) 363
Niemoeller, Martin 507, 512
Nietzsche, Friedrich Wilhelm 171,
176, 630
Nieuwbeerts, P. 496
Nikon (patriarch of Moscow) 354,
358, 362
Nino, Carlos 565
North, J. 136
Oberoi, Harjot 549
ODonnell, G. 572
Oenbach, Rachel and Jacques 518
Oommen, T.K. 910
Oron, A. 383
Oszlak, Oscar 565
Otto I (king of Greece) 343 n5,
361 n42
index of persons
Pagden, Anthony 531
Panaetius 135
Pandey, Gyanendra 545
Papadakis, Aristeides 25, 354, 361
n42
Parekh, B. 202
Pareto, Vilfredo 605
Parsons, Talcott 84, 91, 97, 104, 171,
232, 483, 665, 667669
Pascal, Blaise 622
Pascal, Pierre 354 n26, 358, 614
Paul (Apostle) 283284, 506
Peda Vijaya Rama Raja (king of
Vizianagaram) 399
Peter I (the Great, tsar of Russia)
349, 355, 358361
Pharr, Susan 557
Pinochet, U.A. 628
Piot, Charles 478
Pipes, Richard 341 n3, 347
Plato 133, 322, 503
Plutarch 127
Polanyi, Karl 86
Polybius 130
Popkin, S. 162, 610611
Popper, Karl 224, 605, 618, 624
Posidonius 136
Price, S. 136
Prokopovich, Feofan 355356
Przeworski, Adam 557, 566
Putman, Robert 557
Quigley, Carroll 3
Qutb, Sayyid 508
Radbruch, Gustav 276
Rajasekhara 403
Ram, U. 440 n21
Ramet, Pedro 340
Randeria, Shalini xivxxiii
Ranger, T. 365
Rani, Riva 402
Ranke, Leopold von 96
Ratosh, Y. 387
Rawls, John 175
Redeld, Robert 666
Rickert, Heinrich 276
Ricoeur, Paul 449
Rie, Philip 175 n14
Robinson, Francis 324
Rokkan, Stein 491, 585
Roniger, Luis 23
Rudolph, E. 591
Runciman, W.G. 8
711
712
index of persons
INDEX OF SUBJECTS
Abbasid Caliphate 117316
absence, of limits 586588, 594, 599
absenteeism, electoral 567
absolute relativism 605
absolutizing tendencies, in modern
collective identities 650652
The Absorption of Immigrants (Eisenstadt)
200
abstractions, of modernity 171
accountability 69
public, in Latin America 567
acculturation 5
Achaemenid Empire (Iran) 111,
116117
activists
inuential 641, 644645
political 36
armative action 226
Africa, nation states in 159
agency
concept of 492
societal 528
agentiality 120
Agrarian Conditions in Antiquity (Weber)
261
agriculture, basis of civilizations
149150
Agudat Israel 376377
aid, Western, received by Israel
419420
Akhlq-e Nseri (Tusi) 322323
Albigensian Crusade 302303
Albigensians see Catharism
Algeria, citizenship in 209
alienation 12, 172
Alliance Israelite Universale 523524
alternative modernities 93, 173174,
589
alternatives
to multiculturalism 201204
to Westernization 442
ambivalence
in social life 467
to social order 642
Americas
modernity in 4445
see also Canada; Latin America;
United States
Anabaptists 291
Ancient Judaism (Weber) 262
animals, rights of 213
anthropology
ethnocentrism in 611612
methods, used in sociology xvi,
xviiixix, 290, 461, 471
theories of pollution and taboo
178
anti-Americanism 534
anti-globalization movements 144
in Latin America 554555
anti-Hellenism, in Bulgaria 348 n15
anti-Judaism 283 n54
anti-modernism 173, 242, 670
of Roman Catholic church 594
anti-Semitism
in Bulgaria 348 n15
in France 524525
in Germany 524525
modern 368369
Western 418
in Christianity 506507
anti-Westernism 324325, 440
in Communist Eastern Europe 536
antinomies, of modernity 40
antiquity
capitalism of 261 n1
Webers analysis of 283
anxieties
of autonomy and self-control 178
existential 637
ontological 175n 14
apartheid 194 n1
Arab-Israeli conict 385, 388,
439440, 510511
Arabs, in Israel 385386, 424425
archetypal gures 1314, 250, 258
Archiv fr Sozialwissenschaft und
Sozialpolitik 263264, 268, 269 n17
Argentina
neo-liberalism in 563 n4
privatizations in 565566
Aristotilianism, political 320321
Armenians, Turkish genocide of 258
asceticism
in Middle Ages 301
in modernity 175176, 179
714
index of subjects
Asia
culture of, Webers analysis of
274275
South
Buddhism in 122
Islam in 551
modernity in 157158
assimilation 5
civic 12, 202
Assyria 70
astronomy 313
asymmetries, in center-periphery
relationships 471
atomism 608
Attic Nights (Aulus Gellius) 127
authenticity, search for 217, 221
authoritarian regimes see totalitarian
regimes
autocephaly, in Eastern Orthodox
Church 350
autocratic regimes, political processes
in 36
autonomy 6465, 615, 633
of elites 310311
human behavior reecting 615
of man 33, 4041
problems generated by 68
and self-control, anxieties of 178
of universities in Europe 320
axial age 68, 80, 102103, 174
chronology of 5859
civilizations 11, 292 n8, 484, 668
Chinese 81, 115, 118, 121122
Jewish 509
non-axial 113, 121122
research into 63, 102104
concept of 105107, 111112,
484
cultural crystallization in 104,
107
debates on 5758
extensions of 296
Gauchets analysis of 66, 7076
and history
global 119123, 312
origins of 107109
legacies of 11, 6162, 75, 173
political order in 118
imperial 104, 110112, 116119
reexivity in 106, 112, 118119
religion in 104, 109110, 640
self-denitions in 62
state formation in 80
theories of 175
index of subjects
Brahmins
absence of, in Vizianagaram 400
compared to Levites 279
purity of 504
Brazil, democracy in 558, 573,
576577
Brhadaranyaka Upanisad 406407
brides, sold in marriage, in India
402403
Brides for Sale see Kanyasulkam (Brides for
Sale, Apparao)
bronze age, crisis of 7879
Buddhism
in Japan 185186
Mahayana 109, 121122
in South Asia 122
Buddhist nationalism, in Sri Lanka
551
Bulgaria
anti-Hellenism and anti-Semitism
in 348 n15
Eastern Orthodox Church in
348 n13
bureaucratic organizations 357
Byzantine Empire 117, 340345
Byzantine heritage, of Russia 360
caesaropapism 344345
caliphates
Abbasid 117, 316
and monarchy 316317
theories of 315, 318, 321
Calvinism 175, 288
Canaanites 387388
Canada, attitudes towards immigration
197
capitalism 587
of antiquity 261 n1
criticism of, role of civil society
144145
development of 293
in Europe 540, 591592
rationality of 153
transition from Communism to
494497
caste model, of Jewish religious identity
367368, 370371, 389
caste system, in India 15, 278,
504
Catharism 1516, 299 n16,
300301, 304
and Protestantism 304305
Catholicism 291
in France 336
715
716
index of subjects
civil society
concept of 9, 141, 145147, 235
modern 141143
normative dimensions of 142,
146
and criticism
anti-dictatorial 143144
of capitalism 144145
emergence of 651
in France, Jews in 518
in Germany
Jews in 518520
Weimar Republic 147
in Japan 46
and market 146, 152
relationships with polity and society
88
and self-organization 142, 144
semantic revival of 143144
and the state 142143
and voluntary associations 142,
574575
civility theme, in collective identities
640
civilizational integration, of Near East
61
civilizations 3, 149151, 158,
483484, 501
axial 11, 292 n8, 484, 668
research into 63, 102104
Chinese 60, 7981, 110111,
115, 118, 121122, 160, 185186,
313
clashes between 150, 166, 186,
502, 510, 512, 534, 551552
comparative analysis of ix, xv, 13,
287 n1, 292 n8, 294, 296297,
309, 310, 666, 668
historical 5763, 121122, 312
and cultures 12
European 9, 290292, 456457,
486, 502, 532, 584
exclusionary versus inclusionary
concepts in 502512
Indian 62, 7980, 108, 115116,
118
Iranian 62, 111, 116118, 313314,
316
Islamic 117, 311313, 315321,
324325, 453
Jewish 509
of modernity 6, 31, 287289,
297298, 305306, 670
and modes of production 149150
index of subjects
non-axial 113, 121122
non-Western 186
pluralism of 35
post-axial 118, 296
pre-axial 58, 7879, 108110
regional basis of 150
and religions 3, 149
Roman 89, 456, 502
Western 3, 61, 6566, 150, 290,
314, 415
see also intercivilizational relations
civilized man, images of 3839, 646
civilizing mission
of colonialism 159, 533
of globalization 163
civilizing process 2, 27, 142
clan ties 295
classes
conicts between 154155, 492
politics of 156
clietelism, neo, in Latin America
568569, 578
co-evolution 139
codes
of collective identities 639641,
645, 648
cultural 257258, 336337
cognitive rationality 620621
Cold War 161162
collective beliefs 632
collective guilt 256, 257258
collective identities 245246, 366367,
527, 528531
codes of 639641, 645, 648
construction of 22, 2526,
248249, 631, 636, 638643,
650651
and cultural translations 447
in modernity 2526, 3738, 88,
542, 635, 644653
reconstruction of 14, 559, 571,
643
symbolic representations of 14,
247258
collective memories 253254, 647
collective trauma 256
collectivism
modern 154155
in Western Europe 540
collectivities 635636
boundaries of 37, 529, 636, 641,
644645
membership of 639
national 645646
717
718
index of subjects
index of subjects
and modernity 20, 444, 447,
450455
in Europe 444445, 455460
theories of 444450
cultural trauma 9495, 540
cultures 449, 527
and civilizations 12
comparative analysis of 258
counter 292
of critical discourse 475
European 480
global 20, 338, 444, 450452,
472473
and religion 336337
Roman 127129
and society 59, 463
third 449
customs, norms derived from 629
Daedalus ( journal) 103, 106
Daoism 115, 122
de-civilizing processes 27
de-historicisation 243
de-modernization, and de-secularization
329
de-ontologization, of the political 411
de-politization, of economics 563564
de-socialization 233234
de-Westernization 228, 460
death 253
debates
on axial age 5758
Fischer-Rachfahl 261
on headscarfs in France 241242
Declaration of the Rights of Man and
Citizen (France, 1789) 207,
237238
defense mechanisms, theories of 178
denitions 484
self, in axial age 62
delegative democracy 572
democracies xxiii, 191, 578
citizenship in 207208, 210
consociational 432
delegative 572
disenchantment with 556557, 567
Durkheim on 65
and equality of citizens 211, 213
ethnicity in 12, 206, 208, 217221,
432, 435
in Europe 488489, 494498,
593
foundation myths of 251
fragility of 557558, 562
719
720
index of subjects
index of subjects
education, in Israel 425426
Egypt, ancient 7677
elections, in Latin America 567
The Elementary Forms of Religious Life
(Durkheim) 6667
elites
autonomy of 310311
in Colombia 558
in Eastern Europe 535536
in Islamic civilization 324
in Israel 373375, 381, 422, 433
in Japan 51
in Latin America 553554
in modern societies 5152
as religious forces 391
in Roman Empire 126128, 131,
137
in South Asia 157
and transcendent ideals 502
elitist theories, of democracy 576577
emancipation
of Jews
in France 515516, 525526
in Germany 516518, 525526
of man 3233
emigration
from Latin America 561562
from Poland 538539
of Jews from Russia 384
emotion
and rationality 40
see also romanticism
emperors, in Byzantine empire 341,
343
empires, political systems of
see imperial political orders
empirical observations 247
Encyclopdistes 142
England see United Kingdom
Enlightenment
historiography 267, 288 n2
Jewish 371 n3
and otherness 457458
Epic of Gilgamesh 70
equality
of citizens 90, 207, 209211,
215217, 225, 244, 588589, 616
in Israel 431432
in democracies 211, 213
and freedom 589
esotericism, in Kalinga region
397398
Essays on the Physical, Moral, and Political
Regeneration of the Jews (Grgoire) 515
721
722
index of subjects
index of subjects
The Form of Sociology Paradigms and
Crises (Eisenstadt) 667
foundation myths 250251
fragmentation, of societies 1213, 240
France
anti-Semitism in 524525
attitudes towards immigration
192193, 196197, 214215
citizenship in 207208, 212, 218,
386
collective guilt in 256
headscarf debates in 241242
Jews in 22, 207209, 369, 515,
518
emancipation of 515516,
525526
and modernization 522524, 526
Occitan-speaking Southern 15,
298299
pluralistic versus totalitarian
tendencies in 651
religion in 335336
and nationalism 385386
separation of powers in 629
Franciscans 15, 302, 319
Frankfurt, Grand Duchy of 516
Frankfurt School 2, 39
freedom
and equality 589
escapes from 176177
as European value 586
limits of xxiii, 226227
and security 215217
French revolution 8485, 92, 210,
515
From Generation to Generation (Eisenstadt)
667
fundamentalism 93, 166, 224, 228,
306
Christian 291 n7
Islamic 508
Jewish 510511
market 563
Futuwwa orders 317319
gender bias, in cosmopolitanism 478
gendered symbols, of nation-states 647
genocide 635
geography, and ethnicity 188
Germany
anti-Semitism in 524525
attitudes towards immigration 197,
240
East, Communist regime in 495
723
724
index of subjects
philosophical-political path of
development 114, 118
contacts with other civilizations
312, 314
dichotomy between Greeks and
barbarians 503
ethnocentrism in 502
legacy of 62
Greek Orthodox Church 347348,
361 n42
Greek philosophy 74, 111, 502, 600
inuences on Islamic political
thought 316, 320324
Grundri der Sozialkonomik (Economy
and Society, Weber) 262267,
270, 272, 277
Guatemala, democracy in 558
guilt, collective 256, 257258
Han Empire 111
Harijan (children of God) 504
Hassidism 376 n8
headscarf debates (France) 241242
Heaven, Mandate of 47, 7980, 115
Hebrew language 371372, 373 n6,
377
hegemonic traditions 166
hegemonization, of nationalities
155156
hegemony, European 293294
heresy 1516
repression of 302308
heritages
Byzantine 360
Roman 456457
hermeneutical tradition, in philosophy
445
heroism 1314
failing 252
self-sacricing 257
triumphant 250251, 257
heterodoxy 291, 310, 318319
in South India 398
versus orthodoxy
in Islamic civilization 311312
in medieval Europe 297298,
302, 304
heterogeneity 224225, 504
hierarchical order, in early states 69
Hindu nationalism 546, 548, 552
Hindu-Muslim conicts, in India 23,
545552
Hindu-Sikh conicts, in India 549
Hinduism 122, 504505
index of subjects
human beings see man
human civilization 150
human condition, refusal of limits to
215216
human interaction 663, 666667
indeterminacies of 636637
rationality in 208
human nature 503, 614615
human rights 90, 160, 207, 209, 237,
543, 588589
appeals to 238, 242
in Communist Eastern Europe 495
in Israel 431
and security demands 560
violations of 308
humanitarian cosmopolitanism 503
humility ideals, in Eastern Orthodox
Church 347
Hungary
Communist regime in 495
neo-orthodox Judaism in 521522
hybridization 470
and cultural translations 448
and globalization 167169
hypermodernity 244
Iberoamerica see Latin America
ideals
cultural 670
of humility 347
of poverty 301302
samurai 505506
of submission 507
of transcendence 502
of universal love 506
ideas
of common good 322323
new, irreversibility of 622625
of purity 503505
of social contract 191
identities 245247
American 2627, 531, 597
collective
codes of 639641, 645, 648
concept of 245246, 366367,
527531
construction of 22, 2526,
248249, 631, 636, 638643,
650651
and cultural translations 447
in modernity 2526, 3738, 88,
542, 635, 644653
reconstruction of 14, 559, 571,
643
725
726
index of subjects
European 591596
evaluation of 614
imported from one civilization into
another 314315
and individualism 612, 619
of modernity 31, 9095
performance of 562, 566
religious 330
reversibility of 613
in societies, role of 230
transformations of, in axial age 104
of Western civilization 415
instrumental rationality 620, 624
integration
civilizational, of Near East 61
of Israel in Middle East 418419
and pluralism 225
policies 240
political and economic, in European
Union 599602
intellectuals 59, 475
inter-ethnic relations 208
intercivilizational relations 5051, 60,
297 n13, 312314, 323, 415, 458,
460
intercultural dierences 257, 448449
interests, self 86, 231, 609610
internal institutionalization 193
international conicts 55
International Institute of Sociology
(IIS) xiv
International Society for the
Comparative Study of Civilizations
(ISCS) 666
International Sociological Association
(ISA) xii
international systems, emergence of
4850
intolerance 530
invented traditions 16, 325
Iranian civilization 313314
Achaemenid Empire 111, 117
axial, dualistic-agential path of
development 116, 118
political order in 316
Sassanian Empire 116117
and Zoroastrian religion 62
Ireland 416 n4
irrationality, in modern societies
153154, 162, 206, 210, 216217
irreversibility
of breaches of promissory notes 94
of evolution 606
of individualism 611
index of subjects
of new ideas 622625
of separation of powers principle 622
see also reversibility
Islam 109
conversion to 552
in Europe 17, 337338
in India 23
jihad in 507511
medieval 296, 297 n13, 311
and modernity 242
non-violence in 511
political 324325
religion and politics in 131
in South Asia 551
submission ideal in 507
Islamic civilization
contacts with other civilizations
312313
modernity in 453
orthodoxy versus heterodoxy in
311312
political order in 16, 117, 316320,
321, 324325
state and society in 315
Islamic law 311
Islamic movement 233
Islamic royalism 316, 319320
Islamicate civilization see Islamic
civilization
Israel
ancient 79, 114, 117118
Arabs in 385386, 424425
borders of state of 416417
citizenship in 219
conicts in 391392
with Palestinians 385, 388,
439440, 510511
constitution in 375, 387 n15, 431
democracy in 430433
demography of 422425
economy 426428
education in 425426
elites in 373375, 381, 422, 433
ethnic nationalism in 435436,
439440
ethnicity in 380
extremist groups in 379
families in 423
heterogeneity of 225
human rights in 431
immigration in 373374, 384,
423424, 431
integration into Middle East
418419
727
728
index of subjects
knowledge
institutions for diusion of, in
Europe 591
quest for 587
languages
Hebrew 371372, 373 n6, 377
and identity 187
interest in 8788
local, use in Eastern Orthodox
Church 351
Occitan 298 n14
Telugu 402
Latin, use in Catholic Church 351
Latin America
authoritarianism in 555556
de-politization of economics
563564
democracy in 2324, 553558,
567568, 574, 576579
dualization of societies in 575576
elections in 567
elites in 553554
emigration from 561562
neo-clietelism in 568569, 578
neo-liberalism in 554, 562563
neo-populism in 569574, 578
new social movements 569
politics in 554555, 563564
privatization in 565566
public spheres in 564
security issues in 555561
states in, perceptions of 563564
violence in 558560
law
ethics of 279
Islamic 311
Israeli 431433
in modern societies 210, 627629
natural 238, 321
philosophy of 630631
rationality in 620622
Roman 127, 132133
and Roman religion 133140
Law of Return
in Germany 424 n11
in Israel 370 n2, 431
Laws (Plato) 133
legal order, universal application of 91
legal pluralism 194195
legitimacy
political
citizenship as source of 207, 218
index of subjects
in Roman Empire 129130
requirements of law 621
Letter to the Galatians (Paul) 616
Leveling Crowds (Tambiah) 549
Levites 279281
liberal democracy 172, 432
pluralism as a condition of 13, 223
liberal Judaism 383384, 390 n18
liberal market economy 90
liberal sociology 175, 615
liberalism 633
and modernity 171172, 175
neo, in Latin America 554,
562563
libido sciendi 613
life
social 463, 467, 664
rationalization of 231, 486, 489,
491, 498
styles 156, 164
liminality 249250
limits
absence of, in modernity 586,
587588, 594, 599
of freedom xxiii, 226227
of pluralism 226228
of political body 212213
of rationality 210, 231, 588
refusal of, in democracy 212217
linguistic analysis, interest in 8788
Little Traditions 166167
liturgy
reform of, in Russian Orthodox
Church 354 n26
vernacular, in Eastern Orthodox
Church 351
local languages, use in Eastern
Orthodox Church 351
localism, resurrection of 167
localization, of the global 450, 454
locals 474 n11
Location of Culture (Bhabha) 446
London, as heterogeneous liberal
community 225
love, universal, ideal in Christianity
506
madrasas 320
Maharajas College (Vizianagaram)
401
Mahayana Buddhism 109, 121122
makoto (sincerity) ideal, in Japan
505506
729
man
autonomy of 33, 4041
civilized, image of 3839, 646
control of nature 41, 150151,
216, 239
dignity of 619, 628629, 633
violations of 9495
emancipation of 3233
rational pursuit of self-interest 231
reexivity of 120
Mandate of Heaven 47, 7980, 115
Mann ohne Eigenschaften (Musil) 404
market economy, liberal 90
market fundamentalism 563
marketing, political 578
markets
and civil society 146, 152
for symbolic goods 330
marriages
in India, girls sold in 402403
in Israel, religious inuences on 434
martial arts training, in Japan 506
Marxism 610
and history 154155
as a secular religion 358 n37
and sociology 231
views of modernity 154155, 173
mass communication 235
mass identity 528
mass mobilization
and elitist theories of democracy
576577
and neo-populism 574
Maurya Empire 111
Meiji Restoration ( Japan) 45, 506
memories, collective 253254, 647
Merton College 314
Mesopotamia 76, 77
meta-narratives of modernity 39
methodological individualism 632
methodologies of social sciences
276277
anthropological xvi, xviiixix, 290,
461, 471
metropolis, as center of creative vitality
20, 463464
Metropolis and Province in Intellectual Life
(Shils) 463
metropolitans, of Russian Orthodox
Church 352
Middle Ages 288292
asceticism in 301
formation of modernity in 295297
730
index of subjects
index of subjects
modernization 910, 33, 151, 413
and globalization 161
in Judaism 376377, 519524, 526
and structural dierentiation 5254,
152154
theories 52, 98, 99100, 468,
668669
universal patterns of 670
and Westernization 184185, 439,
441
modes of production, and civilizations
149150
monarchy
and caliphate 316317
and prophecy 321
see also kingship
monastic retreatism 252
money, social importance of 156
Mongol Empire 313
monistic conceptualizations, of
modernity 157
monotheism 188
in axial age 61, 73, 81
Jewish 81
rejection of 300
moral philosophy 85, 115
moral reasoning, in social sciences 89
morality, and rationality 40, 620, 626
Morocco, Islamic law in 195
Moscow, Patriarchate of 352353,
355, 357358
mother-tongue teaching, in
institutionalized multiculturalism
198
movements
anti-globalization 144
grassroots 492493, 495496
heterodox 291
Islamic 233
national 38, 240, 648649
New Age 179
orthodox 291 n7
of protest 44
in Europe 292, 336
in Japan 46
in Latin America 554555
reform
in India 403, 407408
in Judaism 519524
religious, new 206, 218, 329
social 34, 3738, 645, 648
new 155, 492494, 569
womens 493
working class 155
731
732
index of subjects
Netherlands
attitudes towards immigration 197
emergence as nation-state 365366
institutionalized multiculturalism in
196, 198
pillarization in 194, 199200
networks 100
neuroscience, social 501 n1
neutral attitudes, towards immigration
192193, 196
New Age movements 179
new social movements
in Latin America 569
theory 492494
New World, colonialism in 160
Nigeria, city life in 468
noble savage theme 2
nominal denitions 484
non-axial civilizations 113, 121122
non-social principles 239240
non-violence
in Islam 511
promoted by Gandhi 505
non-Western civilizations 186
non-Western modernity 453
non-Western origins, of Europe 456
non-Western population, in Israel
424425, 438439
norms, derived from customs 629
Northern Europe, multiculturalism in
196
Norway, collective guilt in 256
Occitan language 298 n14
Occitan pluralism 1516, 299305
de Ociis (Cicero) 127
Old Testament, creations of 262, 274,
278281
ontological anxiety 175 n14
ontological conceptions, multiplicity of
3233
Open Society (Popper) 224
openness, of politics in modern
societies 36
organizations, bureaucratic 357
Orient, Occident dichotomy 159160,
458, 534
The Origin and Goal of History
(Vom Ursprung und Ziel der Geschichte,
Jaspers) 102, 105
origins
of European civilization 456, 532
of historical thinking 67, 87, 89,
106109, 120
index of subjects
of individualism 72, 606609,
613614, 633
of modernity 7, 32, 157158, 485
of the people in democracies 251
questions of 250
of Zionism 439
The Origins and Diversity of Axial Age
Civilizations (Eisenstadt) 292 n8
Origins of the West (Eisenstadt) 287288
orthodoxy 291 n7
Jewish 376378, 383384, 390,
424, 434
in Germany 521522
versus heterodoxy
in Europe 297298, 302, 304
in Islamic civilization 311312
otherness 530, 639
acceptance of 501
encounters with 474
in Enlightenment 457458
surrender to 475
translations of 449450
Ottoman Empire, legal pluralism in
194195
outsiders, exclusion of 248249
Over-procurator (Russian Orthodox)
356
Oz ve-Shalom 511
Pakistan 504
ethno-nationalist conicts in
549550
Palestinians
conict with Israel 385, 388,
439440, 510511
nation-building by 234
papacy
lack of, in Eastern Orthodox Church
350351
and secular power 346
paradigm
of human dialogue 667
structural-functional, in sociology
xviii
Paradoxes of Democracy (Eisenstadt) 191
parameters 610
parfaits (Catharism) 300301
pariahs 15, 278, 282, 504
parody, modern 407409
participation
and democracy 567, 575577
equal rights to 90, 207, 209
quest for 36
voluntary 574575
733
particularism
and cosmopolitanism 476
and democracy 4, 207, 217221
of nation-states 209210, 219
transcendence of 207, 217218
versus universalism 443, 453454
past, translations of 450
Patriarchate
of Constantinople 352
of Moscow 352353, 355, 357358
Patriot Act (United States) 307
patriotism, constitutional 228, 531
Pauline mission 283
pauperism, voluntary 301302
peoples democracies 623
performative dimension, of
representations of identity 248
peripheries 2021
and center relationships 20, 35,
462467, 472
in anthropology 471
and cosmopolitanism 479480
in Europe 590
transnational 465
perpetrators 14, 253, 255257
Persia see Iranian civilization
Persian Letters (Montesquieu) 458
personal identities 528
phenomenology, historical 83,
121122
philosophical-political path of
development 114, 118
philosophy
Greek 74, 111, 502, 600
inuences on Islamic political
thought 316, 320324
in Han Empire 111
of history 64, 102 n13
of law 630631
moral 85, 115
political 93, 121, 617618
cosmopolitanism in 480
European 320322, 324
Indian 315
Islamic 315, 320324
and religion 74
translation theories in 445446
pilgrims 334
pillarization, of societies 194,
199200, 226227
pioneer-generation, in Israel 373374
pluralism 184
of civilizations 35
conicts resulting from 13, 225
734
index of subjects
index of subjects
in Roman Empire 126, 131, 137
in Russia 348349, 352363
and religions, in early states 6870,
71, 76
in South India 411
theories of, rationality in 620622
of translation 446
Politics (Aristotle) 16, 297 n13, 322,
324
polity, relationships with civil society
and society 88
pollution, anthropological theories of
178
pontices, role of 133134
populism, neo, in Latin America
569573, 578
positivism, juridical 621
post-axial civilizations, imperial
political orders in 118, 296
post-Marxism 231
post-modern sociology 492, 605606
post-modernity 243244, 329, 571
in Europe 21, 491494
and pluralism 226
Western 414
post-social principles 239240
post-social societies 234236, 242
transformations in 243244
post-socialist states
modernity in 494498
regimes of 538539
post-Westerness, of Europe 459460
post-Zionism 387388
poverty, ideal of 301302
power
and cultural translations 448
royal and priestly 76, 7980
separation principle of 621623,
629
transfer of, in Roman Empire
130131
pre-axial civilizations 58, 7879,
108110
pre-modern images 224
pre-modern societies 154
prevention, of crime 627
primitive religions 6668
primordiality themes, in collective
identities 639640, 643, 650
private spheres
in post-social societies 236237, 239
and public spheres 202203
privatization
in Latin America 565566
735
736
index of subjects
of man 120
in modernity 3233, 485, 492
self 120
reform 166
ecclesiastical, by Peter I 355356,
358361
of Judaism
in France 522524
in Germany 519522
movements, in India 403, 407408
Reformation 346, 614
in Germany 335
medieval background of 288, 291
regimes
changes in, post-socialist 494
Communist 495496
totalitarian 36, 143144, 155,
161162, 292, 345, 555556
regions, basis of civilizations 150
reication 172
rejections
of modernity 176177
of monotheism 300
The Relations between Sociological Theory
and Anthropological Research (Eisenstadt)
xviii
relativism
absolute 605
cultural 166, 309 n1
religions
in axial age 104, 109110, 640
and civilizations 3, 149
and culture 336337
ethno 328
in Europe 1617, 594
Christianity 331, 333, 335,
593595
Islam 17, 337338
fundamentalists use of 224
Gauchets analysis of 6569, 74
history of 261262, 267, 271274,
276277
and identities 187
individualization of 203, 327328,
332, 334335, 383
and modernity 1416, 18, 208,
295, 328334
monotheistic 188
in axial age 61, 73, 81
rejection of 300
national 386, 389
and nationalism 18, 365366
in Arab world 385
in France 385386
index of subjects
in Israel 375376, 382386,
388392
in United Kingdom 386
peaceful coexistence of 630
and philosophy 74
and pluralism 188189, 337
and politics 114, 116117
in early states 6871, 76
in Eastern Europe 17, 339363
in Islamic civilization 16, 117,
131, 316321, 324325
in Israel 18, 432, 434435
in Roman Empire 126, 131,
137
in Russia 348349, 352363
in Western Europe 345346
primitive 6668
and rationality 281, 284285, 594,
621, 626, 630
in Christianity 594
ethics 274, 281, 310
in Roman Empire 126129, 632
Christianity 125126, 139140
and Roman law 133140
secular 358 n37
and society, in axial age 7273, 80
sociology of 261, 263285,
327328, 331333
Webers analysis of 261262,
263285, 295, 310
world 104, 109110, 262
economic ethics of 272273
jamborees of 186, 188
religiosity, new 383
religious conicts 11, 187
religious ethics 279 n45
rationality in 274, 281, 310
religious identities 217
Jewish 367369, 376384
religious institutions 330
religious movements, new 206, 218,
329
Religious Rejections of the World and their
Directions (Weber) 176
religious revival
in democracies 218219
theories of 205206, 211
Replies to Critics (Weber) 261
representations
and democracy 566568, 593
of liminality 250
symbolic, of collective identities 14,
247258
Republic (Plato) 133, 322
737
research
and development, in Israel 425
into axial age civilizations 63,
102104
into global history 101102
into inter-ethnic relations 208
into pre-axial age civilizations 58
residence-based citizenship 212213
resignation doctrine, in Eastern
Orthodox Church 347349
retreatism, monastic 252
retrospective individualization 59
reversibility
of institutions 613
see also irreversibility
revival
ethnic and religious 205206, 211,
217, 218219
semantic, of civil society 143144
revolutionary birth of the people,
myths of 251
revolutions 8687
bourgeoisie 161
colonial 161
Democratic 91
European 85
Eastern (1989) 537
French 8485, 92, 210, 515
Great 34
industrial 591592
of modernity 105
proletarian 161
righteousness 177, 179
rights
of animals 213
cultural 220, 238239
demands for 240242
human 90, 160, 207, 209, 237,
543, 588589
appeals to 238, 242
in Communist Eastern Europe
495
in Israel 431
and security demands 560
violations of 308
of minorities 239240, 432
in modern societies 627629
political 212213
social 213214, 238
rituals
coronation, in Russia 363
of exclusion 278, 282
of expelling perpetrators 255256
of failing heroism 252
738
index of subjects
sacrilege 638
salvation 277278
in modernity 177, 179
personal 128
samurai ideals, in Japan 505506
SAP see Structural Adjustment
Programme (SAP)
Sassanian Empire (Iran) 116117
satellite mentality, in Eastern Europe
536
satellites, and metropolis 464
satyagraha (truth) 505
Scandinavia, political parties in 497
Scenarios of power (Wortman) 363
science
cognitive rationality in 620621
in Europe 591
history of 617618, 622623
see also social sciences
Science as Vocation (conference, Weber)
617
Second World, modernity of 161
sects
heterodox 304
in Islam 311
secular ideology, in Roman Empire
127
secular Jews, in Israel 377378,
382383, 435
secular religion 358 n37
secular rulers, in Europe 342343, 346
secularization 327329
in Europe 331
and multiculturalism 448
in Russia 362
theories of 331332
security
and freedom 215217
issues in Latin America 558561
security forces, impunity of 561
segregation, spatial, in Latin America
559
selection processes
of axiological ideas 623
in evolution 632
rational 628629, 631
self-control, and autonomy, anxieties of
178
self-denitions, in axial age 62
self-determination, for immigrant
communities 195
self-examination, existential 175
self-interest 86, 609610
rational pursuit of 231
index of subjects
self-isolation, of Jews 278, 281,
283284
self-organization, and civil society
142, 144
self-projections, in civilizational analysis
57, 60
self-reexivity 120
self-sacricing hero 257
self-understanding, European 142
Seljuk Sultans 317
semiotics 178
separation of powers principle
621623, 629
Sephardic Jews 382
September 11 events, United States
reaction to 306308
The Seven Laws of Noah (Lichtenstein)
511
Shang kingdom (China) 79
Sharia-based policies 321, 325
Shas party 381382
Shiv Shena 549
Silk Route 104
Sinhalese-Tamil conicts, in Sri Lanka
550551
slavery, views of 612613
social action, civil society as a type of
145
social activism 311
social change 667
Social Change, Dierentiation and Evolution
(Eisenstadt) 668
social closure 10
theory of 178
social contract, idea of 191
social control, decrease of 626627
social development 2
social dierentiation 152
social divisions 171
social evolution 605, 616, 631633,
668
social life 664
ambivalence in 467
consensus in 463
rationalization of 231, 486, 489,
491, 498
social movements 34, 3738, 645, 648
new 155, 492494, 569
social neuroscience 501 n1
social order
ambivalence towards 642
destruction of 13
dimensions of 639
and work 142
739
740
index of subjects
and states
conation of 45
in Islamic civilization 315
totalitarian 224
visions of
political 238, 243244
social 230, 237238, 243244
see also modern societies
socio-cultural order 6768
socio-economic analysis, of cultural
reality 268269
sociologists 232
sociology 243, 669670
and anthropology xvi, xviiixix,
290, 461, 471
civilizational analysis in 666
comparative 126, 138
concept of society in 230233,
662663
critical 39
historical 6364, 8485, 605
and historiography 267
Israeli xiiixiv
liberal 175, 615
Marxist 231
post-modern 492, 605606
real denitions in 484
of religion 261, 263285, 327328,
331333
structural-functional paradigm in
xviii
supranational perspectives in
662668
systems theory in 665
of translation 446
Weber on 267268, 270271
Western 486487
World Congress of 662
solidarity 611
sources of 227228
Solidarity movement (Poland)
495496
South Africa, apartheid in 194 n1
South Asia
Buddhism in 122
Islam in 551
modernity in 157158
Souvenirs (de Tocqueville) 86
sovereignty
of citizens 208
crisis of, in Near East 79
dual, in Islamic civilization
316317
of rationality 4142
index of subjects
survival theories, of ethnic and
religious revival in modernity
205206, 217
Sweden, dominant values in 227
Switzerland, heterogeneity of 225
symbolic goods, market for 330
symbolic representations
of collective identities 14, 247258
of liminality 250
symbols
gendered, of nation-states 647
of Jewish tradition 372, 382383,
390
symphonia, principle of 341, 344
systems
political
of empires xvi, xviiixix
separation of powers principle in
621623, 629
theories of 464, 665
of values 540541
taboos
anthropological theories of 178
in modernity 627
Tantric Yoga 397
The Task of the Translator (Benjamin)
445446
technology
and dierentiation 152
in Europe 591
teleology, in axial age concept
112113
television 235
Telugu civilization
literature in 402
modernity in 396
Telugu poets 411412
territorial states 77
territorialization, of Judaism 370
terrorism 242, 306308
Theft of an Idol (Brass) 546
theories
anthropological, of pollution and
taboo 178
of axial age 175
of caliphate 315, 318, 321
constitutional 317318, 321322
of cultural translations 444450
of defense mechanisms 178
of democracy 576577
of dependency 464
of ethnic and religious revival
205206, 211, 217
741
742
index of subjects
trauma
collective 256
cultural 9495, 540
of modernity 649
travel, and cosmopolitanism 474,
477480
triumphant heroism 250251, 257
trust
generated through constructing
collective identities 642
public, in Latin America 555557,
564565
truth
search for, in Hinduism 505
theories of 624625
Truth and Method (Gadamer) 445
tsars, of Russia 353, 356, 361363
Turkey, collective guilt in 258
unanimity rule, in village societies
610611
unifying orientations, versus pluralistic
orientations towards newcomers in
societies 56
United Kingdom
attitudes towards immigration in
198
dominant values in 227
Jews in 368369
nationalism and religion in 386
separation of powers in 629
United States
attitudes towards immigration 193
civic religion in 227
criticism of 177 n21
democracy in 432
heterogeneity of 224225
history of 177 n20
identities in 2627, 531, 597
inter-ethnic relations in 208
modern society in 233
Peace Corps 301 n18
Puritan settlers in 177
relations
with Eastern Europe 538
with Israel 420
social sciences in 98
war on terrorism 306308
unity, achieved through diversity 600
universal human nature 503
universal love, ideal in Christianity
506
universal patterns, of modernization
670
index of subjects
universal translatability, modernity as
condition of 444, 451452
universal values 630
universal-inclusive path of development
115, 118
universalism
of modernity 171
versus particularism 443, 453454
universality 70
of citizenship 212, 237
of social development 2
universe, views of 151
universities, European 314315, 320,
591
untouchables see pariahs
Upanisads 406407
urbanization
in Middle Ages 294295
source of modernity 158
Vom Ursprung und Ziel der Geschichte
(The Origin and Goal of History,
Jaspers) 102, 105
utopian dimensions
of citizenship 12, 211212, 216
of civil society concept 146
of democracy 216217
utopian visions 3536, 371, 628
values 630
colonialisms introduction of
160161
dominant, in pluralistic societies
227228
European 532533, 583596
dierences between East and West
539540
in Israeli society 437
of modernity 21, 309
and rationality 626
systems of, change in 540541
tolerance 226
universal 630
world, surveys of 625626
Zionisms appropriation of 372
Vedic religion 115116, 122
Venezuela, democracy in 568,
571572
verzuiling see pillarization
victims 14, 253254, 257
Viddha-salabhanjika (Rajasekhara) 403
Vienna, Congress of (1815) 516517,
526
village societies, unanimity rule in
610611
743
744
index of subjects