(Barbara A. Fox) Discourse Structure and Anaphora
(Barbara A. Fox) Discourse Structure and Anaphora
General Editors:
In this series
Universal Grammar
39 MICHAEL A. COVINGTON Syntactic theory in the High Middle Ages
40 KENNETH J. SAFIR
Syntactic chains
41
42
43
44
45
Principles of dependency
phonology
48 BARBARA A. FOX Discourse structure and anaphora
49 LAUREL J. BRINTON The development of English aspectual systems
50 DONNA JO NAPOLI
Predication theory
51 NOEL BURTON-ROBERTS
proposition
53
54
55
56
58
59
60
61
English focus
62 STEPHEN R. ANDERSON
A-Morphous Morphology
Supplementary volumes
RUDOLPH p. BOTHA Form and meaning in word formation: a study of
Afrikaans reduplication
AYHAN AKSU-KOC The acquisition of aspect and modality: the case ofpast
reference in Turkish
MJCHEAL 6 SIADHAIL Modern Irish: grammatical structure and dialectal
variation
ANNICK DE HOU WER The acquisition of two languages from birth: a case study
DISCOURSE STRUCTURE
AND ANAPHORA
Written and conversational English
BARBARA A. FOX
University of Colorado, Boulder
CAMBRIDGE
UNIVERSITY PRESS
CAMBRIDGE u n i v e r s i t y p r e s s
Contents
Preface
vii
1 Introduction
1.1 Major themes of the study
1.2 Organization
1
1
4
2
2.1
2.2
2.3
2.4
Conversational analysis
Notation conventions
The turn-taking system
The structural organization of conversation
Conclusion
6
6
10
12
14
3
3.1
3.2
3.3
3.4
3.5
3.6
3.7
16
16
17
18
45
48
62
75
77
78
91
92
93
93
94
111
118
123
132
135
vi
6
6.1
6.2
6.3
6.4
6.5
6.6
6.7
Contents
Anaphora in expository written and conversational English
Introduction
Theories of the differences between spoken and written language
The basic patterns
Demarcating structural units
Different-gender referents and anaphora
Same-gender referents and anaphora
Non-structural factors in anaphora
7 Conclusions
7.1 Localness
7.2 Discourse structures
7.3 Conclusion
137
137
137
139
143
144
147
148
152
152
154
155
Notes
References
156
164
Author index
Subject index
169
171
Preface
viii
Preface
Boulder, Colorado
The royalties from the paperback edition of this book will be donated to
Punana Leo o Honolulu, a Hawaiian language immersion preschool for
the children of O'ahu.
1 Introduction
Introduction
and Duranti 1984 are important exceptions); and relatedly, it fails to take
into consideration the fact that texts are organized as they are not just
because of informational limitations (what Dillon (1981) calls channel
limitations) but also because of socially accepted conventions (cf. Wittgenstein 1958 on language games). As Dillon (1981: 15) has said:
The general point is that if we abstract 'conveying propositional content' as the
common property of written discourses, we have woefully impoverished the notion
of discourse as a human communicative act. Or, to put it another way, we have
created an enormously artificial model of discourse and have obliterated from our
view the elaborate sets of conventions governing particular discourse types and the
ways these can be employed to signal diverse and complex intentions.
The present study, in attempting to provide a complete account of the
distribution of a subset of anaphora - reference to third-person singular
humans in conversation and expository prose, brings out the social as well
as informational aspects of the relationship between discourse and
anaphora. We will see that interactional and affective factors, as well as
genre-specific conventions, do indeed play a significant role in anaphoric
patterning in conversation and writing.
I have limited the scope of this study to third-person singular human
references. I have narrowed the domain in this way to look at anaphora in its
prototypical use: tracking a participant through a discourse (Du Bois 1980;
what Prince (1981) would consider textually evoked references). Other uses
of anaphora, such as the this in example (1) and they in example (2) below,
introduce further complexities: for example, they may refer to previous
utterances, rather than to participants - example (1) - or they may not refer
at all (in the sense of being non-referential: Du Bois 1980) - example (2).
(1)
(2)
Major themes
Introduction
conversational texts, on the other hand, are largely interactional, and the
units of an appropriate model should capture the social action relationships
that hold between pieces of talk, inasmuch as it is these more-than-oneparty actions which structure the talk (see Rubin 1980 for a discussion of
these and other differences between written and "spoken" language). Thus,
while there are clearly interactional and affective aspects of written
monologue texts and informational aspects of conversational texts, these are
not the fundamental structuring units for that mode. It has therefore been
critical in this work to use one model which focuses on the informational
relationships between propositions for the written monologue texts and
another which focuses on the interactional relationships between utterances
for the conversational texts. From the small set of candidates for each type I
selected conversational analysis and rhetorical structure analysis. Inasmuch
as these approaches are likely to be unfamiliar to most readers, they will each
be described in detail in their own chapters.
1.2 Organization
The remainder of the study is organized as follows: Chapter 2 gives an
introduction to the method of structural analysis used for the conversational
data, conversational analysis. The basic units of the model are discussed,
and example passages are analyzed. This chapter is background for Chapter
3, which details the actual anaphoric patterns found in the conversational
texts. Chapter 3 formulates the anaphoric patterns found in the conversational material. It lays out the patterns of anaphora in the conversational
material in terms of the hierarchic organization of the texts. Structural
patterns, as well as non-structural ones (i.e those performing other
functions), are explored. Chapter 4 gives an introduction to the method of
structural analysis used for the monologue expository written texts,
rhetorical structure analysis. The basic units of the model are discussed,
and example passages are analyzed. This chapter provides the background
needed for the analyses offered in Chapter 5. Chapter 5 formulates the
patterns of anaphora found in the expository written texts, using rhetorical
structure analysis as the tool for exploring the structural designs of the texts.
The patterns of anaphora offered in this chapter, as in previous chapters,
are presented in terms of the hierarchic organization of the texts in which
they occur. Chapter 6 compares the anaphoric patterning established for the
conversational and expository texts using quantitative and qualitative
methods of comparison. Evidence is presented which demonstrates that the
Organization
2 Conversational analysis
This chapter is meant as an overview of the fundamental concepts of
conversational analysis which will be put to work in Chapter 3. It is by no
means a complete guide to this approach; I have included only those notions
which will be applied in the analyses in Chapter 3. For a more complete
introduction to CA, see Levinson 1983 or Atkinson and Drew 1979.
Readers already familiar with CA can skip to Chapter 3. 1
Notation conventions
all. The right-hand bracket (]) indicates the place in the utterance at which
the overlap ends (so C's overlap lasts until after M's thin).
An utterance which has more than one double slash in it is overlapped at
more than one place, and the utterances which do the overlapping are given
in sequential order after the overlapped utterance.
G. they're all Keegans like the ones around Greensprings
they're all kind'v, // bout five five, five si//x,
M. They're all from around Greensprin//gs.
C. Yeh
(AD: 14)
Here, M's utterance overlaps G's starting at bout, and C's utterance overlaps
G's starting with the x in six. Notice that C's utterance also overlaps the very
end of M's.
A left-hand bracket at the beginning of two lines indicates that the two
utterances begin simultaneously.
M. Yeh.
[
C. Lo:ng time ago it reminds me
(AD: 14)
The equals sign ( = ) indicates latching, that is, the next speaker begins
without the usual "beat" of silence after the current speaker finishes talking.
In this case there is an equals sign at the end of the? current speaker's
utterance and another equals sign at the beginning of the next speaker's
utterance. If two speakers simultaneously latch onto a preceding utterance
(that is, they begin talking simultaneously), this is indicated in the
transcript with a left-hand bracket preceded by an equals sign.
(R) (h)hh (h)uh (h)uh (h)uh! =
(S) hhh(h) H(h)m]
=[
K. Which la:]mpost?
(SN-4:30)
Here S and K simultaneously latch onto R's laughter.
Numbers given in parentheses indicate elapsed silence, measured in
tenths of seconds. Single parentheses with a raised dot between them
represent a silence that is less than a tenth of a second but still longer than
the usual beat of silence. These figures are not arrived at with a stop-watch,
but are calculated with a verbal counting technique which takes into account
Conversational analysts
the tempo of the preceding talk. Thus a silence which is timed at 0.3 of a
second in one stretch of talk might well be timed at something else in
another stretch of talk if the tempo of the preceding talk is different. The
numbers thus indicate "experiential time" rather than chronological time.
Certain facts about the production of the talk are given through the
orthographic symbols used. Punctuation is used to suggest intonation;
underlining indicates stress. A colon after a letter means that the sound
represented by that letter is somewhat lengthened; a series of colons means
that the sound is increasingly lengthened. Anything preceded by a degree
mark is quiet.
The letter h within parentheses indicates "explosive aspiration," and
usually means some type of laughter is being produced. A series of hs
preceded by a raised dot represents an inbreath (where number of hs is
meant to correspond to the length of inbreath), while the same series
preceded by nothing represents exhaling. Capitalization is used to indicate
increased volume.
Questionable transcriptions are enclosed within single parentheses; the
transcribers thereby indicate that the exact form of the utterance is not
clear. Speaker's initials given in single parentheses means that there is some
question about the speaker's identity. Double parentheses - e.g. ((clears
throat)) - represent non-transcribed material (i.e., noise which is
non-linguistic).
These are the major transcription conventions which will be used in the
data fragments in this and later chapters. For a more detailed guide to CA
notational conventions, see Sacks et al. 1974.2
To help the reader identify the structure of some of the passages, I have
created a simple system of labeling which indicates which adjacency pair an
utterance belongs to, what level of structure it is to be heard at, and whether
it is a first-pair part, a second-pair part, or a third-position utterance. This
simple system works in the following way.
The label has three slots: the first indicates the position in the adjacency
pair - first-pair part, etc. - that the utterance fills (first-pair part is
abbreviated^), second-pair part spp). So, for example, the following
invented example has two utterances, the first labeled^)/), the second spp.
A. Do you have a computer at home?
B. No.
[fpp]
[spp]
Notation conventions
the second adjacency pair the number 2, and so on. The numbering is done
strictly by temporal ordering. All parts of a single adjacency pair (i.e. the
first-pair part and the second-pair part, along with any third-position
utterance) are given the same number. In the following example, we have
two adjacency pairs:
B.
[fpp (1)]
[spp (1)]
[fpp (2)]
(TG:14)
Notice that the fpp and the spp of the first pair are both assigned the number
1, while the fpp of the next pair is assigned the number 2.
The third slot of the label indicates the level of structure at which the
utterance fits in (members of a single adjacency pair are treated as being at
the same level of structure). For example, if we have an announcement pair
followed by a post-elaboration questionanswer pair, the announcement
pair will be labeled as being at a higher level of structure than the
post-elaboration (lower-case letters are used for this slot, beginning with a).
This labeling is meant to capture the impression that the announcement in
such a situation is somehow nuclear, or core, and the post-elaboration is
somehow embedded, or subordinate, or adjunct. An example of this
labeling follows:
M. A:nd ( ) as far as that goes my father's on his
honeymoon. =
= (y:ah ha haha)
K. (Oh::.) Very nice=
K. =Where'd he go.
[fpp (l,a)]
[spp (l,a)]
[fpp (2,b)]
(SN-4:10)
M's utterance is a first-pair part (fpp), and is in the first adjacency pair of the
fragment (1). In addition, it is at the highest level of structure of the
fragment (a). K's first utterance possesses all of the same features, except
that it is a second-pair part (spp). K's second utterance, on the other hand,
is different: it is the beginning of the second adjacency pair, and it is at an
"embedded" level of structure with regard to the first pair (indicated by the
letter b).
This notation system is meant to provide a "map" for some of the
10 Conversational analysis
fragments presented in Chapter 3. It has no theoretical status, and is offered
only as a simple schematic guide for the reader.
11
the next speaker, having predicted the type of TCU that the current speaker
is producing, starts talking, thus overlapping with the very end of the TCU
which the current speaker was heard to be constructing. This type of
overlap is not heard as competitive. In addition, laughter from one party
simultaneous with talk from another party is often not heard as competitive
(but appreciative). An example of terminal (non-competitive) overlap is
given below.
N. Also he sid that (0.3) t what you ea:t, (0.2) end how you
wash yer face has nothing tih do with it,
(0.8)
H. Yer kiddin//g.
N. nNo;,
(HG:II:4-5)
In competitive overlap, on the other hand, the rules of the turn-taking
system are violated, usually by the next speaker starting up before the
projected transition relevance place of the current speaker's TCU. An
example of competitive overlap follows.
H. En I nearly wen'chhrazy cz III: I:lo:ve that mo:vie.
N. y:Yeah I know you lojve tha::t.
In this passage H is not near the end of a TCU (she has just produced the
subject of a subordinate clause) when N starts up.
Competitively overlapping utterances can be characterized by higher
pitch, slower tempo, louder volume, and lengthened vowels.
Silence occurs, obviously, when no one is talking. Not all silences are
equivalent, however. Silence is considered a pause if it is attributable, by
the turn-taking system, to a given party; for example, if current speaker has
selected next speaker, then any silence after current speaker reaches the end
of his/her TCU is a pause attributable to the selected next speaker. The
following is an example of two pauses, both attributable to speaker B
(example taken from Levinson 1983, which I follow in this definition of
gaps and pauses, the latter of which Levinson calls "attributable silences"):
A. Is there something bothering you or not?
(1.0)
A. Yes or no
(1.5)
A. Eh?
B. No.
12
Conversational analysis
N.
(10)
(HG:II:25)
13
Guess what?
What?
I got an IBM PC!
That's great!
(Invented example)
Notice that the insert expansion pair is completed before the other pair
continues.
A post-expansion is a pair which follows another pair. If, for example, an
adjacency pair that seeks to repair some source of trouble in a preceding turn
(known as a repair sequence) is initiated after the possible completion of an
adjacency pair, the repair sequence will be considered a post-expansion:
A.
B.
A.
B.
It is worth taking a brief excursion at this point into the nature of repair
sequences. A repair sequence is often initiated with what is called a
"next-turn repair initiator" (NTRI), which indicates that in the next turn
the next speaker ought to attend to some problem which the current speaker
has encountered with the preceding turn; hence it initiates repair action for
the next turn. A next-turn repair initiator does not, however, only indicate
technical difficulties with hearing, etc.: it often indicates that the speaker of
the NTRI is about to disagree with the preceding turn (as in the invented
example above). A frequent response to this pre-disagreement in the surface
guise of an NTRI is a backdown, in which the next speaker backs down
from the utterance which triggered the disagreement (as in the example
above).
For the purposes of this study, I have identified two other pair relations
and one turn relation: member of a series, post-elaboration, and turn
expansion. These relations should be taken as tentative; they have not been
14
Conversational analysis
2.4 Conclusion
These are the major conventions and concepts that will enter our discussion
of anaphora in conversation in Chapter 3. Additional material about this
Conclusion
15
3 Anaphora in conversational
English
3.1 Introduction
In this chapter, I discuss the distribution of pronouns and full noun phrases
in non-story conversational texts.
In presenting the distributions, I operate in two modes of description,
one of which can be thought of as the "context-determines-use" mode, the
other the "use-accomplishes-context" mode. In the context-determines-use
mode, it is assumed that the hierarchic structure of the talk determines to
some large extent the anaphoric form which the speaker is to use. The type
of pattern offered in this mode says that in context X the speaker will use
anaphoric form Y. In the use-accomplishes-context mode, on the other
hand, it is assumed that it is by virtue of using a particular anaphoric form
that the structure is created.
I have assumed in this study that both modes of operation are always
present for the participants. That is, for the most part knowledge about how
anaphora is usually handled in certain contexts leads a participant to pick
the anaphoric form that is "unmarked" for the context, and by picking this
form the participant displays his/her understanding of what type of context
is currently under development: this display of understanding, in turn, can
create for the other parties present the same understanding (when by
themselves they might have constructed some other sort of understanding
of the current structure). There is thus a continuous interaction, even in the
simplest cases, of the following three steps of reasoning:
1 Anaphoric form X is the "unmarked" form for a context like the one the
participant is in now.
2 By using anaphoric form X, then, the participant displays a belief that the
context is of a particular sort.
3 If the participant displays a belief that the context is of a particular sort, then the
other parties may change their beliefs about the nature of the context to be in
accord with the belief displayed.
The data
17
The data
The conversational data examined in this study cover a fairly broad range.
Telephone and face-to-face, two parties and several parties, single gender
and mixed gender, video-tape and audio-tape, are all represented in the
pool. The conversations were chosen randomly within a set of fixed criteria:
they had to be spontaneous, naturally occurring conversations (rather than
produced in an experimental or induced setting) between friends or
relatives, and they had to contain at least one segment in which at least one
person was referred to more than once. They also had to be transcribed
within the tradition of conversational analysis (see Sacks et al. 1974 and
Chapter 2 of this study for a discussion of transcription practices within this
framework). In addition, the passages had to be non-narrative in nature (see
the discussion below on the comparability of discourse-types, in which I
suggest that expository written texts are in some sense comparable to
non-narrative conversational passages), where narratives are considered to
be relatings of a series of sequenced events. The names of each transcript,
and a brief description of the interactants involved, are given below (very
little ethnographic information is available for these interactions).1
1 TG. A telephone interaction between two college-aged women friends.
Audio-tape.
2 SN-4. A face-to-face, multi-party interaction, involving three college-aged
3
4
5
6
7
8
women and one college-aged man (with a brief appearance of another same-aged
woman), all of whom appear to know the others. Audio-tape.
AD. A face-to-face, multi-party (outdoors) interaction involving three couples, most of which consists of the three men talking about cars and car
races. Video-tape.
Friedell. A face-to-face interaction between a college-aged man and woman
(possibly husband and wife). Audio-tape.
HG:II. A telephone interaction betwen two young women friends. Audiotape.
MTRAC:60-l:2. A telephone interaction between a man and a woman
(formerly married to one another, now separated or divorced). Audio-tape.
US. A face-to-face, multi-party interaction involving as many as seven people
(six men and one woman), in an upholstery shop owned by one of the
participants. Audio-tape.
Clacia. A face-to-face interaction between two women friends. Video-tape.
These eight transcripts form the pool of conversational data used in the
study.
3.3
19
The fairly obvious intuition that the first mention of a referent in a sequence
is done with a full NP is supported by the following data fragments.
B. Eh-yih have anybuddy: thet uh:?
(1.2)
B. -I would know from the English depar'mint there?
A. Mm-mh. Teh! I don't think so.
B. Oh,=
*-B. =Did they geh ridda Kuhleznik yet hhh
A. No in fact I know somebuddy who has her now.
(TG:6)
The first mention of Kuhleznik in the conversation is done with a full NP.
S. She wasn't invited d'the] wedding?
[
M. (I'm g'nuh take her out.)]
(1.0)
M. (She d//oesn' wanna g]o.)
S. (Hardly.])
M. ( )
M. N//o no.]
(R). hhih] hmh-hmh
(0.1)
M. Sh's tryin t'stay away from the wedding "(idea).
(1.0)
Helloj?
Hi: Marsha?
Ye:ah.
How are you.
Fh:ne. Did Joey get home vet?
(MDE:MTRAC:60-l:2:l)
* S.
A.
-B.
(TG:6)
M.
* K.
21
The second-pair part of an adjacency pair does not necessarily signal the
end of a sequence, however. A second adjacency pair can be "tied" to the
first in such a way that the sequence is heard as being continued rather than
closed. Pronouns, as one show of continuing something already started, are
used in these cases. A clear example of this use of pronouns can be seen in
22
[fpp (l,a)]
[spp (l,a)J
[fpp (2,b)]
(SN-4:10)
The pronoun is used in this case because the adjacency pair is possibly
complete after its second-pair part has been produced, but it is not definitely
closed. The pronoun in the second adjacency pair displays to the recipient
that the speaker heard the unit as possibly complete but has extended it.
The ways in which an adjacency pair can be "tied" (Sacks 1971) to a
preceding pair seem to be fairly limited.5 The first type of tying is called a
series. In a series, one adjacency pair is meant to be of the same type as some
preceding pair, that is, the next in a series of similar items. The series could
be of any action-type; in other words, we can find instances of a series of
topic proffers, or of solutions to a problem, or of relevant questions about
something. It is clear that, if an item is possibly a member of series, then its
appearance should not close the adjacency pair to which it is tied (when the
last in the series is complete, the tied-to pair is possibly complete); hence a
pronoun can be used in a next member of a series. In the following passages,
for example, pronouns are used in the second member of a series (their
referents appear in the first member). 6
Examples illustrating the use of pronoun in the second member in a series
are given below.
B.
[fpp (l,a)]
[spp (l.a)]
[fpp (2,a)]
(TG:14)
23
[fpp d.a)]
[spp (l,a)]
[fpp (2,a)J
(SN-4:29)
In each of these cases, the first-pair part of the initial adjacency pair is a topic
proffer which is met in the second-pair part with a response. The first-pair
part of the second adjacency pair is a second topic proffer, which represents
a second attempt to get the matter talked about. In this way the second
first-pair part is another in a series started by the preceding first-pair part.
A second way in which an adjacency pair can be tied to a preceding pair is
by a relation I will call post-elaboration. In this relation, one pair gives a
piece of news, or makes a report, and a subsequent pair gives or seeks
(depending on who does the post-elaboration) details about that piece of
news or report (compare this relation with the elaboration relation in
rhetorical structure analysis). Once again, the initial pair can possibly be
complete when its second-pair part is produced, but a post-elaboration
continues it, and this continuing of a not definitely closed unit is displayed
by the use of a pronoun.
M. Arnd ( ) as far as that goes my father's on his
jipneymoon. =
= (y:ah ha haha)
K.
K.
1.
2.
3.
4.
5.
6.
(Oh::.) Very//nice =
= Where'd he go.
B.
A.
B.
A.
B.
A.
[fpp (1 ,a)]
[spp (l,a)]
[fpp (2,b)]
(SN-4:10)
[fpp
[fpp
[spp
[fpp
[spp
[spp
[fpp (4,b)]
[spp (4,b)]
d,a)]
(2,b)]
(2,b)]
O,b)]
(3,b)J
(l.a)]
7. B .
8. A .
(TG:27)
In this passage, an announcement is made at line 1, and this eventually gets
24
In this case, the post-elaboration (the last line) is produced by the recipient
of the announcement, rather than by its speaker. Nonetheless, the
post-elaboration is done with a pronoun, which is an indication from S that
she has heard the announcement sequence as not definitely closed (in spite
of the material intervening and the fact that she hasn't produced a
second-pair part for the announcement). 7
This is an appropriate time to point out that the mention of the referent in
the initial adjacency pair does not have to come in the first-pair part of that
pair; it can come in the second-pair part and still be pronominalized in the
post-elaboration pair. An instance of this phenomenon is given below.
25
H.
26
40. N.
41.
42. N.
*-43. H.
uhnuhhhh
(0.2)
Well wt's () wt's he H://ke.
hhhhhhhh a- ah: she says
(HG:II: 19-21)
Here, we get an announcement (H's lines 26-9) and then a series of two
post-elaborations initiated by N at lines 30 and 42 (does he want to meet you?
and well what's he like). The pronoun referring to Grace in the second
post-elaboration (at line 43) comes not in the first-pair part, but in the
second-pair part. It is clear from this sort of example - in which eleven lines
separate the last mention of Grace from the most recent mention of her that mere distance between mentions by itself is not what determines
anaphoric patterns; rather, it is the structural properties of the talk that
exert this influence.
Two adjacency pairs do not have to be physically contiguous for one to be
tied to, as a "continuation" of, the other; they can be separated by adjacency
pairs bearing one of the relations described above to the initial pair, and to
one another, as long as the second of the pairs in question returns to the first
of the pairs, that is, bears one of the above relations (i.e. series,
post-elaboration, or post-expansion) directly to that pair rather than to one
27
C. He:y. Where c'n I get a::, uh, 'member the old twenny
three Model T spring.
(0.5)
C. Backspring 't came up like that,
C. Dju know what I'm// talk] what I'm talkin a//bout,]
M. Ye:h,]
M. I thi]nk- I know whatchu mean,
C. Wh'r c'n I get o:ne.
(1.2)
G. Just use a regular one.
(0.7)
C. Mmm I'd jike t'get a, high one if I cou:ld.
(0.7)
G. I know uh-]
15.
16.
17.
18.
19.
20.
21.
22.
M.
t
Lemme ask] a guy at work. He's gotta bunch a'
old clu//nkers.
G. Y'know Marlon Liddle?
(0.2)
M. Well I can't say they're ol' clunkers he's
gotta Co:rd?
(0.1)
M. Two Co:rds,
23.
(f.0)
24. M.
25.
26.
27.
28.
29.
30.
31.
-32.
And
[
C. Not original,
M. Oh yes. Very orii(h)nal
C. Oh::: reall//y?
M. Yah. Ve(h)ry origi(h)nal.
C. Awhhh are you jhittin m//e?
M. No I'm not.
(0.8)
C. What's his name.
(AD:22)
Question
^ * - Appreciations
Here, then, as in the cases we have seen so far, the pronoun displays the
speaker's understanding that the pair being returned to is, although possibly
complete, not yet definitely closed. The pronoun helps to produce the
feeling of "continuing" something that is still going on.
As I have formulated the pattern of return pop, it must be the case that
the sequence which the pop returns to has not been closed down prior to the
return pop. If a sequence has been closed down then a subsequent retrieval
of some portion of the talk of that sequence is not a return pop. The exact
structural status that such a move should have is unclear to me: but at any
rate it is not a return pop, as I have defined that notion here.
Another example of a return pop, with pronoun, appears below.
1.
2.
3.
4.
5.
6.
7.
8.
9.
10.
11.
12.
29
A.
B.
31
Yeah.
hhh So I don'know I haven:'t yihknow. she wasn' home
by the t-yihknow when I leffer school tihday.=
= Mm hm.
Teh! hh So uh I don't kno:w.
(0.3)
En: =
= M//hm
Well my ant went with her anyway this time,
Mm hm,
A.
B.
B.
A.
B.
A.
r
22. B.
23. A.
24. B.
25.
I
My mother didn't goMm hm.
t! hhh But uh? I don" know = She probably haf to go
in soo:n though.
(TG:3-4)
The return pop at line 24 is a return not to the last mention of the
grandmother, which occurs at line 20, but to B's first round of answers at
lines 2-6 (with A's continuers included).11 Here again we see that the
traditional theory of anaphora, which takes into account only the most
recent mention of a referent, neglects a wide range of anaphoric patterns.
It is obviously crucial for this type of analysis that interactants, as well as
analysts, be attuned to the differences between tying to the immediately
;prior talk and return pops. That is, it must be the case, if this analysis is to be
at all meaningful, that recipients hear the difference between these two
types of moves and, perhaps more importantly, that speakers produce their
utterances so as to display whether they are of one or the other type. I would
like to argue here that speakers do indeed build their utterances to display
the level of structure at which they fit in: the "unmarked" level is the
immediately preceding sequence; special techniques are used to indicate
that the utterance returns to a superordinate adjacency pair.
The main technique that I have seen used by speakers to achieve the
effect of a return pop is repetition of words used in the returned-to
sequence/action. Examples of this design follow (the repeated words or
phrases are enclosed in #s).
H. Yea(h)h en I h(h)ung up w(h)u he a(h)nswer
N.
[RETURN]
(HG:II:23)
[RETURN]
(Friedell:9-10)
B.
H.
H.
In each of these cases, exact lexical repetition is built into the utterance to
indicate at what level it is to be heard. Ties to the immediately preceding
adjacency pair are not as regularly designed to exhibit their ties overtly,
hence my characterization of them as the "unmarked" move.
It should not be inferred from this claim about the design of return pops
that all return pops are built with lexical repetition to display their structural
33
position; some return pops do lack this feature. That is, it is not the case that
lexical repetitions are required in all instances to "accomplish" a return pop.
Passages in which return pops are accomplished without lexical repetition
are given below.
1.
2.
3.
4.
5.
6.
7.
8.
9.
10.
11.
12.
13.
14.
C.
15.
16.
17.
18.
19.
20.
21.
22.
23.
24.
M.
25.
26.
27.
28.
29.
30.
31.
32.
C. Not original,
M. Oh yes. Very origj(h)nal
C. Oh::: reall//j?
M. Yah. Ve(h)ry origi(h)nal.
C. "Awhhh are jou shittin m//e?
M. No I'm not.
(0.8)
C. What's his name.
(f.O)
M.
And
(AD:22)
In this passage, the return at line 32 to the utterance at lines 19-20 does not
repeat any of the lexical items in the returned-to utterance.
1. H.
2.
(0.2)
Gra//:ce,
Member Graxe? my fren Gra//xe,
Ye::ah.=
= hhh Ay:::u::n, hhhh she has, these best
frien's.=
N. ~=Uh hu:h,
()
H. tha:t live in: Minneapolis, 'n they have a
so:n.=
N. Oh:.
=[
14. H. who's twunny:: four'r twunny fi//ve. jSumpn,
N.
H.
N.
H.
]=
15.
16.
17.
18.
19.
20.
21.
22.
23.
24.
25.
26.
27.
28.
29.
30.
32.
33.
34.
35.
36.
37.
38.
39.
N.
H.
N.
H.
N.
H.
H.
N.
H.
N.
H.
N.
N.
H.
N.
H.
H.
40. N.
41.
42. N.
43. H.
Uh hujh,
= ptthhhh 'n he's in gra:d school i:n uhhh ()
bio chem 'r "something like thajt, =
=Sounds good,=
=A:n hhhhhh hnh-hnh //sounds kosher? ihhhh =
(shhounds ghhhood)
A:n' he's coming ou:t. here.
(0.3)
January twunny seventh er // something.
thhh
Mmmrnj::::: :::::.
=&): en she awready wrote him about
me en evrythi//ing en she'd lhke
A w r ] _: : g h t.
=(t') f//ix us u:p.
Does he wanna meet ^ou?
(-)
I mean d//z he wannaWell he doesn' have too much've a
choj(h)oice =
=Oh yeh _that's ^ruhh! =
= i- u- e:hhh,
()
u- uhhhh
[
uhnuhhhh
(0.2)
Well wt's () wt's he ]i://ke.
hhhhhhhh a- ah: she says
35
36
line 2 (or to any other line containing a mention of the relevant person).
Rather, they tie, by the relation of post-expansion, to the immediately
preceding adjacency pair (lines 10-12). I conclude from this example that a
pronoun in and of itself does not "accomplish" a return pop, nor does its
mere presence entail a return pop; while there is a close interaction between
return pop and pronominalization, it is not a causal relation in either
direction. They are independent facts which in some cases become
intertwined.
Having looked at pronominalization in return pops, I would like to
present a remarkable passage in which one of the participants displays her
understanding of a return pop by willfully misinterpreting it as "tying" to
the immediately preceding action (instead of back to an earlier pair) in order
to make a little joke. With this action we see thatfor the participants, and not
just for the analyst, there is a very real difference between an utterance that
goes back to an immediately preceding adjacency pair and a return pop.12
1.
2.
3.
4.
5.
6.
B.
A.
B.
A.
B.
A.
7.
8.
9.
10.
11.
12.
13.
14.
15.
16.
17.
18.
*-19.
B.
A.
B.
A.
B.
A.
B.
B.
A.
At line 18 B does a return back to Sibbie's sister had a baby boy (line 1) with
her So I'm sure they 're happy about that, where that refers back to the fact of
the sister having had a boy. At line 19, A on the other hand jokingly
"misinterprets" B's utterance as an expansion on They said she was
tremendous (line 16).13 That A's utterance can come off as a little joke is a
37
()
sequence 2
as
sequence 1 (not closed) interruption
seq 1 (continued)
(0.6)
6. C.
7. M.
8.
9. C.
10. M.
11.
12. G.
13.
14.(C.)
39
sequence 2
interruption
sequence 1 (continued)
A.
B.
A.
B.
Hello
Is Jessie there?
(No) Jessie's over et 'er gramma's fer a couple da:ys.
A'right thankyou,
A.
B.
A.
B.
A.
A.
B.
Yer welxome?
Bye,
Dianne?
Yeah,
OH I THOUGHT that w' z you,
Uh-she's over et Gramma Lizie's fer a couple days.
Oh okay,
41
Thus although the last reference to Hillary is only three lines away from the
most recent mention, it is done with a full NP because of the structure of the
material between these two mentions. Here again, the traditional theory of
anaphora, which uses distance as the main criterion for anaphoric selection,
turns out to neglect the fundamental issues faced by interactants when they
choose among various ways of referring to people.
The following passage also illustrates the claim that return pops close off
the material over which they pop.
1.
2.
3.
4.
5.
6.
7.
8.
9.
10.
11.
12.
13.
C. He:y. Where c'n I get a::, uh, 'member the old twenny
three Model T spring,
.
(0.5)
C. Backspring 't came up like that,
C. Dju know what I'm// talk] what I'm talkin a//bout,]
M. Ye:h,]
M. I thi]nk- I know whatchu mean,
C. Wh'r c'n I get o:ne.
(1.2)
G. Just use a regular one.
(0.7)
C. Mmm I'd like t'get a, high one if I cou:ld.
(0.7)
42
Anaphora
in conversational
14. G.
English
I know uh-]
[
15.
16.
17.
18.
19.
20.
21.
22.
23.
24.
M.
25.
26.
27.
28.
29.
30.
31.
32.
C. Not original,
M. Oh yes. Very origi(h)nal
C. Oh: :: reall//y?
M. Yahi. Ve(h)ry Oigi(h)nal.
C. "Awhhh are ^ou shittin m//e?
M. No I'm not.
(0.8)
C. What's his name.
[two stories intervene]
1.
2.
3.
4.
5.
6.
7.
8.
9.
10.
11.
12.
13.
14.
15.
16.
17.
18.
19.
20.
21.
22.
43
Different-gender referents
45
= u:h-uh k
( )
hhhh I c'n live without her,
hhhhhh
In this example we have two referents, one male and one female, in a
first-pair part of an adjacency pair; the female is referred to with a pronoun
in the second-pair part.
Another example follows.
S. Djiju tell her you had svmpathih-svmpathy pai//ns
for him?
( ) (heh)
M. (h(h)h No.) I din' tell her anyth(h)ing. hhh
(SN-4:28)
Here again, we have a male referent and a female referent mentioned in the
first-pair part; the female is pronominalized in the second-pair part.
The only other example of pronominalization in the environment of
different-gender referents I have found is the following passage, in which
(1) the first-pair part of a post-elaboration contains a pronominal reference
to the (male) person mentioned in the tied-to core pair, and (2) the
second-pair part of a return pop adjacency pair contains a pronominal
reference to the (female) person mentioned in the returned-to pair:
1.
2.
3.
4.
5.
6.
7.
8.
9.
10.
11.
12.
13.
H.
15. N. Uh hu:h,
16. H. =ptthhhh 'n he's in gra:d school i:n uhhh ()
17.
bio chem 'r "something like tha^t,=
18. N. =Sounds ood,=
Different-gender referents
47
19. H.
20. N.
21. H.
22.
23. H.
24.
25. N.
26. H.
27.
28. N.
29. H.
30. N.
31.(H).
32.
33. N.
34. H.
35.
36. N.
37. H.
38.
39. H.
Same-gender referents
49
be via a return pop to the first - then the first is in an active state while the
second one is being produced.
Given those descriptions of active, the pattern for anaphora in the
environment of same-gender referents can be stated as:
By using a pronoun when two referents of the same gender are present in the talk, the
speaker displays to the hearer that the referent intended is to be found in an
adjacency pair which is currently in an active state. If there are two referents of the
same gender that are in pairs that could both be considered active (depending on
what it is the speaker is doing), then the speaker will use other devices in addition to
the pronoun (such as repetition of key words) to guide the recipient to the intended
referent; if the speaker chooses (for whatever reason) not to use such devices, then a
full NP will be used for the reference.
This pattern is examined in detail below.
3.5.1
According to the pattern above, we should expect to find pronouns perhaps in conjunction with other linguistic devices - used to perform
references to persons mentioned in "tied-to" pairs, even if there are other
referents of the same gender physically closer to the pronominal mentions.
The major subgroup of this class is return pops to one referent "over" a
referent of the same gender. An illustration of this use of pronominalization
follows.
1. A.
2. B.
3.
4. A.
5. B.
6.
7. A.
8. B.
9.
10. A.
11. A.
12. A.
13. B.
14.
15. A.
16. B.
17.
18. B.
19. A.
Same-gender referents
51
(assuming for now that the referents are mentioned in different adjacency
pairs) if it is clear which adjacency pair contains the antecedent mention of
the referent - that is, which adjacency pair is being tied-to by the relevant
utterance. The pronoun at line 24 is therefore unambiguous because the
antecedent locus of the utterance at line 24 (and 25) is unambiguous - the
utterance is clearly not tied to the immediately preceding talk but goes back
to the answer started at line 2 (notice that lines 24-5 also repeat the phrase go
in from line 6). And, as the only female referent mentioned in lines 2-12 is
B's grandmother, B thus clearly displays that the grandmother is the
intended referent of the pronoun. The return pop makes the returned-to
item active, and closes the "popped-over" material, and the referential
source of the pronoun lies in the returned-to material. What is critical here is
the speaker's use of a linguistic device other than the anaphor itself to signal
to the recipient the pair to which the utterance is to be tied.
Another similar example of return pop with pronoun in a same-gender
environment appears below.
1.
2.
3.
4.
5.
6.
7.
8.
9.
10.
11.
12.
13.
14.
15.
16.
17.
18.
19.
20.
21.
22.
23.
24.
H.
N.
H.
N.
N.
H.
N.
H.
N.
N.
(HG:II:4-6)
Here again we have a case in which the pair that an utterance ties to is
clearly signalled by the speaker, and this signalling makes the use of a pronoun unambiguous. In this passage, one male doctor is discussed, and N
says, of him and what he said, and that made me feel good. Later, at lines
14-18, another male doctor is introduced, as a source of authority to
support what the first doctor said. Between lines 19 and 36 no mention is
made of either doctor, and then at line 37 we find a pronoun referring to the
first doctor. Notice that in line 37 N repeats (although not exactly) the
phrase used in line 1: he made me feel better anyway. The unambiguous pronominalization is thus possible at line 37 because N clearly
signals her return to an earlier utterance (line 1) in which only one male
referent was mentioned (the first doctor). The referent mentioned in lines
1418 does not in any way compete for the anaphor.
This particular passage makes another critical point about the nature of
anaphora in conversation: contrary to popular belief, the referent of a given
pronoun is not necessarily the referent of the last use of that same pronoun.
Recall that in the present example the most recently mentioned male
referent (that is, before line 37) is the other doctor, not the real referent of
the pronoun. It should be clear that we must look to the structure of the talk,
and how interactants display their understandings of the structure, if we are
to account for the anaphoric patterning in conversational discourse.
Another instance of return pop done with pronoun and repeated lexical
items follows.
1. H. And there wz a ledder fr'm Da:ve.
2.
[repair sequence]
Same-gender referents
53
There are two male referents in this passage: Dave, who is first
mentioned at line 1, and "a guy," who is first mentioned at line 8. According
to traditional theories of anaphora, the pronoun at line 22 should thus be
ambiguous, since there are two same-gender referents in close proximity to
the pronoun. But once again we see the power of structural indicators for
"disambiguating" anaphora: the pronoun in line 22 is part of an utterance
which is a member of an answer series to the question posed by S at line 3;
that is, line 22 pops right over the lines in which the other male referent is
mentioned and picks out, by repeating the key word say, the item to which it
is tied. The lexical repetition helps to accomplish a return pop to a specific
point in the preceding talk, and this return pop allows the use of a pronoun
to be unambiguous.
One last instance of this pattern is given below.
l.C.
2.
Same-gender referents
H.
55
S.
H.
S.
H.
H.
N.
N.
We:::ll,
(0.3)
He #may me feel better# anywa(h)y
N.
(HG:II:4-6)
C.
C.
C.
Same-gender referents
57
Full NPs used when other linguistic devices are not used
26.
(1.0)
27. G. I usetuh go over there the://n 'n, jio:w, Rich Hawkins
28.
from Bellview drives one, fer some guys frm up't
29.
Bellview.
30. M. ((clears throat))
Same-gender referents
31.
32.
33.
34.
35.
36.
37.
38.
39.
40.
41.
42.
43.
44.
45.
46.
47.
48.
49.
50.
*-51.
59
(0.4)
M. Yah.
G. He's my:: liddle sister's brother'n law.
(0.5)
G. He's a policem'n in Bellview b't he- (0.4) I guess
he's not afraid t'drive a ca:r.
(1.0)
G. I d'know what they have tuh drj:ve I haven'even been
over tuh see (im//lately)
M. It's a pretty good ca:r.
(4.2)
G. Evry time I wen over there I froze m'nu:ts.
(1.0)
M. hh hh//hh!
G. You always go over en ni- nice in the afternoon en you
go over there wi//th jus::]t shirtsleeves on 'er just a,
short sleeve shirt" n fore the night is over yer
freezin t'death.
M. Yeah.]
G. Yer not aHowed t'drhnk,
M. Hawkins the one thet hit Al last year over in
Finley
(AD:17-19)
Same-gender referents
61
In the preceding sections of this chapter, we have seen the basic structural
patterns which correlate with the distribution of anaphoric devices. In this
section I would like to demonstrate that, while those patterns are basic, they
are not always followed; that is, there are other, non-structural, factors
which influence anaphora. These non-structural factors are rarely discussed
in the literature on anaphora (Linde 1979 and Duranti 1984 are exceptions)
and thus it is particularly important to examine them here. 23
T h e non-structural factors I have isolated do not seem to form a coherent
group; at least, at this point I don't see any common principle at work in
them. I have therefore presented them below in a list format.
3.6.1
D isagreements
R.
V.
R.
V.
Non-structural factors
63
A.
B.
A.
B.
A.
B.
A.
B.
A.
A.
B.
Hello
Is Jessie there?
(No) Jessie's over et 'er gramma's fer a couple da:ys.
A'right thankyou,
Yer welxome?
Bye.
Dianne?
Yeah.
OH I THOUGHT that w'z you.
Uh-she's over et Gramma Lizie's fer a couple days.
Oh okay,
(US:7-8)
A.
B.
(b)
A.
B.
Non-structural factors
V.
J.
*-J.
65
Assessments
It has been noted by other researchers (for example, Duranti 1984) that a
speaker's attitudes towards characters can be displayed through the
anaphoric devices chosen to refer to those characters. In my own data I have
found something similar, in that it seems that speakers tend to use full NPs
to refer to people in an assessment situation, especially if the assessment is
negative (negative affect). Examples of full NPs in assessments are given
below. Notice that in each case we would have expected, on the basis of
patterns discussed earlier, that a pronoun would have been used.
V. Don' haftuh be a value whenever I do anything not
fuh my wife, my wife wantstuh know why, I did (it).
S.
M.
M.
V.
V.
J.
M.
V.
R.
V.
J.
It is not clear to me why assessments should "induce" the use of full NPs.
Nonetheless, there seems to be a demonstrable pattern of this association in
the data I have examined.
3.6.4
First mentions
We noted at the beginning of this chapter that the first mention of a referent
in a sequence is done with a full NP. This pattern seems obvious enough.
Non-structural factors
67
f
B.
A.
B.
A.
B.
A.
A.
B.
A.
- B.
u-htOh::,
()
H. Bu:t
t
N.
H.
*-H.
My f: face hurts, =
=W't-
()
Oh what'd he do tih you.
Although the pronoun in the last line of this passage could refer to a specific
person known to both H and N, it is more likely that it is just one of a class of
Non-structural factors
69
Yeh.
Okay.
Yeah.
Now he threw money onna ta:ble.
Who//o.
He's no:t uh, he's not a spendthrift Jim.
Oh wuh lemme tellyuh now.
I put fi'dolluhs'n Jim gave me (
)//
yesterday I'm goin tuhnight.=
V. Okay.
M. =You'll have 'em- eh you'll have 'm tuhnight. Seven uh
clock eight uh'clock I'll bring "em over t'yer house.
(US: 76-77)
In this passage, the new unit is marked first with now I'll tell you the reason
and then with Oh well let me tell you now (a type of pre-pre, presumably),
and contains a full NP even though the unit is tied to an action in which the
same referent (Jim) is mentioned.
M.
K.
M.
M.
M.
M.
M.
M.
M.
K.
M.
K.
M.
Non-structural factors
71
(AD:8)
In this passage, M uses a full NP in a second-pair part (line 2) even though
we have seen that usually a pronoun is used in a second-pair part if the same
referent is mentioned in the first-pair part. M's full NP here (i.e. Keegan) is
used to begin a new unit - a list unit of who is around and doing well,
which he then continues with M'Gilton. It is the separateness of M's unit
(that is, that he is not answering C's question but also creating an internally
complex unit on his own) that facilitates the use of a full NP here.
3.6.6
Replacing an action
My wife//caught d'ki:d,=
R. Yeh.
V.
V.
V.
Non-structural factors
73
Here there is a nearly exact repeat of the utterance, done with the same
anaphoric forms as in the original utterance. My claim here is that V's last
utterance is intended to be a replacement for his first.
A common type of replacement occurs when an utterance is in overlap
with someone else's talk, or is not sequentially implicative for the
subsequent talk; in this case the utterance is treated by its speaker as if the
other parties had not "heard" it and it is reproduced (possibly with some
variation from the first try) using the anaphoric form used in the original
utterance. An example of a speaker replacing a previous try with a new one is
given below (the replacements occur at lines 11 and 13):
1.
2.
3.
4.
5.
6.
7.
8.
9.
10.
*-ll.
12.
13.
M. Keegan's
M. out there he's
M. He run,
(0.5)
M. E://r he's uh::
G. Wuhyih mean my:,]
G. My//brother in law's out there,]
M. doin real good this year'n] M'Gilton's
doin real good thi//s year,
C. M'Gilton still there? =
G. =hhHawki//ns
C. Oxfrey runnin-I heard Oxfrey gotta new ca:r.
G. Hawkins is runnin
(AD:8)
N first uses the phrase another doctor in another doctor told me that too. She
then says a doctor at school told me the exact same thing; are we to infer
from this that she has talked to two other doctors who told her the same
thing? Clearly not. What we are meant to hear with N's a doctoral school
utterance is a replacement of her earlier utterance another doctor told me,
with some additional information (adding authority?) about the doctor and
a re-characterization of what was told.
Two adjacent full NPs can thus be heard as coreferential, in a sense, if the
second is designed to be a replacement for the first.
Another instance of a type of replacement is given below.
M. Hawkins the one thet hit Al last year over in Finley en,
(10)
M. flipped him 'n put A] in that bad accident.
(AD: 19)
In this passage, M gives a characterization of a complex event (someone
getting hit in a racing accident), then goes on to give a detail of that event
(someone getting flipped). He has thus moved from a general, higher-level
view to an action-by-action view. In the next clause, however, he returns to
the higher-level view to re-characterize the complex event (a bad accident).
Since he returns to the general view after starting an action-by-action view,
he can be heard to be replacing his original characterization of the general
view with a new characterization (possibly to indicate that the accident was
worse than was suggested by his first characterization). In this last clause he
goes back to the full NP - further indication that he is replacing the first
clause and not the second: the first contains a full NP while the second
contains a pronoun, and since we have seen that a replacement utterance
uses the same anaphoric form as the utterance it is replacing, the
replacement (which uses a full NP) must in this case be replacing the clause
with the full NP.
Summary 75
One final example of this phenomenon is given below.
M. Soon ez Sonny gets back frm the stoh. = Sonny's up et the stoh.
J. Uh hu//h?
[
M. Waif II he gets back.
(US:45)
In this passage, the first sentence from M is "replaced" by the next two
sentences from M: in the first sentence, the fact that Sonny is at the store is
presupposed (you can't come back from someplace unless you're already
there); in the replacement sentences, this presupposition is made explicit,
and what had been done in one clause26 is now broken up into two main
clauses. The point to be made here is that M starts the replacement sentence
with a full NP, even though the referent had just been mentioned in the
immediately preceding clause.
3.6.7
Interim summary
We have seen in this section that, while structural factors establish the basic
patterns of anaphora in conversation, they are not the only factors involved
in any given choice of anaphoric device. That is, there are factors outside of
sequences, adjacency pairs, return pops, etc. that influence which device
will be selected in particular environments. These other factors represent a
wide range of conditions, and it is not yet clear that there is any single
feature which would hold them all together; nonetheless, they function for
our purposes here as a group because they have the interesting effect of
"inducing" the use of one anaphoric device in a structural environment in
which we could have expected the other device. Thus, although structural
properties are crucial in understanding the overall patterns of anaphora in
conversation, our description would be misleading and incomplete if we
ignored the influence of factors such as disagreements, assessments, and
overt recognitionals.
3.7 Summary
In this chapter we identified and traced various patterns of anaphora in
English conversations. It was claimed that as long as a sequence is not yet
closed - if it is not a same-gender environment - a referent within that
sequence could be mentioned using a pronoun (cf. Thavenius 1983). The
The structure of expository prose has captured the interest of a wide range
of disciplines, including rhetoric (Dillon 1981; Young et al. 1970;
D'Angelo 1975; Winterowd 1975), cognitive psychology (van Dijk and
Kintsch 1983; Meyer and Rice 1982; De Beaugrande 1980; Bransford
1979; Sanford and Garrod 1981; Britton and Black 1985), artificial
intelligence (Alvarado 1986; Schank 1982; Brown 1985; McKeown 1982)
and linguistics (Hinds 1979; Grimes 1975; Kamp 1981). While several of
these studies have designed detailed and insightful notations for representing the hierarchical structure of expository prose (for example, the
macrostructures of van Dijk and Kintsch 1983; the argument units of
Alvarado 1986; the rhetorical schemas of McKeown 1982; the conceptual
graph structures of Graesser and Goodman 1985; the structures of Meyer
1985), none of them provides all that is needed for an in-depth exploration
of anaphora. For this study it was necessary to have a notation with the
following characteristics:
Ability to represent a fairly complete range of argumentation relations. A model was
needed that would provide relations like evidence, background, summary,
justification,
Flexibility of combination. Given the range of texts examined (obituaries,
biography, announcements, feature articles), it was important that the basic units be
combinable in a relatively free way, rather than tightly constrained, as in a
grammar.1
Ability to represent texturing. It is now widely recognized that not all parts of a text
hold the same communicative importance - some information is presented as central
to the goals of the text and some as peripheral (Hopper and Thompson 1980;
Grimes 1975). It was critical that the model be capable of capturing in some explicit
way this distinction between central and peripheral for each basic unit.
The system I found that satisfied these conditions was rhetorical structure
analysis (Mann et al. 1982), based in part on Grimes 1975 and McKeown
1982.2 Rhetorical structure analysis forms the basis of the analyses in
Propositions
4.1.2
R-structures
We have seen that, within this model of discourse, texts are treated as
hierarchically organized groups of propositions (or clauses). The groups
79
into which the propositions are arranged are represented here by what are
called R-structures (which stands for rhetorical structures). Most Rstructures consist of a core portion and an ancillary portion, called the
nucleus and adjunct respectively. The nucleus realizes the main goals of the
writer, and the adjunct provides supplementing information for the
material in the nucleus. Not all R-structures have this internal make-up,
however; there are a few that consist only of nuclei (the List structure, for
example), and at least one that has a nucleus and several adjuncts.
R-structures are drawn with their label at the top (such as "Conditional"),
and several lines descending from the top. The nucleus is represented in the
diagrams with a straight vertical line coming down from the R-structure
label, and the adjunct is represented with an arcing line coming out of the
bottom of the nucleus line. The arcing line is labeled with the name of the
relation which holds between the nucleus and the adjunct (reason, for
example). This relation label is usually identical to the label for the
R-structure itself; in some cases, however, the relation carries a different
label from that of the structure. Table 4.1 lists all the R-structures used in
this study and their internal structure. 4
Table 4.1 R-structures
R-structure name
Internal structure
Issue
Conditional
Circumstance
List
Narrate
Reason
Concession
Opposition
Purpose
Response
Contrast
Issue
I background
A real example of the Issue structure is given below (the propositions are
numbered so that the diagram can be more easily followed).
(1)
(2)
(3)
(4)
(5)
background
^
^background
^
"background
81
The entire text can be represented with an Issue structure. The first
proposition is the nucleus of the text, in that it provides the news which the
text is intended to convey. The other four propositions are background
adjuncts - they do not provide evidence for the claim "X has been appointed
dean," nor do they provide details about the appointment; rather they
provide background information which elucidates the claim. This fact is
represented by four separate background adjuncts.8
The Issue structure thus has a unique internal structure (one nucleus and
many adjuncts) and often occupies a unique place in the structure of a text the topmost node.
4.1.2.2 List
The List structure is another of the most prevalent and powerful organizing
units. It has an unlimited number of nuclei (as many as there are items in the
list) and no adjuncts. Each item is seen as a member of the List unit, rather
than as a separate adjunct, because of the impression they create of each
being one in a series (hence they are each only part of a larger unit). In
addition, the members of the list are presented as equal. Syntactic
parallelism is extremely common in this structure. 9
(1)
(2)
(3)
(1)
(2)
(3)
In these examples, each piece is one in a series. Note the strong parallelism
in syntactic and lexical structure within each List structure.
Word reaches him that his masters . . . have changed their minds yet
again on a major issue.
Rochac dictates a new strategy. . . .
One more crisis overcome, he cuts the tension with his favorite
catchphrase. (People, May 26, 1984)
Narrate
(1)
(2)
(3)
4.1.2.4 Reason
Unlike the preceding structures, the Reason structure usually occurs at the
lower levels of the text, and often is realized directly by terminal nodes
(propositions). This R-structure has a nucleus which makes a statement
about something and an adjunct which provides the reason for that
statement (either the reason for making it or the reason for it being so).
Examples of the Reason structure appear below.
(1)
(2)
83
Here the second proposition provides the reason for the situation described
by the first.
(1)
(2)
Here again, the second proposition provides the reason for doing the action
described in the first.
4.1.2.5 Circumstance
The Circumstance structure is another of the lower-level structures. In it,
the nucleus describes a situation and the adjunct gives information about
the circumstances under which the situation occurred (or will occur).
Circumstance differs from the background relation, in that Circumstance
immediately situates a process in time or space, while background gives
information of various types which helps the reader understand the nuclear
material. Examples of the Circumstance structure are given below.
(1)
(2)
of
~^>
In this passage, the first proposition provides the circumstances and the
second provides the situation. The first proposition is thus diagrammed as
the adjunct of the structure, and the second is the nucleus.
(1)
(2)
c?5
"
Conditional
In this piece of text, the first proposition is the adjunct stating the conditions
under which the nucleus, realized by the second proposition, holds.
(1)
(2)
Again, the first proposition is the adjunct and the second is the nucleus.
4.1.2.7 Response
In the Response structure, a problem or question is posed by the writer
which is then responded to with some sort of solution or answer. In this
structure, the answer is the nucleus and the question is the adjunct.
(1)
(2)
85
The first proposition, the question, is the adjunct and the second
proposition, the answer, is the nucleus.
(1)
What was this carapace which Leonard Woolf carried for seventy
years . . . ?
(2) He had above all an unusual capacity to control his feelings. (A House
of Lions, p. 24)
Response
solution
4.1.2.8. Purpose
As one would expect, the Purpose structure has a nucleus which describes
some situation and an adjunct which describes the purpose which that
situation is intended to fulfill.
(1)
(2)
(1)
(2)
we'd win them by our example (Letter to the editor of the Christian
Science Monitor, cited in Mann et al. 1982)
(1)
(2)
4.1.2.10
Concession
(1)
(2)
87
In each case, the conceding adjunct is given in the first proposition and the
nucleus material is given in the second proposition.
4.1.2.11 Contrast
The Contrast structure comes in two forms: in the first, all the contrasted
items are of equal status in the presentation of the material; in the second,
one item is being contrasted with another item, where the latter has more
focal status than the former. In the first case, the Contrast structure consists
of multiple nuclei, in the second case of a nucleus and an adjunct. Examples
of the multiple-nuclei Contrast are given below.
(1)
(2)
(1)
(2)
One airport source said the gunmen may have gone to a nearby Shiite
shanty-town called Hayya Seloum,
but authorities weren't sure what had happened to them. (News item
in the UCLA Daily Bruin, cited in Thompson, class lectures)
Contrast
4.1.3
The Joint
Floating relations
89
For years Leonard knew how not to feel - how to distance himself from
intimacy.
This made for an uneasy calm. (A House of Lions, p. 24)
Embedding
The examples given above have illustrated R-structures using simple data that is, structures realized by terminal nodes. In this section, we shall
examine some more complex data - texts that exhibit embedding.
Any of the pieces of an R-structure can be realized by another
R-structure; that is, either the nucleus or the adjunct (or any of the nuclei in
a multi-nuclei structure) can be realized not directly by a proposition but
textually by an embedded R-structure. Short examples of embedded
structures appear below.
(1)
(2)
(3)
Opposition
opposition
What to do?
Simply send for Harry Fujita, 47, the founder of Iwasaki Images of
America and the Picasso of fake foods.
91
In this passage the highest structure is a Response structure (questionanswer), with the adjunct realized by proposition 1 and the nucleus realized
by an embedded Reason structure, which is realized by propositions 2 and
3. Note that propositions 2 and 3 are in a response relation to proposition 1,
not a reason relation (they are in a reason relation to one another). The
nucleus of the embedded Reason structure is proposition 2, and since the
Reason structure realizes the nucleus of the higher structure, proposition 2
is the nucleus for the passage.
4.3 Summary
In this chapter I have presented the basic concepts and tools of rhetorical
structure analysis. In the next chapter, we will see how these elements are
used in the analysis of naturally occurring written English expository texts,
and will determine what relationships can be discerned between the
structural analyses and the patterns of anaphora exhibited.
5.1
Introduction
In this chapter I examine the distribution of pronouns and full noun phrases
in some expository written English texts. The structural analysis technique
used will be rhetorical structure analysis.
The anaphoric patterns established in this chapter are presented in the
two modes discussed in Chapter 3. These two modes, it will be recalled, are
the context-determines-use mode and the use-determines-context mode
(see also Chapter 3 for a discussion of these modes). I argued in Chapter 3
that both of these modes are always present for conversationally interacting
parties, although in any particular instance one may be more strongly felt
than the other. The argument for this view runs as follows:
1 Anaphoric form X is the unmarked form for a context like the one the
participant is in now.
2 By using anaphoric form X, then, the participant displays an
understanding that the context is of that sort.
3 If the participant displays an understanding that the context is of that
sort, then the other parties may change their understandings about the
nature of the context to be in accord with the understanding displayed
(cf. McHoul 1982).
I would like to propose now that this same cycle of factors lies behind
anaphora in writing as well. Even though the parties (writer and reader) are
not co-present at either the time of writing or the time of reading and hence
cannot directly participate in such a fluid display of understandings, each
feels the other's presence in a way that strongly influences their behavior
towards the text. That is, for a text to be successful (at least in our
audience-oriented culture), the writer must anticipate the reader's
understanding of the text - a developing understanding (since the reader
cannot have full access to the writer's plans from the outset) - and must
The texts used in this study are composed in American English.1 The
instances of written expository texts were selected from four separate
sources, in an attempt to have a broad range of expository texts represented.
The variety of sources was of course limited by the nature of the
phenomenon under study; that is, the text-type had to be a reliable source of
multi-paragraph texts containing multiple references to at least one person.
In addition, the text-type had to be essentially expository, rather than, say,
narrative or procedural. The individual examplars of each source were
chosen randomly within these criteria.2
The sources ultimately chosen were the following:3
1 The Los Angeles Times.
2 The University Bulletin, the newsletter of the University of California
system, which contains information about administrators, faculty, and
staff in the UC system.
95
The patterns
I have taken the terms active and controlling from Reichman (1981), and
will be using them with essentially their original meaning, though
somewhat modified for my own purposes. I will use the term active to refer
to a proposition in an R-structure (either the adjunct or the nucleus) whose
R-structure partner (the nucleus or the adjunct) is being produced. That is,
97
Kenneth Vincent Hollywood, who spent his life opening doors for
filmdom's rich and famous after flopping big in his own stage debut,
has died of cancer.
(2) He would have been 61 years old today. (Los Angeles Times, August 8,
1983)
Issue
background
The R-structure used in this passage is again an Issue structure: the first
sentence is the nucleus (in fact of the whole article) and the second sentence
is a background adjunct (information which helps the reader interpret the
nucleus). A pronoun is used in the adjunct.
This pattern also includes instances in which the referent is mentioned in
the first member of a List structure or a Joint schema - a second mention in
the next member of the List or Joint can be done with a pronoun:
(1)
<
99
Y
Z
sr-o
(1) He prospered.
(2) When Victoria came to the throne
(3) he was living in a comfortable house in or near Tavistock Square. (A
House of Lions, p. 19)
101
Issue
evidence
Q
Circumstance
circumstance
A return pop can also occur if a list of items is being enumerated and there
is a side adjunct on one of the list members, followed by a return to the List
structure:
List
103
(5)
(6)
(7)
For now we will consider only the italicized reference (His) in this
passage. The structure for the whole text is given below (the position in the
diagram of an adjunct to the right or to the left of a nucleus is unimportant
and usually reflects limitations on space).
Issue
background
background
Joint
background
The nucleus of the passage is the first sentence - that is, the fact of Smith's
installment is the "news" which the article is meant to convey. The next
sentence, represented by a Joint structure, is a background structure on the
nucleus of the passage. The next three propositions (in a List structure) are
another background structure on the main nucleus (hence a return pop, but
not the one we are concerned with now). The proposition containing the
italicized pronoun is a third background adjunct off of the main nucleus,
and is the return pop we want to examine now. In this text we thus have a
nucleus and three adjuncts on that nucleus, each produced after the other.
Notice that the second and third adjuncts are not adjuncts of the first
(2)
(3)
(4)
(5)
(6)
(7)
(8)
background
background \ f background
105
The nucleus of this chunk of text is the first sentence. The second
sentence is a background adjunct off of the nucleus, and the third sentence is
an elaboration off of the nucleus. The third sentence is thus a return pop
which pops over the second sentence. The first adjunct (second sentence)
contains no mentions of Leonard, and yet the return pop can be done with a
pronoun9 because the structure of the first adjunct is so simple - a terminal
background node.
(1)
(2)
(3)
(4)
(5)
107
nucleus, thus a return pop. This return pop can be done with a pronoun
because of the relatively simple structure of the intervening adjunct;
although it has some internal structure, it does not begin something new (as
would a new Issue structure) and it does not have a complex nucleusadjunct structure.
The structure of the passage follows.
Issue
elaboration
elaboration
Contrast
Issue
background
In this passage we get a list of the movies Robertson starred in after his
temporary exile from Hollywood. Thus, even though the first member of
the list has an adjunct which does not mention Robertson (but its
completion . . .), the next member of the list can contain a pronoun. This
pattern is repeated between the second and third members of the list: the
second member has a background structure off of it that does not mention
Robertson (It's about Dorothy Strut ton . . .), but the third member starts
right up with a pronoun. Notice that in a strictly linear view of this text we
might think that he could be ambiguous in the last sentence, since there is
another male referent in the immediately preceding clause (the husband).
The hierarchical approach, which sees the text as a List structure, makes a
more accurate prediction about pronominalization.
The patterns examined in this section describe the major uses of pronouns
in return pops. In the next section we shall see how full NPs tend to be used
in returns.
5.2.4
When the structural relation between two mentions of a referent (or the
propositions containing those mentions) is one other than the relations we
have seen above - that is, other than active, controlling, and certain types of
return pops full NPs are used.
Passages illustrating the use of full NP in relations other than active and
controlling are given below.
Clive looked and thought about pictures through his ambivalence of conformity and
rebellion, often tinged also with unconscious pomposity in his endeavor to be
"serious" seeing what the painter had done in his own effort (like Clive's) to make
something out of the world, to give life some shape other than the patterned shapes
of convention. He had, said Virginia Woolf, an odd gift for making one talk sense.
All Clive's life was a quest for a superior "civilization." Clive needed answers to
109
questions that occurred neither to Leonard nor Lytton, nor to the Stephen girls,
since they had been bred from the first to possess the answers.
Much of this seems to have been latent in the boy, who in a good-natured way
accepted and rebelled against his mother's religious precepts and his father's
concrete world. And yet he wanted approval. He wanted to be right, gentlemanly,
proper; the improprieties would come later. Virginia, in her continuing remarks
about him, said he had the mind of "a peculiarly prosaic and literal type". . . . (A
House of Lions, p. 31)
(1)
(2)
(3)
(4)
(5)
(6)
(7)
(8)
110
elaboration
CD
Issue
background
joint
Issue
evidence
Contrast
Contrast
(t)
(7
and going to went away squeaking a little inside contra-indicates the use of a
pronoun in the return pop (the proposition containing the italicized full
NP).
Another example of full NP used in a return pop which pops over
structurally complex material follows.
Leonard was a young Spartan in the heart of chaotic London. Behind him were
centuries of persecution, violence, death. No more, I suppose, than the centuries
behind the Irish or the Huguenots - or the Puritans, before these also became
persecutors. Yet with important differences. Leonard's people had a longer history
of dispersal, an ingrained learned toughness, a curious mixture of inferiorities and
stubbornness, pride and consciousness of race and status. They had seemed at first
"outlandish" in England; this was a grave handicap in a society with strong
boundaries, cultivated stratifications. Leonard Woolf's heritage was strong: a
Biblical ethic, a sense of the importance of work, a built-in discipline of strength, of
control. One had to be proof against life insults. For the centuries had piled insults
on the Jews and made them prize tenaciously a heritage of righteousness that is the
world order imposed on chaos by the Old Testament - which itself is a record of
chaos, crime, rapacity, persecution and privilege.
Leonard Woolf combined Old Testament virtues with an ingrained English sense
of "fair play". . . . (A House of Lions, p. 21)
Although it is not altogether clear to which nucleus the last line ties back
(probably either Leonard was a young Spartan or Leonard Woolf's heritage
was strong), it is clear that in any case the material popped-over is
structurally complex, as we have defined that notion here.
We have seen in this discussion that the basic pattern is to use full NPs
when the proposition containing the relevant last mention of a referent is not
in an active or controlling state, or if the criteria for pronominalization in
return pops are not met. Below I present a discussion of full NPs in yet
HI
(2)
(3)
(4)
(5)
(6)
(7)
background
^
-_^
^background
^ ^
background
113
Notice, with this association of new rhetorical unit and full NP, that it
would not be accurate to say that pronouns are used when the referent is
mentioned in the immediately preceding text, and that full NPs are used
when the referent is mentioned further back in the text. In my expository
texts, fully 38 per cent (204/541) of the full NPs had their referents
mentioned in the immediately preceding clause, so it is not simple distance
that triggers the use of one anaphoric device over the other. Rather, it is the
rhetorical organization of that distance that determines whether a pronoun
or a full NP is appropriate. Here we find a clear instance in which the nonselective formulations predicting pronominalization whenever the referential distance is small simply fail to account for a widespread anaphoric
phenomenon.
It should be kept in mind that the pattern in this section is, in a sense,
hierarchically superordinate to the other basic patterns and would, in a
rule-ordered system, have to be ordered before the basic patterns in order to
ensure correct output.
Table 5.1 supports the claim that new rhetorical units are associated with
the use of a full NP. Twenty short expository articles were used as the basis
for the figures. Of all of the new rhetorical units started, 65 per cent (77/118)
contained full NPs, while of the continuing rhetorical units, 10 per cent
(6/59) contained full NPs. Thus, while pronouns and full NPs can appear in
either type of slot, there is a skewing of full NP towards new rhetorical unit,
and of pronoun towards continuing rhetorical unit.
Although rhetorical breaks are often signalled in expository prose by
paragraph breaks, it would not be accurate to say simply that in expository
prose all paragraphs begin with full NPs. One of the propositions containing
a pronoun in the passage above is paragraph-initial, though not rhetorical
unit-initial. Thus, while paragraphs are rhetorical units of a sort, they are
not the major units which influence anaphora; the units which do influence
anaphora are R-structures, most notably the adjuncts off of Issue
structures.
Table 5.1 Anaphoric device and position in rhetorical unit
New rhetorical unit
Full NP
77
Pronoun
41
Total
118
(93%)
(65%)
(44%)
(35%)
(7%)
(10%)
(56%)
(90%)
59
Total
83
94
177
(5)
(6)
(7)
(8)
Issue
background
^background
115
All the new adjuncts are started with full NPs; the one proposition which
does not start a new adjunct but continues List structure (6) is done with a
pronoun (In addition, he will oversee . . .).
There is thus a correlation between non-new units and pronouns, as well
as between new units and full NPs.
Further examples of members of a List structure being referred to with a
pronoun are given below.
(1) Lytton's speech was filled with the rhetoric of the past.
(2) He knew his Rousseau;
(3) he knew his Voltaire;
(4) he even knew his President de Brosses! (A House of Lions, p. 39)
(1)
(2)
(3)
(4)
(5)
(6)
(7)
List
(1)
(2)
(3)
(4)
(5)
elaboration
Concession
List
concession
(2)
In each of these examples, the references within the List structures which
are coreferential with the referent in the nucleus (off of which the List is an
adjunct) are done with pronouns. This distribution supports the hypothesis
that it is new rhetorical units that are started with full NPs. In cases where
no new unit is started, a pronoun is used.
The following passage brings up another principle in choosing a full NP
over a pronoun: the greater the internal structure of the just-created
structure, the more likely we are to find the current proposition done with a
full NP, even if the current proposition is a next member in a List or
Narrative structure. That is, a return to a List structure is more likely to be
done with a full NP if the preceding member of the List has its own adjunct
(that is, a structure of its own) than if the preceding member has no internal
structure.
Compare the List and Narrative structures of the Albertson article
(above) with the List structure in the Glaser article (below): the non-initial
members of those structures in the Albertson text are done with pronouns,
while the non-initial member of the List in the Glaser text is done with a full
NP (proposition 6). The reason for this difference in anaphora, according to
the hypothesis proposed here, is that the members of the List and Narrative
117
structures in the Albertson article have no internal structure - they are all
terminal nodes; the first member of the List in question in the Glaser text,
however, has a background adjunct (giving the names of the laboratories),
and the next member of the List (Glaser will also assist. . .) is done with a
full NP.
Remember that in an earlier section we saw that a return to a List
structure over an adjunct of a preceding member of the List could be done
with a pronoun (for example in the Robertson passage above), so I am not
claiming here that such a move must be done with a full NP; rather, given
this other set of structuring principles which takes into account the internal
articulation (Koffka 1935) of the preceding and current units, it can be
done with a full NP.
(1)
(2)
(3)
(4)
(5)
(6)
(7)
(8)
(13)
background
In the preceding discussion we have seen that full NPs can, and very often
do, occur in structural environments in which pronouns would have been
predicted to occur. I claimed that the motivation for the use of full NPs in
these situations is rhetorical organization, whereby the internal cohesiveness and the external discohesiveness of rhetorical units is displayed to the
reader. Notions of participant continuity and paragraphing were shown to
be ineffective in accounting for the rich patterning of anaphora in these
texts.
Different-gender referents
119
This time he married a sturdy Scotswoman with all the hardihood and
endurance of the north - and of her race.
Year after year she bore him children. (A House of Lions, p. 35)
Issue
elaboration
Here, both people mentioned in the nucleus of the Restructure are referred
to with pronouns in the R-structure partner (the adjunct).
A similar example follows, in which two referents, of different genders,
appear in the nucleus of the R-structure, and both are pronominalized in the
adjunct.
(1)
(2)
T
Concession
Issue
background
Different-gender referents
121
elaboration
then an elaboration adjunct with a male referent mentioned in it, and then a
return pop over the adjunct to create a second elaboration adjunct. The
return is done with a pronoun, even though a different-gender referent is
present in the popped-over adjunct. The return pop pattern accounts for
roughly 50 per cent of the pronouns in the environment of different-gender
referents.
In all of my texts I found one passage in which pronominalization was
possible in a different-gender environment when the relevant proposition
was controlling rather than active. This passage is given below.
(1) He prospered.
(2) When Victoria came to the throne,
(3) he was living in a comfortable house. (A House of Lions, p. 19)
Issue
evidence
0)
circumstance
It is worth noting about this passage that the "interfering" differentgender referent comes in the adjunct, rather than the nucleus, of the
embedded structure, and in addition the adjunct itself is structurally simple
(a terminal node). Both of these factors no doubt work together to allow
Full NPs are used in cases where anything more "distant" than the active
pattern is in progress, and in return pops if the popped-over material is
structurally complex.
Passages illustrating the use of full NP in a pattern other than the active
pattern are presented below.
(1)
(2)
(3)
(4)
(5)
Leonard got from her both the pleasures and fear of public events, "the
horrors and iniquities of the great world of society and politics as
recorded in the Baptist Times, about the year 1885."
And all this in the untroubled atmosphere of the Lexham Gardens
third-floor nursery, where the boy felt snug and safe.
The fire blazed behind the tall guard;
the kettle sang musically,
and the music mingled with the nurse's reading of serious things. (A
House of Lions, p. 22)
Issue
background
Q
Issue
elaboration
List
The higher nucleus mentions both the referents - Leonard and his nurse.
We then have an adjunct/nucleus which mentions only Leonard, and the
adjunct on this last item - a List structure - contains a reference to the
nurse, done with a full NP. We thus have a controlling pattern, and a full
NP is used for the critical reference.
Another example follows.
(1)
(2)
(3)
(4)
Same-gender referents
123
Issue
elaboration
Issue
background
Issue
background
As before, included under the active pattern are basically (1) propositions
whose R-structure partners are being developed, and (2) propositions that
are being tied to by a return pop. I examine the first of these below.
Pronominalization is possible in an R-structure partner if two samegender referents are mentioned in the same proposition under the following
conditions:
(a)
(b)
Examples illustrating the first pattern (subject > pronoun) are given below.
(Examples are from A House of Lions unless otherwise indicated.)
This is not to say that Virginia's rivalry with Vanessa had diminished. She oscillated
between abasement and respect.
Old Leslie Stephen sat now in Thoby's rooms in the Trinity Great Court. One by
one the young tried to talk to him.
Lytton could hardly undertake the entire history of Warren Hastings. He would
focus on
Quentin Bell has pointed to an interesting slip of the pen Virginia made in a letter to
her friend Violet Dickinson. She begins by saying
Clive asked Lytton to join the luncheon party. He was a little put out to learn that
Lytton had already met Desmond
While FitzGerald doesn't have a quarrel with this year's grand marshal, union leader
Teddy Gleason, he is annoyed by the selection of IRA fugitive Michael O'Rourke as
honorary grand marshal. (People, March 19, 1984)
Examples illustrating the second pattern follow.
Desmond once remarked that Lytton's friendships at Cambridge were more like
loves. One thinks of him as taking possession
Desmond gave him the Oxford miniature Shakespeare and four volumes of Milton,
so that he would carry into remote parts the immortal utterances of the English
tongue.
There are also situations in which both same-gender referents can be
referred to with pronouns.15 This anaphoric pattern arises only when role
Same-gender referents
125
continuity of subject is maintained; that is, the pronoun which is the subject
of the clause in question must be coreferential with the subject of the clause
of the R-structure partner. From a use-determines-context viewpoint, we
could say that the writer signals to the reader, with the use of two pronouns,
that these pronouns should be interpreted as maintaining the grammatical
roles of the active proposition.
Examples of this pattern are given below.
Lytton had written an earlier essay on Hastings. He had seen him as a "superman"
In the phantasmagoria of her inner world, Virginia loved Vanessa. She wanted total
possession of her.
The active pattern covers about 82 per cent of the pronouns in the
environment of same-gender referents.
Another organization in which pronouns can be used in a same-gender
environment is the List return pop. In this situation, two mentions of the
same person, X, can be separated by references to another, same-gender,
person, Y, and the second mention of person X can be done with a pronoun
if and only if the second mention of X is a return pop to another member of a
List structure (or a proposition containing a mention of X) and the
popped-over adjunct is (a) also a member of the List structure and (b)
structurally simple. Schematically, this pattern would appear thus:
Issue
X
List
X
X (pronoun)
The young face was smooth, with firmly lined brows and liquid
gray-green eyes.
(3) She had sensuous lips.
(4) She rarely used makeup.
(5) Somewhere Virginia speaks of "her passionate mouth."
(6) Her voice was beautifully modulated;
(7) her words were carefully paced. (A House of Lions, p. 78)
Issue
elaboration
u)
List
(9)
Same-gender referents
127
Full NP elsewhere
Full NPs are used whenever the circumstances described above are not met.
Some of the cases in which the circumstances are not met are described
below.
If two same-gender referents are mentioned in a proposition and one of
them is mentioned in that proposition's R-structure partner, then a full NP
will be used for the reference in the second proposition if the referent did not
fill the subject role in the first proposition and was also not mentioned in the
next highest nucleus. Examples illustrating this pattern appear below.
But Lytton could not control Clive's appetite for life. Clive was a hungry-forexperience heterosexual. (A House of Lions, p. 45)
It's not for nothing that Kennedy hagiographer Theodore Sorenson is a co-chairman
of Hart's campaign. As Hart's caravan sped onward . . . (People, March 26, 1984)
Keynes . . . could outplay Lytton. All Lytton could do was (A House of Lions,
p. 119)
She had lied to keep shock and suffering from her [Violet]. But Violet, 18 years
older, needed no such defence. (A House of Lions, p. 136)
Furthermore, if the following situation holds, in which a referent (and only
that referent) is mentioned in an R-structure and then another, samegender, referent is mentioned in the R-structure partner, then a full NP is
used for the reference in the second proposition, regardless of that referent's
status in higher R-structures. In this case, since the referent in the first
proposition is in the active pattern, a pronoun would be heard as referring to
it, rather than to the referent currently being mentioned in the second
proposition (even if the latter is mentioned only two clauses back).
Examples of this phenomenon follow.
Elvis had his gilded belt, Elton his spectacular spectacles and now Michael Jackson
has that glittering glove. Rhinestones a-twinkling, the glove lends its wearer a
magical air - as if he could pluck a rabbit from a hat with the same ridiculous ease
Same-gender referents
129
(3)
List
Ref. 2
Pronoun 1
Same-gender referents
131
background
Interim summary
In this section we have examined the ways in which other referents influence
patterns of anaphora. The basic pattern for other-referent environments
appears to be more restricted than the pattern for environments without
other "interfering" referents in that only the active pattern seems to hold:
that is, referents in propositions whose R-structure partner is being
developed are available for pronominalization - any relationship more
embedded than that induces the use of a full NP.
It is important to reiterate that the mere presence of another referent whether same-gender or different-gender - is not the issue here; the crucial
factors for anaphora have to do with the structural patterning of the clauses
(and also in some cases the grammatical roles of the NPs in question). This
critical feature of anaphora accounts for the lack of success some researchers
have experienced in quantifying referent ambiguity and its effect on
anaphora (see Givon 1983). Before we begin quantifying ambiguity, we
need to explore qualitatively, as I have tried to do here, the structural factors
that influence anaphoric patterning.
As Schegloff (p. c) has pointed out, any next reference to a person is a place
where further information about that person can be added. In my
expository texts, this fact is often realized through the use of a full NP complete with modifiers- in situations in which a pronoun would have been
possible according to the structural patterns presented earlier. This
technique is especially widely used in short articles, in which space is at a
premium, and therefore any piece of information that can be packaged in a
modifier or relative clause (instead of a full sentence) will appear in this
"condensed" form, as part of a full NP (Dillon 1981, suggests that this
strategy is used to "add more information about the thing, semicovertly, as
it were" (p. 99)). Examples of this phenomenon follow.
There was one whose passion for literature was imparted to the small boy. Mr. Floyd
made Leonard "dimly aware that lessons - things of the mind - could be exciting and
even amusing." (A House of Lions, p. 23)
Here the full NP is used to introduce a previously unknown name for a
character that was already introduced (one). I do not mean to claim that this
is the only reason that a full NP is used here - the structural principle
discussed in section 5.3 on demarcating rhetorical units may also be
involved; I mean to suggest only that at least part of the motivation for using
a proper noun in this passage may be what I have called the "further
information" function of full NPs.
He was rescued Sunday after crawling to the top of the ravine, where he collapsed
and was spotted by hikers.
"They told me their names," he said. "I forgot them, but I'll never forget their
faces."
The lance corporal was on leave from his job as a small-arms repairman at Camp
Pendleton. (Los Angeles Times, July 26, 1983)
Before this passage, we did not know that Bell was a lance corporal, a fact
that may be significant in judging how well he performed under the stressful
Non-structural factors
133
In these passages again, full NPs are used in conjunction with reduced
pieces of added information (non-restrictive relative clauses). The slots
could have been filled with a pronoun (by the rules of return pop for the
environment of no "interfering" referents) or with full NPs (by the rules of
rhetorical unit demarcation); but we can say again that at least part of the
reason for using a full NP in these cases is the fact that "piggyback"
information is being brought in here in the form of relative clauses, and a
full NP is required for the syntactic environment Referent + relative clause.
5.6.2
Classification
In all of these passages, full NPs are used to categorize the referents,
rather than just establish the referent's identity for the reader.
The difference between this pattern and the previous non-structural
pattern lies in the newness of the information conveyed by the modification:
in the first pattern ("further information"), the reader is given, in a densely
packaged form, new information about the referent; in the second pattern
("classification"), already-known information is used to bring out the
membership-in-a-category facet of the referent's identity. For example, we
knew before reading the passages given above that Leonard was a "young
Jew" and that Clive Bell tended to be thought of as a name-dropper, and that
the person in London (Leonard Woolf) was a young boy.
It is a curious fact about this particular pattern of anaphora that it tends to
occur mainly in literary texts (while the "further information" pattern
occurs in all text-types, although concentrated in short articles). Perhaps
the use of this device, since it does little in the way of hard-core information
conveying, carries a flavor of flowery variation that is more typical of literary
texts than, say, short articles in a university bulletin.
5.6.3
It is very often the case that a reference will be done with a full NP if the
referent is being contrasted or compared, either implicitly or explicitly,
with other people. Examples from A House of Lions are given below.
He [Leonard] also describes how he learned to be the kind of "I" who watches
himself as if he were double - "not I." This kind of self-awareness has been sketched
by many others, not least Emerson and William James in their "me" and "not me." In
Leonard it seemed as if he were both actor and observer: "I cannot avoid continually
watching myself playing a part on the stage." (p. 24)
His [Clive's] laughter was an explosive spasm or guffaw, and in his youth he
possessed distinct crudities that made him seem like some young rural squire out of
Fielding rather than a sensitive poetry-conscious undergraduate at an ancient
college. Leonard Woolf's early environment had been that of a middle-class
intellectual and of a city-bred boy. Arthur Clive Heward Bell's was middle-class
hunting and fishing, (p. 27)
Summary
135
School for Lytton was erratic as well as erotic: his mother worried about his health;
she was determined to ease his life. Unlike Leonard, unlike Clive, who were hearty,
healthy boys, who loved games and learned their Latin and Greek well, and were
heterosexuals, Lytton was not subjected to formal public schools, (p. 37)
At the end of his [Maynard Keynes's] time at Eton, he lived in the school as if it were
his own fine country house and cooperated with his friends in running it. Unlike
Leonard, Clive and Lytton, sons of suburb, countryside, metropolis, John
Maynard Keynes was "all" Cambridge, (p. 48)
The claim being made here is that the use of the (italicized) full NP in each
passage is motivated, at least in part, by the comparative or contrastive
nature of its proposition. I do not mean to imply that this is the only
motivation for using a full NP in all of thf se cases (for example, the last
passage is also an illustration of "further information," since it offers the first
use of the name of the person under discussion); but the comparative/
contrastive aspect needs to be taken into account if we are to explain the full
range of anaphoric patterning in expository texts.
In the preceding sections I have presented some types of non-structureoriented communicative functions which seem to favor the use of full NP. 16
The underlying proposal of this presentation has been that, while hierarchic
structure relations are crucial in the patterning of anaphora in written
English texts, they are not responsible for every use of all the anaphoric
devices that are available to us in English; some of these uses have other
communicative functions as their source. These non-structural uses of
various anaphoric devices have been ignored in recent discourse analysis,
especially with regard to written material, so it is important that they be
recognized in a full treatment of anaphora.
5.7
Summary
6.1
Introduction
139
compare what one typically does when writing with what one typically does
when speaking:
. . . There is no a priori reason why "functionally equivalent" tasks are in fact
"comparable" across the two modes. In a comparison of academic expository prose
and academic lectures, for example, we mightfindfew linguistic differences, and be
tempted to conclude that speech utilizes "literate strategies" and thereby confirm the
view that there are not major differences between speech and writing. But this
conclusion would ignore the fact that lectures, although spoken, are not typical of
the spoken mode. . . . Thus, even though a study of this type would control for
communicative factors, from one perspective it would not be based on comparable
tasks. Rather, it would contrast a typical written task with a highly untypical spoken
task. (Biber 1983: 9)
In light of this discussion, I have chosen to use Biber's notion of
comparability as a basis for choosing "comparable" texts. For the present
study I have selected a large group of expository monologic written texts
from a range of sources which are compared, with respect to anaphora, with
naturally occurring conversations among friends and/or relatives.
We can now turn to a comparison of the anaphoric patterns in the written
and conversational texts.
141
2.52
1.21
Conversational
Written
Full NP
Pronoun
Total
87
548
306
608
393
1,156
(22%)
(47%)
(78%)
(53%)
the proportion of each anaphoric device in the two text types. Although, as
we saw in Chapters 3 and 5, the most recent mention of a referent is not
always the relevant antecedent mention, for conformity with the counting
procedures developed in Givon 1983 I have adopted the most recent
mention as the critical reference. The results suggest that (a) full NPs are
much more prevalent in expository written texts than they are in
conversational texts, and (b) the referential distance for pronouns is much
greater in the conversational texts than it is in the written texts.
Long-distance pronominalization - either of the embedding type or of the
return pop type- is thus basically non-existent in the written texts. There is
thus no single abstract pattern with which we could associate terms like
topic, focus, or consciousness (see Fox, forthcoming, b, for a fuller
discussion of this point). Even for the basic pattern there are too many
differences, brought about by convention and channel limitations (Dillon
1981), to allow us to formulate a unifying strategy of anaphora.5
6.3.1
143
closed-off material, traces which the reader's eye may return to; hence the
reader is less likely to forget the material. Perhaps because of the traces,
then, the intervening material assumes a greater importance in the attention
of the reader than it does when there are no physical traces, and as a result
what appears to be distance assumes a correspondingly greater importance
for anaphora (Dillon 1981; Rubin 1980).
A note of caution regarding such explanations is in order, however. As I
have shown elsewhere (Fox, forthcoming, a), not all genres of written text
show such conservative (and possibly distance-influenced) patterns of
anaphora; the patterns exhibited by written narratives, for example, more
closely resemble the patterns of the conversational texts than those of the
expository texts. It must thus be conceded that it is not just the physical
facts of writing that influence anaphora; the conventions established for
each written genre are also critical in the process.8
Referent not in
preceding clause
Total
Written
Full NP 207
Pronoun 513
Total
(38%)
(29%)
(84%)
(71%)
720
Conversational
Full NP 10 (11%)
(6%)
Pronoun 151 (49%)
(94%)
Total
161
341
95
(62%)
(78%)
(16%)
(22%)
436
77
155
232
548
608
1,156
(89%)
(33%)
(51%)
(67%)
87
306
393
Different-gender referents
145
Awr:: lght.
= 0') fix us u:p.
N.
H.
If both referents are mentioned in the same proposition, then either one
of them can be pronominalized in the R-structure partner.
2 In a return pop situation, if the popped-over material is structurally
non-complex, then the returned-to referent can be pronominalized.
The differences in distribution are discussed below.
In written expository English texts, then, we do not find a pronoun used
to refer to a person in the adjunct of a structure if there is a reference to a
different-gender person in the nucleus of that R-structure. This pattern
differs from the situation in the conversational material in the following
sense. Let me suggest that an adjacency pair and a tying pair can be seen as
roughly equivalent to the nucleus of an R-structure and an embedded
R-structure realization of its adjunct. That is, the following structures can
be seen to be basically equivalent:
fpp => spp
"ft
\
Conversational
Full NP
Pronoun
51
32
7
18
Total
83
(61%)
(39%)
(28%)
(72%)
25
Same-gender referents
147
Conversational
Full NP
Pronoun
142
21
9
12
Total
163
(87%)
(13%)
(43%)
(57%)
21
Written:
Full NP
Pronoun
Total
No interfering referents
Different-gender
Same-gender
312
553
51
32
142 (87%)
21 (13%)
(36%)
(64%)
(61%)
(39%)
865
83
Conversational:
Full NP
Pronoun
16 (6%)
272 (94%)
7 (28%)
18 (72%)
9 (43%)
12 (57%)
Total
288
25
21
163
6.7
In Chapters 3 and 5,1 proposed that there are factors other than structural
ones that affect the anaphoric patterning in texts. That is, I was suggesting
that it is not just the hierarchic organization of clauses and propositions that
determines which anaphoric device will be used at any given point; rather,
there are non-structural factors which also, in perhaps a secondary way,
influence anaphoric choices. The non-structural factors which were claimed
to be relevant for the anaphoric distribution in each of the modes are listed
in Table 6.7. The factors which involve multi-party interaction are
obviously excluded from the written material (this includes disagreements
and replacements of utterances). The others are discussed below.
149
Written
Replacement of an utterance
Disagreeing
Further description
Classification
Comparison and contrast
Overt recognitionals
Assessments
Category membership
In this passage it seems clear that an assessment is being done with a full NP.
The pattern is not widely enough documented to treat it as an established
151
7 Conclusions
7.1 Localness
In Chapter 6, I raised the issue of genre-specific conventions of anaphoric
patterning. As we have seen, there is no single rule for anaphora that can be
specified for all of English (even the limited subset of third-person singular
human examined here); instead, we have a variety of specific patterns which
obviously share a number of general characteristics, but which nevertheless
differ enough to require separate formulation (Fox, forthcoming, b). This
is one level at which patterns are local (specific to a particular genre) rather
than global (specifiable for all of English). There are other levels at which
the idea of localness seems fruitful; it is to these levels that I would like to turn
now.
In his paper "Meaning and memory," Bolinger (1976) presents a model of
language in which a single language is viewed as a "gerry-rigged" system
with no overarching structure; instead, there is tight structure at a lower,
local level, and only loose connections between these tightly organized local
segments (this corresponds in some ways with Wittgenstein's metaphor of
language as a European city). Forms are related by analogy in a pattern of
Localness
153
154 Conclusions
basic in understanding language than has been assumed previously (see also
Bates and MacWhinney, forthcoming; Brooks 1978; Serwatka 1986;
Hopper 1986; and others working in the Connectionist paradigm: Hinton
and Anderson 1981; McClelland and Rumelhart 1985); it is from this local
organization that more general rules and abstractions emerge:
Schemata are not "things." There is no representational object which is a schema.
Rather, schemata emerge at the moment they are needed from the interaction of
large numbers of much simpler elements all working in concert with one another.
Schemata are not explicit entities, but rather are implicit in our knowledge and are
created by the very environment that they are trying to interpret - as it is
interpreting them. (Rumelhart et al. 1986: 18)
This view of patterns as emergent from smaller structures represents a clear
break from the philosophies of language behavior now widely accepted in
linguistics and cognitive science. As such, it is a critical step forward in our
understanding of linguistic behavior.
Conclusion
155
7.3 Conclusion
This model of language, which sees patterning as emergent from smaller,
specific instances, and structure as emerging from the interaction of many
smaller units, comes at a time when new ways of looking at language
behavior, especially discourse behavior, are critical if we are to extend our
understanding of the relationships between language, cognition, and
society. The patterns of anaphora described in this study, in all their
variety, are offered in the spirit of this new tradition of locally emergent
structure, in celebration of the apparent paradox of the local yet abstract
nature of linguistic behavior.
Notes
Introduction
Conversational analysis
1 Reichman (1981) develops a relevant method of analyzing conversation which
she calls "context space theory." It is not complete enough to use for the data I
examine here - it does not, for example, cover interactional units like invitations,
announcements, and their various responses - but her style of analysis has been
critical for some of the notions developed in Chapters 3 and 5, so it is worth
giving a brief overview of her method here.
In this work, Reichman distinguishes twelve relations: support, restatement
of point being supported, interruption, return after interruption, indirect
challenge, direct challenge, concede subargument, prior logical abstraction,
contrastive respecification, analogy, further development.
In addition, each context space - similar to Grosz's focus space - is assigned a
status that reflects its current prominence in the conversation. Some of the
statuses, with their definitions, are given below (Reichman 1981:86). Reichman
uses these statuses in analyzing the anaphora in her data.
Active
157
5
6
159
161
14 In some cases, strictly following one of the principles can make a genre-related
statement, as in the obituary given below - an obituary of a young feminist,
written by a feminist writer for a feminist audience:
Joan Kelly, a leading feminist scholar, teacher, and activist, died of cancer
on August 15, 1982, in New York City.
A founding member of the Renaissance Society of America, she wrote
an important book: Leone Batista Alberti: Universal Man of the
Renaissance. Later, she was to question whether the Renaissance really
did champion a universal humanist ethic for women as well as for men in
her classic essay, "Did Women have a Renaissance?"
Her early political activities marked the beginning of a lifelong
commitment to combine activism with scholarship, practice with theory.
She helped to found the United Federation of College Teachers and
worked for a policy of open enrollment in the City College of New York as
a practical means of overcoming discrimination against minority groups.
During the 1960s she was also deeply involved in the antiwar movement.
In the late 1960s her interests turned to feminism and socialism. . . .
(Ms, December 1982)
The genre convention of beginning new rhetorical units with full NPs is ignored
in this obituary, which almost certainly makes some statement about the
relationship between the writer and the reader and the norms of the larger
society.
15 Cf. Reichman 1981, in which it is claimed that only one referent is in high focus
(and hence pronominalizable) at a time.
16 It is interesting to note in this regard that all the cases described here have
involved the use of full NP where we could have expected pronouns; I found no
non-structural factors which "induced" the use of pronoun where we could have
expected full NP.
6 Anaphora in expository written and conversational English
1 I have avoided the term spoken in this study because it includes all texts
produced by mouth - even orally produced monologues (such as classroom
lectures or speeches). Since I have concentrated explicitly on non-monologic
and spontaneous spoken language, I have preferred to use the narrower term
conversational.
2 An excellent review of the literature on spoken and written language is provided
in Akinnaso 1982.1 have omitted discussion of much of that literature here, since
it is not relevant to the phenomenon under study.
3 I see nothing wrong with defining these terms operationally, in terms of
discourse structure, except that it further burdens already overworked
terminology.
4 This measurement technique is based on the method developed in Giv6n 1983.
5 Cf. Wittgenstein(1958: 12):
If you do not keep the multiplicity of language-games in view, you will
163
referent of the same gender was mentioned in the preceding clause (a) as the
grammatical subject of that clause, or (b) as the only referent in the clause. Initial
mentions of referents were excluded from the count.
13 Recall that further description includes full NPs like the lance corporal which
provide information that was previously unknown about a referent; classification
includes full NPs like the Swede or the child, which provide no new information
about the referent but only serve to place the referent in a category.
14 Phrases which convey negative or positive assessment are used with great elan the dirty bastard, etc. - and are accounted for under Affect and Assessment.
7
Conclusions
1 Some of the points made in the following discussion have also been made in Fox,
forthcoming, b.
2 The analogy with light as particle and light as wave is an apt one, since we can see
light as both static and a dynamic process, depending on our purposes; see
Young et al. 1970.
3 Except perhaps when viewed as a finished transcript by an analyst.
References
References
165
166
References
Keenan, E. and Bennett, T. (eds.) 1977. Discourse across time andspace. Southern
California Occasional Papers in Linguistics 5. Los Angeles: University of
Southern California.
Kintsch, W. 1974. The representation of meaning in memory. Hillsdale, NJ:
Erlbaum.
Koffka, K. 1935. Principles of gestalt psychology. New York: Harcourt Brace.
Ladefoged, P. 1980. What are linguistic sounds made of? Language, 56: 485-502.
Levinson, S. 1983. Pragmatics. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
Linde, C. 1979. Focus of attention and the choice of pronouns in discourse. In T.
Givon (ed.), Syntax and Semantics, vol. 12. New York: Academic Press.
McClelland, J. and Rumelhart, D. 1985. Distributed memory and the representation of general and specific. Journal of Experimental Psychology, 114: 159-88.
McHoul, A. 1982. Telling how texts talk: essays on reading and ethnomethodology.
New York: Routledge & Kegan Paul.
McKeown, K. 1982. Generating natural language text in response to questions
about database structure. PhD Dissertation, University of Pennsylvania.
Mandler, J. and Johnson, N. 1977. Remembrance of things parsed: story structure
and recall. Cognitive Psychology, 9: 111-51.
Mann, W., Matthiessen, C , and Thompson, S. 1982. Rhetorical structures report.
MS.
Marslen-Wilson, W., Levy, E., and Tyler, L. 1982. Producing interpretable
discourse. In Jarvella and Klein (eds.), Chichester: Wiley.
Matthiessen, C. and Thompson, S., forthcoming. "Subordination" and the
structure of discourse. In J. Haiman and S. Thompson (eds.), Clause combining
in grammar and discourse. Amsterdam: Benjamins.
Mayer, R. 1985. Structural analysis of science prose: can we increase problemsolving performance? In Britton and Black 1985.
Meyer, B. 1985. Prose analysis: purposes, procedures, and problems. In Britton
and Black 1985.
- and Rice, G. E. 1982. The interaction of reader strategies and the organization of
text. Text, 2(1): 155-92.
Ochs, E. 1979a. Transcription as theory. In E. Ochs and B. Schieffelin (eds.),
Developmental pragmatics. New York: Academic Press.
- 1979b. Planned and unplanned discourse. In T. Givon (ed.), Syntax and
semantics, vol. 12. New York: Academic Press.
O'Donnell, R. 1974. Syntactic differences between speech and writing. American
Speech, 49: 102-10.
Partee, B. 1984. Nominal and temporal anaphora. Linguistics and Philosophy, 7(3):
243-86.
Pomerantz, A. 1975. Second assessments. PhD Dissertation, University of
California, Irvine.
References
167
168
References
Author index
Kamp, H. 77
Keenan, E. O. 137
Kintsch, W. 1, 77, 78, 91, 155
Koffka, K. 117
D'Angelo, F. 77
de Beaugrande, R. 77
Decker, R. 3
Dillon, G. 2, 77, 78, 132, 139, 141, 143,
155
Dressier, W. 159nl
Drew, P. 6, 15
Du Bois, J. 2
Duranti, A. 2, 62, 64
Fillmore, C. 73
Fox, B. 141, 143, 152, 159n25, 162n8,
163nl
Garrod, S. 77, 157n2
Giv6n, T. 1, 18, 45, 107, 131, 139, 141,
161n4
Goodman, S. 3, 77, 78
Goodwin, C. 15
Graesser, A. 3, 77, 78
Ladefoged, P. 154
Levinson, S. 6, 10, 11, 12, 15
Levy, E. 112
Linde, C. 1, 62, 150
McClelland, J. 153, 154, 155, 159nl
McHoul, A. 93
McKeown, K. 77
Mandler, J. 78, 159nl
Mann, W. 3, 77
MacWhinney, B. 154
Marslen-Wilson, W. 1, 56, 112, 157n2
Matthiessen, C. 3
Mayer, A. 78
Meyer, B. 77, 78, 96, 159n2
Montgomery, M. 15
Ochs, E. 137, 156n2
O'Donnell, R. 137
Serwatka, M. 154
Sidner, C. 1, 76
Smolensky, P. 153, 155, 159nl
Tannen, D. 137, 151
Terasaki, A. 15
Thavenius, C. 75
Thompson, S. 3, 77
Tomlin, R. 112
Tyler, L. 1, 56, 112, 157n2
van Dijk, T. 1, 77, 78, 91, 155
Voloshinov, V. 152
Webber, B. 1
Winterowd, W. 77
Wittgenstein, L. 2, 152, 161n5
Young, R. 77, 163n2
Subject index
active state (of a discourse unit): 48, 51,
57, 95-9, 105, 118, 119, 120-4, 1289, 135, 139, 156nl
adjacency pair chain: 37-8, 158nl4
adjacency pairs: see conversational analysis
adjunct (definition of): 79, 101
affective factors (in discourse): 1, 4, 624,
66
ambiguity: 3, 48, 50-4, 56-7, 60, 108,
123, 128, 131
anaphora:
basic patterns, in conversation: 1845;
in writing: 95111
comparison of conversation and writing:
137-51
different gender: 3; conversation vs.
writing: 144-7; in conversation: 45-8;
in writing: 11823
non-structural patterns (in
conversation): 6275
non-structural patterns (in writing):
132-5
same gender: 3; conversation vs.
writing: 147-8; in conversation: 48
62; in writing: 123-31
traditional theories of: 18, 31, 41, 53,
99, 107, 113, 141, 142, 162n6
apartment layout narratives: 150
assessments: 66, 75, 149-50, 163nl4
breaks in structure: see demarcating new
unit
classification (of a referent): 133-4, 1501
comparison and contrast: 134-5, 150
cognitive science: 1, 154
connectionism: 154; see also local
patterning
consciousness, hearer's: 1, 139
context (determines use) 16-17, 93
context space theory: 156nl
controlling state (of a discourse unit): 95
6, 99-108, 122-3, 135, 139, 156nl
conventions (in discourse): 2, 141, 151;
see also genre
Subject index
text-types: 1, 138-40
comparability of: 138-9
see also genre
texturing: 77
topic: 139-141
topic continuity: 56, 118; see also
anaphora, traditional theories of
transcripts (of conversations): 6
transcription notation: 6-8
173