Pseudo Intellectual Property
Pseudo Intellectual Property
Charles W. Evans1
abstract
Information conforms to the economic definition of 'public good'. Any particular sample
of information is, effectively, a number, and 'ownership' of information is tantamount to
'ownership' of a number. For this reason, legal traditions based on property are ill-suited
to the regulation of information usage rights. We conclude that the contemporary
'intellectual property' rights regime is undergoing a restructuring and that a new regime
based on the legal traditions of contract is emerging more or less spontaneously.
introduction
1 To comment on this paper, please subscribe to the Free Curricula Centre's Discuss List by sending
email to [email protected].
2 Eagles, (1977), "Hotel California," Hotel California, Los Angeles: Elektra/Asylum Records.
Free Curricula Centre Working Paper No. 1 (orig: Aug 2004; this: Feb 2005)
1 of 26
the greater the sovereignty of the consumer and the more efficiently sellers are eliminated
from their entrepreneurial positions when they do not conform to consumers' demands.
In spite of this, "software piracy in China has triggered a much sterner reaction from the
United States than has widespread human-rights violations." (Fisher 1999). The tacit
assumption is that consumers should conform to supplier sovereignty; i.e., that 'pirating'
is evidence of consumer malfeasance rather than supplier recalcitrance. This results, in
part, from the notion that information is a sub-category of property and that unauthorized
copying of information is a sub-category of theft.
Rarely, do journalists question the premises upon which such assumptions are based and
the worldview implied by this terminology goes largely unchallenged. Here, we analyze
market structure, the nature of information, the tensions that exist when business models
are inconsistent with the markets that managers choose to operate in, and solutions based
on contract for the failure of the property metaphor for information.
market structure
In general, the spectrum of market structures runs from Centrally Administered at one
extreme to Public Goods at the other. In between are: Monopoly, Cartel, Oligopoly,
Competitive, and Commodity markets. (Eucken, 1992, 1948)
Monopoly markets have one supplier of a good or service, who can set either price or
quantity supplied, though generally not both3. Unlike the case in centrally administered
markets, consumers of the monopolist's output do so through voluntary transactions and
have the option of not consuming. The distinguishing characteristic of a monopoly
market is price discrimination. In any other market structure buyers, who are charged a
price higher than what other buyers pay, can seek out alternative suppliers. Auctioning
and targeted discounts, are prima facie evidence of monopoly.
Monopoly can be artificial, as in the case of patent, copyright, or franchise, all of which
are created through government action; institutional, as in the case of trademark, which
has evolved as the product of commercial custom; or natural, as in the case of specialized
knowledge, talents, and trade secrets.
Oligopoly markets have a small number of suppliers of a good or service, each of whom
is large relative to the overall market. Oligopolies exist in soft drinks, petroleum, and
3 There are special cases, as when a monopolist does not seek to maximize profit, but these are
unrepresentative of the norm and beyond the scope of this paper.
Free Curricula Centre Working Paper No. 1 (orig: Aug 2004; this: Feb 2005)
2 of 26
airlines, among others. The distinguishing characteristic of an oligopoly market is
interdependence, meaning that the suppliers watch each other very closely, since a sale for
one is a lost sale for the others. Price wars are prima facie evidence of oligopoly.
Cartel markets are a special case of oligopoly, wherein the oligopolists cooperate as a
collective monopoly. This collusion can be explicit, as in the case of trade associations,
labor unions, and organized crime networks, or it can be implicit or tacit, as in the case of
car dealerships, shops in tourist destinations, and many suppliers of professional services,
where a game theoretic of 'don’t rock the boat' prevails. Complaints among suppliers
about 'unfair competition' are prima facie evidence of cartel.
Rivalry within a cartel or oligopoly can be fierce, and even violent. However, we reserve
the term 'competitive' to describe a very different phenomenon, as we see below.
Competitive markets are characterized by large numbers of buyers and sellers, none of
whom represents a significant fraction of the overall market, along with relatively low
barriers to entry and exit. A market can be globally competitive, but locally monopolistic
or oligopolistic, as in the case of many retail outlets. For example, a shop owner might be
able to sell his total output without affecting world prices of the goods that he or she
supplies, yet be either the only or one of a very few shopkeepers in town.
When analyzing markets, it is important to bear such limits in mind. The case of
Microsoft is illustrative here. Microsoft has a global monopoly on the authorized
production of copies of MS Office and MS Windows, in the forms of copyright, patent,
and trademark. Microsoft also has a natural monopoly in the form of brand recognition.
Even though globally there are technologically superior substitutes for Microsoft products
that are available for free, including OpenOffice and NeoOffice, inter alia, in office suite
software and Linux and FreeBSD, inter alia, in operating systems, Microsoft is the local
monopoly provider of such software within many organizations.
Commodity markets are like competitive markets with the distinction that their output is
homogeneous. In other words, one farmer's wheat is fungible with all others'. Likewise,
beef, metal ores, etc. Commodity markets are similar, though not identical to, what some
economists call 'perfect competition', which is a theoretical construct that does not exist
in the real world. The distinguishing characteristic of commodity markets is that
suppliers can sell their entire output without affecting world prices.
Public goods markets are distinguished by output that is non-rivalrous, i.e., one's
consumption does not adversely affect another's, and non-excludable, i.e., one cannot
prevent others from consuming it. Global examples include breathable air, language, and
information. Local public goods are known as club goods, which are available to all
members of some group, but not to non-members. Examples include green areas at a
country club, streets in a private community, etc. On a national scale, military defense,
police protection, and similar services are considered public goods by residents of those
Free Curricula Centre Working Paper No. 1 (orig: Aug 2004; this: Feb 2005)
3 of 26
jurisdictions, but non-residents are generally excluded4. The critical factor here is that the
marginal cost of producing one more unit of consumption is effectively zero, and thus the
market price is effectively zero.
There are few pure public goods in the world Ɨ like air, seawater, etc. Ɨ but there are
many near-public goods, like national parks, beaches, etc. In all these cases, the price of
use is zero, unless they are organized as a club with restricted access. If one tried to
charge a price for air, then potential buyers would simple go to where they can acquire it
for free. Attempts to charge prices for public goods are generally dismissed by the public.
Innovation and invention inexorably dilute monopoly power, pushing markets away from
central administration and monopoly toward competition and public goods. Where there
are monopoly profits to be earned, potential competitors have an incentive to bring
substitutes to market that undercut the monopolist's price, but not enough to eliminate
profit margins completely. For example, a monopoly electricity utility invites competition
in the form of solar panels, fuel cells, windmills, etc., some of which have become
efficient enough in terms of kilowatts-per-dollar to be economically viable in some
remote areas. Thus, competition tends to transform markets from monopoly to oligopoly,
oligopoly to competition, competition to commodity, and commodity to public goods.
(Fuller, 1982)
Mutual funds and private money schemes compete against central banks in the production
of media of exchange. Independent filmmakers and Bollywood compete against
Hollywood in the production of entertainment. Open source software initiatives compete
against commercial software developers in the production of operating systems and
applications.
Marketing, trade associations, and co-opting of the regulatory process are used to
concentrate monopoly power, pushing markets away from commodity toward oligopoly
and monopoly. For example, farmers can differentiate their crops by promoting them as
branded specialty products – e.g., Uncle Bob's Organic Rice, rather than mere commodity
rice – and local merchants can band together to petition for stricter barriers to entry.
In the realm of computer operating systems, we see both forces at work. On the one
hand, unpriced Linux variants have broken Microsoft's monopoly in many sectors,
pushing away from monopoly and toward public goods, while RedHat, YellowDog,
et.al., sell branded versions of Linux that command a premium, pushing away from public
goods and commodity toward competition and natural oligopoly.
Successful entrepreneurs find opportunities in the tensions created by these two forces.
4 We ignore here very interesting cases, like imperialism, international treaty, and other extra-national
expansion of public goods.
Free Curricula Centre Working Paper No. 1 (orig: Aug 2004; this: Feb 2005)
4 of 26
<sidebar>
a note on advertising
5 This contrast is exploited in the movie Brazil (Gilliam 1985), which features advertisements for ducts
from the single bureaucratic supplier, Central Services. The juxtaposition of market medium and
command message creates a tension for comedic purposes.
Free Curricula Centre Working Paper No. 1 (orig: Aug 2004; this: Feb 2005)
5 of 26
-. --- - .... .. -. --.
property
In linguistics, the Whorf-Sapir Hypothesis (Sapir, 1929; Whorff, 1956) holds that the
languages that we speak and our worldviews are interdependent, and that this affects both
how individuals understand the world, form expectations, and implement plans (Sapir,
1929; Whorf, 1956). This idea underlies popular novels, such as We (Zamyatin, 1999),
Anthem (Rand, 1996), and 1984 (Orwell, 1990), in which language is used as a tool of
control. Gadamer's (1989) analysis of culture, which expands on this idea and is widely
cited in the post-moderninst literature, concludes that the meaning of a text will be
different from reader to reader, due to differences in knowledge, experience, and context.
Gadamer's work has been highly influential among some economists who have embraced
this method, known as 'hermeneutics' (Ebeling, 1986; Lachmann, 1990; Lavoie, 1986 &
1990). In the realm of science, Kuhn (1996) and Popper (1977) observe that the
formulation of questions that are considered relevant by the status quo has a strong
influence on which phenomena are studied, the methodologies employed, and the
incorporation of the knowledge discovered into subsequent analysis.
Legal scholars including Cohen (1935), Fisher (1999), Hunter (2002), Lemley (2004b),
and many others, point out that legislation and judicial precedent are often based on
metaphor, ideology, and circular reasoning, especially when the expansion of a category
of rights to cover new technology, shifts in the relative economic importance of
industries, or market process innovation is involved. Although it is not their intention and
they do not state it explicitly, these, and numerous authors whom they cite, provide
evidence confirming the Whorff-Sapir Hypothesis throughout the legislative and judicial
processes in their critiques of legal decisions based on the ideas of, e.g., cyberspace as a
place, information as a private good, and frustrated expectations as theft.
Here, economists have much learn from sociologists. Mainstream neoclassical economics
and New Institutional Economics assume that whatever institutions we observe are, by
definition, the most efficient. Economic Sociology and Austrian School Economics, on
the other hand, recognize that much of what we observe in the realm of human action
Free Curricula Centre Working Paper No. 1 (orig: Aug 2004; this: Feb 2005)
6 of 26
consists of fossilized accidents of history and that there are significant costs involved
with replacing institutions. Ours might not be the best of all possible worlds, but it is the
one that we are in. (Granovetter, 1985; Granovetter & Swedberg, 2001; Lachmann, 1971;
Swedberg, 2003; Weber, 1978)
How the current 'intellectual property' regime came about was not an objective process
that reflected some noumenal reality. It was a social process, in which interested parties
petitioned judges and legislators, who made decisions based on arguments made by and
on precedents cited by the disputants in specific cases and the ideology, rent seeking, and
understanding of economic value theory of the individuals involved (Cohen, 1935; Fisher,
1999). As these decisions became precedents for future legal action and lobbying efforts,
path dependencies were created that resulted in today's 'intellectual property' regime.6
A crude analogy here would be mandating that π=3. Granted, a legislature could do this,
but that would not make it so. The existence of a statute, regulation, or precedent
decreeing information to be a form of property does not necessarily conform to the
underlying reality. There are fundamental differences between apples and haiku. Apples
are excludable and rivalrous private goods; haiku is a public good. Using the legislature
to create a monopoly in the production of a public good is bound to fail, as well as
undermine the public's respect for legislation, regulation, and judicial process in general,
as we discuss in detail below.
6 We leave it to students of Public Choice and Law & Economics to analyze the details of linguistic and
rhetorical effects on political action.
Free Curricula Centre Working Paper No. 1 (orig: Aug 2004; this: Feb 2005)
7 of 26
Language is socially useful apart from law, as air is socially useful, but
neither language nor air is a source of economic wealth unless some
people are prevented from using these resources in ways that are permitted
to other people. That is to say, property is a function of inequality. If
courts, for instance, should prevent a man from breathing any air which
had been breathed by another (within, say, a reasonable statute of
limitations), those individuals who breathed most vigorously and were
quickest and wisest in selecting desirable locations in which to breathe (or
made the most advantageous contracts with such individuals) would, by
virtue of their property right in certain volumes of air, come to exercise
and enjoy a peculiar economic advantage, which might, though various
modes of economic exchange, be turned into other forms of economic
advantage, e.g. the ownership of newspapers or fine clothing. So, if courts
prevent a man from exploiting certain forms of language which another
has already begun to exploit, the second user will be at the economic
disadvantage of having to pay the first user from the privilege of using
similar language or else of having to use less appealing language
(generally) in presenting his commodities to the public. (Cohen, 1935)
With 'intellectual property', we have gone well beyond mere metaphor and now have an
expansion of the definition of 'property' to include the opposite of the original concept
upon which legal traditions of property are founded.
For example, if one duplicated a CD, DVD, book, or other physical embodiment of
information and returned the original to the owner, this would neither reduce the owner's
ability to enjoy his or her copy, nor would it reduce the original creator's ability to make
future copies.
It is often asserted, though never proven, that unauthorized copying represents net loss of
sales. However, such assertions rarely contain falsifiable – thus, testable – claims.
(Popper, 1977) First, given the unknowability of the future, it is impossible to know if a
particular consumer of an unauthorized copy of some information would have bought an
authorized copy at the monopoly price if unauthorized copies had not been available. If
the consumer would have bought an authorized copy, then the 'pirating' would represent a
lost sale; otherwise, it would not. If a particular consumer of an unauthorized copy of
some information would not have purchased an authorized copy at the monopoly price,
Free Curricula Centre Working Paper No. 1 (orig: Aug 2004; this: Feb 2005)
8 of 26
then the consumption of the unauthorized copy would not represent a lost sale, and thus
no damage would have occurred.7 In this regard, possession of unauthorized copies of
information is categorically unlike theft and more like listening to a song playing over the
radio or streamed over the Internet.
Second, to claim that the publisher is a victim, based on the observation that actual sales
are less than projected sales fails several economic tests, not least of which is the
unknowability of the future. No one knows how many of those unauthorized copies
represent lost sales, how many of those unauthorized copies served as advertisement that
inspired some to buy authorized copies who otherwise would not have, how the sales of
related goods and service supplied by the publishers were affected, or how inflated the
sales projections were in the first place.
The copying of information does not hinder the publisher's ability to make copies in the
same way that stealing cans of peas from a grocer's shelves hinders the grocer's ability to
sell peas. Information and physical goods are categorically different. To regulate
information within legal institutions that emerged to attenuate the depletion of physical
resources is to regulate the use of that which cannot be depleted through use according to
the rules of that which must be depleted through use.
7 Granted, there are historical precedents for punishing individuals because of their similarity to those
who have caused damage, but such precedents are seldom cited in the 'intellectual property' rights
literature, and such precedents are generally seen as negative examples.
Free Curricula Centre Working Paper No. 1 (orig: Aug 2004; this: Feb 2005)
9 of 26
Monopolists can set either the price or the quantity of their output – but not both,
otherwise they could set both infinitely high – and form expectations about the other.
Generally, monopoly suppliers of information set the price and sell as many copies as
consumers demand at that price (the alternative would be a fixed-quantity run that were
auctioned). Setting price and expanding output to meet demand is the preferred option
for information suppliers, precisely because the marginal cost of production for copies of
information is trivial.
According to microeconomic price theory, if the supply schedule of a good increases, due
to improvements in reproduction and distribution technology, then the quantity demanded
increases and the price decreases. Unlike competitive markets, monopoly markets do not
have supply schedules, since the monopolist is the entire supply side of the market. The
supply schedule of public goods is a horizontal line where price equals zero.
P P Figure 1
P* P*
MR
D D
MC P’ MC
0 Q* Q 0 Q* Q’ Q
Here, in Figure 1, we have supply and demand graphs representing these two scenarios.
The graph on the left represents a monopoly market. The graph on the right represents a
public goods market.
A monopolist is assumed to set its price at the level that corresponds to the quantity
demanded at which the marginal cost (MC) of reproduction is equal to the marginal
revenue (MR) of the next unit sold. In reality, the demand schedule (D) is unobservable –
and thus unknowable – ex ante. The monopolist must form expectations based on
experience and refine these estimates as new information becomes available. The only
observables are a) P*, the price that the monopolist sets (i.e., the price tag), and b) Q*, the
quantity sold (i.e., the sales records), which may or may not correspond to the intersection
of MC and MR.
In the public goods scenario, market demand is assumed to remain unchanged, but the
price (P) is determined by the intersection of supply and demand, rather than monopolist
fiat. However, when the [black] market supplies a good at a price of zero – the definition
Free Curricula Centre Working Paper No. 1 (orig: Aug 2004; this: Feb 2005)
10 of 26
of public good – then the supply schedule is the same as as the marginal cost curve, which
is a horizontal line where price equals zero.
In the monopoly scenario the quantity demanded (Q*) at the monopolist price (P*) is
lower than the quantity demanded (Q') when price equals zero (P') in the public goods
scenario. To call Q'-Q* "lost sales" is incorrect; Q'-Q* is the number of sales that were
priced out of the market at the monopoly price, but were concluded at the public goods
price of zero. If copies become available for free, more individuals will want them.
Granted, some consumers at the margin would have bought at the monopoly price, if
zero-price copies were not available, but it is impossible to identify which individuals
these are. Tort and criminal law focus on individual human action and not classes; a
system used to prosecute individuals because they resemble those who have caused
damage, is highly problematic and generally associated with non-democratic regimes.
information
Invoking our first point, above, we note that as bits, information can be encoded as a
string of 1s and 0s. A photograph of my daughter on my computer is stored as a string of
1s and 0s, which my computer interprets according to some set of rules built into the
computer and programmed into the operating system (itself, a long string of 1s and 0s).
Likewise, the draft of this article and all other files and programs on my computer are
unique strings of 1s and 0s.
We can make these calculations for any information, whether it is a text, audio file, design
schematic, movie, etc. Each individual sample of information exists as a binary number.
Forbidding one to possess a copy of information is exactly the same as forbidding one to
Free Curricula Centre Working Paper No. 1 (orig: Aug 2004; this: Feb 2005)
11 of 26
store a specific number on one's computer. If we call this 'intellectual property', then
were are claiming that it is possible to own a number.
Imagine a machine that is of unknown with a knob bearing the numbers 1-9. With a bit
of experimentation, one could set the knob to 1 – i.e., input "1" – and observe the
machine's behavior, and then 2, 3, 4, ..., 9, and note the behaviors.
Now, imagine a machine with enough capacity to enter numbers on the order of, e.g.,
22,500,000,000, or more. One could then try 1, 2, 3, 4, ..., 22,500,000,000, etc., and observe the
machine's behaviors.
In the first case, very few would call the setting of the knob 'programming'. However, the
experiments with the two machines differ only in terms of scale. Few would try to own
the number 5 in relation to its effect on the first machine, even though claiming title to
numbers in relation to their effects on machines of the second kind is routine.
Granted, discovering which numbers result in useful behavior entails considerably more
work than implied above. 22,500,000,000 is a very large number, and it would take a very long
time to discover it through the simple iterative process described.8 It takes a considerable
amount of work to arrive at the number that corresponds to the behavior that an
information producer seeks. Whether one is editing a movie, writing software, drafting a
text, or whatever, there is considerably more effort involved than merely guessing the
right number.
We know now that a thing does not gain economic value based on the amount of work
required for its creation, as is often asserted in the 'intellectual property' literature.
Otherwise, individuals who employed less efficient production processes would be
rewarded with greater returns than those who employed more efficient means.
Prior to the late 19th Century, economists – including John Locke, Adam Smith, and Karl
Marx – believed that value was created by mixing one's labor with the land, and that the
more labor mixed with raw materials, the greater the value of the final output. John
Locke's thought was instrumental in the drafting of the Constitution of the United States
of America9 – most relevant here is Section 8, Clause 8 – and this Labor Theory of Value
still underlies a great deal of legislation in the USA and elsewhere. (Fisher, 1999)
In the 1870s William Stanley Jevons in Manchester, Carl Menger in Vienna, and Léon
Walras in Lausanne independently discovered what Friedrich von Wieser later christened
the Marginal Theory of Value, which underlies modern economic thinking. According to
8 If one could devise a way to carry out such a program, perhaps by employing genetic algorithms, then
one potentially could undermine the 'intellectual property' rights regime through such an exercise of
invoking a number, testing its behavior on a variety of operating systems, iterating the number, and then
testing its behavior, ad infinitum, claiming copyright – and possibly patent – rights along the way.
9 John Locke's "life, liberty, and property" was the inspiration for Thomas Jefferson's "life, liberty, and the
pursuit of happiness" in the Declaration of Independence.
Free Curricula Centre Working Paper No. 1 (orig: Aug 2004; this: Feb 2005)
12 of 26
this theory, a thing gets its value from the interplay of supply and demand in the
marketplace. Regardless of how much work has gone into the production of a thing, it
will have economic value (i.e., a price greater than zero) only if a) someone wants it and
b) there is not enough of it for everyone who wants it to become satiated.
At any given moment in any given place, there is only so much land, so many cans of
peas, and so many cars, and this is almost never enough to fully satiate demand for them.
With information, on the other hand, one can produce enough copies, at approximately
zero cost, for everyone who wants them to become satiated.
A common publisher's gambit is to claim that the high fixed costs of production for
information requires strong 'intellectual property' rights legislation; otherwise – it is
asserted though never proven – the production of movies, books, and medicines would
slow significantly. If weaker 'intellectual property' rights legislation would hinder
creativity, then strengthened 'intellectual property' rights legislation in the form of
perpetual terms for copyright and patent, along with harsh punishment for 'intellectual
property' rights violators, should lead to an explosion of creativity, even though
subsequent creators would be precluded from recombining existing information without
first incurring the cost of title searches license fees.
Similar arguments have been used with regard to software by erstwhile monopolists and
proven by the market to be inaccurate. Linux, FreeBSD, and other free operating systems
are made available to anyone who wants a copy and are actively maintained by all-
volunteer open source software communities. OpenOffice, NeoOffice, Apache,
PostgreSQL, PHP, X11, and a host of other mission-critical applications are all freely
available and widely used worldwide.
Arguments based on the Labor Theory of Value – i.e., creators of information should have
protections based on property rights, because of the upfront costs involved – are based on
an understanding of value that was abandoned by economists nearly 150 years ago, and
do not correspond with observable human action.
This point bears repeating: from the standpoint of modern economic understanding, fixed
costs of production are irrelevant with regard to the market price for a good. If they were
relevant, then markets would reward inefficient producers with higher prices for their
output, since that output would contain the additional labor needed to overcome the
inefficiency. The only relevant effects production costs have are on producers' profits.
For example, two producers, who are exactly alike in every other way, but have different
costs of production, will realize different levels of profit when they sell their output to the
market. If the producer with higher production costs tried to recover those costs through
Free Curricula Centre Working Paper No. 1 (orig: Aug 2004; this: Feb 2005)
13 of 26
higher prices, then buyers would buy from the lower-price supplier, leaving the higher-
price supplier with no sales.
With information, publishers incur production costs for the originals of the movies, audio
recordings, texts, etc. that they produce, which 'pirates' reproduce and distribute at low
cost in competition with the publishers' monopoly-priced copies. This leaves publishers
with the choice of changing business models or seeking alternative employment, as
consumers assert their sovereignty.
Publishers' current business model is to collect monopoly rents from public goods. It is
based on medieval landholding, rather than modern commercial activity. (Swedberg,
1998b; Weber, 1978) When a publisher has completed a movie, audio recording, text,
other information, that information is treated as a 'property', as if it were a tract of land,
rather than as a productive process. Once complete, the information remains unchanged
over long periods of time, until the 'director's cut', remix or live version, second edition,
or other modification is released. The publisher then hires printers, binders, distributors,
etc., to work this property, until the rents no longer cover the production costs. When the
property is depleted, the publisher abandons it for a more fertile property.
In other words, 'intellectual property' is treated as static wealth, rather than as a tool that is
used in the production, distribution, and promotion of consumer goods. This model
worked well, when reproduction technology was primitive. However, now that such
technology is standard equipment on computers that cost less than $500, the costs of
enforcing 'intellectual property' rights are growing exponentially as the costs of
reproduction fall asymptotically toward zero.
Adding more tension to the use of 'intellectual property' as a metaphor for information is
the fact that copyright and patent represent a very unusual kind of 'property right' that is of
limited duration. Their possession is less like ownership, and more like lease or loan.
Ownership of durable physical goods is quasi-immortal, in the sense that an owner can
sell his property to buyers, give it away as voluntary gifts, or bequeath it to heirs, who
enjoy full ownership rights in perpetuity (ignoring abandonment, eminent domain, and
other issues that are ancillary to this discussion). This is not the case with copyright and
patent, which are limited in duration by the statutes that create them.
The possessor of a copyright or patent does so at the pleasure of the legislators in power,
and only for as long as current legislation decrees. Since legislators determine the terms
and conditions of copyright and patent, the state is the ultimate owner of 'intellectual
property'. Physical property is confiscated by agents of the state as a punitive measure;
'intellectual property' rights expire as a matter of course, like leases and loans.
When we combine legal traditions based on property with obsolete economic reasoning
about the nature of value to the regulation of public goods, this results in a situation
where market forces are in opposition to legislation. The history of this kind of dinosaur
Free Curricula Centre Working Paper No. 1 (orig: Aug 2004; this: Feb 2005)
14 of 26
industry protection suggests that if publishers continue to engage the services of
government to shore up their moribund business models, rather than reorganize along
more market-compliant lines, they place themselves in opposition to consumers' demands
and risk being replaced by entrepreneurs who conform to consumer sovereignty.
That publishers continue to try to reestablish their old monopoly positions through state
intervention is to be expected. A person will undertake a course of action, in general, if
the expected benefit is greater than the expected costs, include the alternatives given up in
undertaking that course of action. Publishers will lobby for more draconian 'intellectual
property' rights enforcement, as long as they expect that the net benefits of trying to
maintain the status quo are greater than the net benefits of reorganizing.
This does not change the underlying economic reality; it merely explains why threatened
monopolists and oligopolists spend so much time and money influencing legislation and
public opinion. As noted above, indefensible monopoly positions invite competition from
innovative entrepreneurs. Given the very large rents accruing to publishers (Love, 2000)
and the very low barriers to entry caused by advances in information technology, it is
inevitable that information monopolists and oligopolists will face increasingly
competitive market conditions. The current trend in the economically developed
countries is to fight change rather than embrace it. This strategy could have exactly the
opposite effect in the long run that what is intended. When the legal environment in one
jurisdiction dissuades innovation, in favor of entrenched interests, industries migrate.
alternatives
For example, instead of investing in one or two blockbuster films per year, Hollywood
movie studios could spread their money across a larger number of smaller-budget films.
This is the model embraced by India's Bollywood film makers, who turn out almost 1,000
films per year. At this pace, it is very difficult for the makers of unauthorized copies to
keep up, and consumers enjoy much greater variety.
Free Curricula Centre Working Paper No. 1 (orig: Aug 2004; this: Feb 2005)
15 of 26
advertisers would have an incentive to distribute the film as widely as possible, in order
to maximize the exposure of their products. Possibly, copying would be encouraged.
Publishers could include rivalrous prizes – e.g., lottery tickets, autographed postcards,
onetime-use access codes, etc. – in the package along with the CD, DVD, book, or other
physical embodiment of the information. Alternatively, they could include the consumers
in the production process, as is the business model of ArtistShare, one of whose
participants won a Grammy for fan-financed, web-only jazz album. (Zeidler, 2005)
With movies, publishers could reverse the currently common practice of providing
superior versions of their products on media that are easy to duplicate. Instead of selling
'director's cut' versions and including additional material on the DVD, the publishers
could reserve the superior versions for cinema display, which is easier to police, and
distribute abridged versions on DVD. In this way, the full-price box-office version would
be more desirable than the bowdlerized home version.
With music, CDs could be used as promotional material for live performances, rather than
the primary means by which the performers share their craft and earn their incomes. As
with the Bollywood example above, publishers could spread their investments across a
larger portfolio of regional performers, rather than concentrate on a handful of
international megastars. This way, consumers would have more access to live
performances than with the current system of an annual visit from this season's pop idol.
The news media provide a positive example for education and entertainment publishers to
follow. Caribbean Net News, CNN Online, Space.com, and a host of other advertiser-
supported outlets provide current news at no cost to the user, along with utilities that
make it very easy to copy and print their stories. Rather than depend on the proceeeds
from selling physical embodiments of information that are easily copied, music and
movie publishers could offer access to the information for free via media that carry
advertising. The popularity of advertiser- and listener-supported television and radio
throughout the world suggests that this is a viable model. Apple Computer's iTunes
service is evidence that this model works well online, as well as in broadcast form.
The point of such brainstorming is that, as the market structures of the entertainment,
education, and news industries evolve, it is incumbent upon publishers to adapt, in order
to comply with consumers' demands and not be replaced by more market-compliant
competitors. Publishers, business students, and readers of this article are encouraged to
explore these and even more innovative ideas involved not so much the melting of a
monopoly regime, as with a sublimation which bypasses the middle phase altogether and
goes straight from monopoly pricing to ubiquitous cost-free access to the end user.
Free Curricula Centre Working Paper No. 1 (orig: Aug 2004; this: Feb 2005)
16 of 26
contract
The suggestions above can work well for many purposes, but there are instances in which
information creators would like to continue to collect monopoly rents. It is possible to do
so, but without the underlying inconsistencies of 'intellectual property'.
Fisher (1999) points out that modern 'intellectual property' legislation and rhetoric
perpetuates the myth of the heroic creator; that lone composer, inventor, or poet toiling
away in obscurity, driven by some persistent muse. The reality is that economically
significant information is much more commonly the result of division of labor with many
specialists coordinating their efforts through the market process. The production of a
book employs not only the author, but editors, proofreaders, lawyers, fact checkers, sales
managers, cover designers, etc. Likewise, audio recordings are produced through the
efforts of composers, lyricists, sound engineers, producers, set musicians, etc., and one
need only read the credits scrolling up the screen at the end of a movie to get a sense of
the small army of talent involved with its production.
Free Curricula Centre Working Paper No. 1 (orig: Aug 2004; this: Feb 2005)
17 of 26
Nonetheless, there are situations where the creator or discoverer of some information
wants to share it, but on monopolistic terms. For example, one might have devised a
trading algorithm that would enable market speculators to realize greater profits than the
trading systems currently employed. In this situation, the creator could bind the potential
client to a non-disclosure agreement (NDA) that stipulated remedy in the event of breach.
Granted, as Benjamin Franklin is supposed to have said, "One person can keep a secret.
Two people may be able to keep a secret. Three people can keep a secret, but only if two
of them are dead." The enforcement of 'intellectual property' rights is very difficult, as
well; administrative convenience and ease of enforcement are not distinguishing
characteristics here. Our point here is to base the regulation of human action on traditions
that are compliant with the nature of information and on consumer sovereignty.
Even though this is not the goal here, one could generalize this position and plausibly
argue for dispensing with the concept of property altogether, by construing title to
property as a contract between titleholder and government, wherein government agents
agree to protect one's title to specified goods and parcels of land, in exchange for tax
dollars and obedience. All of the elements of a valid contract are here, including offer,
acceptance, consideration, date, duration, jurisdiction, remedy, etc. To protest that this is
not a contract, because one does not enter into arrangements with government voluntarily,
is to ignore the option to emigrate. If one chooses to live in a jurisdiction, then one tacitly
agrees to the terms thereof, or risk the penalties of breach. Generalizing even further, one
could construe transactions as contracts of very short duration, but we digress.
The point here is not to argue for the general contractarian case, but to point out that one
could do so and that it is possible to regulate the disposal of private goods, which fit well
within property traditions, through contract. This is more extreme than the mundane
observation that end users of information enter into license agreements, which suffice to
limit human action, and easily obviate the need for misapplied property traditions.
Rather than invoking copyright as a kind of property right, in order to protect one's
intellectual output, one could bind recipients by contract to keep information confidential,
not copy it, or whatever else the terms stipulated. Thus, if a publisher, creator, or
distributor discovered unauthorized copies, it would have grounds for a complaint of
breach. The existence of unauthorized copies of 'intellectual property' would suggest the
possibility of abandonment, if the publisher did not take due care to assert its property
rights. For example, when a studio employee releases an unauthorized copy of a new
movie – which is the case, much more often than a viewer with a camcorder – a
Free Curricula Centre Working Paper No. 1 (orig: Aug 2004; this: Feb 2005)
18 of 26
reasonable person would assume that the damage was perpetrated by the studio employee,
and not the member of the public who downloaded a copy from a public network.
If, as described above, one discovered a large, useful number and one agreed to share its
identity with another, on the contractual understanding that the latter would keep the
identity confidential, then terms of remedy in the event of breach could be negotiated, and
invoking increasingly self-contradictory 'intellectual property' rights would be obviated.
discussion
The will to monopolize is ubiquitous11. Monogamy and the first two Old Testament
Commandments are very well established examples. The practice of marketing is based
on differentiating oneself from the masses and establishing oneself as the sole supplier of
some good or service. This position enables the supplier to charge a premium for its
output, as witnessed by differences in prices between branded and generic goods.
Consumers benefit from monopoly relationships through reduced search costs, as when
one deals with the same customer or supplier over time. (Geertz, 1978; Uzzi, 1997) For
example, one often tends to go to the same hair dresser, dentist, or local restaurant,
because this is easier than seeking out and building trust with new service providers.
However, for every benefit there is a concomitant cost. With monopoly, the cost – known
as 'rent' – is the premium paid for the convenience. As long as the expected benefit is
greater than the rent paid, an individual will continue to frequent a supplier exclusively.
Once a monopoly is established, monopolists are often jealous of their rents, and fight to
retain them. History is full of examples of guilds, unions, and other monopoly
organizations engaging in acts of violence in an attempt to maintain their positions. At a
less pugnacious level, a small-town shopkeeper will lament a customer's frequenting a
competitor, an employer will prohibit 'moonlighting', or a landlord will forbid subletting.
For each good and set of local circumstances, there is a market-optimal level of monopoly
that is determined by consumers' desire for search-cost reduction and suppliers' desire for
monopoly rents. This is illustrated in the graph below, where S represents suppliers'
willingness to incur the costs of establishing and maintaining monopoly power, and D
represents consumers' willingness to tolerate monopoly.
When rents are very high, the amount of monopoly power that consumers are willing to
tolerate is low (i.e., they will seek out substitutes), and the monopoly power that suppliers
seek is high (the red line); when rents are very low, the amount of monopoly power that
consumers are willing to tolerate is high, and the amount of monopoly power that
suppliers are willing to incur the cost of maintaining is low (the green line).
11 Here, we include mopsony – an exclusive buyer in a market – within the term 'monopoly', as the
distinction is not salient to this discussion.
Free Curricula Centre Working Paper No. 1 (orig: Aug 2004; this: Feb 2005)
19 of 26
rent Figure 2
S
r*
0 m* monopoly
The point corresponding to (m*,r*) represents the level of rents accruing to the supplier
that just offsets the consumer's search costs. If the rents were higher than r*, then the
consumer would begin seeking alternatives, and the supplier would begin marketing more
heavily, lobbying for stricter zoning requirements, etc. If the rents were lower than r*,
then the consumer will spontaneously seek out monopoly relationships by frequenting the
same merchants (Geertz, 1978) and the supplier will behave like a commodity seller and,
in the extreme case, simply lay its goods out for sale.
rent Figure 3
S
r*
r'
D' D
0 m' m* monopoly
Today, we are witnessing a change in the demand for information that can be illustrated
with the graph above. Because of the introduction of low-cost, high-quality substitutes,
consumers are less willing to pay monopoly rents for information (D') than they were
before (D). Where once a publisher's brand served as a signal for quality, this is no longer
uniquely the case. Technology has improved to the point that tools for making
unauthorized copies are standard equipment – or even integral design features – of even
low-end computers.
As illustrated in the graph above, even though suppliers' tastes have not changed – as
evidenced by the actions of the MPAA, RIAA, inter alia – consumers' tastes have changed
dramatically. Consumers have become less tolerant of monopoly rent, as low-cost, high-
quality substitutes have become available. Suppliers' attempts to maintain the status quo
at r* are directly responsible for the tension that now exists with unauthorized copying.
Attempts to maintain the level of monopoly rents at r* are attempts to create price floors.
Artificially high price floors invariably lead to oversupply, i.e., suppliers flood the market
with goods that go unsold. This could explain some of the publishers' frustration, as
Free Curricula Centre Working Paper No. 1 (orig: Aug 2004; this: Feb 2005)
20 of 26
consumers eschew largely homogeneous storylines, soundtracks, and curricula, and
embrace information innovation from unexpected sources.
Increasingly, innovation today comes from hitherto unknown suppliers, who forego the
normal protections of copyright and patent. This is most pronounced in the open source
movement in software, but one sees this idea spreading to other fields, including open
source hardware and free curricula. It would be unsurprising to see entertainment
embrace this model, as well.
Erstwhile monopolists can embrace these changes and co-opt some of the emerging
market, as Apple and Sun have done by releasing key parts of their operating systems, and
some musical groups have done by releasing samples of their music. Hollywood,
Bollywood, and independent film makers could follow suit easily, by employing strategies
like those discussed above.
The position of suppliers that do not embrace change and assume an adversarial stance
vis-à-vis consumers are depicted by the point o in Figure 4, below. Here, suppliers are
trying to maintain the ex ante level of rent, in spite of consumer pressure to conform to
new market conditions, which has the inevitable consequence expressed in the cliché,
"The tighter you squeeze, the more slips between your fingers," as consumers seek a level
of monopolization corresponding to m°, rather than the level that corresponds to m'.
rent Figure 4
S
o
r*
r'
D' D
0 m° m' m* monopoly
In conventional terms, this means that consumers in the (r*,m°) scenario will have more
of an incentive to experiment with unfamiliar alternatives – as when business managers
begin looking more closely at Linux and OpenOffice – even though this carries relatively
higher search costs, than consumers in the (m',r') scenario – as when a publisher releases
a free, unsupported version of its output, as well as a support-fee-based, 'Pro' version – in
which some consumers are more likely to consider the 'Pro' version than to turn their
backs on the publisher, altogether.
Free Curricula Centre Working Paper No. 1 (orig: Aug 2004; this: Feb 2005)
21 of 26
The (r*,m°) scenario in Figure 4 is often justified on 'intellectual property' rights grounds.
The idea is that rights are created by the law, and violation of those rights is like any other
property violation. (Roberts. 2002)
This, however, begs several questions, not least of which are a) What is 'the law'?, b)
Whose law?, c) What limits the law?, d) What are rights?, and a host of others. It is not
our purpose here to settle debates that have raged for millennia, but we do address some
of the more common positions taken in 'intellectual property' debates.
By 'law' does one mean legislation, laws of nature, or principles that apply everywhere
and always (whether man-made or natural)? The first is a very weak source, as it is
notorious for internal inconsistencies and special-interest exceptions; the second is open
to wide debate. The third can be abused, as well, as we illustrate below.
If the law is the same thing as legislation, then are all legislatures considered equal?
If yes, then the laws of the USA are equally relevant to the laws of Cuba, Saddam
Hussein's Iraq, and 1994 Rwanda. This, clearly is useless as a guiding principle. This is
tantamount to saying that anything goes.
If no, then what extra-legal principles apply? Majority rule has its shortcomings as seen
in Rwanda in 1994. Religious law generally makes no mention of 'intellectual property'.
Natural rights are open to wide interpretation. Even something as seemingly harmless as
internal consistency is useless here, as this would rule out virtually all national and local
bodies of legislation.
If we are to avoid sinking into the morass of moral relativism, we must look elsewhere
for our guiding principle.
Let us recall that the institution of property evolved in response to overuse of scarce
resources. It was a solution for a social problem. With the breakdown of 'intellectual
property' as a viable metaphor, we are witnessing the emergence of a new social problem.
The solution, like the solution for the problem of resource overuse, is to be found in
observable human action, rather than in prescriptive edicts.
A full analysis of this is beyond the scope of this brief article. Such an analysis would
include a historical and theoretical analysis of prohibition, democracy, and ethics. It
Free Curricula Centre Working Paper No. 1 (orig: Aug 2004; this: Feb 2005)
22 of 26
would include sections in each of these areas on phenomenology versus teleology,
descriptive versus prescriptive bases, and atomistic versus embedded choice and action.
Here, we have room only for superficial ostensive definitions.
To whit, people are going to do what people are going to do; prohibition creates
incentives for the establishment of black markets; if the expected benefit exceeds the
expected cost, including opportunity costs, then an individual will undertake a given
course of human action.
While it is understandable that individuals will lobby for the creation of legislation that
serves their special interests at the expense of the general population, there are limits to
what they can achieve. The logic of concentrated benefits with disperse costs enables the
institution of unrepresentative statutes, regulation, and prohibitions with little complaint
from the voting public, but this does not imply that the legislation will be effective.
As entrepreneurs who "fail to produce in the cheapest and best possible way the
commodities which the consumers are asking for most urgently... suffer losses and are
finally eliminated from their entrepreneurial position" (Mises, 1980), governments that
fail to represent the will of the people are eliminated from their ruling positions.
Democracies tend to be fairly resilient in this regard, as politicians who more closely
represent the will of the people replace those who do not over time. Representative
governments tend to repeal or amend statutes when the enforcement cost is greater than
the benefit to taxpayers, as perceived by voters. Sometimes these changes are very long
in coming, but when they do come, the change itself can be very swift. (Granovetter,
1978)
Free Curricula Centre Working Paper No. 1 (orig: Aug 2004; this: Feb 2005)
23 of 26
references
Benkler, Yochai, (2004), "Sharing Nicely: On Shareable Goods and the Emergence of Sharing as a
Modality of Economic Production," Yale Law Review, 114 (2): 273-358,
http://www.yalelawjournal.org/pdf/114-2/Benkler_Final_YLJ114-2.pdf
Cohen, Felix, (1935) "Transcendental Nonsense and the Functional Approach," Columbia Law Review,
35: 809, 814-817, http://cyber.law.harvard.edu/bridge/LegalRealism/35cohe.txt.htm
Ebeling, Richard M., (1986), "Toward a Hermeneutical Economics: Expectations, Prices, and the Role
of Interpretation in a Theory of the Market Process," in Kirzner 1986: 39-55.
Economist, The, (11 Nov 2004), "Monopolies of the Mind," The Economist,
http://www.economist.com/opinion/displayStory.cfm?story_id=3376181
Eucken, Walter, (1992 [1950]), The Foundations of Economics: History and Theory in the Analysis of
Econmic Reality, New York: Springer Verlag.
Eucken, Walter, (1948), "On the Theory of the Centrally Administered Economy: An Analysis of the
German Experiment" (T.W. Hutchinson, trans.) [parts I & II], Economica New Series, 15 (May,
Aug): 79-100; 173-193.
Evans, Charles W., (forthcoming), "Developmental Economics: Prolegomena to a General Theory of
Human Action," Free Curricula Centre Working Papers, 2.
Fisher, William W., III, (1999), "The Growth of Intellectual Property: A History of the Ownership of
Ideas in the United States," Eigentumskulturen im Vergleich, Göttingen, Germany: Vandenhoeck &
Ruprecht, 265-291, http://cyber.law.harvard.edu/property99/history.html
Fuller, Richard Buckminster, (1982), Critical Path, New York: St. Martin's.
Gadamer, Hans Georg, (1989 [1960]), Truth and Method, revised (Trans. J. Weinsheimer, D. Marshall),
New York: Crossroad.
Geertz. Clifford, (1978), "The Bazaar Economy: Informatin and Search in Peasant Marketing,"
Supplement to the American Economic Review, 68 (May): 28-32.
Gilliam, Terry, (1985), Brazil, Hollywood, CA: Universal Studios.
Granovetter, Mark S., (1985), "Economic Action and Social Structures: The Problem of
Embeddedness," American Journal of Sociology, 91(3): 481-510.
Granovetter, Mark S., (1978), "Threshold Models of Collective Behavior," American Journal of
Sociology, 83(6): 1420-1443.
Granovetter, Mark S.; Richard Swedberg, (2001), The Sociology of Economic Life, Boulder, CO:
Westview.
Gross, Irena Grudzinska, (2001), "The Post-Postsociety: The Decline, Fall, and End of Practically
Everything," Social Research, (Winter).
Harriss, John; Janet Hunter; Colin M. Lewis, Eds., (1995), The New Institutional Economics and Third
World Development, New York: Routledge.
Hodgson, Geoffrey M., (1999), Evolution and Institutions, Northampton, MA: Edward Elgar.
Hodgson, Geoffrey M. (Ed), (2003), Recent Developments in Institutional Economics, Northampton,
MA: Edward Elgar.
Free Curricula Centre Working Paper No. 1 (orig: Aug 2004; this: Feb 2005)
24 of 26
Hovenkamp, Herbert J., Mark David Janis; Mark A. Lemley, (2003), "Anticompetitive Settlement of
Intellectual Property Disputes," UC Berkeley Public Law Research Paper No. 113,
http://ssrn.com/abstract=380841
Hunter, Dan, (2002), "Cyberspace as Place, and the Tragedy of the Digital Anticommons, Ver. 2.1"
California Law Review, forthcoming http://ssrn.com/abstract=306662
Hunter, Dan, (2004), "Teaching and Using Analogy in Law," Journal of the Association of Legal
Writing Directors, 2 (Fall): 151-168, http://www.alwd.org/JALWD/Hunter.pdf
Hunter, Dan; F. Gregory Lastowka, (2004), "Copyright's Empire," Working Paper,
http://jonescenter.wharton.upenn.edu/papers/2004/wp04-07.pdf
Kirzner, Israel M., Ed., (1986), Subjectivism, Intelligibility, and Economic Understanding: Essays in
Honor of Ludwig M. Lachmann on His Eightieth Birthday, New York: New York University.
Klein, Peter G, (2000), "New Institutional Economics" (in Bouckaert, Boudewijn; Gerrit De Geest,
Encyclopedia of Law and Economics, Vol 1), Northampton, MA: Edward Elgar: 456-489.
Kuhn, Thomas, (1996 [1962]), The Structure of Scientific Revolutions, Chicago: University of Chicago.
Lachmann, Ludwig M., (1990), "Austrian Economics: A Hermeneutic Approach," in Lavoie 1990: 134-
146.
Lachmann, Ludwig M., (1971), The Legacy of Max Weber, Berkeley: The Glendessary Press.
Landa, Janet Tai, (1994), Trust, Ethnicity, and Identity: Beyond the New Institutional Economics of
Ethnic Trading Networks, Contract Law, and Gift-Exchange, Ann Arbor: University of Michigan
Press.
Landsburg, Steven E. (2002), Price Theory and Applications, 5 ed., Cincinnati, OH: South-Western.
Langlois, Richard N., (1995), "Transaction Costs, Production Costs, and the Passage of Time"
(Working Paper), Storrs, CT: University of Connecticut.
Langlois, Richard N., (1992), "Orders and Organizations: Towards an Austrian Theory of Social
Institutions" (in Austrian Economics: Tensions and New Directions, Bruce J. Caldwell and S.
Boehm, Eds.), Boston: Kluwer, 1992.
Lavoie, Don, Ed., (1990), Economics and Hermeneutics, London: Routledge.
Lavoie, Don, (1986), "Euclideanism versus Hermeneutics: A Reinterpretation of Misesian Apriorism,"
in Kirzner 1986: 192-210.
Lemley, Mark A., (2004a), "Ex Ante versus Ex Post Justifications for Intellectual Property," UC
Berkeley Public Law Research Paper No. 144, http://ssrn.com/abstract=494424
Lemley, Mark A., (2004b), "Property, Intellectual Property, and Free Riding," Stanford Law and
Economics Olin Working Paper No. 291, http://ssrn.com/abstract=582602
Lemley, Mark A., (1999), "The Modern Lanham Act and the Death of Common Sense," Working
Paper, http://ssrn.com/abstract=147788
Love, Courtney, (2000), "Courtney Love Does the Math," Salon.com, 14 June,
http://www.salon.com/tech/feature/2000/06/14/love/index.html
Mises, Ludwig von, (1980), Planning for Freedom. South Holland, IL: Libertarian Press.
Negroponte, Nicolas, (1995), "Bits and Atoms," Wired, 3.10 (1 Jan.),
http://web.media.mit.edu/~nicholas/Wired/WIRED3-01.html
Free Curricula Centre Working Paper No. 1 (orig: Aug 2004; this: Feb 2005)
25 of 26
North, Douglass C., (1990), Institutions, Institutional Change, and Economic Performance, New York:
Cambridge University.
Orwell, George, (1990; [1949]), 1984, New York: Signet.
Popper, Karl, (1977 [1934]), The Logic of Scientific Discovery, London: Routledge.
Rand, Ayn, (1996; [1938]), Anthem, New York: Signet.
Rao, Pinninti Krishna, (2002), The Economics of Transactions Costs, New York: Palgrave.
Roberts, Russell, (2002), "Napsternomics: What's the Most Effective Way to Protect Intellectual
Property?" The Library of Economics and Liberty Contributors' Forum, (3 June),
http:www.econlib.org/library/Columns/Robertsnapster.html
Rogers, Everett, (2003), Diffusion of Innovations (5th ed.), New York: Free Press,
Sapir, Edward, (1929), "The Status of Linguistics as a Science," Language 5: 207-214.
Swedberg, Richard, (2003), Principles of Economic Sociology, Princeton, NJ: Princeton University.
Swedberg, Richard, (1998a), Max Weber and the Idea of Economic Sociology, Princeton, N.J.:
Princeton University.
Swedberg, Richard, (1998b), "Max Weber's Vision of Economic Sociology," Journal of Socio-
Economics, 27 (4): 535-555.
Uzzi, Brian, (1997), "Social Structure and Competition in Interfirm Networks: The Paradox of
Embeddedness," Administrative Science Quarterly, 42: 35-67.
Weber, Max, (1988 [1904]), "Die 'Objektivität' sozialwissenschaftlicher und sozialpolitischer
Erkenntnis," in Gesammelte Aufsätze zur Wissenschaftstheorie, Tübingen: J.C.B. Mohr.
Weber, Max, (1978 [1968]), Economy and Society: An Outline Interpretive Sociology, Berkeley, CA:
University of California.
Weber, Max, (1949), The Methodology of the Social Sciences, New York: Free Press.
Whorf, Benjamin L., (1956), Language, Thought and Reality, New York: Wiley.
Zamyatin, Yevgeny, (1999; [1924, 1920]), We, New York: Eos.
Zeidler, Sue, (2005), "Jazz Composer Nabs Grammy After Web-Only Sales," Reuters, (13 Feb),
http://www.reuters.com/newsArticle.jhtml?type=topNews&storyID=7613511
Free Curricula Centre Working Paper No. 1 (orig: Aug 2004; this: Feb 2005)
26 of 26