Consciousness, Causality, Quantum Physics
Consciousness, Causality, Quantum Physics
(Reprinted with permission from Journal of Scientific Exploration, 11:1, pp. 69-78,
Spring 1997)
Abstract -- Quantum theory is open to different interpretations, and this paper reviews
some of the points of contention. The standard interpretation of quantum physics
assumes that the quantum world is characterized by absolute indeterminism and that
quantum systems exist objectively only when they are being measured or observed.
David Bohm's ontological interpretation of quantum theory rejects both these
assumptions. Bohm's theory that quantum events are party determined by subtler forces
operating at deeper levels of reality ties in with John Eccles' theory that our minds exist
outside the material world and interact with our brains at the quantum level. Paranormal
phenomena indicate that our minds can communicate with other minds and affect
distant physical systems by nonordinary means. Whether such phenomena can be
adequately explained in terms of nonlocality and the quantum vacuum or whether they
involve superphysical forces and states of matter as yet unknown to science is still an
open question, and one which merits further experimental study.
Introduction
Quantum theory is generally regarded as one of the most successful scientific theories
ever formulated. But while the mathematical description of the quantum world allows the
probabilities of experimental results to be calculated with a high degree of accuracy,
there is no consensus on what it means in conceptual terms. Some of the issues
involved are explored below.
Quantum uncertainty
According to the uncertainty principle, the position and momentum of a subatomic
particle cannot be measured simultaneously with an accuracy greater than that set by
Planck's constant. This is because in any measurement a particle must interact with at
least one photon, or quantum of energy, which acts both like a particle and like a wave,
Bohm's ontological interpretation of quantum physics rejects the assumption that the
wave function gives the most complete description of reality possible, and thereby
avoids the need to introduce the ill-defined and unsatisfactory notion of wave-function
collapse (and all the paradoxes that go with it). Instead, it assumes the real existence of
particles and fields: particles have a complex inner structure and are always
accompanied by a quantum wave field; they are acted upon not only by classical
electromagnetic forces but also by a subtler force, the quantum potential, determined by
their quantum field, which obeys Schrdinger's equation. (Bohm & Hiley, 1993; Bohm &
Peat, 1989; Hiley & Peat, 1991)
The quantum potential carries information from the whole environment and provides
direct, nonlocal connections between quantum systems. It guides particles in the same
way that radio waves guide a ship on automatic pilot -- not by its intensity but by its
form. It is extremely sensitive and complex, so that particle trajectories appear chaotic.
It corresponds to what Bohm calls the implicate order, which can be thought of as a vast
ocean of energy on which the physical, or explicate, world is just a ripple. Bohm points
out that the existence of an energy pool of this kind is recognized, but given little
consideration, by standard quantum theory, which postulates a universal quantum field - the quantum vacuum or zero-point field -- underlying the material world. Very little is
known about the quantum vacuum at present, but its energy density is estimated to be
an astronomical 10108 J/cm (Forward, 1996, pp. 328-37).
In his treatment of quantum field theory, Bohm proposes that the quantum field (the
implicate order) is subject to the formative and organizing influence of a superquantum
potential, which expresses the activity of a superimplicate order. The superquantum
potential causes waves to converge and diverge again and again, producing a kind of
average particlelike behavior. The apparently separate forms that we see around us are
therefore only relatively stable and independent patterns, generated and sustained by a
ceaseless underlying movement of enfoldment and unfoldment, with particles constantly
dissolving into the implicate order and then recrystallizing. This process takes place
incessantly, and with incredible rapidity, and is not dependent upon a measurement
being made.
In Bohm's model, then, the quantum world exists even when it is not being observed
and measured. He rejects the positivist view that something that cannot be measured or
known precisely cannot be said to exist. In other words, he does not confuse
epistemology with ontology, the map with the territory. For Bohm, the probabilities
calculated from the wave function indicate the chances of a particle being at different
positions regardless of whether a measurement is made, whereas in the conventional
interpretation they indicate the chances of a particle coming into existence at different
positions when a measurement is made. The universe is constantly defining itself
through its ceaseless interactions -- of which measurement is only a particular instance
-- and absurd situations such as dead-and-alive cats therefore cannot arise.
Thus, although Bohm rejects the view that human consciousness brings quantum
systems into existence, and does not believe that our minds normally have a significant
effect on the outcome of a measurement (except in the sense that we choose the
experimental setup), his interpretation opens the way for the operation of deeper,
subtler, more mindlike levels of reality. He argues that consciousness is rooted deep in
the implicate order, and is therefore present to some degree in all material forms. He
suggests that there may be an infinite series of implicate orders, each having both a
matter aspect and a consciousness aspect: "everything material is also mental and
everything mental is also material, but there are many more infinitely subtle levels of
matter than we are aware of" (Weber, 1990, p. 151). The concept of the implicate
domain could be seen as an extended form of materialism, but, he says, "it could
equally well be called idealism, spirit, consciousness. The separation of the two -matter and spirit -- is an abstraction. The ground is always one." (Weber, 1990, p. 101)
connection between consciousness and the quantum vacuum: for example, Charles
Laughlin (1996) argues that the neural structures that mediate consciousness may
interact nonlocally with the vacuum (or quantum sea), while Edgar Mitchell (1996)
believes that both matter and consciousness arise out of the energy potential of the
vacuum.
Neuroscientist Sir John Eccles dismisses the materialistic standpoint as a "superstition",
and advocates dualist interactionism: he argues that there is a mental world in addition
to the material world, and that our mind or self acts on the brain (particularly the
supplementary motor area of the neocortex) at the quantum level by increasing the
probability of the firing of selected neurons (Eccles, 1994; Giroldini, 1991). He argues
that the mind is not only nonphysical but absolutely nonmaterial and nonsubstantial.
However, if it were not associated with any form of energy-substance whatsoever, it
would be a pure abstraction and therefore unable to exert any influence on the physical
world. This objection also applies to antireductionists who shun the word "dualist" and
describe matter and consciousness as complementary or dyadic aspects of reality, yet
deny consciousness any energetic or substantial nature, thereby implying that it is
fundamentally different from matter and in fact a mere abstraction.
An alternative position is that which is echoed in many mystical and spiritual traditions:
that physical matter is just one "octave" in an infinite spectrum of matter-energy, or
consciousness-substance, and that just as the physical world is largely organized and
coordinated by inner worlds (astral, mental, and spiritual), so the physical body is largely
energized and controlled by subtler bodies or energy-fields, including an astral modelbody and a mind or soul (see Purucker, 1973). According to this view, nature in general,
and all the entities that compose it, are formed and organized mainly from within
outwards, from deeper levels of their constitution. This inner guidance is sometimes
automatic and passive, giving rise to our automatic bodily functions and habitual and
instinctual behavior, and to the regular, lawlike operations of nature in general, and
sometimes it is active and selfconscious, as in our acts of intention and volition. A
physical system subjected to such subtler influences is not so much acted upon from
without as guided from within. As well as influencing our own brains and bodies, our
minds also appear to be able to affect other minds and bodies and other physical
objects at a distance, as seen in paranormal phenomena.
indistinguishable, and one of the events could not be said to cause the other through
the transfer of force or energy, for no such transfer could take place infinitely fast. There
would therefore be no causal transmission mechanism to be explained, and any
investigations would be confined to the conditions that allow correlated events to occur
at different places.
It is interesting to note that light and other electromagnetic effects were also once
thought to be transmitted instantaneously, until observational evidence proved
otherwise. The hypothesis that nonlocal connections are absolutely instantaneous is
impossible to verify, as it would require two perfectly simultaneous measurements,
which would demand an infinite degree of accuracy. However, as David Bohm and Basil
Hiley (1993, pp. 293-4, 347) have pointed out, it could be experimentally falsified. For if
nonlocal connections are propagated not at infinite speeds but at speeds greater than
that of light through a "quantum ether" -- a subquantum domain where current quantum
theory and relativity theory break down -- then the correlations predicted by quantum
theory would vanish if measurements were made in periods shorter than those required
for the transmission of quantum connections between particles. Such experiments are
beyond the capabilities of present technology but might be possible in the future. If
superluminal interactions exist, they would be "nonlocal" only in the sense of
nonphysical.
Nonlocality has been invoked as an explanation for telepathy and clairvoyance, though
some investigators believe that they might involve a deeper level of nonlocality, or what
Bohm calls "super-nonlocality" (similar perhaps to Sheldrake's "morphic resonance"
(1989)). As already pointed out, if nonlocality is interpreted to mean instantaneous
connectedness, it would imply that information could be "received" at a distance at
exactly the same moment as it is generated, without undergoing any form of
transmission. At most, one could then try to understand the conditions that allow the
instant appearance of information.
The alternative position is that information -- which is basically a pattern of energy -always takes time to travel from its source to another location, that information is stored
at some paraphysical level, and that we can access this information, or exchange
information with other minds, if the necessary conditions of "sympathetic resonance"
exist. As with EPR, the hypothesis that telepathy is absolutely instantaneous is
unprovable, but it might be possible to devise experiments that could falsify it. For if
ESP phenomena do involve subtler forms of energy traveling at finite but perhaps
superluminal speeds through superphysical realms, it might be possible to detect a
delay between transmission and reception, and also some weakening of the effect over
very long distances, though it is already evident that any attenuation must be far less
than that experienced by electromagnetic energy, which is subject to the inverse-square
law.
As for precognition, the third main category of ESP, one possible explanation is that it
involves direct, "nonlocal" access to the actual future. Alternatively, it may involve
clairvoyant perception of a probable future scenario that is beginning to take shape on
the basis of current tendencies and intentions, in accordance with the traditional idea
that coming events cast their shadows before them. Bohm says that such
foreshadowing takes place "deep in the implicate order" (Talbot, 1992, p. 212) -- which
some mystical traditions would call the astral or akashic realms.
tested. Such investigations could deepen our knowledge of the workings of both the
quantum realm and our minds, and the relationship between them, and indicate whether
the quantum vacuum really is the bottom level of all existence, or whether there are
deeper realms of nature waiting to be explored.
References
Bohm, D. (1984). Causality and Chance in Modern Physics. London: Routledge & Kegan Paul. First published in 1957.
Bohm, D. & Hiley, B.J. (1993). The Undivided Universe: An ontological interpretation of quantum theory. London and New York: Routledge.
Bohm, D. & Peat, F.D. (1989). Science, Order & Creativity. London: Routledge.
Broughton, R.S. (1991). Parapsychology: The Controversial Science. New York: Ballantine Books.
Crick, F. (1994). The Astonishing Hypothesis: The Scientific Search for the Soul. London: Simon & Schuster.
Dennett, D.C. (1991). Consciousness Explained. London: Allen Lane/Penguin.
Eccles, J.C. (1994). How the Self Controls Its Brain. Berlin: Springer-Verlag.
Forward, R.L. (1996). Mass Modification Experiment Definition Study, Journal of Scientific Exploration, 10:3, 325.
Giroldini, W. (1991). Eccles's Model of Mind-Brain Interaction and Psychokinesis: A Preliminary Study, Journal of Scientific Exploration, 5:2,
pp. 145-61.
Goswami, A. with Reed, R.E. & Goswami, M. (1993). The Self-Aware Universe: How consciousness creates the material world. New York:
Tarcher/Putnam.
Hameroff, S.R. (1994). Quantum coherence in microtubules: A neural basis for emergent consciousness? Journal of Consciousness Studies,
1:1, 91.
Herbert, N. (1993). Elemental Mind: Human Consciousness and the New Physics. New York: Dutton.
Hiley, B.J. & Peat, F.D. (eds.) (1991). Quantum Implications: Essays in honour of David Bohm. London and New York: Routledge.
Inglis, B. (1984). Science and Parascience: A history of the paranormal, 1914-1939. London: Hodder and Stoughton.
Inglis, B. (1992). Natural and Supernatural: A History of the Paranormal from the Earliest Times to 1914. Bridport/Lindfield: Prism/Unity. First
published in 1977.
Jahn, R.G. & Dunne, B.J. (1987). Margins of Reality: The Role of Consciousness in the Physical World. New York: Harcourt Brace.
Laughlin, C.D. (1996). Archetypes, Neurognosis and the Quantum Sea. Journal of Scientific Exploration, 10:3, 375.
Milton, R. (1994). Forbidden Science: Suppressed research that could change our lives. London: Fourth Estate.
Mitchell, E. with Williams, D. (1996). The Way of the Explorer: An Apollo Astronaut's Journey Through the Material and Mystical Worlds. New
York: Putnam.
Pagels, H.R. (1983). The Cosmic Code: Quantum Physics as the Language of Nature. New York: Bantam.
Purucker, G. de (1973). The Esoteric Tradition. Pasadena, California: Theosophical University Press. 2nd ed. first published in 1940.
Sheldrake, R. (1989). The Presence of the Past: Morphic Resonance and the Habits of Nature. New York: Vintage.
Sperry, R.W. (1994). Holding Course Amid Shifting Paradigms. In New Metaphysical Foundations of Modern Science, edited by W. Harman
with J. Clark. Sausalito, California: Institute of Noetic Sciences.
Talbot, M. (1992). The Holographic Universe. New York: HarperPerennial.
Thornton, M. (1989). Do we have free will? Bristol: Bristol Classical Press.
Tiller, W.A. (1993). What Are Subtle Energies? Journal of Scientific Exploration, 7:3, 293.
Weber, R. (1990). Dialogues with Scientists and Sages: The Search for Unity. London: Arkana.