Against Rationalism
Against Rationalism
Michael Rosen
Rationality and the issues associated with it have always occupied a central
place within the Western philosophical tradition. Moreover, as the humanities
and social sciences have found themselves under assault from post-modernists
and deconstructionists, the role of rationality has also become a pressing
problem well beyond the borders of philosophy. In this paper I am going to
take issue with one of the most familiar ways in which rationality has been
conceived within the Western tradition of thought. Rationalism, as I shall call
it, embodies a particular conception of the nature of human action, choice and
well-being. The purpose of the paper is to call that conception into question
and to suggest the possibility of alternatives. But I should make clear at the
outset one thing that my purpose is not. It is not my intention to mount an
attack on the notion of rationality itself, either the general notion or the idea of
rationality in ethics. On the contrary. My hope is that these notions can be
defended better once we rid ourselves of certain prejudicial conceptions
regarding human nature. To put it briefly, I should like to free rationality from
rationalism.
discursive reason is not guaranteed and that it is not merely reason that must
hold the passions in check. So even in the ideal state, the Republic, a way must
be found for desire to be kept in its place. Plato puts a vivid example of the
way in which the appetite contradicts reason into Socrates's mouth:
...Leontion, son of Aglaion,...was on his way up from the Peiraeus,
outside the north wall, when he noticed some corpses lying on the
ground with the executioner standing by them. He wanted to go and
look at them, and yet at the same time he held himself back in disgust.
For a time he struggled with himself and averted his eyes, but in the
end his desire got the better of him and he ran up to the corpses,
opening his eyes wide and saying to them, There you are, curse you
a lovely sight! Have a real good look!2
Plato believes that his ideal citizens must have thumos: a third element
whose presence is responsible for giving reason power to surmount appetite
and desire. This capacity is held to be innate in human beings but can also be
trained. In that case the thumos can enforce the claims of reason against the
power of appetite:
So the reason ought to rule, having the ability and foresight to act for
the whole, and the thumos ought to obey and support it. And this
concord between them is effected, as we said, by a combination of
intellectual and physical training, which tunes up the reason by
Watson (ed.), Free Will (Oxford: O.U.P., 1982), pp. 81-95, p. 94.
Discursive Rationalism
(1) One view, which we might call discursive rationalism, identifies reason
itself as the effective means by which the self emancipates itself from its
slavery to a particular set of empirical desires. Discursive rationalism is, in a
certain sense, rationalism in its purest form. It asserts the distinctive capacity
of human beings to be motivated by the knowledge gained through reflection.
The tradition of discursive rationalism starts, I think, obviously enough, with
Plato and continues through the varieties of Greek thought to the extent that
the latter embodies the view that philosophical reflection is an essential means
for the practical achievement of the good life. The vein of discursive
rationalism comes to the surface as a theme in the philosophy of German
Idealism, culminating in Hegels vision of the unity of theoretical and practical
rationality in Absolute Knowledge and again in Jrgen Habermass hugely
2
3
Practical Rationalism
(2) But not all rationalism is discursive rationalism. Indeed, not even Plato is
committed to discursive rationalism alone. As the passage quoted above makes
clear, reason on its own in Platos view is not enough to enable us to overcome
our desires if the latters force is not otherwise held in check. Thus another
form of rationalism seeks to achieve self-mastery not directly, by rational
discourse addressed to ones own self, but indirectly, by rational action aimed
at changing ones desires. If Plato is the great initiator of discursive
rationalism, Aristotle, surely, is the founding father of practical rationalism:
the advocate of training and habituation in the service of discretionary selfcontrol. The supposition here is that we can diminish the power of unwanted
desires by acting repeatedly in such a way that they are overridden.
Pessimism
(3) So far, I have divided rationalism between those who believe that the end
of rational self-mastery is achieved by discursive means from those who
believe that it is to be achieved by means of educative practice always
remembering that the two themes may be married, more or less happily, within
individual thinkers. (We have seen as much in Plato, and the same is true of
Aristotle.) But there is one further approach to the rationalist ideal of human
self-development that has played an extremely significant role in the history of
shall be as one not there, and so I shall overcome both you and the
games. They heard him, but none the less took him with them,
wanting perhaps to discover whether he could actually carry it off.
When they arrived and had found seats where they could, the entire
place seethed with monstrous delight in the cruelty. He kept his eyes
shut and forbade his mind to think about such fearful evils. Would that
he had blocked his ears as well! A man fell in combat. A great roar
from the entire crowd struck him with such vehemence that he was
overcome by curiosity. Supposing himself strong enough to despise
whatever he saw and to conquer it, he opened his eyes. He was struck
in the soul by a wound graver than the gladiator in his body, whose fall
had caused the roar. The shouting entered by his ears and forced open
his eyes. Thereby it was the means of wounding and striking to the
ground a mind still more bold than strong, and the weaker for the
reason that he presumed on himself when he ought to have relied on
you. As soon as he saw the blood, he at once drank in savagery and did
not turn away. His eyes were riveted. He imbibed madness. Without
any awareness of what was happening to him, he found delight in the
murderous contest and was inebriated by bloodthirsty pleasure. He was
not now the person who had come in, but just one of the crowd which
he had joined, and a true member of the group which had brought him.
8
that it is basically correct. The practical issue, then, is about the effective
means (if there are any) for realizing that ideal, whilst the philosophical one
concerns its metaphysical presuppositions and ethical implications. Moreover
one would have to be blind not to see that the twentieth-century political
movement that most consciously rejected the rationalist picture of human
nature produced effects of unspeakable barbarism.
Nevertheless, and however tentatively, I should like to take up that
challenge. At the same time, I should like to draw your attention to a current of
thought about human nature that exists, for the most part, outside the main
stream of the philosophical tradition but that is, I believe, no less worthy of our
attention for that. The critique of rationalism that I will develop will have three
main ingredients. First, I shall present a view according to which the rationalist
ideal of increasing the discretionary power of choice vis--vis first-order
desires is not appropriate. Next, I shall suggest that the pessimists critique of
the effectiveness of rationalist means is at least plausible. Finally, I shall
develop a view according to which the use of rationalist means to develop selfcontrol, to the extent that they are in fact effective, are damaging to attitudes
and psychological states that human beings should value.
It will be recalled that the rationalist ideal as I presented it envisaged a
situation in which human beings were able to reject or endorse any of their
first-order desires as they wished. I left it open which, if any, they should
endorse or reject, or in terms of what criteria they should do so. This was a
12
desire in the moral case but that, when it comes to undesirable desires, they are
ineffective or even counter-productive. As a matter of fact, for reasons that
would take me too far from my main argument to go into here, that is precisely
Rousseaus view.
The outline of Rousseaus anti-rationalist position is by now, I hope,
emerging. Not all first-order desires are equally good (or bad). Some those
that embody piti are good for a familiar reason: they incorporate concern for
others. Others, in particular those that are generated by the vain selfishness that
Rousseau calls amour-propre, are bad, again for a familiar reason, namely,
that they are self-multiplying and insatiable. Thus (although this is one of the
pervasive myths about him) Rousseau is no irrationalist.
Nor is he a pessimist. Like Augustine, Rousseau challenges the idea
that reasoning (the private and independent exercise of the power of
reflection) is a suitable means to achieve moral rationality and self-command.
Yet here the two part company, for, unlike Augustine, Rousseau does not
believe that self-command is impossible, except by the miraculous means of
divine grace. Rousseau believes that there is a rational order to the world and it
is both discernible by human beings and capable of being followed by them
although to be able do so their reason must be (as Rousseau expresses it in
mile) perfected by feeling.15) Our failures are the result of lives lived
15
redundant in the moral sphere (Reason alone teaches us to know good and
evil. (mile, quoted in The Indispensable Rousseau, p.185.); and that mastery
over the passions is a good thing (see mile, Book 5).
It seems clear that, for Rousseau, reason has more than one sense.
Affirmatively, it is the capacity to judge rightly, feel appropriately, and to
match our actions to our feelings. Negatively, it is the exercise of reflection
and speculation in abstraction from direct experience. It is all too easy,
therefore, to suppose either (on the basis of his critical remarks) that Rousseau
is an irrationalist, or, if the more positive statements are included, that he is
simply confused.
16
Discours sur l'origine de l'ingalit, p. 199.
upon us. Numerous striking examples that I had collected put the
matter beyond all dispute; and thanks to their physical basis they
seemed to me capable of providing an external code which, varied
according to circumstances, could put or keep the mind in the state
most conducive to virtue. From what errors would reason be preserved,
and what vices would be choked even before birth, if one knew how to
compel the brute functions to support the moral order which they so
often disturb? Climates, seasons, sounds, colours, darkness, light, the
elements, food, noise, silence, movements, repose: they all act on our
machines, and consequently upon our souls, and they all offer us
innumerable and almost certain opportunities for controlling those
feelings which we allow to dominate us from their very onset... I made
very little progress with this work, however, the title of which was La
Morale Sensitive ou le Matrialisme du sage.17
Where Augustine considers the senses to be a permanent threat to the
feeble defences of reason, for Rousseau, the world of the senses is not held to
be inherently inimical to human rationality; nor is the remedy for incontinence
the development of discursive reasoning or the dull repetition of habit, but the
search for a healthy and balanced form of experience. Rousseau's aim is to
develop reason (in the sense of the power of the self to perceive, feel and act
rightly) by bringing it into balance with its environment.
17
techniques and the endorsement of a rationalist ideal for the self) does indeed
have practical effects, even if these are not the achievement of the rationalist
ideal of self-command. These effects amount to the establishment of a certain
personality or character-type, the rationalist self.
(2)
The effect of the rationalist self is to cause the selfs experience to lose
at least part of its intrinsic value. The claim is that certain kinds of experience,
like piti, have value not just in promoting a good end (motivating moral
action) but intrinsically.
Once again, I shall focus the discussion by presenting it through the
thought of an anti-rationalist thinker, in this case, the novelist Stendhal and his
book De lamour. The book turns on a distinction between two types of lover
and the different experiences that they have of love. The distinction is
epitomized in the contrast between two fictional characters: Goethes Werther
and Don Juan. Each represents a different character type. Don Juan is the type
of the active, goal-directed individual. He lives his life under the domination
of his ongoing projects. Insofar as he responds to the outer world with his
feelings, those feelings are positive or negative insofar as what he encounters
favours or obstructs his ends. For the Don Juan, according to Stendhal,
Love... is a feeling akin to a taste for hunting. It is a craving for an activity
that needs an incessant diversity of stimuli to challenge skill. 18 Don Juan is a
kind of reductio ad absurdum of rationalism.
Werther, on the other hand, is the passive, sensitive lover. His feelings
are essentially responses, inasmuch as he allows his perceptions of value to be
given to him unexpectedly and, at times, quite irrationally in the context of
his love. The Wertherian lover sees the world as a lover does. That is, he sees
reality in a certain way because he is in love. Yet, in contrast to the Don Juan,
he does not see the world simply as a means towards the satisfaction of his
desires. Stendhal's key idea is that sensitive love makes possible a kind of
imaginative perception: what he calls crystallization, based on an analogy
that he repeats several times in the book:
At the salt-mines of Salzburg, they throw a leafless wintry bough into
one of the abandoned workings. Two or three months later they haul it
out covered with a shining deposit of crystals. The smallest twig, no
bigger than a tom-tit's claw, is studded with a galaxy of scintillating
diamonds. The original branch is no longer recognizable.
What I have called crystallization is a mental process which
draws from everything that happens new proofs of the perfection of the
loved one.19
The imagination, in other words, enriches and beautifies the world for
us; it gives the sensitive lovers experience a value that it would not otherwise
have, even if it leads to actions and judgements that would seem to the
outsider demeaning or absurd.20 Don Juan, by contrast, can never experience
this enrichment of the world.21
Stendhal, Love, translated by G. and S. Sale (Harmondsworth: Penguin,
1975) p. 209.
19
Love, p.45
20
Passionate love spreads all Nature in her sublimity before a mans eyes, like
something invented only yesterday. He is surprised never to have noticed the
strange sights he now perceives. Everything is new, alive, and pulsating with
the most passionate interest. A lover sees the woman he loves in every skyline,
18
Unlike Werther, for whom realities are shaped by his desires, Don
Juan's desires are imperfectly satisfied by cold reality, as in ambition,
avarice and other passions. Instead of losing himself in the bewitching
reveries of crystallization his attitude is that of a general to the success
of his tactics, and in brief he destroys love instead of enjoying it more
than others, as is commonly believed.22
Although Werther perceives the world as containing values, it is not
that his valuings are claimed to be objectively correct as Stendhal makes
clear, they are subjective and, perhaps, to the outsider, wholly unintelligible.
Yet that is not Stendhals point. What gives those valuings their value is not
their objective truth but the fact that such a mode of perception has an
affective richness and depth that itself gives value to the individuals
experience. From the Don Juans point of view, Werthers valuations serve no
overriding end. Nevertheless, Stendhal has no hesitation in declaring that a
Werther is happier than a Don Juan, for the latter reduces love to the level of
an ordinary affair.23
Rationalism, to the extent that it encourages the production of
character-types such as Don Juan at the expense of Werther, leads to a loss of
and as he travels a hundred leagues to catch a momentary glimpse of her each
tree, each rock speaks to him in a different way and teaches him something
new about her. Love, p. 209.
21
Instead of the tumult of these magical visions, Don Juan requires that
external objects, which he values only in proportion to their utility, should be
given piquancy by some new intrigue. Love, p. 209.
22
Love, p. 206
value, the anti-rationalist claims. Yet what is particularly significant is that the
criteria for the assessment of value available from within the rationalist
tradition of ethical thought provide no clear way of registering this loss. Does
the Don Juan undergo fewer pleasurable experiences than the Werther?
Probably not. Does he satisfy fewer of his desires? Quite possibly not. Are his
first-order desires less consonant with the discretionary power of his will?
Certainly not. Has he developed fewer of his powers? No. Are the long-term
projects in terms of which he frames his life less ambitious, coherent and well
realized? Again, it would seem not. So why, then, should someone think that
he is worse off?
The history of Western philosophy offers us a huge diversity of
answers regarding the nature of human well-being (I made reference to a few
of them in the previous paragraph). Yet it is significant that, according to many
of those criteria, it is the Don Juan who appears to be leading the more
successful life. According to Stendhal, the Don Juan is simply less happy:
his experience is qualitatively inferior. Yet philosophys received notions of
what makes life valuable seem to be incapable of registering that fact. I do not
suppose, however, that I am alone in finding Stendhals case for the superior
value of the sensitive lovers experience over that of the Don Juan perfectly
intelligible indeed persuasive. If this is something that ethical theory has
23
Love, p. 206
difficulty in accounting for, then the problem lies on the side of philosophy, it
seems to me.