How To Read A Film-J Monaco
How To Read A Film-J Monaco
The Critic
FILM THEORY:
FORM AND FUNCTION
The Critic
Chapter
Intro
In Mel Brookss and Ernest Pintoff s funny and insightful short film The Critic
(1963), we watch abstract animated shapes perform on the screen as we hear
the voice of Brooks, an old man, puzzle his way happily through the significance of this art:
Vot da hell is dis?!
Mus be a cahtoon.
Op. Mus be boith. Dis looks like boith. I remembeh when I was a boy in
Russia biology.
Op! Its born. Whatever it is, its born. Look out! Too late. Its dead already.
Vots dis? Usher! Dis is cute! Dis is cute. Dis is nice. Vot da hell is it? Oh. I know
vot it is. Its gobbage. Dats vot it is! Two dollas I pay for a French movie, a foreign movie, and now I gotta see dis junk!
The first shape is joined by a second, and Brooks interprets:
The Critic
Yes. Its two two things dat, dat, datthey like each other. Sure. Lookit da
sparks. Two things in love! Ya see how it got more like?it envied the other
thing so much. Could dis be the sex life of two things?
The scene changes again and Brookss old codger begins to lose interest:
The Critic
Vot is dis? Dots! Could be an eye. Could be anything! It mus be some symbolism. I tink its symbolic of junk! Uh-oh! Its a cock-a-roach! Good luck to
you vit ya cock-a-roach, mister!
As the artistic short comes to a close, the critic passes final judgment:
I dunno much about psychanalysis, but Id say dis is a doity pictcha!
The Critic is humorous partly because Brooks manages, in the short space of
his three-minute monologue, to touch on a number of vital truths about criticism. Two dollas we pay for a movie; what do we get for it? How do we determine cinematic value? How do we know whats symbolic of junk? There are
others in the audience with Mel Brookss critic who seem to be enjoying the
film. Are values, then, entirely relative? Are there any true universal rules for
film art? What does film do? What are its limits?
Questions like these are the province of film theory and criticism, two related
but not identical activities that have as their common end an increased understanding of the phenomenon of film. In general, theory is the abstraction; criticism is the practice. At the lowest end of the scale, we find the kind of criticism a reviewer practices: more reportage than analysis. The reviewers function
is to describe the film and evaluate it, two relatively simple tasks. At the upper
end of the scale is the kind of film theory that has little or nothing to do with
the actual practice of film: an intellectual activity that exists primarily for its
own sake, and often has its own rewards, but doesnt necessarily have much
relation to the real world. Between these two extremes there is much room for
useful and interesting work.
A number of important dichotomies govern the work of film theory. The
first, the contrast between the practical and the ideal, is suggested by the difference between criticism (practical) and theory (ideal).
Closely associated with this is the contrast between prescriptive and
descriptive theory and criticism. The prescriptive theorist is concerned with
what film should be, the descriptive theorist only with what film is. Prescriptive
theory is inductive: that is, the theorist decides on a system of values first, then
measures actual films against his system. Descriptive theory, in contrast, is
deductive: the theorist examines the entire range of film activity and then, and
only then, draws tentative conclusions about the real nature of film. Theorists
and critics who prescribe are naturally concerned about evaluation; having
The Critic
strong systems of values, they logically measure real films against their requirements and judge them.
The third and most important governing dichotomy is that between theory
and practice. The fact is, no filmmaker needs to study the theory in order to
practice the art. Indeed, until recently, very few filmmakers had any interest in
theory. They knew (or did not know) instinctively what had to be done. Gradually, however, as film art became more sophisticated, a bridge between theory
and practice was established. Many contemporary filmmakers, unlike their predecessors, now proceed from strong theoretical bases. Even Hollywood offices
are now full of cinema studies Ph.D.s; since the generation of Coppola, Scorsese, and Lucas (film school students all) took charge, advanced degrees have
provided an important entree in the studio system.
This is a major change in the way Hollywood does business. Indeed, the
Hollywood style, which to a great extent still dominates film history, never produced a codified body of theory. On the face of it, the Hollywood film of the
thirties and forties depended on a complex and powerful esthetic system, yet
there is no Hollywood theory as such. No art needs theory; no artist needs an
advanced degree. When academic study becomes a requirement for employment, the very nature of the art changes: it becomes self-conscious and it probably becomes less exciting. You dont have to be a wild-eyed romantic to believe
that its the renegades who break the rules who make the most intriguing art.
Formal training ensures a certain level of journeyman competence, but it tends
to suppress creativity. We trade off the excitement of genius for the assurance of
branded quality. This may explain what has happened to American film since
the early seventies.
The old masters, of course, played it by ear. The best that D. W. Griffith
(who inspired so many theorists) could come up with was a rather dizzy idea
that the human pulse beat was the secret metronome of effective filmmaking.
In Pace in the Movies (Liberty magazine, 1926), he wrote:
The American school makes an effort to keep the tempo of the picture in
tune with the average human heartbeat, which, of course, increases in rapidity
under such influences as excitement, and may almost stop in moments of pregnant suspense.
The Critic
Griffiths
Pace in the
Movies
Luxembourg
Conference
Eisensteins
A Closeup
View
Much of this sort of after-the-fact cogitation was the result of films own inferiority complex as the youngest of the arts. Christian Metz suggests that the
function of such criticism, psychoanalytically, is to rescue film from its badobject status. More simply, the thinking went: if film can support a weighty
system of theory, then it must be just as respectable as any of the other, older
arts. This may seem a rather childish motive for film theory, but it was not so
long ago that film was commonly regarded by educated people as not to be
taken seriously. In the U.S., for example, film did not become a generally
accepted subject for study in colleges and universities until about 1970. So the
impetus for much of early film theory was to gain a degree of respectability.*33
Because of this desire for respectability many of the earliest works of film theory were prescriptiveoften quite pretentiously so, but sometimes intriguingly
elaborate. Continuing the psychoanalytic metaphor, we can think of this as the
ascendancy of films superegoits sense of the artistic communitys standards
of behavior and respectabilityas it struggled to be treated as an equal, and
mastered its natural libidinous impulses. Standards were necessary, and film
theorists provided them. Now that film theory has matured, it is much less
likely to insist on rules and regulations often derived from outside the domain
of film itself and instead concentrates on developing its own more flexible and
more sophisticated values.
Within any specific film theory, there are a number of oppositions at work. Is
the theory mainly esthetic or mainly philosophical? Does it deal with the relationships of parts of cinema to each other, or the parts of a specific film to each
other? Or does it concern itself with the relationships between film and culture,
film and the individual, film and society?
Sergei Eisenstein, still the most fecund of film theorists, used cinematic terminology to describe the difference between various approaches to film study.
In his 1945 essay A Close-up View he described long-shot film theory as
that which deals with film in context, which judges its political and social
implications. Medium-shot film criticism, meanwhile, focuses on the human
scale of the film, which is what most reviewers concern themselves with.
Close-up theory, however, breaks down the film into its parts and
resolves the film into its elements. Film semiotics and other theories that
attempt to treat the language of film, for example, are close-up approaches.
Lindsays The
Art of the
Moving
Picture
Yet Lindsay understood very early onafter The Birth of a Nation (1915)
but before Intolerance (1916)that the real strength of film might lie in precisely the opposite direction. In Thirty Differences Between Photoplays and
the Stage he outlined an argument that was to become a major concern of film
theorists throughout the twenties and into the thirties as he explained how the
two seemingly parallel arts contrasted. This became the dominant theme as
film theorists tried to establish a separate identity for the adolescent art.
Lindsays last chapter on esthetics, Hieroglyphics, is even more insightful.
With profound insight, he wrote:
The invention of the photoplay is as great a step as was the beginning of picture-writing in the stone age.
Lindsay
Poems
He then goes on to treat film as a language and, although his analysis may be,
as he suggests, a fanciful flight rather than a sober argument, it nevertheless
points directly to the most recent stage of development in film theorysemiotics. Quite an achievement in 1915 for an antiacademic poet enamored of the
barbaric yawp and untrained in the scholarly disciplines!
Nor does Lindsay stop with the internal esthetics of film. The third section
of his book is devoted to the extrinsic effects of the photoplay. Again, the discussion is not so important for its concrete contributions to our understanding
of the medium as it is as an early historical marker, yet one of Lindsays most
idiosyncratic theoriesalways dismissed by later theorists and criticsbears
further examination.
Lindsay suggests that the audience should engage in conversation during a
(silent) film rather than listen to music. No one took his suggestion seriously; if
they had, we might have developed a cinema that was communal and interactive much earlier than we did. Many Third World films (as well as those of
Godard) were designed, despite their soundtracks, as first statements in conversation between filmmaker and observer. In short, Vachel Lindsay as poet and
passionate lover of film intuited a number of truths that more academic theorists, limited by their rigid systematic thinking, never could have understood.
A year after Lindsays paean to movies first appeared, it was joined by another
major contributiondirectly opposed in style, approach, and tone, but just as
valuable: Hugo Mnsterbergs seminal The Photoplay: A Psychological Study
Mnsterbergs
The Photoplay
His intellectual analysis of the phenomenon not only provided a muchneeded cachet but also remains even today one of the more balanced and objective outlines of film theory. Mnsterberg was committed to bridging the gap
between professional theory and popular understanding. Intellectually the
world has been divided into two classes, he wrote, the highbrows and the
lowbrows. He hoped that his analysis of the psychology of film would bring
these two brows together. Sadly, his book was ignored for many years and was
only rediscovered by film theorists and students in 1969.
Like Lindsay, Mnsterberg quickly understood that film had its own special
genius and that its esthetic future did not lie in replicating the kind of work
that was better done on stage or in the novel. Like the poet, the professor also
understood that film theory must take into account not only implicit esthetics
but also explicit social and psychological effects. He calls these two facets the
Inner and the Outer developments of motion pictures, and he begins his
study with a discussion of them.
His most valuable contribution, however, predictably lies in his application
of psychological principles to the film phenomenon. Freudian dream psychology was a useful tool for many popular theories of cinema from the twenties
on. Mnsterbergs approach, however, is pre-Freudian (which is one good reason why it was ignored for so long); at the same time he is an important precursor of Gestalt psychology, which makes his approach seem surprisingly contemporary. Freudian film psychology emphasizes the unconscious, dreamlike
nature of the experience and therefore concentrates on the passive attitude
toward the medium. Mnsterberg, in contrast, develops a conception of the
relationship between film and observer as interactive.
He begins by describing how our perception of movement in moving pictures depends not so much on the static phenomenon of persistence of vision
as on our active mental processes of interpretation of this series of still images.
Venice
festival
Thirty years later, this active process became known as the Phi phenomenon.
Mnsterberg had described it (without labeling it) in 1916.
In chapters titled Attention, Memory and Imagination, and Emotions,
he then develops a sophisticated theory of film psychology that conceives of
film as an active processa strongly mental activityin which the observer is
a partner with the filmmaker. In a second section, titled The Esthetics of the
Photoplay, he investigates some of the ramifications of this view of the process. In shifting attention away from the passive phenomenon of persistence of
vision and toward the active mental process of the Phi phenomenon, Mnsterberg established a vital logical basis for theories of film as an active process. At
the time, this theory was prescriptive rather than descriptive. During the first
thirty or forty years of film theory, the concept of the medium as essentially
passive and manipulative was dominant, as it is in film practice. Yet Mnsterbergs understanding of the medium as at least potentially interactive would
eventually be redeemed.
Curiously, Lindsays and Mnsterbergs books were the last really significant
works of film theory produced in the U.S. until quite recently. It seemed as if
film theory was beside the point once Hollywood began to dominate film practice. By the early twenties, the focal point of film theory had shifted to Europe
and was for fifty years dominated by French, German, and Eastern European
thinkers.
Like the British tradition, the American line of development of theory/criticism has been mainly practicalconcerned with concrete criticism rather than
abstract theory. Ideally, it is not a less valuable tradition because of this practical
orientation, but because it is diffuse it is not so easy to describe or to study.
Concentrated single volumes of abstract theory lend themselves to analysis
much more readily, a fact that should be remembered, since it tends to distort
our conception of the shape of developing film theory.
Paradoxically, one of the first signs of the growing vitality of film theory in
Europe in the twenties was found in the work of Louis Delluc, who, although
he produced several volumes of theory (Cinma et cie, 1919; Photognie, 1920),
is best remembered as a practicing daily film critic, filmmaker, and founder of
the cin-club movement. Together with Lon Moussinac, he established film
reviewing as a serious undertaking, in direct contrast to the reportage and puff
publicity then common. Delluc died in 1924, before his thirty-fifth birthday,
Andrew on
Phenomenology
In his useful introduction to the subject, The Major Film Theories (1976), J.
Dudley Andrew adopted categories derived from Aristotle to analyze the structure of film theory. He approached various theories by four avenues: Raw
Material, Methods and Techniques, Forms and Shapes, and Purpose and
Value. We can further simplify the categories if we realize that the two central
onesMethods and Techniques and Forms and Shapesare simply opposite facets of the same phenomenon, the first practical, the second theoretical.
Each of these categories focuses on a different aspect of the film process, the
chain connecting material, filmmaker, and observer. The way in which a theory
arranges these relationships to a large extent determines its aim, and is a direct
function of its underlying principles. Those theories that celebrate the raw
material are essentially Realist. Those that focus first on the power of the filmmaker to modify or manipulate reality are, at base, Expressionist: that is, they
are more concerned with the filmmakers expression of the raw materials than
with the filmed reality itself.
These two basic attitudes have dominated the history of film theory and
practice ever since the Lumire brothers (who seemed to be obsessed with capturing raw reality on film) and Mlis (who obviously was more interested by
what he could do to his raw materials). It is only recently that the third facet of
the process, the relationship between film and observer (in Aristotles terms
Purpose and Value), has begun to dominate film theory, although it was
always implicit in both Realist and Expressionist arguments. The semiotics of
film and the politics of film both begin with the observer and work back
through the art of the filmmaker to the reality of the raw materials on the other
side.
Arnheims
Film
and Reality
every one of the other, older arts was moving toward greater abstraction, less
verisimilitudeless matter with more art. Why shouldnt the adolescent
upstart, film, move in this direction as well? Moreover, if film was in fact to be
considered a mature art, it was necessary to show that the activity of the art of
film was just as complex and demanding as, say, the activity of painting.
Expressionism, by placing emphasis on the manipulative power of the filmmaker, served this function nicely.
More important, perhaps, is the second reason theories of Expressionism
dominated the first fifty years of film theory: there was very little room for private or personal art in film. Because it was so expensive, cinema had to be a
very popular form. Theories of Realism demand that we see the observer as a
participant in the process. If film is strictly a commodity, how could we justify
making the consumer work for his entertainment? As a product, film had to
be manipulative: the more effect the film had, the better value for the money
the consumer had spent. In fact, most popular film is still judged by this simple
rule: witness the success of such mind-blowers as The Exorcist (1973), Jaws
(1975), Alien (1979), and Terminator 2 (1991). In this economic sense, movies
are still a carnival attractionrides on roller coasters through chambers of horror and tunnels of loveand Realism is totally beside the point.
The two standard, most succinct, and colorful texts describing the contrasting Expressionist and Realist positions are Rudolf Arnheims Film as Art (published first in German in 1933 as Film als Kunst and translated into English
almost immediately) and Siegfried Kracauers Theory of Film: The Redemption of
Physical Reality (first published in 1960). Both books are stronglyalmost belligerentlyprescriptive. Both present revealed truths as if film theory were a
matter of pronouncements rather than investigations. Yet both remain memorable and have become classics of the literature of film, not only because they
each neatly summarize the positions of their respective schools, but also in no
small part because they are so sententious: more complex, less determinist theories of film are obviously not so easily remembered.
Arnheim had a distinguished career as a psychologist (he was the author of
Art and Visual Perception: A Psychology of the Creative Eye, 1954), so it is no surprise to discover that the basic tenets of Film as Art are psychological. But
unlike his predecessor Mnsterberg, he is more concerned with how film is
made than with how it is perceived. The thrust of his small volume can be
Kracauers
Theory
The conflict between Realism and Expressionism that colors nearly all film theory is not so direct, explicit, and nicely balanced as it might at first seem. The
relationship is more dialectical than dichotomous, so that Realist theory grows
out of Expressionist theory just as Expressionist theory had, in its turn, grown
out of the urge to build an artistic reputation for film.
Siegfried Kracauers magnum opus, Theory of Film: The Redemption of Physical Reality, coming twenty-seven years after Arnheims elegant, lean prescription, is in contrast a sprawling, sometimes blunt, often difficult investigation
into wide-ranging theories of Realism that had been developing slowly over a
period of more than twenty years. Expressionism, because it is self-limiting and
self-defining, is relatively easy to outline. Realism, on the other hand, is a
vague, inclusive term that means many things to many people. All students of
literature have run into the problem of Realism before. Is Jane Austen, who
wrote precisely about a very narrow segment of society, a Realist? Or is breadth
as important as depth to the Realist sensibility? Is Naturalism, rather easily
defined as an artistic form based on Determinist philosophy, a kind of Realism,
an offshoot from it, or in direct opposition to it? In film, too, Realism is a
slippery term. The Rossellini of Rome, Open City (1945) is a Realist, but
what about the Rossellini of The Rise to Power of Louis XIV? Or Fellini? Are politics necessary to Realism? What about acting? Are documentaries always more
realistic than fiction films? Or is it possible to be a Realist and still be a story
teller? The catalogue of questions about the nature of film Realism is endless.
Kracauer covers many of them, but his book is by no means a complete survey of the quirky definitions of the word. It is a theory of film, not the theory of
film. Like Arnheims essay, it chooses a single central fact of the film experience
Sergei
Eisenstein
V. I.
Pudovkin
During the 1920s, the period immediately following the Russian Revolution, the Soviet cinema was among the most exciting in the world, not only
practically but theoretically. There is no doubt that the Soviet filmmaker-theorists wanted not only to capture reality but also to change it. Realism, at least
esthetically, is not particularly revolutionary: as we have noted, it tends to deny
the power of the filmmaker and therefore makes film seem to be less powerful
as a tool to effect social change. During this periodbefore Stalin imposed the
doctrine of Socialist Realism (which is neither Realist nor especially Socialist)two filmmakers, V. I. Pudovkin and Sergei Eisenstein, produced not only
Pudovkins
theory of
montage
Very soon after the revolution of 1917, a filmmaker named Lev Kuleshov was
put in charge of a workshop. Pudovkin was one of his students as was, briefly,
Eisenstein. Unable to find enough filmstock to fuel their projects, they turned
to reediting films already made, and in the process discovered a number of
truths about the technique of film montage.
In one experiment, Kuleshov linked together a number of shots made at
varying times and places. The composite was a unified piece of film narrative.
Kuleshov called this creative geography. In probably their most famous
experiment, the Kuleshov group took three identical shots of the well-known
prerevolutionary actor Moszhukin and intercut them with shots of a plate of
soup, a woman in a coffin, and a little girl. According to Pudovkin, who later
described the results of the experiment, audiences exclaimed at Moszhukins
subtle and affective ability to convey such varied emotions: hunger, sadness,
affection.
In his two major works, Film Technique (1926) and Film Acting (1935),
Pudovkin developed from the basic root of his experiments with Kuleshov a
varied theory of cinema centered on what he called relational editing. For
Pudovkin, montage was the method which controls the psychological guidance of the spectator. In this respect, his theory was simply Expressionist
that is, mainly concerned with how the filmmaker can affect the observer. But
he identified five separate and distinct types of montage: contrast, parallelism,
symbolism, simultaneity, and leitmotif (reiteration of theme).
Eisensteins
theory of
montage
Eisenstein set up his own theory of montageas collision rather than linkagein direct opposition to Pudovkins theory. In a series of essays beginning
in the early twenties and continuing throughout most of his life, he worked
and reworked a number of basic concepts as he struggled with the shape and
nature of cinema.*34 For Eisenstein, montage has as its aim the creation of
ideas, of a new reality, rather than the support of narrative, the old reality of
experience. As a student, he had been fascinated by Oriental ideograms that
combined elements of widely different meaning in order to create entirely new
meanings, and he regarded the ideogram as a model of cinematic montage.
Taking an idea from the literary Formalists, he conceived of the elements of a
film being decomposed or neutralized so that they could serve as fresh
material for dialectic montage. Even actors were to be cast not for their individual qualities but for the types they represented.
Eisenstein extended this concept of dialectics even to the shot itself. As shots
related to each other dialectically, so the basic elements of a single shotwhich
he called its attractionscould interrelate to produce new meanings. Attractions as he defined them included
Battleship
Potemkin
stills
every aggressive moment every element that brings to light in the spectator those senses or that psychology that influence his experienceevery element that can be verified and mathematically calculated to produce certain
emotional shocks in a proper order within the totality [Film Sense, p. 231].
Battleship
Potemkin
clip
Alexander
Nevsky
Balzs on
language
Like Eisenstein, Bla Balzs worked out his description of the structure of cinema over a period of many years. Hungarian by birth, he left his native country
after the Commune was overthrown in 1919 and spent time thereafter in Germany, the Soviet Union, and other East European countries. His major work,
Theory of the Film: Character and Growth of a New Art (1948), summarizes and
comments on a lifetime of theorizing. Because he had practical experience in
the art and because he developed his theory over a number of years, Theory of
the Film remains one of the most balanced volumes of its kind.
Sharing many of the basic Formalist principles of Eisenstein and Soviet literary critics of the twenties, Balzs manages to integrate these concepts with certain Realist principles. He was fascinated by the secret power of the closeup
to reveal details of fact and emotion and developed a theory of the true province of film as micro-dramatics, the subtle shifts of meaning and the quiet
interplay of emotions that the closeup is so well equipped to convey. His earliest book on film had been entitled The Visible Man, or Film Culture (1924). It
made this essentially Realist point strongly and probably influenced Pudovkin.
But while he celebrated the reality of the closeup, Balzs also situated film
squarely in the economic sphere of influence. He realized that the economic
foundation of film is the prime determinant of film esthetics, and he was one of
the earliest film theorists to understand and explain how our approach to any
film is molded and formed by the cultural values we share. Predating Marshall
McLuhan by many years, he anticipated the development of a new visual culture that would resurrect certain powers of perception that, he said, had lain
dormant. The discovery of printing, he wrote, gradually rendered illegible
the faces of men. So much could be read from paper that the method of conveying meaning by facial expression fell into desuetude. That is changing now
that we have a developing, reproducible visual culture that can match print in
Andr Bazin
Bazins
Ontology
Bazins
Language
Astruc: La
camrastylo
Closely associated with this concept of the value of ambiguity are the twin
concepts of the presence and reality of space. Bazin, in a later essay, suggests
that the essential difference between theater and cinema lies in this area. There
is only one reality that cannot be denied in cinemathe reality of space. Contrariwise, on the stage space can easily be illusory; the one reality that cannot be
denied there is the presence of the actor and the spectator. These two reductions are the foundations of their respective arts.
The implications for cinema are that, since there is no irreducible reality of
presence, there is nothing to prevent us from identifying ourselves in imagination with the moving world before us, which becomes the world. Identification then becomes a key word in the vocabulary of cinematic esthetics. Moreover, the one irreducible reality is that of space. Therefore, film form is
intimately involved with spatial relationships: mise-en-scne, in other words.
Bazin did not live long enough to formulate these theories more precisely,
but his work nevertheless had a profound effect on a generation of filmmakers,
as did Eisensteins (but as Arnheims and Kracauers prescriptions did not).
Bazin laid the groundwork for the semiotic and ethical theories that were to
follow. More immediately, he inspired a number of his colleagues on Cahiers du
Cinma, the magazine he founded with Jacques Doniol-Valcroze and Lo Duca
in 1951. The most influential film journal in history, Cahiers provided an intellectual home during the fifties and early sixties for Franois Truffaut, Jean-Luc
Godard, Claude Chabrol, Eric Rohmer, and Jacques Rivette, among others. As
critics, these men contributed significantly to the development of theory; as
filmmakers, they comprised the first generation of cinastes whose work was
thoroughly grounded in film history and theory; their filmsespecially those
of Godardwere not only practical examples of theory but often themselves
theoretical essays.
For the first time, film theory was being written in film rather than print.
This fact itself was evidence that the vision of critic and filmmaker Alexandre
Astruc was being realized. In 1948, Astruc had called for a new age of cinema,
which he identified as the age of camra-stylo (camera-pen). He predicted that
cinema would gradually break free from the tyranny of what is visual, from
the image for its own sake, from the immediate and concrete demands of the
narrative, to become a means of writing just as flexible and subtle as written
language.*35 Many earlier theorists had spoken of films language; the con-
Cahiers
covers
Truffauts
Une
certaine
tendance...
Doinel
Godard on
montage:
English
Godard on
montage:
French
Godard on
Godard
This led to some rather absurd opinions on individual films, as Bazin points
out, but by its very egregiousness the Politique des auteurs helped to prepare
the way for a resurgence of the personal cinema of authors in the sixties who
could wield Astrucs camra-stylo with grace and intelligence. Cinema was
moving from theories of abstract design to theories of concrete communication. It was not material Realism or even psychological Realism that counted
now, but rather intellectual Realism. Once it was understood that a film was
the product of an author, once that authors voice was clear, then spectators
could approach the film not as if it were reality, or the dream of reality, but as a
statement by another individual.
More important than Truffauts Politique, though much less influential at the
time, was Jean-Luc Godards theory of montage, developed in a series of essays
in the middle fifties and best expressed in Montage, mon beau souci (Cahiers
du Cinma 65; December, 1956). Building on Bazins theory of the basic opposition between mise-en-scne and montage, Godard created a dialectical synthesis of these two theses that had governed film theory for so long. This is one
of the most important steps in film theory. Godard rethought the relationship
so that both montage and mise-en-scne can be seen as different aspects of the
same cinematic activity.
Montage is above all an integral part of mise-en-scne, he wrote. Only at
peril can one be separated from the other. One might just as well try to separate
the rhythm from a melody. What one seeks to foresee in space, the other
seeks in time. Moreover, for Godard, mise-en-scne automatically implies
montage. In the cinema of psychological reality that derived from Pudovkin
and influenced the best of Hollywood, cutting on a look is almost the definition of montage. Montage is therefore specifically determined by mise-enscne. As the actor turns to look at an object the editing immediately shows it
to us. In this kind of construction, known as dcoupage classique, the length
of a shot depends on its function and the relationship between shots is controlled by the material within the shotits mise-en-scne.
Weekend
Brice Parain
with Anna
Karina
Plastic or material Realism deals only with what is signified. Godards more
advanced intellectual or perceptual Realism includes the signifier. Godard was
also in the habit of quoting Brechts dictum that Realism doesnt consist in
reproducing reality, but in showing how things really are. Both of these statements concentrate the Realist argument on matters of perception. Christian
Metz later elaborated this concept, making an important differentiation
between the reality of the substance of a film and the reality of the discourse in
which that substance is expressed. On the one hand, he wrote, there is the
impression of reality; on the other the perception of reality.
Godards
Camera
Eye
Godards
Les
Carabiniers
Les
Carabiniers
Le Gai Savoir
British
Sounds
track
British
Sounds
feminist
sequence
Vladimir
and Rosa
Vladimir and
Rosa: the
image of
sound
Tout va bien:
tracking shot
Tout va bien:
mise-enscene as
montage
Discussing
Til Victory
Godards
notebooks
Mnch on
Benjamin
Tout va bien and Letter to Jane (both 1972) are probably the most important
of Godards theoretical works during this period. The former summarizes what
he had learned from his experiments; the latter is, in part, an autocritique of
the former.
Tout va bien involves a filmmaker and a reporter (husband and wife) in a
concrete political situation (a strike and the worker occupation of a factory)
and then studies their reaction to it. From this it builds to an analysis of the
entire filmic process of production and consumption. Godard reworked his
earlier synthesis of montage and mise-en-scne in economic terms, seeing cinema not as a system of esthetics but as an economic, perceptual, and political
structure in which the rapports de productionthe relationships between
producer and consumerdetermine the shape of the film experience. The
emphasis is not on how cinema relates to an ideal system (esthetics) but rather
on how it directly affects us as viewers. Films ethics and politics therefore
determine its nature.
This was not a particularly new idea; Balzs was aware of this dimension of
film. In the thirties and forties, the Frankfurt school of social criticism (Walter
Benjamin, Theodor Adorno, and Max Horkheimer, mainly) had examined
film in this context, most notably in Benjamins very important essay The
Work of Art in the Age of Mechanical Reproduction. Benjamin had written:
For the first time in world history, mechanical reproduction emancipates the
work of art from its parasitical dependence on ritual. Instead of being based
on ritual, it begins to be based on another practicepolitics. Benjamin, however, was speaking of an ideal. Godard had to show how commercial cinema
had usurped what Benjamin had termed films unique ability to shatter tradition, tamed it, and made it serve the purposes of a repressive establishment. It
was this subliminally powerful idiom that Godard knew had to be broken
down.
Letter to Jane, a forty-five-minute essay about the ideological significance of a
photo of Jane Fonda (one of the stars of Tout va bien), carries out this process in
detail. Working with Jean-Pierre Gorin, Godard attempted to analyze the signification of the esthetic elements of the photo. The angle, design, and relationships between components, Godard showed, have delicate but real ideological
significance. By the time of Letter to Jane, Godard was by no means alone in
this dialectic, semiotic approach to film.
Letter to
Jane
Letter to
Jane
No
apologies
for all the
Godard
Barthes on
Pleasures of
the Text
Metz on
Language
While Godard was studying on film the consequences of the idea that the sign
forces us to see an object through its significance, Christian Metz and others
were studying in print the ramifications of that dictum. In two volumes of
Essais sur la signification au cinma (the first of which appeared in English translated as Film Language: A Semiotics of the Cinema), published in 1968 and
1972, and in his major work Language and Cinema (1971), Metz outlined a
view of film as a logical phenomenon that can be studied by scientific methods.
The main points of Metzs thesis have already been discussed in Chapter 3. It
will suffice here simply to outline the broad principles of what is the most elaborate, subtle, and complex theory of film yet developed.
Semiotics is a general term that covers many specific approaches to the study
of culture as language. With strong roots in the linguistic theories of Ferdinand
de Saussure, it uses language as a general model for a variety of phenomena.
The approach first took shape in the cultural anthropology of Claude LviStrauss in the fifties and early sixties. This structuralism quickly became
accepted as a general worldview. Michael Wood described the nature of this
intellectual fashion succinctly:
Structuralism is perhaps best understood as a tangled and possibly unnameable
strand in modern intellectual history. At times it seems synonymous with modernism itself. At times it seems to be simply one among several twentieth-century formalisms. And at times it seems to be the inheritor of that vast project
which was born with Rimbaud and Nietzsche, spelled out in Mallarm, pursued in Saussure, Wittgenstein, and Joyce, defeated in Beckett and Borges, and
is scattered now into a host of helpless sects: what Mallarm called the Orphic
explanation of the earth, the project of picturing the world not in language but
as language [New York Review of Books, March 4, 1976].
In short, structuralism, with its offspring, semiotics, is a generalized worldview that uses the idea of language as its basic tool.
Metzs approach to film (like all film semiotics) is at once the most abstract
and the most concrete of film theories. Because it intends to be a science, semi-
Ecos
Toward
a Logic of
Culture
Now Metz felt he had a system of logic that would permit the real analysis of
the film phenomenon. Montage and mise-en-scne had been thoroughly redefined as the syntagmatic and paradigmatic categories. These Cartesian coordinates determined the field of film.
Metz next turned, in Language and Cinema, to a thorough exposition of the
system of codes that govern cinematic meaning. Within the syntagmas and
paradigms of film theory, what determines how we acquire meaning from a
film? Contemporary mathematical set theory plays an important part in his
elaborate structure of codes. Making the differentiation between film and
cinema that we noted earlier, Metz explained that the concept of codes transcends the limits of film. Many codes that operate in film come from other
areas of culture. These are nonspecific codes. Our understanding of the murder in Psycho (1960), for example, does not depend on specifically cinematic
codes. The way in which Hitchcock presents that murder, however, is an example of a specific cinematic code. Finally, there are those codes that cinema
borrows from or shares with other media. The lighting of the shower sequence
Diagram M.
codes.
The next differentiation of codes follows logically. If some codes are specific
to cinema and some are not, then of those specific codes, some are shared by all
films and some by only a few, while others are unique to certain individual
films. The diagram visualizes this logic:
Heaths
Film
and System
Carrolls
Address to
the Heathen
Pasolinis
Unhappy
Youths
Horkheimer
& Adorno:
Dialectics of
Enlightenment
Agees
Letter
Along with other semioticians, Metz in the late seventies moved on to a discussion of the psychology of filmic perception, most successfully in his long
essay The Imaginary Signifier, which appeared simultaneously in both
French and English in 1975. Drawing on basic Freudian theory as rephrased by
Jacques Lacan, he psychoanalyzed not only the cinematic experience but also
cinema itself. Because of its great debt to Freud, whose theories are now much
less highly regarded in America than they once were, this trend in film semiotics elicited much less interest among English-speaking followers of semiotics
than among its French practitioners.
While Metz received the most attention, he was by no means alone in his
semiotic pursuits. The movement has been central to French intellectual life for
a long time. Roland Barthes, although mainly a literary critic, contributed significantly to the debate in cinema before his death in 1980. Raymond Bellour
wrote widely; his two extended studies of sequences from Hitchcocks The Birds
and North by Northwest are of special interest. In Italy, Umberto Eco and Gianfranco Bettetini made significant contributions, and Pier Paolo Pasolini,
although as he put it an amateur theorist, produced some interesting analyses
before his untimely death.
In England, semiotics found an early and receptive home in the journal
Screen and led to the establishment of the English school of Cin-structuralism. Peter Wollens Signs and Meaning in the Cinema, the major argument of
which is outlined in Chapter 3, was the most important English-language contribution to the broad outline of semiotic theory.
In the U.S., semiotics had little effect, except to serve as a tool for academics
involved in the growth of film scholarship in colleges and universities in the
seventies and eighties. Highly intellectualized, abstract theories of cinema have
never been popular in America.
The native tradition of the U.S. has been practical criticism, often with a
social if not exactly political orientation, stretching from Harry Alan Potamkin
and Otis Ferguson in the thirties through James Agee and Robert Warshow in
the forties to Dwight Macdonald, Manny Farber, and Pauline Kael in the sixties and seventies. Andrew Sarris, although he doesnt fit into this sociological
tradition, had a marked effect on the course of film criticism in the U.S. in the
sixties and seventies through his work in popularizing the auteur policy.
Sarris:
Happy
Birthday
JFK
Kael: A
Note
on the Title
Sarris:
Citizen
Kael
Kael: The
Movie
Lover
Haskell on
The Female
Star
Solanas on
Third
Cinema
There are no younger critics now writing regularly who have yet established
critical personas as strong as Sarriss, Kaels, or even John Simons in the sixties
and seventies. Since the rise of television-show criticism in the early eighties,
thumbs have replaced theories. Thats not to say there arent a lot of intelligent
people writing about film today; theres just no one with an interesting theoretical ax to grind.
The main tradition of American criticism has preferred to see films not so
much as products of specific authors but as evidence of social, cultural, and
political currents. Especially in the work of Kael, Molly Haskell, and others,
this strain of social criticism was modified to include an intensely personal
focus. Practically, American criticism is not so far removed from the French
theoretical tradition at the moment. Both are strongly concerned with the
problem of perception. The difference is that the Europeans, as has been their
wont, prefer to generalize and to develop elaborate theories, while the Americans, true to tradition, are more interested in the everyday experience of specific phenomena.
Concurrent with the growth of semiotics on the Continent was a revival of
Marxist criticism. The French journals Cahiers du Cinma and Cinthique managed to combine the semiotic and the dialectic traditions in the late seventies.
In England, too, semiotics often had a distinctly political cast. In America,
much of recent theory sees film as a political phenomenon, albeit abstractly
rather than practically.
During the seventies, the developing theory of film in the Third World was
also of interest. A major document here was Toward a Third Cinema, by
Fernando Solanas and Octavio Getino (Cineaste IV:3, 1970). More a manifesto
than a theory, the South American filmmakers essay suggested that the first
cinemaHollywood and its imitatorsand the second cinemathe more
personal style of the New Wave or authors cinemawould yield to the
third cinema, a cinema of liberation that would consist of films that the System cannot assimilate and which are foreign to its needs, or films that
directly and explicitly set out to fight the System. Perhaps that happened
somewherein Chile for a few years in the early seventies, for examplebut
with the benefit of hindsight we can discern a lot of wishful thinking in that
statement. The world was moving too fast, and the political models of the thirties were no longer viable.
Bundtzen:
Monstrous
Mothers
Thelwell:
The Harder
They Come
Schrader on
Transcendentalism
Althusser on
Reading
Capital
New
Historicism
Colloquium
Gledhill on
Feminist
Criticism
Kirby: Male
Hysteria
and Early
Cinema
Bloom:
Map of
Misreading
Politics of
Film Study
Colloquium
Postmodern
Colloquium
zoom to the rhythmic pulse of montage, movies are sexual. They are not only
about sexual politics; they are sexual politicssubject and object united.
The present course of film theory is away from prescription, toward description. People who think about film are no longer interested to construct an ideal
system of esthetics or political and social values, nor do they see their main aim
as finding a language to describe the phenomenon of film. These critical tasks
were accomplished earlierwith aplombby the critics we have discussed in
this chapter.
The job of film theory now is truly dialectical. As a fully matured art, film is
no longer a separate enterprise but an integrated pattern in the warp and woof
of our culture. Cinema is an expansive and far-reaching set of interrelating
oppositions: between filmmaker and subject, film and observer, establishment
and avant garde, conservative purposes and progressive purposes, psychology
and politics, image and sound, dialogue and music, montage and mise-enscne, genre and auteur, literary sensibility and cinematic sensibility, signs and
meaning, culture and society, form and function, design and purpose, syntagmas and paradigms, image and event, Realism and Expressionism, language
and phenomenology, sex and violence, sense and nonsense, love and marriage
a never-ending set of codes and subcodes that raises fundamental questions
about the relationships of life to art, and reality to language.
Jurassic
technology?
Film more
important
than life?