BBC - Ethics - Introduction To Ethics - Ethics - A General Introduction
BBC - Ethics - Introduction To Ethics - Ethics - A General Introduction
What is ethics?
At its simplest, ethics is a system of moral principles. They affect how people make decisions and lead their
lives.
Ethics is concerned with what is good for individuals and society and is also described as moral philosophy.
The term is derived from the Greek word ethos which can mean custom, habit, character or disposition.
Ethics covers the following dilemmas:
how to live a good life
our rights and responsibilities
the language of right and wrong
moral decisions - what is good and bad?
Our concepts of ethics have been derived from religions, philosophies and cultures. They infuse debates on
topics like abortion, human rights and professional conduct.
Approaches to ethics
Philosophers nowadays tend to divide ethical theories into three areas: metaethics, normative ethics and
applied ethics.
Meta-ethics deals with the nature of moral judgement. It looks at the origins and meaning of ethical
principles.
Normative ethics is concerned with the content of moral judgements and the criteria for what is right or
wrong.
Applied ethics looks at controversial topics like war, animal rights and capital punishment
1/8
4/2/13
www.bbc.co.uk/ethics/introduction/intro_1.shtml
2/8
4/2/13
3/8
4/2/13
The problem for ethical realists is that people follow many different ethical codes and moral beliefs. So if there
are real ethical truths out there (wherever!) then human beings don't seem to be very good at discovering
them.
One form of ethical realism teaches that ethical properties exist independently of human beings, and that
ethical statements give knowledge about the objective world.
To put it another way; the ethical properties of the world and the things in it exist and remain the same,
regardless of what people think or feel - or whether people think or feel about them at all.
On the face of it, it [ethical realism] means the view that moral qualities such as wrongness, and likewise
moral facts such as the fact that an act was wrong, exist in rerum natura, so that, if one says that a certain
act was wrong, one is saying that there existed, somehow, somewhere, this quality of wrongness, and that
it had to exist there if that act were to be wrong.
R. M Hare, Essays in Ethical Theory, 1989
Moral realism
Moral realism is based on the idea that there are real objective moral facts or truths in the universe. Moral
statements provide factual information about those truths.
Subjectivism
Subjectivism teaches that moral judgments are nothing more than statements of a person's feelings or
attitudes, and that ethical statements do not contain factual truths about goodness or badness.
www.bbc.co.uk/ethics/introduction/intro_1.shtml
4/8
4/2/13
In more detail: subjectivists say that moral statements are statements about the feelings, attitudes and
emotions that that particular person or group has about a particular issue.
If a person says something is good or bad they are telling us about the positive or negative feelings that
they have about that something.
So if someone says 'murder is wrong' they are telling us that they disapprove of murder.
These statements are true if the person does hold the appropriate attitude or have the appropriate feelings.
They are false if the person doesn't.
Emotivism
Emotivism is the view that moral claims are no more than expressions of approval or disapproval.
This sounds like subjectivism, but in emotivism a moral statement doesn't provide information about the
speaker's feelings about the topic but expresses those feelings.
When an emotivist says "murder is wrong" it's like saying "down with murder" or "murder, yecch!" or just
saying "murder" while pulling a horrified face, or making a thumbs-down gesture at the same time as saying
"murder is wrong".
So when someone makes a moral judgement they show their feelings about something. Some theorists also
suggest that in expressing a feeling the person gives an instruction to others about how to act towards the
subject matter.
Prescriptivism
Prescriptivists think that ethical statements are instructions or recommendations.
So if I say something is good, I'm recommending you to do it, and if I say something is bad, I'm telling you not
to do it.
There is almost always a prescriptive element in any real-world ethical statement: any ethical statement can
be reworked (with a bit of effort) into a statement with an 'ought' in it. For example: "lying is wrong" can be
rewritten as "people ought not to tell lies".
5/8
4/2/13
Intuitionism
Intuitionists think that good and bad are real objective properties that can't be broken down into component
parts. Something is good because it's good; its goodness doesn't need justifying or proving.
Intuitionists think that goodness or badness can be detected by adults - they say that human beings have
an intuitive moral sense that enables them to detect real moral truths.
They think that basic moral truths of what is good and bad are self-evident to a person who directs their
mind towards moral issues.
So good things are the things that a sensible person realises are good if they spend some time pondering
the subject.
Don't get confused. For the intuitionist:
moral truths are not discovered by rational argument
moral truths are not discovered by having a hunch
moral truths are not discovered by having a feeling
It's more a sort of moral 'aha' moment - a realisation of the truth.
Consequentialism
This is the ethical theory that most non-religious people think they use every day. It bases morality on the
consequences of human actions and not on the actions themselves.
Consequentialism teaches that people should do whatever produces the greatest amount of good
consequences.
One famous way of putting this is 'the greatest good for the greatest number of people'.
The most common forms of consequentialism are the various versions of utilitarianism, which favour actions
that produce the greatest amount of happiness.
Despite its obvious common-sense appeal, consequentialism turns out to be a complicated theory, and
doesn't provide a complete solution to all ethical problems.
Two problems with consequentialism are:
it can lead to the conclusion that some quite dreadful acts are good
predicting and evaluating the consequences of actions is often very difficult
Virtue ethics
Virtue ethics looks at virtue or moral character, rather than at ethical duties and rules, or the consequences
of actions - indeed some philosophers of this school deny that there can be such things as universal ethical
www.bbc.co.uk/ethics/introduction/intro_1.shtml
6/8
4/2/13
rules.
Virtue ethics is particularly concerned with the way individuals live their lives, and less concerned in assessing
particular actions.
It develops the idea of good actions by looking at the way virtuous people express their inner goodness in
the things that they do.
To put it very simply, virtue ethics teaches that an action is right if and only if it is an action that a virtuous
person would do in the same circumstances, and that a virtuous person is someone who has a particularly
good character.
Situation ethics
Situation ethics rejects prescriptive rules and argues that individual ethical decisions should be made
according to the unique situation.
Rather than following rules the decision maker should follow a desire to seek the best for the people
involved. There are no moral rules or rights - each case is unique and deserves a unique solution.
Moral absolutism
Some people think there are such universal rules that apply to everyone. This sort of thinking is called moral
absolutism.
Moral absolutism argues that there are some moral rules that are always true, that these rules can be
discovered and that these rules apply to everyone.
Immoral acts - acts that break these moral rules - are wrong in themselves, regardless of the circumstances
or the consequences of those acts.
Absolutism takes a universal view of humanity - there is one set of rules for everyone - which enables the
drafting of universal rules - such as the Declaration of Human Rights.
Religious views of ethics tend to be absolutist.
Why people disagree with moral absolutism:
Many of us feel that the consequences of an act or the circumstances surrounding it are relevant to
whether that act is good or bad
Absolutism doesn't fit with respect for diversity and tradition
www.bbc.co.uk/ethics/introduction/intro_1.shtml
7/8
4/2/13
Moral relativism
Moral relativists say that if you look at different cultures or different periods in history you'll find that they
have different moral rules.
Therefore it makes sense to say that "good" refers to the things that a particular group of people approve of.
Moral relativists think that that's just fine, and dispute the idea that there are some objective and
discoverable 'super-rules' that all cultures ought to obey. They believe that relativism respects the diversity of
human societies and responds to the different circumstances surrounding human acts.
Why people disagree with moral relativism:
Many of us feel that moral rules have more to them than the general agreement of a group of people that morality is more than a super-charged form of etiquette
Many of us think we can be good without conforming to all the rules of society
Moral relativism has a problem with arguing against the majority view: if most people in a society agree
with particular rules, that's the end of the matter. Many of the improvements in the world have come
about because people opposed the prevailing ethical view - moral relativists are forced to regard such
people as behaving "badly"
Any choice of social grouping as the foundation of ethics is bound to be arbitrary
Moral relativism doesn't provide any way to deal with moral differences between societies
Moral somewhere-in-between-ism
Most non-philosophers think that both of the above theories have some good points and think that
there are a few absolute ethical rules
but a lot of ethical rules depend on the culture
www.bbc.co.uk/ethics/introduction/intro_1.shtml
8/8