Colin Rowe: Space As Well-Composed Illusion: Christoph Schnoor
Colin Rowe: Space As Well-Composed Illusion: Christoph Schnoor
Christoph Schnoor
Space-talk
It seems almost certain that space-talk made its decisive entry into the critical
vocabulary of American and English architects with the publication of Sigfried
Giedions Space, Time and Architecture in 1941, and Nikolaus Pevsners An
Outline of European Architecture in 1943. Certainly, before the early 1940s,
English-speaking readers appear to have been relatively underexposed to the
analysis of buildings in terms of space and, since then, have come to accept
such analysis (Bruno Zevi, Architecture as Space, 1957, might be an instance) as
a relative commonplace; and, quite possibly, Le Corbusier might be taken as a
representative of something to the same effect related to French usage. For,
while Le Corbusiers publications seem to be distinctly dumb as regards
space-talk, with him too the new critical vocabulary (ineffable space) seems
to insinuate itself during the course of the 1940s and to become explicitly
advertised in New World of Space (1948). However this may be, when AngloAmerican usage is considered, there remain two, possibly three, exceptions to
what has just been stipulated: Bernard Berenson; his disciple Geoffrey Scott;
and, maybe, Frank Lloyd Wright.1
British-born architectural historian Colin Rowe is well known for his intriguing
analyses of modern architecture. But rarely did Rowe examine architectural space
explicitly as a scholarly subject-matter as he commences to do here, in this footnote
to a 1979 lecture. And even as he does, the topic seems to be to him of such
insignificance that it can only be picked up with a note of contempt: space-talk
does not imply that anything serious could lie behind the word. Thus, this essay
investigates a neglected aspect, both in terms of Rowes essays as in scholarly
critique of them: neither has he himself explicitly written about space nor has any
scholar explicitly examined the role of architectural space in his writings which
might simply mean that there is nothing to say?
Despite such under-representation of the topic both on Rowes part and on
the part of his critics, this paper argues that not only does space play a very
Colin Rowe, The Present Urban Predicament, lecture delivered at The Royal Institution, London in
1979, in: Alexander Caragonne (ed.), As I was saying. Recollections and Miscellaneous Essays, Cambridge,
Mass. and London: MIT Press, 1996, Vol. 3, 165220, here 219.
1
Christoph Schnoor
important role in his writings, but also that Colin Rowe is in fact one of the few
post-war historians to have conveyed differentiated spatial analyses of modern
architecture. It is argued that their success lies in the fact that Rowe showed no
interest in the notion of pure space as Nikolaus Pevsner might have but that he
understood architectural space as relevant only when contaminated with
ambiguity and active character: Rowe categorizes modernist space in terms of
oppositions such as flatness versus depth and horizontal versus vertical, as well as
the overlap of conflicting scales or whole systems, while infusing space with the
notion of movement.2 Rowe also belongs to the small number of post-war historians
who introduced the analysis of modernist spaces to an English speaking audience,
having dealt with the subject in his pice de jeunesse of 1947, The Mathematics of the
Ideal Villa. Thus, he should have included his own writings in the introductory
quote. It is suggested that space plays the most important minor part in his
writings. This essay investigates how the above categories affect Rowes readings of
and writings on space and where their intellectual sources might be located; further
it suggests that it is through the marriage of aspects of composition with Rowes
intense interest in perception, that space becomes either the carrier or the other
central item that is used to transport his arguments.
The role of architectural space in Rowes essays has not been separately
addressed by scholars reviewing his writings, either. Out of Mauro Marzos 2010
volume LArchitettura come testo e la figura di Colin Rowe, a collection of essays on
Rowe as summary of a conference held in Venice in 2008, particularly Katia
Mazzucco, Francesco Benelli and Sbastien Marot establish the historiographic
background of Rowes education in art history as provided by Rudolf Wittkower in
London.3 Historian Anthony Vidler has, in his Histories of the Immediate Present,
recently described Rowes approach to historiography as Mannerist Modernism,
devoting a full chapter on Colin Rowe.4 Vidler lucidly points out the significance of
Rowes Mannerism and Modern Architecture of 1950, stressing how much Rowe
was inspired by Michelangelos architectural juxtapositions and clashes, and how he
applied them to his reading of, for example, Le Corbusiers architecture. Thus,
This paper was made possible by a travel grant by Unitec Institute of Technology in Auckland, New
Zealand. The author was able to visit the Rowe library in Austin/Texas in 2010 which not only holds
Rowes books but additionally an assembly of Rowes documents fragments of published and
unpublished writings. The author gratefully acknowledges the opportunity to present preliminary
versions of this paper both at the Journal of Art Historiography Colloquium Constructing the Discipline
held in Glasgow in 2010, and at the Collins-Kaufmann-Forum at the Columbia-University in New
York. He expresses thanks to Katia Mazzucco for her comments, and to Mary McLeod and Barry
Bergdoll for their joint invitation and ensuing discussions. Further particular thanks go to Francesco
Benelli and Francesco Passanti for their assessments and advice.
3 These are: Katia Mazzucco, Lincontro di Colin Rowe con Rudolf Wittkower e unimmagine del
cosiddetto metodo warburghiano; Francesco Benelli, Rudolf Wittkower e Colin Rowe: continuit e
frattura and Sbastien Marot, Extrapolating Transparency, in: Mauro Marzo (ed.), Larchitettura come
testo e la figura di Colin Rowe, Venezia: Universit Iuav di Venezia and Marsilio, 2010.
4 Anthony Vidler, Histories of the Immediate Present. Inventing Architectural Modernism, Cambridge,
Mass./London: MIT Press, 2008, chapter Mannerist Modernism: Colin Rowe, 61-106.
2
Christoph Schnoor
Vidler suggests that Rowes central modus operandi was that of a Mannerist
Modernism: his art of producing unexpected juxtapositions and of finding
architecturally ambiguous situations is indeed central to Rowes writings and
possibly to his interest in architecture overall. Vidler, however, does not discuss
Rowes spatial analyses. Werner Oechslin has repeatedly pointed at the significance
of Rowes writings, not the least in his introduction to the German version of Peter
Eisenmans PhD thesis, where he locates Rowes approach to the analysis of formal
principles within the context of Rowes studies with Wittkower.5 Moreover, in the
introduction of Transparenz, the German version of Rowes and Robert Slutzkys
examination of phenomenal transparency, Oechslin traces the origins of this article
in the Texas-years of Rowe, Slutzky and Swiss architect Bernhard Hoesli.6 But as
much as analysis of formal principles is discussed, Oechslin does not approach the
spatial implications of such analysis. Alexander Caragonne ambitiously
reconstructed the Texas Rangers years and gave a historiographically significant
account of the work of the group of architects and historians at work in
Austin/Texas in the early 1950s.7
Rowes analyses of urban space, particularly in Collage City, and their huge
implications for urban planning from the 1970s onwards, do not form part of this
enquiry. Rather, and in order to stay concise, this essay predominantly draws on The
Mathematics of the Ideal Villa Rowes publication of 1976 which includes essays
dating from 1947 to 1959, augmented by archival material from Rowes estate. Of
the essays in this volume, at least six argue partially through the means of analyzing
space: The Mathematics of the Ideal Villa, Transparency: Literal and Phenomenal,
Chicago Frame, Neo-Classicism and Modern Architecture I/II and La
Tourette. Of these, particularly Mathematics, Transparency and NeoClassicism I/II are called on for closer investigation.
Werner Oechslin, Out of History? Peter Eisenmans Formal Basis of Modern Architecture, in:
Peter Eisenman, Die formale Grundlegung der modernen Architektur, Zurich: gta, 2005, 1261.
6 Werner Oechslin, Transparenz: die Suche nach einer verlsslichen Entwurfsmethode nach den
Prinzipien der modernen Architektur, in: Colin Rowe and Robert Slutzky, Transparenz, Zurich: gta,
1997 (1968), 920.
7 Alexander Caragonne, The Texas Rangers. Notes from an Architectural Underground, London and
Cambridge, Mass.: MIT Press, 1995.
5
Christoph Schnoor
Schmarsow spoke of Architektur als Raumgestalterin: August Schmarsow, Das Wesen der
architektonischen Schpfung, Leipzig: Hiersemann, 1894.
9 Notes in the margins by Rowe suggest this title.
10 Fragmented typescript, 32b, Colin Rowe library, Charles-Moore Foundation, Austin/Texas.
11 Nikolaus Pevsner, An Outline of European Architecture, London : John Murray 1948 (1943), 215.
12 Fragmented typescript, n. pag., Colin Rowe library, Charles-Moore Foundation, Austin/Texas.
13 Colin Rowe and Fred Koetter, Collage City, Cambridge, Mass.: MIT Press, 1978, 42.
8
Christoph Schnoor
Composition? Ordinance
If, on the one hand, the notion of pure space is met with scepticism, but space as an
aspect of architecture might indeed occupy a central minor role in Rowes work,
what aspects of aesthetic analysis and criticism does it need to be combined with in
order to become more acceptable? In 1956, two years after having written Character
and Composition (the essay was only published in 1974), one obvious hint comes
from an unpublished letter by Rowe to Louis Kahn, in which Rowe referred to his
conversation with Kahn of a few weeks earlier about their opposed interests in
growth and composition:
And I took the side of COMPOSITION and then had great difficulty in
explainin[g] what I meant by it. You deplored COMPOSITION because it
appeared to be no more than a manipulation of forms for the sake of effect.
You wanted to GROW a building, and I, I think, suggested that I wanted to
COMPOSE it. Or at least I was very emphatic about the PARTI.
I still am; but I do wish that I had had the time to explain myself more
completely, and had been able to indicate that the composition of which I was
speaking was the result of a process of dialectic, and not of an irrelevant
fantasy or purely arbitrary choice.14
Rowe adds what he understood composition to be: I dont like the word. I prefer
formal structure, or organisation, or perhaps anything ORDINANCE which implies
to me accepting of irreducible facts and the working out of their logical
consequences.15 One wishes to know the end of this conversation, but even from
this snippet it becomes apparent that while Kahn might have insisted on something
like letting the building compose itself, Rowe wished to understand composition
as entering into an argument with the objective data with a life of their own in
which one cant intervene as which he read Kahns hexagonal or cubic cells.16 He
was searching for the formal structure and for the logical consequences and
possibilities that derive from this structure.
It might be appropriate to listen to Rowes own words on composition in
order to determine what he meant by this. But his somewhat cryptic essay
Character and Composition that could provide clarification is indeed an oddball in
The Mathematics of the Ideal Villa. Attempting to historically trace the usage of the
terms character and composition in the English language architectural literature,
the essay clarifies as much as it obscures. Rowe points out that since both words are
Colin Rowe, letter to Louis Kahn of 7 February, 1956, unpublished typescript, Colin Rowe library,
Charles-Moore Foundation, Austin/Texas.
15 Rowe, letter to Kahn of 7 Feb 56.
16 Rowe, letter to Kahn of 7 Feb 56.
14
Christoph Schnoor
now somewhat suspect to the strictly orthodox, their suspicions do prompt some
investigation of a possible relationship and the ideas which this relationship
involves.17 It remains unclear whether Rowes attempt is to salvage both terms from
disappearance or whether the essay should be read as equally critical as supportive.
On the one hand, he sarcastically scolds the 1920s modernists for their functionalist
rhetoric and the partial irrelevance of their statements since their works were not
as functionalist as they professed them to be but on the other hand the essay is not
a full rehabilitation of the terms character and composition either.
The above mentioned letter dates from the time when Rowe analyzed a
project by Louis Kahn for a Jewish Community Center in Trenton, New Jersey.
Rowe assesses Kahns architecture as firm and palpable against the qualities of
Mies architecture as delicate and tentative.18 He summarizes Kahns Trenton
design as emphatically the most complete development to date of themes which
were there scarcely allowed to surface; and [] it seems so far to present the most
comprehensive solution to the problems initiated by the anxiety to introduce
centralization and/or the vertical stressing of space.19 This is of course a direct
reference to the compositional principles of the Beaux-Arts and thus one could
wonder about Rowes own personal preferences did he not propose to Louis Kahn
that he favoured composing a building over growing it? But it has to be clear that
Rowe, particularly in the 1950s, while attempting to reformulate the teaching
curriculum in Austin/Texas, at a school that had strongly relied on the Beaux-Arts
tradition, was trying to establish a sense of architecture as composed structural and
spatial entities: composition not as composition in the traditional Beaux-Arts sense,
but rather as using a system which underpins the design and which allows to work
with or against it, to support or to interrupt it.
Aspects of spatiality
Mathematics of the Ideal Villa: ambivalent readings of space
In The Mathematics of the Ideal Villa of 1947, Rowe introduces a set of opposites in
order to examine the similarities and differences between some of Palladios and Le
Corbusiers villas. With this, Rowe lays the foundation stone for most of his later
examinations of spatial aspects in modern architecture.
The topic of illusion and confusion is introduced in the comparison of Le
Corbusiers Villa Stein/de Monzie with Palladios Villa Malcontenta, in saying that
there is at Garches a permanent tension between the organized and the apparently
fortuitous. Conceptually, all is clear; but, sensuously, all is deeply perplexing.20 At
Colin Rowe, Character and Composition, in Colin Rowe, The Mathematics of the Ideal Villa and Other
Essays, Cambridge, Mass.: MIT Press, 1976, 62.
18 Colin Rowe, Neo-Classicicm II, in Rowe, The Mathematics of the Ideal Villa, 154.
19 Rowe, Neo-Classicicm II, 154.
20 Colin Rowe, The Mathematics of the Ideal Villa, in: Rowe, The Mathematics of the Ideal Villa, 12.
17
Christoph Schnoor
this stage, Rowe does not yet have the methodological tools to structurally analyze
this confusion; the discovery of phenomenal transparency will assist him in this.
Rowe also establishes the notion of space as implying movement. But it is
not the movement of a visitor through space; instead, it is a notion of movement that
implies volition on the part of the architecture, in this case the Villa Stein/de Monzie
as initiated by its architect:
That is, by gouging out a large volume of the block as terrace and roof garden,
he introduces a contrary impulse of energy; and by opposing an explosive
movement with an implosive one, by introducing inversive gestures alongside
expansive ones, he again makes simultaneous use of conflicting strategies.21
An important dichotomy that Rowe establishes in Mathematics is the
relative flexibility of the plan in Le Corbusiers Villa Stein/de Monzie in combination
with rigidity in section versus Palladios limited possibilities in plan but freedom in
section: Rowe relates such choices of freedom, based on the structural system used,
directly to the question of centrality and peripherical quality of a plan, establishing
that in the Villa Stein/de Monzie, the necessary equidistance between floor and
ceiling conveys an equal importance to all parts of the volume in between; and thus
the development of absolute focus becomes an arbitrary, if not impossible,
proceeding.22 He further points out that Le Corbusier accepts the principle of the
horizontal extension; thus, at Garches central focus is consistently broken up,
concentration at any one point is disintegrated, and the dismembered fragments of
the center become a peripheral dispersion of incident, a serial installation of interest
around the extremities of the plan.23 This establishes a framework Rowe was able to
pick up some ten years later, in his Neo-Classicism essays, when analyzing
modernist notions of space in terms of what he called International Style space.
Christoph Schnoor
truly modernist, as they seem to have reintroduced the cult of the axis.24 These are
Louis Kahns project for a Jewish Community Centre in Trenton of 1956 and houses
by Marcel Breuer or Philip Johnson, but also by less well-known practices as John
Johansen or Bolton and Barnstone, all of the decade between 1947 and -56. In the
first of these articles, Rowe predominantly examines the underlying theory, whereas
in the second essay he investigates the formal appearances of modernist space.
Wondering about the theoretical implications of a reappearance of symmetrical
layout that could be termed neo-Palladian, Rowe formulates the problem as
follows: Either we are scarcely able to accept these buildings as examples of
modern architecture; or we are scarcely able to accept modern architectures
theoretical professions.25 It must be clear that Rowe is prepared to accept neither of
his own propositions, calling the one absurd and the other distressing. Admitting
that modernist theory is something less than a consistent doctrine and something
more than a body of principles26, and thus prone to some contradictions in itself, he
undertakes an analysis of what he terms International Style space, in order to be
able to examine the neo-Palladian design characteristics against the modernist forms
they deviated from:
[S]ince it is implied that, while the elements of this new spatial order may all
have been present for many years, their effective synthesis was an
achievement of the twenties, it will be useful to clarify certain precepts of what
will here be called (for the want of any better term) International Style space.27
For the purpose of his investigation, he defines International Style space particularly
as the space of Le Corbusiers Villa Stein/de Monzie in Garches of 1928, Mies van
der Rohes house for the Berlin Building Exhibition of 1931 and of Le Corbusiers
foyer for the Centrosoyus Building, Moscow, which he reads as manifestations of
the spatial revolution of the twenties.28 To this list, Mies van der Rohes Barcelona
Pavilion could easily be added and its space described as follows:
In the Barcelona pavilion the walls are screens but they do not define a fixed
volume. The volume beneath the post-supported slab roof is in a sense
bounded by imaginary planes. The walls are independent screens set up
within this total volume, having each a separate existence and creating
Colin Rowe, Neo-Classicism and Modern Architecture I, in: Rowe, The Mathematics of the Ideal
Villa, 121.
25 Rowe, Neo-Classicism I, 121.
26 Rowe, Neo-Classicism I, 123.
27 Rowe, Neo-Classicicm II, 141.
28 Rowe, Neo-Classicism II, 141.
24
Christoph Schnoor
subordinate volumes. The design is unified by the slab roof on its regular
supports, not by the usual continuous screen walls.29
The plan can be composed almost entirely in terms of the needs it must
provide for, with only minimal concessions to the inescapable needs of sound
construction.30
But these lines are not from Rowe. Instead, they are taken from Henry Russell
Hitchcock and Philip Johnsons 1932 publication in which they coined the term The
International Style. Surprisingly, in their above sketch of the Barcelona pavilion
they show a disregard for any discussion of modernist plan and space from an
aesthetic and perceptual point of view, despite their mention of space as volumes.
Their analysis of this space, as witnessed in Mies van der Rohes Barcelona pavilion,
is neither very haptic nor precise, and their analysis of the plan is almost
functionalist, despite their claim to define a new style.
Rowe is more sophisticated in his analysis of International Style space. He
firstly summarizes the underlying principle of the new kind of space, stating that it
was demanded that columns be disengaged from walls and be left free to rise
through the open space of the building. [] Detached from the liberated columns,
the walls were now to become a series of freely disposed screens.31 And in variation
of what he had outlined in his 1947 comparison of Palladio with Le Corbusier, Rowe
emphasizes that the International Style Space was characterized by a tendency to
emphasize a peripheric rather than a central expression of the building.32 Referring
to Theo van Doesburgs spatial drawings, he adds that the center was to be
gradually abolished and the composition was to be developed in the opposite
direction. Or to paraphrase Gropius, the new demand led to the dead symmetry of
similar parts being transmuted into an asymmetrical but equal balance.33 Exploring
the specific relationships between column, roof and wall, Rowe notes the necessary
abolition of visible beams in this system and thus highlights a central aspect that led
to the perception of a new kind of space:
Further it should be noticed that, on the whole, International Style space was a
system which tended to prohibit any display of beams; and, rather than the
upper surface of the roof slab being flat, it seems even more certainly to have
required that the under surfaces of the roofs and floors should present
uninterrupted planes.34
Henry-Russell Hitchcock and Philip Johnson, The International Style, New York and London: Norton,
1966 (augmented edition of The International Style: Architecture since 1922, New York and London:
Norton, 1932), 48.
30 Hitchcock and Johnson, The International Style, 41.
31 Rowe, Neo-Classicism II, 141.
32 Rowe, Neo-Classicism II, 143.
33 Rowe, Neo-Classicism II, 143.
34 Rowe, Neo-Classicism II, 143.
29
Christoph Schnoor
Taking the intended freedom of the plan as a starting point, he argues that column
and underside of the roof had to remain separate in order not to lead to a
compartmentalization of space and thus to a violation of something of the freedom
of the plan.35 He further asserts that
the appearance of beams could only tend to prescribe fixed positions for the
partitions; and, since these fixed positions would be in line with the columns,
it was therefore essential, if the independence of the columns and partitions
was to be asserted with any eloquence, that the underside of the slab should
be expressed as an uninterrupted horizontal surface.36
Without explicitly naming it so, Rowe thus describes the character of the
International Style Space as a partly a-tectonic, sculptural space whose exponents
had to go through considerable efforts in order to arrive at a symbolic highlighting
of the new spatial achievements. Tectonic expression of the post- and lintel system
would have led to a structured, interrupted underside of the ceiling and would
have meant spatial expression of structural bays or cells. Rowe further clarifies that
[l]ike all other spatial systems that of the International Style resulted from a
reappraisal of the functions attributed to the column, the wall, and the roof.37
Therefore, it is only logical that he should investigate their new roles in detail. But
as innocent as his remark like all other spatial systems may seem, it indicates that
Rowe thereby positions the International Style Space within the history of
architectural theory in which the role of the column in relation to the wall has been
discussed for centuries. Abb Laugier, whose Essai sur larchitecture might have
influenced Le Corbusier in the development of his Maison Dom-Ino principle, for
example had demanded that the column must be free-standing so that its origin
and purpose are expressed in a natural way38, and had claimed that the use of
pilasters is one of the great abuses that have found their way into architecture.39
Thus with his spatial-structural analysis of the International Style space, Rowe
implicitly refers to the century-old debate of the role of the column in architecture.
Yet, Rowe does not quite go as far in this essay as assessing the symbolic role
of this detachment of column and wall; whereas, in his Chicago Frame essay of
1956, he had established the reasoning behind Mies van der Rohes decisions as to
symbolize the skyscrapers role for modernization.40 In his pre-war buildings such
as the Barcelona Pavilion, Mies used the columns to express a sense of a higher
10
Christoph Schnoor
order permeating the building. Instead of pointing this out, Rowe simply identifies
the column particularly in Mies architecture to be a caesura in a general space41
that does not spatially express the structural bay or of structural cells.
In Neo-Classicism II, Rowe further points at the different priorities of
Mies and Le Corbusiers spatiality. He differentiates between Mies who provided
the most literally perfect transcription of this delicate and complex system of logic
and Le Corbusier who did not seem to be concerned with so much consistency,
calling his distinctions between support and enclosure often perfunctory.42 He
points at the horizontality of Mies spaces, stating that his vertical planes trail out
suggestively, peripherically, into the landscape,43 whereas Le Corbusier had not
avoided the conflict between the inherent horizontality of the structural system and
the closed verticality of his buildings. Rowe suggests that in the Villa Stein/de
Monzie in Garches, Le Corbusier condensed all the long walls which contribute to a
rotary, pinwheeling moment to Mies buildings into the perimeter of a single block
where they acquire an explosive, emphatic, enriched quality very different from
Mies spaces.44
Rowe continues with a lucid analysis of Mies use of columns as it changed
from Berlin to Chicago, but it is here where this essay should be left. It will have
become obvious by now that Rowe manages to talk about space without talking
about space, that he does not attempt to define the qualities of the empty volume
that space is, but that he examines it through the analysis of the space-defining
elements, as walls, floor, ceiling and columns. He approaches spatiality through the
elements that intentionally order, rhythmicize and structure space.
In reassessing Hitchcock and Johnsons brief description of the Barcelona
Pavilion, one will find that they do attempt to name space, in saying that the walls
are screens but they do not define a fixed volume and that the walls are
independent screens set up within this total volume, having each a separate
existence and creating subordinate volumes. They speak about a hierarchy of
perceived volumes, whereas Rowe tends to define the space through the tangible
elements, and in this is more precise than Hitchcock and Johnson.
11
Christoph Schnoor
12
Christoph Schnoor
49
50
13
Christoph Schnoor
dialectic between fact and implication. The reality of deep space is constantly
opposed to the inference of shallow; and, by means of the resultant tension,
reading after reading is enforced. The five layers of space which, vertically,
divide the buildings volume and the four layers which cut it horizontally will
all, from time to time, claim attention; and this gridding of space will then
result in continuous fluctuation of interpretation.51
This topic of depth versus flatness is a recurring element in Rowes writings,
perhaps summed up by an undated set of four manuscript pages, in which he lists
four postulations, the first of which is: A slightly bizarre but tenable proposition:
that, while painting is always the simulation of three dimensions in the reality of
two more often than not great architecture is the simulation of two dimensions
in the reality of three.52
14
Christoph Schnoor
15
Christoph Schnoor
16
Christoph Schnoor
17
Christoph Schnoor
Colin Rowe, Mannerism and Modern Architecture, in: Rowe, The Mathematics of the Ideal Villa, 44.
Rowe, Mannerism and Modern Architecture, 44.
76 Giedion, Space, Time and Architecture, 493.
77 Robert Venturi, Complexity and Contradiction in Architecture, New York: Museum of Modern Art, 1966.
78 Hitchcock and Johnson, The International Style.
79 Rowe, Mannerism and Modern Architecture, 45.
80 Giedion, Space, Time and Architecture, 493.
74
75
18
Christoph Schnoor
Giedions and Rowes ways of reading the architecture of the Bauhaus building are
very closely related in terms of the metaphors used and in their shifting between
analysis and taking the perspective of the observer, as far as the comparison
between Space, Time and Architecture and Mannerism and Modern Architecture of
1950, is concerned. However in Transparency: Literal and Phenomenal, written six
years later, Rowe almost completely reverses his admiration for Gropius
achievement, criticizing him for the adherence to literal transparency, indirectly
distancing himself from Giedion, while celebrating Le Corbusiers technique of
creating phenomenal transparency, in the simultaneity of opposing ways of reading
architectural figure or space. Transparency is one of the few co-authored essays in
Rowes career and indeed a central one. Maybe a third author should have been
mentioned, even if he was not directly part of the writing as such. It seems that
architect Bernhard Hoesli was involved in the discovery and interpretation of
architectural phenomenal transparency from the start, and that this involvement led
to a historiographic complexity that still needs to be disentangled.81 What is clear so
far is that Rowes perception of space changed and possibly became more complex
through his proximity to Slutzky and Hoesli during his Austin years.
The potential intellectual short circuit in Transparency as discussed above
needs to be picked up because it points in two directions: Rowes is the approach of
an intellectual eye, and there is a close similarity between Le Corbusier and Rowe,
in terms of style and content, and, to take this further, it could be claimed, that there
would be no Rowe without Le Corbusier.82 The various instances discussed all
indicate that his writing is not concerned with space as a void, perceived by the
spectator standing inside such as one could imagine experiencing the Pantheon
but that he appreciates the artistic and intelligent manipulation of forms in order to
arrive at double readings. These double readings can take place as reading of
flatness versus depth on the faade of the Ca dOro or the Villa Schwob, or they
appear between faade and volumetric development, as in the Villa Stein/de
Monzie.
They also happen in urbanism, as Rowes interpretation of the Manica Lunga
on the Quirinale in Rome demonstrates. The reader may allow the slight digression
into urban questions: Rowes examination of the Manica Lunga has always been
overshadowed by its much better known brother idea, the comparison of the Uffizi
with the Unit. But where the Uffizi-Unit pairing is a very obvious dichotomy of
figure and ground, Rowes attention to the Quirinale reveals his interest in spatial
complexity: in order to demonstrate how the shortcomings of Le Corbusiers Unit
Rowe speaks of its own emphatic isolation could be addressed in terms of urban
space, he decides to more closely address the Palazzo del Quirinale:
This will have to remain the subject of another paper which is currently under development.
As indicated in Christoph Schnoor, Drawing with words: Colin Rowes imaginative historiography,
in: Michael Chapman and Michael Ostwald (eds.), Imagining. Proceedings of the 27th International
Conference of the Society of Architectural Historians Australia and New Zealand (SAHANZ), Newcastle,
Australia, 2010, 35964.
81
82
19
Christoph Schnoor
20
Christoph Schnoor
One last element needs to be brought in, only hinted at so far: One of the
most important means of interpreting space for Rowe seems to be the idea of
movement implied in buildings. While in many instances he examines space by
analyzing object-qualities and the objects compositional properties, in his analysis
of International Style Space he gets much closer to space as a phenomenon. Having
summarily stated that the charm of Miess spaces at this date lay in their peculiarly
limpid quality, in their lyrical sensitiveness to the most expensive materials, he
compares Mies vertical planes [that] trail out suggestively, peripherically, into the
landscape, as already quoted above, with Le Corbusiers solutions that bring
together an outward movement with inward containment:
[Le Corbusier] had always been predisposed to internalize the peripheric
incident as, for instance, at Garches, where all the long walls which
contribute a rotary, pinwheeling movement to Miess buildings are condensed
into the compass of a single block within which they acquire an explosive,
emphatic, enriched quality, completely distinguished from the relaxed
Miesian serenity.87
Whereas above the emphasis lay in the comparison of the horizontality of Mies
architecture versus Le Corbusiers verticality, charged with tension, here it needs to
be observed that verbs like trail, and adjectives as peripherical, rotary,
pinwheeling, even more so explosive as opposed to relaxed are used to express
not only movement, but also to imply forces perceived behind the movement:
tension and pressure; an organic energy. These qualifications remarkably activate or
energize the built elements and illustrate what both a visitor to the spaces might
feel, and what the designer himself might have felt while drawing this element of
the building: invisible forces that offer and negate possibilities.88
As alluded to above, this technique goes back to Wlfflin and to Theodor
Lipps, the father of the theory of Einfhlung. On the one hand Lipps writings
informed Geoffrey Scotts Architecture of Humanism; and on the other hand, the idea
of Einfhlung, taken into Heinrich Wlfflins Prolegomena of a Psychology of
Architecture from Robert Vischer and Hermann Lotze, lies behind Wlfflins
analyses of the baroque in his Principles of Art History, which was in Rowes
possession. It is suggested here that Rowe, even if unwittingly, used analytical
methods and categories closely related to Wlfflins comparison of Renaissance and
Baroque in their relation to position and movement. In the section on the Linear and
Painterly in his Principles of Art History, Wlfflin says: Of course, all architecture
[] reckons with certain suggestions of movement; the column rises, in the wall,
living forces are at work, the dome swells upwards, and the humblest curve in the
21
Christoph Schnoor
decoration has its share of movement, now more languid, now more lively.89 And
the idea of movement is clearly expressed in Renaissance and Baroque:
Massiveness and movement are the principles of the baroque style. It did not
aim at the perfection of an architectural body, nor at the beauty of growth, as
Winckelmann would have put it, but rather at an event, the expression of a
directed movement in that body. [] Rather did the baroque concentrate the
whole strength of the building at one point, where it breaks out in an
immoderate display while the rest remains dull and lifeless. The functions of
lifting and carrying, once performed as a matter of course, without haste or
strain, now become an exercise of violent and passionate effort.90
Giedions and Rowes analyses of modernist buildings sound as if infused with this
quality of Wlfflins analyses of the Baroque.
Is it at the end, that Rowe combines van Doesburg with Wlfflin via Giedion
and his interpretation of Mannerism? Space is not described and analyzed as
experiential. Since Rowe argues at times with Gestalt theories, it may be seen as
perceptual, but only in the abstract sense of an analytical perception, an intellectual
way of seeing rather than an immediate, sensory perception. Rowes architectural
space might be the well-composed space of illusion and multi-layered perception,
the interplay between flatness and depth or between surface and space, combined
with a sense of Einfhlung into the movement and energy embodied in the elements
of architecture: column, wall and floor; and all this mostly found in and explored
through the work of Le Corbusier.
Christoph Schnoor is Associate Professor in Architecture at Unitec Institute of
Technology in Auckland, NZ; Programme Director for the Master of Architecture
(Professional) from 200709; forthcoming chapter Space and the body: Concepts of
the corporeal in Le Corbusiers work, in: Kirsten Wagner und Jasper Cepl (eds.):
Krperbilder in der Architektur / Images of the Body in Architetcure, Berlin: Wasmuth,
2012; authored book La Construction des villes. Le Corbusiers erstes stdtebauliches
Traktat von 1910/11, Zurich: gta 2008; current research on Colin Rowe in the larger
context of the analysis of spatial and formal principles in modern architecture.
Dr.-Ing. Christoph Schnoor
Unitec Institute of Technology
Auckland, New Zealand
[email protected]
89
90
22