The doctrine of sovereignty asserts that in every society where there is law, there is a relationship between habitual obedience from subjects and habitual obedience from a sovereign to no one. This chapter examines two key points of this doctrine: 1) whether the habit of obedience is sufficient to account for continuity of lawmaking authority and persistence of laws, and 2) whether being above the law is necessary for a supreme lawmaker. The author argues that mere habit is not enough, and that rules designating a succession of lawmakers are required for continuity of authority and persistence of laws. While a sovereign may face non-legal practical constraints, they are not truly limited by law as long as they are not acting under orders from another lawmaker.
We take content rights seriously. If you suspect this is your content, claim it here.
Available Formats
Download as DOCX, PDF, TXT or read online on Scribd
0 ratings0% found this document useful (0 votes)
241 views
Chapter IV. Sovereign and Subject
The doctrine of sovereignty asserts that in every society where there is law, there is a relationship between habitual obedience from subjects and habitual obedience from a sovereign to no one. This chapter examines two key points of this doctrine: 1) whether the habit of obedience is sufficient to account for continuity of lawmaking authority and persistence of laws, and 2) whether being above the law is necessary for a supreme lawmaker. The author argues that mere habit is not enough, and that rules designating a succession of lawmakers are required for continuity of authority and persistence of laws. While a sovereign may face non-legal practical constraints, they are not truly limited by law as long as they are not acting under orders from another lawmaker.
We take content rights seriously. If you suspect this is your content, claim it here.
Available Formats
Download as DOCX, PDF, TXT or read online on Scribd
You are on page 1/ 4
IV.
Sovereign and Subject1
In criticizing the simple model of law as coercive orders we have so far raised no questions concerning the sovereign person or persons whose general orders continue according to this conception, the law of any society. Indeed in discussing the adequacy of the idea of an order backed by threats as an account of the different varieties of law, we assumed that in any society where there is law, there actually exist a sovereign: a person or body of persons whose orders the great majority of society habitually obey and who does not habitually obey any other person or persons.2
1 This chapter deals entirely with the Doctrine of Sovereignty which
asserts that in every human society where there is law, there exists a relationship between subjects rendering habitual obedience and a sovereign who renders habitual obedience to no one.The author emphasized two points which are of special concern. The first point deals with the concept of a habit of obedience -- that which is required on the part of those to whom the sovereigns laws are applicable and whether such habit would account for the two salient features of most legal systems: continuity of the authority to make law and the persistence of laws such that it succeeds those who made the law and those who followed it. On the other hand, the second point deals with the position occupied by the sovereign.
2 Hart, Concept of Law (1949), p. 50
The doctrine of sovereignty asserts that in every
human society, where there is law, there is ultimately to be found the simple relationship between subjects rendering habitual obedience and a sovereign who renders habitual obedience to no one. This vertical structure relationship between sovereign and subject is as essential a part of society which possesses law, as a backbone is of a man. Two points in this doctrine are of special importance. The first point concerns the idea of a habit of obedience,3 which is all that is required on the part of those to whom the sovereigns laws apply. The second point concerns the position occupied by the sovereign above the law: he creates law for others and so imposes legal duties or limitations upon them whereas he is said himself to be legally unlimited and illimitable.4 The Habit of Obedience and the Continuity of Law The idea of obedience is not free from complexities. However, it is not easy to state the connection between the giving of the order and the performance of the specified act in order that the latter should constitute obedience. Until, this 3 The first point inquires whether such a habit is sufficient to account for two salient features of most legal systems: the continuity of the authority to make law possessed by a succession of different legislators , and the persistence of laws long after their maker and those who rendered him habitual obedience have perished.
4 The second point inquires whether the legally illimitable status of the supreme lawgiver is necessary for the existence of law.
concern is settled, the whole idea of a general habit of
obedience to the laws of a country must remain obscure. Suppose that there is a population with a territory in which Rex, as an absolute monarch, reigns for a very long time. He controls his people by general orders backed by threats requiring them to do various things which they would not otherwise do, and to abstain from things which they would otherwise do. Though there was trouble on the first years of reign, things had settled down and the people eventually followed his orders. It will be true of most people in our imagined community, at any time after the initial period of trouble, that they have generally obeyed the orders of Rex and are likely to continue to do so. It is noted that in the social institution under Rex, the habit of obedience is a personal relationship between each subject and Rex; each regularly does what Rex orders him to do or not to do. Further, it can be observe in such institution that all that is required from the community to constitute Rex as the sovereign are the personal acts of obedience on the part of the ruled. Each of them only needs to obey, and as long as there is regular obedience, no one in the community needs to express his view as to whether or not his obedience to Rex is right and proper. Unity is likewise present in the institution of Rex so that it may be called a state. This unity is constituted by the fact that its members obey the same person, event though they may have no views as to the rightness of doing so. Let us now suppose that, after a successful reign, Rex dies leaving his son Rex II who then starts to issue orders. The fact that there was obedience to Rex orders
does not automatically guarantee that there will also be
habitual obedience to the orders issued by Rex II. We shall have to wait and see whether the people will follow the orders of Rex II to be able to say that he is now sovereign and his orders are law. Only after a considerable a period of time to which his orders are followed before we can establish that there established a habit of obedience. However, if there is a rule that provides for the succession of the eldest son, then Rex II will have the title and the right to issue orders, which will lead us to say that said orders are already law before the habitual obedience was established. There are three salient differences between habits and rules as follows: a. For a group to have a habit, it is enough that their behavior in fact converges; b. Where there are rules, deviation from standard is generally accepted as a good reason for making it; and c.
The internal aspect of rules.
Acceptance of a rule by a society at one moment
does not guarantee its continued existence. There may be revolution; the society might reject the rules. Thus the statement that the legislator has the right to legislate presupposes the existence of a rule providing that the legislator may do so. The continuity of legislative authority which characterizes most legal systems depends on that form of social practice which constitutes the acceptance of a rule. It may be summarized that even if Rex, whose general
orders are habitually obeyed, such habitual obedience are
not enough as basis for the next legislator to succeed and for the continuity of the legislative power because of the reasons that habits are not normative, and habits cannot refer to a class or line of successive legislators. Just because there is habitual obedience in one legislator doesnt not mean that there will also be habitual obedience to the succeeding legislator. The Persistence of Law In 1944 a woman was prosecuted in England and convicted for telling fortunes in violation of the Witchcraft Act (1735). This is an example of a legal phenomenon that a statute enacted centuries ago may still be law today.5 We cannot narrow the application of laws and conclude that their survival and applications solely depend on the lifetime of their makers and those people who initially obeyed them. In simple terms or our previous Rex example, consider REX I, II, and III, all qualified to legislation under a general set of rule. When the individual ruler dies, the legislation he created lives on and carried on to the next legislator. An ingenious attempt to explain such phenomenon was made by Hobbes, echoed by Bentham and Austin, said that the legislator is he, not by whose authority the laws were first made, but by whose authority they now continue to be laws. Legal Limitations on Legislative Power 5 How can a law made by an earlier legislator, long dead, still be a law for a society that cannot be said habitually to obey him?
In the doctrine of sovereignty, the general habit of
obedience of the subject has, at its complement, the absence of any such habit in the sovereign. He makes law for his subjects and makes it from a position outside any law. It is important to understand that the legally unlimited power of the sovereign is his by definition. This means that the power of the legislative power can only be limited if the legislator creating such legislations were acting under the orders of another legislator. Therefore, if he is sovereign, then he is not following any other legislator and there are no legal limits in his legislative power. This theory does not insist that there are no limits on the sovereigns power, only that there are no legal limits on it. The sovereign, however, may decide to defer in performing legislative powers depending on the surround circumstance and the consequences of exercising such power. Example, he may defer from exercising such power if he fears a revolt or uprising will be staged against him should he exercise such power. This may be considered as limit to his power. However, it cannot be considered as legal limits as he is not under any obligation to abstain from legislation. In summary, established by Hart:
the
following
are
the
concepts
a. Legal limitations on legislative authority consist
not of duties imposed on the legislator to obey but of disabilities contained in rules which qualify him to legislate;
b. In order to establish that an enactment is law,
we have to show that it was made by a legislator who was qualified to legislate under an existing rule and that either no restrictions are contained in the rule or there are none affecting this particular enactment; c. In order to show that we have independent legal systems, we have to show that the rules which qualify legislator do not confer superior authority on those who have also authority over other territory; d. We must distinguish between a legally unlimited legislative authority and one which, though limited, is supreme in the system; and e. The legislators habits of obedience are at the most of some indirect evidential importance.
The Sovereign Behind the Legislature
There are in many world legal systems in which the body is subject to legal limitations on the exercise of its legislative powers; yet the enactments of such legislature within the scope of its limited powers are plainly law. Examples of substantive limitations are the separation of powers, the bill of rights, particularly the provision which provides that no person shall be deprived of life, liberty, or property without due process of law. If a legislature is subject to limitation which can be removed by the members of the legislature, then such legislature has no legal limitation. Viewed differently, the difference between a legal system in which the ordinary legislature is free from legal limitations, and one where the legislature is subject to them, appears merely as a difference between the manners in which the sovereign electorate chooses to exercise its sovereign powers.