Visual Poetics
Visual Poetics
Micke lial
The collection grew oat of the conviction that the relations between the arts
have something more to offer than the study of each art can offer alone.
Mieke Bal
Rochester and Utrecht, January 1988
t
i^u\
^ &8;
1
$5-1^5
zt
N o rm a n B r y so n
183
184
Norman Bryson
Let us take from Lessing this notion of the image as atemporal, or allai-once. Obviously it corresponds to a certain truth of ordinary experience.
Paintings stay still; they dont move around the walls; their figures dont slip
out of the frame and gambol about when no one is looking. Sometimes a cult
of ideal form aspires to a shedding o f times contingencies, so that the forms
we see in painting are taken out-of the temporal flux. Or painting may eschew
ideal form and instead set dolvn an unidealized and transient moment. If we
think of the image in terms o f abstraction, and identify painting with the forms
held on the picture plane as surface flatness, time seems notably absent: no
reference to a temporal world or to narrative sequence complicates the pre
vailing stasis. Idealization, realism, and abstraction concur in the timelcssness
of images. Such timelessness allows one to think of a painting as a substance
in Aristotles sense: as an entity having (i) stable location in a single place; (ii)
independent self-existence, requiring nothing but itself in order to exist; (iii)
permanent or enduring form. A metaphysics of substance seems built into the
format of Western painting, into the picture frame. In a sense we can dispense
with frames and regard them as extrinsic to painting; yet even without its
actual frame Western painting is a structure o f framing, and within the frame
substance is held in a state purer than substances in nature. In nature substances
may move, unfold, blend, dissolve, but in the frame substance is held and
displayed in Aristotelian purity: as requiring nothing elseno other paintingin order to exist; as independently self-existent, in a single place, and in per
manent essence.
The first question I want to raise is: what kind of entity is the image, and
if it is not in fact a substance, what is it? Thinking of the image as substance
is obviously untrue to certain aspects of ordinary experience. Images do change:
after five seconds some are completely dead; others get better after the first
ten minutes. Images can also change through an individuals life, and arc one
thing in one decade, something else a decade later. The substance-view of the
image starts to founder the mom ent we shift the point of view of the discussion
to the spectator. In actual experience, looking at an image is a radically tem
poral process, which changes from moment to moment. If we think of the
saccadic movements of the eye, what vision experiences is an image distributed
across discontinuous leaps. Each act of looking attends to a different area of
the image and discloses a partial view, as vision transits through the image in
endless stops and starts. Each view finds a different perch or purchase on the
image, and the successive views are strung together serially, in a flow of time.
One might want to say that gradually these partial views are assembled, like
the pieces of a jigsaw, into a complete image, a total state, which gathers
together and supersedes the work of assemblage. Yet we do not ordinarily
experience vision as ever achieving that totality or saturation. If we could see
that way, then looking at an image would reach a distinct terminus; but vision
seems interminable. It is such that until the moment we drop wc have to go
185
oil looking; we cannot make vision stand still or repeat itself perfectly. The
state of totality is never achieved, is always postponed, is always ahead. Nor
is the idea of accumulating vision quite true to experience: when we look at
a painting we arc constantly revising our previous apprehensions, erasing or
regrouping our findings.
Let us frecze-frame an individual moment of looking and for convenience
call it a glance. The temporality of the glance is, in actual viewing, both re
tentive and protentivc: it brings with it the wake of previous views and even
as it occurs is fell as leading on to the next view. It is an occasion of experience
whose being is its becoming, which perishes immediately on attainment of
completion. The glance is an entity hard to map according to Aristotelian
substance. Since its constitution retains the past and is oriented to the future
it tacks the all-al-onceness of substance. Rather, it is a structure of interpe
netration; past and future interpenetrate it without obstruction.
The interpenetration runs, that is to say, both backwards and forwards.
When wc recognize a Pieta or a Nativity, recognition proceeds by relating the
present occasion back to past occasions when we have seen Pietas and Nativ
ities, back to their monographic conventions. Iconography provides the clearest
example of the retentive structure of the glance, yet it is not only iconographic
forms but all forms that are recognized in this way. And this is true from the
start: even the first form we rectognize is one which is related to a previous
case, and in the logic of inauguiation at work here even the first instance is
already interpenetrated by the past. The glance is a structure without origi
nation. The forward" or protentivc structure of the glance is a function of
the endless mobility or insatiability of vision. When we look at an image, wc
cannot stop our looking: looking goes on, nothing can arrest it; it seeks always
the next view and the next image, and this seeking is built into, is the foun
dation for, each individual glance in the very moment that it occurs.
Now consider what kind of image stands before, or is proposed and
assumed by, the glance. It, too, is structured according to absence of origin,
retentive-protentive temporality, and interpenetration. In a classical concep
tion of the image such as Lessings, the image inhabits a stable location in a
single place; it is a permanent or synchronic form. In the alternative view of
the image which 1 am briefly exploring here, each o f those classical fixities is
unsettled. The image is found to lack all-at-onceness, independent self-exist
ence, permanent form. We can analyze this post-classical or at least other
conception of the image either macrosco pi tally, and consider the individual
image in relation to other images, or microscopically and consider the in
dividual image by itself (though what by itself might mean is exactly the
issue).
In the macroscopic view, the image contains within itself, and is inter
penetrated without obstruction by, the whole suit of prior images, as well as
by the further, as vet empty set of future images, all of which co-exist with or
186
Norman Bryson
187
188
Norman Bryson
189
190
refuge from the paternal, coercive empire of signs (in Barthes), as an intrin
sically theological concept (in Heidegger). These are the positions which, for
discussion to advance, must be refused.
To think of the*body as an arena of encukuration rather than as the
substrate to onculuiration is, I would say, easier since Foucault, and harder
since Derrida. If our understanding of signs is thoroughly materialist, then the
material aspect of painting is itaturally thought of as continuous with its status
as sign: since signs are material work, no contradiction arises. The problem
with differun.v is that, by identifying meaning as movement between significrs.
as their mobile inter-relation, the sign is in some sense ^materialized. If the
relation which one signifier has to the rest is posited as synchronicaliy and
diachronically endless, then any local and limited operation of the sign (so
that it acts as x -> y. rather than x n) must seem a descent into contest, a
more or Jess repressive constriction oflheinftrmist expansion ofsigns, a capture
of the sign by matter. A dualism is insrituted between the local and material
capture of the sign by context and the signs inherent expansiveness (such
dualism can be criticized as the unexorcized classicism of Derridas workl. In
terms of painting, this model produces a two-tier account: painting as infor
mation, painting as mute matter. As information, painting can then be thought
to be an infinitely intertcxtual structure, which, overturning the repressive
agency of the frame, Hies out to meet all other paintings under conditions of
mutual dependence and mutual arising. As matter, painting can by the same
token be thought of as the absence of information and as sheer figurality:
as the inert pigment on canvas. One interesting consequence of the extreme
claim for the massive imertextuality of images is that an obverse picture also
presents itself: painting as an art of the material substrate, of pigment below
a threshold o f information, as pre-semiotic or semantic. Such a position ac
tually concurs with the dcpoliticized and reactionary conception of embod
iment in painting as the realm below sign activity and cultural work. All that
is lacking is a rhetoric which then celebrates that substrate as a primitive
expression o f Beingall that is missing is the lyricism of the Siren Song.
One of the most useful texts arguing against such dualism must be Pierre
Bourdieus Outline o f A Theory o f Practice (Cambridge University Press, 1976),
a work which has never, 1 think, been adequately recognized (and has been
eclipsed, like Lyotards Discours, Figure, by later work and later transforma
tions of its author). Bourdieus concept of practice is dose to what is meant
here by embodiment: work with material signs which takes place always (i) in
an actual social and economic arena, and (ii) under conditions of real time.
Bourdieus insistence is that when we look at sign activity we resolutely avoid
reducing it to information, and that we take into particular account its structure
of local and material negotiation, Bourdieus book argues, by example and is
dense: all I can indicate here are some schematic cases. In the case of arranged
marriages (the context is anthropology), while the ceremony of marriage can
191
19
Norman Bryson
193
are not appropriately analyzed through models based on texts; they disobey
the formula ut piciura poesis\ and they frustrate the hopes of any easy Visual
Poetics.
-i-j:..;