Epidemiological Research - An Introduction - An Introduction
Epidemiological Research - An Introduction - An Introduction
Epidemiological Research:
An Introduction
123
O.S. Miettinen I. Karp
McGill University Universite de Montreal
Universite de Montreal Montreal, QC
Montreal, QC Canada
Canada
Cornell University
New York, NY
USA
In my life ever since medical-school graduation half-a-century ago, Ive had the
dream of reaching true understanding of the theory of the research that would best
serve to advance the knowledge-base of medicine, of genuinely scientific medicine.
Olli Miettinen wrote this a year or so ago in his Epidemiological Research: Terms
and Concepts. For those who have had the privilege to witness his odyssey since
the 1970s, the current book comes as both a wonderful revisit of the past and
a great leap into the future. Miettinens text accompanying his course in the
1970s at Harvard was the first systematic introduction to theoretical epidemiology
(Greenland) and can be viewed as the start of modern epidemiology (Morabia).
But he never published it and therefore the book that you read now is the first
published introduction to epidemiological research by the father and grand master
of modern epidemiology.
Epidemiological Research: An Introduction, the current book of Miettinen,
in collaboration with his junior colleague Igor Karp, is a true milestone for
epidemiology, but a cautionary word may be in place about the introduction. I
remember Miettinen referring to his courses as basic, but not basal. The current
book, similarly, is basic, but not basal. It is introductory in that it develops the objects
and methods of epidemiological research from first principles, but it does so in a
breathtakingly sophisticated way, alternatingly grand and subtle in argumentation,
visionary and down-to-earth, broad and deep. For this reader one thing is particularly
clear: Miettinens discussion is still unparalleled in our field, the logic and coherence
is as spellbinding as ever (and I need to think a bit more, and better, if and when I
do not fully understand what he writes).
The structure of this book must be a treat for all epidemiologists. From epidemi-
ology: grappling with the concept through etiology as a pragmatic concern and
the object of study to the books core on objects design and methods design,
it is like travelling to familiar destinations along new roads. Although Miettinen
has always stressed the importance of objects design from first principles, I think
this book is the first to treat this topic systematically and somewhat extensively.
And although Miettinen has published quite comprehensively on the fallacies in the
v
vi Foreword
design of epidemiological studies and their remedies, I find his discussion of the
etiologic study fresh and summarized aptly and succinctly in e pluribus unum and
e unum pluribus.
What will be the effect on the practice of epidemiological research? I have no
doubt that it will be vast, but also that it will be slow to come. In the long run,
his arguments will turn out to be irresistible, although most likely modified and
expanded. It is like the effect of epidemiological research on medical practice: it is
hardly ever direct, it nearly always takes a long time, but in the end it makes a true
core contribution.
I pay tribute to the father of modern epidemiology, and recommend this volume
to assist in deep epidemiological introspection. It will benefit epidemiology and
epidemiologists greatly.
vii
viii Preface
References
1. Miettinen OS. Important concepts in epidemiology. In: Olsen J, Saracci R,
Trichopoulos D. Teaching Epidemiology. Third edition. Oxford: Oxford University Press,
2010.
2. Miettinen OS. Epidemiological Research: Terms and Concepts. Dordrecht: Springer, 2011.
Acknowledgements
Miettinen fils a polymath, even if thus far without the evidentiary portfolio of
writings studied a late-version manuscript of this book. We asked him to imagine
the youngest one of his children, the only one still young enough to realistically
consider, as a potential student of one of this youngsters paternal grandfathers
fields (theory of epidemiological research, the other one being theory of meta-
epidemiological clinical research) and to consider critically! this text as the
textbook in that youngsters introduction into this field. And we asked him to
comment from the general industrial perspective on what we wrote (sect. 14.5) about
epidemiologists role in quality assurance economic as well as medical in the
hospital-based segment of healthcare, which in Canada now absorbs about half of
the ever less sustainable fiscal burden of the countrys public-health industry.
He delighted us, for one, with a learned commentary on introductory teaching of
scholarly subjects at large and on how this text conforms with the most notable ideas
about it; and for another, he provided us with an equally insightful commentary on
industrial quality assurance in general and on its implications for modern public-
health practice. And for good measure, he permitted us to incorporate both of these
commentaries in this book (Apps. 4, 5).
We also asked Albert Hofman, of Erasmus University Medical Centre, Rotter-
dam todays preeminent leader of teaching on all aspects of epidemiological
research, from introductory courses on up, in the Erasmus Summer Programme in
particular to critically review a near-final draft of this book, with a view to his
possibly writing the Foreword to it.
Hofman indeed was kind enough to read the draft, and he had quite gratifying
words to say about it. What is much more, he did agree to write the Foreword. We
are much obliged to him.
ix
Contents
xi
xii Contents
The Black Death of 1348 and 1349, and the recurrent epidemics of the fourteenth
and fifteenth centuries, were the most devastating natural disasters ever to strike
Europe [ref.]. : : : Europe about 1420 could have counted barely more than a third
of the people it contained one hundred years before. So writes David Herlihy in his
The Black Death and the Transformation of the West (1997; p. 17).
Herlihy continues: The devastating plagues elicited a social response that
protected the European community from comparable disasters until the present
(p. 17). And: One hundred years ago, the great bacteriologist Louis Pasteur
declared: It is now in the power of man to cause all parasitic diseases to disappear
from the world [ref.] (p. 18).
Regarding Pasteurs grand vision, it is instructive to consider the history of
epidemics of smallpox, also known as variola.
As there never was any effective treatment for this commonly-fatal communica-
ble disease, healthcare directed to it always focused on prevention. Pre-scientifically
this was a matter of variolation: immunization against variola by means of
inoculation (i.e., injection of attenuated matter from variola patients pustules,
to produce a mild case of the disease). Records of this practice in China date
back to the sixth century BCE, but in Britain and its American colonies it became
rather commonplace only in the early 1700s. While fully effective, it remained
controversial on account of concerns about its safety (unintended causation of
severe, commonly fatal cases of the disease).
The dawn of science relevant to the practice of variolation was heralded by
Benjamin Franklins work on this. His goal was simple and straightforward. He
wanted to give anxious patients evidence that it was safe to have their children
inoculated. The data he assembled were most impressive. : : : This, and more, on
Franklins work on variolation can be found in I. Bernard Cohens The Triumph of
Numbers: How Counting Changed Modern Life (2005; p. 90 ff.).
Then came what has been, arguably at least, the most spectacular scientific
breakthrough in medicine, resulting in the introduction and adoption of vaccination
as the replacement of inoculation in the prevention of smallpox. (Vaccinia was a
synonym for cowpox, the smallpox vaccine being based on matter from pustules of
cowpox a disease similar to but milder than smallpox.) The scientific breakthrough
introducing vaccination was not a triumph of numbers (cf. above): it resulted
from Edward Jenners work on a single (young) person. But the resulting triumph
in medicine was, ultimately, complete: a concerted global program of vaccination,
launched by the World Health Organization, resulted in eradication complete
elimination of the smallpox virus from human populations.
In his Civilization: The West and the Rest (2011), Niall Ferguson asserts that what
distinguished the West from the Rest the mainsprings of global power were six
identifiably novel complexes of institutions and associated ideas and behaviours
(p. 12). One of these he specifies (p. 13) as:
1.1 Epidemiology as Practice of Healthcare 3
Medicine a branch of science that allowed a major improvement in health and life
expectancy, beginning in Western societies, but also in their colonies
Looking for the answer, the student might explore, for example, the websites
concerning Ottawa Public Health, the agency providing medical and paramedical
healthcare for the community/population of Canadas capital city. This agency is
constituted and functioning in accordance with the Health Protection and Promotion
Act of the province of Ontario, in which Ottawa is located. The purpose of this
Act is to provide for the organization and delivery of public health programs
and services, the prevention of the spread of disease and the promotion and
protection of the health of the people of Ontario. Among the Mandatory health
programs and services this Act specifies, quite notably, Collection and analysis of
epidemiological data (italics ours).
Pursuant to this Act, Ottawa Public Health is headed by a Medical Officer of
Health, who is a physician with provincially legislated powers to promote and
protect the publics health (italics ours). The other personnel of this agency is
composed of specialized teams of health professionals and support staff, including
: : : physicians, epidemiologists, : : : (italics ours).
This agency periodically publishes the City of Ottawa Health Status Report. The
latest one, from 2006 (as of Dec. 2011), presents a wide range of health-related in-
formation on mortality, morbidity, communicable diseases, reproductive outcomes,
4 1 Epidemiology: Grappling with the Concept
The physicians who, in Ottawa and elsewhere, produced the community diagnoses
about, say, the SARS and H1N1 (swine flu) epidemics and directed the population-
level programs to control these, and physicians who are caring for, say, occupational
populations as populations (rather than individually), we really think of as epi-
demiologists in the practice of epidemiology of community-medicine, that is. We
really do not think of them as users of epidemiology in something that is not
epidemiology.
1.2 Epidemiology as Health Research 5
Students of epidemiological research are prone to be left confused about the essence
of this line of research, at least early in their studies. To wit, one of us wrote his thesis
for the degree of Master of Public Health, in 1964, on Epidemiology and Its Method,
which at the time were topics of vigorous debate in the American Journal of Public
Health. Drawing from the various then-prevailing definitions, he merely synthesized
them in the framework of explicit principles as amounting to this: Epidemiol-
ogy is the science of the occurrence of health and illness; the scope of epidemiology
is the entirety of the occurrence of health and illness; and the method of epidemiol-
ogy is essentially the scientific method but may have some distinctive characteris-
6 1 Epidemiology: Grappling with the Concept
tics. He thus found, most notably, that to his elders epidemiology was a science, and
only this, rather than the practice of community medicine, this alone (cf. Schilling
in sect. 1.1). He refrained from expressing his own views about these ideas of his
elders (even though he hadnt been brought up in the Presbyterian culture).
David Lilienfeld son of the eminent epidemiologist Abraham Lilienfeld when
he still was a college student in the 1970s, took a more-than-casual interest in what
his fathers field really was. He delved deep into the literature on the matter; and
he brought to view 23 published definitions of epidemiology, the first one from
1927. Dissatisfied with them all, he added one of his own: epidemiology is a
method of reasoning about disease that deals with biological inferences derived from
observations of disease phenomena in population groups. (The culture surrounding
his youthful development different from that of the youngster alluded to above
presumably was the one which, quite uniquely, encourages critical study of the
Scripture, even.)
We present, in Table 1.1 below, seven notable definitions of epidemiology, from
1956 to the present. The strong impression from these definitions, disappointing to
us, is that epidemiology is seen to be a matter of research alone, and this, even,
without any inherent service relation to the practice of healthcare different from,
say, that of oncological research in relation to the practice of oncology (cf. above).
It seems that the research is seen to be conducted for the sake of the research itself,
as though there were no practice of epidemiology being served by the research (cf.
sect. 1.1).
It really does seem, on the basis of those definitions, that among epidemiological
researchers of late there hasnt been any conception of epidemiology as practice
of healthcare. Sight seems to have been lost of the field pioneered by Hippocrates
pre-scientifically, as most notably described in his Of the Epidemics; this field
made vastly more consequential by the spectacular scientific contributions to it by
Edward Jenner, John Snow, Louis Pasteur, and Robert Koch, among others; this
field later extended to combating also epidemics of non-communicable illnesses
such as congenital malformations, cancers, degenerative cardiovascular diseases,
and diabetes; this field now combating even endemic rates of population occurrence
of whatever type of illness. These practices do exist (sect. 1.1), and they are very
important. But these practices of community medicine, according to the definitions
in Table 1.1, are not epidemiology; and Ottawa Public Health, when it periodically
reports on the health of the citys residents, as determined in its practices there, is
not, according to those definitions, reporting on epidemiology. (Cf. sect. 1.1.)
According to most of those definitions in Table 1.1, epidemiology is merely the
study of something, sometimes alternatively (and unjustifiably; cf. above) said to
be the science of that something; and to this has recently and only exceptionally
been added application of the results of that study. We take those definitions to be
intended to mean that epidemiology is, in the only meaning of the term, a line of
research population-level research on the rates of occurrence of phenomena of
human health.
In those definitions there is no expression of the conception of a certain
type of practice of healthcare as inherently being epidemiology, even when its
knowledge-base does not derive from epidemiology-the-study. The knowledge-base
1.2 Epidemiology as Health Research 7
of mass screening for tuberculosis has been entirely clinical and, thus, not even in
part the result of epidemiological study. Such screening therefore has not been
epidemiology according to any of those definitions. Nor were the recent population-
level efforts to control the SARS and H1N1 (swine flu) epidemics epidemiology,
as they were programs of the practice, not ones of mere study.
However well this is done, the implication is that excluded from epidemiological
research is the basic or bench research that underpins, for example, the develop-
ment of vaccines. In these terms by the form of its objects one can define only
a part of what we take to be epidemiological research (cf. above). This, we hold,
should be the idea. For by no means is all of the research relevant to dealing with
communicable-disease epidemics, for example, singular in the form of its objects,
just as, say, oncological research isnt.
Insofar as there is taken to be a definitional form of the objects of epidemiological
research, this has to do with research on phenomena of health on the population
mass level, the level of community medicine. Relative to the clinical level,
phenomena of health on this higher level have new, emergent properties. On
the clinical level a given phenomenon of health characterizes an individual at a
particular moment in time; the phenomenon either is or is not associated with
that person-moment; it either is or is not occurring in it; it has no frequency of
occurrence at that person-moment. On the population level, by contrast, any given
phenomenon of health inherently occurs, and doesnt occur, in association with a
multitude of person-moments. It has, thus, the emergent quality of the frequency
the rate of this occurrence. This is the central element in the form of the objects
in epidemiological research on the population (rather than bench) level.
A health phenomenons rate of occurrence (on the population level) is, inher-
ently, a quantitative phenomenon; but the rate quite generally is non-singular in
magnitude. Its level varies according to various determinants of this level; it is a
function of its determinants. Therefore, epidemiological research, when addressing
rates of occurrence of phenomena of health, necessarily has occurrence relations as
its objects: a health phenomenons rate of occurrence in relation to as a function
of its determinants, this in a defined domain of people.
Given those definitions in Table 1.1 above, it should be noted that population-
level epidemiological research is not about the distributions of the phenomena of
health; and that the determinants of the rates of occurrence of phenomena of health
are not objects of epidemiological research only rates relations to these are. On
the clinical level, cases of a phenomenon of health inherently have a distribution by
gender and age, for example, while on the population level the phenomenon has
a rate of occurrence that may, or may not, depend on gender and age. And, for
example, behavioral determinants of the occurrence of phenomena of health are
objects of study in behavioral and social sciences and not in epidemiological
research, which is biomedical science (though not constituting a science; cf. above).
and their critical testings, as the philosopher Karl Popper explains in his venerable
Conjectures and Refutations (1963). In these terms there may be no limits to
scientific progress, as the polymath David Deutsch argues in his The Beginning of
Infinity (2011). A wonderful biography of oncological research is The Emperor of
All Maladies (2010) by Siddharta Mukherjee.
When a line of health research is defined by the form of its objects, without
coherence of the material objects, as epidemiological research now commonly is
(sect. 1.2 above), there is a corresponding opportunity together with, as usual, a
corresponding risk. That the focus in this research is on objects of a singular form
that of occurrence relations (sect. 1.2) provides for the development of a more-or-
less coherent body of theory to guide research on objects of that form, a learnable
research discipline for professional study of phenomena of health on the population
level and of non-health phenomena just the same. An associated risk is a certain
formalism in the research replacement of creative and critical thought by mere
conformity with the prevailing professional norms, unjustifiable ones included.
The discipline of how to conduct population-level health research is the sub-
ject of several contemporary textbooks of Epidemiology (e.g., MacMahon and
Trichopoulos, 1996, and Rothman et alii, 2008), implying that this discipline is
the denotation the only one of epidemiology. To us this is, however, only one
the most recent, a third meaning of the term (cf. sects. 1.1, 1.2), and a questionable
one at that.
The Enlightenment maxim Sapere aude! (Dare to reason!), eminently prop-
agated by the philosopher Immanuel Kant among others, should be understood
to apply to the prevailing teachings about epidemiological occurrence research as
well. After all, questioning received knowledge (scholastic) was at the very core
of Enlightenment; and the Enlightenment outlook in turn was the springboard of
the enormous progress in science subsequent to the advent of this outlook in the
seventeenth century, as Ferguson explains (sect. 1.1) even if, arguably at least,
its antecedent scientific progress was at the root of Enlightenment. (In the pre-
Enlightenment era, Copernicus dared publish only post-humously, while Galileo
was more courageous than that and suffered for it.)
When people in our post-industrial societies concern themselves with that which
is the concern in community medicine in epidemiology in this meaning of
population-level practice of preventive healthcare (sect. 1.1) they think of their
nutrition diet and dietary supplements first and foremost. It therefore is
particularly illustrative of epidemiological research in this disciplinary sense of
it, to examine its accomplishments with focus on nutrition: what is known? what
is the basis of this knowledge from epidemiological research? and what does this
say about the scientific prowess of our contemporary discipline of epidemiological
research?
We devote much of chapter 2 of this book to this topic. It illustrates the stagnation
that in research tends to flow from formalism and from its associated academic
routine of counting publications instead of contributions. The central flaw in todays
disciplinary framework of epidemiological research is, as we will illustrate, its
10 1 Epidemiology: Grappling with the Concept
focus on the methodology of the research, without regard for disciplined objects
design before methods design. (Stagnation consequent to formalism in societal
development was a major concern of the Soviet leader Michael Gorbachev when he
launched his famous programs of openness/glasnost and restructuring/perestroika.)
As set forth in the three sections above, there now is epidemiology in three different
meanings of the term; and there could just as well be a fourth one: given that
there is epidemiology in the meaning of the theory concepts and principles
(and terminology) of epidemiological research (sect. 1.3 above), a related, more
proximal but very different meaning of epidemiology would be that of the theory
of epidemiological practice, a theoretical discipline yet to be introduced, even
though that of clinical practice has been in Up from Clinical Epidemiology &
EBM (2011) by one of us.
Given the prevailing triad of meanings of epidemiology (sects. 1.1, 1.2, 1.3
above), a student now pursuing an academic degree in epidemiology unspecified
(as now is usual) needs to be clear on which one of the prevailing three meanings
of the term is the one of his/her chosen future career. For this is a prerequisite for
understanding how the studies preparatory to the career should be composed from
the three epidemiologies that now may be available for study.
As for epidemiology in the meaning of a discipline of research, the most
important orientational questions are these: Does a future practitioner of community
medicine need to study this? and, To what extent does study of this discipline
constitute the necessary preparation for a career in epidemiological research? To
that first question our answer is simple: Not really, but an introductory course might
be a justifiable investment of time and effort, with merely impressionistic education
the aim of this. (The future practitioner really would need to study the theory
concepts and principles of the practice, were such study to be available, and then
the current knowledge-base of this practice and how to update this knowledge.) And
to that second question our answer, below, is rather involved. Preparation for a career
on the theory of population-level epidemiological research the development and
teaching of this is a very uncommon concern of the student, and it thus is not our
express concern in this book, even though an introductory course on epidemiological
research is very useful for the future theoretician as well.
The student whose future career will be one of population-level epidemiological
research needs to make good choices in relevant areas. One of these now receiving
much too little attention has to do with the substantive focus in the studies,
including in any thesis work (of which the subsequent research commonly is an
unwitting extension). For (s)he needs to understand that society does not sponsor the
research in order that the researchers can indulge in their interests; there needs to be
a societally justifiable purpose in the research (cf. Preface). Consider two examples:
1.4 Epidemiology as a Subject of Study 11
Parallel with this program of maintaining awareness of the goings-on in the field
there is, of course, the need for a counterpart of this in respect to epidemiological
research, which, ideally at least, is in the service of the practice. The research at
large deserves only superficial following, to remain up-to-date on what the topics
are. On the other hand, research in ones own area of subject-matter needs to be
followed both inclusively and in depth, the relevant basic research included.
No good purpose in the education of epidemiological researchers, we think, is
served by a general course addressing research on select topics in substantive epi-
demiology, given the great diversity of subject-matter in the students future lines of
epidemiological research or, for that matter, of epidemiological-type research that
actually is extraepidemiological. Equally meaningless are seminar presentations of
studies on a limitless melange of subject-matter, empty of content that the audience
at large should consider for self-development as epidemiological researchers.
Last, but by no means least, the most obvious point here: For future researchers
on population-level topics of the epidemiological form (as superficially specified
in sect. 1.3 above) the generally directly-relevant preparatory studies toward good
choices are ones of the theory of that research. Epidemiology in this research-
discipline sense is what the studies principally are about. Study of it should be
materially indeed, critically helpful in efforts to optimize decisions about what,
exactly, to study a matter of the studies objects design and also how to study
it a matter of the studies methods design so long as at issue is population-level
(rather than basic) research.
It may not be obvious, however, what these theory studies, even in their broadest
outlines, are or should be about. But even before this question there is the one about
the necessary prerequisites for these studies. The student should master certain
general concepts of medicine and science, but the availability of a suitable reference
text should allow inquiry into these as needed, rather than necessarily in advance
of the studies on the theory specific to population-level epidemiological research.
(Cf. Preface.)
The student absolutely needs a background in (probability theory and then)
statistics. For as mathematics is to physics, so statistics is to population-level
epidemiological research. Major background study of mathematics is an absolute
prerequisite for any serious study for a career in physics; but: mathematics is not
the theory the embodiment of the concepts and principles of physics, nor is
physics an outgrowth of mathematics (a field of meta-mathematics, as it were). The
objects of population-level epidemiological research are generally about frequencies
(sect. 1.2) and hence statistical in form; such epidemiological research therefore is
statistical research in form (while medical in substance). But as with mathematics in
relation physics, statistics is not, nor does it subsume, the theory of population-level
epidemiological research.
Students of epidemiological research thus need to have suitable preparatory
education in (probability theory and) statistics, and of course the necessary math-
ematical preparedness for this. The suitable education in statistics would mainly
focus on topics of multiple regression; and it would not confuse and mislead
1.4 Epidemiology as a Subject of Study 13
the students with endogenously statistical ideas about research with survey
research, sample size determination, multiple hypothesis testing, and data-
suggested hypotheses, among others. For, to say it again, statistics is not, nor does
it subsume, the theory of statistical science.
The rest of this book is, in the main, quite extensive an exposition of what
we think these theory studies should be about, on the introductory level. But in
utterly succinct terms, as insinuated above, it can be said that at issue really are
only two broad topics: objects design and methods design for population-level
epidemiological research. With these broad topics suitably construed, theory of
epidemiological data analysis (really, synthesis of the data to the study result)
becomes essentially a non-topic.
As a student setting out to prepare for a career in epidemiological research
grapples with the concept of epidemiology per se and that of epidemiological
research in relation to this these frustrating topics at the very outset of the studies
(s)he would do well, we think, being mindful of two principles bearing on this.
1. Critical for progress in any field of science generally is propitious definition of
the field in question. Highly illustrative of this is the historical fact that chemistry
started its spectacular progress only once Robert Boyle distinguished between
mixtures and compounds; defined elements as constituents of compounds,
introducing the term analysis for the study of these compositions (cf. data
analysis as a term for data synthesis, above); and defined chemistry itself by its
being not about mixtures but about compounds. These revolutionary ideas he
set forth in his book fittingly entitled The Sceptical Chymist (1661).
The student of epidemiological research should reflect on the relative merits
of defining epidemiological research as (a) the study of the distribution and
determinants of phenomena of health in human populations (or some variant of
this), or as (b) research including basic research for advancement of the
practice of community medicine, of epidemiology in this meaning.
2. Read not to contradict, nor to believe, but to weigh and consider (ref. 1
below). In his/her understanding of the theory of epidemiological research, the
student of this will ultimately be alone, solely responsible for his/her own (sic)
understanding. For the vision of one man lends not its wings to another man
(ref. 2 below). (A practitioner of epidemiology, by contrast, needs to defer to
experts shared beliefs knowledge in this meaning on the substantive topics
that are relevant.)
References
1. Bacon F. Of studies. In: Bacon F. The Essays or Counsels Civil and Moral. Edited with an
Introduction and Notes by Brian Vickers. Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1999; p. 134.
2. Gibran K. On teaching. In: Gibran K. The Prophet. New York: Alfred A Knopf, 1970.
Chapter 2
Epidemiological Knowledge: Examples
Taubes (ref. in sect. 2.1 above) makes a quite compelling case for cancer, too,
being a disease of civilization, emerging in all essence only with the advent of the
civilized diet low in fats and high in carbohydrates as a feature of agricultural
societies, up to 10,000 years already.
He describes as a piece of seminal work a 120-page report by Richard Doll
and Richard Peto, in 1981, that reviewed the existing evidence on changes in
cancer incidence over time, changes upon migration from one region of the world to
another, and differences in cancer rates between communities and nations (p. 209).
They concluded, Taubes says, that diet was causing 35 percent of all cancers,
though the uncertainties they considered to be so vast that the number could be
as low as 10 percent or as high as 70 percent (pp. 209-10).
By the end of the 1990s, clinical trials and large-scale prospective studies
had demonstrated that the dietary fat and fiber hypotheses of cancer were almost
assuredly wrong, and similar investigations had repeatedly failed to confirm that red
meat played any role (p. 211).
2.2 Nutrition and Oncogenesis 19
The Cancer Prevention Overview (PDQ ) of the U.S. National Cancer Institute,
the Health Professional Version of this (consulted in December 2011, last modified
04/29/2011), gives the following synopsis of that massive WCRF/AICR review:
With respect to dietary factors that may protect against cancer, the greatest consistency
was seen for fruits and non-starchy vegetables. In the WCRF/AICR report, conclusions
were reached that both fruits and non-starchy vegetables were associated with probable
decreased risk of lung cancer. Thus, even for the two dietary exposure classes that the
current evidence suggests may have the greatest cancer prevention potential, the evidence
was judged to be less than convincing and was applicable to only a few malignancies.
From this it may appear that the WCRF/AICR review had nothing to say about
cancer prevention in accordance with either one of the two hypotheses addressed
by Taubes not by avoidance of fats nor by avoidance of carbohydrates, in the
diet. These topics are, however, among the 61 (sic) items of food and drink
the WCRT/AICR report addressed in terms of total fat and foods containing
sugars, and neither one of these two did the WCRF/AICR experts judge to confer
convincing increased risk or probably increased risk for any of the 13 cancers
(by site; table in the foldout; cf. Taubes quote from the review above). Those
experts judgements were based on review of studies on humans, non-experimental
(cohort and case-control studies) as well as experimental.
20 2 Epidemiological Knowledge: Examples
Based on its own reviews, the NCI places no dietary factors under Risk factors
causally associated with cancer nor under Risk factors with uncertain associations
with cancer. It says only this:
Observational epidemiologic studies (case-control and cohort studies) have suggested
associations between diet and cancer development, but randomized trials of interventions
provided little or no support. : : : Ecologic, cohort, and case-control studies found an asso-
ciation between fat and red meat intake and colon cancer risk, but a randomized controlled
trial of low-fat diet in postmenopausal women showed no reduction in colon cancer. The
low-fat diet did not affect all-cancer mortality, overall mortality, or cardiovascular disease.
Evidently, the NCI places more reliance on randomized trials than ecologic,
cohort, and case-control studies. But it leaves open the possibility that the trials
have been about relatively short-term effects, which is not what the fat and
carbohydrate hypotheses are about.
The NCI site addresses vitamin and dietary supplement use, under the rubric
of Interventions. The antioxidants among these have no representation at all
under those with proven benefits. Under the other rubric, those with no proven
benefits, the NCI paints the big picture thus:
Some have advocated vitamin and mineral supplements for cancer prevention. Many
different pathways for anticancer effects have been invoked. A commonly tested hypothesis
is that antioxidant vitamins may protect against cancer, based on the premise that oxidative
damage to DNA leads to cancer. However, the evidence is insufficient to support the use of
multivitamin and mineral supplements or single vitamins or minerals to prevent cancer [ref.]
: : : Research into the potential anticancer properties of vitamin and mineral supplements is
ongoing, and the results continue to reinforce the lack of efficacy of vitamin supplements
in preventing cancer. Results from several large-scale randomized trials were published in
2009. [The supplementation] : : : did not reduce : : : had no benefit : : : was not efficacious
: : : was not efficacious : : : [produced] an increase : : :
But again, were those randomized trials addressing the much-delayed effect of
reduced DNA damage, in early life, on occurrence of overt cancer in middle age or
later? See sections 7.1 and 7.2.
For reasons of symmetry, as the saying goes, we could have invoked the neologism
presbogenesis a` la atherogenesis and oncogenesis to denote the process of
biological ageing (of tissues; Gr. presbus, old man).
From the vantage of nutrition and health, the ultimate concern is not the
occurrence nor the nature of this process but the rate of it, its rate in causal relation to
nutritional determinants of it, micronutrient supplementation of diet included. The
slower is this rate, the longer tends to be (by a reasonable presumption) the duration
of life, including life free of (overt) cardiovascular disease from atheromatosis
and free of (overt, adult-onset) cancer. These degenerative diseases (along with
arthrosis and dementia, i.a.) can be viewed as largely being manifestations of
relatively advanced stages of this (cumulative) presbogenesis.
Taubes (ref. in sect. 2.1) reviews the spectacular benefits of semi-starvation on
the health and longevity of laboratory animals (p. 218 ff.). The calorie-restricted
animals live longer because of some metabolic or hormonal consequences of semi-
starvation, not because they are necessarily leaner or lighter (p. 219). And, back to
his leit motif, he writes (pp. 219-20) this:
The characteristics that all these long-lived organisms seem to share definitively are reduced
insulin resistance, and abnormally low levels of blood sugar, insulin, and insulin-like growth
factor. As a result, the current thinking is that a lifelong reduction in blood sugar, insulin,
and IGF bestows a longer and healthier life. The reduction in blood sugar also leads to
reduced oxidative stress : : : [Italics ours.]
Peoples concern to preserve their health is most pronounced in such truly modern
countries as the U.S.; and, as weve noted, this concern translates into preoccupation
with diet first and foremost. In these countries, peoples main dietary health-concern
now most commonly is prevention and/or control of obesity.
Given the major epidemic of obesity that has emerged in the U.S. and elsewhere
in the last few decades, public-health officials, too, now view obesity as the
main diet-related health problem in countries such as the U.S. Their concern is
accentuated by the common conception of obesity as a causal precursor of diabetes
and cardiovascular disease.
In the context of this major epidemic there has been no commensurate surge in
research into the etiology/etiogenesis of obesity barogenesis could be the term for
weight gain (Gr. baros, weight) as the causation of weight gain has been taken
to be obvious and well known, on a-priori grounds. Gary Taubes (ref. in sect. 2.1)
addresses this situation quite critically.
Everyone concerned with this matter, Taubes included, is committed to the first
law of thermodynamics that of the conservation of energy as it bears on the
storage of energy (as fat) in adipose (fat) tissues: If over a given interval of time
there is a given change in the amount of energy a person has stored as fat, this
is associated with a corresponding, energy-equivalent cumulative difference, over
that interval of time, between the persons energy intake (from diet) and energy
expenditure (in physical activity, i.a.) and conversely, of course.
The ordinary reading of this equivalence focuses on the idea quite correct
that any induced imbalance/difference in the rates of energy intake and energy
expenditure, cumulatively over an interval of time, produces its energy-equivalent
change in the amount of adipose tissue. And from this flows, first, the idea that to
avoid weight gain, the need is to see to it that the intake of energy does not exceed
the expenditure of it, and, second, the idea that for weight reduction the need is to
decrease the (weekly or so) quantity of ones energy intake and/or to increase that
of energy expenditure (by increasing physical activity).
Taubes relates the appearance, in 1976, of Theodore Cooper, then U.S. Assistant
Secretary of Health, as an expert witness before U.S. Senator George McGoverns
committee which was developing its Dietary Goals for the United States. Cooper
first testified that the consumption of high carbohydrate sources with the induction
of obesity constitutes a very serious public health problem in the underprivileged
and economically disadvantaged (p. 404).
But in response to the Senators looking for a rule of thumb, Cooper reversed
that first statement: I think in order to have an effective reduction in weight and
a realignment of our composition we have to focus on fat intake (p. 406). Taubes
sees this as a turning point in both public policy and research on obesity:
The shift in the nutritional wisdom was now taking place, driven by the
contagious effect of Ancel Keyss dietary-fat/heart-disease hypothesis on the closely
related field of obesity. Any diet that allowed liberal fat consumption was to be
considered unhealthy (p. 410). The small contingent of influential nutritionists
from Fred Stares department at Harvard provide an example of how this process
of entrenchment evolved. : : : (p. 411). The result is an enormous enterprise
dedicated in theory to determining the relationship between diet, obesity, and
disease, while dedicated in practice to convincing everyone involved, and the lay
public, most of all, that the answers are already known and always have been
an enterprise, in other words, that purports to be a science and yet functions like
a religion (pp. 451-2).
In closing here, an instructive vignette from earlier history. In his Bismarck (2011),
Jonathan Steinberg describes one of that great statesmans sons, suffering from
obesity, as having been helped to lose weight by following instructions from his
doctor, Ernst Schweninger (p. 413). And then, with the Reich Chancellor himself,
in 1883, again desperately sick, this son of his brought Schweninger to see him (p.
414) also obese, and famously gluttonous to boot.
Schweninger saved Bismarcks life by : : : [prescribing] a new diet for the
entire family tea or milk with eggs for breakfast, a little fish and roast meat
(no vegetables) at noon, a small jug of milk at 4:00 and yet another in the evening
24 2 Epidemiological Knowledge: Examples
(p. 416). The pains, the facial neuralgia, and the headaches vanished. Bismarck
was able to ride again. His weight began to go down, : : : From 1886 on [till his
death in 1898] he never went above 227 pounds, a perfectly reasonable weight for a
man six feet four (p. 415).
Bismarck retained Schweninger as his personal physician for the rest of his
life, and in gratitude Bismarck imposed his House Doctor on the Berlin medical
faculty, which regarded him as a charlatan and refused to talk with him (p. 416).
In public education about healthy diet, a very eminent recent governmental message
in Canada has emphasized the need to change the typical salt (sodium chloride)
consumption from the prevailing mean of over 8 g/day to less than 4 g/d for
persons of all ages and with even lower target levels for those under 10 or over
50 years of age. In this aspect of diet the proximal concern is the level of blood
pressure: prevention or amelioration of hypertension. (This term is a common
medical misnomer for relatively high blood pressure, which might better be termed
hemohyperbarism; Gr. haima, blood, Gr. baros, weight, pressure). Hypertension,
in turn, is of concern as a major cause of vascular disease (cardiac and cerebral).
Taubes (ref. in sect. 2.1) makes the point that Systematic reviews of the evidence
: : : have inevitably concluded that significant reductions in salt consumption
cutting our salt intake in half, for instance, which is difficult to accomplish in the
real world will drop blood pressure by perhaps 4 to 5 mm Hg in hypertensives
and 2 mm Hg in the rest of us. : : : So cutting our salt intake in half : : : makes
[in proportional terms] little difference (p. 146). Available not yet to Taubes
but to the Sodium Working Group as background for its 2010 recommendations
to Health Canada also was A comprehensive review on salt and health and
current experience of worldwide salt reduction programmes by F.J. He and G.A.
MacGregor, published in Journal of Human Hypertension 2009; 23: 363-84.
Until the recent salt hypothesis began receiving serious attention in the 1960s,
Taubes explains, the investigators paid little attention to nutritional explanations
for the rise in blood pressure that accompanied Western diets and lifestyles. : : :
Of course, the same societies that ate little or no salt ate little or no sugar or white
flour, so the evidence supported both hypotheses, although the investigators were
interested only in one (p. 146).
The laboratory evidence that carbohydrate-rich diets can cause the body to
retain water and to raise blood pressure, just as salt consumption is supposed
to do, dates back over a century. : : : In the late 1950s, a new generation of
investigators rediscovered the phenomenon, : : : By the early 1970s, researchers
had demonstrated that the water-retaining effect of carbohydrates was due to the
insulin secreted, which in turn induced the kidneys to reabsorb sodium rather than
excrete it, and that insulin levels were indeed higher, on average, in hypertensives
than in normal individuals. (Pp. 148-9).
2.6 Epidemiologic Reviews in Review 25
Given our fundamental tenet that epidemiology is (practice of) community medicine
(sect. 1.1), we first examine the 2005 issue, concerned with epidemiological
approaches to disasters, to determine whether population-level medical care for
disaster-afflicted populations was viewed as being epidemiology. Of main interest
in this respect is the Editorial in that issue, by the eminent epidemiologist Michel
Ibrahim.
As evidenced in this issue, Ibrahim wrote, epidemiology has an important
role to play in the study of characteristics of populations affected by disasters and
the deaths and injuries that follow. A seminal article : : : shows epidemiologic ap-
proaches to disaster assessment at its best. : : : As presented in several papers in this
26 2 Epidemiological Knowledge: Examples
issue, epidemiologic methods and public health strategies are important in assessing
and containing disasters. : : : The time-honored prevention and control measures
come into play: : : : vaccinating high-risk groups against infectious diseases : : :
The final paragraph is particularly telling: Now more than ever, public health
preparedness has become a high priority of governments that must have the ability
to predict, prevent, and control disasters and their consequences. Adequate funds are
crucial to achieve this purpose, but epidemiologic know-how also has a role to play.
Now, as a disaster an earthquake with or without a tsunami, say produces
public-health problems in terms of epidemics of injuries and other illnesses, it is, as
Ibrahim said, the responsibility, specifically, of the governments public-health offi-
cials to predict, prevent, and control these epidemics. The leading officials in this
naturally are (practicing) epidemiologists. As remains commonplace, Ibrahim wrote
about public-health practices when at issue were, specifically, the epidemiological
varieties of these (cf. sect. 1.1, i.a.). He wrote about epidemiologists in the practice
of community medicine in the practice of epidemiology, that is (cf. sect. 1.1).
Related to the essence of epidemiology, the point that social epidemiology now is
on the ascendancy came up in section 1.4. And it is of note that in the period from
2001 to 2011, the 2004 issue was expressly devoted to this, while related to this also
was the 2009 issue. Suffice it here to quote from the Introduction to the 2004 issue,
by Lisa Berkman:
Social epidemiology, disguised in other forms and known by other names, has been with
us for decades, if not centuries. : : : the field is not a new one, nor are epidemiologists
the only scientists contributing to a deepening understanding of the social determinants of
health. : : : I would argue that the important insights of social epidemiologists are based on
the training they have in the assessment of health, disease, and biological pathways and the
capacity to integrate upstream social dynamics into their modeling of disease causation.
[Italics ours.]
By 1969, enough familiarity with the field exists that Leo G. Reeder presents a major ad-
dress to the American Sociological Association called Social Epidemiology: An appraisal
[ref.]. Defining social epidemiology as the study of the role of social factors in the etiology
of disease [ref.], he asserts that social epidemiology : : : seeks to expand the scope of
investigation to include variables and concepts drawn from a theory [ref.] in effect, calling
for a marriage of sociological frameworks to epidemiologic inquiry. [Italics in the original.]
Recall, a propos, from section 1.4 a counsel of Francis Bacon: Read not
to contradict, nor to believe, but to weigh and consider. Something to here
weigh and consider in particular is this: Given that epidemiological research
without the social adjective addresses population occurrence of illness in relation
to characterizers of the populations individual members their constitutional,
environmental, and behavioral characterizers as a matter of biomedical research,
isnt it natural to think of study of the distribution of these determinants in
(human) populations/communities/societies as social and behavioral rather than
biomedical research, as a supplement to, rather than a type of, epidemiological
research? (Cf. sect. 1.4.)
And here is something more specific to weigh and consider. As epidemiologists
by their biomedical research have come to know how rates of various illnesses in
human populations are determined, causally, by the pattern of histories of, say,
smoking in the population, social epidemiologists have nothing to add to this,
whatever may be their claims about the training they have in the assessment
of health, disease, and biological pathways. By the same token, epidemiological
researchers of the established, biomedical variety are not experts on the patterns of
smoking in human populations and, especially, on how best to reduce these. They
defer to social epidemiologists a misnomer for medical sociologists on this,
and, ultimately, to policy-promulgating societal authorities.
And finally here, while social epidemiology has been with us for decades
(Berkman, above), it remains inchoate: the order of the day evidently still is
conceptualization of what it is, rather than review of its accomplishments in the
advancement of the knowledge-base of community-level preventive medicine.
A propos of section 2.2 above, it is of interest that one article did address fat intake in
the etiogenesis of prostate cancer, and that none of them dealt with the etiogenetic
role of the carbohydrate composition of diet. Illustrative of that particular review
is this: Data from several ecologic studies have shown positive correlations (r
0.6) between per capita intake of total, saturated, or animal fat and prostate
cancer incidence or mortality [refs.]. : : : Although several case-control studies
found positive associations (odds ratio (OR) 1.3) between total fat intake and
the risk of prostate cancer [refs.], only slightly fewer failed to find this relation
[refs.]. : : : Because cohort studies of diet and cancer avoid the problem of recall
bias and are less prone than case-control studies to other [sic] selection biases, they
are generally given more weight in overall assessments of the literature. Three such
studies : : : examined total fat and prostate cancer; two of these studies [refs.] found
a positive association (relative risk 1. 3).
So, with descriptive/ecologic studies again the point of departure, the empha-
sis was on the now-perceived two principal types of analytic study: case-control
and cohort studies, the former producing findings in terms of odds ratio, the
latter in terms of relative risk and both with no indication of what contrast (based
on the quantitative determinant) was at issue. Review of the findings of a given one
of the latter two types of study were taken to be a matter of noting what proportion
of the studies found a positive association and what proportion failed to find this
relation. And the studies none of them of basic science were seen to be marred
by potential biases.
All of this is, at present, rather typical of epidemiological concepts, terminology,
thinking, and writing; and we find it to be, in many ways, disagreeable. For a
student these excerpts from this review are indicative of what now is out there, even
if it remains far from being understood correctly interpreted and evaluated. We
present our critical understandings in the ensuing chapters, and we suggest that the
2.6 Epidemiologic Reviews in Review 29
student return to these passages for critical examination of them after having studied
chapter 6 at least.
This review of dietary fat in the etiogenesis of prostate cancer was placed
under the rubric of environmental factors as distinct from genetic factors and
hormones and growth factors, but we think in terms of a triad of categories for
illness-causing factors: constitutional, environmental, and behavioral. All somatic
factors, whether congenital (e.g., genetic) or acquired (post-natally), we think
of as constitutional (with hormones and growth factors among these). And we
decisively separate behavioral factors active ones of lifestyle, such as dietary
habits from factors that are, passively, environmental (from the vantage of a given
person).
The last, brief section in this issue of the Reviews is noteworthy by its title:
Prevention and control. So, prevention and control of the occurrence of prostate
cancer these matters of practice apparently were taken to be matters of
epidemiology (rather than extra-epidemiological practice of public health). But this
is not very clear from the three reviews under this rubric, one of them addressing
chemoprevention of prostate cancer, the other two screening for it. However, one
of the two screening reviews clearly went to matters beyond research, to matters of
practice of screening:
In summary, patients must be informed about the risks and benefits of prostate cancer
screening before it is carried out. : : : If screening (and eventual treatment) is to be offered
to asymptomatic patients, it should be offered to those in whom age and health status are
such that they may benefit from early detection of a disease which may have a protracted
natural history [meaning course in the absence of treatment; cf. above].
The current, major epidemic of obesity, in the U.S. and elsewhere (sect. 2.4), makes
the 2007 issue both timely and interesting.
The lead article, by B. Caballero, provides an introduction to this issue of the
Reviews. It pointed out that,
In spite of extensive research over the past decades, the mechanisms by which people attain
excessive body weight and adiposity are still only partially understood : : : As discussed
in this overview, there is an increasing consensus among obesity experts that changing the
obesogenic environment is a critical step toward reducing obesity. Reversing the factors
: : : that lead to increased caloric consumption and reduced physical activity would require
major changes in urban planning, transportation, public safety, and food production and
marketing. [Italics ours.]
The 2011 issue of the Reviews, on screening a topic in respect to prostate cancer
already (above) began with an Overview by R. Harris. Under the important
subheading of Where we are and where we may be heading he wrote this:
Overall, then, the present truths about screening are that it is sometimes effective in
improving health outcomes, that it is also associated with important harms, : : : With few
exceptions, the contribution of screening to improving the health of the public is small, : : :
Perhaps we should not think of screening as our primary prevention strategy but rather use
screening to make a real, but limited contribution to population health for a few conditions.
: : : Fletchers [ref.] thoughtful perspective on breast cancer screening is consistent with this
vision of the future of screening. : : :
2.7 Overview of the Achievements 31
S.W. Fletcher, whom Harris so put on a pedestal, wrote about Breast cancer
screening: A 35-year perspective. She made the familiar but ever-so-stunning
points that randomized trials of breast cancer screening have involved more than
650,000 women, and that even so, no other cancer screening has produced such
heated controversy. Multiple reviews have been published, : : : See Appendix 2.
Regarding the formulation of ideas and recommendations about screening for
a cancer, Fletcher described the pivotal roles that have been played by two task
forces, from the vantage of herself having been a founding member of both of
them. She gave no justification for the formation, membership, or functioning of
these task forces. See Apps. 1, 2, and 3.
Both the Canadian and U.S. task forces emphasized the importance of ran-
domized trials in their assessments of and recommendations for cancer screening
(italics ours). And illustrative of the results of these trials is this passage by Fletcher:
The most recent meta-analysis [by the U.S. Preventive Medicine Task Force, of the results
of the eight trials, having involved the total of over 650,000 participants, as noted above]
found that breast cancer mortality reduction among women invited to screening was 15%
for women aged 39-49 years, 14% for women aged 50-59 years, and 32% for women aged
60-69 years, with corresponding numbers needed to invite to screening to prevent 1 breast
cancer death of 1,904, 1,339, and 377, respectively [ref.].
The alert student will have taken note of the subtitle of Taubes book (ref. in
sect. 2.1), the element of controversial science in it. Taubes quotes Henry Blackburn,
the eminent cardiovascular epidemiologist, as having written, in 1975, that two
strikingly polar attitudes persist on this subject [i.e., the etiology/etiogenesis of
coronary heart disease, as to whether it has to do with fats or carbohydrates in the
diet], with much talk from each and little listening between (p. 22).
At the root of the controversies are, as Taubes explains, two aberrations of
the culture surrounding epidemiological research: inattention to relevant basic
research and dogmatism, among the investigators and also the agencies sponsoring
the research.
One of us was an author in a paper indicating that alcohol consumption
indeed does prevent coronary heart disease. Puzzled why evidence of this had
not been published from the Framingham Heart Study, in the blue books of
which the association (negative) had been quite apparent, he asked one of the FHS
investigators about this. The answer was that this colleague himself actually wrote a
manuscript on it. But: its approval process in the sponsoring agency the National
Heart and Lung Institute of the U.S. went, quite exceptionally, all the way up to
the head of the Institute; and he blocked the articles publication on the ground that
knowledge of this salutary effect of alcohol consumption would promote alcoholism
among the American people.
Taubes gives several examples of censorship, doctrinaire investigators self-
censorship as well as censorship by their sponsoring agencies. Particularly in-
structive about the role of institutional dogmatism are his descriptions of how
institutional ideas specifically of what the truth about the matter at issue is play a
role in the selection of like-minded experts to committees with the charge to review
the evidence and to seek to determine what the truth is, thus making official the
conception of the truth that the agency already was holding.
In the framework of this culture surrounding the relevant scholarship, people
have been taught, for decades, to avoid fats in their diets; and so they have consumed
carbohydrates instead and have grown obese, quite possibly as a consequence of
this. Now, somewhat hesitantly, the reversal of this teaching is taking place; now
the idea increasingly is that to be avoided are those carbohydrates, the consequence
naturally being increase in the consumption of fats (and proteins too).
These matters should be seen to be at the very core of non-communicable,
chronic disease epidemiological research and knowledge. Yet the importance of
them is not manifest in the topics addressed in Epidemiologic Reviews in 2001-2011.
Moreover, these quite generally ignore the relevant basic science and have no
genuine knowledge to present. It took Taubes a free-lance science-writer with no
official credentials in epidemiological research to teach us about these matters,
with unprecedented range of and depth of insights in the coverage.
To be sure, epidemiological research of this more recent, chronic-disease genre
(the dichotomy communicable vs. non-communicable actually is nowhere near
coterminous with the acute-chronic dichotomy) has served to discover, and to an
extent quantify, the effects of a large number of health hazards, those of cigarette
smoking prime among these. But even in respect to this prime example, the history
2.7 Overview of the Achievements 33
of progress is less than glorious: Franz Muller, in his medical thesis in Germany in
1939, gave quite compelling evidence to the effect that the main cause, by far, of the
lung-cancer epidemic (which had been evolving for decades already) was smoking
of cigarettes; and very strict anti-smoking policies were adopted in Germany, in
part on the basis of this knowledge. Yet, as Robert Proctor in his The Nazi War
on Cancer (1999) points out, Wynder and Grahams famous paper from [1950]
characterized tobacco merely as a possible etiologic factor in the increase of the
disease (p. 196).
While Mullers study involved a mere 86 cases of death from lung cancer
and 86 living and healthy controls, 28 other case-control studies with a total
of 15,492 cases and 101,215 controls, and seven very large, expensive, and time-
consuming cohort studies one of them with a cohort of 1,085,000 persons were
conducted before it got to be a piece of official knowledge in the U.S. that smoking
causes lung cancer. This landmark event took place as late as in 1964, in the form
of the publication of the Surgeon Generals Smoking and Health report. To say that
which would go without saying, an enormous number of people have died of lung
cancer as a consequence of their smoking in the quarter-century before 1964.
Given that epidemiological research has as its raison detre the advancement of
community medicine, there should be continual transmutation of epidemiological
evidence into genuine epidemiological knowledge. The requisite innovations for
the advancement of epidemiological knowledge we discuss in section 13.6 and
in Appendix 3, while perfunctory programs to derive recommendations/guidelines
for practice from evidence, without attention to expert knowledge, we address in
Apps. 1 and 2.
While the Epidemiologic Reviews are supposed to be comprehensive and
critical, we find them to be strikingly uncritical loose in both concepts and
principles. The epitome of this lack of discipline (sect. 1.3) is the piece by an
eminent clinical epidemiologist a founding member of the Canadian and U.S.
task forces on preventive medicine on an enormous amount of research that
substantively has amounted only to heated controversy, this on a topic that in
critical conception is wholly extrinsic to preventive medicine! See Apps. 1 and 2.
Chapter 3
Etiology as a Pragmatic Concern
se but only if a lower level of blood pressure is taken to be the alternative (while
with a higher BP the alternative, the given BP is a potential preventive cause of
non-occurrence of stroke).
The other shared feature is this: Something that in general terms is a cause of the
outcome need not be so in a particular instance, even when present; in a particular
instance it is only a potential possible cause. Whether it in a given, individual
instance actually was, or will be, causal will generally remain unknowable. On
the individual, clinical level, only probabilistic knowing is realistic to pursue for
etiognosis as well as for intervention-prognosis knowing about the probability
(objective) that the potential cause actually was, or will be, causal to the outcomes
occurrence (its change from non-occurrence to actually occurring).
This said about the commonalities, another difference also is worth noting here.
It has to do with the causal contrast, specifically with the causal determinants index
category in the contrast, representing the presence of the cause, as distinct from
the reference category, representing the alternative to (rather than mere absence
of) the cause. An etiognostic potential cause is what it happens to be: a particular
pattern of the determinant status constitutional, environmental, or behavioral
over the entire span of etiogenetically relevant time (retrospective), deviating from
the corresponding, defined reference status throughout this period of time. In
intervention-prognostic causation, by contrast, the potential cause is what it is taken
to be, by choice, as for both its type and the duration of its implementation; it is
algorithmic for the duration of its implementation (notional or actually planned),
just as is its defined alternative.
Following these subtleties, it may be good to concentrate the mind by returning
attention to the difference profound between the etiognostic and intervention-
prognostic questions: In community medicine it is one thing to consider to what
extent the current level of morbidity from a particular illness is due to the
populations distribution by history in respect to a particular cause of it, this
distributions deviation from the reference distribution; and it is quite another thing
to consider what would be the prospective change in that morbidity if a particular
intervention were adopted (prospectively). The issue of the role of smoking in the
etiogenesis of the prevailing rate of lung-cancer incidence is profoundly different
from that of the change in this rate that would result from the adoption of a particular
regulation concerning smoking, including as for the attainability of gnosis about it.
A modality of a doctors action aimed at prevention of an illness in the client,
in clinical as well as community medicine, commonly is education of the client
(individual or population) about possible change in health-relevant lifestyle. This
is not actual intervention on the course of the clients health, not intervention by
the doctor nor by the client any more than, say, intention-to-treat based on
randomization is actual intervention in an intervention trial. In community medicine,
an actual intervention (preventive) is a change brought about by adopted public
policy into the peoples constitutions (as to, e.g., immunity), environments (e.g.,
pollution control), or behaviors (e.g., use of seatbelts). In clinical medicine an
intervention is a physician-effected change in the clients constitution (e.g., by
injection of a vaccine or a medication, or by tonsillectomy). Yet, even though
38 3 Etiology as a Pragmatic Concern
Apart from surveys and surveillances directed to health hazards and general
promotion of healthy constitutions, environments, and behaviors in the cared-for
population, a community doctors concern is to get to know about the rates of
morbidity from various illnesses in the population that (s)he is caring for to achieve
community diagnosis in this multifaceted sense and then to devise specific ways
of reducing those rates, unduly high ones in particular.
Regarding a given one of those unduly high rates, the epidemiologists
development of a plan to reduce it begins with his/her answer to the question, Why
is this rate this high in this population at this time? What is causing this rate to be
this high? The beginning of the control of morbidity from a particular illness thus
is the answer or the set of answers to this question about etiology/etiogenesis,
to this specifically etiognostic question. The rate at issue must be either specific in
terms of its descriptive determinants or suitably adjusted for these, so that its high
level does not have a descriptive, acausal explanation but needs a causal one.
Etiogenetic explanation of the rate of morbidity from a particular illness in a
particular population at a particular time addresses the proportion of the rate that
is caused by the factor at issue (by the pattern of its retrospective presence, in
lieu of the defined alternative to this, in the members of the population). This is
the proportion of the existing rate that would not be there but for the populations
patterns of positive histories for the factor (ceteris paribus).
This explanation the perception of this overall etiogenetic proportion the
epidemiologist can derive from two types of input. One of these types of input
is, generally, peculiar to the cared-for population at the time in question. If the
etiogenetic history is simply binary, such as use/non-use or seatbelt at the time of
road accident, this first input is the proportion of the cases of the illness in which the
affected person has the history of the factor/cause (non-use of seatbelt, say) having
been present in the relevant past (i.e., in which the person had the index history and
the case thus could have been caused by the factor at issue). This is the proportion
of the cases of the illness and hence of the rate of morbidity from the illness
that would be attributable to the factor were its presence (retrospective) always
to be etiogenetic to cases of the illness occurring in association with its presence
(retrospective).
The other input into the overall etiogenetic proportion into the proportion now
purportedly (ref. below) commonly termed attributable fraction (population) can
be a matter of general epidemiological knowledge about cases of the illness that
are associated with the potentially etiogenetic antecedent. It is the proportion of
these antecedent-associated cases such that the antecedent actually is causal to the
3.3 Etiology as a Clinical-medicine Concern 39
exogenous agent (an ingested medication, say), (s)he is confronted with the clinical-
type etiognostic question: Why is this person having this illness at this time? or,
What agent is producing this adverse reaction in this person at this time? The former
type of question (s)he may be able to regard as inconsequential, as the particular
etiogenesis may not have implications for the management of the case at hand nor
for prevention of recurrence of the illness. The answer to the latter kind of question,
by contrast, is quite commonly consequential for the management of the case and
practically always for prevention of its recurrence.
When setting out to meet this challenge, the clinician in ideal practice at least
recalls the known causes of the outcome at hand, ascertains the patients history
in respect to each of these, and translates these histories into the corresponding
etiognostic probabilities. Relative to etiognosis about a particular cause in explain-
ing a particular rate of morbidity in a practice of community medicine, the clinical
situation is generally characterized by greater detail in the history about the potential
cause and also about the host of the outcome about various aspects of the general
etiogenetic triad (constitution/environment/behavior).
In a court of law, the plaintiff in a class action suit may be alleging that something
industrial a particular practice or environment or product is causal to a particular
illness experienced by people exposed to it; and in particular, that this is so in each
case of the illness in a particular class of exposed people in general and, therefore,
in each case among the members of the plaintiff class of people. A case may also
be brought to a court of law by an individual against a company or against his/her
own doctor, alleging damage to his/her own health from an industrial environment
or product or from a medical action.
The legal issue can be (as in the U.S.) whether the existence of the causal
connection between the health outcome and its antecedent exposure is more
probable than its non-existence. In a class action suit this has to do with such
particulars of the exposure and the persons as are definitional to the class; and in
the individual suit the issue is analogous to this, only more specific in its particulars.
In courts of law, just as in the practices of community and clinical medicine, there
thus are issues about the etiology/etiogenesis of illness. But arguably different from
medical practices, the legal practices related to etiogenesis of illness should involve
express focus on the general question of what is known in the community of the
relevant experts about the causal connection at issue, about the probability of its
existence in such individual cases as the one(s) at issue. The relevant knowledge
is about the proportion of instances like the one(s) at issue in general such that
the antecedent is causal to the outcome, this proportion being the probability
in question. Given the amount of relevant detail on an individual plaintiff, the
knowledge-base for rational resolution of the legal cases tends not to derive
3.4 Etiology as a Legal Concern 41
conditionally on the set of confounders and thus, free of confounding by them, and
calculation of this result for the factor-conditional etiogenetic proportion can be
based on this functions fitted counterpart.
1. Policies about DUI. Legal and other public-policy stipulations about DUI
(driving under the influence, of alcohol) are principally guided by information
about the excess rate of fatal injuries that in the population within the policy-
makers purview is attributable (causally) to peoples DUI, as defined, perhaps
distinguishing among some demographic strata (by categories of age, most notably).
This DUI-attributable excess rate of car-accident fatalities (in a given demo-
graphic stratum, say) is the overall rate of these fatalities in the population in
question, regardless of causation, multiplied by the proportion of the overall rate that
is attributable to DUI; and the latter, that overall etiologic/etiogenetic proportion,
in turn, is the product of two proportions: the proportion particularistic, in the
population at the time of the fatalities occurring in association with DUI, and
the proportion more-or-less general of DUI-associated fatalities that actually are
DUI-attributable (sect. 3.2). The latter proportion presumably is practically invariant
over whatever demographic strata of the population of public-policy concern (so
long as the distribution of the severity of the inebriation is practically the same over
the strata).
It thus is knowledge of the etiognostic, rather than intervention-prognostic, type
from etiologic/etiogenetic research that matters in this example; and that other type
of research-based knowledge wouldnt even be practical to pursue for the purpose
here (see below).
2. Policies about seatbelt use. The requisite knowledge-base for public policies
about seatbelt use is, in its nature and genesis, quite analogous to that concerning
DUI; but the other genre of causal research is now realistic and instructive to
consider.
In the spirit of intervention-prognostic research (sect. 3.1), one would think
of, and address, drivers staying in a given category of the risk factor (use/non-
use of seatbelt) over considerable amounts of accrued mileage; and the study
would address the incidence of fatal injury to the driver, from traffic accidents, for
the contrasted categories. For categories of appreciable degrees of inebriation the
capturing of this type of experience is quite unimaginable, but for driving with and
without the use of the seatbelt it isnt.
Even though rather practicable in respect to seatbelt use, that alternative to the
etiognostic outlook and approach is not the preferable one in this case, either. The
rate has a multitude of determinants, both causal and acausal, other than the use/non-
use of seatbelt. In the face of this complexity, sufficient for policies about the use
of seatbelt is knowing its consequent proportional reduction general in the rate,
this reduction in conjunction with what the rate local in the absence of seatbelt
4.1 Some Introductory Examples 45
use is or would be. The relevant absolute reduction in the rate is the product of these
two (cf. sect. 3.2), that general input into it naturally taken to be independent of that
ad-hoc input.
So, again, the etiognostic genus of causal research is sufficient while also
obviously simpler than its intervention-prognostic alternative.
3. Policies about smoking. Like DUI and non-use of seatbelt, smoking is a matter of
peoples behavior that is of concern to promulgators of societal policies directed to
promotion and preservation of public health (i.e., the health of the population in the
policy-makers purview; sect. 1.1). But the legal-regulatory stipulations restricting
the peoples admissible behaviors are in this context supplemented by regulation
of the peoples environments: the concern is not only to ban smoking in various
particular types of setting; the peoples environments are controlled as to whether,
or what types of, tobacco products can be available (where and to whom, according
to age). Another difference is that community-level health education about the
behaviors their health implications is promoted by the policies being that
the risky behavior in many settings remains admissible (different from the examples
above).
The policy-makers direct concern is to reduce morbidity from illnesses for which
smoking is etiogenetic, especially from illnesses through which smoking is a ma-
terial contributor to mortality in the population. They thus need to learn from the
epidemiologist(s) caring for the population in respect to illnesses such as lung can-
cer the prevailing rate of mortality in the population; or, more to the point, they need
to learn the total mortality from smoking-related illnesses in the aggregate. And they
need to learn the proportion of this mortality really of the underlying morbidity
that is attributable (etiogenetically) to the peoples (histories of) smoking (sect. 3.2).
In these, essential terms the scientific knowledge-base of public policy about
smoking is analogous to that of the two examples above, with the relevant
knowledge from epidemiological research again being of the etiognostic rather
than of the intervention-prognostic type. A difference is, however, that smoking
as the etiogenetic factor does not explain (causally) a proportion of the cases that is
anywhere near invariant across all demographic strata of the population of concern.
Regarding age in particular, the general (epidemiological) knowledge needs to be
stratum-specific, including in respect to the typical positive history of smoking in
materially relevant respects.
Once thus informed about the excess mortality from smoking-related illness (by
categories of age, at least), the regulators would like to have an added input into their
decisions about the various possible regulatory interventions under consideration,
namely the intervention-prognostic magnitudes of the effects of these (also by
categories of age, at least). Knowledge about the magnitudes of these effects is,
however, very impractical to acquire by epidemiological (or other) research. But it
also is rather immaterial for the regulatory decisions, as cost-effectiveness is not
really an issue in these decisions.
For community-level health education about smoking-related life-styles, it is
essential to have research-based knowledge sketchy knowledge at least about the
46 4 Etiology as the Object of Study
Very important to appreciate about causation is the fact that it is not a phenomenon,
that it thus is not subject to being observed. It is, instead, what Immanuel Kant
termed a conception a priori, a noumenon. In this sense, as Kant points out, causation
is akin to, say, space and time not formed by experience but innate.
The concept of causation, noumenal as it is, has been remarkably baffling to
many notable philosophers. Insofar as the Greek aitia (etymologic to the etio- prefix)
can justifiably be translated as cause, Aristotle envisioned four fundamental genera
of cause: material, formal, effective, and final; but of these, only effective aitia
actually is a cause and specifically etiogenetic/etiognostic rather than intervention-
prognostic cause (sect. 3.1) in our contemporary meaning of cause.
William of Ockham (1285?1349?) is now commonly (though falsely) taken to
have been the originator of the important principle of parsimony (L. parsimonia,
frugality), namely that concepts are not to be multiplied beyond necessity; and one
of his applications of this principle was advocacy (sharp, as usual, a` la Ockhams
razor) of seeing causation to be an unnecessary concept, an undeserving supple-
ment to that of regular succession. Similarly, the eminent empiricist philosopher
David Hume (17111776) argued that knowable only is constant conjunction, in
lieu of causation. And subsequent positivist philosophers, even of the twentieth
century, had no use for noumenal concepts, such as causation.
Philosophers, while much concerned to understand what is and what is not
real (ontologically admissible to consider), have thus been conspicuously out of
touch with the realities of medicine. Hippocrates (460? BCE370? BCE), already,
is taken to have brought forth the fundamental idea that illnesses are not divinely
instigated; that instead, the beginning of the disease process is an offending material
(materia peccans) bringing the bodily humors (blood, phlegm, yellow bile, and
black bile) into a state of bad mixture (dyskrasia). Akin to this, a subsequent
concern in medicine has always been to understand the occurrence of an illness
(individually or in a population) as a matter of causal explanation, and beyond this,
to intentionally cause a change in a persons or populations health for the better
(cf. sect. 3.1). Without the concept of causation medicine would be as passive about
peoples health as, say, philosophers commonly elect to be about everything in their
surrounding reality (insofar as they, perhaps only grudgingly, grant its existence)
and cosmologists necessarily are about the goings-on in the cosmos.
In this aloofness from reality, philosophers have been in the Platonic mode. To
his persona as the first academic [Plato] added or superimposed the complementary
persona of the first intellectual, by which I mean someone who thinks ideas matter
more than people. So writes the eminent historiographer Paul Johnson in his
Socrates: A Man of Our Times (2011; p. 11).
where RRi D Ri /R0 , the ith rate ratio, the index rate divided by the reference rate.
This measure of the etiogenetic proportion of interest, while based on phenomena
(rates), adduces a new challenge: the magnitude of this RRi , based on crude
(unadjusted) overall rates as it is, can have extraneous explanations in addition
to the etiogenetic proportion in question; therefore, the need is to consider the
corresponding RRi that is not subject to extraneous explanation.
4.3 Standardized RR as the Result 49
P
where j denotes summation over the strata (j D 1, 2, : : : ) and WP j D PTj /PT is the
latent weight for the specific rate, Rj D Cj /PTj , in the jth stratum. ( j Wj D 1).
Given this structure of a crude rate, it follows that two or more rates are
mutually standardized for one or more stratification factors if they involve the
same (standard) set of weights for their stratum-specific component rates. And
a standardized rate ratio is based on two mutually standardized rates.
50 4 Etiology as the Object of Study
The implication of this standardization principle here is this: Of the crude index rate,
R1i , among those with the ith index history for the potentially etiogenetic factor in
the study base, the proportion actually caused by the factor the factor-conditional
etiogenetic proportion (sect. 3.2) is addressed by
b
RRi 1 RRi ;
b
b
where RRi is the standardized rate-ratio in a particular meaning. First, RRi in- b
volves R1i , the crude unadjusted index rate (conditional on the ith index history).
Second, it involves R0i , the reference rate adjusted to the latent structure of the
index rate (of its denominator input). And third, this adjustment of R0i involves all
extraneous determinants (acausal as well as causal) of the reference rate in terms of
which the index and reference experiences differ.
While any choice of shared weights generally serves the purpose of standardiza-
tion (attainment of comparability in particular respects), here the weights need to be
b b
thought of as those that are latent in the crude index rate (which rate therefore needs
no adjustment for the RRi ). For only with these weights does the RRi represent
the empirical value of the factor-conditional etiogenetic proportion the proportion
b
of the cases with the antecedent that are caused by the antecedent (sect. 3.2).
It is good to learn to think about this RRi as the observed-to-expected, or Oi /Ei ,
ratio of the number of cases in the index experience of the study base:
b
RRi D .Ci =PTi /
hX
j
X
PTij R0j
j
PTij
i
X
D .Oi =PTi / Ei PTij
j
D Oi =Ei :
Actually, this Ei is only the empirical counterpart of the actual null value
corresponding to Oi , and we hence prefer the notation in
b
RRi D Oi =EO i :
where R1 is the crude index rate (with positive history for the factor at issue) and
R0 is the reference rate (with positive history for that factors defined alternative)
adjusted to the latent structure of R1 in respect to all extraneous determinants
(acausal as well as causal) of the reference rate in terms of which the latent
structures of the crude index and reference rates (R1 and R0 ) differ, these rates
characterizing an experience in the domain of the object of study; and where
O is the observed number of cases contributing to the index rate and E is the
corresponding null-expected numbers empirical counterpart.
This is the standardization approach to obtaining an empirical value for the core
object of an etiogenetic study the study result in terms of the O/E ratio serving
to derive the corresponding result for the factor-conditional etiogenetic proportion.
Involved is maintenance of the occurrence relations conditionality on extraneous
determinants of the outcomes rate of occurrence of the reference rate, that is.
This leads to consideration of the outcomes rate of occurrence as a joint
function (descriptive) of the etiogenetic determinant at issue and the presumedly
inclusive set of the reference rates extraneous determinants involved in the needed
conditionality. In the framework of such a joint function the relation of the rate to the
determinant at issue is inherently conditional on the set of extraneous determinants,
given that the form of the function is realistic.
In an extremely simple situation the etiogenetic determinant would have only
three (nominal) categories index, reference, other and the conditioning would
52 4 Etiology as the Object of Study
involve only, say, gender and age. The correspondingly designed function the
occurrence relation designed as the model for the rate, R might be as simple as
R D B0 C B1 X1 C B2 X2 C B3 X3 C B4 X4 ;
where the Bs are (presumed) parameters (constants) of Nature and the Xs are (ad-
hoc adopted) statistical variates (which the determinants they represent arent):
X1 D indicator of index history (X1 D 1 if this, 0 otherwise)
X2 D indicator of other history (so that X1 D X2 D 0 implies reference history)
X3 D indicator of male gender
X4 D age as the number of years (i.e., age/yr).
What is simple about that situation is not merely the all-or-none nature of the set
of possible etiogenetic histories and the (presumed) need to condition the relation of
R to these on gender and age only; and an added simplicity is the feature that R is a
numerical quantity not incidence density but a proportion-type rate (of incidence
or prevalence).
And for that simple situation that model is quantitatively simple in two of its
implications: that the magnitude of the effect at issue (the difference between R1 ,
involving X1 D 1 together with X2 D 0, and R0 , involving X1 D X2 D 0) is constant
(B1 ) over (i.e., unmodified by) gender and age; and that full conditioning by gender
and age is provided for by their very simple simply additive representation in
that model (without, say, X5 D X4 2 , X6 D X3 X4 , and X7 D X3 X5 ).
In terms of the fitted counterpart of this simple model we have RO 0j defined for
each of the strata by gender and age (focusing on typical age in each stratum).
P The
standardized reference rate R0 corresponding to the crude index rate R1 is j Wj RO 0j ,
where the weights derive from the index experience. Then, R1 /R* 0 D O/E implies
the empirical value for the factor-conditional etiogenetic proportion (see above).
The stratification in the derivation of the O/E ratio actually is unnecessary.
b
Associated with each index case (among the O number of these) is the corresponding
RO 1j and R O 0j implied by the fitted model; and hence the corresponding RRj
also. Thus,
EO D
X
1 RRj ;
j
b
where the summation is over the index cases (O in number), their profiles in terms
of gender and (actual) age.
A slightly but importantly modified version of that simple model is this log-linear
one:
X4
log .R/ D Bi Xi ;
0
4.4 The Object Imbedded in a Model 53
where X0 D 1. The modification is that the linear compound (of the Bs, with the
Xs the coefficients in it) now represents the magnitude of the logarithm (natural,
Napierian) of the numerical (dimensionless) rate. In terms of this model,
where exp denotes exponential of; that is, antilog (base e) of.
Insofar as this model is correct as to its implication that the difference in log (R)
corresponding to X1 D 1 (and X2 D 0) versus X1 D 0 (and X2 D 0) is constant over
gender and age, and the bearing of gender and age on log(R) is correctly represented
in reference to the subdomain in which X1 D 0 (and X2 D 0) the implication is that
the models fitted counterpart implies
b
RR D O=EO D exp .B1 / :
X5 D X1 X3 ;
RR D exp .B1 C B5 X3 /
D exp .B1 / given X3 D 0 .female gender/
D exp .B1 C B5 / given X3 D 1 .male gender/ :
This model thus implies directly the gender-specific values of the RR but the overall
RR* only through the values of R1j and R0j it thus defines (cf. above).
But, as noted above, this stratification actually is unnecessary. Log-linear models
for a rate, whether a proportion-type rate per se or the numerical element in
incidence density, are the ones of principal concern in etiogenetic research. Without
having to derive values of RO 1j and RO 0j , the values of RR
c j are obtained directly from
the fitted RR function (of its modifiers). Then, as above,
b
RR D O EO D C1
X
cj ;
1 RR
j
54 4 Etiology as the Object of Study
b
where C1 is the number of index cases of the illness (ones occurring in association
with the antecedent at issue), the summation is over all of these cases, and RRj is
the empirical RR corresponding to the modifier profile of the jth one of these cases.
This point likely deserves to be restated, though somewhat differently. Log-linear
modeling of the rate at issue in etiogenetic research is commonly appropriate to
consider. That the model is log-linear implies no inherent restriction on the form
of the occurrence relation how the rate, or the rate ratio, is a function of age,
for example. Insofar as such a model actually is well designed (as to the form of
the occurrence relation in its referent domain), including sufficiency of the built-
in conditionality of the rates relation (descriptive) to the risk factor at issue, the
modeling provides ready definition of the critically relevant RR* (addressed above
and in sect. 4.3).
Thus far the focus here has been on models in the context of an all-or-none index
history. This needs to be supplemented by consideration of the more general case in
which
so that index histories involve X1 > 0 with X2 D 0 and the reference history is
represented by X1 D X2 D 0. Now the interest is in results specific to non-zero values
of X1 , and corresponding to the ith non-zero category the fitted function is evaluated
at X1 D i and X2 D 0 to derive the corresponding RRi D Oi /E i (cf. sect. 4.2).
As we noted at the end of section 4.3 above, modeling of the occurrence relation
and study of the relevant parameters imbedded in the model does away with
the problems that characterize the needed conditioning when adjusting R0 to R0 in
the framework of cross-stratification, especially when the number of strata is quite
large. For there is no feasibility problem and not much loss of efficiency in the study
of RR* in consequence of inclusion of added potential confounders into the model.
But this adduces a new problem: uncertainty about the adequacy of the model in
providing the intended conditioning of the rates (descriptive) relation to the risk
factor at issue. The solution is devoid of the desired feel for the data.
With all this said about the designed object of an etiogenetic epidemiological
study, it may be appropriate to recall one of the most important contributions of
Immanuel Kant into scientific thought. He taught that it is not a scientists role to
simply read the Book of Nature, by accruing experience in such terms as it happens
to present itself. Instead, (s)he is to define, before whatever research experience, the
terms in which (s)he needs to consult Nature. In epidemiological research, the form
of the occurrence relation at issue defining the object(s) of study is to be defined
before actually having the experience, and the role of the research experience is,
merely, to supply empirical content of that preset form.
The deployment of modeling is generally necessary in (non-experimental)
etiogenetic research but that uncertainty about the models adequacy in providing
for the intended conditionality and that lack of feel for the data can be overcome.
See section 5.4.
Chapter 5
Etiologic Studies Essentials
Abstract Given that a defined study base is a sine-qua-non for any admissible type
of etiogenetic study, and that each person-moment in it is to represent the domain
of the designed model for the cases rate of occurrence, it generally cannot be
operationally formed, nor even directly defined; it must be defined as a segment
of the population-time within a defined source population-time, a source base. The
latter, in turn, is formed by the course of a defined source population over a particular
span of time, with this population possibly defined indirectly, as the catchment
population (of cases) secondary to the directly-defined manner of case identification.
Cases of the outcome event are identified, comprehensively, in the source-base
experience, and a fair sample of the source base (of the infinite number of person-
moments constituting it) is drawn. The resulting first-stage case and base series are
reduced to instances from the actual study base (as defined), to the actual pair of
study series.
The model log-linear for the cases rate of occurrence implies its correspond-
ing logistic model to be fitted to the data (with Y D 1 and Y D 0 for the case and base
series, respectively), yielding a result for the rate ratio of interest, as a function of
the modifiers of this as they are accounted for in the model. This, in turn, provides
for calculation of the expected number of index cases in the calculation of the
essential result, that for the factor-conditional etiogenetic proportion.
These calculations under the designed model lack the intuitive appeal of those
based on cross-stratification of the data according to the confounders being con-
trolled. A solution to this problem is stratification by a unidimensional confounder
score, provided by the fitted logistic function evaluated at the reference category
of the etiogenetic determinant under study. Examination of the data in these strata
allows verification of freedom from confounding by the extraneous determinants ac-
counted for, and the calculation of the desired result is intuitive and straightforward.
Whereas the designed form of an occurrence relation for the (rate of) occurrence
of the illness at issue in a defined domain defines the object parameters for an
etiologic/etiogenetic study, and whereas an actual study of that occurrence relation
(of the object parameters in it) is to document experience of that form, the first-
order topic in the design of an actual etiogenetic study is selection of a particular
experience for that documentation.
The end result of this selection the adopted study base usually is an
aggregate of population-time from the designed occurrence relations domain, for
documentation of incidence density (of an event-type outcome), the dependence of
this rate on the determinants of it in the form of the predesigned occurrence relation.
The person-moments in this study base (infinite in number) represent the designed
occurrence relations defined domain (for the outcomes occurrence), and associated
with each of these person-moments is an/the index history or the reference history,
or, perhaps, some other history. Besides, the person-moments constituting the
study base may have been designed to satisfy various admissibility criteria of a
purely practical sort the person at the time being compos mentis and fluent in a
particular language, for example.
A study base of this type is defined in stages. Defined before the study base
itself is the source base, and the study base proper is then defined by applying
the admissibility criteria to the person-moments constituting the source base. The
source base also is defined in two stages. The first stage is the selection of and
commitment to a particular source population.
The definition of the source population may be direct that of the resident
population of a particular metropolitan area or the prescribers to a particular health-
insurance plan, for example. Alternatively, direct primary definition may be
given to the scheme of identification of cases of the illness/outcome at issue, which
makes the source population to have an indirect definition secondary to this: it gets
to be the catchment population of this scheme the entirety of those who, at any
given moment, are in the were-would state of: were the outcome event (clinical
inception of the illness) now to occur, the case would be caught by that scheme.
With the source population defined, the actual source base for an etiogenetic
study of incidence density (in causal relation to histories in respect to the risk
factor at issue) needs further definition, in terms of time. For dynamic source
populations (being open for exit, and hence having turnover of membership), such
as the residents of a particular metropolitan area, the source base is generally
defined as the source populations course over an interval in calendar time. The
same can be true of a source base formed from a previously formed, multipurpose,
cohort-type source population (which is closed for exit, even by death). But if the
source population is a cohort formed ad hoc, then the members contributions to
the population-time of the source base are prone to start from their enrollments
into the cohort, at different points in calendar time, but end simultaneously in
calendar time if not earlier, due to death or loss to follow-up.
5.2 Case Series, Base Series 57
Given the source base for an etiogenetic study of the usual type, dealing with
incidence density, the actual study base within it indeed is merely defined, not
formed by any process of admissions (of person-moments) into it. The study
population generally is dynamic even if the source population is a cohort: a persons
contribution to the population-time of the study base begins when admissibility to it
first gets to be satisfied, and it ends when those criteria no longer are satisfied; the
study population thereby has turnover of membership (which here is the meaning of
dynamic).
Exceptionally, the study base is one for a proportion-type rate, and so therefore
also is the source base in which this is imbedded. Both of these are constituted by a
series of person-moments, a finite enumerable series, instead of an aggregate
of population-time (constituted by an infinite number of person-moments).
Given the study base and the case series providing numerator inputs into
(quantification of) the outcomes index and reference rates of occurrence in this
study base, obviously needed also is a source of the corresponding denominator
inputs; that is, needed also is a base series to accompany that case series, to provide
denominator inputs into (the documentation of) the ratio of the index and reference
rates in the study base.
When, as is usual, the study base is an aggregate of population-time (for study of
incidence density), the base series necessarily is a sample of the study base (as the
population-time of it is constituted by an infinite number of person-moments). As
a sample a stochastically representative one the base series provides numbers
(tallies) proportional (stochastically) to the population-time referents of the rates of
comparative concern; and proportionality in this sense is all that is needed, as the
etiogenetic interest is not in rates per se but only in their ratios (sects. 4.2, 4.3, 4.4).
When the study base is a series (enumerable, finite) of person-moments, census
of it for the base series always is an option in principle; but it may not be justifiable
on the ground of its inefficiency. Census may be unjustifiable if, in a study of a
proportion-type rate, there is a procedural distinction between the acquisition of the
case series and that of the base series. But there may be but a single series of the
person-moments constituting the study base, with the case series identifiable only
as a subset in this base series.
A base series is to represent the study base at large, and not merely of that
segment of the base in which a case of the outcome is not associated with the person-
moment. When the study base is one of population-time, a sample (finite) of it (of
the infinite number of person-moments in it) is not expected to include any instances
in which the outcome event is associated with a person-moment in the sample. But
in a sample and especially in a census of a study base constituted by a series
(finite) of person-moments, instances of the outcome can be involved in the base
series and to the extent they are, they belong there.
The two series from the study base the case series and the base series naturally
are documented in respect to everything that is involved in the designed occurrence
relation. And whatever may be the format of the primary documentation of those
data and the codings applied to these, in the end the data are in the form of
realizations of the statistical variates in the designed occurrence relation. In these
terms there is a data matrix with columns for Y, X1 , X2 , etc., where Y D 1 and
Y D 0 indicate the presence and the absence, respectively, of a case of the outcome
at issue (i.e., membership of the instance the person-moment in the case or the
base series).
In the usual situation in which the designed model addresses incidence density,
fitted to the data is the logistic counterpart of that model:
X
log Pr .Y D 1/ =Pr .Y D 0/ D B0 C Bk Xk :
k
5.3 Model Fitting, Study Result 59
The intercept (B0 ) in this reflects, in part, the chosen size of the base series
relative to that of the case series; but the rest of the parameters are, quantitatively,
the same as in the designed occurrence relation including, of course, the subset of
those parameters constituting the actual objects of the study (sect. 4.4).
More directly relevant for the knowledge-base of etiognosis about the rate of
morbidity is a result secondary to this direct one. The study produced an observed
number of cases of the outcome in association with the ith index history for
the etiogenetic determinant (of the outcomes rate of occurrence). This observed
number (Oi D Ci ) divided by an estimate (E i ) of the corresponding expected
number equals the crude overall index rate (Ri ) divided by the overall reference
rate adjusted to the structure of Ri :
b
Ci =EO i D Ri =R0 D RRi
(sect. 4.3). This is the empirical counterpart (from the study at issue) of the RR that
determines the factor-conditional etiogenetic proportion (among the O D C1 cases):
.RRi 1/=RRi (sect. 4.3).
The model-fitting counterpart of this RR* is
b
RRi D Ci =
X
1=RRij ;
j
where the RRij set corresponds to the Ci set: it is the set of RR values from the study-
produced RR function corresponding to (the profiles of) the Ci subset of cases, and
the summation is over the members of the Ci set (sects. 4.3, 4.4).
If at issue is a proportion-type rate on the basis of an enumerable (finite) set
b
of person-moments, the designed log-linear model (sect. 4.2) is fitted to the data
(possibly a single series) as such; and the results for the RR function, RR , and
the factor-conditional etiogenetic proportion flow from this quite analogously with
b
those having to do with incidence density (above).
With that RRi set (i D 1, 2, : : : ) the principal results of the study, their
precisions need to be quantified (incl. for the purposes of its synthesis with the
corresponding results from other studies), perhaps best in terms of their associated
95% confidence intervals. That interval implies its counterpart for the factor-
conditional etiogenetic proportion of interest.
A simple way to accomplish this begins with fitting a model involving separate
indicators for the index histories with no product terms based on these and noting
the fitted value of each of the corresponding parameters .B/ O together with its SE
(standard error). Then, a 95% interval for the logarithm of RR * i can be derived as
h
b
i
log RRi .1 2:0=w/ ;
60 5 Etiologic Studies Essentials
where w is the realization of the Wald statistic that point estimate of the
O divided by its SE. This has an obvious counterpart for the
coefficient, B,
b
overall RR .
b
Deriving the RR and a measure of precision of this is reasonable to do even
when the study is one of hypothesis testing about the very existence of the
b
etiogenetic connection, and not yet a study on the magnitude of an established
etiogenetic connection. For, the magnitude of the empirical RR is informative
for this qualitative purpose together with the null P-value (from that Wald statistic,
perhaps). For synthesis of the result with those of other studies, relevant is the fitted
logistic function together with the SEs of the relevant coefficients in it.
b
Any serious etiogenetic research is characterized by the resulting rate ratios
RR s conditionality on a reasonably complete set of extraneous determinants (of
the magnitude) of the reference rate. This generally means that the traditional cross-
stratification approach to the conditioning with its propensity to break down in
the context of multiple dimensions in the cross-stratification is now commonly
replaced by the modeling approach (sect. 4.4). But the ideal approach arguably is
one which captures the virtues of each of those two approaches while avoiding the
drawbacks of each of them.
Given a history of the all-or-none type, the notation for the frequencies in the j-th
stratum in cross-stratification (by gender, categories of age, etc.) could be taken to
be this:
D D 1 D D 0 Total
c1j c0j Cj
b1j b0j Bj
where the sizes of the subsets for this stratum of the overall case series (of size
C) and base series (of size B) are Cj and Bj , respectively; and of these, the further
subsets from the etiogenetic determinants index category (D D 1) and reference
category (D D 0) are of sizes c1j and c0j from the Cj , and b1j and b0j from the Bj .
The set of J tables like this gives the centrally relevant parameter the RR
b
determining the factor-conditional etiogenetic proportion (sect. 5.3 above) the
empirical value
b
RR D C1 =EO 1 D C1 =
X
EO ij
j
D
X
j
c1j =
X
c1j =RRj
j
b
X X
D c1j = c1j = c1j =b1j = c0j =b0j
j j
X X
D c1j = b1j c0j =b0j :
j j
5.4 Demystifying the Modeling 61
b
Upon these preparatory steps, the production of the actual main result the value
of .C1 =EO 1 / or RR proceeds as outlined above. And the precision of this result
can quantified as outlined in section 5.3.
Chapter 6
Etiologic Studies Typology
membership in the cohort deployed for all the studies in the framework of the
famous Framingham Heart Study misnomer for cardiovascular disease research
program founded on a source cohort recruited from the town of Framingham in
Massachusetts has not undergone any attrition, not even on the basis of the original
members deaths. Even though practically all of this cohorts members already are
deceased, they still constitute an undiminished source population for studies on
the basis of the in vivo data on them. The collection of all of the data was once
prospective (T > T0 ) in cohort time but it always was, and still is, retrospective
(T < T0 ) in any study time of exploiting the data.
The nature of the resident population of the town of Framingham, from which the
cohort was recruited, is different. This population is open for exits, for terminations
of membership by death, for example. As a consequence of the exits in conjunction
with new entries, this population has turnover of membership; it is a dynamic
population in this sense. The FHS could have been constructed in the framework
of this resident population of the town, as such, as its source population. Like
the cohort recruited from it, this dynamic population could have been subjected
to biennial surveys for routine data collection. The actual FHS cohort, as it got to
be documented, would now be identifiable from the database that could have been
produced from this dynamic source population.
What in etiologic/etiogenetic research is now routinely termed cohort study used
to be known as prospective study (and also as follow-up study), distinguishing it
from what was termed retrospective study (and alternatively case history study); but
the prospective-study precursor of the cohort-study term was discarded on the
ground that its antonym got to be viewed as unduly denigrating of the perceived
alternative to it, now known by the higher-sounding name case-control study.
In a cohort study (so-called, in etiogenetic research), a cohort-type study
population is recruited from the chosen source population (cohort-type or dynamic).
As of the time of the enrollments (at T D 0 on the scale of cohort time) the members
of this cohort are documented in relevant respects, most notably as to their histories
in respect to the etiogenetic determinant at issue. The members are then followed
(into prospective cohort time) to document the occurrence/non-occurrence of the
illness whose etiogenesis is being studied. And the thus-accrued data are analysed
(meaning synthesized) to express how the outcomes occurrence was related to
the divergence in the causal determinant (with certain conditionings in this; cf.
sect. 4.4) the outcome prospective and the determinant retrospective on the scale
of cohort time.
The idea in the genesis of the cohort study (on etiogenesis) was to emulate the
intervention-prognostic experiment, the intervention trial (clinical); but in such a
trial the outcomes prospective occurrence is related to prospective (sic) divergence
in the causal determinant (the interventions), both of these in cohort time. On this
basis already, this paradigm was ill-chosen without appreciation of the profound
difference between etiogenetic and interventive causations, at issue in etiognosis
and intervention-prognosis, respectively (sect. 3.1).
The genuine essentials of an etiogenetic study flow directly from the nature of
this genre of causation (sects. 3.1, 4.2; ch. 5), with no paradigmatic role for the
intervention trial in this. And as for etiogenetic causation, critically important to
6.2 Case-control Study: Its Essence Corrected 65
appreciate is its retrospective nature, from the vantage of time of the outcomes
occurrence/non-occurrence (at in association with a particular person-moment;
sect. 5.1). For this reason and in this sense, any etiogenetic study is to be thought of
as inherently being a retrospective study (while any intervention-prognostic study
inherently is a prospective study; ch. 9).
Given that in a cohort study (on etiogenesis) the causal histories are docu-
mented as of the enrollments into the study cohort so that the T0 of etiogenetic time
is made to coincide with the T0 of cohort time the outcome theoretically ought to
be ascertained at this same point in time; but this theoretically correct cohort study
is impracticable, as an infinite number of these person-moments would be required
(as the requisite size of the cohort ! 1 as duration of follow-up ! 0).
Insofar as a cohorts follow-up inherently prospective in cohort time indeed is
to be taken as definitional to cohort studies (on etiogenesis), important corrections
in the rest of the concept the cohort fallacy need to be made. The cohort must
be seen to be (not the study cohort but) only the source cohort; and its follow-up
must be seen to be (not merely the means to identify the outcome events but) the
formation of the source base, from which to identify the first-stage case series and
to draw a suitable first-stage base series, etc. as outlined in chapter 5 above.
Upon these corrections, the concept of cohort study is none other than that
of a first-principles etiogenetic study in the framework of a cohort-type source
population. This cohort feature of the study, in itself, is of no quality consequence
to the study, which actually involves a dynamic study population forming the study
base (sect. 5.1). It is consequential only if the cohorts follow-up was/is used to
document the etiogenetic histories before the person-moments in the case and base
series, and if this is materially relevant to the validity of these histories.
A cohort study, as it has been construed, is prone to be quite onerous to carry out.
In order that the cohorts follow-up yield a reasonably large number of the outcome
events, needed generally is the enrollment and at-enrollment documentation of
quite a large cohort and its follow-up for quite a long time. The main feature of a
cohort study, says the I.E.A. Dictionary of Epidemiology (specified in sect. 3.2),
is observation of large numbers over a long period (commonly years) : : :
Much more practical is a study that, instead of the enrollment and follow-up
of a cohort, begins with a case series; and especially, if it ends with that series.
Fritz Lickint in 1929 was the first to publish statistical evidence joining lung
cancer and cigarettes [ref.]. : : : His evidence was fairly simple, constituting what
epidemiologists today call a case series showing that lung cancer patients were
particularly likely to be smokers. : : : Franz H. Muller [in his] 1939 medical
dissertation [ref.] presents the worlds first controlled epidemiological study of the
tobacco-lung cancer relationship, : : : His analysis was what we today would call
a : : : case-control study, meaning that he compared : : : the smoking behavior of
66 6 Etiologic Studies Typology
lung cancer patients with that of a healthy control group of comparable age (ref.
below; italics ours). Muller did not have to enroll and document a large cohort, and
then to follow it for years, to get his documented 86 cases and 86 controls.
Reference: Proctor RN. The Nazi War on Cancer. Princeton: Princeton University Press,
1999; pp. 183, 194-96.
Relative to the cohort study (in its uncorrected form), the case-control study
(also in its uncorrected form; above) has, apart from its practicality, the theoretical
virtue that the causal histories are specified on a scale of (retrospective) time whose
T0 is the time of outcome on the scale of the relevant, etiogenetic time.
On the other hand, though, while the cohort study has a study base of sorts
(the series of person-moments of enrollment into the cohort), the case-control
study is devoid of any inherent referent for its result in the form of study base.
The results referent is a case group together with its control group (cf. above).
There thus is no inherent specification of a population-time, or of a series (finite,
enumerable) of person-moments, for which rates or rate ratios are documented.
And as there is no inherent conception of study base as the referent of the study
result, there is no base series to supplement the case series, to provide information
about the denominator inputs into the compared rates. The case-control study
is, thus, grossly at variance with the essentials of etiogenetic studies set forth in
sections 5.1 and 5.2. Seen to represent the reverse of the cohort study, it has
been alternatively termed the trohoc study (trohoc being the heteropalindrome
of cohort); and the profound fallacy in it may thus be termed the trohoc fallacy.
As the comparison of the index and reference rates of the outcomes occurrence
in a defined study base is replaced by comparison of cases with controls, which
comparison does not correspond to the causal contrast (cause present vs. its defined
alternative present, in the study base), strange things happen things that should
have been interpreted as indicating that the comparison is anomalous. One of these is
the phenomenon of overmatching, which is prone to occur in case-control studies
but not in cohort studies. Had Muller in his case-control study (above) matched
his controls to his cases according to some close correlate of smoking (such
as habitual match-carrying), the distribution of his controls by smoking history
would have been very similar to that of his cases, while no matching of non-
smokers to smokers, by whatever correlate of smoking, in a cohort study would
have the corresponding consequence in respect to their relative rates of subsequent
occurrence of lung cancer.
Closely related to this anomalous consequence of matching in case-control
studies is another one. Matching of the controls to the cases in these studies
has commonly been thought of as being a means to prevent confounding. But
prevention of confounding (distinct from control of it) can only be a matter of
seeing to it that the index and reference segments of the study base have suitably
balanced similar distributions according to the potential confounder an
extraneous determinant of the outcomes rate of occurrence in the reference segment
of the study base (sect. 4.3). And given the absence of study base in the concept, a
6.3 Cross-sectional Study: Its Essence Redefined 67
case-control study does not provide for detection of actual confounding nor even
for meaningful thinking about it (about this feature of the study base).
The case-control study thus requires a fundamental correction in terms of
introduction of the ever-necessary concept of study base (sect. 5.2). And secondary
to this, it requires the understanding that cases are not a group of people but a series
of person-moments with this study base as its referent by representing the entirety
of the cases occurring in it and that for the controls for it to be meaningful at
all, they actually need to constitute a fair sample of this study base, to form a base
series in this meaning (cf. sect. 5.2).
The way the cases of the outcome (illness) are identified in a case-control study
implies its corresponding catchment population as the studys source population.
This is the population (dynamic) whose membership is defined by the were-would
state of: were the outcome event now to occur, it would be caught by the studys
case ascertainment scheme (cf. sect. 5.1). This can be the way indirect of defining
the source population for the etiogenetic study that comes about as a result of the
necessary corrections introduction into the case-control study. For the source base
defined by the case ascertainment over a span of time the case ascertainment is
complete by definition, and the challenge is fair sampling of that source base for the
first-stage base series.
Alternatively, upon the correction, the source population is defined directly (as
the adult resident population of a particular metropolitan area, say; sect. 5.1), and
complete case ascertainment for the source base is now the challenging part (while
fair sampling of it is not).
Under Cross-sectional study, the I.E.A. dictionary (specified in sect. 3.2) gives
this:
A study that examines the relation between diseases (or other health-related characteristics)
and other variables of interest as they exist in a defined population at one particular time.
The presence or absence of disease and the presence or absence of the other variables (or,
if they are quantitative, their level) are documented in each member of the study population
or in a representative sample at one particular time. The relationship between a variable and
the disease can be examined (1) in terms of the prevalence of disease in different population
subgroups defined according to the presence or absence (or level) of the variables and (2)
in terms of the presence or absence (or level) of the variables in the diseases versus the
nondiseased. Note that disease prevalence rather than incidence is normally recorded in a
cross-sectional study [ref.]. The temporal sequence of cause and effect cannot necessarily
be determined in a cross-sectional study.
We suggest that, actually, the essence of the cross-sectional etiogenetic study is,
simply, this: The study base is formed as a single series of person-moments, as in a
cohort study, but outcomes associated with these person-moments are ascertained
with no follow-up the outcome being presence/absence of prevalent case of the
illness at those person-moments.
68 6 Etiologic Studies Typology
Abstract One of Immanuel Kants most seminal teachings was the idea that a
scientist does not learn by simply observing, reading Nature; that (s)he learns by
reading into Nature the terms in which (s)he thinks about Nature. It is in these terms
that (s)he, in a study, interrogates Nature seeks tentative answers to questions
(s)he poses.
In respect to population-level etiogenetic research this means that, preparatory
to a study, the researchers think, deeply, about the rate of occurrence of a health
phenomenon the event of a cancer becoming clinically manifest, say in a
particular domain initially defined by a range of age alone, perhaps. And they
think about the phenomenons rate of occurrence in causal relation to something in
the peoples past their diets antioxidant content, perhaps.
With such a sketchy point of departure, the investigators need to proceed to refine
their idea, in that example the particular meanings they elect to associate with the
generic terms in: the (rate of) occurrence of cancer in causal relation to histories
in respect to their diets antioxidant content, this in a particular domain of the
occurrence. They need to decide whether their thinking in this is specific to a
particular type of cancer and a particular type of antioxidant, or whether it is generic
in one or both of these respects. They need to specify their thinking in respect to the
range of time for the etiogenetic role of dietary antioxidants, retrospectively as of the
outcome event (its occurrence/non-occurrence). And they need to decide whether
the domain of the study is to be age-restricted and one of no previous clinically
manifest cancer, for example.
Upon decisions like these, the investigators go on to design a statistical model
(log-linear) for the outcomes occurrence in the defined domain, with determinants
in the form of statistical variates (Xs). The parameters of Nature constituting the
objects of study are imbedded in this model, the design of this model amounting to
the studys objects design.
A future with examples like this is envisioned in this chapter. As of now, a studys
objects design is not even in the common vocabulary of epidemiological research.
comes (rate of) occurrence is that the study result the empirical occurrence
relation will be informative about the causal connection at issue. In reality,
however, faulty objects design (just as faulty methods design) can make the study
result misinformative about the causal connection, about its strength in meaningful
terms in a given direction, even apart from the potential incompleteness of its
conditionality on all of the potential confounders.
In what follows, we address the principles of an etiogenetic studys objects
design in the contexts of two generic examples, very different in kind.
The first example here is about something that we already touched upon in
section 2.4 explicitly and in section 7.1 implicitly, namely the etiogenesis of prostate
cancer. In section 2.4 we quoted from a review of studies there had been
several cohort and case-control studies but no experimental ones on dietary
fat in the etiogenesis of this cancer, and here we consider one of each of these
two purportedly principal types of etiogenetic study (ch. 6). To these we add a
subsequent experimental study on the same factor but in relation to a different
cancer. Besides, as for diet deficient in the antioxidant selenium in the etiogenesis of
prostate cancer, we examine another case-control study and also the experimental
study for which it was a partial prompting (there having been no other case-control
studies nor any cohort studies before the trial). These five studies are:
1. Shuurman AG et alii. Association of energy and fat intake with prostate carci-
noma risk. Results from the Netherlands cohort study. Cancer 1999; 86: 1019-27.
2. Hayes RB et alii. Dietary factors and risks for prostate cancer among blacks
and whites in the United States. Cancer Epidemiology, Biomarkers & Prevention
1999; 8: 25-34.
3. Beresford SAA et alii. Low-fat dietary pattern and risk of colorectal cancer. The
Womens Health Initiative Dietary Modification Trial. JAMA 2006; 295: 643-54.
4. Yoshizawa K et alii. Study of prediagnostic selenium level in toenails and the
risk of advanced prostate cancer. Journal of the National Cancer Institute 1998;
90: 1219-24.
5. Lippman SM et alii. Effects of selenium and vitamin E on risk of prostate
cancer and other cancers. The Selenium and Vitamin E Cancer Prevention Trial
(SELECT). JAMA 2009; 301: 39-51.
For broadest orientation here, it needs to be appreciated that, in practically
relevant terms, prostate cancer (or any cancer, for that matter) begins with the
inception of sickness from it (once the cancer becomes overt clinical in its
progression), and only this event is subject to the formation of the case series in
an etiogenetic study. Any study of the etiogenesis of prostate cancer thus must
be understood to actually be about the etiogenesis of (the event of) the onset of
symptoms and/or signs of it. All five of those studies addressed cancer in the
meaning of the event of its clinical inception.
Related to this, and of equally fundamental relevance to the objects design of
a study on the etiogenesis of cancer is a duality of phases in the development
of symptomatic cancer: the first, pathogenetic phase of this (of pathologic changes
7.2 Some Principles of the Design 77
Prevention Overview web page of the U.S. National Cancer Institute, that The
results of the [SELECT; ref. 5 above] indicated that taking daily selenium or vitamin
E or both did not reduce the incidence of prostate cancer compared with placebo
[ref.]. For recruited into that trial were men in their 50s of age or older (rather than
young children) and their median follow-up was 5.46 years (rather than decades).
Thus, by its nature that trial actually was solely about the cancers promotion, while
the hypothesis presumably was about its initiation.
The principle that thus was violated in all five of those example studies is this:
A meaningfully designed object for an etiogenetic hypothesis-testing study may
be infeasible to study (validly); and when it is, it should not be studied through
ersatz objects that actually are meaningless in respect to the biological essence of
hypothesis. The problem is much worse than futility: it is risking misunderstanding
of the study result, not understanding that it is meaningless in respect to the actual
hypothesis. It should be understood that some objects of desirable and meaningful
epidemiological knowledge are not subject to practicable population-level study;
that in respect to them it is necessary to settle for such insights and population-
level surmises as can be derived from more basic epidemiological research (cf.
sect. 1.2).
Apart from their temporal aspects, the causal contrasts in those five studies, from
# 1 to # 5 respectively, were these: a given level of fat intake (kcal/day) vs. another,
also conditionally on total energy intake; a given level of foods high in animal fat
(grams/day) vs. another, and the same in terms of such foods as a proportion of
total energy intake; reductions in fat together with increase in vegetables, fruits, and
grains vs. continuation of usual diet; a given level of toenail selenium content vs.
another, also conditionally on calcium intake and lycopene intake; and a given level
of supplementary antioxidant intake vs. placebo intake.
As in studies # 1 and # 2, meaningful quantification of fat intake indeed is
conditional on total energy intake, perhaps expressed as the proportion of the
latter. But such quantification remains meaningless except when at issue actually is
conditionality on or proportion of total energy intake from fats and, isocalorically,
specified alternative nutrients (carbohydrates, most notably), with total energy
intake a possible added element in the designed occurrence relation. The contrast in
# 3 is a bit of an approximation to what thus is needed, while that in # 4 is sensible,
though only isocalorically. Concerning diet supplementation with antioxidants, # 5
is impeccable as for the meaning of the factor contrast (when not considering its
temporal aspects).
The principle that in this aspect of those example studies object designs was
incompletely heeded is this: While the causal (index) histories in an etiogenetic
study are to be explicitly defined and meaningful as such, meaningful explicit
definitions also are to be given to the alternative(s) to these. The proper concept
of the alternative antecedent the reference history in an etiogenetic contrast is
not simply absence of the index history at issue.
Concerning the determinant contrast, the example studies considered here raise
this question: Insofar as it is reasonable and indeed preferable to study the effect
(etiogenetic) of total fat content of diet, without distinctions between, say, fats from
7.2 Some Principles of the Design 79
meats and dairy products as components of this, is it not better, by analogy, to study
total antioxidant content of diet instead of studying particular components of this?
(Cf. sects. 2.2, 7.1.)
And in the same vein, as the fat and antioxidant contents of diet are hypothesized
to be etiogenetic to various types of cancer, the question that arises is: Shouldnt the
object of study focus on the cancers unspecified instead of focusing on a given one
of them in any given study? (Cf. sects. 2.2, 7.1.)
The principle bearing on answering these two questions is this: Uncalled-
for distinction-making among potentially etiogenetic factors and among health
outcomes conduces to uncalled-for complexity and its consequent confusion and
retardation of progress, and it is, therefore, to be avoided. In those five example
studies there generally wasnt even a practical, study-efficiency reason to focus on
particular antioxidants or particular cancers instead of composites of these. And,
by the way, in studies of smoking in the etiology of cancer, progress would have
been even slower than it actually was (sect. 2.7) had distinctions been made among
particular brands of cigarette, while the initial focus on cancers of the airways was
obviously well-justified (while concern for any cancer, without distinctions, would
have further retarded the progress).
A technical problem that attends the focus on a component in a family of
conceptually related factors of etiogenetic potential is the need to control all of
the others as potential confounders in any non-experimental study on the singled-
out component. In the case-control study on selenium level (as measured from
toenails) in the etiology of prostate cancer (# 4 above), lycopene intake but intake
of no other antioxidant was controlled, and the operational meaning of this one type
of extraneous antioxidant intake (and calcium intake too) was left unspecified.
The principle that thus comes to focus is this: In non-experimental testing of an
etiogenetic hypothesis, histories of potential confounders need to be conceptualized
in truly meaningful terms and accurately documented in these terms (for full control
of them). When this is not possible, the object of study needs to be modified to
eliminate such a problem or, the project is to be abandoned altogether. Study of the
aggregate intake of antioxidants, without focus on any given one of the components
in this, is free of confounding by intakes of extraneous antioxidants. (Different from
potential confounders, etiogenetic hypothesis-testing does allow some fuzziness in
the histories involved in the causal contrast[s].)
While an etiogenetic study is about the rate of the outcomes occurrence in causal
relation to the etiogenetic determinant of this, ultimately in terms of the rate ratio for
the index category versus reference category contrast(s), those five example studies
were quite variable in what their respective results were said to be about. Reported
from the cohort study (# 1) was rate ratio. From the two case-control studies
(# 2 and # 4) the results were said to be odds ratios, and from the two experimental
studies (# 3 and # 5) reported were hazard ratios.
The principle pertaining to that variety is this: When the health phenomenon at
issue in an etiogenetic study is an event (rather than a state) and the etiogenesis at
issue is not very acute as was the case in all five of those studies the proper
comparative measure dictating the objects of study is rate ratio in the singular
80 7 Etiologic Studies Objects Design
meaning of incidence density ratio (in a defined abstract domain); and the empirical
counterpart of this from any study thus also properly is an IDR, this in reference to
the population-time constituting the study base and the contrast of its index segment
against its reference segment defined as of the person-moments constituting the
study base (and not as of the persons entries into the study base).
While the examples above were about diet excessive in fats or deficient in
antioxidants in the etiogenesis of overt, symptomatic cancer, our added example
is a related one and equally important: lack of screening really lack of screening-
associated presymptomatic treatments in the etiogenesis of fatality from a cancer.
Illustrative of the state of objects design in this research is a review of the results
of this research in respect to breast cancer:
Demissie K et alii. Empirical comparison of the results of randomized trials and case-control
studies in evaluating the effectiveness of screening mammography. Journal of Clinical
Epidemiology 1998; 51: 81-91.
The idea was to derive summary risk estimates separately from each of the two
types of study, for comparison in the spirit that, in principle, the same parameter was
being quantified in each of the studies, even if the results of the two types of study
may differ on account of incomplete adherence to the intervention categories in
the randomized trials.
The authors repeated the prevailing idea that The gold standard for evaluating
screening programs is the randomized controlled trial (RCT) (sect. 2.6), adding
that Case-control studies are easier to perform but their role in this area is
controversial. They gave several references to articles (and to one book) in which
the principles of the case-control studies on screening have been delineated.
Before getting to the particulars of that review, we give our introduction into
the principles concerning the respective generic types of object that actually are
addressed in those two types of study on the intended consequence of screening for
a cancer.
That gold standard RCT of epidemiological researchers and policy advocates
regarding screening for a cancer is one in which seemingly healthy persons are
randomly assigned to one of the two arms of the trial. One of these commonly is
simply that of usual care (undefined, variable) in respect to the cancer, while in
the other arm the experimental one of the study the care is defined to the
extent that the participants are invited, or actually scheduled, to undergo periodic
screenings for the cancer in terms of an initial test, with positive result of this
test prompting referral to clinical care (for further diagnostics, undefined, and
possible early treatment, undefined, upon rule-in diagnosis, undefined). The trial
design involves specification of the time interval between successive rounds of the
testing and also the number of these rounds, together with the duration of follow-up
(as of randomization). The concern is to document the mortality from the cancer
over the duration of the follow-up in each of the two arms of the trial with a
view to documentation of the proportional reduction in that mortality (due to the
screening/testing).
7.2 Some Principles of the Design 81
The most eminent example of these gold standard trials now is the most recent
one, the National Lung Screening Trial in the U.S. Pertaining to it, the National
Cancer Institute of the U.S. released, on 28 October 2010, a statement saying,
among other things, that The primary goal of the NLST was to determine whether
[sic] three annual screenings with low-dose helical computerized tomography
(LDCT) reduces mortality from lung cancer relative to screening with chest x-ray
(CXR). The trial had been designed to have 90% statistical power for detecting 20%
reduction in such mortality. The essential result prompting the trials termination
was that in the LDCT and CXR arms of the trial the respective rates of death
from lung cancer over the 58 years of follow-up since entry into the trial were
245.7 and 308.3 per 100,000 person-years, and this was taken to imply
a (308.3 245.7)/308.3 D 20.3% reduction in lung-cancer mortality by LDCT
relative to CXR (Table 3 in the statement). The relative deficit in mortality from
lung cancer in the LDCT arm exceeded that expected by chance, even allowing for
the multiple analyses conducted during the course of the trial, presumably taken to
imply that the reduction was not due to chance.
Some editing is called for here. First, the mortality from lung cancer in the LDCT
arm having been 20.3% lower than in the CXR arm does not mean that LDCT (really
its associated treatments) reduced the mortality by 20.3% relative to what it would
have been in the people in this arm of the trial had CXR been used instead of LCDT.
And second, even though the trial was designed for detecting 20% reduction in such
mortality (with 90% probability) and was stopped with the idea that the mission
had been accomplished, in truth there was no such detection, nor could there have
been. Reduction is an effect, and effect is not a phenomenon, subject to observation
and, hence, detection and quantification (sect. 4.2). The reduction might have been
10%, or perhaps 40%; its specific magnitude is unknowable, that 20.3% being a
composite of the reduction together with the workings of bias and chance. (The
95% confidence interval, not given in the NCI statement, is 631%.)
The statistical power calculation alluded to in that statement implies that
associated with three annual screenings with [LDCT], instead of CXR, there is, if
any, a particular degree of proportional reduction in mortality from lung cancer a
constant proportion over time as of the initiation of the screening, fully operative in
whatever duration of follow-up.
Related to this is our first principle concerning the mortality reduction in a
trial such as the NLST: The proportional reduction in mortality from the cancer
is nothing like a constant over time from the beginning of the screening (for the
generally short duration of it) to the end of the follow-up (for an arbitrary duration
of it). It thus is logically inadmissible to quantify the reduction by pooling the
experience across the entire duration of the follow-up. The proper concern in a trial
like this is to address the incidence density of death from the cancer as a function of
time since the initiation of the screening. And that function is, of course, different
for different durations of the screening.
This leads to our related, second principle: Reduction in mortality from a
cancer subsequent to screening can occur only if the cancers treatments under
the screening those early treatments are more commonly curative than those
82 7 Etiologic Studies Objects Design
With these principles as the background we now return to that review meta-
analysis by Demissie et alii (ref. above).
That reports Table 1 was entitled Design, population and characteristics of
screening approach of randomized control [sic] trials. As we noted above, critically
important determinants of the magnitude of such mortality reduction as is addressed
in these screening trials are the duration of the screening and the duration of the
follow-up (as of randomization) these, naturally, in addition to the nature of the
entire regimen to pursue early diagnosis about the cancer, including the time interval
between successive rounds of this regimens application. That table reveals no
specifics about the diagnostic regimens (not even their initial tests and the definitions
of their positive results). The number of rounds of the screening is specified for
each study (the range is from 1 to 7 among the trials), and specified also is the
time interval between the rounds of screening (it was 1233 months). It thus can
be deduced that the durations of the screening ranged from 2 to 12 years. The
duration of follow-up is specified, ranging from 7 to 16 years. Given the trials
great variability in such result-relevant aspects of their respective methodologies, no
7.3 The Result of the Design 83
into this medical thinking. In the designed occurrence relation, the outcomes rate of
occurrence is represented by a chosen occurrence measure, ordinarily the logarithm
of the numerical element in the outcome events incidence density (sect. 4.4). The
magnitude of this measure is formulated as a function (linear) of a set of statistical
variates (numerical) adopted ad hoc as representations of the person characterizers
on which this magnitude depends according to the design of the occurrence
relation that defines the objects the object parameters of the study.
We emphasize this because it represents a major departure from the prevailing
thinking and practice in etiogenetic research. As it is, quite sharp a distinction is
being made between study design and the studys data analysis, so that the study
design does not define the parameters the objects of study the empirical values of
which are to be derived by suitable synthesis (sic) of the data by suitable fitting of
(the operational counterpart of) the designed occurrence relation to the data. We thus
emphasize the need to integrate the medical and statistical aspects of the research
just as the material and mathematical aspects are integrated in physics (in, e.g.,
Maxwells equations on electromagnetic radiation).
We thus emphasize the need to think of etiogenetic research as inquiry into the
magnitudes of defined statistical parameters of Nature, whether qualitatively (as to
existence of deviations from their null values) or quantitatively (as to the magnitudes
of those deviations).
The here strongly advocated explicit, up-front design of the objects of study, and
this, specifically, as a matter of design all the way to the statistical form of the
occurrence relation implying the statistical objects of (the statistical parameters
for) study, has as its most straightforward implication the conceptual form of the
result that the result is empirical rate-ratio as a function of certain modifiers of its
magnitude, as we already have noted.
A related, minor implication is that an etiogenetic studys objects design implic-
itly defines the objective of the study: to produce evidence about the magnitudes of
the parameters that were designed to constitute the objects of the study.
Very important is the objects designs bearing on the studys methods design.
Suffice it here to refer back to sections 2.2 and 7.2 and, for example, the
discussions there of how seriously misleading has been all of the research
purportedly critically relevant randomized trials included on diets deficient in
their antioxidant content in the etiogenesis of cancers. Without due regard for
deliberate and thoughtful and also knowledge-driven objects design, these trials
methodologic routines have implied results in reference to very recent diets (or diet
supplementations) on the scale of etiogenetic time (retrospective as of the time of
the occurrence/non-occurrence of the cancers entering the clinical phase of its
development). Proper attention to objects design, we argued, would call for the
causal contrast to refer to the earliest decades of life, with the domain for the
7.4 Implications of the Design 85
outcomes occurrence representing rather late decades of life. And we noted, too,
that insofar as the nature of a meaningfully designed set of objects makes the study
methodologically impracticable, refraining from study is preferable to a study that
is inherently misleading on account of the form of its result.
Finally, what has here been said about objects design for etiogenetic studies
implies the need to stop classifying etiogenetic researchers as being either epi-
demiologists or biostatisticians, as this fosters disintegration of the medical and
statistical aspects of the research, while integration of these two really is called for
(cf. above). And once the necessary integration takes manifestation in the objects
design in terms of an occurrence relation with statistical variates and statistical
parameters, Statistical Methods vanishes from the study report while Objects Design
enters.
Chapter 8
Etiologic Studies Methods Design
Abstract Once the studys objects design has defined what the investigators are
concerned to shed light on the values of what parameters of Nature in what do-
main, conditionally on what extraneous determinants on the outcome phenomenons
rate of occurrence they can turn their attention to the studys methods design. In
it they define how they aim to measure those parameters values ultimately by
means of fitting the logistic counterpart of the objects-defining log-linear model for
the outcomes occurrence to the data (the realizations of Y, X1 , X2 , : : : ) on the
studys case and base series. The resulting empirical rate-ratio function translates
into the result for the etiogenetic proportion of interest (chap. 4 Abstract).
The methods design of an etiogenetic study proceeds in two distinct stages.
In the first stage, the objects-defining occurrence relation that was designed in
reference to Nature in the abstract is adapted to the actual study, translated into the
operationalized model. The independent variates in the logistic model to be fitted
are defined in reference to this counterpart of the theoretical model. The second
stage of the methods design defines the means by which empirical content of that
form is judged to be best obtained. While the essence of the study has an a-priori
definition, many particulars of it remain to be specified/designed (chap. 6 Abstract).
This second stage of the studys methods design is governed by the imperative
of validity assurance, descriptively, together with the desideratum of efficiency
optimization. Both of these, in turn, are governed by principles of the studies
methods design.
Apart from efficiency, a determinant of the studys informativeness is its size;
but this is not subject to principles-guided optimization, with one exception: when
a violation of principle is detected in the studys objects design or in its methods
design in respects other than study size (number of datapoints in the two series), the
optimal indeed, correct size of the study is zero.
with the way in which the source population will be selected/defined. The chosen
definition may be direct; or it may be indirect, as the catchment population
secondary to the way in which cases of the outcome are identified (to which direct
definition is given).
Either way, an important methodological consideration is the operational defini-
tion of the illness at issue, notably as to whether it should be restricted to cases are in
their manifestations typical and also severe for reasons of helping to assure validity
of the study. This restriction in the operational definition of a case of the illness
facilitates complete case identification from a directly defined source population;
and it makes more concrete the source population with indirect definition of it,
thereby facilitating its fair sampling of the source base (for the first-stage base series;
sect. 5.2).
Among the orientational considerations also is this: Should the conditionality
of the outcomes rate of occurrence on potential confounders, called for by the
studys objects design, indeed be pursued in terms of documentation and control,
or should this be replaced by prevention of the confounding by redesign of
the occurrence relation or suitable design of the study base as representation of
the domain? For example, as smoking represents a generally poorly controllable
potential confounder, the solution may be restriction of study domain to life-long
non-smokers. As another example, confounding by the level of fever in the study
of aspirin use in the etiogenesis of Reyes syndrome in the domain of febrile
illness in childhood may be prevented by contrasting aspirin use with the use
of another antipyretic (acetaminophen, say). On the other hand, prevention of
confounding by socio-economic status in the study of etiogenesis by occupational
exposure to a toxin may be accomplished by forming the source population of
workers in such a way that the exposure at issue can be presumed to be, in this
population, uncorrelated with SES (cf. sect. 6.4). In experimental causal research,
the preeminent means of prevention of confounding, specific to T0 of cohort and
scientific time, is randomization, while prospective confounding may be prevented
by blinding (which may require placebo comparison).
These examples might suffice to convey the point that even though cohort,
case-control, and cross-sectional study do not represent defensible design
alternatives to each other in etiogenetic research (sect. 6.5), there really are
options very notable ones in the studys methods design beyond the operational
reformulation of the objects-defining occurrence relation together with its domain
(sect. 6.6).
for the study, complete validity generally being unattainable. Another, secondary
concern desideratum rather than an imperative is maximization of the studys
efficiency, within the limits of the attainable.
An etiogenetic studys validity can be, and needs to be, thought of in two stages.
The study is descriptively valid to the extent that the object parameters empirical
values in its result would converge to those of the corresponding parameters
of Nature (defined by the designed occurrence relation) were the study size to
approach infinity (so that chance imprecision of the empirical values would be fully
eliminated). Insofar as those parameters have locally (in the studys place and at
its time) specific values, then this amounts to definition of the studys local validity,
in descriptive terms. And the study is causally (etiogenetically) valid to the extent
that its result is not only descriptively valid but also free of confounding.
Lack of validity in an etiogenetic study is, most broadly, of one or more of three
types. It is constituted by selection bias and/or documentation bias taking away from
descriptive validity and, of course, by confounding bias as a potential added element
in the lack of causal validity.
Selection bias results from violation of one or both of two principles. One of these
principles is that commitment to the source base must be made independently of
even a hunch about what the result from the study base in it, specifically, would
be; and by the same token, the commitment must be adhered to independently of
the findings from what was designed to be the study base. The associated other
principle is that a study base (within the source base) must be the result of the
study subjects entries into and exits from it independently of the outcome itself.
This generally means entries and exits independently of precursors (prodromata) of
the outcome. However, for validity of etiogenetic study, actually required is only
that there not be differential dependence on precursors of the outcome between the
contrasted experiences.
Selection bias of that first kind is akin to result-dependent submission of the
study report for publication, and to the study reports result-dependent acceptance
for publication. Both of these violations of principle very common and knowingly
committed! conduce to publication bias in the aggregate of published studies
on any given (set of) object(s) of study, and this in turn makes for unavoidable
selection bias in the study base of any derivative study on the magnitudes of
the object parameter(s) (sect. 13.1). Publication bias could be eliminated by a simple
innovation in medical journalism (sect. 13.6).
Selection bias of that second kind is tantamount to the study base being distorted
by failures in the implementation of the protocol. By the same token, its prevention
is a matter of stringent adherence to the protocol in its implementation, so long as
the protocol itself is sound.
Documentation bias, in sharp contrast to selection bias, is not at all about the
study base per se. Whatever the study base is, the occurrence relation in it the
operationalized counterpart of what was designed in reference to the abstract
should be documented correctly, validly in this sense. In this documentation, bias
8.2 Some Principles of the Design 91
The identification of the extraneous outcome events for the base series
generally all of them, as defined, occurring in the study base is to be, in
relevant respects, completely analogous to that for the case series: definition of the
admissible cases, canvassing all of the care facilities for them (sic), etc. (see above).
This makes (the common practice of) matching by hospital inadmissible whenever
the care facilities for the extraneous cases differ from those for the cases of interest.
The distribution of the case series (by a correlate of the etiogenetic history) can
be used as a (partial) guide for stratification of the sampling for the base series, the
other guides being the histories varied distributions and the samplings varied unit
costs across the strata. (See efficiency below.)
If the base sampling is stratified by person-characterizers other than what
already is involved in the designed (and operationalized) occurrence relation, the
stratification factors need to be added to those in the pre-designed occurrence
relation (i.e., the result is to be made conditional on these, too).
Confounding bias in the result of an etiogenetic study has two possible sources:
the designed theoretical occurrence relation may (and commonly does) fail to
make the objects of study sufficiently conditional on extraneous determinants of
the outcomes (rate of) occurrence; and the operationalized counterpart of this
conditioning may be deficient as a representation of that conditioning.
Insufficient conditionality on extraneous determinants in the theoretical occur-
rence relation is not inherently a matter of the set of accounted-for potential
confounders being incomplete. Another source of the problem is inadequate
conceptualization and hence inadequate representation of a determinant that
is accounted for. For example, history of smoking likely is, generally, quite
inadequately accounted for by inclusion, in the log-linear model, of a single term
for pack-years of cigarette smoking. The same is true of a single term for years of
education in conditioning for socio-economic status. And when use of aspirin has
been studied in the etiology of Reyes syndrome in the domain of febrile illness
in childhood, a major concern has been potential confounding by the level of the
fever, the meaning of which is obfuscated by the antipyretic effect of the aspirin
use.
When problems in the conceptualization and/or documentation of a confounder
(or in the modeling of its role as a determinant) are unsurmountable, making control
of confounding (characterizing the study base) impracticable, the need is to consider
possible attainability of prevention of confounding (from characterizing the study
base); see section 8.1 above.
size of the study base) and/or by increasing the size of the base series. This raises
the question about the efficiency-optimal relative sizes of these two series when
both of them can be expanded; and the answer is that optimal is the size ratio that
is the inverse of the square root of the unit-cost ratio between the two series. But if
the size of the case series is a given, the studys informativeness can be increased
only by increasing the size of the base series which does not provide appreciable
further increase once the base series already is, say, fivefold in size relative to the
case series. A large base series is prone to be cost-ineffective, inefficient.
Among the distributional determinants of an etiogenetic studys efficiency also is
the designed distribution of the base series across strata of the study base. It remains
commonplace to match the base series to the case series, meaning that it is chosen so
as to have identical distributions for the two series, by gender and age, for example;
but this is not efficiency-optimal (while irrelevant for validity). Efficiency-optimal
is sampling that is proportional to informativeness and inversely proportional to
the square root of unit-cost of the sampling; and a stratums informativeness is
proportional not only to the number of cases from it but also to the product of
the proportional sizes of the index and reference segments of the stratum-specific
segments of the study base.
Once the objects design for an etiologic/etiogenetic study has been followed by its
corresponding methods design, the investigators are ready to produce the study
protocol, which defines, in all relevant detail, the study methodology all the way
to the synthesis of the collected data into the study result together with its associated
measures of the imprecisions of the empirical values of the object parameters.
The study protocol has direct bearing on the study report, the core of which is
evidence about the object parameters in dual terms: the study result together with its
associated measures of imprecision for one, and the genesis of these numerics for
another with description of the salient features of the protocol the core input to the
latter, supplemented by information about deviations from it in the implementation
of the designed methodology.
The study protocol commonly is to be supplemented by the studys manual of
operations or, as a modern counterpart of this, a web-based management system,
governing and guiding the study procedures with a view to quality assurance in
respect to adherence to the protocol.
Insofar as the operationalized version of the occurrence relation is true to the
theoretical one it represents and the rest of the methodology indeed is, as intended,
practicable and successfully implemented, the ultimate implication of this is that the
study result will be, in essence, descriptively unbiased (sect. 8.2 above). The extent
to which a descriptively unbiased result also is causally unbiased is a question of
the studys methodology; but it also is a question of its objects design (sect. 8.2
above).
8.3 Implications of the Design 95
The study results degree of causal unbiasedness together with its precision
determine the burden of evidence from the study. The precision is determined by
the studys efficiency together with its size.
It bears emphasis that there are not, nor can there be, tenable principles of
optimizing the size of an etiogenetic study the number of datapoints (person-
moments) in its study (case and base) series save for one: for a study with
an identifiable violation of tenable principles in its objects design or methods
design, the optimal size is zero. Any scheme of sample-size determination is but a
mapping of an arbitrarily selected value for a measure of the results precision to its
corresponding size of the study; and the result derived from it is commonly changed,
drastically, by reviewers of the grant application to zero (with corresponding
adjustment of the budget).
Chapter 9
Etiologic Studies Intervention Counterparts
(potential) enrollment is sought and obtained, this may initially be followed only
by tentative enrollment. For, the admissibility criteria may need to be assessed more
comprehensively and/or more closely; and there may be a need to furtively test the
persons adherence to an agreed-upon plan for some simulated intervention.
The process leading to a persons definite enrollment into the study cohort is
completed if, and when, the assignment experimental, generally randomization-
based to a particular intervention occurs. This is the study cohorts membership-
clinching event, after which there will be no exit from the membership (sect. 6.1).
This study population is formed from, rather than embedded in, the source popula-
tion (cf. sect. 5.1), and it thus has its (prospective) course independently from that
of its source population (which usually is open dynamic rather than closed).
Two tasks are executed at the time of a persons enrollment into the study
cohort, at this T0 of cohort time as well as of actual scientific time. One of these
tasks naturally is documentation of the relevant facts which, in the operationalized
(methodological) version of the initially designed occurrence relation, have this T0
as their temporal referent. And the other one, just as naturally, is the assignment
of the intervention, possibly with blinding of the assignment (for prevention of
prospective confounding and/or assurance of validity of outcome assessment). If one
of the interventions actually is no intervention at all, it may need to be represented
by placebo intervention in the context of blinding.
In the post-T0 period, too, there are two tasks to be executed. One of these again is
a matter of observation and it related documentation, while the other one is in the na-
ture of execution and enforcement, having to do with the commitments of the study
subjects and, notably, those of the research personnel too. The documentation has to
do with protocol adherence for one, and with the outcomes both effectiveness- and
safety-related for another. And the execution and enforcement of the intervention
commitment is a post-T0 task even in the context of an acute intervention, given that
the protocol specifies this as the only (sic) intervention (so long as the documented
outcomes may be affected by extraneous interventions).
Given that all that is to be performed in the post-T0 (post-randomization) period
in an intervention experiment, follow-up is too passive-sounding as a term for
it. To wit, studied are effects of actual interventions, not those of intentions to
be subjected to an intervention (or to its defined alternative; sect. 3.1). Effects
in medicine, and in its simulated practice in intervention experiments likewise,
characterize actions, not mere intentions to act; and they can be unintended as well
as intended effects of actions, never of mere intentions to act.
Once the data have been collected and entered into the trials database, the
outcome events of a given type (those relevant of effectiveness, say) that occurred in
the study base can be identified from the database, and as a supplement to this case
series can be selected a suitable base series as in a logically construed etiogenetic
study (sect. 6.5). For each of these two series, the database allows the identification
of the type of the intervention and the duration of this (since T0 ); and the same is
true of all other relevant information (incl. that documented at T0 ).
Fitting the logistic counterpart of the designed log-linear model for the outcome
events incidence density to the data (the designed statistical variates realizations)
102 9 Etiologic Studies Intervention Counterparts
in the two series, results in a documentation of the experience in terms of the events
incidence-density ratio as a function of intervention time (T), type of intervention,
and the persons prognostic indicator profile at T0 .
But as at issue actually is not an etiogenetic study but an interventive one, the
interest is not in the (causal) rate ratio but the rate proper, the events incidence
density as a joint function of all of those determinants of its level. To derive this
function for the incidence density of the outcome event at issue, a representative
(simple random) sample of the study base is to be drawn to constitute the base
series. Then, the desired function for incidence density can be derived as
where B is the size of the base series, PT is the amount of population time
constituting the study base, and L is the linear compound arising from the logistic
models fitting to the data on the case and base series. The corresponding empirical
function for cumulative incidence and risk from time T D 0 to T D t is
Z t
When the outcome at issue is a state of health and the concern thus is to
derive the corresponding prevalence function, the base series need not be derived
by representative sampling; the only requirement is that it be independent of the
presence/absence of the outcome state at the sampled person-moment. For, the
designed prevalence function is fitted to this single series, with no involvement of
quasi-rates and rate ratio. The logistic model for the prevalence is fitted to the data.
The logit of the prevalence at T D t, in the study base, is taken to be the resulting
functions realization at this point in time since the interventive T0 .
In an intervention trial of that usual, parallel type, any intervention contrast is an
asymmetrical one, just as is any etiogenetic contrast. The concern is not to compare
one intervention with another one. Instead, the concern is with only one intervention
at a time, with its effect on the (rate of) occurrence of the outcome at issue when this
intervention the index intervention in the contrast is present in lieu of its defined
alternative the reference intervention in the contrast. The role of the reference
arm in the trial is to provide for surmising what the outcomes rate of occurrence in
the index arm would have been had this subcohort been subjected to the reference
intervention instead of the index intervention (cf. sect. 4.3).
This parallel arrangement is needed when, as is usual, one of these two
conditions obtains: the alternative indeed is an actual intervention, another possible
intervention of choice; or it is absence of any actual intervention but the outcomes
rate of occurrence in the absence of any intervention cannot be presumed to be
(practically) constant over the follow-up time in the trial.
By the same token, there is no need for a reference arm when an intervention
is contrasted with no intervention and the outcomes rate of occurrence can be
presumed to be (practically) constant over a period of time before and after the
9.4 The Ethics in the Experiments 103
ethical obligation, now strictly binding to the researchers, has to do with the study
subjects informed consent to the participation: without such consent from each
of the study subjects, the study is deontologically unethical. This is commonly
accompanied by deontological guidelines for the maintenance of confidentiality of
the information collected on the study subjects.
Informed consent in intervention-prognostic research on humans is commonly
thought of as pertaining, specifically, to each study subjects enrollment into a trial,
with experts equipoise about the interventions relative merits seen to be an added
prerequisite for ethical solicitation of the enrollment; but both of these ideas are
untenable, arguably at least.
As the decision to enter into a trial is to be an informed one, so logically should
also be continued participation in it, notably when new information accrues from
the study itself and/or from concomitant other studies: the information for the
consent should be updated, as indicated. But as it now is, the trials Data Safety
and Monitoring Board or its equivalent, in the light of merely the accruing data
in the trial itself and in the context of its own valuations, periodically decides to
continue the trial until, perhaps, abruptly calling it to a halt (notably as, suddenly,
there is a statistically significant difference, as P < ).
And equipoise, insofar as it should be seen to be relevant at all, should be that
of each potential study subject, whose subjective valuations matter in addition to
whatever objective information is supplied by experts. But actually, a potential study
subject should be free to volunteer for the advancement of the knowledge-base of
the practice of epidemiology (sect. 1.1) even in the face of whatever disutility this
action may subjectively seem to entail to the volunteer. By the same token, there
should not be any deontological prohibition of solicitation of participation in an
experiment, given provision of all of the relevant information about it. After all,
the investigators experimentation on him- or herself is not being considered to be
ethically inadmissible (see sect. 12.3).
Overall, the ethics of human experimentation in epidemiological research re-
mains incompletely developed even in respect to its broadest principles, and much
could be said about disingenuous heeding of such ethical deontological norms
as generally are being formally upheld.
learn from experiences in actual practice, documented for the purposes of practice
(rather than science) given that the compared interventions actually are being used
in actual practice.
In contemplating this alternative to experimentation, it is to be borne in mind
that the objects of epidemiological intervention studies have a particular structure
(sect. 9.2); and that, consequently, the intervention studies themselves have a
structure characteristic of them (sect. 9.3.).
The question about possible non-experimental alternatives to intervention exper-
iments in population-level epidemiological research thus takes this form: Can quasi-
experimental alternatives to those experiments, when distinctly more feasible to
construct, also be without appreciable compromise of validity? Such studies would
be, by definition, like their experimental counterparts as for the structure of them,
but they would not actually be experiments in terms of that which is definitional to
intervention experiments as distinct from their quasi-experimental counterparts: the
genesis of this structure, specifically the adoptions of the interventions for the (sole)
purpose of learning about their effects (sect. 9.1).
In quasi-experimental intervention studies the interventions are ones adopted so
as to elicit their already known, or at least presumed, intended effects. In these,
the intervention-study structure is achieved not by constructing it but, instead, by
suitable selection of the study subjects so as to achieve the needed structure as
though an experimental protocol had been followed.
The central reservation about quasi-experimental intervention studies relates,
naturally, to the very feature that makes them only quasi-experimental in the study
of intended effects (of interventions). Non-experimental, non-randomized studies
of the intended effects of alternative interventions are prone to be subject to incom-
pletely documentable and, hence, less than adequately controllable confounding by
indication in studies of the interventions intended effects, notably when used are
data recorded for the purposes of actual practice (rather than for research).
Ill-documented particulars of the indications severity bear on the risk of the
outcome at issue, and they may also have differential bearing on the choice of
intervention. This problem of potentially uncontrollable confounding by indication
generally is, however, much lesser in epidemiological research on preventive
interventions than in clinical research on therapeutic interventions, on account of
the generally simpler indications in the former.
Quasi-experimental intervention studies do have their place in the development
of the scientific knowledge-base of epidemiological practice, and the place is
characterized by simple indication for acute interventions and interest in long-term
effects of these, so long as the alternative interventions have been in use for long-
enough period of time.
Chapter 10
Causal Studies Acausal Counterparts
preventive or therapeutic. But we must point out that in a very eminent little book,
The Strategy of Preventive Medicine (1992), Jeffrey Rose this highly esteemed
professor of epidemiology argued otherwise. He accented the importance of the
cumulative effect on the population level of even minor gains by the individuals
involved. In this books Preface he wrote, The essential determinants of health of
society are thus to be found in mass characteristics: : : : effective prevention requires
changes which involve the population as a whole.
Women in the population that an epidemiologist serves do not look for guidance
from the epidemiologists health-education in respect to reduction of their risks for
prostate cancer; but they do look for guidance in respect to prevention of coronary
heart disease and stroke, for example. Interest in, and relevance of, prevention-
oriented measures of maintenance of low-risk lifestyle naturally depends on the
perceived level of risk for the illness at issue. An epidemiologists health-education
thus needs to provide for individual risk assessments in the community (s)he serves.
While rate inherently is a population-level concept in epidemiology, risk inher-
ently has to do with individuals (as members of a population perhaps). Risk is, for
an individual, the probability in the objective, relative frequency meaning of this
that the outcome adverse at issue will come about. It inherently is conditional
on whatever is the known risk profile prognostic profile of the particular person
at the time of the risk assessment, the prognostication in this sense. The (profile-
conditional) probability/risk of the outcomes occurrence is defined in reference to
a particular risk period for this, and it is the proportion of instances of the risk profile
in general in the abstract such that the outcome will occur within this period.
Risk per se is acausal, having to do with this proportion conditionally on a particular
intervention (such as none) with no causal contrast involved. It also is, for scholarly
purposes at least, conditional on surviving extraneous causes of death over the risk
period at issue.
In preventive medicine, risk assessment is relevant for decisions about
prevention-oriented actions in two stages. The first stage is assessment of
background risk, meaning risk conditional on no (new) prevention-oriented action
no change in, say, dietary habits. And if this risk is assessed and deemed high enough
to entertain such a change, change-conditional risks also need to be assessed for
assessment of the changes in risk over various periods that would result from the
action being considered. These two types of risk, considered jointly in respect to
a given potential action on the part of a particular individual at a particular time,
imply the causal risk difference relevant to the decision about the action.
110 10 Causal Studies Acausal Counterparts
The generic object of study for risk assessments with a view to potential prevention-
oriented action, for individuals decisions about the action, is a risk function
designed for a defined domain of risk assessment. This function may address the risk
conditionally on no action (preventive), or the risk may be formulated as a function
also of a potential action/ inaction with a view to the individualized risk difference
by the action, reflecting the effect (preventive) of this action when adopted in lieu
of no action.
Regardless of whether potential prevention-oriented action is involved, the risk
is modeled as a function of prognostic indicators relevant to consider as definers of
subdomains of the functions domain; and the function generally needs to define the
risk not for a single risk period but as a function of prognostic time as to the form
of those functional dependencies of the risk.
The risk for breast cancer overt, life-threatening cancer of a breast is very high
for women with certain exceptional mutant BRCA 1 and/or BRCA 2 genes. This
topic is of considerable healthcare concern, as screening for these very major risk
factors is practicable, as effective preventive interventions (by tamoxifen use or
even by bilateral mastectomy) are available options, and as screening for the cancer
(with a view to enhanced curability) is practicable all of this, naturally, in clinical
medicine.
Even though this care is, by its very nature, a matter of clinical, rather than
community, medicine, it nevertheless is a concern from the vantage of public
health and its attendant public policies, now that clinical healthcare has been
brought to the public domain via the advent of national health insurance. On the
other hand, though, the promulgators of the public policies are constrained by the
social contract that leaves the medical professions autonomous free of societal
domination in specifically medical aspects of the care.
This topic differs quite profoundly from the ones addressed in section 4.1 in that
the public policies about it are not legalistic-regulatory and directed to the publics
behaviors or environments outside the realm of (professional) healthcare. They are,
instead, directed to the relevant healthcare (clinical), by physicians. But consistent
with autonomy of the medical professions, the public policies are not normative
stipulations concerning the care; they are about societal reimbursements of the costs
of the care.
So, what do the promulgators of healthcare policies (on reimbursements) princi-
pally need to know about clinical care related to this genetic aspect of breast cancer?
and how will they get to know it? It is relevant to note first, in the particular context
here for a start, that they do not need to know about the etiogenetic proportions
for those genotypes in cases of breast cancer associated with those genotypes, from
causal research of the etiogenetic genus. The frequency prevalence of each of
those genotypes is a matter not of human behavior (unpredictable, capricious, as in
the first three of the four examples in sect. 4.1) nor of peoples environments (also
quite variable) but of human biology, and these rates are knowable from genetical-
epidemiological research. But again, policy promulgators need not know about these
proportions either.
Instead, the policy-makers need is to know about the risk of coming down
with overt breast cancer say, life-time cumulative risk of this among women
with those genetic traits, this naturally from descriptive, acausal research for risk
assessment (ch. 10). And in particular, the policy-makers need to know much more
from specifically clinical research so as to have the scientific basis, supplemented
by economic facts, for assessing the cost-effectiveness of the care, this being central
to the perceived justifiability/unjustifiability of societal reimbursement of its cost.
11.2 Epidemiologists Outlook 115
As we repeatedly let on in the two sections above, screening for a cancer, in itself,
does not reduce mortality from the cancer as, contrary to common claim, it is not
an intervention. Only the screening-afforded early treatments (in lieu of later ones)
have the potential for that consequence (in causal terms), on the ground of enhanced
curability of otherwise fatal cases of the cancer.
And we also showed, in section 11.3 above, that this curability gain is not
manifest in the proportional reduction in cumulative mortality from the cancer in
such screening trials as ordinarily are designed and carried out; that such a mortality
reduction generally grossly underrepresents the proportion of cases that are curable
by early treatment among otherwise incurable, fatal cases of the cancer; that, in
fact, nothing quantitatively meaningful is studyable by means of such trials. And
qualitatively, the mere existence of the reduction generally should be understood not
to be a hypothesis but a corollary of the attainability of earlier, latent-stage diagnosis
and the enhanced curability consequent to this.
Harkening back, again, to the example in section 10.3 above, that curability rate
(69%) for early-detected, otherwise fatal cases obviously is, in principle, studyable
by means of an actual intervention trial. In it, some of the baseline screen-detected
cases (a random subset) of the cancer would be treated without delay, others only if
and when they progress to overt, symptomatic disease.
118 11 Studies on Screening for a Cancer
the cancers outcome. But in this segment of the cohort time the attained rate
of cures at baseline, in otherwise fatal cases, is not manifest in (the complement
of) the ratio of the cumulative rates of mortality from the cancer (in one minus
this ratio), as included in the screened-arm experience are deaths from cases that
only subsequently were detectable but were not detected by the screening. The
mortality ratio in this segment of follow-up is, thus, substantially diluted toward
unity (from the 1.00 0.69 D 0.31; cf. sect. 11.3 above).
Now, consider an RST that involves also regular repeat screenings annual ones,
say and suppose the latent cases detectable by these screenings also would have
their fatal outcomes 2-12 years following the detections in the absence of early
treatment. In this RST there can be a period of follow-up time in which deaths
from the cancer in the trials screening arm are reduced by a proportion identical
to the screening-associated rate of cures of otherwise fatal cases. This period, if
there, begins at 12 years of follow-up on the condition that the screenings duration
exceeds 12 2 D 10 years; and the length of this period is the same as the duration
of that exceedance.
In this period of maximal reduction in the mortality, if it exists (by the duration of
the screening), all deaths from the cancer in the trials screening arm are associated
with a history of diagnosis under the screenings repeat screenings and their
associated early treatment. The diagnoses about these cases were either screening-
based or prompted by symptoms appearing between scheduled screenings. In these
cases the early diagnosis its associated treatment failed to halt the cancers
progression to its fatal outcome.
Addressed in the foregoing has been study of the extent of a cancers enhanced
curability by means of experimental experience with the way case-fatality rate
from the cancer is affected by screening (by its associated early treatments).
With this clinical matter settled (more or less), the genuinely epidemiological
question remains, as it is about the mortality consequence of the introduction of
a public-health program to reduce the deaths incidence density (sect. 11.2). The
program could be one of mere reimbursement of the cost of the initial test in the
diagnostics constituting the screening, coupled with education of the public about
the screening (in the clinical domain); or it could be education about, and provision
of, community-level service as a matter of providing the screenings initial testing
(sect. 11.2).
So, the research clinical research outlined above actually is about curabil-
ity implications of mortality experience with experimental screening, while the
question relevant to epidemiological practice is about the mortality implications of
that curability, this in reference to the contemplated public-health program(s). This
question is not addressed by this research nor is it subject to being answered by any
epidemiological research. But to the extent depending on indications and quality
assurance the screening is clinically justified, it also is public-health-justified,
now that clinical medicine, too, is public-health medicine (given national health
insurance). For more on these challenging matters, see Appendix 2.
120 11 Studies on Screening for a Cancer
Lack of screening for a cancer (of its associated early treatment) is etio-
logic/etiogenetic to death from the cancer. The extent to which this is so naturally
is studyable only where the screening has been available (but not routinely used).
And it is studyable to learn about the here-essential parameter of Nature the
curability gain from screening-based early diagnoses only in settings in which the
screening has been available long enough.
These opportune settings ones in which the screening-afforded gain in curabil-
ity could be quantified by means of etiogenetic studies already are quite common;
and they really should be made use of for this purpose, for the serious problems
inherent in the gold standard trials in this quantification (sects. 7.2, 11.3, 11.4) are
not shared by their etiogenetic counterparts.
The study base needs to be defined (as to age, i.a.) in such a way that associated
with each person-moment in it there was an opportunity for the screening in the
relevant past, 212 years ago in the example in section 11.3 above. Thus, if the
cancer at issue in this example is that of breast and it was introduced over 12 years
ago to women 5070 years of age and has continued to be available only to women
in this range of age, the study base needs to be restricted to women 6272 years of
age; for, women younger than 62 years of age did not have access to screening as
long as 12 years ago, and women more than 72 years of age did not have that access
as recently as two years ago. If the screening for that range of age was introduced
less than 12 years ago, no-one in the population had access to the screening for the
entire period of 212 years ago, so that a valid study base cannot yet be defined in
this setting.
For the case series (of death from the cancer, in a suitably defined study base
as to age, i.a.), the index history need not be that of regular screening throughout
the period of 212 years prior to the death (to continue the example). A sufficient
substitute for this has to do with the time of the cancers diagnosis (rule-in dgn.): at
the time of the diagnosis the person was under screening, so that the diagnosis either
resulted from screening or was a symptoms-prompted interim diagnosis within a
regular-type cycle of the screening. (Additional screenings outside this particular
cycle could not have had any potential role in prevention of the death, so that
history about those screenings is irrelevant in the definition of the index history.)
The corresponding reference history in the case series is: diagnosis while not under
screening; that is, diagnosis not preceded by on-schedule initial test, with negative
result of the screening.
Definition of the index history for the base series presents the challenge that there
is no counterpart for the routine positive history of diagnosis (rule-in) about the
cancer in the case series, no inherently corresponding time on which to focus it and,
consequently, the reference history also. The solution of choice to this dilemma is
to use the case series as the guide to this timing: as a case (of death from the cancer)
has occurred at a particular time in age and calendar time, this prompts a number of
probes into the study base, into the same stratum of time (age and calendar time);
11.5 Meaningful Etiologic-type Study 121
and for this set of person-moments in the study base, the screening history is defined
in reference to the same time at which the first manifestation of the cancer (positive
test result, or symptom) occurred in the member of the case series.
With the case series from the source base restricted to the limited range of age
that is to characterize the study base (see above) and with the base series time-
matched to this, another restriction also is of note here. Study of the curability gain
requires that only one detected case of the cancer characterizes the histories in the
case series, with none the counterpart of this in the base series.
If this is all that is in the scientific essence of the study design, then the data from
the study lead to a set of 2 2 tables, each specific to a confounder stratum at the
time of the outcome:
I R Total
c1j c0j Cj
b1j b0j Bj
where I and R denote the index and reference history (of screening), respectively,
and Cj and Bj are the stratum-specific sizes of the case and base series, respectively
(cf. sect. 5.4). And the confounder-adjusted empirical measure of the rate ratio (for
death from the cancer, contrasting I with R) is
b
RR D
X
j
c1j =
X
j
b1j c0j =b0j
(cf. sect. 5.4); and the corresponding empirical measure of the curability gain from a
b
round of screening (from screen diagnoses when added to interim diagnoses within
the round) is the complement of this, 1 RR .
b
If the data are examined separately by categories of the etiogenetic time
(retrospective as of the outcomes in the two series), presumably the RRs for more
distant times are seen to be lower than those for more recent times (see Table 11.1
in sect. 11.3). This, while true, is irrelevant for the quantification of the curability
gain so long as the rate of the screenings use has been essentially constant over that
range of retrospective time as evinced by the I/R ratio in the reference series over
b
that span of time. Otherwise averaging of the time-specific RRs their logarithms
is called for, with the RR the antilog of this average (unweighted).
The foregoing implicitly involves the premise of no confounding in the study
base according to extraneous determinants other than calendar time and age of the
incidence density of death from the cancer. But insofar as there is, in the study base,
potential confounding by other factors, they need to be accounted for in the model
for the incidence density and, accordingly, in the logistic model fitted to the data
perhaps leading to stratification according to a confounder score (sect. 5.4).
As this is a non-experimental study on causation (of the etiogenetic sort),
the question is, as always in this genre of studies, whether all of the potential
confounders were identified and adequately documented, for control in the synthesis
of the data to the result of the study. Now, undergoing a round of screening or
122 11 Studies on Screening for a Cancer
refraining from this is a purposive course of action, and the indications of risk
bearing on the decision about this action are known to the decision-makers and
hence knowable to the investigators. The question is, though, whether the facts about
these can validly be ascertained for both of the study series from the next of kin in
both of them.
While paradigms for research are important and tenable paradigms are
particularly desirable, they should not be seen to define the boundaries of productive
research. Some problems require extraparadigmatic solutions, even ones worthy of
Nobel Prize for Physiology and Medicine.
which we see as representing the cohort and trohoc fallacies, respectively (sects. 6.1,
6.2). We suggest replacement of these by a singular conception of the nature of
(population-level) etiogenetic studies: the etiogenetic study (sect. 6.5).
As for intervention research, we can be seen to adhere to the prevailing,
randomized-trial paradigm, except for a proposed modification of it. We propose
that the object of the trial should not be a hazard ratio but an intervention-
prognostic probability function, and we delineate the way in which this can be
studied in the framework of such data as already are routinely collected in these
trials (sects. 9.2, 9.3).
Mass application of a screening test is taken to be an important type of
intervention preventive intervention by epidemiologists and by promulgators
of policies for healthcare (sect. 2.6, i.a.). For this reason we address screening
research specifically, research on screening for a cancer in this book (ch. 11,
i.a.). But we hold those ideas of epidemiologists and promulgators of healthcare
policy to be mistaken, and screening for a cancer to be a topic first and foremost a
diagnostic topic in clinical medicine (sects. 11.1, 11.2, i.a.). It is only because of
that common misunderstanding that we address screening (for a cancer) in this book
on epidemiological, rather than clinical, research. Further attention to it we give in
Appendix 2.
A student being introduced into epidemiological research should not be left with the
idea that hypotheses about etiology/etiogenesis derive solely from epidemiological
studies on humans (with populations as units of observation perhaps; cf. sects. 2.1,
2.2, 2.6), or that testing of such hypotheses is best done by means of non-
experimental etiogenetic study (sect. 6.5). The route to success may well be
extraparadigmatic. In what follows, we illustrate this by the genesis of the idea that
the etiogenesis of peptic ulcer involves a role for a bacterium.
The research, in Australia, that led to the discovery of the role of Helicobacterium
pylori as the principal agent in the etiogenesis of peptic ulcer, gastric and duodenal,
128 12 Some Paradigmatic Studies
led the investigators to Stockholm, to receive the Nobel Prize. In outlining this
research, we draw from and direct the student to two articles:
1. Van der Weyden M et alii. The 2005 Nobel Prize in physiology or medicine.
Med J Aust 2005; 183: 612-4.
2. Atwood KC. Bacteria, ulcers, and ostracism? H. Pylori and the making of a
myth. Skeptical Inquirer Magazine 2004; vol. 28.6. Available at: http://www.
csicop.org/si/show/bacteria ulcers and ostracism h. pylori and the making of
a myth/. Accessed November 9, 2011.
The essentials of this research, according to reference 1 above, illustrate some
of the human hallmarks of revolutionary research. These include:
being at the right place at the right time, and seeing what other people had seen
but thinking of what nobody else thought [ref.];
the role of serendipity;
a passion for research that abandons personal safety with self-experimentation;
and
the inevitable resistance of the medical establishment as research undermines
current dogma.
That last point is, however, disputed, seen to be a misrepresentation of what
merely was the skepticism that is inherent in the scientific outlook (ref. 2).
Notable about the genesis of the hypothesis is that there were no insights
from basic science suggesting it, nor did the hypothesis arise from data on the
occurrence of peptic ulcer in any human population. It arose from Barry J. Marhalls
review of J. Robin Warrens records on his 25 cases of endoscopic biopsy, many of
them showing mysterious, spiral micro-organisms. The diagnoses in these cases
were duodenal ulcer in two, gastric ulcer in seven, gastritis in 12, and erosions and
scars in four (ref. 1).
The two future Nobel laureates next conducted a prospective study on 100 cases
of endoscopy, in which they, as the first researchers ever, came serendipitously
upon successful cultivation of the mysterious organism, which they named Heli-
cobacterium pylori. In the resulting data there was a strong association between
gastritis and the presence of this bacterium. It was found in all patients with
duodenal ulcer and 80% of patients with gastric ulcer. In contrast, the presence was
rare in patients with non-steroidal drug-related ulcers (ref. 1).
Then, Marshall and his colleagues showed that bismuth salts (which had been
used to treat gastritis and peptic ulcer disease for many years) killed H. pylori in
vitro; and, in clinical studies, that bismuth cleared H. pylori but the infection would
recur unless metronidazole was added to the regimen (ref. 1).
While the first prospective studys acceptance for publication by The Lancet was
an exceptionally protracted process following rejection by the Gastroenterologic
Society of Australia Marshall carried out another type of study as well, very small
and very dramatic. He asked [a colleague] to perform a gastric biopsy on him and
then ingested a pure culture of H. pylori (109 organisms). All was well for 5 days, but
then he developed halitosis [bad breath], morning nausea, and recurrent vomiting of
12.3 Successful Extraparadigmatic Studies 129
acid-free gastric juice. A gastric biopsy on Day 10 showed severe acute gastritis and
many H. pylori. The symptoms spontaneously resolved after 14 days, : : : (ref. 1).
This constituted highly suggestive evidence that the organism caused gastritis.
But it was far from conclusive, because it involved a single subject and was reported
by the very author most wedded to the hypothesis. Thus, replication by others would
have been required. Perhaps more important was that the subject, who was none
other than Marshall himself, failed to develop an ulcer. Note also that the disease
resolved without treatment (ref. 2).
What finally convinced doubters of both cause and treatment was something
that by its very nature took several years to establish. : : : The first trial that was
both large enough and rigorous enough to be noticed was conceived by Marshall
and Warren in 1984 : : : [They] reported that the recurrence rate of duodenal ulcer
was much lower in patients whose H. pylori were eradicated than in those whose
bacteria were not, : : : Since the authors were the original proponents of the bacterial
hypothesis, moreover, any firm conclusions would first require confirmation by
others. This was not ostracism; it was appropriate scientific skepticism (ref. 2).
While Marshall and Warren have irrevocably changed clinical practice and have
alleviated much human suffering (ref. 1), they also have made a major contribution
to the discipline of etiogenetic epidemiological research: they have, unwittingly,
reminded both teachers and students that this research, when successful in its
hypothesis generation, and testing of the hypothesis too, is not inherently a matter
of competent adherence to established paradigms, or to what used to be termed
the epidemiologic method. Their work is paradigmatic of the potential prowess of
extraparadigmatic etiogenetic research.
Chapter 13
From Studies to Knowledge
Evidence from an epidemiological study is, as just set forth, imbedded in the report
from the study; and specifically it is, so we implied, constituted by words and
numbers describing the studys results on the magnitudes of the parameters in
134 13 From Studies to Knowledge
the designed object of the study, these together with description of the genesis of
these results, verbal and numerical description of this too, augmented by measures
of the consequent imprecisions of the parameters empirical values.
Interpretation of this evidence we take to be formation of a view of what this
reporting of the evidence actually means, what the thus-communicated evidence
actually is. We thus sharply distinguish between interpretation of evidence, in this
meaning of it, and inference from the evidence (sect. 13.4 below).
In the context of the present level of development of the shared concepts and
terms among epidemiological researchers, the interpretation of the report of, and
hence the evidence from, epidemiological studies can be challenging, insofar as
avoidance of misunderstanding is the concern (sect. 2.6). To the extent that this
is the case, it is a serious problem. For, Where concepts are firm, clear and
generally accepted, and the methods of reasoning and arriving at conclusion are
agreed between men (at least the majority of those who have anything to do with
these matters), there and only there is it possible to construct a science, formal or
empirical. So wrote Isaiah Berlin in his venerable The Proper Study of Mankind:
An Anthology of Essays (Hardy H, Hansheer R, Editors; 1997; p. 61).
Emblematic about the status quo are some central routines in epidemiological
study reports at present. There still eminently is cohort study and case-control
study, rather than merely the etiologic/etiogenetic study (sect. 6.5). And even
though these two are thought of as alternatives to each other, reported from the
former usually is a result in terms of relative risk, with odds ratio the common
counterpart of this from the latter (sect. 2.6) both of these terms properly
referring to a parameter rather than the result of a study (which in the context
of an etiologic/etiogenetic study generally is the ratio of two empirical rates,
two incidence densities). Significantly increased risk in the determinants index
category is a common expression for the strictly particularistic fact that the rate
in the study experience was higher in this category, and that the difference was
statistically (sic) significant the actual risk implications of this, if any, being
a matter not of experience per se but inference from it (sect. 13.4 below). Just
as unobservable/undocumentable as causal increase in risk or rate is, of course,
reduction (inherently causal) in it, also commonly reported as a purported result
of an epidemiological study (sect. 2.6). Neither one of them can be found in, or
shown by, an epidemiological study.
Particularly great challenges of interpretation are exemplified in Appendix 2.
as its referent, while the study result inherently has a particularistic referent (i.e.,
the study base, spatio-temporally specific). This constitutes a notable challenge for
learning about descriptive acausal, purely phenomenal objects of study already.
The challenge is greater yet when the object of study is causal noumenal in this
sense and the study proper is, as is commonplace, non-experimental and subject
to biases even in descriptive terms.
Thus, however correct may be someones interpretation of the evidence from a
study (as to what the report from the study means in this respect; sect. 13.3 above),
his/her inference about the object of study in the light of the evidence remains a
matter of subjective judgements, leading only to his/her personal opinion about the
abstract truth in question.
Scientific research, epidemiological like any other, is a quest for scientific knowl-
edge for presumably truthful insights into the abstract.
Whereas evidence from epidemiological research on any given object of inquiry
provides for only personal opinions about the truth at issue (sect. 13.4 above),
the challenge that immediately results from this is reasonable conceptualization
of the nature, the essence, of epidemiological knowledge. And with this resolved,
it remains to understand how the evidence on any given object of desired, epi-
demiological knowledge can be translated into that knowledge. These challenges
have remained too little addressed and incompletely resolved, with the consequence
that epidemiological knowledge, even on obviously important topics, still tends to
remain ill-defined or controversial (ch. 2).
Pre-scientifically it used to be known firmly, for a very long time that disease
commonly is a matter of aberrant distribution among the four humors in the body.
It also was known that miasma vapors emanating from the soil, swamps, and
decaying organic matter are causal to disease, and that disease can be alleviated
(or perhaps even cured) by blood-letting.
In this modern era of health science it has just recently become known, from
epidemiological research, that dietary fats are causal to cardiovascular disease, while
research previously had persuaded experts that it was dietary carbohydrates that had
this effect; and the latter may get to be the knowledge in the future as well (sect. 2.1).
Epidemiological knowledge, even in this era of epidemiological science (in the
research meaning of this), is not inherently true; it is, even, subject to being a denial
of previous scientific knowledge science being, by its nature, self-corrective rather
than simply (linearly) progressive. It is, first-off, knowledge in the sense of experts
(in the relevant scientific community) having come to a more-or-less common,
shared belief about the truth at issue. These experts can defend their shared belief;
their knowledge is active in this sense.
Secondarily, there is others knowledge about the experts shared belief, passive
knowledge in this sense, knowledge that cannot be justified by those who possess
136 13 From Studies to Knowledge
it. Most people know that dietary fats are causal to cardiovascular disease, but only
experts on the subject can justify this belief (with the justification subject to being
mistaken).
The public-health authorities of Denmark, in 2011, adopted a public policy
consequent to their second-hand knowledge secondary to first-hand, expert
knowledge about the health consequence of fats in the diet. They introduced a
tax on purchases of foods high in saturated fats. This policy may well be ill-founded
and even counterproductive: the result may well be, for one, an epidemic of obesity
in Denmark, just as there already is in the fats-averse U.S., for example.
Express formulation of expert knowledge on matters epidemiological has not
been prone to emerge spontaneously in the relevant scientific community; it
has required deliberations and formulations and by topic-specific expert com-
mittees. But this, too, has been problematic, as that which emerges is prone to
be dependent on which set of experts constitutes the committee, among other
factors.
Spontaneous movement from evidence to knowledge within the relevant sci-
entific communities could be, so we believe, substantially enhanced by suitable
innovations in medical journalism (sect. 13.6 below); and related to this, the culture
of task forces on preventive healthcare could and should be substantially
improved (Apps. 1, 2, 3).
Two examples of express efforts to derive knowledge from the evidence produced
by epidemiological research (incl. bench research; sect. 1.2) are particularly
instructive: the work on the Smoking and Health report (1964) of an ad-hoc
advisory committee to the Surgeon General of the Public Health Service of the U.S.
Department of Health, Education, and Welfare; and the work on the continually
accruing IARC Monographs on the Evaluation of Carcinogenic Risks in Humans,
IARC being the International Agency for Research on Cancer within the World
Health Organization.
The smoking-and-health committee received from the National Library of
Medicine a total of 1,100 articles (p. 14). In addition to the special reports
prepared under contracts, many conferences, seminar-like meetings, consultations,
visits and correspondence made available to the Committee a large amount of
material and a considerable amount of well-informed and well-reasoned opinion
and advice (p. 15).
There were an uncounted number of meetings of subcommittees and other lesser
gatherings. Between November 1962 and December 1963, the full Committee held
nine sessions each lasting from two to four days (p. 15).
All members of the Committee were schooled in the high standards and criteria
implicit in making scientific assessments; if any member lacked even a small part
of such schooling he received it in good measure from the strenuous debates that
took place at consultations and at meetings at the subcommittees and the whole
Committee (p. 19).
It is advisable, however, to discuss briefly certain criteria which, although
applicable to all judgements involved in this Report, are especially significant for
13.5 Knowledge from the Evidence 137
judgements based upon the epidemiologic method : : : When coupled with the other
data, results from epidemiologic studies can provide the basis on which judgements
of causality can be made (pp. 1920; italics ours).
In carrying out studies through the use of this epidemiologic method, many
factors, variables, and results of investigations must be considered to determine first
whether an association actually exists between an attribute or agent and a disease.
: : : If it be shown that an association exists, then the question is asked: Does the
association have a causal significance? (p. 20).
To judge or evaluate the causal significance of the association : : : a number of
criteria must be utilized, no one of which is an all-sufficient basis for judgement.
These criteria include:
(a) The consistency of the association
(b) The strength of the association
(c) The specificity of the association
(d) The temporal relationship of the association
(e) The coherence of the association
These criteria were used in various sections of this Report. the most extensive and
illuminating account of their utilization is found in chapter 9 in the section entitled
Evaluation of the Association Between Smoking and Lung Cancer (p. 20).
The application of these criteria led to these Conclusions in respect to lung cancer
(p. 196):
1. Cigarette smoking is causally related to lung cancer in men. : : : The data for women,
though less extensive, point to the same direction.
2. The risk of developing lung cancer increases with duration of smoking and the number
of cigarettes smoked per day, and it is diminished by discontinuing smoking.
3. The risk of developing cancer of the lung for the combined group of pipe smokers, cigar
smokers, and pipe and cigar smokers is greater than in non-smokers, but much less than
for cigarette smokers. The data are insufficient to warrant a conclusion for each group
individually.
Three remarks may be called for here. First, at the time of this Report, epidemi-
ology was commonly defined as research by means of the epidemiologic method
(cf. above), and its principal types were termed, as in this Report, prospective
study and retrospective study (which later got to be termed cohort study and
case-control study, respectively).
Second, the criteria for causal inference deployed by the Committee were the
considerations famously elaborated by the statistician A.B. Hill the year after
the Reports publication. (He was not a member of the 10-member Committee;
its statistician was W.G. Cochran.) But those criteria/considerations are largely
untenable. To wit, the strength of a non-causal association can be very strong, as
in the case between match-consumption and lung cancer, for example; and this
association exhibits a strong dose-response pattern a topic under Coherence of
association (p. 123).
138 13 From Studies to Knowledge
Third, curiously missing from the criteria is the biological plausibility of the
associations causality, which Hill included, and the plausibility of confounding
as an explanation of the association, which Hill did not include. The section
immediately in front of Conclusions is entitled Other Etiologic Factors and
Confounding Variables (p. 183 ff), but it simply expands on the point that
a causal hypothesis for the cigarette-smoking-lung cancer relationship does not
exclude other factors (p. 193). The ones addressed are Occupational Hazards,
Urbanization, Industrialization, and Air Pollution, Previous Respiratory Infec-
tion, and Other Factors. There is no word about any of these or any other
confounders as possible explanations of the association between smoking and lung
cancer.
Looking back at these excerpts from the Preamble to the IARC Monographs, the
points of instructive note include these:
1. Whereas we think of carcinogenic factors in the categories of constitutional,
environmental, and behavioral, IARCs classification of carcinogenic agents
is quite different from this. Those specific chemicals, groups of related
chemicals, complex mixtures are, to us, potential carcinogenic factors only
when they are constituents (acquired) of a persons constitution, or subject to
becoming constitutional on account of a persons behavior or environment;
occupational factors are, to us, either behavioral or (micro-)environmental;
exposures are, to us, all environmental (even if as a result of behavior);
behavioural practices are not, to us, alternatives to cultural ones but,
potentially, cultural in their origin; all organisms are, to us, biomedical; all
carcinogenetic agents are, to us, chemical, physical, or biological, involved
in the constitutional, behavioral, or environmental carcinogenic factors (such as
inflammation, smoking, and air pollution); and causation is, to us, that which
a cause may bring about, depending on susceptibility to the cause, without the
latter being a carcinogen (while sunlight is a carcinogen, albinism is a related
susceptibility factor but not a carcinogen).
2. IARC distinguishes between epidemiological and experimental data, imply-
ing that epidemiological data inherently are non-experimental. To us, research
data are epidemiological if the intent in their production was to advance the
practice of community medicine, with the research quite possibly experimental,
including in the laboratory (sect. 1.2).
3. IARC is concerned not only with identification of carcinogenic hazards but also
with quantification of carcinogenic effects dose-response assessment. The
Monographs have emphasized the former, understandably, as epidemiologi-
cal research has tended not to get past hypothesis testing (ch. 2).
4. IARC sees itself in the service of public-health authorities in their decisions
about preventive-oncologic measures, but: no recommendation is given. This
is in sharp contrast with what is done by the Canadian Task Force on Preventive
Health Care and by the Preventive Medicine Task Force in the U.S.; and we
think that the IARC is right on this important matter. See Appendices 1 and 2.
5. IARC has a very elaborate scheme of assuring the greatest possible validity
of its Conclusions, which again is instructive of how major is the transition
from evidence to knowledge, seen to result only from experts consensus
evaluation of the evidence. As the Working Groups have to strive to achieve
consensus, the question is, How concordant would tend to be the conclusions
of two or more similarly constituted and similarly working expert groups,
addressing the same question.
6. IARC reflects our contemporary normal-science conception of types of epi-
demiological study on humans. Exceptionally, though, it prefers to use
correlation study as the term for what now is commonly known as ecological
study. The preference is curious, as the adjective is no more apt a descriptor
of studies with populations as the units of observation than studies of the
13.5 Knowledge from the Evidence 141
(as considerations) but A.B. Hill despite the obvious untenability of many
of these (cf. the Smoking and Health example above).
12. The Conclusions, representing the knowledge formulated by any given Working
Group, like those assessments/evaluations of the evidence from the studies, also
are only qualitative in nature (cf. # 11 above, in contrast to # 3). Yet, only
quantitative knowledge is the appropriate basis for authorities to set threshold
limit values, for example (cf. # 3 and # 4 above).
this, by the very nature of science, that has the capacity to converge into experts
shared belief, into genuine knowledge on a topic in medical (as in any other) science;
and difficulties in this would also serve to underscore the deficiencies in the available
evidence, inviting remedies for them.
As for quintessentially applied epidemiological and meta-epidemiological
clinical science specifically, a third kind of needed medical journalism concerns
its theory concepts and terminology for a start (Preface) and then principles
(sect. 1.3). This, too, is less than satisfactory at present, in that consensus-seeking
public discourse is missing in this area as well. And so it still is that textbooks of epi-
demiological research generally are mainly about study of the etiology/etiogenesis
of disease rather than illness (disease/defect/injury or morbus/vitium/trauma);
addressed is methodology of the research in total disregard of the studies objects
design; and in the studies themselves a major distinction still is routinely made
between cohort and case-control studies instead of proceeding from each of
these into the corresponding corrected conceptions, into that which is essential in
all etiologic/etiogenetic studies in this genre of them (chs. 5, 6). As another major
example, the textbooks still are prone not to make the profound distinction between
inquiries that are epidemiological research and ones that are part of epidemiological
practice (sect. 14.1).
More on the needed innovations in the translation of evidence into knowledge for
the practice of community medicine is given in Appendix 3.
As for the evidence itself in specifically epidemiologic journals, its publication bias
remains a serious problem; but this too is remediable: Reporting on population-
level epidemiological studies should be accepted for publication before any results
are at hand that is, upon the authors having completed the Introduction, Objects
Design, and Methods Design sections of the report and the sections having passed
peer review as well as review by the journals editorial board. No report should be
accepted belatedly, after the study plans implementation has already begun. Each
timely acceptance of the study plan for ultimate publication of the report should be
a matter of accessible record (incl. for the purposes of grant applications and their
peer reviews, in addition to the needs of derivative studies).
That early acceptance of the ultimate report on a study would not mean that
whatever gets to be written in it under Results and Discussion and in the
Summary/Abstract has advance approval for publication. The journals editorial
board has the responsibility (to the scientific community) to make sure that the
writing accords with the principles of this. Prime among these is the imperative
to clearly and correctly distinguish between particularistic facts about study results
and inferential ideas based on these. As for this, pervasive still is writing about study
results as though causality (or lack of it) had been observed and documented in a
study (cf. sect. 4.2). Quotes in this text illustrate this misleading writing, starting in
section 2.2 (showed no reduction in, did not affect).
With these innovations, epidemiologic journals would much better focus on
genuine contributions to evidence, minimizing obfuscating litter-ature. I coined
the term litter-ature to denote that too much of the medical literature is littered
13.6 The Needed Innovations 145
with misleading and false-positive findings, writes Eric Topol in his The Creative
Destruction of Medicine: How the Digital Revolution Will Create Better Health
Care (2012; pp. 31-2).
We add that even more influential as a source of publication bias generally is
the common opposite: cleaning out of the literature reports with negative results,
commonly meaning only relatively imprecise results, however valid.
Chapter 14
Fact-finding in Epidemiological Practice
Cancer Care Ontario) and the Provincial Health Planning Database. The Provincial
Health Planning Database contains information also on rates of injuries, poisonings,
suicide, etc.
Besides, Ottawa Public Health can obtain the information on the rates of
communicable-diseases morbidity from the Integrated Public Health System of the
Ontario Ministry of Health and Long-term Care.
Given that good healthcare is not only medically but also economically good not
only effective but cost-effective as well and given also the ever-deepening cost
crisis in modern, societally sponsored healthcare in modern public health, that
is the topic of quality assurance in clinical healthcare deserves more deliberate
consideration here than the little sketch above, ultimately with a view to the
role(s) we think practicing epidemiologists need to adopt as genuine clinical
epidemiologists, without the term being self-contradictory.
With screening for a cancer now a misguided exception (Apps. 1, 2), clinical
medicine has retained a good deal of autonomy within the society even after
the advent of national health insurance. Societies regulate industries as for the
marketing of medications and medical devices, but they still refrain from regulation
of the use of these products or other professional actions by clinicians.
Regarding the autonomous quality-assurance in clinical medicine, M.S. Liang
and P. Fortin wrote in 1991 (Ann Rheum Dis; 50: 522-5) that The American
experience with quality-assurance programmes prompted a Committee of the
Institute of Medicine of the National Academy of Sciences to conclude that for
Medicare recipients the current system is in general not very effective and may have
various unintended consequences [ref.]. The Canadian system has similar roots but
to date has avoided some of the excesses of the American system. This paper traces
the growth and contrasts the system of quality assurance in America and Canada.
152 14 Fact-finding in Epidemiological Practice
In the summary of their essay, those authors wrote that Americas system
[of quality-assurance programs] is pluralistic, administratively very complex (and
expensive!). In contrast, Canadas system is smaller in size, less expensive, and run
by doctors. Both are increasingly preoccupied with bottom line and with linking
quality to cost containment efforts. They pointed out that no one argues [i.e.,
questions] that health care can be improved and that a portion of the expenditure
devoted to health care should be used to evaluate how we are doing, adding that
the costs of the system and the responsibilities of the system must be examined
carefully : : :
In 1992, A survey of medical quality assurance programs in Ontario hospitals
was published by B. Barrable (CMAJ; 146:153-60). It was predicated on this: It
is generally believed that in recent years fewer hospital medical staffs have been
undertaking quality assurance activities. : : : Several reasons have been suggested
for this, including but not limited to the following five:
Confidentiality and fear of liability : : :
A lack of compensation for physicians who involve themselves in quality
assurance activities in addition to their regular clinical workload. : : :
A loss of uniqueness and ownership. : : : [The quality assurance standards of the
Canadian Council of Health Facilities Association, adduced in 1983] were very
prescriptive about how medical staffs should conduct quality assurance. Before
[1983] these activities were referred to as medical audits and were the exclusive
domain of physicians [ref.]
A dearth of expertise in conducting quality assurance activities. : : :
The absence of comprehensive and clear legislation to encourage and, indeed,
mandate practical approaches to medical quality assurance. : : :
The survey questionnaire was sent to The person deemed by the chief executive
officer : : : to be most responsible for medical administration, in All teaching,
community, chronic care, rehabilitation and psychiatric hospitals that were members
of the Ontario Hospital Association as of May 1992. Of the 245 member hospitals,
participants from 179 (73%) responded, indicating a wide variety of quality
assurance activities. Most common was that In-hospital deaths were reviewed in
157 (88%) of the hospitals.
The legislature of Ontario introduced, in 2010, An Act Respecting the Care
Provided by Health Care Organizations (Bill 46), amending or repealing various
previous laws. This law stipulates that Every health care organization shall
establish and maintain a quality committee for the health care organization. This
committee is to monitor the quality of the services and report on this to the respon-
sible body, with reference to appropriate data. It also is to make recommendations
and to ensure that suitable materials on best practices are supplied to the care
providers. Every healthcare organization also is to carry out surveys of consumer
and provider satisfaction (annually and biennially, respectively).
This law, which calls itself the Excellent Care for All Act, 2010, mandates
the quality committee To oversee the preparation of annual quality improvement
plans. These must contain, at a minimum, (a) annual performance improvement
14.5 Quality Assessment of Hospital Care 153
targets; (b) information concerning the manner in and the extent to which health
care organization executive compensation is linked to achievement of those targets;
and (c) anything else provided for in the regulations.
In the city of Ottawa (in Ontario) in 2011, one such plan was published
(as required) by the Montfort Hospital (http://www.hopitalmontfort.com/
QualityImprovementPlan.cfm). The plan is:
to ensure that at least 65% of employees use proper hand hygiene before initial
patient contact by March 31, 2012
By March 31, 2012, achieve a substantial reduction in post-operative infection
rate for abdominal hysterectomies : : :
In collaboration with our partners, reduce the number of days that patients must
wait for an alternate level of care (ALC) from 18% to 16.7%, : : :
Reduce the wait times in the Emergency Department by 10% for patients with
complex conditions and admitted patients : : :
Increase the percentage of patients who would recommend the hospital to their
friends and family from 73.9% to 85% : : :
[Etc.]
To each stated objective is attached the statement of how it will be achieved.
For the Ottawa Hospital, the corresponding QIP (http://www.hopitalottawa.
on.ca/wps/wcm/connect/3870600046545f60a990fd2940f23d1f/QIP short-e.pdf?
MOD=AJPERES) is orientationally described by this Overview:
The Ottawa Hospital (TOH) aims to become a top North American hospital in terms
of quality and safety of patient care. To this end, our Quality Improvement Plan (QIP)
enhances hand hygiene and decreases the rates of hospital acquired infections. It improves
effectiveness by avoiding preventable deaths and unnecessary readmissions, and continues
our record of a balanced budget. It ensures patients are placed in the appropriate care setting
when they no longer need acute care. Those who need care will see reduced wait times
in Emergency. These actions will increase patient satisfaction and the quality and safety
of care.
Monitor adherence to established best practice guidelines for central line infections,
ventilator associated pneumonias, and medication reconciliation at discharge.
Reduce Emergency Room overload through initiatives geared to reducing inpatient
occupancy rates, including improving patient flow and reducing the number and length
of stay of alternate level of care patients.
Using champions and physician leads to promote hand hygiene as well as encouraging
patients to ask staff to wash their hands.
Use innovative ways to assess and improve patient satisfaction.
The foregoing, with its focus on Canadas Ontario province and the nations
capital city Ottawa in it, is instructive of the principal segment of public-health
practice in the modern framework in which clinical medicine is public healthcare
consequent to the advent of national health insurance.
154 14 Fact-finding in Epidemiological Practice
The very first lesson from those facts is this: The Ontarian society, as the third-
party payer of clinical healthcare, wishes to be assured that the societally sponsored
care is of good quality, not only medically but economically as well. An expression
of this is the very name of Ontarios Bill 46: Excellent [sic] Care for All [sic] Act
(cf. above). In the Preamble of that Act, the first one of the nine brief statements
about The people of Ontario and their Government is that they Believe in the
importance of our system of publicly funded health care services and the need to
ensure its future so that all Ontarians, today and tomorrow, can continue to receive
high quality health care.
Next to this belongs the lesson that the Ontarian people and their provincial
government actually do not believe that all Ontarians now have, or in the future will
have, high-quality healthcare: for, the government of the province is now mandating
Quality Improvement [sic] Plans to be periodically developed and published by all
of the provinces hospitals (cf. above).
Third and most important, the provinces government evidently presumes to be
competent to tell the hospitals personnel how the quality of care in them can and
must be improved: it specifies the generic nature, though not the genesis, of those
Quality Improvement Plans it requires.
It deserves note here that just before the Excellent Care for All Act was
introduced, the provinces Ministry of Health and Long-term Care called attention
to opportunities for improvement (http://www.health.gov.on.ca/en/ms/ecfa/pro/
legislation/ecfa presentation 20100503.pdf). In Ontario (population about 13 mil-
lion), it said,
Forty thousand patients were admitted to hospital last year for ambulatory care sensitive
conditions that could have been better managed in the community
Last year, there were 140,000 cases of patients readmitted to hospitals within 30 days of
original discharge
Over 5,000 x-rays and 49,000 electrocardiograms were performed last year for patients
about to undergo cataract surgery, when evidence shows these tests to have no clinical
benefit
Many Ontarians with diabetes and other chronic diseases are still not receiving all care
recommended by clinical guidelines
The scientist [has] neither the moral competence nor the moral right
to use the lecture-room or the learned journal
to pronounce what ought to be done.
Max Weber, 1918
The first two of those here highly-relevant, orientational quotes above we drew from
an indirect source, The Scientific Life: A Moral History of a Late Modern Vocation
(2008) by Steven Shapin. He also cites three notable definitions of vocation right
up-front, none of them consistent with the self-proclaimed mission of the CFTPHC
(below).
As epidemiological research inherently is in the service of the practice of com-
munity medicine, and as this practice epidemiological is community-level
preventive medicine, it is educational for a student of this research to gain
familiarity with the Canadian Task Force on Preventive Health Care. Two sources
of information about it are (refs. 1, 2):
References:
1. http://canadiantaskforce.ca
2. Canadian Task Force on Preventive Health Care. Procedure Manual.
http://www.ualberta.ca/mtonelli/manual.pdf.
Drawing further from reference 1 in Appendix 1 above, there is this piece of news:
November 21, 2011 The Canadian Task Force for Preventive Health Care has released
an updated guideline for breast cancer screening in average risk women aged 4074 : : :
The new guideline, which weighs the potential harms of false positives and unnecessary
biopsies against the potential benefits : : : updates prior guidelines by the Task Force from
1991 and 2001. (Italics ours; cf. App. 1 above.)
And there is also the guideline itself, separately for ages 4049, 5069, and
7074, specifically in respect to mammography (as distinct from MRI and clinical
breast examination). For this intervention the full specification is mammography
(film or digital) every 2 to 3 years. Everything about the guideline is contained on
a single page.
For those three ranges of age the respective Recommendations are: not routinely
screening, routinely screening, and routinely screening. Each of these is
characterized as weak, the first two on the ground of moderate quality evidence,
the third based on low quality evidence. (For the meaning of weak, see App. 1
above.)
The Basis of Recommendation is specified, separately, for each of those three
ranges of age. As an example, all that is said in reference to the age range 7074 is
this:
Women who do not place a high value on a small reduction in breast cancer mortality and
are concerned about false positive results of mammography and overdiagnosis may decline
screening. About 480 women aged 7074 die of breast cancer in Canada each year.
Besides, as for this range of age, For every 1,000 women screened for about
11 years, about 5 women will unnecessarily undergo surgery for breast cancer
(italics ours).
To us it is very unclear what it is that thus is being said and really meant in respect
to Canadian (sic; App. 1) women 7074 years of age (who are without personal
or family history of breast cancer, without known BRCA 1 or 2 mutation, or prior
chest wall radiation). How can the option to decline screening be a basis for
recommendation for screening? How can the annual number (sic) of breast-cancer
deaths within this lustrum of age be a basis for recommendation about screening
within this same, narrow range of age? or is it that at issue actually is initiation of
screening in the early 1970s of age? And when said is that To save one life from
breast cancer over about 11 years in this age group [of 5 years], about 450 women
would need to be screened every 2 to 3 years, is this about periodic screening in
the early 1970s or over about 11 years starting in the early 1970s? And is that
statement about one averted death over about 11 years a statement about the
duration of screening or about the time horizon for the averted death or both?
That statement about every 1,000 women screened for about 11 years presum-
ably is about women in whom the screening is initiated in the early 1970s of age.
Thus it presumably is about screening that could be continued up to age 86 or so.
But: No data from our review addresses the benefits of screening in women : : :
older than 74, implying that at issue actually is screening in the early 1970s only,
for up to 5 years, and not for about 11 years starting at that age.
While the obfuscation in this guideline/recommendation statement is severe to the
point of suggesting, to us, that it is intentional, science writers for newspapers
evidently captured a simple message:
Five days after the publication of these guidelines/recommendations, a national
newspaper of Canada (The Globe and Mail) announced, in a very prominent
headline, that Provinces re-evaluate breast screening. The subheading read:
Health-care providers are taking a fresh look at their rules and the costs of
administering them. The article proper, by Renata DAlesio, was about how those
guidelines from the CPTFHC have sparked a fiery national debate over which
women should receive x-rays and how often.
In that same issue of that paper, another eminent headline read, Cures for
cancer at any cost; and the associated subheading was, The benefits of breast
and prostate screening have been proved exaggerated, but we are no less invested in
them. The author, Margaret Wente, ascribed that exaggeration idea to a statement,
in 2009, by the chief medical officer of the American Cancer Society. Wente said
that The backlash [to the exaggeration idea] was ferocious. : : : The whole drama
was repeated in Canada this week, : : : . The value of mammography screening,
especially for younger women, has been decisively disproven. Many experts say it
is of no value. Period.
One week after these articles, a headline in the same newspaper read, When
emotion prevails over cold, hard science. The subheading was, Exceptionalism
helps explain why mass breast cancer screening persists despite evidence it does
Appendix 2: CTFPHC on Screening for Breast Cancer 163
more harm than good. The author, John Allemang, like his two predecessors
(above), wrote as though he fully understood what the Task Force was saying. So
he presented a very clear chart with the opening predicate: If 2,100 women, 4049,
at average risk of breast cancer were screened every 2 years for 11 years. In it he
presented the consequent numbers of cases of harm, while only 1 woman would
escape a breast-cancer death, all of this pictorially illustrated.
The harms obviously would be incurred in the course of those 11 years, but what
about the deaths that would be averted? By any reasonable presumption, the bulk
of them would have occurred after that 11-year period of screening. Allemang did
not indicate his understanding of what the Task Force meant in this regard, notably
whether its time horizon for deaths was limited to those 11 years of screening; nor
did he comment on his understanding of the relevance of the statistic that About
470 women aged 4049 die of breast cancer in Canada each year, being that
11-year screening initiated at age 49 presumably bears on deaths in the 1970s, even.
He wrote about what he saw as the implications of cold, hard science when the
Task Force itself based its recommendations on moderate quality evidence and
low quality evidence (cf. above).
As we, different from science writers for popular press, have difficulties in
understanding what the Task Force is saying about screening for breast cancer, and
as The particular characteristic that distinguishes the Task Force methodology from
traditional approaches in decision making on prevention issues is that evidence takes
precedence over consensus (App. 1 above), we took a look at the evidence that was
used. This the Task Force specifies in the Canadian Medical Association Journal
2011; 183: 1991-2001.
We found that two of the seven trials used as the sources of evidence enrolled
women in the 7074 range of age. In these, the total number of women of this age
assigned to the screening arm of the trials the CTFPHC reported to be 10,339, but
based on the trial reports themselves we found it to be 10,339 C 296 D 10,635. The
rest of the numbers are to the effect that the CTFPHC focused on the larger one of
those experiences.
In this trials report the duration of screening on women aged 7074 at its
initiation is not given in the original report; but according to the PDQ website of
the NCI (of the U.S.), its duration was 3 years, not about 11 years. The typical
duration of follow-up (from entry into the trial) was 13 years overall but unspecified
for those entering in the early 1970s of age.
The rates of death from breast cancer in the two subcohorts (N1 D 10,339,
N0 D 7,307) evidently were derived, simply, as 49/10,339 and 50/7,307, their
difference being 2.10/1,000, not 2.22/1,000. The number needed to screen, as
defined (App. 1), thus was 1,000/2.10 D 480, not 450, at issue being screening for
three (rather than about 11) years and death from breast cancer within 13 years
(rather than ever). This 480 is but the statistical point estimate from evidence so
imprecise as a matter of quantity rather than quality of the evidence that the
null P-value (one-sided) for the rate difference (and rate ratio) is as large as 0.04,
164 Appendix 2: CTFPHC on Screening for Breast Cancer
and derived from a study in which the Risk of bias, according to the CTFPHC,
was serious even with no regard for the incompleteness of the adherence to the
regimens in the trials two arms.
The Task Force drew the evidence for the three ranges of age solely from seven
randomized trials, evidently believing that these indeed represent the useful segment
of the research, of the entirety of it. At the core of this belief is the idea highly
aberrant that the initial test in screening is an intervention, together with the
associated idea common that an interventions intended effect is to be studied
by means of a randomized trial.
Such is the CTFPHCs reverence of randomization in the continuation of its
tradition of excellence that it seemingly takes no notice of the quality-relevant
particulars of this, while others see a sequence of embarrassments in this regard.
In his cancer-focused The Emperor of All Maladies (2010), Siddhartha Mukher-
jee relates some of the sad stories. In the Health Insurance Plan trial in New York,
the entries into the study cohorts, randomly separated as to intention-to-screen,
were initially without any determination/confirmation of the asymptomatic status,
the women in the control arm of the trial not even knowing of their involvement in
the trial; and later, women who were symptomatic on entry were removed from the
index cohort, but they could not be removed from the reference cohort (p. 297).
Edinburgh was a disaster. : : : [Various irregularities by both the doctors and
the patients] confounded any meaningful interpretation of the study as a whole
(p. 298). And the nature of the randomization completely undid the Canadian trial
(p. 2989).
So here we have gained some insight into the Task Force working with its renewed
commitment and vision to continue its 25-year tradition of excellence in which
a distinguishing characteristic is that evidence takes precedence over consensus
(App. 1). We see that this group makes authoritarian declarations of the form of
knowledge (present or future tense) but with content that in principle is formed
by mere results of studies, even very low quality evidence in this limited
meaning of evidence; and what is much more, those declarations can be grossly
counterfactual about the studies actual results. It is with this pseudo-knowledge
as the principal input that the CTFPHC engages in its main mission: the faux pas
(App. 1) of formulating authoritarian guidelines/recommendations for the practice
of healthcare clinical care.
Evidence per se, especially when misinterpreted (sect. 13.3) and seriously
misrepresented, should not take precedence over consensus-seeking deliberations
among genuine experts on a given topic of the knowledge-base of preventive
healthcare (sect. 13.5) of what is correctly understood to be preventive healthcare
(see below).
Given what the CTFPHC says about its work in a general way (App. 1) and what it
now says about screening for breast cancer specifically (above), and given also what
science writers say about those new recommendations/guidelines (above), some
additional critical comments are in order for the student to weigh and consider
(F. Bacon, sect. 1.4):
Appendix 2: CTFPHC on Screening for Breast Cancer 165
5. While we had great difficulty understanding what the CTFPHC is now saying
about screening for breast cancer and actually found the purportedly evidence-
based statements to be seriously misleading about the evidence, and while the
primary-care doctors receiving its Recommendations on screening for breast
cancer likely are equally uncertain about what is meant, women do understand
what a given round of screening for breast cancer is about: detecting and
treating, at this time, a latent case of breast cancer, should a detectable case
be present at this time this with a view to the thus-enhanced prospects of cure
166 Appendix 2: CTFPHC on Screening for Breast Cancer
of the cancer. The word cure is in the title of Ms Wentes column prompted
by the recent CTFPHC report (cf. above) while no reference to this concern is
made in that report.
6. The following should be agreeable by anyone seriously concerned with the
intended consequences of mammographic screening for breast cancer:
There is to be a definition, for a given round of the screening, of the
diagnostic algorithm in all relevant respects (all the way to the rule-in
diagnosis following biopsy); and this is to be supplemented with definition
of the treatment algorithm following the cancers rule-in diagnosis.
In reference to these regimens, the doctors, rational concern is to know,
specifically for the woman at issue, at the time: (a) the probability that a
single round of application of the defined diagnostic algorithm would result
in rule-in diagnosis of the cancers presence; (b) the probability that the
possibly detected cancer actually would be a life-threatening one; (c) the
probability that the (possibly detected) cancer, if indeed life-threatening,
would be curable by the defined early treatment while being incurable by
any available late treatment; and (d) the time to the death that thus might
be averted (ideally the probability distribution of this time, conditional on
otherwise surviving).
These concerns are in sharp contrast to the CTFPHCs key question:
Does screening with mammography : : : decrease mortality from breast cancer
: : : ?
7. As for the unintended, harmful consequences of such a defined single round of
diagnostics and potential early treatment, the concern is to know, again for the
woman at issue, at the time, the probabilities of: (a) positive result (as defined
by the algorithm) of the initial mammography (nothing false about this so
long as a correct algorithm is correctly followed); (b) biopsy resulting from
the work-up following positive mammography (nothing unnecessary about
this so long as, again, : : : ); and (c) being treated for a cancer that actually is
not life-threatening (cf. part b above, the treatment in these cases, too, being
necessary per the calculated risks accounted for in the protocol).
8. Even if all of this (nos. 6 and 7 above) be known from clinical (sic) research,
unknown from research would remain the valuations that the particular woman
at issue, at the time, associates with the probability of getting an already
extant, latent case of otherwise fatal cancer cured by early treatment and with
the probabilities of harms from the processes involved. All that the womans
realistic doctor can possibly hope to provide is that scientific knowledge input
to the decision. The woman herself brings the valuations and, then, integrates
these two sets of inputs informally into a decision about (the round of) the
screening at the time.
9. If the CTFPHC would understand the nature of the requisite knowledge-base
for rational decisions about mammographic screening for breast cancer, it
would realize that the relevant research remains essentially non-existent. While
it should understand its proper mission to be the formulation of the requisite
Appendix 2: CTFPHC on Screening for Breast Cancer 167
knowledge experts consensus alone (`a la IARC; sect. 13.5), in the prevailing
absence of the requisite knowledge it has a particularly compelling imperative
to refrain from putting forward purportedly research-based recommendations
for practice. And even if the scientific knowledge be there, it should understand
that [Science] knows nothing of policy or utility, of better or worse (App. 1).
10. The CTFPHC, after having studied this Appendix, should also study
Appendix 3 below and then reconsider its renewed commitment and vision to
continue its 25-year tradition of excellence (App. 1).
11. The Public Health Agency of Canada (of which the CTFPHC is part; App. 1)
should be clear on whether it still in this era of national health insurance
upholds its social contract in respect to medicine, continuing to respect the
professions autonomy and limiting its public policies about, for example,
screening for an illness to matters of cost reimbursement and its consequent
concern for cost containment consistent with medically good-quality care
(sect. 14.5).
Appendix 3: Needed Task Forces on Preventive
Healthcare
healthcare. These task forces would not formulate their own consensus opinions
on various topics; they would arrange suitable ad-hoc panels of even more
differentiated, ultimate experts to do this.
One rather obvious example of these task forces would be that focused on
radiation effects on health. It would arrange one expert committee to address the
health implications of the use of mobile phones; another one focusing on the safety
of the body scannings taking place at airports; and a third one on the health hazards
attendant to medical imagings (incl. in screenings for cancers); etc.
The very multifarious topic of nutrition as a determinant of health would
obviously require expertise very different from that having to do with radiation as
a health hazard. In this centrally important area, at least two separate task forces
would be needed, as the issues are so different between macro- and micronutrients.
In the formation of these, and other, task forces, one overarching principle is the
one already insinuated by these examples: they should be differentiated according to
the respective determinants they focus on, with no restriction on the health outcomes
of concern. There thus should not be a task force for preventive cardiology, another
for preventive oncology, etc. And there should not be separate task forces according
to the recipients of the knowledge general practitioners and community-level
educators, for example.
A` la IARC, the product from each expert panel should indeed be knowledge, not
guidelines/recommendations. For, Science never tells a man how he should act;
: : : (App. 1).
Related to all this, wed like to propose, for good measure, one task force
of a very different kind. The various expert panels focusing on their respective
areas of prevention-relevant research would have a shared problem: they would
need to pursue consensus essentially through their intra-panel discourse alone,
given the paucity of public discourse on the evidence per se for one, and on
inference from evidence for another (sect. 13.6). So, a useful purpose would be
served by an undifferentiated, single Task Force on Prevention-oriented Science,
making recommendations on how to improve the journalism environment of this
enormously important segment of health science (cf. sect. 13.6).
Appendix 4: On Introductory Teaching
of Scholars
K.S. Miettinen
An adequate introduction into a scholarly field might prepare the student for further
studies, and perhaps for initial steps in practice; but an excellent introduction is more
ambitious: it establishes the foundations needed for a career, perhaps half a century
in duration, and it specifically plants, at the beginning of that career, those seeds
which may, with suitable experience and reflection, mature into wisdom by the time
of retirement. A sign of an excellent introductory text is that the student repeatedly
returns to it, cherishes it, and continues to deepen his understanding of it throughout
his career. As DAlembert put it, To completely understand the elements [of a
science] requires more than simply knowing what they contain. One must also know
their use, applications and consequences. : : : The distinctive trait of a good book
about elements is leaving much to think about.
In reviewing numerous cherished introductions on my technical bookshelf, a
number of common characteristics stand out: the best introductions motivate the
field, clarify concepts, establish methodology (perhaps abstracted from progression
of method), identify points of divergence from and convergence with related
fields, warn the student about logical and conceptual problems, and recommend
approaches for prudently navigating those problems.
An example of excellent introductory texts is Linus Paulings General Chem-
istry, a text which has stood the test of time (since 1947) and changed how
chemistry is taught, specifically in introductory courses. The text motivates chem-
istry by depicting the universe as being composed of matter and radiant energy;
weaves an exposition of scientific methodology into the sequence of chapters in an
incremental fashion; explains difficult concepts such as temperature with precision;
and identifies points of divergence from and convergence with physics.
The present introduction into epidemiological research has these same qualities,
as it moves from grappling with the essence of the field to the knowledge that has
been achieved; clarifies important concepts such as the study base; and identifies
points of convergence with and divergence from related fields such as statistics and
sociology.
Points of divergence and convergence are often unknown to those who learn
their field after it has reached steady state. For instance, a student searches in vain
through modern introductions into logic for the reason why logic was reformulated
in early twentieth century, or where modern logic diverges from classical logic.
But fortunately, Alfred Tarskis Introduction to Logic and to the Methodology
of Deductive Sciences is still available. Tarski explains the revolution in logic in
terms of establishing the foundations of mathematics (and deductive science more
generally), and throughout the text he points out the corresponding simplifications
(e.g., neglect of the logic of properties a matter of meanings as distinct from
the logic of classes, properties being unnecessary for establishing foundations of
mathematics). Tarski is a case in point of what W. Edwards Deming repetitively
emphasized, that teaching of beginners should be done by a master, not by a hack,
because so much of excellent introductory teaching consists of establishing nuanced
understanding of fundamentals. An implication of masters teaching introductory
courses is that these courses should generally have the highest students-to-teacher
ratios, as beginners are the most common kind of student and masters the least
common kind of teacher.
Tarskis inside knowledge also includes recognition of something that Deming
never pointed out, namely that among masters we should prefer those of that
generation which participated in the most recent revolution in the field.
This introduction into epidemiological research presents the insights of a seminal
participant in the most recent revolution in the field, the theory innovations of the
1970s. In this transition to developing introductory material the senior author fol-
lows in the footsteps of scholars such as Andrei Kolmogorov, who famously toward
the end of his career chose to focus on publishing introductory texts, developing a
new state program of education in mathematics, and teaching introductory courses
to young elite students in the belief that cultivating mastery of fundamentals in
the next generation of mathematicians was the most valuable contribution he could
make.
All fields of scholarly study have logical and conceptual problems; only the
most dogmatic (and least enlightened) teachers would present their field as being
problem-free. For instance, among the conceptual problems in mathematics are
the semantic problem of what particular numbers (such as 3) mean, and the
ontological problem of what infinity is. The solution of this in modern mathematics,
via deployment of the abstract method, is to banish meanings of numbers as
leading to too many fallacies; numbers are defined by the rules they follow without
otherwise having any specific meaning. A good introduction (such as that of
Timothy Gowers) tells the student that for every number A apart from 0 there
is a number C such that AC D 1 is a rule (the rule of multiplicative inverses), and
that this is a rule for which zero is not an exception; it has no exceptions. Since the
rules of arithmetic have no exceptions (else following the rules wouldnt sufficiently
define numbers) and infinity does not conform to the rules of arithmetic, infinity
is not a number. Such are among the first conceptual problems that a student of
mathematics should be introduced to; there are many others.
Appendix 4: On Introductory Teaching of Scholars 173
Logical problems in a science generally are of two kinds: problems within the
field, and problems about the field. In mathematics, for instance, a good introduction
would familiarize the student with Goldbachs conjecture (a simple unproven
apparent truth) and Wiles proof of Fermats last theorem (how can we know it
is a proof?), as well as Skolems paradox (do we understand what a real number
is?). Such problems do not need to be solved for the student to have a successful
career in a field, but understanding their difficulty is effective inoculation against
professional hubris.
Poor introductions, by contrast, misrepresent the field at issue through dangerous
simplifications that may make delivering the content to the student easier, but at
the risk of misleading the student as to truth. For instance, in one introduction
into statistics I read that the objective of statistics is to make an inference about a
population based on information contained in a sample and to provide an associated
measure of goodness for the inference. This is, of course, a simplification that
allows development of a mathematical body of statistical theory, but as a statement
of objectives it is false in general, though perhaps true in special cases (such as
opinion polling).
A better introduction into statistics would warn the student that this simplifica-
tion, which undergirds the theory, is generally false, and that the general objective
is to make inferences based on samples that can be validly applied beyond the
population of which the sample is representative. For instance, the objective of
the Framingham Heart Study surely was not limited to learning about the 1948
population of the town of Framingham. Going as far as is reasonable to validate
inference from past data to future experience (a special form of the problem of
inference to unsampled populations) without dogmatically reifying a metaphysical
state of nature is the topic of Walter Shewharts parvum opus Statistical Method
from the Viewpoint of Quality Control, a cherished introduction that I routinely
reread. (Shewhart also addresses the more ambitious question of what evidence for
the existence of a state of nature would look like; and as both Shewhart and his
most prominent apostle Deming point out, all rigorous attempts to develop evidence
indicating the existence of a state of nature have failed.)
Whereas all scholarly fields have logical problems, a good introduction explains
those problems while demonstrating valid ways to navigate them. For example,
Athanasios Papoulis classic introduction into Probability, Random Variables, and
Stochastic Processes opens with a chapter on the logical difficulties with the very
concept of probability (independence of the axioms and the various definitions),
which leads to demonstration of how comparing the quantum mechanical theories
of Maxwell/Boltzmann, Bose/Einstein, and Fermi/Dirac requires using three defi-
nitions of probability in a three-stage process. The classical (a priori) definition is
used to develop quantum mechanical models, the axiomatic definition is implicit in
the theory of probability with which the models are manipulated, and the relative
frequency definition is used in empirical testing of the model predictions. The
logical problem of developing the theory of probability is exposed to the student
174 Appendix 4: On Introductory Teaching of Scholars
rather than concealed, and prudent handling of the resulting difficulties is then
demonstrated.
The present introduction to epidemiological research gives the student similar
exposure to logical difficulties with what now are held as standard epidemiological
methods (such as cohort and case-control studies), and presents their needed
corrections.
Should any child of mine choose a career in epidemiological or related research
I would look forward to their being taught from this text, by one of the authors or
some other master, with the hope that the youngster would be a fertile receptor and
career-long cultivator of the wisdom sown here.
Appendix 5: Quality Assurance for Modern
Public-health Practice
K.S. Miettinen
what to search for; but the identification of an assignable cause of variation (an
object of repair, retraining, or disciplinary action) is never made on the basis of
the sampled data, it is made only on the basis of a thorough inquiry triggered by
statistical anomalies in the sample data.
There are details of Demings perspective that would lead to augmentations of
the quality assessment program sketched in section 14.5 beyond sampling of the
records by sampling of the processes to produce new data. Some of these may
be worth mentioning. In the text the authors proposed review, by an in-hospital
panel, of narratives of the care of individual patients. This is, no doubt, salutary,
and representative of the activities of development programs in all professions
But the Deming perspective is not to focus on the sequence of processes that a
unit (e.g., a patient) passes through, but rather focus on the sequence of units that
pass through an identifiable process (e.g., colonoscopy). Both perspectives provide
valuable information, but it is the latter perspective that enables the statistical search
for evidence indicating nonrandom variation.
The rates of untoward findings should not be the basis for remedial action
as suggested in the text: Deming often made the point that rates themselves
do not communicate whether a system is operating at capacity. Instead, they
provide raw material which epidemiologists would be well qualified to critically
examine in searching for evidence of performance levels outside of system control
limits. Epidemiologists would provide this service by combining rates of untoward
findings with other facility-specific information, for example on demographics of
the served population, caseload during the period in question, experience level of
staff, etc., to assess whether an observed rate of untoward findings deviates enough
from experience across other facilities to warrant an inquiry into the existence of
assignable causes of variation at that facility.
These details of a program of quality improvement can be worked out once hos-
pital administrators become acquainted with and adopt the conceptual framework of
continuous improvement. There will, however, be institutional obstacles to adopting
this framework, which need to be thought through. Demings industrial quality
improvement philosophy requires close collaboration among the parties involved
in ways that differ from models of confidentiality and proprietary information
currently fashionable in medicine. In manufacturing-related industrial settings, part
of the means to avoid expensive inspections of purchased goods (e.g., parts pur-
chased from a supplier for further assembly) is the requirement that vendors provide
evidence of quality control of their processes along with their deliveries, so that
purchasers can confirm that a lot of goods was produced under suitably controlled
circumstances; the goods themselves are not inspected; instead, information about
the vendors internal processes is disclosed along with the delivery. In a hospital
setting, the analogue would be providing to those concerned, patients included, a
report on the degree of uniformity achieved in the processes relevant to the quality
of the provided care.
Even though medical institutions are supposed to be self-policing, it is not
enough to supply quality-assessment reports to the hospitals quality-assurance
boards and government regulators, for these entities are not interested in the quality
178 Appendix 5: Quality Assurance for Modern Public-health Practice
in the classical sense of the term. They do not have a stake in the quality of care,
as they do not suffer the consequences of poor-quality care. While the persons in
those functions may well have the best interests of patients and society at heart,
management practices are generally anchored to the interests associated with the
positions involved, rather than to presumptive virtues of the people assigned to those
positions. Society at large, and patients in particular, have a stake in the quality of
healthcare, so they are the genuinely interested parties to whom evidence of internal
quality control should ultimately be disclosed.
Administrators and regulators have a two-tiered responsibility in quality control:
first, to drive the continuous pursuit of quality within systems operating as designed,
and second, to rationally redesign systems operating at the limits of their capacity
for better performance. It is with respect to the first of these two that assurance of
performance should be provided to patients and to society at large, and it deserves
note that this is not information of a professionally esoteric kind; information
about the state of control of internal processes is largely non-technical and thereby
comprehensible to the general public. This information does not tell patients
whether their specific care will be (or was) good or not, but it can assure them
that the systems that care for them are operating at capacity, that is, that the
care being provided is statistically as good as can be reasonably expected of the
system. On the other hand, information supporting redesign of workflows should be
shared within competent professional communities, notably among administrators
of similar facilities across the jurisdiction involved.
The application to medicine of the quality control methods of industry at large
is complicated by the fact that medicine is a service industry (not unlike, e.g.,
the hospitality industry). Even though the methods pioneered in manufacturing
have been successfully applied in service industries as well, banking and hotels
being outstanding examples, many problems specific to service industry have been
identified in these applications.
One of the most difficult problems in service industries in general is that
enterprises tend to serve captive audiences; there is little pressure from distant
competitors, and therefore considerable difficulty in motivating the necessary
constancy of purpose necessary for continuous improvement. In line with this, there
are rarely two general hospitals operating across the street from one another, and
hospitals at a distance are only slightly in competition with one another.
Another problem of service industries is that they do not face elastic market
demand; a service enterprise cannot expand the overall volume of business in its
segment (e.g., by productivity breakthroughs that lower costs); it can at best take
market share from competitors. Thus, a hospital that lowers the cost of delivering
babies may take business away from other hospitals, but it is unlikely to affect the
overall number of births in a given population. Improvements in the cost of child
birth are not rewarded with a baby boom.
In service industries there is a tendency to sample users of the of service
regarding their satisfaction, while really needed for quality control is sampling of
the processes that go into providing service. Just as quality control in manufacturing
cannot be based on examining finished products, so also quality control in medicine
Appendix 5: Quality Assurance for Modern Public-health Practice 179
A E
Allemang, J., 163 Einstein, A., 173
Armstrong, B., 19
Atwood, K.C., 128
F
Ferguson, N., 2, 3, 9
B Fermi, E., 173
Bacon, F., 13, 27, 125, 164 Feynman, R., 17
Barrable, B., 152 Fletcher, S.W., 30, 31
Beresford, S.A.A., 76 Fortin, P., 151
Berkman, L., 26, 27 Franklin, B., 2
Berlin, I., 134
Bismarck, O., 23, 24
Blackburn, H., 32 G
Bohr, N., viii Gibran, K., 13
Boltzmann, L.E., 173 Goldbach, C., 173
Bose, S.N., 173 Gorbachev, M., 10
Boyle, R., 13, 124 Gowers, T., 172
Bronowski, J., 17, 22 Graham, E., 33
Greenland, S., 7, 39
C H
Caballero, B., 29 Hansheer, R., 134
Cochran, W.G., 137 Hardy, H., 134
Cohen, B., 2 Harris, R., 30, 31
Cooper, T., 23 Hayes, R.B., 76
He, F.J., 24
Herlihy, D., 2
D Hill, A.B., 137139, 142
DAlembert, J., 171 Hippocrates, 6, 47
DAlesio, R., 162 Hofman, A., vi, ix
Deming, W.E., 156, 172, 173, Hume, D., 47
175177
Demissie, K., 80, 82, 83
Deutsch, D., 9 I
Dirac, P.A.M., 173 Ibrahim, M., 25, 26
Doll, R., 18, 19 Ipsen, J., 7
W
O Wald, A., 60
Ockham, W., 47 Warren, J.R., 128, 129
Olsen, J., viii Weber, M., 157
Wennberg, J., 108, 156
Wente, M., 162, 166
P Wynder, E., 33
Papoulis, A., 173
Pasteur, L., 2, 6
Pauling, L., 171 Y
Peto, R., 18 Yoshizawa, K., 76
Subject Index
O Rate ratio
Obesity, 2224, 25, 2930, 126, 127 Adjusted r. r., 50, 59
Occupational health, 4, 68, 69 Crude r. r., 48, 49
Occurrence relation, 8, 9, 51, 52, 54, 5659, Standardized r. r., 4952
61, 99, 100 Recommendations, 138, 142, 158, 161
Omega-3 fatty acids, 17, 18 Research
Oncogenesis. See Cancer Basic r., 5
Oncology, 5, 6, 8, 9 Epidemiological r., 5
Ottawa Public Health, 3, 4, 148150 Oncological r., 5, 8
Overmatching, 66 Risk
R. assessment, 109, 110
Relative r., 28, 134
P R. factor, 4, 38, 44
Paradigm, 124129 R. function, 102, 110
Parameter of Nature, 52 R. indicator, 110
Parsimony, 47 R. period, 109, 110
Person-moment, 5658, 99 R. profile, 109
Placebo, 89, 101 R. ratio, 125
Policy, 44, 45, 114, 115, 126, 136, 142, 158
Population
Catchment p., 56, 67, 71 S
Closed p., 56, 63 Salt, 24
Cohort-type p., 56, 64, 65 Sampling (for base series)
Dynamic p., 56, 57, 64, 65 Discriminate/stratified s., 71, 92, 141
Open p., 56, 64 Indiscriminate/unstratified s., 71, 91, 141
Source p., 56, 57, 64, 65, 68, 69, 71 Matched s., 94, 141
Study p., 56, 57, 64, 65, 67, 68, 71 S. by extraneous outcomes, 91
Precision, 5961, 93, 95 Science
Prevention/preventive, 25, 7, 16, 19, 20, 22, Applied s., 5
2427, 29, 30, 3740, 76, 78, 98, 105, Basic s., 5
108110, 114, 118, 126, 136, 138, 140, Epidemiology as s., 2, 5
148, 157159, 163165, 169170 Normal s., 124, 143
Preventive Medicine Task Force. See Task Paradigms in s., 124
Force Philosophy of s., 124
Public health, 3, 4, 148, 150, 151, 153, 156, Public discourse in s., 143
175180 S. writers, 162
Screening, 25, 80, 114122, 158, 161
Series
Q Base s., 5761, 6371, 75, 88, 89, 99, 101,
Quality assurance/control, 148, 150152, 120
154156, 175180 Case s., 47, 5760, 6468
Smallpox, 2, 5
Smoking, 32, 45, 65, 136
R Smoking and Health, 32, 136138
Rate Source base, 56
Adjusted r., 38, 50, 51 Statistical methods, 85
Crude r., 4852 Statistical variate, 52
Index r., 48 Statistics, 12, 171
Overall r., 48, 49 Study
R. as emergent phenomenon, 8 Case-control s., 57, 65
Reference r., 48 Cohort s., 63
R. ratio, 48, 49 Cross-sectional s., 67
Specific r., 49 Derivative s., 132
Standardized r., 49 Etiogenetic/etiologic s., 47, 51, 5660
186 Subject Index
T V
Task force Vaccination, 2, 108
Canadian TF on Preventive Health Care, Validity. See also Bias
142, 157, 161 V. assurance, 91, 122
Needed TFs, 169 Variola. See Smallpox
Preventive Medicine TF, 31, 142
Teaching
Introductory t., 10, 171174 W
Temporal relation, 75, 77, 100, 101, 137 Wald statistic, 60
The Epidemiologic method, 7, 137 World Cancer Research Fund, 19
Theory of research, 9, 10, 74, 144 World Health Organization, 2, 136, 169