Heidel 1909 - The ἄναρμοι ὄγκοι of Heraclides and Asclepiades
Heidel 1909 - The ἄναρμοι ὄγκοι of Heraclides and Asclepiades
OF THE
By PROFESSOR W. A. IIEIDEL
WESLEYAN UNIVERSITY
This content downloaded from 132.187.253.29 on Tue, 21 Mar 2017 10:55:29 UTC
All use subject to http://about.jstor.org/terms
6 UK A. Heidel [Igog
1 See Paul Tanniery, " Ecphante dle Syracuse," Archzivffiir Ceschz. der fT
phie, xi (1898), 263-269. Ml. 'T'annery was apparently not aware that the same
conjecture had been made two years earlier by Otto Voss, de Heraclidis Pont/ici
Vita et Scrip/is, Rostock, I896, p. 64. According to Voss, Ilicetas also is to be
regar(ded in the same light as Ecphnantus; but by parity of reasoning Philolaus
might be claimed as belonging to the same class, since the two points of (loctrine
attributed to Hicetas are also ascribed to Philolaus. It is best to dissociate the
personalities. So far as concerns Ilicetas, he should be considered rather with
referenice to the great interest in EJp- uara in Alexandrine tinmes. On this see
Brusskern, de lmerz-im Izve/ztazruv .Scr4p/oribus Graecis, Bolnn, 1864.
2 The forged writings of Ocellus and Timaeus are a part of the same campaign
to claim everything for the Pythagoreans. Probably neither was a real character;
the latter, however, was helped to a seemingly historical existence by Aristotle's
occasional metho(d of quoting the Timzaeais of Plato; e.g. de Animiza 4o6b 2 6 o T-
/0atos upvooXo/yeL 7r9v 1JX'Vv KLVELV r- o-Cosa (cp. Plato, Tim. 34 A, 36 C), and
de Senssu 437b 15 Wo7rep o TI',uawOs Xi,yes (cp. Timii. 45 D). This suggests how
Ecphantus and possibly I-licetas might come, in the course of uncritical excerpt-
ing, to he regar(led as historical persons.
3 Hippol. Refut. I, 15 (Diels, Dox., 566, II) E?oj1 m1 eivrxL evaaViqOtvv 'rCv 6VTWV
Xca3eZv -yvGo-tv, 6pt{etv U cW'm vo.iuetv (giving the text of Diels, Vor-sokr.2, 265, 29 ff.
Sextus Empir., adv. ath. VII, 201 6r7t -y&p -yivovr6 7Ltves r7 TOL07-0 a Lo)vTres,
rpo0mrrov 7re7roiWrKev TAvrioAos 6 ar 3 Ts aAKam7)sLaS, Pv 3eurip' TLOV KaVOVLKLV P177T
-ypdm'as raiira "&XXos / 7TLS, 'v eVTaTPLKV vA oi6ev6s 3e6repos, wr7o6gevos U KaI
)XocTorcas, e/7f110670 T's iL v a'a-0751ets 6VT1s KaCl iX?70bs Cv-TLtprets eEivatL X6Aymp
P7UV 6XCtwS mjas KacTaXaold3vetv." eOLKe Cyp - L1 Ko ttv 6 Av Lo'os... 'OKX?prLa
677v T6v t'aTrp6v atcVITTe00at, advatpouvTa cAev rT6 7)yUOVLK/V, Karr 'a T6v a6r6v %p6vo7
avTz -yev6pgevov.
This content downloaded from 132.187.253.29 on Tue, 21 Mar 2017 10:55:29 UTC
All use subject to http://about.jstor.org/terms
Vol. xl] The c'iap'uo t 7ol of Heraclides and Asciepiades 7
1 For Ecphantus, see Aetius, I, 3, 19 (Dox. 286b 7). For Asclepiades, see
Sextus Empir., adv. Alaht. VIII, 220 ATKX-qrtd5 e U 'Ws elvorcidews vPoqr6.v PyK6 v e'v
vo'qroZs capaLdjoaLtv and ib. PI, 5 vo'q rtves ev 7epuZv 7r6pot. The 7r6pot are defi-
nitely stated to be void by Galen, de Usu Par/ium Vri, 13 (III, 470 K.) clv o,uov
OVT el7lvCLWTKev 'ACTKX-7rtdar')s oUT, e6'wrep EVypw, 5vvacr6v lv ci a-rv ras airTas l'eupeZv
LS 6&YKOVS Kal Kevo'P aVad/oVpTt T7oV -yyvo/gvCwv a'raVrwV ras adpXcas; de Siip/ic.
Medic. A. 14 (XI, 405 K.) e7rtTK67rTeoTOat U, 'Ws efpqrats, ,r L6vov et 7waxvgepis
e-TTLt ) Xerro,uepi)s ' rCoV eteraco,dvwv /xapjAdLaKPv o,Ta, a,X' et KaC acpata Kat
7rVKVP. XVyw 57) aLpatapJ is 7a g6pta &LaXa/.pdverat XwpatS KevaZs, erto-ra/dvcpv
7i3V 5&qXov6,rt Kal Me.V?7Fd-V(pV T7)V o'LTav, 67Tt ,U7) KaOdirep 'EvLKo06p Kal A*,kKX?-q
7rtal 5OKe6, dXX7 'TTLP aepos 7rXhp-qs ep &7rao- ToLs LpaLoLs T/a.Tpv ?7 KEVP Xwpa.
2 Cp. Sextus Empir., adv. Alath. VII, 202. Is the treatise there mentioned the
`E/.7reLpLKa (or 'IarpLKa, cp. I, 202) vbro,utv?pjara referred to adv. Math. I, 6i ? Cp.
Galen, de Usu Par/ium, v, 5. His treatise, like that of Sextus, is no longer
extant.
3 Like the In/roduc/io and the Historia Philosophica.
4 See above, n. I, and below, p. 8, n. 2.
5 They are called dvappua o-cuara, de Usu Partium, XVII, I (IV, 350 K.); cp.
de Differ. Morbor. (vi, 839 K.) 0VK OiP lV IITTL 7b TLOV wwv -wga, KaOa7rep j
,rouos ' 'E7rLKo6peLoS X 7-iV dvdpuwp Ti T7V 'ACTKX?7prtdov. In de Usu Par/ium,
Xi, 8 (III, 873 K.) we meet 7a?s T' `E7rwKOvP1ons dr6/ioLS Kal 7oZs 'Ao-KX72rLa5eots
9'yKOLS. See below, p. 8, n. 2.
6 lb.
This content downloaded from 132.187.253.29 on Tue, 21 Mar 2017 10:55:29 UTC
All use subject to http://about.jstor.org/terms
8 1X. A. Heidel [1909
This content downloaded from 132.187.253.29 on Tue, 21 Mar 2017 10:55:29 UTC
All use subject to http://about.jstor.org/terms
Vol. xl] Tfz/ adVap/zot 6'ycot of Heraclides and Asclepiades 9
This content downloaded from 132.187.253.29 on Tue, 21 Mar 2017 10:55:29 UTC
All use subject to http://about.jstor.org/terms
10 W A. Heidel [1909
310 ff., though it greatly complicates the problem. I am inclined, with Diels, to
regard many of the differences between Iypot. III, 30-32 and adv. A1a/h. IX, 359
as duie to the additions of Sextus; but the division of the latter table into two
groups and the omission of Strato (or rather, perhaps, the addition of Strato to
the former table) are intimately connected. But, if that be so, can we attribute
this change to Sextus? See below, n. 4. Tlhe analytical table, acdv. Math. x,
310 ff., is probably the work of Sextus. The error in regard to Heraclides and
Asclepiades, noted below, can hardly be supposed to date from an earlier period.
1 Adv. Mat/-. IX, 359 ff-
2 Hypot. 1II, 30-32. Diels has Nv'ell shown how closely parallel this table runs
to [Galen] /is/or. P/zi/os. c. i8 and [Clement] Reecogn. viii, 15, and has traced
it to a Stoic source, which he dates between Seneca and the Antonines. Perhaps
the way in which Sextus alludes to the L7ro-Ls OX-q of the Stoics (Hypot. III, 31;
cp. adv. Mat/u. X, 312) tends to confirm his conclusion. I may add here that the
failure to distinguish in this table (as in the first) between corporeal and incor-
poreal elements may have been in part responsible for the attribution of 'ideas'
to Democritus in Pseu(do-Clement (see Diels, Dox., 251); for in our first table
Plato's i3EaL are mentioned (though omitted in the second), and in Pseudo-
Clement Plato appears only as postulating the four elements: "ignem, aquam,
aerem, terrain."
3 On these see Diels, Dox., 249 ff.
4 See above, n. 2, for Democritus and his "ideas." Here we may note
that the "limits of bodies," regarded as the elements of the ca0?7,ua7TLKO0 -
are omitte(l l)y Pseudo-Clement -naturally suggested something corporeal. The
numbers of the Pythagoreans were, I think, unquestionably corporeal, and so
Aristotle regarded them. See my article " Hepcas and A7reLpov in the Pythagorean
Philosophy," Archiv fur Gesch. der Philos., XIV (1901), 384-399, and Burnet,
Early Greek P'hilosophy,2 337 ff. Burnet, whose latest statement is much in-
This content downloaded from 132.187.253.29 on Tue, 21 Mar 2017 10:55:29 UTC
All use subject to http://about.jstor.org/terms
Vol. xl] The " 'vaprot &yicot of Heraclides and Asclepiades II
debted to my article, makes it seem probable that the Pythagoreans called their
solid units 6YKOL. But this fact had quite dropped out of the consciousness of
these late epitomists. If, therefore, as seems probable, they invented the doc-
trine of Ecphantus, it was due to some such cause as the uncritical grouping of
distantly related doctrines. It was a case of the night in which all objects look
black. In Pseudo-Clement, Strato (for so we should doubtless read, with Diels,
for Cal/istratus), with his "qualitates," follows immediately after Pythagoras, as
Strato supplanted Plato in the second table of Sextus. Plato's Ideas were felt to
be sadly out of place in this company. That this change was due to Sextus, is
not altogether probable; as we have seen, Plato is in the list of Pseudlo-Clement,
though there is no mention of his Ideas, unless we loolk for them in the ' Ideas'
attributed to Democritus.
1 Adv. Math. X, 310 ff. Probably, though not certainly, this table owes its
origin to Sextus himself, who elsewhere also shows acquaintance with less familiar
accounts of philosophical doctrines, such as occur repeatedly in tables 3 and i.
In general the agreement is most palpable between tables 3 and 2. T his makes
all the more striking the contradiction in regard to Asclepiades.
2 H)pof. III, 33 oV -yap 317rov 3vvU0o16/e0a KaL TOLs 7repI 'AOKX?pz-q7LciV OVyKarTa-
TrO-Oa Opavo,aT& CIpaL Ta o& ToLXeCa XgXyovOt KaL roLd, KaL -rots repl A-)u6KpLTov,
dTo/ua T7LvTa elvat q/XO-KOVOt KaL L7rota, KaIt- TOCS 7lrepL 'Avataay6pav, 7-rto-av alo-0-1-rTv
7rOt6T?6Tarr repl TraLs o'goto/uepelats a7roXel7roVo-Lv. For Anaxagoras, see above, p. 8,
n. 3 and p. 9, n. i. While Sextus is clearly somewhat uncertaini in his mind as to
the relation of Asclepiades and Anaxagoras, - if he had been sure of his facts he
would hardly have treated the doctrines of the four men as quite distinct, - he
makes it evident enough that Heraclides and Asclepiades, like Anaxagoras,
regarded the 6-yKOt as qualitatively determined. That the qualities, or avva3U
were indefeasible was shown above, p. 8, n. 3 and p. 9, n. i. We shall presently
find this same doctrine attributed to Ecphantus.
This content downloaded from 132.187.253.29 on Tue, 21 Mar 2017 10:55:29 UTC
All use subject to http://about.jstor.org/terms
I 2 W. A. Ileidel [I 909
1Adv. Math. X, 318 e' d7repwpv 3' 136oaoav T-' J TW'v rpayuaTowv ye'VEtp o0L
wep 'Avatay6pav T6V KXatovtovoP Ka w6KpLroP Ka' 'E7rKoupo' KL lXxot ra-
1rXz?eOs, a\\XX' o ue.v 'Avata-y6pas et 6/LoIwv TOLs -yeppvwg/OLL, ol R rep' TOp A?71AOLKpL-
TOV Kal 'ErIKoUpov et aLVOLooWV TE KKl adraOCvv, Tro)Tv(Tt TWV dr6Awp, ol 6R rep -rTV
RTovrK6V JHpaKX613qV Kart 'ATKrX?7rtcai)v t~ avo/loi'wv gPv 7ra0LqTWV se', Kacacrep -rCv
avdp,uwv py6KWP. One might be temptedl to suspect an error in the text; but the
carefully wrought analysis quite excludes that possibility. If, as I believe is
manifest, there is an error here, it must be charged to Sextus and not to a copy-
ist. I shall try presently to explain his error.
Comparison with the case of Galen (see above, p. 8, n. 2) suggests that Sextus
was troubled by the knotty problem of aLoXwoLSts. He was clear that the Monists,
who postulated a single, qualitatively determinate substance, e.g. water, implied
aXXolwo-Ls in the clevelopnielt of other things out of their apXy'7 (cp. adv. Ala/h.
X, 328). Aristotle had inisisted on this. But the means of effecting dXolrwas
(according to Aristotle) used by the Atomists were not so clear: indeed, w as the
birth of quality out of the 'ahrotop a clear case of arXXowcorts at all ? In regard to
Anaxagoras (and Heraclides and Asclepiades also, apparenitly) the case was
further complicated by the conception of T7rLKpTreLa, according to which certain
qualities predominating in the g-tyAa 'overpowered' others. Was there, or was
there not, acXXowo-Ls here ? Aristotle did not kniow, though he was fain to think
there was: was not the 7rdLTa 6AoO of Anaxagoras a ev ? The elusive concept of
adXXoowo-s, utterly foreign to the pre-Socratics, and disallowed by many in later
times, wrought sad havoc in the history of Greek thought as recounted by the
doxographers. On all this see my " Qualitative Change in Pre-Socratic Philoso-
phy," in Archzivfiar Gesch. der Phi/os. XIX (I906), 333-379.
This content downloaded from 132.187.253.29 on Tue, 21 Mar 2017 10:55:29 UTC
All use subject to http://about.jstor.org/terms
Vol. xl] The dvap,ot 'yKcot of Heraclides and Asciepiades I 3
1Adv. A/a/li. III, 5 o1)TC -yovv TpUTiJi vbroo&6eT KeXp'o-OaT oag/ev Tiv 'AOKX
irtdi7nv ELS KacLTaOKeIV7V T'S ThP 7VrpeT67o e7OL0I7qS eVPLTT7edOWS, gUt,a 1sP 67JTL P01
TtpVs eto Lt ep7/LV 7rhpOL, /LEy4poneLLet /a4oTpopres dXjXXXv, lev)TLpL Rh 67t 7rdVToO
VLypOu /Lhp'qKacL 7Ve6/aTos eK X6yy Oewp opqTiiV 6YK&JV POUV'VpdpVoLTaT V atwpos dv
/u'TCrV, TplTrJ U 6'rt d3atdXeorToi rtpes et's rO &KT6s et 'gCv dVrobopai yivovTat, r
,uev 7rXeiovs 7rowr U eXLdTTovs 7rpos Tr17V eveOT'7KVtav 7replTaTaLoV. Cp. adv. A/
VIII, 220, and Susemihl, op. cit. II, 433, n. 84, and 436, n. IOI.
2 Apud Euseb. P.E. XIV, 23 db-61ovs U evcaLi Oaotpv dcsO6repot (Epicurus and
Democritus) Kal XVyeoOat 3ta -'qv &Xvro oTrepp6-TrqLa. ol U Ta's dr61sovs /eTopo-
daLavTres dgepl oacortv evLat w'uararoaT r TOO 7ravrTos u Lp-q e i~v c nd3tatp& Pv 6VT&pV (vVT-
Oerat -ar 7rdvra Kal ets d &aLXeTaL. Kal TO6-rwpV baoi TWrV acgep63v 6vo/aTo7rotLv
AL63opov (i.e. D. Cronus) -ye-yovpva. 6vo/sa L, bao-tv, aVrTo7s &XXo 'HpaKXe6i?7s
OL,LEPOS eKdXeXoeV 6-yKovs, 7rap ov Kacl AOKX?77rtd3i7s o ILTp6S eLKX1pov6n7o-e Tr6 6vo/a.
Dionysius is engaged in an attack on Epicurus for religious reasons ; Asclepia-
des and Diodorus Cronus fall equally under the ban, more or less on general
principles.
3 This name recurs in the table of [Galen] His/or. Philos. IS.
4 The list of Pseudo-Clement preserves the name 6-yKOL, but not the qualifying
adjective. [Galen] In/rod. XIV. 250 K. KaT& U 'AO KX 77rLd'r7v o-ToteZca dvOpdnrov
This content downloaded from 132.187.253.29 on Tue, 21 Mar 2017 10:55:29 UTC
All use subject to http://about.jstor.org/terms
I4 W. A. Heidel [I9o9
6'YKOL OpaVuO70 Kai r6pot. Aeius 1, I3, 4 (Diels, Dox. 312b io) 'HpaKXe6o1s OpacL-
a0aaTe. The expression Opa6o-gara is used also of Empedcocles, Aet. I, I3. I (Dox.
312,3); that the-se fragments are called 0IIOLOIuEPiI (ib.) is essentially true (see
above, p. 9, n. I), thouglh the expression is transferred from the Aristotelian termi-
nology applied to Anaxagoras. There can be no doubt that in the expression 7rpb
TWV orTotXetwv there is a suggestion of the view that the Opa6o-uara of Empedo-
cles were analogous to the &rotos IX- of the Stoics, out of which the o.rotxeta
grew by taking on qualities (aMoXoutcus ?). I have elsewhere shown that Aristotle
was tempted to impute this doctrine to Empedocles and Anaxagoras, because he
rashly assumed the fv of the uoa?pos and the raivra 1oiov to be also bootov. See
next note, where a sort of d7rotos V'X7 is imputed to Asclepiades. The 4bry}UaTa
or 4,7Wy/Ltcira attributed (ib.) to Heraclitus are of the same character; they refer
to the fiouents and efuents of the Heraclitic 'o', typified by civauv4ao-ts. All
these 68KOL were of course Opavur-roi, whether the philosophers felt called upon to
state the fact or not. It was the Eleatic dialectic which made it necessary to affirm
expressly or to deny the possibility of a Touj e's dretpov.
1 De ilorb. Acut. I, 14 Primordia namque corporis primo constituerat (sc.
Asclepiades) atomos, corpuscula intellectu sensa, sine ulla qualitate solita atque
ex initio comitata, aeternum se movenitia, quae suo incursu offensa, mutuis ictibus
in infinita partium fragmlenta solvantur magnitudine atque schemate (lifferenitia,
quae rursum eunaz'o sibi adiecta ve/ cozziuzcta omnzia faciunt sentsibi/ia, vinm in
semet mutationzis hlabenttia aut per meagnitud(iinem ant per muzDlitudiinem aut per
schema aiut per ordinemi. Nec, inquit, ratione carere videtur, quod nuilius faci-
ant qua/ita/ts corpora. A/iu(l enjiniz Partes, a/jud universi/atein sequitur;
argentum denique a/blum est, sed eius affrica/io nigr-a . caprinumz cornzu nigru;ni,
sed eius a/ba serrago. . . . Fieri autem vias complexione corpusculorum intel-
lectu sensas, magnitudine et schemate differentes, per quas succorum ductus solito
meatu percurrens, si nullo fuerit impedimento retentus, sanitas maneat, impeditus
vero statione corpusculorum morbos efficiat. The parts italicized deserve a word.
The clauses ' quae . . . sensibilia' and ' quod . . . corpora' imply that when the
6yKOL are shivered they lose all qualitative determination, which they acquire in
turn by a sort of avvepavPwO6ss; but we kniow that such was not the belief of
Asclepiades, whose a r/baTa were Opavafra KaL Wrota (Sextus Empir. Hypot. III, 33).
This applies not merely to the larger 6fyKOL, but also to the Opa6o/sar-a. Indeed
this is stated in the clause ' Aliud enim partes, aliud universitatem sequitur,'
and is implied in the illustrations of silver and horn. Similar cases were dis-
cussed by Anaxagoras (see Zeller, I, 987, n. I), and doubtless the same explana-
tion was given; to wit, that every larger 6-YKOS or mass is a )UysYa and has i
quality determined by the predominant ingredient, an(l that in certain cases
(compare the blackness of water and the whiteness of snow in Anaxagoras'
illustration) the large mass showed a marked difference in (apparent) quality
This content downloaded from 132.187.253.29 on Tue, 21 Mar 2017 10:55:29 UTC
All use subject to http://about.jstor.org/terms
Vol. xl] Tze 'vap" ot 6'y1cot of Heraclides and Asclepiades I5
This content downloaded from 132.187.253.29 on Tue, 21 Mar 2017 10:55:29 UTC
All use subject to http://about.jstor.org/terms
I6 WW A. Heidel LI909
doctrine of Asclepiades: ' And all these (referring to the awdcraTa or 6yKoL) are
things possessed of specific (i16as. Should we perhaps here have the misplaced
dt&ovs ?) qualities (the text has Irt3oX&s, ' perceptions,' the subjective correlate
of qualities: cp. the ' sensibilia ' of Caelius) and differences (again the subjective
correlate, ' distinctions,' &taX'VfLs), the congeries following (i.e. being qual
tively like the specific differences and qualities of the 6YKOL) and not divorcing
itself from them (it may be fanciful, but I am renminded of Anaxagoras, fr. 8
d7roJCKor7-at 7reXKeL) but taking its predicate in accordlance with the total com-
plexion (again the subjective correlate, 'conception,' e'vvoLav) of the body."]-
The last sentence reminds one of Anaxagoras, who held 6,rou 7rXeo-rov 9Kao7-ov
eXeT, roJ aoKeTV ellvat r'1v 4/6tv roi wrpdiyfgaros. Cp. Arist. Phys. A. 4, 187b 2-7
1A&tius i, 13, 2 (Diels, Dox. 312). Stobaeus here has 'HpacKXeuros 7rp6 roO
eEV6s 0oKet rtt 4&fryfsara KaTaXeretLv; Ps. Plutarch has 'H. -y a'crL4f
X-aXfTra Kai a)uep'z et'Oa&yet. Diels, ad loc., suggests that PXdXftora Kac al/Lp
added here by mistake, transferred from the next section devoted to Xenocrates
and Diodorus Cronus; but this is specious rather than probable. The doctrine
there attributed to Xenocrates is probably false, and a somewhat similar case
occurs in 1, 14, 3 and 4, where (even if, with Diels, we interchange the names
' Leucippus' and 'Anaxagoras') the assimilation of the O'soLopoepiI to the &roA
both being pronounce(d roXvoX'4pova, is evident and misleading, to say the lea
To Leucippus, differences of oXX,ua were ultimate; to Anaxagoras, they must
have been almost unmeaning. Other cases occur, which I forbear to mention.
For the 4&frqyfara rp6 roO evos (an 67rotos vXr7 ?), see p. I3, n. 4.
2 Phizlosoph. A, I5 (Diels, Dox. 566), EKqbavr6s rts 2;vpaKO6OLOS e/o4 ,)-A
acXrqtPv'iv mXV 6vmcov XaJe3v -yv(iotv, opi?etv U c's voIp1etv. mai pIAv rp&ra d&ta
eivaL ottf1aaa Kat 7rapaXXwayas av6mcv rpeFs v'rdpXetv, I.4tye0os oXu/,a 5dvaf.Lv,
mra aiOrmai -ylve-Oat. 'Pvat i m6 T rX\tos avOmdv C ptot0/tVOP KaL TOlimO 6tmretpov (p
ably, with Duncker, we should read diptfuLvcv&Jv Katam TOmro, d7retpov). KLVfrLOOat U
Ta att6IaTa Il'iTe i'r6 3dpovS IL,Te 7rX-oy's, a\'X v'ro' Oteas oUPaveWS, Pv PoOP Kai
This content downloaded from 132.187.253.29 on Tue, 21 Mar 2017 10:55:29 UTC
All use subject to http://about.jstor.org/terms
Vol. xll The avapuot O"y/coL of Herac/ides and Asciepiades I7
4'vx'r rrpooa'yope6et. ro6-rov IAYv oi5 rbP K60/.OV edvpaL i6av, 3 6 Kai oroatpoet86
irb OIcas 8vldV4[ews ye'yovivat. Tr'P U 'y?)P /.4oP K6070U KLVEcTcOa irep rTo abris
K&rTpOp US rpos acpaToX\p. Cp. Aetius, III, 12, 3 (Diels, Dox. 378). This con-
stitutes the sum of our record regarding Ecphantus excepting the report of his
atomic monads to be considered later. In the passage quoted above note that
the ad?aipeTa ocwLcara .possess &ipal.Uts or quality. This use of 3tva,.ts is probably
derived from medicine (cp. Hippocrates, above, p. 8, n. 2), where properties appear
definitely as functional. That the -d64gara are said to differ in size and shape,
need not detain us; the statement is doubtless true, but (as in the case of
Anaxagoras, see preceding note) lacks significance, except as an indication of the
assimilation of corpuscular doctrines to Atomism, where these distinctions were
fundamental because they served to explain the resultant differences in quality.
1 Zeller, op. cit. J, 495, called attention to the fact that this doctrine was a
reminiscence of the Platonic.
2 Cicero, AN. D. i, 13, 34, Ex eadem Platonis schola Ponticus Heraclides puerili-
bus fabulis refersit libros et modo mundum, tum mentein divinam (sc. deum) esse
This content downloaded from 132.187.253.29 on Tue, 21 Mar 2017 10:55:29 UTC
All use subject to http://about.jstor.org/terms
I8 W. A. Heidel [1909
1 Mention was make above (p. i6, n. i) of the ariepi Kai 1Xa'XLTra attributed
to Xenocrates, he being classed with Diodorus Cronus. Zeller, II, aIoI8, n. I,
discusses this point. It seems to me a clear case of confusion, closely parallel to
that of Ecphantus, and adds another argument in favor of the identification of
Ecphantus and Hferaclides.
2 Aeius, 1, 3, I9 (Diels, Dox. 286) 'EKaroPTos E2paKocTLoS els TrYv lvOla-yopehoy
irvrrYv 1-r ai&tapera aowc/ara Kai T6 KEP6v. Trs yip HuVOayOpOK&s uovcdas oTros
ipLBTOS aire6b7?viaTo O-waTucKus.
3 Mention was made above (p. 6, n. I) of the interest in ebp5cuaTa in Alexan-
drine times. Heraclidos himself appears to have been a leader in this department.
Who it was wvho discovered this ' discovery' of Ecphantus we do not know; but
we do know that there were many untenable hypotheses put forward. The cases
of Hicetas and Ecphantus probably belong to this class and their ' discoveries'
were published at a time when real criticism was at an end. That Cicero quotes
Theophrastus for Hicetas is probably due to the confusion noted above, p. 6, n. 2
This content downloaded from 132.187.253.29 on Tue, 21 Mar 2017 10:55:29 UTC
All use subject to http://about.jstor.org/terms
Vol. xl] The acvap,ot 6',ycot of Heraclides and Asclepiades I9
1 It is not necessary to catalogue them here, since nobody has presented any
arguments but those which were suggested by the systems of Heraclides and
Asclepiades. Some were of course correct, but they were mere guesses.
2 Except Herwerden, to whom I owe the references. He says, Lexicon Graec.
Suppi.. "&cvcLp,uos: Philostrat. De Gymn. XXIX, 5 et XLVIII, 13 Volckmar ra6u'
vrap/tou, coxendicem laxam, tribuit viris provectioribus aut rei venereae indul-
gentibus. "
3 P. 156, i f., ed. Jiuthner: i de iK 7rpO1qK6VTVco (sc. o7ropa) ME iXeYKTga
Xe7rTv6 /t&v To7Tots TO6 3pia, KUaOdSet1 U at KXE&IES, b7raveOT7KVZaL U& al qXIjeT
Ka9aI7rep TOZS re7OVqK6ot, Kat o0XOP T0o67OLS dvap/oP Kat Tra gV6511 ciOeviP.
4 P. 174, 28 f., ed. Jiuthner: Tois 8' 9t &Opo&Otw(v PKOVTaS yVgPatoggPoVS /eP
irXelw 9tyTef * T'7_v L'O.X6P TE 'YCp brO8f8'&K6T1ES Kai 0TEVOi T6 7rpvega KaL T&S op/&1S
&TOXgOL Kai acra'9oO^T1es T6V 7r6OVwV Kat T7r TOaOTa &XIOKeO0a d aPoUPTas U KXe1s
Te &v d7ro&t1arTO KOIXfl Kar I0.XIOv dp/aOv Kat 7rXep& vl7roXapa"TToVOa Kat iPvXp6-
Trjs acaTos. Jiithner rightly directs attention to the similarity of the two pas-
sages. It is evident that they aim to represent a frame loosely put together and
broken in strength. A good firm hip is a prime requisite for an athlete. In
This content downloaded from 132.187.253.29 on Tue, 21 Mar 2017 10:55:29 UTC
All use subject to http://about.jstor.org/terms
20 W A. Heidel [I909
c. 34 the requirements for a boxer are set forth: etpeLr UT av'7T6V Kat'o f
6vzra-yes (well-knit, the opposite of dvap/Aov!)- rl -yap rpo/3oX?'r T6Wv xetpCv a7
Kpefdavvvat r[6 o]o[Aa, ei] gir7rl /3eg3atov uxoZro roO LoXiov. Jiithner re
dvap/Aov loXiov "1 ungefiuge Hiifte."
1 Such persons are often described as emaciate, more especially about the eyes
(Arist. de General. Antimal. 747a 13-17; Galen, VI, 443 K.; Oribasius, V, 587,
B. and D.); cp. [Arist.] Physiogn. 8o8a 12; [Arist.] Probl. 876a 36; 876b 5;
879b 8-II, 30; 880b 8) and the hips ([Arist.] Probl. 876a 36 ff. and 879b 8-
II, 30).
This content downloaded from 132.187.253.29 on Tue, 21 Mar 2017 10:55:29 UTC
All use subject to http://about.jstor.org/terms
Vol. xl] The c'vap"^ot icot of Heraclides and Asciepiades 2I
This content downloaded from 132.187.253.29 on Tue, 21 Mar 2017 10:55:29 UTC
All use subject to http://about.jstor.org/terms