Optimality Theory PDF
Optimality Theory PDF
Optimality Theory
General editors: s . r . a n d e r s o n , j . b r e s n a n , b . c o m r i e , w.
d r e s s l e r , c . e w e n, r . h u d d l e s t o n, r . l a s s , d. l i g h t f o o t,
j . ly o n s , p . h . m a t t h e w s , r . p o s n e r , s . r o m a i n e , n . v.
s m i t h , n. v i n c e n t
O P T I M A L I T Y T H E O RY
In this series
ren kager
The Pitt Building, Trumpington Street, Cambridge, United Kingdom
The Edinburgh Building, Cambridge CB2 2RU, UK
40 West 20th Street, New York, NY 10011-4211, USA
477 Williamstown Road, Port Melbourne, VIC 3207, Australia
Ruiz de Alarcn 13, 28014 Madrid, Spain
Dock House, The Waterfront, Cape Town 8001, South Africa
http://www.cambridge.org
Preface page xi
1 Conicts in grammars 1
1.1 Introduction: goals of linguistic theory 1
1.2 Basic concepts of OT 3
1.3 Examples of constraint interaction 14
1.4 The architecture of an OT grammar 18
1.5 Interactions of markedness and faithfulness 27
1.6 Lexicon Optimization 32
1.7 A factorial typology of markedness and faithfulness 34
1.8 On dening segment inventories 43
1.9 Conclusion 47
References 425
Index of languages 445
Index of subjects 447
Index of constraints 451
ix
PREFACE
xi
Preface
its generative ancestors will be the topic of chapter 2, although the issue will
reoccur in later chapters (specically 4, 5, and 9).
Optimality Theory is not a theory of representations, but a theory of inter-
actions of grammatical principles. More accurately, the issue of representations is
orthogonal to that of constraint interaction. Therefore the divergence from earlier
generative models is less clear-cut in this respect. Most OT literature on phono-
logy, for example, assumes the representational alphabet of non-linear (metrical
and autosegmental) phonology. In this book, the emphasis will be on prosodic
phenomena, partly reecting a tendency in the eld, and partly the research inter-
ests of the author. Some of OTs most striking results have been reached in the
domain of prosodically governed phenomena, such as syllable-dependent epenth-
esis (chapter 3), interactions of syllable weight and metrical structure (chapter 4),
and prosodic targets in reduplication (chapter 5). However, our discussion of these
phenomena serves to highlight results of OT that are relevant beyond prosody. To
support this point, a range of segmental phenomena will be analysed throughout
the book. Finally, OT has consequences for representational issues which are more
closely connected with grammatical interactions, in particular for featural under-
specication, as will be shown in chapters 1, 3, and 9.
Optimality Theory is a general theory of grammar, rather than one of phono-
logy. Therefore this book is not limited in its empirical scope to phonological
phenomena, but it also contains chapters on the learnability of OT grammars
(chapter 7) and extensions to syntax (chapter 8). Finally, chapter 9 will address a
number of important residual issues in OT, focussing on opacity, and discussing
current developments in assumptions on lexical representations (versus allomor-
phy), optionality, absolute ungrammaticality, and various functionally oriented
approaches to phonology.
During its brief period of existence, OT has sparked off a large output of
articles, PhD dissertations, and volumes. Here we will review a selection of this
research output, in a way that maximally highlights the theorys contribution to
insights into language. In chapters 2 and 58, one particular piece of research
will be focussed on, while placing it against a broad theoretical background.
Chapter 2 focusses on the analysis of post-nasal-obstruent-voicing effects by
Pater (forthcoming), and serves to highlight factorial typology, OTs explanation
of conspiracies, and to introduce Correspondence Theory. Chapter 5 is devoted to
the Correspondence Theory of reduplication by McCarthy and Prince (1995a,
forthcoming), emphasizing the emergence of the unmarked and parallelism of
evaluation, and also extending the notion of correspondence to relations between
outputs. Chapter 6 discusses Benuas (1995) paper on output-to-output correspond-
ence in truncation, and its extensions to stem-based afxation, while comparing
OT and derivational theory for cyclic phenomena. Chapter 7 discusses work by
xii
Preface
Tesar and Smolensky (1993, 1998) on the learnability of OT grammars, and its
dependence on basic OT notions, such as strict domination, minimal violation,
and assumptions on lexical forms. Chapter 8 is devoted to the analysis of Wh-
movement and its relation with auxiliary inversion and do-support in English by
Grimshaw (1997), pointing out the relevance of OT outside phonology.
This book is not a general introduction to phonology, and the reader should
come equipped with a basic knowledge of derivational Generative Phonology,
including rules and representations, and some knowledge of Minimalist Syntax
for chapter 8. Exercises have been added to chapters 17 to increase analytic
skills and reection on theoretical issues. Moreover, each chapter contains a list
of suggestions for further reading.
The idea for this book arose during a course I taught at the LOT summer school
at the University of Amsterdam in 1995. Stephen Anderson, who was present at
this course, suggested basing an OT textbook on its contents. For his role in
originating this book, I owe him special thanks.
Parts of this book are based on research reported on earlier occasions. Chapter
4 is partly based on Kager (1997a), rst presented at the workshop on Derivations
and Constraints in Phonology, held at the University of Essex, September 1995.
Chapter 6 contains results from Kager (forthcoming), presented at the conference
on the Derivational Residue in Phonology, Tilburg University, October 1995. I
wish to thank the organizers of these events: Iggy Roca, Ben Hermans, and Marc
van Oostendorp. Research for this book was partly sponsored by the Dutch Royal
Academy of Sciences (KNAW), whose support is gratefully acknowledged.
For their comments on earlier versions of chapters I wish to thank Peter Ackema,
Stephen Anderson, Roger Billerey, Gabriel Drachman, Nine Elenbaas, Bruce
Hayes, Claartje Levelt, Ad Neeleman, Joe Pater, Bruce Tesar, Wim Zonneveld,
and an anonymous reviewer. These comments have led to a number of substantial
improvements. Needless to say, I take the blame for any mistakes in content or
my presentation of other researchers ideas. Thanks to Martin Everaert for supply-
ing the child language data discussed in chapter 7.
Finally, this book would not have been nished without the encouragement and
patience of my colleagues, friends, and family. Jacqueline, this book is dedicated
to you.
xiii
1
Conicts in grammars
1.1.1 Universality
The central goal of linguistic theory is to shed light on the core of grammatical
principles that is common to all languages. Evidence for the assumption that there
should be such a core of principles comes from two domains: language typology
and language acquisition. Over the past decades our knowledge of linguistic
typology has become more and more detailed, due to extensive eldwork and
ne-grained analysis of data from languages of different families. From this large
body of research a broad picture emerges of unity in variety: core properties of
grammars (with respect to the subsystems of sounds, words, phrases, and mean-
ing) instantiate a set of universal properties. Grammars of individual languages
draw their basic options from this limited set, which many researchers identify
as Universal Grammar (UG). Each language thus reects, in a specic way, the
structure of language. A second source of evidence for universal grammatical
principles comes from the universally recurring patterns of rst language acqui-
sition. It is well known that children acquiring their rst language proceed in
remarkably similar ways, going through developmental stages that are (to a large
extent) independent of the language being learnt. By hypothesis, the innateness
of UG is what makes grammars so much alike in their basic designs, and what
causes the observed developmental similarities.
The approach to universality sketched above implies that linguistic theory
should narrow down the class of universally possible grammars by imposing
restrictions on the notions of possible grammatical process and possible inter-
action of processes. In early Generative Grammar (Chomsky 1965, Chomsky and
Halle 1968), processes took the shape of rewrite rules, while the major mode of
interaction was linear ordering. Rewrite rules take as their input a linguistic
representation, part of which is modied in the output. Rules apply one after
another, where one rules output is the next rules input. It was soon found that
this rule-based theory hardly imposes any limits on the notion of possible rule,
1
Conicts in grammars
nor on the notion of possible rule interaction. In the late 1970s and early 1980s,
considerable efforts were put into constraining both rule typology and interac-
tions. The broad idea was to factor out universal properties of rules in the form
of conditions.1 While rules themselves may differ between languages, they must
always respect a xed set of universal principles. Gradually more and more
properties were factored out of rules and attributed to universal conditions on
rules and representations. Developments came to their logical conclusion in
Principles-and-Parameters Theory (Chomsky 1981b, Hayes 1980), which has as
its central claim that grammars of individual languages are built on a central core
of xed universal properties ( principles), plus a specication of a limited num-
ber of universal binary choices ( parameters). Examples of parameters are the side
of the head (left or right) in syntactic phrases, or the obligatoriness (yes/no)
of an onset in a syllable. At the same time, considerable interest developed in
representations, as a way of constraining rule application, mainly with respect to
locality (examples are trace theory in syntax, and underspecication theory in
phonology). Much attention was also devoted to constraining rule interactions,
resulting in sophisticated theories of the architecture of UG (the T-model) and
its components (e.g. Lexical Phonology, Kiparsky 1982b).
1.1.2 Markedness
What all these efforts to constrain rules and rule interactions share, either implic-
itly or explicitly, is the assumption that universal principles can only be universal
if they are actually inviolate in every language. This interpretation of universal-
ity leads to a sharp increase in the abstractness of both linguistic representations
and rule interactions. When some universal principle is violated in the output of
the grammar, then the characteristic way of explaining this was to set up an
intermediate level of representation at which it is actually satised. Each gram-
matical principle thus holds at a specic level of description, and may be switched
off at other levels.
This absolute interpretation of universality is not the only one possible, how-
ever. In structuralist linguistics (Hjelmslev 1935, Trubetzkoy 1939, Jakobson
1941; cf. Anderson 1985), but also in Generative Phonology (Chomsky and Halle
1968, Kean 1975, Kiparsky 1985) and Natural Phonology (Stampe 1972, Hooper
1976), a notion of markedness plays a key role, which embodies universality in
a soft sense. The idea is that all types of linguistic structure have two values,
one of which is marked, the other unmarked. Unmarked values are cross-
linguistically preferred and basic in all grammars, while marked values are cross-
linguistically avoided and used by grammars only to create contrast. For example,
1
For example, Subjacency was proposed as a universal condition on syntactic movement rules
and the Obligatory Contour Principle as a universal condition on phonological rules.
2
1.2 Basic concepts of OT
all languages have unrounded front vowels such as [i] and [e], but only a subset
of languages contrast these vowels with rounded front vowels such as [y] and [].
Hence, the unmarked value of the distinctive feature [round] is [round] in
front vowels. At a suprasegmental level, markedness affects prosodic categories.
For example, the unmarked value for syllable closure is open since all lan-
guages have open syllables (CV, V), while only a subset of languages allow closed
syllables (CVC, VC).2 The notion of markedness is not only relevant to sound
systems. Markedness principles have been proposed for morphological and
syntactic systems as well (Chomsky 1981a).
The markedness approach of linguistic universality is built on two assump-
tions. First, markedness is inherently a relative concept: that is, a marked linguis-
tic element is not ill-formed per se, but only in comparison to other linguistic
elements. Second, what is marked and unmarked for some structural distinc-
tion is not an arbitrary formal choice, but rooted in the articulatory and perceptual
systems. By this combination of two factors, markedness allows an interpretation
of universality that is fundamentally different from Principles-and-Parameters
Theory, in which markedness has no substantive status in the grammar, but func-
tions as an external system of annotations on parameter values, evaluating a
grammars complexity.3
3
Conicts in grammars
The remainder of this chapter is organized as follows. Section 1.2 will introduce
basic notions of OT: conict, constraints, and domination, which will be exem-
plied in section 1.3. In section 1.4, we will discuss the architecture of an OT
grammar. Section 1.5 will deal with interactions of markedness and faithfulness,
relating these to the lexicon in section 1.6. A factorial typology of constraint
interactions will be developed in section 1.7 and applied to segment inventories
in section 1.8. Finally, section 1.9 presents conclusions.
First consider what a hypothetical language would look like at one extreme of the
spectrum: a language giving maximal priority to the expression of lexical con-
trasts, while imposing no markedness restrictions. We endow this language with
the combined segment inventories of the worlds languages, roughly 50 conson-
ants and 30 vowels (Ladefoged and Maddieson 1996). We drop combinatory
markedness restrictions, allowing all logically possible segment combinations to
form a lexical item. Permutation of these 80 segments into lexical items of two
6
1.2 Basic concepts of OT
segments already produces some 6,400 items, including [ph], [x], and [.],
all highly marked. But why stop at two segments per item? By sheer lack of
phonotactic limitations, nothing rules out lexical items of 37 or 4,657 segments,
or even longer. Now consider the fact that the number of possible lexical items
increases exponentially with the number of segments (80n) so that at segmental
length 6 we already approximate an awesome 300 billion potential lexical items.
Clearly no human language requires this number of lexical contrasts, hence there
is room to impose markedness restrictions on segments and their combinations in
lexical items. Since such restrictions make sense from an articulatory and percep-
tual point of view, we expect to nd them.
Let us now turn the tables to nd out what a language at the other extreme
would look like, a language giving maximal priority to markedness, and minimal
priority to the expression of lexical contrasts. Let us assume that this language
limits its lexical items to the general shape of CV* (sequences of consonant
vowel), with C {p,t,k} and V {,a}.4 The complete set of potential monosylla-
bles contains 6 items {p, pa; t, ta; k, ka}, the set of disyllables contains 36 (or
62) items ({pp, pap, kp . . . }), trisyllables 216 (or 63), etc. But stop! We are
overlooking the fact that the unmarked length of lexical item is two syllables (this
is the minimum size in many languages and by far the most frequent size in most
languages). Since we are assuming that this language is maximally concerned
about markedness, we should limit word size to two syllables. The bitter conse-
quence is a mini-lexicon containing at most 36 items. Now consider the fact that
the lexicon of an average natural language contains some 100,000 items.5 It is
clear that giving maximal priority to markedness implies an acute shortage of
lexical contrasts, which no language can afford.
This comparison of two extremes shows that languages may, in principle at
least, go astray in either of two ways: by giving blind priority to expression of
lexical contrast, resulting in massive costs in terms of markedness or, at the other
end of the spectrum, by giving unlimited priority to markedness reduction, result-
ing in a fatal lack of contrast.
4
These limitations are actually grounded in speech production and perception: every consonant
is maximally different from a vowel (hence, all consonants are voiceless stops). Every vowel
is maximally different from other vowels (a 2-vowel set, a). Every consonant is maximally
different from other consonants (place of articulation restricted to labial, alveolar, and velar).
Every vowel is preceded by a consonant (no word-initial vowels, no hiatus). Every consonant
precedes a vowel for optimal release (hence no consonant clusters nor word-nal Cs).
5
Suppose that our hypothetical language would not respect word size restrictions, having at its
disposition all possible CV*-shaped items. Here, with a maximal density of lexical contrast,
all potential items up to seven syllables long would not sufce to build the required size of
lexicon. This would only reach to a moderate total of (46,656 + 7,776 + 1296 + 216 + 36 +
6) = 55,986 lexical items. The average item in this language would be over six syllables long.
Without doubt, speaking would become a rather time-consuming activity.
7
Conicts in grammars
In sum, we have seen that every grammar must reconcile the inherently compet-
ing forces of faithfulness to lexical contrasts (the inertness which draws output
forms back to their basic lexical shapes) and markedness (minimization of
marked forms). However, as we are about to nd out, Optimality Theory recog-
nizes no unitary or monolithic forces of faithfulness or markedness: the picture
is more fragmented. In the grammars of individual languages, the overall conict
between both forces assumes the form of ner-grained interactions of individual
constraints. At this level, where individual constraints compete, languages are
quite diverse in their resolutions of conicts between markedness and faithful-
ness. A language may give priority to faithfulness over markedness with respect
to some opposition, but reverse its priorities for another opposition.
Let us now turn to the implementation of these basic ideas in Optimality
Theory.
C1 C2 . . . Cn
Candidate a
Candidate b
Input Candidate c
Candidate d Output
Candidate . . .
The optimal output candidate is the one that is most harmonic with respect to
the set of ranked constraints. Harmony is a kind of relative well-formedness,
taking into account the severity of the violations of individual constraints, as
determined by their hierarchical ranking. That is, violation of a higher-ranked
6
Elimination of less-harmonic candidates is portrayed in (1) as a serial ltering process, but we
will learn to view it as a parallel process, with higher-ranked constraints taking priority over
lower-ranked constraints.
8
1.2 Basic concepts of OT
Markedness constraints require that output forms meet some criterion of struc-
tural well-formedness. As the examples below illustrate, such requirements may
take the form of prohibitions of marked phonological structures, including seg-
ment types (2a), prosodic structures (2b), or occurrences of segment types in
specic positions (2c).
Faithfulness constraints require that outputs preserve the properties of their basic
(lexical) forms, requiring some kind of similarity between the output and its
input.
Faithfulness constraints are, strictly speaking, not pure output constraints, since
they take into account elements at two levels: input and output. In contrast,
markedness constraints never take into account elements in the input.8 The
important thing is, however, that both kinds of constraints refer to the output
(exclusively so in markedness, and in relation to the input in faithfulness). OT has
no constraints that exclusively refer to the input. (This is a crucial difference from
classical generative phonology, as we will see in chapter 2.)
From a functional viewpoint, faithfulness constraints protect the lexical items
of a language against the eroding powers of markedness constraints, and thereby
serve two major communicative functions. First, they preserve lexical contrasts,
making it possible for languages to have sets of formally distinct lexical items to
express different meanings. Phrasing it slightly differently, with an emphasis on
contrast, we may say that faithfulness is what keeps the shapes of different lexical
items apart. Second, by limiting the distance between input and output, faithful-
ness constraints restrict the shape variability of lexical items. Faithfulness thus
keeps the contextual realizations of a single morpheme (called its alternants)
from drifting too far apart. This enhances the one-to-one relations of meaning and
form. In sum, the overall function of faithfulness is to enforce the phonological
shape of lexical forms in the output, as a sort of inertness limiting the distance
between outputs and their basic shapes.
Two more assumptions are to be made about constraints in OT: they are uni-
versal and violable requirements on some aspect of linguistic output forms. Let
us now focus on each of these properties of constraints. The rst property is
7
We will see later that some markedness constraints do have antagonists.
8
See chapter 9 for OT models which weaken this assumption.
10
1.2 Basic concepts of OT
In its strongest interpretation, by which all constraints are part of UG, this implies
that all constraints are part of the grammars of all natural languages. This is not
to say that every constraint will be equally active in all languages. Due to the
language-specic ranking of constraints, a constraint that is never violated in one
language may be violated but still be active in a second language, and be totally
inactive in yet a third language. This strong interpretation, which leaves no room
for language-specic constraints, nor for constraint variability, will be slightly
relativized below.
For phonological markedness constraints, universality may be established by a
variety of factors, ideally in combination. The rst sense of universality is typological:
a constraint states a preference for certain structures over other types of struc-
tures, which reoccurs in a range of unrelated languages. Segmental markedness
constraints, for example, may be validated by inspecting the relative markedness
of segments in inventories on a cross-linguistic basis. (Such an overview is pre-
sented in Maddieson 1984.) However, any exclusively typology-based deni-
tion of universality runs the risk of circularity: certain properties are posited as
unmarked simply because they occur in sound systems with greater frequency
than other marked properties.
Hence, a second (non-circular) criterion of universality should ideally accom-
pany typological criteria: phonological markedness constraints should be phonetic-
ally grounded in some property of articulation or perception. That is, phonetic
evidence from production or perception should support a cross-linguistic prefer-
ence for a segment (or feature value) to others in certain contexts. For example,
there is articulatory evidence (to be reviewed in chapter 2) that voiced obstruents
are preferred to voiceless obstruents in a position immediately following a nasal.
Indeed many languages avoid or disallow voiceless post-nasal obstruents, neu-
tralizing voicing contrasts in this position.9 Even though a growing number of
constraints has been phonetically grounded (see the suggested readings at the end
of this chapter), such grounding is still lacking for others.
It should be clear from this discussion that we should be very careful about
positing any constraint lacking both typological motivation and phonetic ground-
ing, even if there is compelling motivation for it from the language data under
analysis. Nevertheless, not all constraints that have been proposed in the OT lit-
erature satisfy both criteria, indicating that the major issue of universality of
constraints has not yet been resolved, since analysts do not share the same criteria.
In this book, whenever we employ a constraint that strikes us as parochial or
9
Post-nasal voicing and its typological consequences will be discussed in detail in chapter 2.
11
Conicts in grammars
12
1.2 Basic concepts of OT
So we assume that each output form of the grammar is by denition the best
possible in terms of the hierarchy of constraints, rather than the form which
matches all constraints at the same time. Perfect output forms are principally
non-existent, as every output form will violate at least some constraints. There-
fore the selection of the optimal output form involves setting priorities.
This is where a hierarchy comes into play. Conicts are resolved by domination:
This tentative denition will be rened below in section 1.4, on the basis of more
complex cases.
The ranking of constraints can be demonstrated by a tableau: this lists two
(or any number of ) output candidates vertically in random order, and constraints
horizontally, in a descending ranking from left to right. The cells contain violation
marks * incurred by each candidate for the constraint heading the column.
Schematically:
a. + candidate a *
b. candidate b *!
The optimal candidate is marked by the index +. This candidate is (8a), which
has no violations of the higher-ranked constraint C1, a constraint violated by its
competitor (8b). Note that the optimal candidate (8a) is actually not impeccable
itself: it has a violation of C2, but this aw is insignicant to the outcome.
Although the pattern of violations for C2 is the reverse of that for C1, this does
not help candidate b. Its violation of C1 is already fatal, indicated by the accom-
panying exclamation mark ! and the shading of cells whose violation content is
no longer relevant. In sum, candidate (a) is optimal as no candidate is available
that fares better, satisfying both constraints at the same time. A violation of C2 is
taken for granted, as long as C1 can be satised.
We now turn to exemplication of the ideas that have been introduced thus far.
13
Conicts in grammars
(9) *Voiced-Coda
Obstruents must not be voiced in coda position.
This is a typical markedness constraint, which bans a marked segment type (here:
voiced obstruents) from the syllable coda (which is itself a marked position).10
Coda obstruents are voiceless in Dutch, as illustrated by the following
alternation:
If this constraint were the only one relevant for these forms, then things would
be simple. Violators could be dismissed without second thoughts. But in actual
grammars things are not that simple since constraints may make conicting
requirements about output forms.
A second constraint of the universal inventory is a typical faithfulness con-
straint, requiring that the input value of the feature [voice] be preserved in the
output.
(12) Ident-IO(voice)
The specication for the feature [voice] of an input segment must be
preserved in its output correspondent.
10
Actually *Voiced-Coda can be interpreted as the conjunction of two markedness statements,
an idea to which we will return in chapter 9.
14
1.3 Examples of constraint interaction
This informal denition is precise enough for our present purposes. (We will
return to the important notion of correspondence, particularly in chapters 2 and
5.)
In a correspondence diagram of the Dutch word [bt] bed the input and out-
put segments that are correspondents of one another are connected by vertical lines.
[b t] Output
Observe the conict: the evaluation of both output forms is different for each
constraint.
This conict requires resolution, which is the task of the constraint hierarchy.
The form [bt] emerges as the optimal output of the grammar, given the following
fragment of the phonology of the language:
(18) Tableau for the input /bd/, assuming the Dutch ranking
Candidates: *Voiced-Coda Ident-IO(voice)
a. + [bt] *
b. [bd] *!
The optimal candidate in the top row, [bt], incurs a violation of Ident-IO(voice)
while it satises *Voiced-Coda. Suboptimal [bd] has exactly the reverse pattern
of violations: it has a violation mark for *Voiced-Coda, but none for Ident-
IO(voice).
Being presented with these two output candidates, the grammar (whose only
goal is selecting an optimal output) must settle for a candidate that has a violation
of a lower-ranked constraint, simply because no perfect output candidate is avail-
able, satisfying both constraints. This point can be made more general: constraints
are intrinsically conicting, hence perfect output candidates will never occur in
any tableau:
(19) Fallacy of perfection: no output form is possible that satises all
constraints.
An output is optimal since there is no such thing as a perfect output: all that
grammars may accomplish is to select the most harmonic output, the one which
incurs the minimal violation of constraints, taking into account their ranking.
Nothing better is available.
Observe that the result of the constraint interaction in Dutch is a neutralization
of the voicing contrast in a specic context: the syllable coda. That neutralization
indeed takes place can be easily shown by the following set of examples:
(20) a.i /bd / bt bed
a.ii /bd-n/ b.dn beds
b.i /bt/ bt (I) dab
b.ii /bt-n/ b.tn (we) dab
16
1.3 Examples of constraint interaction
Neutralization of the sound shapes of two lexical items is the ultimate conse-
quence of the domination of markedness over faithfulness. The lexical contrast
between /bd / and /bt/, residing in the value of voicing of their nal stem con-
sonants, might (in principle at least) have been preserved in all morphological
contexts in which they occur. But this is not the case, and a complete neutraliza-
tion occurs, into [bt].
(22) Harmonic ranking of two output candidates for the input /bd / in
English
[bd] [bt]
That is, assuming an input /bd/, [bd] is more harmonic than [bt] with respect
to the ranking in (21).
Again, we illustrate this ranking with the help of a tableau, evaluating the same
candidates as we used in tableau (18) for Dutch. Observe that Ident-IO(voice)
and *Voiced-Coda have changed places:
(23) Tableau for the input /bd/, assuming the English ranking
Candidates: Ident-IO(voice) *Voiced-Coda
a. [bt] *!
b. + [bd] *
The net result of this ranking is that the index pointing at the optimal output has
shifted downwards (as compared to tableau 18) to the second candidate under
consideration, that is, [bed]. Note that by this ranking, English preserves the
phonological contrast between distinct lexical items, as in bed [bd] versus bet
17
Conicts in grammars
of ranked constraints, and selecting the optimal output among these. These two
components are known under the names of Generator (or Gen) and Evaluator
(or Eval ). This grammatical organization is schematically represented in a func-
tion notation as follows:
That is, Gen is a function that, when applied to some input, produces a set of
candidates, all of which are logically possible analyses of this input. Similarly,
Eval is a function that, when applied to a set of output candidates, produces an
output, the optimal analysis of the input. In addition to Gen and Eval, the gram-
mar contains a lexicon storing all lexical forms that are input to Gen. Recapit-
ulating, we nd the following model of the grammar:
The only true restriction imposed on all output candidates generated by Gen is
that these are made up of licit elements from the universal vocabularies of lin-
guistic representation, such as segmental structure (features and their grouping
below the level of the segment), prosodic structure (mora, syllable, foot, prosodic
word, etc.), morphology (root, stem, word, afx, etc.), and syntax (X-bar struc-
ture, heads/complements/speciers, etc.). Within these limits, anything goes.
Since Gen generates all logically possible candidate analyses of a given input,
the OT grammar needs no rewrite rules to map inputs onto outputs. All structural
changes are applied in one step, in parallel. The evaluation of these candidate
analyses is the function of the Evaluator, the component of ranked constraints,
discussed in section 1.4.3. There we will also discuss the issue of whether or not
Eval is able to deal with an innite candidate space.
11
For example, rewrite rules may be blocked if their output would violate a MSC, or may be
triggered to repair a violation of a MSC.
20
1.4 The architecture of an OT grammar
First, the constraint hierarchy contains all universal constraints (a set called Con),
which are ranked in a language-specic way. We (tentatively) assume that all
constraints are ranked with respect to each other, so as to exclude variable and
undetermined rankings. (For cases in which two constraints cannot be ranked with
respect to each other, due to a trivial lack of interaction, we nevertheless assume
some ranking, arbitrarily one or the other.)
Moreover, within the hierarchy, dominance relations are transitive:
Second, with respect to violation marks, we assume that each output candidate is
provided with as many marks as it has violations for a constraint. This number of
marks potentially ranges from zero until innite. However, for purposes of deter-
mining optimal outputs, an innite number of marks is never practically relevant.
The essence of minimal violation of constraints is that every violation of a con-
straint serves a purpose: to avoid a violation of some higher-ranked constraint.
This is a property which is stated by Prince and Smolensky (1993: 27):
For example, the Generator component is free to submit any kind of analysis of
(English) /bd/ that is couched within the universal alphabet of representational
options, including excessively unfaithful candidates such as [plow] and [mtrs].
But these candidates will be (hopefully!) ruled out regardless of constraint rank-
ing, since they violate faithfulness constraints without compensation from reduc-
tions in markedness. This economy property of OT will be discussed in more
detail in section 1.7.5.
21
Conicts in grammars
Third, we have not yet precisely formulated in which way the evaluation of output
candidates by ranked constraints proceeds. Eval determines the harmonic status
of output candidates, and eventually the most harmonic or optimal candidate. To
this end, it uses a process by which the set of candidates is reduced until the point
is reached at which one output remains. This is a multi-step process, schematic-
ally repeated below from (1):
(30)
C1 C2 . . . Cn
Candidate a
Candidate b
Input Candidate c
Candidate d Output
Candidate . . .
The major property of this evaluation process is that it applies from one state to
another without looking ahead to following steps. That is, the elimination of
candidate outputs by a constraint Cn is never affected by a lower-ranked constraint
Cn+m. Stated in a non-serial manner, this implies:
Optimality does not involve any kind of compromise between constraints of dif-
ferent ranks.
To illustrate strict domination, let us return to tableau (8) the cases of simple
domination and ask what would have happened if the rst candidate had had
not one but two violations of C2. The following tableau shows that even here, the
rst candidate would still be optimal, even though its total number of violations
is greater:
(32) Strict domination: multiple violations of a lower-ranked constraint
C1 C2
a. + candidate a **
b. candidate b *!
There is yet another sense in which domination is strict, which is not illustrated
by (32) constraint violations are never added for different constraints. The
added violations of two lower-ranked constraints (C2 and C3) are not able to
cancel out a single violation of a higher-ranked constraint (C1):
a. + candidate a * *
b. candidate b *!
(34)
C1 C2
Candidate a
Candidate b
Candidate c
Candidate d
Candidate . . .
a. + candidate a * *
b. candidate b **!
Finally, if multiple candidates have the same number of violations for C1 (and this
equals the minimal violation in the set), then all survive and are passed on for
evaluation by the next constraint down the hierarchy, C2.12
(36) Tie between candidates (with lower-ranking constraint decisive)
C1 C2
a. + candidate a * *!
b. candidate b *
Of course, ties between candidates may also arise between forms that have
no violations at all, or between forms that have two, three, or any number of
violations.
24
1.4 The architecture of an OT grammar
optimal output, but their violation must be minimal. Given the chance, any con-
straint (regardless of its position in the hierarchy) will be active in determining
the optimal output.
a. + candidate a * *
b. candidate b **!
c. candidate c *!
That C2 is dominated is apparent from the fact that candidate (38c) is less har-
monic than (38a), even though it has no violations of C2 . But C2 is still active,
since it dominates C3 .
arguments below, and for some others, see chapter 10 of Prince and Smolensky
(1993).
Firstly, it is a well-accepted assumption among linguists that there is a distinc-
tion between the grammar (competence) and its cognitive implementation (per-
formance). This distinction is assumed in most formal theories of grammar, and
particularly in generative linguistics (Chomsky 1965). Therefore a model of
grammar is adequate to the extent that it explains observed systematicities in
natural languages, and the grammatical judgements of speakers. Explaining the
actual processing of linguistic knowledge by the human mind is not the goal of the
formal theory of grammar, but that of linguistic disciplines (such as psycholin-
guistics, neurolinguistics, and computional linguistics). The central point is that a
grammatical model should not be equated with its computational implementation.
Secondly, turning now to computational plausibility, the fact that candidate
space is innite does not imply that the problem is logically unsolvable. You may
convince yourself of this by thinking of arithmetic or any kind of numerical
problem. For example, there is a unique solution to the equation 3n2 3 = 45,
which you will be able to nd after a moments thought, even though the can-
didate set (let us say, all integers) is innite. From a computational viewpoint, the
decisive factor is that a guaranteed method (an algorithm) exists that will cer-
tainly produce a solution for any input. Therefore, no simple argument against OT
as being computationally intractable can be based on the observation that can-
didate space is innite.13
Thirdly, smart computational strategies may eliminate suboptimal candidates
by classes, rather than on a one-by-one basis. As soon as a candidate has been
excluded due to its violation of some constraint C, the evaluation process can
immediately eliminate all other candidates that violate this constraint C more
severely. This leads us to yet another property of candidate space that might be
put to use in computational evaluation models. By far the great majority of
candidates proposed by Gen can never be selected as optimal, under any possible
ranking of constraints. Such intrinsically suboptimal candidates can be readily
identied as follows: they share with another candidate (of the same input) some
set of violation marks, but have at least one additional violation of some other
constraint (an example will be discussed in section 1.7.5). Sophisticated evalua-
tion strategies may capitalize on this. Since the identication of intrinsically sub-
optimal candidates involves no ranked constraints, innite candidate space may
be drastically reduced by eliminating the worst-of-the-worst of candidates by pre-
processing prior to the evaluation by ranked constraints. Since this preprocessing
13
Conversely, a nite set of candidates does not guarantee that a problem is logically solvable.
This argument is due to Alan Prince (presentation at Utrecht University, January 1994).
26
1.5 Interactions of markedness and faithfulness
would eliminate the great majority of candidates, the ultimately relevant remain-
ing part of candidate space may well have quite manageable proportions, and
perhaps even reduce to a nite set (Hammond 1997).
Whether or not a computational method can be established for the evaluation
of an innite candidate space in OT grammars is still largely an open issue, but
encouraging results are available. For example, Karttunen (1998) demonstrates
that the computation of the most optimal surface realization of any input string
can be carried out entirely within a nite-state calculus, subject to the limitation
(Frank and Satta (1998)) that the maximal number of violations is bounded.
Karttunen adds that [i]t is not likely that this limitation is a serious obstacle to
practical optimality computations with nite-state systems as the number of con-
straint violations that need to be taken into account is generally small.
When we say that English lacks a contrast of oral and nasal vowels, we do not
imply that English completely lacks either kind of vowels, but only that no word
pairs occur that are distinguished by orality/nasality of their vowels. Whatever
variation there is between oral and nasal vowels is totally conditioned by the
context and does not reect lexical specication. Vowels are nasal when they
precede a tautosyllabic nasal, and are oral in all other contexts. This complement-
ary distribution, and the corresponding lack of word pairs that differ only in the
specication of some feature, is what denes an allophonic pattern. How can the
allophonic pattern in (40) be stated in terms of violable constraints?
In order to answer this question, we must rst identify the set of constraints
which are involved. Universally, nasal vowels are marked as compared to oral
vowels. Most of the worlds languages completely lack nasal vowels, having oral
vowels only (Maddieson 1984). Languages may have both oral and nasal vowels,
but no languages have only nasal vowels. In sum, when a language has nasal
vowels, it must also have oral vowels. The marked status of nasal vowels is
expressed by the context-free markedness constraint in (41), which militates
against nasal vowels:
(41) *VNASAL
Vowels must not be nasal.
When this constraint is undominated in some language, then all of its vowels will
be oral, regardless of their lexical specication, or their position in the syllable
(before an oral or nasal).
Moreover, many languages tend to nasalize vowels in precisely the position
where they are nasal in English: before a tautosyllabic nasal stop. The vowel thus
anticipates the nasality of the following stop, a preferred state of affairs from the
viewpoint of perception and articulation (Cohn 1993a).14 Again, a markedness
constraint expresses the universal markedness, ruling out oral vowels that precede
a tautosyllabic nasal:
(42) *VORALN
Before a tautosyllabic nasal, vowels must not be oral.
14
Cohn (1993a) argues that nasalization in English vowels is gradient, and has no phonological
status, as in French. For the sake of the argument, we will assume here that English nasaliza-
tion is in fact categorical, although it is crucially non-contrastive.
28
1.5 Interactions of markedness and faithfulness
Richness of the Base implies that English (as any other language) is allowed the
option of setting up a contrast of oral and nasal vowels in its underlying repres-
entations. However, this hypothetical contrast is never realized at the surface,
because with respect to nasality/orality in vowels, English happens to be a lan-
guage of the type (44a), which gives priority to markedness over faithfulness.
Whatever lexical contrast of nasality there might be in vowels will be obscured
by effects of markedness. The input faithfulness constraint that is crucially dom-
inated in English requires that surface values of nasality in vowels are identical
to their underlying values:
(45) Ident-IO(nasal)
Correspondent segments in input and output have identical values for
[nasal].
Let us now return to the allophonic pattern (40) and nd out how this results from
the interaction of the three constraints that were introduced earlier. In terms of
constraint interaction, faithfulness to the lexical specication of a vowel is com-
pletely dominated by markedness constraints reecting markedness of orality/
nasality in vowels. In terms of ranking, Ident-IO(nasal) is dominated by both
markedness constraints:
The question which arises next is how both markedness constraints, *VORALN and
*VNASAL, are ranked with respect to each other. As we observed earlier in connec-
tion with the context-free constraint *VNASAL, any language in which this is undom-
inated will totally lack nasal vowels in its surface patterns. This is not the case in
English, however, where nasal vowels do occur (as allophones of oral vowels) in
specic positions, that is, before tautosyllabic nasal stops. We must therefore
rene the ranking in (46) to that in (47):
This ranking states that nasal realization of vowels before tautosyllabic nasal
consonants takes priority over a total lack of nasality in vowels. In sum, both
nasal and oral vowels occur at the surface, but their distribution is xed, rather
than free.
This ranking is illustrated in the tableaux (4851). First consider the case of an
oral vowel in the actual output, for example sad [sd]. When we assume that this
has an oral vowel in its lexical representation, e.g. /sd/, matching its surface
status, we arrive at the rst tableau (48). Candidate (48a) is optimal as it violates
30
1.5 Interactions of markedness and faithfulness
a. + [sd]
b. [sNd] *! *
The losing candidate [sNd] (48b) is less harmonic than (48a) in two respects. It
contains a nasal vowel, fatally violating the markedness constraint *VNASAL. It
violates Ident-IO(nasal) as well, as the nasal vowel in the output fails to match
its oral correspondent in the input.
Because of Richness of the Base, we must guarantee that this correct result is
not negatively affected when we make different assumptions about the nasality of
vowels in the input. Indeed, the same candidate [sd] is selected when the input
would contain a nasal vowel, e.g. /sNd/, here in deance of its surface form. This
is shown in tableau (49). Again markedness uniquely determines the outcome,
without interference on the part of the faithfulness constraint Ident-IO(nasal).
a. + [sd] *
b. [sNd] *!
Note that in this case Ident-IO(nasal) is violated in the optimal candidate. This
motivates the ranking *VNASAL Ident-IO(nasal), a markedness constraint dom-
inating faithfulness. That is, even if the input of sad were to contain a nasal vowel,
its nasality would be wiped out in the surface form by markedness constraints.
This is of course the central result that we need to account for allophonic varia-
tion, in a theory which assumes Richness of the Base.
We can only rightfully claim to have captured the complementary distribution
of oral and nasal vowels if we can prove the total irrelevance of the input for
words which surface with nasal vowels, for example sand [sNnd]. Again we
consider two underlying forms, one with an oral vowel and the other with a nasal
vowel. Tableau (50) shows that an underlying form with an oral vowel /snd/
results in an optimal output with a nasal vowel, [sNnd]. This is due to the un-
dominated context-sensitive markedness constraint *VORALN, which requires that
vowels are nasal before a tautosyllabic nasal stop:
31
Conicts in grammars
a. [snd] *!
b. + [sNnd] * *
Observe that two markedness constraints, *VORALN and *VNASAL, are in conict
here. The former requires a nasal vowel in the output whereas the latter militates
against it. The fact that the actual output [sNnd] has a nasal vowel shows that
*VORALN dominates *VNASAL. (If the ranking had been reverse, the result would
have been in favour of candidate 50a, which has an oral vowel.) Observe also that
the underlying orality of the vowel in sand does not affect the outcome. Ident-
IO(nasal) is violated in the optimal output, since it contains a nasal vowel whereas
the input contains an oral vowel. This conclusion is essential to the argument
that faithfulness is dominated by both markedness constraints. We have already
reached this conclusion for *VNASAL in tableau (49), and now we conrm it for
*VORALN.
a. [snd] *! *
b. + [sNnd] *
A comparison of tableaux (50) and (51) reveals the complete inactivity of the
faithfulness constraint Ident-IO(nasal). We conclude that the orality/nasality of
the underlying vowel is completely irrelevant to the surface distribution of oral
and nasal vowels.
This principle is, in its turn, an elaboration of an idea of Stampe (1972), who
suggested that underlying forms should always match surface forms in the
absence of evidence to the contrary. (The masking effect of one underlying form,
/sNd/, by another, /sd/, is called Stampean occultation in Prince and Smolen-
sky 1993.)
An alternative to Lexicon Optimization is to assume that certain inputs contain
no specication with respect to a feature (Kiparsky 1985, Steriade 1987, Arch-
angeli 1988). This underspecication analysis of nasality in vowels is based on
the idea that the burden of explanation for contrastive versus allophonic patterns
is in the underlying form, rather than in the relationship between underlying form
and surface form, as is the case in OT.15
15
See Smolensky (1993), Inkelas (1995) and It, Mester, and Padgett (1995) for comments on
underspecication in OT.
33
Conicts in grammars
34
1.7 A factorial typology of markedness and faithfulness
of this kind are logically possible, yet unattested. Can this situation be described
by a reranking of the constraints governing nasality in vowels? Conversely, we
should ask what language types would arise by reranking a number of constraints
that are motivated in the analysis of an individual language. Does reranking of
these constraints produce attested languages as well?
Taken quite literally, the reranking approach would predict that any new gram-
mar that arises from a reranking of any pair of constraints will precisely cor-
relate with one of the worlds languages. This prediction is based on the deeply
naive assumption that every possible ranking should be instantiated by some
attested language. This is naive, just as it is deeply naive to expect that all logic-
ally possible permutations of genetic material in the human genome are actually
attested in individual humans. Therefore, in order to test the typological predic-
tions of the theory of contrast and contextual neutralization presented in this
section, we will rerank types of constraints (rather than individual constraints) of
the general types faithfulness, contextual markedness, and context-free mark-
edness. The resulting factorial typology will be matched with broad typological
diversity between languages, along the dimensions that these constraint types
represent. (Of course, this is not to deny that cases can occur in which it is more
useful to compute factorial typologies of individual constraints.)
35
Conicts in grammars
The attentive reader may have noted that we have only four rankings here, rather
than the predicted six (or 3!). This reduction is due to the fact that in rankings
(53a) and (53d), the mutual ranking of the bottom two constraints is of no import-
ance to the outcome.
The following subsections discuss how these situations arise from these rank-
ings, and also illustrate each ranking by tableaux for contrastive nasality in vowels.
of the vowel (preceding a nasal [n] or an oral [l]). All four possible inputs {/pan /
~ /pn/ ~ /pal / ~ /pl /} map onto oral output vowels:
a. pn *!
b. + pan *
a. pn *!
b. + pan * *
a. pl *!
b. + pal
a. pl *!
b. + pal *
Observe that the ranking of *VORALN and Ident-IO(nasal) with respect to one
another is totally irrelevant to the outcome, since the orality of the vowel is
uniquely determined by *VNASAL.
Ranking (53b) produces the typologically common case of allophonic varia-
tion, of which we have already encountered an example in the form of vowel
nasalization before tautosyllabic nasals in English. As compared to the previous
ranking, (53a), this ranking maintains complete neutralization, yet it allows for
some variation in output values for the relevant feature. For example, both values
of nasality in vowels do occur in surface forms, although their distribution is
totally determined by the context. Vowels are nasal before nasal consonants
(regardless of their input specication), and they are oral in all other contexts
(regardless of their input specication). Although tableaux of English examples
have already been presented in section 1.5.2, we include new tableaux here for
maximal clarity:
37
Conicts in grammars
a. + pn * *
b. pan *!
a. + pn *
b. pan *! *
a. pl *! *
b. + pal
a. pl *!
b. + pal *
The two remaining rankings in the factorial typology, (53c) and (53d), produce
varying degrees of contrastiveness, as we will see below.
a. + pn * *
b. pan *!
38
1.7 A factorial typology of markedness and faithfulness
a. + pn *
b. pan *! *
a. pl *! *
b. + pal
a. + pl *
b. pal *!
a. pn *! *
b. + pan *
a. + pn *
b. pan *! *
a. pl *! *
b. + pal
39
Conicts in grammars
a. + pl *
b. pal *!
These three constraints are ranked in the following way in Dutch, instantiating the
pattern of positional neutralization (53c) with respect to the feature [voice]:
This ranking states that a voiceless realization of obstruents in coda position takes
priority over preservation of [voice] in coda obstruents. However, preservation of
input values of [voice] takes priority over the complete devoicing of obstruents.
In sum, the contrast of voiced and voiceless obstruents is positionally neutralized
in the syllable coda. Elsewhere, a contrast is possible input values of [voice] are
preserved in the output.
40
1.7 A factorial typology of markedness and faithfulness
In terms of concrete examples, this ranking correctly predicts that the output
of /bd/ is [bet], which is unfaithful to input values for [voice] only in its coda
consonant. But the voiced onset consonant /b/ is protected from the complete
devoicing of obstruents required by the context-free markedness constraint VOP
(hence, *[pet]). This interaction is shown by tableau (60), containing all four
logically possible combinations of [voice] in the onset and coda consonants:
a. + [bt] * *
b. [pt] **!
c. [bd] *! **
d. [pd] *! * *
This does not imply that [bt] is the optimal candidate under any ranking: it
clearly is not (only consider rankings in which either *Voiced-Coda or VOP is
undominated). It does imply, however, that [pd] is intrinsically suboptimal
which means that it will never be selected as optimal under any logically possible
ranking of the three constraints under consideration.
This result, although apparently limited to the interaction of the three con-
straints in tableau (60), in fact has broader typological implications. A prediction
follows from it, which is stated in general terms as follows. Assume a context-
free markedness constraint banning one value of a feature [F], and another
context-sensitive markedness constraint banning the same value [F] in a specic
context. The prediction is that no language can have a contrast of [F] exclusively
in the context where a context-sensitive markedness constraint bans [F]. This
seems to be correct, although further testing may be required.
One particular language type excluded is one that has a lexical contrast of
voicing exclusively in syllable codas. See the following hypothetical pattern of
contrast:
Such a language would preserve a contrast of voice in the coda, but neutralize it
elsewhere. That is, it would map an input /bd/ onto an optimal output [pd]. But
we have just seen that such a mapping is ruled out on principled grounds, since
it involves the selection of an intrinsically suboptimal candidate. The asymmetry
between onsets and codas is due to a context-sensitive markedness constraint
42
1.8 On dening segment inventories
*Voiced-Coda which rules out [+voice] in the syllable coda, while there is no
analogous context-free markedness constraint which rules out any feature of voice
specically in the onset.
Alternative theories which do not assume markedness to be the actual sub-
stance of the grammar fail to derive this general prediction. For example, a rule-
based theory in which the notion of markedness is an external criterion fails to
predict that hypothetical languages such as (62) should not exist. This is because
phonological rules that neutralize a contrast of voice are natural in any context,
regardless of whether they apply in onset or in coda position. A rule neutralizing
voicing in onsets is natural in this general sense, and no language that has this
rule is committed to having a second rule neutralizing voicing in codas as well.
Therefore a grammar which neutralizes a voicing contrast in all contexts except
in codas should be possible, even though it would be complex (in the sense that
different rules would be employed, instead of a single general one).
(64) Ident-IO(Place)
The specication for place of articulation of an input segment must
be preserved in its output correspondent.
Let us now consider two grammars differing only in the ranking of Ident-
IO(Place) with respect to the markedness constraints of (63). One grammar that
we will consider ranks Ident-IO(Place) above both markedness constraints:
This grammar is maximally faithful to its input place of articulation, due to high-
ranked Ident-IO(Place). It is more important to be faithful to the input place of
articulation of a segment than to its output markedness. The tableaux (67.iii),
one for each input segment /p/ and /t/, illustrate this:
a. + [. . . p . . .] *
b. [. . . t . . .] *! *
a. [. . . p . . .] *! *
b. + [. . . t . . .] *
This grammar is less faithful (than the one in 66) to its input place features. It
blocks the surfacing of any labial in the input since the markedness constraint
45
Conicts in grammars
militating against this segment type outranks the faithfulness constraint Ident-
IO(Place). Accordingly, any input labial surfaces as a coronal, if it surfaces at
all:16
a. [. . . p . . .] *!
b. + [. . . t . . .] * *
a. [. . . p . . .] *! *
b. + [. . . t . . .] *
16
Of course one might also consider the logical possibility that input labials are simply deleted
there is no way of telling the difference between both possibilities since it is impossible to
establish the presence of input labials.
46
1.9 Conclusion
Derivational theory arrives at the same result by stipulating that the output of
(lexical) rules must contain no segments that are not part of the input inventory:
this is referred to as the structure-preserving property of phonological rules
(Kiparsky 1985).
Another interesting consequence of this theory of segmental markedness is
that it predicts that unmarked segments will emerge wherever faithfulness con-
straints are put out of control. Some segment types in every inventory (for
example, coronals) are less marked than other segments, even though the gram-
mar allows both more and less marked segments at the surface level, due to high-
ranked faithfulness constraints. However, given the chance, the grammar will still
favour unmarked segments over marked segments. This occurs in special situa-
tions in which, for some reason, input faithfulness requirements no longer hold.
This prediction has been conrmed robustly for a wide range of situations in a
wide range of languages.
Consider, for example, epenthesis: a segment appears in the output exclusively
for phonotactic reasons, as in the case of a vowel inserted to break up a consonant
cluster. By its very nature, the inserted vowel lacks a counterpart in the input. It
cannot be subject to input faithfulness, so that its featural content is fully deter-
mined by markedness factors. The prediction is that epenthetic segments are
segmentally unmarked or easily inuenced by segments in their contexts. This,
and other related observations, is presented in (71).
The observations in (71ac) will all be conrmed in later chapters, in the light
of insights into faithfulnessmarkedness interactions.
1.9 Conclusion
In this chapter we have laid out the foundations on which OT is built, and pointed
out the most important linguistic phenomena that fall in its scope. In the discus-
sions throughout this chapter, one aspect of OT stood out: the interaction of
47
Conicts in grammars
faithfulness and markedness. We have seen that all general phonological phe-
nomena discussed here are variations on this theme: the notion of contrast, and,
related to this, allophonic variation, neutralization, and lexical representations,
and nally, the notion of segment inventory. In every case, a phonological pattern
resulted from (more or less complex) interactions of constraints that preserve
lexical input properties (faithfulness), and others that reduce output markedness.
In later chapters of this book, we will maintain this perspective, and generalize it
to a range of other linguistic phenomena.
The following eight chapters of this book will each be devoted to a research topic
in which OT has left its marks. Chapter 2 addresses functional relations among
processes, comparing OT with rule-based theory from this perspective. Chapter 3
discusses syllable structure and related phenomena, such as syllabically governed
epenthesis and deletion. Chapter 4 deals with metrical phenomena, particularly
word stress and quantity effects. Chapter 5 addresses the morphologyphonology
interface, focussing on reduplication, and also extends the notion of correspond-
ence beyond relations of input and output. Chapter 6 further extends correspond-
ence to relations between morphologically related output forms, covering
paradigm regularity. Chapter 7 is devoted to the issues of learnability and acqui-
sition. Chapter 8 contains applications of OT outside phonology in syntax.
Finally, chapter 9 discusses residual issues, focussing on issues that deserve further
research (in particular, opacity) as well as on current theoretical developments.
Constraints in phonology
Hayes, Bruce (1986) Inalterability in CV Phonology. Language 62. 321 51.
McCarthy, John (1986) OCP effects: gemination and antigemination. Linguistic
Inquiry 17. 20763.
48
1.9 Further
1.9 Conclusion
Reading
Odden, David (1986) On the role of the Obligatory Contour Principle in phono-
logical theory. Language 62. 353 83.
Paradis, Carole (1988) On constraints and repair strategies. The Linguistic Review
6. 71 97.
Yip, Moira (1988) The Obligatory Contour Principle and phonological rules: a
loss of identity. Linguistic Inquiry 19. 65100.
General introductions to OT
Archangeli, Diana (1997) Optimality Theory: an introduction to linguistics in the
1990s. In D. Archangeli and D. T. Langendoen (eds.), Optimality Theory: an
introduction. Oxford: Blackwell. 132.
Burzio, Luigi (1995) The rise of Optimality Theory. Glot International 1:6. 3 7.
Prince, Alan and Paul Smolensky (1997) Optimality: from neural networks to
universal grammar. Science 275. 1604 10.
Sherrard, Nicholas (1997) Questions of priorities: an introductory overview of
Optimality Theory in phonology. In Roca. 4389.
Founding papers of OT
McCarthy, John (1993) A case of surface constraint violation. In C. Paradis and
D. LaCharite (eds.), Constraint-based theories in multilinear phonology, spe-
cial issue of Canadian Journal of Linguistics 38. 169 95.
Prince, Alan and Paul Smolensky (1993) Optimality Theory: constraint interac-
tion in generative grammar. Ms., Rutgers University, New Brunswick, and
University of Colorado, Boulder. RuCCS-TR-2. [To appear, Cambridge,
Mass.: MIT Press.]
OT in computational phonology
Eisner, Jason (1997) Efcient generation in primitive Optimality Theory. Pro-
ceedings of the 35th Annual Meeting of the Association for Computational
Linguistics. [ROA-206, http://ruccs.rutgers.edu/roa.html]
Ellison, Mark T. (1994) Phonological derivation in Optimality Theory. Proceed-
ings of the fteenth International Conference on Computational Linguistics,
II. Kyoto, Japan. 100713. [ROA-75, http://ruccs.rutgers.edu /roa.html]
Hammond, Michael (1997) Parsing syllables: modeling OT computationally. Ms.,
University of Arizona. [ROA-222, http://ruccs.rutgers.edu /roa.html, parser
code available from author, http://www.u.arizona.edu /~hammond]
Walther, Markus (1996) ot simple A construction-kit approach to Optimal-
ity Theory implementation. Ms., Heinrich Heine Universitt, Dsseldorf.
[Software and paper can be downloaded from http://www.phil-fak.uni-
duesseldorf.de/~walther/otsimple.html. Also ROA-152, http://ruccs.rutgers.
edu /roa.html]
EXERCISES
1 Japanese
Consider the following distribution of [g] and [] in Japanese (It and Mester
1997):
50
1.9
1.9Conclusion
Exercises
a. State the generalization for the distribution of [g] and []. Categorize
this distribution in terms of the typology discussed in section 1.7.
b. Account for this generalization by a set of ranked constraints.
c. Support your analysis by tableaux of geta and kafi.
2 English
Consider the following English word pairs, some of which display alternations of
voice:
a. What are the underlying forms of the sufxes in (i) and (ii)?
b. To account for these alternations, you need a new constraint. State
this constraint (as generally as possible). To what extent is this con-
straint phonetically grounded?
c. Rank the constraints, motivating each individual ranking by at least
one form. Support your analysis by tableaux of cats, dogs, hens,
twelfth, and eighth.
51
2
The typology of structural changes
2.1 Introduction
In this chapter we will learn how a range of phonological processes can be
triggered by a single markedness constraint, depending on its interactions with
faithfulness constraints. Unity in diversity among processes is predicted by OT,
due to its surface-oriented nature. To satisfy a markedness constraint in the out-
put, various repair strategies can be applied to the input; whichever is chosen
depends on the relative ranking of different faithfulness constraints. The main
result of this chapter will be a typological one: functionally related phonological
processes arise by reranking universal constraints. This factorial typology of pro-
cesses is based on Correspondence Theory (McCarthy and Prince 1995a, forthcom-
ing), a subtheory of faithfulness constraints allowing a limited set of structural
changes, such as deletions, insertions, fusions, and featural changes.
This chapter is organized as follows. Section 2.1 will compare OT and rule-
based theory with respect to their core devices: constraints versus rewrite rules.
Section 2.2 will discuss the analysis of Pater (forthcoming) of nasal substitu-
tion in Indonesian, a process avoiding Nt (a nasal-and-voiceless-obstruent se-
quence) and introduce major correspondence constraints. Section 2.3 will develop
the factorial typology of Nt effects, while section 2.4 will focus on conspirac-
ies of related processes within a language. Finally, section 2.5 will present
conclusions.
52
2.1 Introduction
Although rewrite rules are language-specic in the sense that not all grammars
share the same set of rules, their format is universal. A, B, X, and Y are natural
classes of elements:
Each aspect has a counterpart in OT. First, the trigger is a negative constraint
(*XAY), dening a conguration to be avoided. Second, the structural change
becomes a context-free rewrite operation (A B), which is attributed to the Gen-
erator component, one out of many changes possible under Freedom of Analysis.
53
The typology of structural changes
54
2.1 Introduction
All analyses proposed by Gen are submitted to Eval for parallel evaluation. Cru-
cially, all candidate analyses of (7) which change /A/ are evaluated in a single
pool of candidates together with those of (8), which employ different types of
changes. Each analysis has a price tag attached, in terms of constraint violations.
The single analysis that is perfectly faithful to the input, /XAY/, is the canonical
violator of the markedness constraint *XAY. All candidate analyses changing the
input violate one or the other faithfulness constraint, depending on the nature of
the change. Hence, the relative success of each candidate fully depends on the
interaction of *XAY with other constraints.
If *XAY is undominated, some change must be made. The nature of this change
(deletion, insertion, feature change, etc.) depends upon the relative ranking of
faithfulness constraints. Generally speaking, the lowest-ranking faithfulness con-
straint is the one to be violated in the actual output. For example, any grammar
in which segment preservation (Max-IO) outranks featural identity (Ident-
IO) will prefer a featural change A B to the deletion of A. Other structural
changes arise under different rankings of faithfulness constraints, yielding a fac-
torial typology of structural changes. (See section 2.3.)
55
The typology of structural changes
This reoccurrence of a common output factor which guides different rules, with-
out being explicitly stated in the rules, is called a conspiracy (Kisseberth 1970).
As we will see in section 2.2, functionally related processes are straightforwardly
dealt with by OT.
Before OT, phonologists had already realized that output constraints are neces-
sary ingredients of grammatical theory. As a response to rule conspiracies and
the Duplication Problem, they introduced output constraints to block or trigger
the application of rules. Among the rst output constraints were the OCP in
autosegmental theory (no identical adjacent autosegments, Goldsmith 1976),
and the No-Clash constraint in metrical theory (Liberman 1975). Such additions
resulted in mixed models, containing both rules and output constraints. Various
proposals were made for interactions of rules and constraints, such as the Theory
of Constraints and Repair Strategies (Paradis 1988), and Persistent Rule Theory
(Myers 1991).
Mixed models naturally lead to overlapping functions of rules and constraints,
as rules preserve specic structural conditions. These state congurations to be
56
2.1 Introduction
blind to their own outputs, which they produce mechanically. Moreover, each rule
is blind to the output of the derivation as a whole, which arises only after the last
rule has applied. It is thus predicted that the application of a rule can never
depend on its eventual consequences at the surface.
To appreciate the unlimited potential of intermediate representations in rule-
based theory, consider the following hypothetical derivation.
(11) Lexical form: /XAY/
Rule 1 A B / X ___ XBY
Rule 2 Y Z / B ___ XBZ
Rule 3 B C / X ___ Z XCZ
Surface form: [XCZ]
Segment B is rst introduced by Rule 1, then triggers a change in a neighbouring
segment Y due to Rule 2, and is nally deleted by Rule 3. Segment B, which plays
an active role in the derivation, is not present in the input nor in the output. It is
abstract, being present only at an intermediate stage of the representation between
the application of Rules 1 and 3. Rule-based theory predicts that such situations
should occur in natural languages, since they arise as a natural consequence of
rule interaction.
In contrast, OT attributes major importance to the surface level in the interac-
tion of constraints, disallowing access to intermediary levels between the input
and output. Constraints refer to either the output alone (in markedness con-
straints), or the input and output in combination (in faithfulness constraints of the
correspondence format). This predicts that no property of phonological forms
depends on information that is not present in the output either in the output
alone, or in the relation between the input and output.
It is, of course, an empirical matter to decide on the correctness of this prediction.
Do phonologies of natural languages ever show the degree of abstractness pre-
dicted by rule-based theory, as illustrated in derivation (11)? It has been argued,
on the basis of evidence from well-studied cases, that phonological rules may
refer to elements at a level of representation that does not coincide with the output
(see Kisseberth 1969 on Yokuts). In most of such cases this level was identied
as the input, which is not an intermediate level. But in other cases the abstract
element was indeed argued to be introduced by rule (see Brame 1974 on Pales-
tinian Arabic). Both types of opacity are potential problems for surface-oriented
OT we will return to this issue in chapter 9. Meanwhile, however, it seems fair
to conclude that the radical abstractness of the type (11) that rule-based theory
predicts to be possible in natural languages is rarely if ever attested. Over-
whelmingly, phonological generalizations refer to the output, possibly in relation
to the input.
58
2.2 Nasal substitution and related effects
The generalization can be stated as follows: when the input contains a sequence
of a nasal followed by a voiceless obstruent, the latter is deleted, leaving its place
of articulation on the nasal. This is arguably a case of coalescence (segment
fusion), since the consonant in the output has the characteristics of both input
counterparts: the nasality of the lefthand consonant, and the place of articulation
of the righthand consonant. Turning to (12b), we see that a voiced obstruent is
retained in the output form, as part of a nasal-plus-voiced-obstruent cluster. At
the lexical level, the forms in (12a) differ from those in (12b) only in their voicing
of the rst stem consonant.
To reinforce the arguments for the coalescence analysis, let us rst try to side-
step it by breaking the substitution pattern into two ordered rules. Such an ana-
lysis is actually possible, but we will soon nd that it is inadequate. It runs as
follows. Nasal assimilation copies the place of articulation of the obstruent onto
the nasal; then a second rule deletes a voiceless consonant which follows a nasal:1
1
This is a so-called counterbleeding rule order: deletion might have eliminated the context of
application for assimilation by applying rst, but failed to do so. The reverse bleeding rule
order is discussed below. See chapter 9 for further discussion of counterbleeding in OT.
59
The typology of structural changes
Pater (following Stahlke 1976) points out that an ordered rule analysis predicts
that both rules should occur independently. While nasal assimilation is a cross-
linguistically highly common process, no typological evidence seems to exist for
the second rule in isolation. That is, post-nasal voiceless consonant deletion
seems always to apply in combination with nasal assimilation. By splitting the
process of nasal substitution into two parts, the incorrect prediction is made that
assimilation and deletion may apply in the reverse order in different languages,
as in the derivation below:
In sum, the fact that the two changes cannot be typologically disentangled, and
the fact that the nasal always preserves the place of articulation of the deleted
consonant, both point to a coalescence: the input nasal and voiceless stop merge
into a single nasal of the place of articulation of the input stop. An ordered rule
analysis entirely misses this point. (See de Haas 1988 for similar arguments about
vowel coalescence.)
There is independent evidence for the coalescence analysis within the phono-
logy of Indonesian. Consider the reduplication pattern of prexed roots (Lapoliwa
1981):
Examples (15b c) show that the nasal of a prex is not normally copied by
reduplication, and that reduplication is limited to segments of the root. The prex-
nal nasal in (15c) is [], a nasal with the default place of articulation. But
example (15a) shows that a prexal nasal that is the result of nasal substitution
is copied along. The criterion for the copying of a nasal cannot be that it is
60
2.2 Nasal substitution and related effects
(16) *Nh
No nasal plus voiceless obstruent sequences.
2
There is a complementary perceptual explanation due to Ohala and Ohala (1993).
61
The typology of structural changes
substitution is only one. Moreover, the full range of effects is due to interactions
of *Nt with other (mostly faithfulness) constraints.
Output: m1,2
With respect to feature identity it will be clear that the fusion of two non-identical
segments typically involves the violation of some Ident-IO constraints. This is
because a single output segment cannot preserve the feature specications of both
input segments if these are conicting. In a fusion of /Np/ into [m], for example,
featural specications of both input segments /N, p/ are preserved, except for the
manner features of input /p/. For /p/, the features specifying sonority class, nasal-
ity, and voicing fail to reoccur in output [m], leading to violation of various
Ident-IO constraints. On the other hand, some feature specications of the input
segments are preserved. Place of articulation of input /p/ is preserved in output
[m], as well as manner of input /N/. Nor is there any loss of identity for place of
articulation for input /N/, which is arguably unspecied for place features. On the
whole, we nd that violations of featural identity are minimal: they are limited to
manner of the input obstruent.
As Pater points out, OT predicts that segment fusion should be more likely
when the input segments are more similar: that is, when the violation of faithful-
ness constraints involved is relatively small. We will return to the role of featural
3
Below we will nd that Nt-sequences do occur root-internally in Indonesian. Then we will
address the issue of what makes nasal substitution apply only across morpheme boundaries.
62
2.2 Nasal substitution and related effects
faithfulness in fusion in more detail in section 2.2.2. There we will also address
the question of what causes the obstruent (rather than the nasal) to give up its
manner specications.
(18) Linearity-IO
The output reects the precedence structure of the input, and vice
versa.
This constraint is violated by diagram (17) in the following way. In the input the
segment /N/ precedes the segment /p/. Both segments share a correspondent [m]
in the output. But no precedence relation is dened on the output segment [m],
since it is not a sequence of segments but a single segment. (Of course, the
subscripts on input and output segments have nothing to do with linear ordering.)
The output has lost information that was present in the input (its precedence
structure) a clear violation of faithfulness.
Pater argues that Linearity-IO is independently needed in correspondence
theory as the constraint militating against metathesis. Metathesis is the phenom-
enon of two segments reversing their linear order:
Output: C2 C1
4
McCarthy and Prince (1995a) argue for a separate anti-coalescence constraint: Uniformity:
(i) Uniformity-IO
No element of the output has multiple correspondents in the input.
Contrary to Linearity, this makes no demands on the linear ordering of morphemes in the
input. This is a genuine advantage, as the assumption that morphemes are linearly ordered in
the input is problematic, as we will see in chapter 5 on reduplication. (For linear ordering of
morphemes may well depend on phonological information that is not present in the input.) See
also Lamontagne and Rice (1995) for analysis of coalescence in Correspondence Theory.
63
The typology of structural changes
Again, no segments are deleted or inserted, but the precedence structure is not
preserved in the output.
We now return to the analysis of nasal substitution in Indonesian and consider the
ranking of the constraints introduced so far. The very fact that Linearity-IO
is violated in nasal substitution (i.e. coalescence) gives evidence that *Nt ranks
above Linearity-IO. The ranking argument has the following logical form:
That is, the faithful candidate [mm1p2ilih] is less harmonic than the coalesced
candidate [mm1,2ilih]. From this it follows that *Nt (the constraint that is vio-
lated in the losing candidate [mm1p2ilih]) dominates Linearity-IO (the con-
straint that is violated in the winning candidate [mm1,2ilih]).
This ranking argument is proved by the following tableau:
a. mm1p2ilih *!
b. + mm1,2ilih *
Written in the standard rule format, these four processes seem to have little in
common. But a generalization lurks beneath the surface: all four processes apply
in the context of a nasal plus voiceless consonant. To put it even more strongly: all
four processes have the effect of undoing this context: they avoid the violation
64
2.2 Nasal substitution and related effects
of *Nt. However, this functional unity is left unexpressed in the rule format.
Consider the following hypothetical rule, applying in the same context of nasal
plus voiceless consonant:
Judging by its context of application, this hypothetical rule falls into the same
class of rules as those in (22). Yet it has a completely different status, since it
fails to avoid a violation of *Nt. In order to express the typologically favoured
status of these rules over other rules that apply in the same context, such as (23),
the markedness criterion of rule-based theory must have the power to detect the
output goals of rules. However, the goal of a rule can be detected only by taking
into consideration both its structural context (here: Nt) and its structural change
(here: undoing Nt). To detect a rules goal is, by itself, in contradiction to the
fundamental assumption of rule-based theory that rules apply blindly, ignorant of
their eventual effects at the surface. Building surface-sensitivity into rules would
move rule-based theory closer to surface-oriented OT see again section 2.1.2.1.
The fact that all four processes in (22) except vowel epenthesis are typologic-
ally attested is by itself sufcient reason to favour a theory which expresses their
functional unity. But an even stronger case is made by Pater on the basis of the
observation that some of these processes cooccur within a single language. While
the occurrence of functionally related rules in different languages might still be
taken as coincidental, their cooccurrence in the same language is an even stronger
argument for OT. These cases will be discussed in section 2.3.
The actual response to *Nt in a particular language follows from the interac-
tion of *Nt with the set of faithfulness constraints. The logic of this interaction
can be stated as follows. Assume some high-ranked markedness constraint, such
as *Nt. To satisfy it, a change is necessary, which will inevitably violate some
faithfulness constraint. By itself the fact that some change is to be made does not
predict which change will be made. But we know beforehand that the grammar
will militate against any change regardless of what it may be, simply because any
change will violate at least some faithfulness constraint. It may seem as if every
grammar makes the following contradictory requirement:
This is like making the impossible requirement: remove the stain from the carpet,
but do not use water, or foam, or acid, or scissors, or . . . How to break the spell?
However, the requirement in (24) is contradictory only when each of the logic-
ally possible changes is equally expensive in terms of violations of faithful-
ness. Of course, in OT structural changes are never equally expensive, due to
strict domination. Therefore, the relative ranking of the faithfulness constraints
determines the change which serves as repair of *Nt. This is the central insight
which lies at the heart of OTs ability to deal with functionally related processes
that is, with process typology.
Violation must be minimal, hence the grammar will select output forms which
satisfy the higher-ranking constraints, at the expense of violations of lower-
ranking constraints. This means that the lowest-ranking faithfulness constraint
will be violated. In sum, the specic method which a language selects to satisfy
some high-ranking markedness constraint only depends on the lowest-ranking
faithfulness constraint. (In terms of the stained carpet analogue used above, one
might say that using scissors or acid to remove the stain would ruin the carpet,
outweighing the gains, so that the least expensive option is using foam, at least if
water does not do the job.)
Next observe that the relative ranking of the faithfulness constraints that dom-
inate Faith-IOn is immaterial to the outcome. The violation of Faith-IOn alone
sufces to avoid violation of all other constraints; this is to say that no further
violations of higher-ranking faithfulness constraints are necessary. Since unnec-
essary violations are always avoided, none of the faithfulness constraints domin-
ating Faith-IOn will in fact be violated. This, in its turn, means that we will
typically nd no positive evidence for the mutual ranking of the set of higher-
ranking faithfulness constraints. Positive evidence for ranking is always contin-
gent upon the violation of a constraint in the actual form. Therefore all we know
is that Faith-IOn is ranked below all the other faithfulness constraints. The ranking
of the set of remaining faithfulness constraints cannot be established.
For Indonesian we already know that the dominated constraint Faith-IOn must
be Linearity-IO. We now substitute Linearity-IO in (25), and also replace the
abstract set of faithfulness constraints {Faith-IO1, Faith-IO2 . . .} by the set of
informal faithfulness constraints of (24). After doing this, we arrive at:
66
2.2 Nasal substitution and related effects
But this is, of course, not the end of the story. We must now formalize the
constraints that are loosely referred to as No-deletion, No-epenthesis, etc. in
(26) as correspondence constraints, which militate against divergences of input
and output along one dimension. Informally, the general format of this type of
constraint is as follows:
(27) Correspondence constraint: the output equals the input for some
property P.
(28) Max-IO
Input segments must have output correspondents.
(No deletion)
Output: p2
The very fact that this strategy is left unemployed in Indonesian points to the
conclusion that Max-IO dominates Linearity-IO:
67
The typology of structural changes
That is, the preservation of input segments in the output has a higher priority than
the preservation of precedence relations of the input. This ranking argument is
proved correct by tableau (31):5
a. mp2ilih *!
b. + mm1,2ilih *
(32) Dep-IO
Output segments must have input correspondents.
(No epenthesis)
5
To complete formally the argument that Max-IO dominates Linearity-IO, we must show that
a third candidate [mp2ilih], which deletes input / N/, does not violate Linearity-IO. (If both
31a and 31b were to violate Linearity-IO, then Max-IO would be decisive regardless of its
ranking.) On a more formal interpretation of Linearity-IO, this constraint cannot be violated
under deletion. That is, precedence relations can only be distinct if both input segments have
correspondents in the output.
68
2.2 Nasal substitution and related effects
Output: 1 p2
The output segment [] lacks an input correspondent, in violation of Dep-IO.
The observation that the epenthetic output *[m1p2ilih] is ill-formed again
leads to a ranking argument of a type that is now familiar:
(34) Dep-IO Linearity-IO
m1p2ilih mm1,2ilih
Tableau (35) conrms the correctness of this ranking:
a. m1p2ilih *!
b. + mm1,2ilih *
a. mm1b2ilih *!
b. + mm1,2ilih *
70
2.2 Nasal substitution and related effects
Output: [nasal] p1 p2
Again a subtle technical problem arises that must be solved to make the analysis
work. If denasalization is to be effectively excluded by Ident-IO(nasal), then this
constraint must not be violated by the optimal coalescence candidate [mm1,2ilih].
We repeat the diagram for coalescence with the relevant feature specications for
[nasal] added:
Pater argues, though, that there is a major difference between denasalization (41)
and fusion (42). It is known from many processes involving [nasal] that only the
positive specication of this feature is ever phonologically active. This observa-
tion has led several researchers (Cohn 1993b, Piggott 1993, Rice 1993, Steriade
1993, Trigo 1993) to assume that [nasal] is a monovalent feature, one that has
only one (positive) value. Under denasalization, [nasal] is lost from input /N/ (see
43a). But under nasal substitution there is no such loss of [nasal] from input /N/,
nor from the input obstruent (see 43b).
direction. For example, if the input specication of some feature must be pre-
served in the output, then the direction is from I to O, as in (44):
(44) Ident-IO(nasal)
Any correspondent of an input segment specied as F must be F.
(No denasalization)
a. mp1p2ilih *!
b. + mm1,2ilih *
(49)
Input: /mN1-p2ilih/ *Nt Dep Max- Ident-IO Ident-IO Linearity-
-IO IO (nasal) (ObsVce) IO
a. + mm1,2ilih *
b. mm1b2ilih *!
c. mp1p2ilih *!
d. mp2ilih *!
e. m1p2ilih *!
f. mm1p2ilih *!
Of course, the fact that each candidate violates precisely one constraint is not a
logical necessity, but a restriction on the candidate set made for presentational
reasons only. Gen is free to propose any candidate analyses violating more than
a single constraint of the set in tableau (49). These candidates would, of course,
be suboptimal to those in (49).
For example, in addition to the candidate set evaluated in (49) we may consider
a candidate having violations of both Linearity-IO and Ident-IO(nasal). This
candidate would have both coalescence and loss of [nasal] from the input, as in
*[mp1,2ilih] (50c). We might even consider another candidate having, on top of
violations of Linearity-IO and Ident-IO(nasal), an additional violation of
Ident-IO(ObsVce), as in *[mb1,2ilih] (50d). These overly-unfaithful candidates
are simply excluded by the current hierarchy:
7
Yet another candidate, discussed by Pater at the end of his paper, involves nasalization of the
post-nasal obstruent, as in *[mm1m2ilih] with a geminate nasal. Given the current constraint
ranking this candidate is actually optimal, as it has no violations of any constraints in tableau
(49). (According to Pater this pattern is attested in Konjo, where it is partially conditioned by
the type of prex.) Note that this gemination candidate [mm1m2ilih] minimally differs from
the fusion candidate [mm1,2ilih] in the following way. In the former, the output segment [m2]
is specied as [nasal], contrary to its input correspondent /p/. In the fusion candidate, the
specication [nasal] of the output segment [m1,2] reoccurs in one of its input correspondents,
/N1/. We therefore assume that the gemination candidate is ruled out by a constraint militating
against [nasal] in an output segment whose input correspondent is not specied as [nasal]. A
constraint that has this effect is Ident-OI(nasal), that is, the reverse of Ident-IO(nasal).
73
The typology of structural changes
(50)
Input: /mN1-p2ilih / *Nt Dep Max- Ident-IO Ident-IO Linearity-
-IO IO (nasal) (ObsVce) IO
a. + mm1,2ilih *
b. mp1p2ilih *!
c. mp1,2ilih *! *
d. mb1,2ilih *! * *
Why even pay attention to these candidates? Is it not merely logical that the
worst of the worst is excluded? But actually we have arrived at an important
result here: OT predicts that the simplest change should be made to avoid the
violation of some markedness constraint. Although two, or in fact any possible
number of changes could be made in order to avoid violation of *Nt, only one
change sufces: nasal substitution (or coalescence). No more changes occur than
are strictly necessary. Prince and Smolensky (1993) have stated this as the Eco-
nomy principle of OT, repeated below from chapter 1 (29):
(51) Economy: banned options are available only to avoid violations of
higher-ranked constraints and can only be banned minimally.
In chapter 1 we have already arrived at a similar result in the discussion of
devoicing in Dutch, but then we did not take into account any alternative strat-
egies of avoiding violation of obstruent voicing in codas. Here we have found
evidence for the economy property from a case that involves a consideration of
various possible changes, rather than just one.
Let us now nd out if rule-based theory makes the same prediction of economy.
The notion of faithfulness is absent from rule-based theory altogether, so it is
difcult to see how application of a rule might be blocked in a case where an
earlier rule has already accomplished a surface target. However, rule-based the-
ory happens to arrive at the same prediction of economy for rules sharing the
same structural description. This prediction follows from rule ordering. Consider,
for example, the functionally related rules of Post-nasal voicing and Denasaliza-
tion (before voiceless obstruents). Whichever applies rst will destroy the context
of application for the other rule:
(52) Mutual blocking of functionally related rules by ordering
a. Input: /mp/ b. Input: /mp/
Post-nasal voicing mb Denasalization pp
Denasalization --- Post-nasal voicing ---
Output: [mb] Output: [pp]
74
2.2 Nasal substitution and related effects
Both cases exemplify bleeding rule orders: one rule destroys the context of
application for another rule. Rule-ordering is indeed crucial to economical out-
puts, as simultaneous application of both rules would produce *[bb], a non-
economical output. The equivalence of rule-ordering theory and OT with respect
to the mutual blocking of functionally related processes is not generally extend-
able to all cases of economy, however. In later chapters (for example, chapter 8
on syntax), we will nd that OT offers a more principled account of economy
phenomena than rule-based theory. But also see chapter 9 for a discussion of
opacity, a phenomenon which apparently falsies economy.
The next subsection will rene the analysis of nasal substitution in Indonesian by
showing the relevance of morphological context. This discussion will be based on
data of nasal plus obstruent sequences which we have not looked into so far.
8
Nasal substitution does not apply across all prexroot junctures. Certain prex boundaries are
opaque to nasal substitution, for example /mN-pr-besar/ [mmprbesar] to enlarge.
75
The typology of structural changes
This is the general ranking schema for non-application of a process within a root.
(When the markedness constraint would dominate both others, no root-effect
would occur.)
Pater goes on to propose a root-particular version of Linearity-IO:
(56) RootLin-IO
The output reects the precedence structure of the input segments of
the root, and vice versa.
This ranking correctly accounts for the blocking of root-internal fusion, as shown
in the following tableau:
a. + m1p2at *
b. m1,2at *! *
9
This ranking has been argued to be universal, but this is difcult to establish. It is only when
root-faithfulness (the more specic constraint) dominates the general constraint that any root-
faithfulness effects become apparent. Under the reverse ranking, with the general constraint
taking priority, root-faithfulness is simply suppressed.
76
2.2 Nasal substitution and related effects
Finally we need to integrate this partial ranking with the other correspondence
constraints argued for in the previous section. This in fact is quite simple. Within
roots no alternative strategies (neither deletion, epenthesis, post-nasal voicing, nor
denasalization) are ever employed to avoid violation of *Nt. Hence, all corres-
pondence constraints militating against these strategies dominate *Nt. The com-
plete ranking is given in (59).
a. + m1p2at *
b. m1,2at *!
(61) Uniformity-IO
No element of the output has multiple correspondents in the input.
(No coalescence)
a. mm1p2ilih *!
b. + mm1,2ilih *
77
The typology of structural changes
Let us now balance the pros and cons of this analysis. On the positive side, it
avoids root-specic faithfulness constraints, thereby restricting the machinery
of OT. Root-particular faithfulness constraints may eventually turn out to be
independently required but the null-hypothesis is that faithfulness constraints
are blind to morphological structure. Another advantage is avoidance of the
assumption that morphemes must be linearly ordered in the input. (In chapter 5
we will see that this assumption is problematic because of afxations whose
linear position with respect to the stem depends on output phonological structure,
such as inxation and reduplication.) On the negative side, it sets up a corres-
pondence constraint for coalescence, losing the unied account of coalescence
and metathesis.
78
2.3 The typology of *Nh
*Ni effects
Output: T2
This involves the violation of Max-IO. Hence we may infer that Max-IO is the
lowest-ranking faithfulness constraint in the hierarchy:
This ranking predicts nasal deletion, as illustrated below for the candidate set
previously evaluated in the Indonesian tableau (49). Participating segments are
indicated by symbols (N = nasal, T = voiceless obstruent, D = voiced
obstruent).
10
Recall that the Indonesian case is analysed as a fusion rather than the deletion of the obstruent
on the basis of various kinds of evidence: the stability of the obstruents place of articulation,
as well as the behaviour of substitutions under reduplication.
11
Pater suggests that nasals are weaker than obstruents in various respects. First, nasals tend
to assimilate the place of articulation of the obstruent, rather than the reverse. Second, the
deletion of nasals in Nt (rather than obstruents) suggests a similar weakness. Apparently,
faithfulness requirements for obstruents are stricter than those for nasals. To implement this
idea, Pater proposes to relativize faithfulness constraints with respect to major class, branch-
ing out Max-IO into ObsMax (No deletion of obstruents) and NasMax (No deletion of
nasals), with the former universally outranking the former.
79
The typology of structural changes
(66)
Input: / N1 T2/ *Nt Dep Ident-IO Ident-IO Linearity- Max-
-IO (nasal) (ObsVce) IO IO
a. N1,2 *!
b. N1 D2 *!
c. T1 T2 *!
d. + T2 *
e. N1T2 *!
f. N1 T2 *!
Tableau (70) evaluates various candidates that match the alternative *Nt effects.
(70)
Input: / kam1-p2a/ *Nt Dep Max- Ident- Linearity- Ident-IO
-IO IO IO(nasal) IO (ObsVce)
a. kam1,2a *!
b. + kam1b2a *
c. kap2p2a *!
d. kap2a *!
e. kam1p2a *!
f. kam1p2a *!
Puyo Pungo Quechua shares with Indonesian the phenomenon that the ban on
Nt sequences is relaxed root-internally. (An example presented by Pater is [9iki]
soot.) Of course this points to the undominated position of RootLin-IO, sim-
ilarly to Indonesian.
Output: [nasal] t1 t2
81
The typology of structural changes
(74)
Input: /maN-tunu / *Nt Dep Max- Ident-IO Linearity- Ident-
-IO IO (ObsVce) IO IO(nasal)
a. man1,2unu *!
b. man1d2unu *!
c. + mat1t2unu *
d. mat2unu *!
e. man1t2unu *!
f. man1t2unu *!
in the hierarchy. Finally, we repeat the conclusion from section 2.2.2 that OT
predicts that languages make economical use of the available repair strategies.
This prediction follows from the minimization of violation of constraints, one of
the corner stones of OT.
In the next section we will strengthen these conclusions by a discussion of the
co-occurrence of multiple *Nt effects within a single language.
12
For approaches to loan word phonology in OT, see Yip (1993) and It and Mester (1995).
83
The typology of structural changes
The rst building block is the ranking that accounts for nasal substitution, as well
as its root-internal blocking. This is copied straight away from the analysis of
Indonesian:
84
2.4 Conspiracies of nasal substitution and other processes
That is, Linearity-IO can be violated under pressure of *Nt, while RootLin-
IO cannot.
The second building block is post-nasal voicing, which we copy from the
analysis of Puyo Pungo Quechua:
That is, featural identity of voice in obstruents can be violated under pressure of
*Nt.
One question remains: what is the relative ranking of Linearity-IO and
Ident-IO(ObsVce)? This is in fact a specic form of a general analytic prob-
lem stated above: how could both Linearity-IO and Ident-IO(ObsVce) be the
lowest-ranking correspondence constraint in the hierarchy? Now we see the rele-
vance of the idea of designating fusion as the primary *Nt effect, and post-
nasal voicing as the secondary *Nt effect. This has a direct implication for
the relative ranking of both correspondence constraints involved. This is stated
below:
85
The typology of structural changes
(81)
Input: /eN1-p2ati/ RootLin- *Nt Ident- Linearity-
IO IO(ObsVce) IO
a. + em1,2ati *
b. em1b2ati *!
c. em1p2ati *!
Even though fusion disrupts the inputs linear ordering of segments, no fatal
violation of RootLin-IO follows from this. This is because the violation involves
segments belonging to different morphemes. The violation of Linearity-IO in
the optimal form [em1,2ati] is taken for granted since this is the least expensive
violation of a correspondence constraint in the hierarchy.13
Turning to the post-nasal voicing tableau, we see that RootLin-IO precludes
the option of fusion, which is otherwise the primary *Nt effect. With fusion
ruled out, the grammar is thrown back onto its secondary resources in dealing
with Nt sequences, post-nasal voicing:
(82)
Input: /sitam1p2a/ RootLin- *Nt Ident- Linearity-
IO IO(ObsVce) IO
a. sitam1,2a *! *
b. + sitam1b2a *
c. sitam1p2a *!
The fusion candidate, which was still a winner in the previous tableau, is now
taken out of the race by RootLin-IO. Of the remaining candidates, the one with
post-nasal voicing incurs the least expensive violation.
13
The difference with tableau (58) for Indonesian is that Ident-IO(ObsVce) is now included, in
a position below *Nt.
86
2.5 Conclusion: a comparison with rule-based theory
(83)
Language Strategy employed Rule
a. Indonesian Nasal substitution [son, voice] / [+nasal] ___
b. Kelantan Nasal deletion [+nasal] / ___ [son, voice]
c. (unattested) Vowel epenthesis V / [+nasal] ___ [son, voice]
d. Puyo Pungo Post-nasal voicing [son] [+voice] / [+nasal] ___
e. Mandar Denasalization [+nasal] [nasal] /___[son, voice]
As we have observed earlier, the rules of this set are functionally related, but the
nature of the relationship is very difcult to capture in rule-based theory. The
diagram below portrays four of these rules as changes from an initial state
[+nasal][voice]. The four output states are placed next to the diagram.
It is clear that this set of output states share no positive characteristics: they do
not form a natural class. All that unites them is the fact that they are not
[+nasal][voice]. However, this is a negative characteristic, which also includes
many more states than those of (84ae). Aiming at a positive common denition,
one might note that all are derivationally related to a common single input state
[+nasal][voice]. Again, this denition is not sufciently precise, as it includes
many more output states than the above set. The single denition to capture
accurately the relevant set of output states combines both criteria: it denes the
set as (i) being derivationally related to the input state [+nasal][voice], as well
as (ii) not matching the output state [+nasal][voice]. Or to put it in plain prose,
these are precisely the rules that repair the ill-formed input conguration *Nt.
Rule-based theory is able to capture the functional unity of rules only at the
expense of becoming teleological that is, by acknowledging the insight that
structural changes function to undo their structural descriptions.
The same point can be made with even more force on the basis of the func-
tionally related rules of post-nasal voicing and nasal substitution in OshiKwan-
yama. The shared goal of both rules is precisely to avoid the sequence [+nasal]
[voice]. Again, this goal is not one that can be simply inferred from the statements
of both rules. Their structural changes may differ, but both function to avoid *Nt.
Conspiracies cannot be explained by rule-based theory, but they are within the
scope of explanation of OT. This success is due to two factors. First, OT denes
structural well-formedness on surface representations, rather than on input (or
87
The typology of structural changes
Rule-ordering theory
Bromberger, Sylvain and Morris Halle (1989) Why phonology is different. Lin-
guistic Inquiry 20. 5170.
Kenstowicz, Michael and Charles Kisseberth (1979) Generative phonology:
description and theory. New York: Academic Press. [chapter 2, Phonological
rules and representations, and chapter 8, Rule interaction]
Factorial typology
Myers, Scott (1997a) OCP effects in Optimality Theory. Natural Language and
Linguistic Theory 15. 84792.
EXERCISES
88
2.5 Conclusion: a comparison with rule-based
2.5 Exercises
theory
2 Kikuyu verbs
Kikuyu (Clements 1985b) has alternations due to interacting processes which
affect place of articulation, continuancy, and voicing, as illustrated by the follow-
ing verb forms:
14
Pater, based on Newton (1972), reports that [i]n all dialects, the nasal is deleted within the
word [ii.a], and in most dialects, including Cypriot, it is deleted in an article preceding a noun,
except in slow, deliberate speech [ii.b].
89
The typology of structural changes
90
3
Syllable structure and economy
3.1 Introduction
The syllable is a major ingredient of phonological generalizations. It is crucial
in dening phonotactic patterns: well-formed sequences of segments, in particu-
lar of consonants and vowels. The syllable also governs patterns of epenthesis
and deletion, as discussed below. It supplies a level of prosodic organiza-
tion between segments and higher-level prosodic units: the foot and the pro-
sodic word (chapter 4). Finally, the syllable functions in the demarcation of
morpheme edges, as we will see below, and in dening the position and shape
of afxes (particularly inxes, discussed here, and reduplication, to be discussed
in chapter 5).
The syllable is dened as a prosodic category organizing segments in
sequences according to their sonority values. Each syllable has a sonority peak
(nucleus), usually a vowel, possibly surrounded on both sides by margin segments
of lower sonority, usually consonants (onset, coda). We make the slightly simpli-
fying assumption that syllables are organized into constituents in the following
way:
(1)
O N C O N C
t e m ple t
This at structure denes the syllable as a constituent that has a tripartite organ-
ization, consisting of an onset, a nucleus, and a coda, of which only the nucleus
is universally obligatory. We assume that consonants must be syllabied into
margins, that is onset or coda, while vowels must be syllabied as nuclei. Yet this
simple at syllabic model can be used to explain important cross-linguistic obser-
vations. Languages differ with respect to syllable structure along various dimen-
sions related to the tripartite structure of (1), the onset, nucleus, and coda, as we
91
Syllable structure and economy
will see shortly in section 3.2.1 The model will serve as the basis of the analysis
of epenthesis and deletion in section 3.35.
Syllabic well-formedness will turn out to be yet another instantiation of the
basic conict between faithfulness and markedness (or structural well-formed-
ness). The range of syllable types allowed by individual languages arise by
interactions of syllabic well-formedness constraints and segmental faithfulness
constraints. The precise nature of these interactions will be the primary con-
cern of this chapter. Again we will pay much attention to the issue of language
typology, as we did in both earlier chapters. Finally, by dening syllable well-
formedness in terms of constraint interactions, this chapter also presents the
point of departure for further applications of the syllable in stress systems and in
prosodic morphology in later chapters.
In this chapter we will review results of research on syllable structure, and place
these in the overall perspectives of the goals and issues in OT. First, in section
3.2 we will look into basic typological observations on syllable structure, and see
how OT captures these by well-formedness constraints. Section 3.2 will place
syllable-governed epenthesis and deletion in the perspective of conicts between
well-formedness and faithfulness. Our discussion will draw heavily on the typo-
logical results of Prince and Smolensky (1993), transposed into a correspondence
format. After studying epenthesis patterns in various languages, we will develop
a factorial typology of syllabic well-formedness and faithfulness constraints in
section 3.3. This will explain some major cross-linguistic properties of epenthesis,
in particular its economy. Next section 3.4 will deal with the cross-linguistically
common case of blocking of epenthesis and deletion at word edges. This will lead
us to the introduction of the concept of alignment (McCarthy and Prince 1993a),
the matching of (morphological and prosodic) edges, enforced by constraints.
Section 3.5 addresses the quality of epenthetic segments, focussing on their min-
imal markedness and contextual colouring, relating these properties to the discus-
sion of segment inventories of chapter 1. Phonotactic functions of the syllable, in
particular coda conditions, will be the topic of section 3.6. Finally, section 3.7
will summarize the results.
92
3.2 The basic syllable typology
have revealed solid cross-linguistic preferences for certain syllable types over
other types. In this section we will focus on a well-known cross-linguistic asym-
metry of onsets and codas: syllables prefer to begin with a consonant, whereas
they prefer to end in a vowel.
Following standard terminology, we will refer to syllable-initial consonants as
the onset of the syllable. The important typological nding with respect to
onsets is that all languages allow them, and none exclude them. That is:
Accordingly languages fall into two large classes: those allowing onset-less syl-
lables, such as Japanese, Diola-Fogny, Ponapean, and English, and those that do
not allow onset-less syllables, such as Temiar, Axininca Campa, and Arabic (It
1989). The crucial point is that no languages are known that disallow onsets.
Some languages actually supply an onset when no consonant is available in
the input. Such epenthesis of a consonant in onset position occurs in Axininca
Campa (Payne 1981, It 1989, McCarthy and Prince 1993b), see the examples in
(3).
Note that [t]-epenthesis applies only in (3a), where two vowels are adjacent in
the input, while there is no need for epenthesis in (3b), where the input supplies
a consonant as an onset to the nal syllable. We will return to this pattern of
consonant epenthesis in section 3.3.2, where we will analyse it as an interaction
of syllabic well-formedness and faithfulness constraints. Here we will focus
on the syllabic well-formedness aspect, the avoidance of onset-less syllables, to
which we now turn.
We conclude from the typological results and epenthesis data that the presence
of an onset is an unmarked situation as compared to its absence. This is expressed
in the structural well-formedness constraint Onset (It 1989, Prince and Smolen-
sky 1993):
(4) Onset
*[ V (Syllables must have onsets.)
This constraint requires that syllables must not begin with vowels; it is satised
only by syllables that have an initial consonant, or onset. Therefore languages
in which Onset is undominated have obligatory onsets. Finally, Onset is
93
Syllable structure and economy
grounded in the articulatory and perceptual systems: the best starting point for
a vowel is a preceding consonant (rather than another vowel).
At the right margin of the syllable, the unmarked situation is the reverse, because
here the lack of a consonant is universally preferred to the presence of one:
Again, languages fall into two large classes, according to whether they allow or
disallow codas. For example, Arabic, Tunica, and English allow codas, while
Fijian, Mazateco, and Cayuvava disallow codas (Blevins 1995). Crucially, no
languages are known in which syllables must have codas.
As before, languages may employ strategies to repair imperfect syllables,
such as the epenthesis of a vowel in order to avoid a coda. Such epenthesis occurs
in Boumaa Fijian (Dixon 1988), a language in which syllables strictly conform to
the shapes CV or V. Consider the following words, all realizations of English
loans ending in consonants:
Both language typology and the wide-spread occurrence of processes which avoid
codas suggest that the unmarked situation is for syllables to lack codas. This
unmarked situation is encoded in the following well-formedness constraint.
(7) No-Coda
*C ] (Syllables are open.)
This constraint requires that syllables must not end in a consonant, or coda.
Languages in which No-Coda is undominated have open syllables only. Like
Onset, this constraint is grounded in the perceptual system: coda consonants,
particularly those standing before another consonant, tend to be unreleased, and
hence lack perceptual cues that are present in prevocalic consonants, which are
released (Ohala 1990, Steriade 1995b).
In sum, the two syllable form constraints Onset and No-Coda evaluate the
four logically possible syllable types as below:
94
3.2 The basic syllable typology
This is not a tableau: observe that the constraints are not in a conicting relation-
ship, but merely cross-classify the four logical possibilities. The conclusion to be
drawn from this table is that CV is the perfect syllable shape, while all remain-
ing shapes {CVC, V, VC} are less perfect, by having a coda, or lacking an onset,
or having both defects.
This follows from the fact that both well-formedness constraints, Onset and
No-Coda, favour an onset syllabication of (10a) over the alternative coda
syllabication of (10b):
a. + ba.ba
b. bab.a *! *!
2
In the literature two languages have been reported to be exceptional to this generalization, by
syllabifying a single intervocalic consonant backward as the coda of the preceding syllable.
Both cases, Oykangand (Sommer 1981) and Barra Gaelic (Borgstrm 1937), are doubtful,
however. See for discussion Clements (1986), McCarthy and Prince (1993b), Blevins (1995).
95
Syllable structure and economy
complex codas, that is, codas consisting of two or more consonants. In such a
language, codas must be simple, that is, consist of one consonant.
Observe that the use of the terminology complex and simple already sug-
gests a markedness relation in this respect: indeed many languages restrict the
complexity of syllable margins complex onsets are universally marked as com-
pared to simple onsets; complex codas are marked as compared to simple codas.
The unmarked status of simple onsets and codas is supported by various kinds of
evidence.
First consider the implicational universals below:
3
Lynch (1974: 87) reports that word-initial consonant-glide-clusters are permitted.
4
The actual form is [kam.np.R.npn]. Here /a / has undergone a process of rounding into []
applying when /a / is adjacent to a velarized labial (Lynch 1974: 97).
5
We focus on obligatory epenthetic vowels, abstracting away from optional epenthetic vowels
that may be inserted in clusters of two consonants before unstressed vowels (Lynch 1974: 84).
96
3.2 The basic syllable typology
Complex onsets CV, CVC, CCV, CCVC CV, CVC, CVCC, CCV, CCVC, CCVCC
allowed (Spanish,6 Sedang) (English, Totonac)
This shows that two structural well-formedness constraints are needed to capture
margin complexity: one for onsets, and another for codas. These constraints are
stated below:
(15) *ComplexOns
*[ CC (Onsets are simple)
(16) *ComplexCod
*CC ] (Codas are simple)
Any language in which *ComplexOns is undominated has simple onsets only (this
is the case in languages such as Japanese, Yokuts, Finnish, and Tunica). And any
language in which *ComplexCod is undominated allows no complex codas, if it
allows codas at all (as is the case in Japanese, Yokuts, Spanish, and Sedang).7
6
Spanish rarely allows complex codas word-nally, e.g. biceps (Harris 1983). Another language
of this type is Canela-Krah (Popjes and Popjes 1986).
7
Whether or not a language has codas depends on the ranking of No-Coda, the constraint ruling
out codas regardless of their complexity.
97
Syllable structure and economy
duress of faithfulness. In the next section we will take a detailed look at the
interaction of faithfulness and syllabic well-formedness.
The epenthetic output [no.ko.ma.ti] contains a segment that has no input coun-
terpart, a violation of faithfulness. Still, this is preferred to the faithful candidate
*[no.ko.ma.i], which has a syllable without an onset, thus violating Onset. We
recognize a now-familiar theme, the conict of well-formedness (here, avoid-
ance of marked syllable structure) and faithfulness (here avoidance of lexically
unsponsored segments). In sum, epenthesis involves a resolution of this conict
at the expense of faithfulness: the costs of inserting a (non-underlying) segment
are less than those of imperfect syllable structure. This section will develop an
optimality model of epenthesis capturing this insight, which has a range of typo-
logical consequences. Before looking into the model, we need to discuss briey
its theoretical origins.
98
3.3 Epenthesis and the conict of well-formedness and faithfulness
(18)
O N C O N O N O N
n o k o m a t i [nokomati]
In this model epenthesis is a fully automatic consequence of syllabication, a
spell-out of an empty templatic position. Accordingly there are no rules of epen-
thesis, but only rules of syllabication enforcing the syllable template. Whether
or not epenthesis applies in a language only depends on the template: this may
require specic positions to be obligatory. Anticipating OT constraint ranking, It
(1989) argues that templates enforce universal syllabication principles with dif-
ferent strengths. For example, languages such as Axininca Campa (which enforce
onsets by consonant epenthesis) use a strengthened version of the Onset Principle
(avoid onset-less syllables). This version It dubs the Strict Onset Principle:
onset-less syllables are impossible. Thus, cross-linguistic variation in onset
epenthesis is due to a single binary parameter: languages select either the weak
Onset Principle or the strong Strict Onset Principle.
Prince and Smolensky (1993) take these ideas to their logical conclusion, deriving
relative strength of templatic principles from constraint ranking. In their Opti-
mality model, output constraints assume the function of dening syllabication
and epenthesis. The grammar is an evaluation device selecting the most harmonic
output from an innite candidate set, according to a language-specic ranking
of universal constraints. OT does away with language-specic templates: cross-
linguistic variation in epenthesis patterns is explained by variation in constraint
ranking. For example, Prince and Smolensky argue that in languages enforcing
syllable onsets by consonant epenthesis, Onset takes precedence over the faith-
fulness constraint Fill, requiring that syllable positions must be lled with
underlying segments. Note that Fill is indeed violated in the output (18). This
output is unfaithful to its underlying segments as it contains a syllabic position
that is left unlled by an underlying segment.
Prince and Smolenskys model is known as Containment Theory, after its cen-
tral assumption that no element may be literally removed from the input form.
The input is thus contained in every candidate output, including those candidate
outputs in which it is left unpronounced. In Containment Theory, the deletion of
a segment does not involve its removal from the output (this is ruled out by
containment). Instead the input segment is left unparsed by a syllable, hence
phonetically uninterpreted (compare Stray Erasure in McCarthy 1979, Steriade
1982, It 1986). Analogously to Fill, deletion is penalized by a faithfulness
99
Syllable structure and economy
O N O N C
m a p [ma] a p [tap]
Correspondence Theory (McCarthy and Prince 1995a) drops Prince and Smolen-
skys notion of containment. That is, it is no longer required that the input be
contained in each output candidate. Consequently epenthetic segments are no
longer viewed as the phonetic interpretations of empty positions, but rather as
(full-edged) output segments that have no counterparts in the input. This cor-
rectly predicts that the feature contents of epenthetic segments may participate
in phonological processes (Davis 1995). The faithfulness role of containment,
restricting divergence between input and output (penalizing overparsing and
underparsing), is transferred to correspondence. Correspondence, as we learned
in chapter 1, is a relation between pairs of segments in the input and output. It is
subject to constraints requiring various kinds of congruence between segments in
input and output (such as identity, linearity, etc.). In spite of the differences
between Containment Theory and Correspondence Theory, the latter preserves the
insight that epenthesis and deletion both reect the dominance of syllabic well-
formedness over faithfulness. In the following subsections we will develop a
correspondence model of epenthesis capturing this insight.
(20) Dep-IO
Output segments must have input correspondents. (No epenthesis)
Output n o k o m a t i
Other examples of Axininca Campa show that epenthetic [t] occurs between every
pair of vowels that are in adjacent morphemes in the input:
Epenthesis in onsets shows that Axininca ranks Dep-IO below Onset, the struc-
tural well-formedness constraint whose violation epenthesis avoids. Onset epen-
thesis involves the following ranking:
8
Dep-IO was introduced in chapter 1, but left unillustrated.
101
Syllable structure and economy
a. + no.ko.ma.ti *
b. no.ko.ma.i *!
(26) Max-IO
Input segments must have output correspondents. (No deletion)
Importantly, Max-IO does not require that an input segment and its correspond-
ing output segment have identical feature content. (This requirement is made by
another faithfulness constraint introduced in chapter 1: Ident-IO.) All that is
required by Max-IO is that for every output segment there is some input segment
corresponding to it. This is tantamount to a ban on the deletion of input segments
hence Max-IO is the anti-deletion constraint.
Consider the following diagram, which shows that Max-IO is actually violated
in the output candidate *[no.ko.ma], as the input segment /i/ has no output
counterpart:
9
Rather arbitrarily, we consider the deletion of a sufx vowel, rather than a root vowel both
options are equivalent with respect to the violation of faithfulness involved. But see chapter 2
for McCarthy and Princes proposal that root faithfulness outranks afx faithfulness.
102
3.3 Epenthesis and the conict of well-formedness and faithfulness
Output n o k o m a
Compare this diagram with the one in (21), to see that epenthesis and deletion
are mirror-image cases from the viewpoint of input correspondence.
The fact that Axininca Campa prefers consonant epenthesis to vowel deletion
tells us that Max-IO dominates Dep-IO. The former is not violable under duress
of Onset, whereas the latter is. Combining our conclusions, we arrive at the
following total ranking:
This ranking is illustrated by the following tableau, which contains both candid-
ates of the preceding tableau, plus the deletion candidate (29b):
a. + no.ko.ma.ti *
b. no.ko.ma *!
c. no.ko.ma.i *!
Note that each candidate incurs a violation of one constraint. As we may predict
from the discussion in chapter 2, the optimal output (29a) violates the lowest-
ranking faithfulness constraint, here Dep-IO. The lowest-ranking faithfulness con-
straint is, by denition, the one whose violation is least expensive. It is violated
in order to avoid violation of both higher-ranking constraints, Onset and Max-
IO, whose mutual ranking is irrelevant here.
The insight that the lowest-ranking constraint determines the outcome allows
us to construct a factorial typology of these three constraints. Only three rankings
need to be considered, one for each constraint in lowest-ranking position:
Ranking (30a) produces the case of onset epenthesis, where Dep-IO is violated,
of which Axininca Campa is an example. Ranking (30b) is the case of vowel
deletion in hiatus, to avoid an onset-less syllable, violating Max-IO. This is also
a cross-linguistically common strategy occurring in languages such as Modern
Greek and Yokuts. Finally, ranking (30c) represents languages that disallow dele-
tion and epenthesis as strategies to avoid onset-less syllables: when all strategies
to attain unmarked structures are blocked, marked structures are necessarily
allowed. This happens at the expense of syllabic well-formedness (Onset).
This is also a cross-linguistically common case, occurring in English and other
languages.
In sum, we have found that the range of syllable structures of a language depends
on the interaction between syllabic well-formedness and faithfulness. In the next
section we will extend the factorial typology to all four constraints that were used
so far: Onset, No-Coda, Dep-IO, and Max-IO. This extended typology will
explain some major cross-linguistic properties of epenthesis and deletion.
a. + [A]
b. [B] *!
a. + ba.ba
b. ba.ba * *
105
Syllable structure and economy
The epenthetic candidate (34b) is less harmonic than its non-epenthetic compet-
itor (34a) in two respects, as it violates both No-Coda and Dep-IO. Conversely
no well-formedness constraints are satised by (34b) which (34a) violates. This
means that (34b) will always be less harmonic than (34a), in any grammar,
regardless of the ranking of the constraints. (Since any violation will be fatal to
34b, no exclamation marks have been added.)
By the same reasoning, no vowel will be epenthesized adjacent to another
vowel, since that produces unnecessary violations of both Onset and Dep-IO:
a. + ba.ba
b. ba.i.ba * *
a. + ba.ba
b. ba.i.ba *!*
10
In fact, languages are known in which the epenthesis of an entire syllable is forced by
superordinate prosodic well-formedness constraints. For example, syllable epenthesis may
augment a monosyllabic form in order to satisfy a high-ranking minimal word constraint to
the effect that every word be disyllabic; cf. McCarthy and Prince (1993b). See chapter 4.
106
3.3 Epenthesis and the conict of well-formedness and faithfulness
element, its addition is ruled out by faithfulness constraints. This is what occurs
in tableau (36). There is no bonus for addition of the structurally perfect epen-
thetic syllable in the columns below the well-formedness constraints Onset and
No-Coda, but simply a lack of marks, indicating an absence of violation of these
constraints. In this respect, the epenthetic candidate (36b) fares no better than the
faithful candidate (36a). In the end, it is faithfulness that swings the balance in
favour of (36a).
The third prediction is that epenthesis always applies minimally. That is, no more
segments are epenthesized than are strictly required to minimize the violation of
syllabic well-formedness. This prediction is actually a corollary of both predic-
tions made above. Epenthesis serves to minimize the violation of well-formedness
constraints. Any additional epenthesis on top of this minimum, which yields no
further gains in well-formedness, is unnecessary hence it is blocked by faith-
fulness, as we will illustrate in the next section.
Note that all suboptimal righthand forms are perfectly structured strings of CV
syllables. All syllables have (simple) onsets, while none have codas. But in spite
of their structural perfection, these candidates fall short of being selected. Appar-
ently, vowel epenthesis is not available in Lenakel as a general strategy to avoid
codas, but only as a more restricted strategy to avoid complex codas and onsets.
To put it differently, input faithfulness takes priority over avoidance of codas:
(40) Vowel epenthesis unavailable to avoid codas
Dep-IO No-Coda
In sum, the faithfulness constraint Dep-IO is sandwiched between two syllabic
structural well-formedness constraints, *Complex and No-Coda:
(41) Preliminary ranking for Lenakel vowel epenthesis
*Complex Dep-IO No-Coda
Tableau (42) considers ve candidates differing only in the number of epenthetic
vowels. At the top we nd the most faithful candidate (42a), which has no viola-
tions of Dep-IO; at the bottom is the structurally perfect candidate (42e), which
has no violations of well-formedness constraints *Complex and No-Coda. The
winner, (42c), stands in between both extremes. Still there is no trade-off
between faithfulness and well-formedness, as everything follows from strict
domination.
a. kamn.Rann *!* **
b. kam.np.Rann *! * **
c. + kam.np.Ra.npn ** **
d. ka.mp.np.Ra.npn ***! *
e. ka.mp.np.Ra.np.np ***!*
Candidate (42c) is optimal since it has the minimal number of violations of Dep-
IO that are necessary to avoid violations of *Complex. This minimum number of
violations is two: fewer would not do to avoid complex margins (42ab), while
more violations are ruled out by faithfulness (42de).11 In conclusion, epenthesis
is economical no more vowels are inserted than are strictly necessary to avoid
violations of syllable well-formedness.
11
Of course, the prediction that epenthesis applies minimally is relativized to the grammar. In
Lenakel minimal has a different meaning than in a language which completely avoids codas
(due to undominated No-Coda).
108
3.3 Epenthesis and the conict of well-formedness and faithfulness
That No-Coda is still active despite the fact that it is dominated is shown by
the tableau of [tp.na.
l]:
a. tna.
l *! *
b. + tp.na.
l * *
c. pt.na.
l * **!
d. tp.na.
.lp **!
109
Syllable structure and economy
What blocks epenthesis initially? Naively, one might be tempted to relax the
constraint Onset in word-initial syllables. This would lead to a specic version
of this constraint:
However, (46) is not a very illuminating way to approach this pattern. The rst
problem is its relation to the general constraint Onset, which has no such excep-
tion clause. If this is replaced by (46), then we can no longer explain the fact
that in some languages all syllables must have onsets, regardless of their position
in the word. Alternatively, if (46) is interpreted as independent of the general
constraint, then a redundancy problem arises: the same requirement (syllables
must have onsets) is stated by two separate constraints in the universal inventory.
Such a redundancy should be avoided, as it amounts to the loss of generalization.
A second problem is that (46) fails to explain why the exception clause for onsets
holds for word-initial syllables, that is, for word-initial position. There is much
evidence (from a range of phenomena other than epenthesis) that the left edge of
the word is respected by phonological changes. This inertness of the left word
edge is expressed by the constraint Align-L (after McCarthy and Prince 1993a):13
13
McCarthy and Prince (1993a) state Align-L on the Stem, rather than on the Grammatical
Word.
110
3.3 Epenthesis and the conict of well-formedness and faithfulness
(47) Align-L
The left edge of the Grammatical Word coincides with the left edge
of the PrWd.
tosampi
Morphological structure
GrWd
Note that the left edge of the Grammatical Word is dened by the initial segment
of the stem [o], whereas the left edge of the Prosodic Word is dened by the
epenthetic segment [t]. Hence both edges do not coincide, in violation of Align-L.
The relation between [t]-epenthesis and its blocking in word-initial position now
becomes clear. It is just another interaction of conicting, violable constraints:
alignment takes priority over avoidance of onset-less syllables. This is stated in
the ranking in (49), which includes the subranking Onset Dep-IO from (23)
above:
Having factored out the left-edge effect, we may now dispense with the odd
exception clause in the Onset constraint (46), restoring this constraint to its
original generality.
A translation of (49) into a prose statement would read as follows:
111
Syllable structure and economy
As Prince and Smolensky (1993) point out, such exception clauses are highly
common in generalizations about linguistic patterns. OT is ideally suited to cap-
ture such situations. Constraints are the substance of the theory, expressing lin-
guistic generalizations without qualication about exception clauses. The latter
function, encoding the relative scopes of generalizations, is attributed to the con-
straint hierarchy. Therefore, constraints can be highly general, as long as they are
violable as well.
A full account of the Axininca epenthetic pattern should also address the ranking
of Max-IO. Earlier we found that Max-IO and Onset were both undominated,
but that was before the initial blocking data in (45) had entered the picture, telling
us that Onset is dominated. However, we still have no reason to demote Max-
IO, and we will keep it at the top of the hierarchy, where it sits together with
Align-L:
a. + o.sam.pi *
b. to.sam.pi *! *
c. sam.pi *!
The ranking Max-IO Onset has no negative consequences for the analysis
presented in section 3.3.2. This ranking correctly predicts that vowel deletion is
not allowed as a strategy to avoid onset-less syllables in Axininca Campa.
This question is now answered as follows: both starred output forms violate
alignment at their right edges. A word-nal epenthetic vowel is misaligning since
it breaks PrWds coincidence with the right edge of the Grammatical Word. This
112
3.3 Epenthesis and the conict of well-formedness and faithfulness
ar
a r kh ar
ar k kam n Ra n n kam n Ran n
a. ar.
arkh *! **
b. + ar.
a.rpkh * **
c. ar.
ar.
p *! * **
d. a.rp.
a.rpkh **! *
e. a.rp.
a.rp.
p *! ***
113
Syllable structure and economy
(56) /t-n-ak-ol/
PrWd PrWd
Prosodic organization
tna
l tna
l
Morphological organization
GrWd GrWd
(57)
Input: /t-n-ak-ol / Align-L Align-R *Complex Dep-IO No-Coda
a. tna.
l *! *
b. + tp.na.
l * *
c. pt.na.
l *! **
d. tp.na.
.lp *! **
(This does not affect the ranking argument given earlier for Dep-IO No-Coda,
because epenthesis never applies to avoid codas, regardless of position.)
Having ruled out epenthesis at both edges of the word, we now turn to yet another
potential output form for (52b), *[ka.mpn.Ra.npn], which differs from the optimal
output [kam.np.Ra.npn] only in the position of the leftmost epenthetic vowel. The
diagram below shows both candidates:
114
3.3 Epenthesis and the conict of well-formedness and faithfulness
(58) /kam-n-Ran-n/
kam n Ra n n ka mn Ra n n
What we see is that epenthesis harmonizes with the morphological structure
of the word in the following way: ideally each morpheme begins a new syl-
lable; epenthesis helps to attain this goal by inserting a vowel directly after a
morpheme-initial consonant, rather than before it.15 This is yet another form of
morpho-prosodic alignment, now between the edges of morphemes and those
of syllables. More precisely, we may state this as:
(59) Align-Morph-L
The left edge of a morpheme coincides with the left edge of a
syllable.
If this were undominated, then no syllable would contain segmental material
belonging to different morphemes. (For maximally one morpheme can be left-
aligned with a syllable.) Considering the syllabication of the optimal output
[kam.np.Ra.npn], we see that Align-Morph-L cannot be undominated. Here the
nal morpheme /-n / is not left-aligned with a syllable, but instead shares a syl-
lable with the nal consonant of the preceding morpheme /-Ran-/.
115
Syllable structure and economy
Next, Align-Morph-L can also be ranked with respect to Dep-IO. The argument
is based on the forms [ar.
a.rpkh] and [tp.na.
l]. Both forms violate Align-
Morph-L to some extent. To repair the misalignment of morphemes and
syllable edges, one might attempt to add epenthetic syllables, resulting in [a.rpkh-
a.rpkh] and [tp-np-akh-l]. But this leads to fatal additional violations of Dep-IO:
a. kamn.Rann *!* ** **
b. + kam.np.Ra.npn ** * **
c. ka.mpn.Ra.npn ** **! **
d. kam.np.Ran.np *! ** **
116
3.4 Generalized Alignment
a. ar.
arkh *! * **
b. ar
.arkh **! **
c. + ar.
a.rpk h
* * **
d. a.rp
.a.rpkh **! **
(65)
Input: /t-n-ak-ol/ Align- Align- *Complex Dep-IO Align- No-
L R Morph-L Coda
a. tna.
l *! *** *
b. tna
.l *! ** **
c. + tp.na.
l * ** *
d. tp.np.a
.l **! **
This concludes the analysis of epenthesis in Lenakel. We have seen how the
interaction of three types of constraints (syllabic well-formedness, faithfulness,
and morpho-prosodic alignment) produces a complex pattern of epenthesis. Our
most important ndings are economy (epenthesis only when necessary) and
alignment (the edges of morphological constituents and prosodic constituents
must coincide). The next subsection elaborates on the second nding, extending
the notion of alignment to new applications.
(Selkirk 1986, Selkirk and Shen 1990). This edge-based theory of the syntax
phonology interface was adopted into OT by McCarthy and Prince (1993a), who
claim that the prosodymorphology interface should be dened exclusively in
terms of alignment constraints. Yet, alignment not only serves to match edges of
morphological and prosodic categories, but also edges of phonological constitu-
ents (syllable, foot, PrWd). In recent OT the notion of alignment has assumed a
range of applications that goes far beyond the types of cases seen above.
In all alignment constraints seen so far, Align-L, Align-R, and Align-
Morph-L, the edge of a grammatical category (grammatical word or morpheme)
is paired with the edge of a prosodic category (prosodic word or syllable). See
(66):
Four aspects of this constraint format merit discussion: (i) categories that may
appear in alignment constraints, (ii) the choice of the edges, (iii) the order in
which the categories appear in the constraint, and (iv) how to evaluate violations
of alignment constraints.
First, the categories Cat1 and Cat2 range over the alphabets of grammatical and
phonological categories, for example:
118
3.4 Generalized Alignment
16
An example is Align-Afx (McCarthy and Prince 1993b) which aligns the left edge of a sufx
with the right edge of a PrWd.
119
Syllable structure and economy
The scope difference will turn out to have considerable empirical effects which,
however, we will not be able to illustrate until chapter 4 on metrical theory.
However, here we may already fathom the potential relevance of the asymmetry
by spelling out the conditions under which the different constraints in (69ab) are
satised or violated.
Consider the schematic examples in (70). The rst constraint, Align (Stem, R,
, R), is violated by any stem whose right edge fails to coincide with the right
edge of some syllable. This is the case in (70c), where the rightmost syllable is
separated from the right edge of the stem by one or more extrasyllabic segments.
In (70d) no syllable is present, in which case violation is self-explanatory. The
constraint is satised in (70a) and (70b).
tableau contained multiple violation marks, this was always due to multiple
independent violations of an absolute constraint in a single candidate, rather than
to gradient evaluation. Alignment constraints are typically evaluated gradiently,
measuring the distance between both edges referred to in the constraint.
Gradient evaluation implies that some unit must be specied by which viola-
tions are measured. If an alignment constraint requires two edges to match, then
are violations of the constraint measured in segments, syllables, or perhaps fea-
tures? No general answer to this question has been given in the literature, and it
has been proposed that the element type is established on a constraint-by-
constraint basis. However, the segment is by far the most common element meas-
ured by alignment constraints, and it seems to be a default. Apparently distances
are measured in syllables only by alignment constraints which refer to feet, locat-
ing stresses with respect to edges, which will be discussed in chapter 4.17
17
It has been suggested that alignment constraints which refer to units of a prosodic category
Cn are evaluated by units of the next-lower category in the prosodic hierarchy, Cn1. Syllable
and foot indeed stand in such a relation. See chapter 4 for the analysis of word edge effects
in metrical systems, and its relation with extrametricality.
121
Syllable structure and economy
The prex skips over the initial onset, settling itself between a consonant and
vowel in the base, with which it integrates into a well-formed sequence of sylla-
bles. (Tagalog is a language allowing for complex onsets and for codas.) What
inxation apparently avoids is an output in which the vowel of -um- lacks an
onset, while its consonant syllabies as a coda, as in *um-tawag. Avoidance of
ill-formed syllables is what drives -um-inxation.
Apparently the morphology (um-afxation) depends on the prosody of the
output. This is an important insight and we will see that it can be easily expressed
in OT, because of its parallelism. Constraints of morphological well-formedness
are ranked in a single hierarchy together with constraints of syllabic well-formed-
ness. Both types of constraint evaluate the same candidate set, of which a single
candidate is selected as optimal with respect to the total, integrated hierarchy.
Here we can discern a morphological constraint making requirements on the
position of -um- in the word, which conicts with constraints of syllabic well-
formedness. As always, conicts are resolved in conformity with the core prin-
ciples of strict domination and minimal violation.
The analysis by Prince and Smolensky (1993) of this pattern is strikingly sim-
ple, and directly encodes the dominance of prosody over morphological require-
ments. The prosodic constraint that comes into play here is No-Coda, repeated
below from (7):
(72) No-Coda
*C ] (Syllables are open.)
(73) Align-um-L
Align the left edge of -um- with the left edge of the PrWd.
In fact, this is nothing but the requirement that -um- is a prex. This require-
ment is stated in the form of an alignment of -um- with the Prosodic Word. Like
other constraints, this morphological constraint is in principle violable. As we will
see, the violability of Align-um-L is the key to its distribution. All we need to
assume is that this is a gradient constraint, that evaluates candidates as to their
relative success in placing -um- at the left edge.
The following ranking of No-Coda and Align-um-L produces the mixed effect
of inxation in some contexts, and of prexation in other contexts:
18
Align-um-L renames Prince and Smolenskys Edgemost(um, L).
122
3.4 Generalized Alignment
a. um.grad.wet ***!
b. gum.rad.wet ***! g
c. + gru.mad.wet ** gr
d. gra.um.dwet ** g r a!
e. gra.dum.wet ** g r a! d
f. grad.wu.met ** g r a! d w
g. grad.we.umt ** g r a! d w e
h. grad.we.tum ** g r a! d w e t
Candidate (75a), where -um- is a genuine prex, has three violations of No-
Coda, one more than necessary. (The present tableau does not evaluate any
candidates having fewer than two violations of No-Coda, since these would
violate other top-ranking faithfulness constraints, such as Max-IO and Dep-IO.)
No improvement with respect to No-Coda is reached in candidate (75b), which
inxes -um- between the rst and second consonants of the base. Each of the
remaining candidates (75ch) incurs two violations of No-Coda. Among these,
the one is selected that minimally violates the next constraint down the hierarchy,
Align-um-L. This is a gradient constraint, violations of which are measured by
segments lying between the left word edge and the afx -um-. The optimal output,
(75c), minimally violates Align-um-L, hence maximally respects the prexal
status of -um-. All remaining candidates (75dh) violate Align-um-L to a larger
degree than is strictly necessary.
As mentioned earlier, this analysis is based on parallel evaluation of prosodic
and morphological constraints. Any theory that separates out the evaluation of
morphological and prosodic well-formedness to different levels cannot capture
the same generalization. For example, compare the way in which rule theory might
deal with the Tagalog pattern. This analysis would involve extraprosodicity of
123
Syllable structure and economy
the word onset, rendering it invisible to afxation. Next, -um- is prexed to the
residue (here the word minus the word onset), which begins with a vowel. Finally,
the word onset is rendered visible again, producing the effect of um-inxation.
This analysis leaves unexpressed the relation between the prosodic shape of the
afx, -um- (VC), and its surface distribution, immediately after the word onset.
Extraprosodicity is unable to make this connection, since it is formally separ-
ated from the afxation that it serves to potentiate. Under this analysis the fact
that the inx has the skeletal shape VC is an arbitrary property. For example,
an extraprosodicity analysis handles with equal ease an imaginary pattern for a
hypothetical inx with the shape CV, say -mu-, for example in mu-abot, t-mu-
awag, gr-mu-adwet.
One might argue that such inxations never arise because they would seriously
violate the phonotactic principles of the language (more specically, the require-
ments that onsets be maximally binary, and that hiatus is ill-formed). However,
this is precisely the point to be made against the extraprosodicity analysis: it fails
to express the overall contribution of prosodic well-formedness to the distribution
of the inx -um-.
124
3.5 The quality of epenthetic segments
125
Syllable structure and economy
Of course, this is only a schematic typology. In reality the factors in this typo-
logy are not unary, but composite. Context-free markedness comprises the set
of individual featural markedness constraints, grouped in hierarchies that are to
some extent universal. And the factor context-sensitive markedness denotes a
set of constraints whose ranking is, again, partly universal. The interaction will
usually not result in a complete victory of one factor over the other, but a more
fragmented picture will be presented, with contributions made by both context-
free and contextual factors. Once again we turn to Lenakel for exemplication.
19
As well as after /v/. This surprising fact becomes more natural upon considering the phonetics
of /v/: a high central glide with varying, though weak, amounts of bilabial articulation
(Lynch 1974: 21). That is, /v/ shares both its centrality and height with [].
126
3.5 The quality of epenthetic segments
c. /k-ar-pkom/ kar.bq.
m theyre heavy (p. 90)
d. /r-m-n/ r.m.qn he was afraid of him/it (p. 88)
First note that both epenthetic vowels are [low, +back, round], all featurally
unmarked values. More formally, epenthetic vowels never violate any of the fol-
lowing context-free markedness constraints:
To pinpoint the difference between epenthetic and lexical vowels, let us address
the issue of what licenses lexical vowels such as low [a], round [o][u], or front
[e][i] in Lenakel. The answer resides in featural faithfulness to the input. What
makes an epenthetic vowel different from a lexical vowel is that only the latter
has input specications, among which are values such as [+low], [+round], or
[back]. Lexical vowels are faithful to their input as Ident-IO constraints for
different features outrank context-free markedness constraints:
20
Unmarkedness of epenthetic vowels arises in underspecication theory (Archangeli 1988) by
featural emptiness. That is, an epenthetic segment is maximally underspecied.
127
Syllable structure and economy
Next, what causes the contextual variation in vowel height among the epen-
thetic vowels? This variation reects interaction of a context-free markedness
constraint with a contextual markedness constraint. This interaction, which was
schematically presented in (79b) as the ranking of contextual colouring,
involves a pair of markedness constraints. In Lenakel, the dominated member
of the pair is a context-free markedness constraint, violated in contexts where
[] appears. This is a constraint militating against high vowels:
(85) + high]
*[+
(86) Cor-high
Coronals are followed by high vowels.
Cor-high sets up the pressure under which *[+high] may be violated. Accord-
ingly, it must dominate *[+high]:
Integrating this interaction with the current ranking, we arrive at the complete
hierarchy:
(89)
Input: /t-n-ak-ol/ Ident-IO *[+low] *[+round] *[back] Cor-high *[+high]
a. t.na.
l * * **!
b. + tp.na.
l * * * *
c. ti.na.
l * * *! * *
d. tu.na.
l * **! * *
e. ta.na.
l **! * **
f. tp.n.
l *!* **
The bottom candidate (89f) represents the reduction of the input vowels /a/ and
/o/ to [] and [], respectively. These are the least marked vowels, taking into
account contextual factors for this form. Such a reduction is excluded by Ident-
IO, a shorthand notation for three Ident-IO constraints with respect to individual
features [low][round][back].
Next consider tableau (90) of the form [tr.mn]. Again a subset of candidates
(90ce), containing either front, rounded, or low epenthetic vowels, are excluded
by the context-free constraints. The bottom candidate (90f) fatally violates featu-
ral faithfulness. The remaining pair (90ab) are evaluated vacuously by Cor-high
since only the lexical vowel violates it, while the epenthetic vowel is not in the
relevant context (following a coronal). These candidates are submitted to the next-
lower constraint, *[+high], which selects the former (90a) because its epenthetic
vowel [] is non-high:
(90)
Input: /to-rm-n/ Ident- *[+low] *[+round] *[back] Cor-high *[+high]
IO
a. + tr.mqn * *
b. tr.mpn * * *!
c. tr.min * *! * *
d. tr.mun **! * *
e. tr.man *! * *
f. tr.mqn *! *
This tableau shows that schwa [] is the minimally unmarked vowel with respect
to the context-free markedness constraints. Hence, it appears as the epenthetic
vowel wherever possible: wherever contextual constraints do not stand in its way.
129
Syllable structure and economy
21
Steriade (1995a) mentions Hindi, Hungarian, Basque, Maltese Arabic, and Tiberian Hebrew
as languages in which epenthetic vowels have lexical properties.
130
3.6 Coda conditions
(92) Coda-Cond
*Place]
The intended interpretation of this constraint is: a coda cannot license place
features.22 That is, a coda can contain place features only when these are simul-
taneously associated with a syllable position outside the coda, such as the second
syllables onset in (93a):
(93) a. b.
C V C C V C V C C V
k a p a k a k p a
22
This slightly simplies the discussion, abstracting away from the Linking Constraint, which
in It (1989) accounts for the distinction between (93a) and (93b). Prince (1984), Goldsmith
(1990), and It and Mester (forthcoming) propose various technical explanations of homorg-
anicity. See chapter 9 for a radically different approach, known as positional faithfulness.
131
Syllable structure and economy
Shared place of articulation between the coda and the following onset is therefore
not in violation of the Coda-Cond. In contrast, the /k/ in the coda of structure
(93b) violates it.
Although no alternations are present, we must allow the possibility of con-
sonant clusters in the input whose members have different places of articulation,
e.g. /kakpa/. This follows from the assumption of Richness of the Base: OT has
no constraints on inputs. Any (hypothetical) heterorganic inputs should be over-
ruled by Coda-Cond. This implies that one consonant in the cluster must lose its
place features, thereby violating:
(94) Ident-IO(Place)
Correspondents in input and output have identical place features.
Now assume a hypothetical input /kakpa/. A strictly faithful analysis of this input
would be [kak.pa], with the rst syllables coda violating Coda-Cond. The opti-
mal analysis eliminates the place features of one of the consonants in the cluster
/kp/. See tableau (96).
The epenthetic vowel makes the lefthand consonant in the cluster to syllabify
as an onset, rather than as a coda. As an onset, this consonant can maintain its
place features without violating Coda-Cond, while at the same time satisfying
Ident-IO(Place). But of course, these benets come at a cost: a violation of the
anti-epenthesis constraint Dep-IO. This scenario is expressed by the following
ranking:
133
Syllable structure and economy
Observe that although vowel epenthesis leads an output syllabication that has no
coda, it is not triggered by No-Coda. (Ponapean allows for homorganic coda
onset sequences.)
Finally we must address the fact that the coda condition is violable in Ponapean
in a specic context: the nal consonant of the word, a coda itself. What blocks
epenthesis in word-nal position? Arguably, this blocking effect is due to Align-
R, as in Lenakel (see section 3.3.4.2). This implies the subranking Align-R
Coda-Cond, which is integrated in the nal ranking below:
A tableau shows the interaction of these four constraints for [na.kep] inlet:
(101)
Input: /nakep/ Align-R Ident-IO(Place) Coda-Cond Dep-IO
a. na.ke.pi *! *
b. na.ke *!
c. + na.kep *
Candidate (101a) fatally violates Align-R. Another strategy to satisfy the coda
condition, seen in candidate (101b), is the deletion of place features from the
coda consonant, which yields a glottal stop []. This runs into a fatal violation of
Ident-IO(Place), however.23
It readily appears that the core of the analysis must be a domination of Coda-
Cond over the anti-deletion constraint Max-IO:
23
Ponapean allows homorganic nal clusters, for example, mand tame, emp coconut crab.
Here alignment blocks nal epenthesis (*[em.pi]), while economy rules out medial epenthesis
(*[em.ip]), which fails to cancel the violation of the coda condition. Note that homorganicity
of nal clusters is not predicted under an extrametricality analysis (It 1989).
134
3.6 Coda conditions
We cannot present the complete analysis before having addressed two interesting
issues, each of which merits detailed discussion: the choice of the deleted con-
sonant in a cluster, and the immunity of the word-nal consonant. Both issues
have consequences for the view of the morphologyphonology interface.
The rst issue is the choice of the deleted consonant in the cluster. Observe
that the lefthand consonant is deleted, while the righthand consonant is preserved.
A possible interpretation of this is that a coda consonant, rather than an onset
consonant, is deleted. But how can a coda-onset asymmetry on deletion be
accounted for in a theory based on output constraints? Should we rst syllabify
the input to identify the deleted consonant as a coda, before we can delete it?
(104)
(105) a. b.
24
This analysis misses the generalization that a coda consonant is deleted, rather than an onset
one. Chapter 9 will sketch an alternative analysis based on positional faithfulness.
135
Syllable structure and economy
(106) Align-Morph-L
The left edge of every morpheme coincides with the left edge of a
syllable.
a. let.ku.jaw **!
b. + le.ku.jaw * *
c. le.tu.jaw *! * *
The second issue is the preservation of the word-nal consonant. Apparently the
grammar of Diola-Fogny exerts pressure to leave the right edge of the grammat-
ical word unaffected. This actually overrides the coda condition. What constraint
is responsible for the preservation of the rightmost segment in the word?
In earlier sections (section 3.3.4.2 on Lenakel and section 3.6.2 on Ponapean)
we encountered an alignment constraint that might, in principle at least, do the
job. This constraint is Align-R, requiring that the right edge of every grammat-
ical word coincide with the right edge of a PrWd. See the diagrams below:
GrWd GrWd
But now observe that both structures are perfectly aligned since the rightmost
segment of each GrWd matches the rightmost segment of PrWd. In (108a) this
rightmost segment is [w], and in (105b) it is [a]. Both are the rightmost remaining
136
3.6 Coda conditions
segments of the grammatical word, which are rightmost in the PrWd. Therefore
standard alignment does not work.
What we are looking for is a novel type of alignment, which actually inspects
the correspondence relation between the rightmost segments in the input and
output. Input output diagrams of the two major candidates clarify the kind of
correspondence relation which is relevant. This relation is intact in (109a), while
it is broken in (109b):
Output: l e ku j aw Output: l e ku j a
The relevant correspondence constraint focusses on the rightmost segments in the
input and output. It identies the rightmost segment of the output grammatical
word, and then it identies the rightmost segment of the input grammatical word.
When the segments are correspondents, as in (109a), then the constraint is
satised. But when the segments are not correspondents, as in (109b), then the
constraint is violated.
This correspondence constraint is Anchoring-IO (McCarthy and Prince
1995a):
(110) Anchoring-IO(GrWd, R)
Any segment at the right periphery of the output GrWd has a cor-
respondent at the right periphery of the input GrWd.
(No deletion/epenthesis at the edge.)
25
Not counting Uniformity-IO, which was briey discussed at the end of chapter 2.
26
See chapter 5 (section 5.7), for more on this unication.
137
Syllable structure and economy
The tableau of [le.ku.jaw] shows its two main competitors, [let.ku.jaw] and
[le.ku.ja], as well as their evaluation under the hierarchy.
a. let.ku.jaw **!
b. + le.ku.jaw * *
c. le.ku.ja *! **
Note that this exemplies a perfect twofold domination: each lower ranking con-
straint is violated to avoid violation of a higher-ranking constraint. The nested
logical structure of the generalization is stated below:
(114) Input consonants are preserved,
except when these have place features and are syllabiable as codas,
except when these stand at the right edge of a grammatical word.
This nishes the analysis of Diola-Fogny consonant deletion. In the discussion
section below we will return to the relation of this pattern to the other two
patterns (assimilation and epenthesis) discussed earlier in this section.
[Place] [Place]
[Place] [Place]
All three rules share a common structural description: all are triggered by a coda
that fails to share its place of articulation with the following onset. All function
to eliminate this conguration, by different structural changes. The rst rule
assimilates the onsets place features back to the preceding coda, making it share
its features. The second rule inserts a vowel between the onset and the coda,
turning the offending coda consonant into an onset. And the third rule atly
deletes the coda consonant.
However, there is no formal recognition of this functional unity among the
rules. The argument is analogous to the one made in chapter 2 for the processes
applying in the *Nt (nasal-plus-voiceless-consonant) context. To capture the
functional unity of a set of rules, it does not sufce for these rules to share a
structural description. Nor does it sufce for their outputs to lack codas with
place features. The proper generalization combines both aspects: all rules function
so as to eliminate the conguration that forms their structural description. Any
theory that fails to recognize the output as a level at which phonological general-
izations hold fails to capture the functional unity of these phonological processes.
In contrast, OT captures this functional unity straightforwardly, thereby creating
unity in typological diversity.
3.7 Conclusion
Syllables are key factors in stating phonological generalizations. In this chapter
we have focussed on two types of phenomena in which syllables play a major
role: epenthesis and the phonotactics of coda consonants. Throughout this chap-
ter we have kept an eye on a set of more general issues in OT:
Process format. We have learned that syllable-dependent processes, like any
other phonological processes, involve interactions of markedness constraints
and faithfulness constraints. A change (deletion, insertion, or featural change)
is made at the cost of some faithfulness constraint, but only to avoid the violation
139
Syllable structure and economy
Syllables in OT
Broselow, Ellen, Su-I Chen, and Marie Huffman (1997) Syllable weight: conver-
gence of phonology and phonetics. Phonology 14. 4782.
Rosenthall, Sam (1997) The distribution of prevocalic vowels. Natural Language
and Linguistic Theory 15. 13980.
EXERCISES
1 -um-inxation in Ilokano
Ilokano (Hayes and Abad 1989) has a pattern of um-inxation that is almost
identical to that of Tagalog, discussed in section 3.4.2. For Ilokano it is reported
that speakers have the free variant g-um-radwet next to gr-um-adwet.
2 Epenthesis in Harari
Consider the following two paradigms of the root /sbr/ break in Harari (Leslau
1958, Kenstowicz and Kisseberth 1979):
For the purposes of the problem, you are free to ignore the variation in the stem
shapes (/sbr/ versus /sbr/), which is under morphological control.
141
4
Metrical structure and parallelism
4.1 Introduction
This chapter deals with word stress patterns in the framework of OT. Within
phonology, word stress patterns stand out as being typically governed by conict-
ing forces, as was recognized in studies in pre-OT metrical phonology. Before we
can actually point out the interactions of conicting metrical constraints, we must
rst become familiar with some results of the metrical theory of word stress.
(1) (. * ) PrWd-level
(* .)( * .) Foot-level
.l.b.m Syllable-level
The rhythmically strong syllables are initial in the foot: such feet are called
trochees. Each foot is represented by a pair of parentheses, and an asterisk on top
of the strong syllable, while the weak syllable has a dot. We will refer to the
strong syllable of a foot as its head, and to the weak syllable as its non-head. Note
that the strong syllable of the nal foot is more prominent than that of the initial
foot. This weakstrong relationship between feet is represented by yet another
metrical constituent, on the next-higher prosodic level that of the PrWd. Again,
relative prominence is marked by a dot and an asterisk, now sitting on top of
heads of feet.
Extensive research in the typology of word stress (e.g. Hayes 1995) has shown
that stress patterns are a domain of potentially conicting forces, among which
are rhythm (the pressure toward regularly alternating distributions of strong and
142
4.2 Word stress: general background
We will proceed as follows. In section 4.2, we will become familiar with the
major cross-linguistic forces in word stress, among which are rhythm, quantity-
sensitivity, and edge-marking. This section will also introduce the representational
tools of metrical theory, the universal alphabet of prosodic categories, including
the syllable, the foot, and the PrWd. In section 4.3 we will present a case-study
of Hixkaryana, and see how this language accommodates the conicts between
metrical forces. In the course of this case-study, metrical forces will be trans-
lated one by one into a small set of metrical constraints. These constraints will be
placed in a broader typological perspective in section 4.4, where a number of
basic interaction schemata will be introduced. Section 4.4 also develops a facto-
rial typology by reranking a subset of metrical constraints, matching it against
what is known about cross-linguistic variation in stress systems. A case-study of
another language, Southeastern Tepehuan, will serve to highlight a comparison
with rule-based parametric metrical theory in section 4.5. Finally, section 4.6 will
deal with the interactions between metrical constraints and faithfulness con-
straints, which point to parallellism and a typical OT perspective.
minimal word typically equals a single foot, a rhythmic unit consisting of two
syllables or two moras (length units). Languages may actively reinforce a binary
word minimum by prosodically expanding any word that would otherwise fall
below the minimum, by adding an augment of a mora or vowel to a subminimal
word. This is illustrated by examples from Levantine Arabic (lengthening, 2a) and
Iraqi Arabic (epenthesis, 2b), both from Broselow (1995):
The binary foot size is related to the rhythmic property, which will be discussed
below.
These positions are ranked in decreasing order of popularity among the worlds
languages. The low ranking of pattern (3c) illustrates a dispreference against nal
stress, evidence for which will be adduced in section 4.3. (Secondary stresses are
left unmarked in 3.)
Some languages mark both edges of a word, while other languages mark edges
of morphemes contained within a word (root, stem, afx). Both strategies are
exemplied by Sibutu Sama, a language of the southern Philippines (Allison
1979). The word is marked on its prenal syllable, and the stem and every prex
on their initial syllables:
This example illustrates how word stress may serve to highlight morphological
structure.
144
4.2 Word stress: general background
The rhythmic property. Stress languages have a clear tendency towards rhythmic
patterns, with strong and weak syllables spaced apart at regular intervals. Rhyth-
mic alternation is manifested in a number of ways: by avoidance of adjacent
stressed syllables (clashes) or long strings of unstressed syllables (lapses).
Rhythmic alternation is directional, that is, oriented with respect to an edge of
the word, beginning or end. For example, Pintupi (5a) stresses the initial syllable
plus following alternate non-nal syllables, while Warao (5b) stresses the prenal
syllable and alternating preceding syllables.
Bracketed two-syllable portions are metrical feet: the smallest units of linguistic
rhythm. All feet in (5) are trochees: here the initial syllable is strong and the
second weak. As we will see below, languages may also select iambs (whose
second syllable is strong).
The rhythmic spectrum is occupied at one end by languages that have a max-
imally dense rhythmic organization, like Pintupi and Warao. Yidi (Dixon 1977)
even enforces binary rhythm by apocopating a vowel of words with three or ve
syllables, to make it t the binary mould:
Australian language Nunggubuyu (Hore 1981; 7a) and the South American lan-
guage Hixkaryana (Derbyshire 1979; 7b):
Mutually reinforcing relations of prominence and quantity are highly typical for
stress systems. (Although stress may be attracted by high-toned vowels, quant-
itative processes supporting tonal contrasts are rare in tone and pitch accent
languages.)
Ft Foot
Syllable
Mora
Every prosodic category in the hierarchy has as its head an element of the next-
lower level category. More precisely, every PrWd contains a (main-stressed) foot,
every foot contains a (stressed) syllable, while every syllable contains a mora, a
unit of quantity.
(1989), we will assume moraic theory. According to this theory, a syllables quan-
tity is a function of its number of weight-bearing units, or moras. Universally,
short vowels are represented by one mora, while long vowels have two. The mora
is symbolized by the Greek letter :
t a t a n t a t a n
These diagrams represent weight, omitting the division into subsyllabic constitu-
ents onsetnucleuscoda.1 CV syllables are universally light (monomoraic), while
CVV syllables are universally heavy (bimoraic). The weight of a CVC syllable
depends on whether or not its coda consonant is moraic. This varies from lan-
guage to language, and is determined by the ranking of Weight-by-Position
(Hayes 1989, Sherer 1994):
(11) Weight-by-Position
Coda consonants are moraic.
In the notation of quantitative foot shapes, we will use L for a light syllable and
H for a heavy syllable. The head of the foot (stressed syllable) will be marked
by bold-face. It is a topic of debate whether the foot inventory should be enforced
by violable constraints, or hard-wired in the universal alphabet of prosodic
representations.3 In section 4.4, we will nd out to what extent this seemingly
1
Not taking a position on the issue of whether moraic theory should incorporate a subsyllabic
constituent rhyme (see for an overview Steriade 1988b), we will maintain these labels as
convenient shorthand notations. For reasons irrelevant here, we assume non-moraic consonants
(onsets, and coda consonants in light syllables) to adjoin below moras.
2
Weight-by-Position was originally conceived of as a parameter, since languages differ in
analysing CVC syllables as light or heavy.
3
For example, unheaded feet have been proposed by Crowhurst and Hewitt (1995), double-
headed feet by Bye (1996), and non-moraic syllables by Kager (1989) and Kirchner (1991).
147
Metrical structure and parallelism
The generalization that governs the lengthening pattern is the following: in words
of three or more syllables, every even-numbered non-nal open syllable is
stressed, and its vowel is lengthened. This alternating length pattern can be char-
acterized as iambic: it involves a grouping of syllables into weakstrong rhyth-
mic units, of which the strong syllable is lengthened (Hayes 1995). In (13) this
rhythmic unit, the canonical iamb (LH), occurs once in words of three and four
syllables, and twice in ve-syllable words.
Surprisingly, in a disyllabic word consisting of two open syllables, the rst
syllable (rather than the second) is lengthened:
Turning now from open syllables to closed syllables, we nd that these are always
stressed, but that their vowels never lengthen. Even though closed syllables fail
to undergo lengthening themselves, they do affect the lengthening pattern of open
syllables, serving as reference points in counting syllables. For example, in words
that have a closed syllable in initial position, the lengthening pattern is similar to
that of (13), but with the difference that it is shifted one syllable to the right:
148
4.3 Case-study: rhythmic lengthening in Hixkaryana
First, the rule that assigns iambs (Step 3) is not intrinsically connected to the
rule that lengthens open syllables in strong positions of feet (Step 5), although
both rules aspire toward a single output target: the canonical iamb (LH). This
generalization is missed.
Second, this analysis relies on an intermediate stage in the derivation of disyl-
labic words in which a degenerate foot (L) is temporarily allowed (Step 4). This
foot is repaired at the surface by lengthening its vowel into (H). This (L) foot is
abstract since the output pattern contains only (H) and (LH). Again, a general-
ization is missed.
Third, the analysis fails to explain why a degenerate foot is assigned in disyl-
labic words, whereas the prenal syllable of the longer words in (18) remains un-
parsed. That is, Step 4 is just an ad hoc incarnation of culminativity it only applies
in disyllabic words to satisfy the imperative that every word must have a foot.
4.3.2 An OT analysis
Instead we will nd it more fruitful to look at Hixkarayana length and stress
as a system of conicting preferences. We will nd out how these conicts are
resolved by comparing the actual outputs with potential outputs, which might
have arisen if the priorities between preferences had been different. That is, log-
ically possible but suboptimal outputs serve to support ranking arguments. Rank-
ing arguments will turn out to have a general form: for a pair of an actual form
and a suboptimal form, a constraint violated by the suboptimal form (but satised
in the actual form) dominates a constraint of which the violation pattern is the
reverse. (A more complete and formal treatment of what constitutes a ranking
argument in OT will be presented in chapter 7.)
In each step, we will proceed as follows. First an actual form will be juxtaposed
with a potential form, one which might have been, but is not, realized. We will
then identify two conicting preferences, relating these to the cross-linguistically
recurrent properties of stress systems of section 4.2. Preferences will then be
translated into universal metrical constraints, which will be ranked one by one on
the basis of the available empirical evidence. Finally, we will integrate the sub-
ranking thus found into the (current) total ranking for the metrical pattern of
Hixkaryana.
The metrical constraints to be introduced in the analysis of Hixkaryana will be
discussed in more detail in section 4.4. (There proper credit will be given to their
inventors, and all constraints will be motivated in more detail, paying attention to
their function and format.)
It is apparently more important to leave the nal syllable unfooted than it is for
every foot to be a canonical (LH) iamb. Both preferences can be translated
directly into metrical constraints. The rst states that nal syllables must not be
metried:
(20) NonFinality
No foot is nal in PrWd.
The second constraint denes the best rhythmic shape of the iamb, a foot
having weakstrong prominence and a quantitative make-up light-heavy (Hayes
1995). Uneven-Iamb says that (LH) is a better iamb than (LL) or (H):4
(21) Uneven-Iamb
(LH) (LL), (H)
The harmony statement in (19) translates into a ranking argument for these
constraints:
Tableau (23) supports this ranking. Each candidate violates one constraint while
satisfying the other. The optimal candidate is (23a) since it satises the highest-
ranking constraint of the two, NonFinality:
a. + (kw).ja *
b. (kwa.j) *!
We will now extend this simple ranking (using the same basic method) until we
arrive at a complete characterization of the Hixkaryana lengthening pattern.
4
In section 4.4.5 we will decompose requirements on prominence (iambs vs. trochees) and
quantitative structure (LL vs. LH, H vs. LH, etc.) that are combined in Uneven-Iamb.
151
Metrical structure and parallelism
Let us consider another potential way out of the dilemma of conicting con-
straints. It seems that both the Scylla of NonFinality and the Charybdis of
Uneven-Iamb can be avoided by an output that has no feet at all. This unparsed
output vacuously satises both Uneven-Iamb and NonFinality, simply because
it has no foot to be evaluated. Then why would Hixkaryana still prefer the input
/kwaja/ to surface with a foot, even when this foot fails to match the best form?
The unparsed output violates the imperative that grammatical words must have
prosody the culminative property:
(25) GrWd=PrWd
A grammatical word must be a prosodic word.
From this constraint it indirectly follows that grammatical words must have min-
imally one foot. Recall from section 4.2.2 that every prosodic category (PrWd,
foot, and syllable) takes as its head a category of the next-lower category. There-
fore, every PrWd must have a foot as its head. Requiring PrWd-status of a
grammatical word thus amounts to requiring that it must have at least a foot.
The preference for grammatical words to be PrWds (hence to have feet) is
stronger than the dispreference against bad iambs:
a. + (kw).ja *
b. kwaj *!
A second piece of evidence showing that nal syllables are strongly preferred to
remain unfooted is the length pattern of words with four open syllables. Here the
second syllable is lengthened, while the fourth syllable remains short. Apparently
the left hand parse, with a single canonical (LH) iamb, is preferred to the right
hand parse, which has two:
This shows that it is more important to leave the nal syllable unfooted than it is
for all syllables to be parsed by feet. Or, translating the latter preference into a
constraint:
(29) Parse-Syl
Feet are parsed by feet.
The resulting ranking of these two constraints is:
(30) NonFinality Parse-Syl
a. + (a.).wo.wo **
b. (a.).(wo.w) *!
rst and third syllable long). Both two-foot parses are rejected, though, in favour
of a single-foot parse. This shows that it is more important for every foot to be a
canonical (LH) iamb, than it is for all syllables to be parsed by feet. Or, in terms
of constraint ranking:
(34) Uneven-Iamb Parse-Syl
This ranking is supported by a tableau:
a. + (a.).wo.wo **
b. (a.).(w).wo *! *
c. ().(o.w).wo *! *
This is an important result showing that ranking arguments are consistent with
transitivity. To see this, we must recapitulate some results. Firstly, NonFinality
dominates Uneven-Iamb (see tableau 23). Secondly, Uneven-Iamb dominates
Parse-Syl (see tableau 35). Thirdly, NonFinality dominates Parse-Syl (tab-
leau 31), conrming transitivity of strict domination. We now arrive at the fol-
lowing hierarchy:
(36) GrWd=PrWd, NonFinality Uneven-Iamb Parse-Syl
Tableau (37) summarizes two results booked so far. It proves Uneven-Iamb
Parse-Syl, as well as NonFinality Parse-Syl (as already established by
tableau 31):
a. + (a.).wo.wo **
b. (a.).(w).wo *! *
c. (a.).(wo.w) *!
The optimal candidate (37a) violates Parse-Syl more severely than any of its
competitors (37b c). However, these competitors fatally violate either NonFi-
nality (37c) or Uneven-Iamb (37b), both of which dominate Parse-Syl.
What other preferences govern the length pattern of Hixkaryana? For example, is
there any evidence for quantity-sensitivity apart from a preference for the canon-
ical iamb? Such evidence indeed exists, and it comes from two sources.
154
4.3 Case-study: rhythmic lengthening in Hixkaryana
The rst nding is that it is more important to stress heavy syllables than for
every foot to be a (LH) iamb. Evidence comes from the pair in (38). The actual
form stresses a heavy syllable, but has a non-canonical foot (H). The suboptimal
form has one canonical foot, but fails to stress the heavy syllable.
(39) WSP
Heavy syllables are stressed.
This constraint is violated by any heavy syllable that is not prominent, either
within a foot or outside a foot. The harmonic relation in (38) translates into a
ranking argument:
This evidence tells us that it is more important to stress heavy syllables than it is
for all syllables to be parsed by feet. We now infer the ranking
155
Metrical structure and parallelism
Tableau (44) lays out the most complex interaction of metrical constraints that
we have seen thus far, involving the full hierarchy in (43) except GrWd=PrWd.
(44)
Input: /tohkur jehona/ NonFinality WSP Uneven- Parse-Syl
Iamb
a. + (th).(ku.r j).ho.na * **
b. (th).(ku.r j).(h).na **! *
c. (th).(ku.r j).(ho.n) *! *
d. (toh.k).(r je.h).na *! * *
j
e. toh.(ku.r ).ho.na *! ***
(46) Dep--IO
Output moras have input correspondents.
What the harmonic comparison (45) directly tells us is that Dep--IO is dominated
by Ft-Bin, which we will learn to know as the anti-degenerate-foot constraint:
(47) Ft-Bin
Feet are binary under moraic or syllabic analysis.
156
4.3 Case-study: rhythmic lengthening in Hixkaryana
This means that we can now add Ft-Bin and Dep--IO to the hierarchy, and
locate the latter as accurately as possible in a position directly dominated by
Uneven-Iamb:
What remain to be claried are the factors that determine the position of feet
with respect to the edges of the PrWd. We have already seen that words of four
open syllables fall into a metrication that has only one canonical iamb (see 33).
Still, this single foot can be placed in two different positions, even respecting
NonFinality in both cases. Comparison of the actual four-syllable form with a
potential form shows that the foot is preferrably initial in the word. (This is
Hixkaryanas form of demarcative stress):
This preference for feet to be initial in the PrWd is translated into a maximally
general constraint:
(51) All-Ft-Left
Every foot stands at the left edge of the PrWd.
constitutes a violation, as only one foot per PrWd can be strictly initial. We thus
nd that it is more important for all syllables to be parsed by feet than it is for
every foot to stand at the left edge:
(52) (ne.m).(ko.t).no (ne.m).ko.to.no
Accordingly, we nd the important ranking:
(53) Parse-Syl All-Ft-Left
The resulting integrated hierarchy of all constraints for Hixkaryana is in (54):6
(54) GrWd=PrWd, NonFinality, Ft-Bin, WSP
Uneven-Iamb
Parse-Syl
All-Ft-Left, Dep--IO
Note that we now predict that WSP must dominate All-Ft-Left, by transitiv-
ity. This prediction is conrmed by the comparison in (55):
(55) (kha.n).(nGh).no (kha.n).nph.no
The following display summarizes all rankings that we have found, and for
each ranking, the evidence on which it is based.
(56)
Its more important: than it is:
to leave the nal syllable unfooted for every foot to be a (LH) iamb
NonFinality Uneven-Iamb
(kw).ja (kwa.j)
for every word to contain a foot for every foot to be a (LH) iamb
GrWd=PrWd Uneven-Iamb
(kw).ja kwa.ja
to avoid (L) feet to avoid vowel length
Ft-Bin Dep--IO
(kw).ja (kw).ja
for every foot to be a (LH) iamb to avoid vowel length
Uneven-Iamb Dep--IO
(to.r).no (to.r).no
6
This analysis has been inuenced by analyses of iambic patterns in Axininca Campa (McCa-
rthy and Prince 1993b, Hung 1994) and Carib (Van der Hulst and Visch 1992, Kenstowicz
1995).
158
4.3 Case-study: rhythmic lengthening in Hixkaryana
(57)
Input: /kwaja/ Non- GrWd= Ft- WSP Un- Parse- All- Dep
Finality PrWd Bin even- Syl Ft- -
Iamb Left -IO
a. + (kw).ja * * *
b. (kw).ja *! * *
w
c. k a.ja *! **
d. (kwa.j) *! *
(58)
Input: /torono/ Non- GrWd= Ft- WSP Un- Parse- All- DEP
Finality PrWd Bin even- Syl Ft- -
Iamb Left -IO
a. + (to.r).no * *
b. (to.r).no *! *
c. (to.r).(n) *! * ** **
159
Metrical structure and parallelism
(59)
Input: /aowowo/ Non- GrWd= Ft- WSP Un- Parse- All- Dep
Finality PrWd Bin even- Syl Ft- -
Iamb Left -IO
a. + (a.).wo.wo ** *
b. a.(o.w).wo ** *! *
c. (a.).(w).wo *! * ** **
d. (a.).wo.wo *! **
e. (a.).(wo.w) *! ** **
(60)
Input: /tohkur jehona / Non- GrWd= Ft- WSP Un- Parse- All- Dep
Finality PrWd Bin even- Syl Ft- -
Iamb Left -IO
a. + (th).(ku.r j).ho.na * ** * *
j
b. (th).ku.(r e.h).na * ** **! *
c. (toh.k).(r je.h).na *! * * ** **
4.3.3 Conclusions
This analysis of Hixkaryana illustrates important ingredients of the analysis of
word stress patterns: basic metrical constraints and their interactions in producing
a rhythmic pattern. Note in particular the following four rankings:
(61) Binary rhythm starting at the left word edge
Ft-Bin Parse-Syl All-Ft-Left
(62) Metrical inertness of the nal syllable
NonFinality Parse-Syl
(63) Subminimal lengthening
GrWd=PrWd, Ft-Bin Dep--IO
(64) Iambic lengthening
Uneven-Iamb Dep--IO
These ranking schemata will be placed in broader typological perspective in sec-
tion 4.45.
160
4.4 A set of metrical constraints
(65) Ft-Bin
Feet are binary under moraic or syllabic analysis.
A foot must contain either two moras, as in (H) or (LL), or two syllables, as in
(). A key function of Ft-Bin is to exclude degenerate feet (L), which contain
161
Metrical structure and parallelism
a single light syllable. Many languages have an absolute ban on degenerate feet,
due to undominated Ft-Bin. The usual diagnostic of undominated Ft-Bin is the
absolute enforcement of the minimal word.
Enforcing rhythmic binarity, Ft-Bin also plays a key role in rhythmic alterna-
tion. Note that Ft-Bin by itself does not sufce to guarantee the binary alterna-
tion of weak and strong syllables. This requires something more all syllables
must be parsed by feet (Hayes 1980, Halle and Vergnaud 1987, Prince and Smo-
lensky 1993):
(66) Parse-Syl
Syllables are parsed by feet.
Syllables violating this constraint (any which are not parsed by a foot) will be
assumed to be metried as immediate daughters of PrWd. This assumption is
known as weak layering (It and Mester 1992). The Hixkaryana example
[(to.r).no], represented hierarchically, has a weakly-layered nal syllable, one
that is unparsed by a foot:
(67) PrWd
Ft
to.ro.no
Only the nal syllable, the one that is unparsed by a foot, violates Parse-Syl.
In combination, high-ranking Ft-Bin and Parse-Syl have the effect of enforc-
ing binary alternation: a parse of the word into multiple binary feet. When a word
can be fully parsed by binary feet without any violation of Ft-Bin or Parse-
Syl, the foot distribution is uniquely determined by both constraints. Then an
exhaustive parsing arises, with all feet packed tight together. This is the case, for
example, in words with an even number of light syllables; see (68a). But in words
with an odd number of light syllables, one syllable must remain that cannot be
parsed by binary feet. Accordingly, there are multiple ways in which a maximally
dense distribution of feet can be achieved; see (68b).
(68) a. ()()() Exhaustive parsing: feet packed tightly
b.i ()()()
b.ii ()()()
Non-exhaustive parsing: multiple options
b.iii ()()()
b.iv ()()()
Here the constraint pair Ft-Bin or Parse-Syl fails to uniquely determine foot
distribution. To produce a genuine rhythmic distribution of feet, one oriented
162
4.4 A set of metrical constraints
toward a specic edge of the word, a foot alignment constraint must pick out one
of the parsings in (68b.iiv). Such a constraint is stated below after McCarthy and
Prince (1993a):
(69) All-Ft-Left
Align (Ft, Left, PrWd, Left)
Every foot stands at the left edge of the PrWd.
This is an alignment constraint of the general format Align (Cat1, Edge1, Cat2,
Edge2) (see chapter 3), requiring that the left edge of every foot coincide with
the left edge of a PrWd. This is satised only in the case of a single foot standing
at the absolute left edge of the word: any additional foot will incur a violation,
since two feet cannot both stand at the left edge. If undominated, All-Ft-Left
enforces a single foot per PrWd a non-iterative pattern.
But then how can All-Ft-Left resolve ties among candidates containing multi-
ple feet, such as those in (68)? The answer is simple and straightforward. Each
foot that is not in absolute initial position incurs some violation of All-Ft-Left.
If we count the distance between a foot and the left word edge in syllables, then
each foot will incur a violation of All-Ft-Left that equals this number. In words
containing multiple feet, we simply add up violations for individual feet to arrive
at the total violation of All-Ft-Left. The candidate incurring the smallest total
violation wins. This is an example of a gradient constraint.
Reversing the ranking of both constraints will have the effect of a right-oriented
rhythm:
163
Metrical structure and parallelism
7
In section 4.4.3 we will see that such patterns arise due to interactions with word alignment
constraints.
164
4.4 A set of metrical constraints
a. + (p.i).(k.la).tju * **
b. (p.i).ka.(l.tju) * ***!
c. pu.(.ka).(l.tju) * *, **!*
d. (p.i).ka.la.tju **!*
e. (p.i).(k.la).(tj) * **, ****
Undominated Ft-Bin rules out degenerate feet (as in 74e), at the expense of
violations of Parse-Syl (74ad). But since Parse-Syl is minimally violated, any
metrications having multiple unparsed syllables (74d) are ruled out. All remain-
ing metrications have multiple feet (74ac), at the expense of multiple violations
of All-Ft-Left. Minimal violation of All-Ft-Left results in an optimal output
whose collective feet stand as close as possible to the left word edge this is
(74a).
Related to rhythmic distribution of stresses, two more preferences have been
observed to be strong in many languages. First, adjacent stressed syllables
(clashes) are often avoided:
(75) *Clash
No stressed syllables are adjacent.
*Clash has its roots in pre-OT work (Liberman 1975, Liberman and Prince
1977, Prince 1983, Hammond 1984, Selkirk 1984). See section 4.4.5 for further
discussion.
Second, nal syllables are metrically inert, in a double sense. For Hixkaryana,
we have seen that nal syllables must be unfooted the PrWd must not end in a
foot. But for many other languages, a somewhat weaker requirement holds that
the nal syllable must be unstressed the PrWd must not end in a stressed
syllable. Both requirements are put in a single statement in Prince and Smolen-
skys version of NonFinality:
(76) NonFinality
No prosodic head is nal in PrWd.
165
Metrical structure and parallelism
(77) GrWd=PrWd
A grammatical word must be a PrWd.
The prosodic hierarchy guarantees that every PrWd dominates at least one foot
hence the combined result of GrWd=PrWd and the prosodic hierarchy is that
every grammatical word has at least one stressed syllable the culminative prop-
erty. (Most languages make a distinction in prominence among multiple feet in a
word. The issue of how to capture this distinction by constraints, and how to
locate the strongest foot primary stress in a word, will be dealt with in section
4.4.3.)
Related to GrWd=PrWd is the notion of word minimum the requirement that
a word have minimally two moras or syllables. A word minimum can be enforced
in various ways, for example by subminimal lengthening, making a monomoraic
word bimoraic, or by the epenthesis of a vowel into a monosyllabic word, making
it disyllabic. The example below is taken from Mohawk (Piggott 1995):
8
*Clash and NonFinality were collapsed by Hung (1994) into a single constraint Rhythm
every strong syllable must be followed by a weak syllable. See Elenbaas (1996, 1999) for
empirical arguments against this merging.
166
4.4 A set of metrical constraints
a. + (k.tats) *
b. (ktts) *!
c. ktats *!
The rst pair of metrical alignment constraints, Leftmost and Rightmost, align
the strongest foot (or head foot) with a specied edge of the word. (These
constraints are named after Edgemost from Prince and Smolensky 1993):
(81) a. Leftmost
Align (Hd-Ft, Left, PrWd, Left)
The head foot is leftmost in PrWd.
b. Rightmost
Align (Hd-Ft, Right, PrWd, Right)
The head foot is rightmost in PrWd.
The function of peak-aligning constraints is dual. First, they serve to locate the
primary stress on a foot standing at the specied edge of the word. Thus far we
have had no constraints making prominence distinctions among feet; since most
languages make such distinctions, (81a, b) are well-supported.
The second function of Leftmost/Rightmost is perhaps less obvious it
appears in the analysis of so-called bidirectional stress systems. Such systems are
characterized by a rhythmic pattern that is oriented toward two word edges, rather
than toward a single edge. For example, the Australian language Garawa (Furby
1974, Hayes 1980, McCarthy and Prince 1993a) stresses the initial syllable and
alternating syllables preceding the penult. Feet are oriented toward the right edge
(as is evident from words of seven or more syllables), but the primary stress is
always initial. See (82a).
167
Metrical structure and parallelism
By undominated Leftmost, every word has an initial main stress foot (excluding
83f). By Ft-Bin, all feet are binary (excluding 83g). Among the remaining can-
didates, Parse-Syl picks out candidates that have a single unparsed syllable
(excluding 83d e). The survivors (83ac) differ only in the distribution of their
168
4.4 A set of metrical constraints
three feet (of which the initial one is xed by Leftmost). Minimal violation of
All-Ft-Right draws all feet as close as possible to the right edge, selecting
(83a). In sum, main stress is placed at the left edge due to Leftmost, while all
other stresses are distributed directionally due to All-Ft-Right.
The second pair of demarcative constraints is stated in (84):
(84) a. Align-Wd-Left
Align (PrWd, Left, Ft, Left)
Every PrWd begins with a foot.
b. Align-Wd-Right
Align (PrWd, Right, Ft, Right)
Every PrWd ends in a foot.
These constraints are functional antagonists of All-Ft-Left and All-Ft-Right.
Instead of making a requirement about feet (in terms of word edges), they make
a requirement about word edges (in terms of feet). Accordingly, they are violated
when no foot is present at the specied edge of the word. (Recall the discussion
of asymmetric alignment in chapter 3, section 3.4.1.)
The analytic function of these constraints resides in complex bidirectional sys-
tems, of which an example, Indonesian (Cohn 1989), is given below:
(85) Indonesian: Ft-Bin, Rightmost Align-Wd-L Parse-Syl
All-Ft-R
a. bi.(c.ra) speak
b. (kn.ti).nu.(.si) continuation
c. (.ro).(d.na).(m.ka) aerodynamics
d. (.me).ri.(k.ni).(s.si) Americanization
In Indonesian primary stress falls on the penultimate syllable, while words of
minimally four syllables long have an initial secondary stress. Words of six or
more syllables display an alternating stress pattern starting at the right edge.
Ignoring the right-aligned position of primary stress, this foot distribution looks
much like that of Garawa (82a), with one major difference: three-syllable words
have a right-aligned foot, rather than a left-aligned foot. Upon comparing the
Indonesian pattern to that of Piro (82b), we nd that everything is identical except
words of seven syllables long. These have secondary stress on the third syllable
in Piro, but on the fourth syllable in Indonesian.
(86)
3 syllables 5 syllables 7 syllables
Indonesian bi.(c.ra) (kn.ti).nu.(.si) (.me).ri.(k.ni).(s.si)
Garawa (pn.ja).a (k.ma).a.(.i) (n.ki).i.(k.rim).(p.yi)
Piro ru.(:.:a) (s.lwa).ye.(hk.kna) (r.slu).(n.ti).ni.(tk.na)
169
Metrical structure and parallelism
In sum, the Indonesian rhythmic pattern is a hybrid of the Garawa and Piro
patterns. It has undominated Rightmost, as in Piro, but the active foot-alignment
constraint is All-Ft-Right, as in Garawa. Accordingly, ranked in between
undominated Rightmost and All-Ft-Right in the Indonesian grammar must be
Align-Wd-Left:
(88)
Input: / bicara/ Ft-Bin Rightmost Align-Wd- Parse-Syl All-Ft-
Left Right
a. + bi.(c.ra) * *
b. (b.ca).ra *! * *
c. (b).(c.ra) *! **
The tableau of a seven-syllable word shows that Indonesian and Piro have
distinct metrical grammars: alternating stresses run from the right edge in Indo-
nesian, rather than from the left edge, as in Piro.
(89)
Input: /amerikanisasi / Ft- Right- Align- Parse- All-Ft-Right
Bin most Wd-Left Syl
170
4.4 A set of metrical constraints
A factorial typology of iterative systems with strictly binary rhythm arises on the
basis of this ranking schema when we vary the rankings of All-Ft-X with respect
to the PrWd-alignment constraints. (Ft-Bin remains undominated throughout the
factorial typology.)
Observe that other rankings of these constraints, or of different values for X and
Y, will result in a duplication of patterns that have already been covered.
(93) WSP
Heavy syllables are stressed.
WSP relates syllable weight and metrical prominence. Or, as argued by Prince
(1983), this amounts to the natural requirement that intrinsic sonority prominence
of heavy syllables be registered as stress prominence. This relation between
sonority and prominent positions in prosodic structure can also be seen in syl-
labication segments of the highest sonority are the optimal syllable peaks
(Prince and Smolensky 1993).9
Two additional foot-form constraints determine the rhythmic type of feet (that is,
iambic or trochaic):10
(94) a. RhType=I
Feet have nal prominence.
b. RhType=T
Feet have initial prominence.
These constraints simply state the position of the head in a foot, without requiring
that this matches its quantitative make-up. Partly this function is carried out by
WSP, but this is not the end of the story, as we will now see.
Tabulating the quantitative shapes of iambs and trochees that violate neither
Ft-Bin nor WSP, we arrive at the following:
The combined ltering functions of WSP and Ft-Bin still underdetermine the
choice of quantitative make-up of iambs and trochees. For example, consider two
logically possible iambic and trochaic parses of the following sequences:
9
Related constraints require that stressed syllables be heavy (SWP, Riad 1992) or that within
a domain the heaviest syllable be stressed (Pk-Prom, Prince and Smolensky 1993).
10
For arguments that RhType=I should be eliminated as a constraint, see van de Vijver (1998).
172
4.4 A set of metrical constraints
Extensive cross-linguistic research into stress systems (Hayes 1995) reveals that
the best quantitative shapes of disyllabic iambs and trochees are (LH) and (LL),
respectively.
We have already observed a preference for uneven iambs (LH) to even iambs
(LL) in the length pattern of Hixkaryana. Hayes (1995) supports the uneven iamb
with cases of iambic lengthening from many languages. There is ample cross-
linguistic evidence for the reverse preference for quantitative evenness in trochaic
systems. For example, English and Fijian shorten a long vowel precisely in those
contexts where the resulting light syllable is footed with a following light syllable
in an even (balanced) trochee (LL). The example below is from English (Myers
1987, Prince 1990):
Ideally, a single explanation would exist for the markedness of both uneven (HL)
trochees and even (LL) iambs. Various attempts at rhythmic explanations have
been made in the pre-OT literature, which will not be reviewed here (Hayes 1985,
1995, Prince 1990). Let us instead consider an approach developed in Kager
(1993, 1995), based on the idea that a heavy syllable is rhythmically composed
of two microbeats, one on each composing mora (Prince 1983). In (99) the
microbeats of a heavy syllable are represented in a grid-notation (where * rep-
resents a strong beat, and . a weak beat):
(H) (L L) (H L)
(101) a. ending in strongweak b. not ending in strongweak
(i) * . (ii) . *. . *
[] [][] [][]
(H) (L H) (L L)
Note that at this micro-rhythmic level, the cross-linguistically preferred feet {(H),
(LL), (LH)} end in a strongweak contour, while dispreferred {(HL), (LL)} do
not end in such a contour. The preference for feet of the rst type is stated in the
following constraint:
(102) Rh-Contour
A foot must end in a strongweak contour at the moraic level.
We will assume that this constraint underlies the quantitative asymmetry in the
foot inventory. Languages having this constraint in a high-ranked position of the
grammar employ strategies to avoid (HL) trochees or (LL) iambs, depending on
interactions with specic faithfulness constraints. Languages having it in a low-
ranked position, specically below faithfulness constraints preserving input quan-
tity, will allow these anti-rhythmical feet, which gives the impression of quantity-
insensitive stress.
Let us now turn to some other issues in the theory of quantity-sensitivity. The
rst relates to the often made assumption that quantity-sensitivity is a property
of languages as a whole (and of prosodic systems in particular), which can be
switched on or off. In the pre-OT literature, this was encoded as a parameter
of foot construction (Hayes 1980), or a choice of foot type from the universal
inventory (moraic trochee versus syllabic trochee, Hayes 1995). If the OT
approach is generally correct, then this holistic view cannot be correct, for the
following reasons.
First, it is held that grammars are rankings of all universal constraints, rather
than rankings of specic sets of constraints selected on a language-specic basis.
This has an important consequence: all constraints are potentially active in every
grammar. The presence of a quantity contrast11 in a language leaves open the
11
For example, a vowel length contrast reects the domination of faithfulness (Max--IO) over
markedness (No-Long-V, Rosenthall 1994).
174
4.4 A set of metrical constraints
ranking of metrical constraints which refer to this quantity contrast (such as WSP
or Rh-Contour). It is then predicted that constraint re-rankings produce various
degrees of quantity-sensitivity. Typological studies of trochaic languages with
quantity contrasts (Kager 1992a, b) conrm this scattered picture: there is a range
from fully quantity-sensitive systems, in which every heavy syllable is stressed,
to systems which assign more importance to other factors, such as binary rhythm,
at the expense of stress on heavy syllables. (But no language completely disrespects
its quantity-contrast in its metrical system, and there is always some aspect to
which quantity does matter. For example, most languages have bimoraic word
minima.)
The second reason for which quantity-(in)sensitivity cannot be a global prop-
erty of languages is that the pre-OT foot inventory is decomposed into rhythmic
and quantitative constraints, such as FtBin, WSP, Rh-Contour, and RhType.
Under this approach, no direct counterpart of quantity-insensitive feet remains, and
quantity-disrespecting effects which were previously attributed to the syllabic
trochee must now be reattributed to rhythmic constraints. As pointed out by
Kager (1992a, 1995), one of the strongest rhythmic factors to produce quantity-
disrespecting stress patterns is clash avoidance. When No-Clash takes pre-
cedence over WSP, some heavy syllables must give up their prominence in order
to avoid a clash with a neighbouring stressed syllable. This is the case in Estonian,
Finnish, and other trochaic languages. (See Alber 1997 for an analysis along these
lines.)
(Churchward 1953, Mester 1991, Prince and Smolensky 1993, Hayes 1995)
breaks the long vowel:
The grammars of both languages have undominated foot shape constraints Ft-
Bin and Rh-Contour, as well as undominated Rightmost. But they differ min-
imally in the reranking of Onset and Max--IO. Fijian gives up input quantity
to attain the perfect bimoraic foot at the right edge (violating Max--IO):
(104)
Input: /siii/ Ft-Bin Rightmost Rh-Contour Onset Max--IO
a. + (s.i) *
b. si.(.i) *!
c. (si.i) *!
d. (si).i *!
e. (si).() *!
(105)
Input: / huu-/ Ft-Bin Rightmost Rh-Contour Max--IO Onset
a. (h.) *!
b. + hu.(.) *
c. (hu.) *!
d. (hu). *!
e. (hu).(f) *!
176
4.5 Case-study: rhythmic syncope in Southeastern Tepehuan
Before we can look into the contexts of syncope, we must discuss the place of
the accent. Accent falls on the initial stem syllable when it is heavy (long-
vowelled or closed), see (106ac). It falls on the second stem syllable if this is
heavy while the rst syllable is light; see (106df). (No stem begins with a sequ-
ence of two light syllables: this output gap is due to syncope.) The accent pattern
points to a single iamb (H) or (LH) at the left edge:
(106) #(H) #(LH)
a. (vo).hi bear d. (ta.ka).rui chicken
b. (kr).va goat e. (sa.pk) story
c. (tat).pM eas f. (ta.pGM) ea
As mentioned, Southeastern Tepehuan has a vowel alternation12 that is due to
syncope of vowels in even-numbered open syllables (107c), including long vowels
12
Two other vowel alternations will not be discussed here: vowel shortening and apocope. See
Kager (1997a) for an integrated analysis of syncope, apocope, and shortening.
177
Metrical structure and parallelism
(107d). Syncope applies in the domain of the stem, which may include a reduplic-
ant prex (107b d).
The central question is: what is the relation between metrical structure and syn-
cope? The alternating nature of syncope suggests a foot-based analysis. Yet there
is no secondary stress pattern supporting this hypothesis.
4.5.2 An OT analysis
Our analysis of syncope in Southeastern Tepehuan starts from the following
observation. Syncope obviously occurs at the expense of input vowels, hence
there must be some output target that is achieved at the expense of faithful-
ness. Below we will argue that this target is exhaustive parsing of syllables
by feet. By deleting vowels, the number of syllables will be reduced as well,
and thereby the number of violators of Parse-Syl. To those who have carefully
read through the previous sections, syncope may sound a rather absurd strategy
to achieve an exhaustive metrical parsing. Did we not conclude from analyses of
Hixkaryana, Pintupi, Warao, Garawa, and other languages, that exhaustivity is
attained by multiple (iterative) footing, hence rhythmic alternation due to a rank-
ing Parse-Syl All-Ft-L? Why would languages which opt for this ranking
need vowel deletion to achieve exhaustivity? This question is equal to asking
under what conditions vowel deletion is triggered in Southeastern Tepehuan.
What is the difference between the strategies, iterative footing and syncope, in
terms of constraint rankings? It resides in the priorities of three factors: faithful-
ness to input vowels (Max-V-IO), proximity of feet to edges, and exhaustivity.
Core rankings are below:
178
4.5 Case-study: rhythmic syncope in Southeastern Tepehuan
Let us now consider how this syncope scenario is encoded in constraint interac-
tion. We start by observing that ranking (109b) has two subrankings, All-Ft-L
Parse-Syl and Parse-Syl Max-V-IO. Both will be motivated below.
First, Southeastern Tepehuan has non-iterative footing. This implies that it
has the reverse ranking (at least, as compared to Pintupi) of All-Ft-L and
Parse-Syl:
179
Metrical structure and parallelism
a. + (tGMt).ro.pi **
b. (tGM).(tM.r).(p) *!, ***
a. + (tGMt).ro.pi ** *
b. (tGM).tM.ro.p ***!
Observe also that the optimal forms of (112) have not yet completely achieved
the target, as they still contain two unparsed syllables each. How can exhaustivity
form the pressure behind syncope if it cannot be achieved completely? The
answer is typical of OT: there is yet another factor which precludes the full
achievement of the target, and this has priority. To nd out what this factor is, all
we have to do is take exhaustive parsing to its ultimate logical conclusion, and
see what happens.
Note that optimal forms of (112) cannot be compressed any further by the
deletion of additional vowels without fatally violating rigid syllable phonotactics
of Southeastern Tepehuan, requiring syllables to have non-branching margins.
This is due to undominated *Complex.
180
4.5 Case-study: rhythmic syncope in Southeastern Tepehuan
a. + (tGMt).ro.pi **
b. (tGMt).rpi *! *
c. (tGMt).rop *! *
Next observe that, unlike vowels, consonants are never deleted under pressure
of exhaustivity. For example, the stem /karva/ might, in principle, surface as a
single (LH) iamb without violation of Parse-Syl, if only one of its medial
consonants were deleted: e.g. *(ka.v) or *(ka.r), rather than (kr).va. This
never occurs outputs must preserve the consonants of their inputs. Therefore
Max-C-IO must dominate Parse-Syl:
a. + (kr).va *
b. (ka.v) *!
c. (ka.r) *!
This is the basic analysis: modications will later be added, in a more detailed
discussion. But it is not too early to claim an important result. This is that we
have an explanation for the alternating or rhythmic character of syncope. Syncope
of vowels in adjacent syllables would necessarily lead to consonant clusters that
cannot be parsed by canonical syllables, while any deletion of consonants is
blocked (see again 11516 for evidence).
181
Metrical structure and parallelism
Another immediate result, again typical of OT, is this: if the target of syncope
is exhaustive parsing of syllables into feet, then we predict that no deletion takes
place when nothing can be gained by it when it would yield no progress in terms
of syllable parsing. This is exactly what we nd. In (118) syncope fails to apply,
simply because it would not move the output any closer to the target, exhaustivity.
Everything else being equal, it is always better to be faithful to input segments:
Thus Max-V-IO may be dominated, but that does not mean that its role is
neglectable:
a. + (ta.ka).rui *
b. (tk).rui * *!
c. (ta.ka).(ri) *!
Thus far we have developed the idea that exhaustivity of metrical parsing and
left foot alignment have priority over realizing underlying vowels in the output.
Forces that drive vowel deletion are effectively counterbalanced by phonotactics:
syllables must not have branching margins. Having completed the core of the
analysis, we now move on to some residual matters.
First consider the fact that there is another potential method by which outputs
may improve their completeness of metrication. By shortening the initial long
vowel in /tMM-tMrovi/, a canonical (LH) iamb would be created in the proper
place, producing *[(tM.tGr).pi]. This output would fare better in terms of exhaust-
ivity than the actual output [(tGMt).ro.pi]. What blocks initial shortening here is
the templatic requirement that the reduplicative prex must equal a heavy syllable
(McCarthy and Prince 1986, 1993b):13
(120) Red=
The reduplicant equals a heavy syllable.
13
The prosodic size of the reduplicative prex (a heavy syllable or a light syllable) is based on a
stem-specic choice: compare the examples in (107b d) with those in (108bd). Reduplica-
tive allomorphy is apparently not governed by phonological or morphological factors. See
Kager (1997a) for details.
182
4.5 Case-study: rhythmic syncope in Southeastern Tepehuan
a. + (tGM-t).ro.pi **
b. (tM-tGr).pi *! *
This signals that the constraint militating against vowel lengthening, Dep--IO,
dominates the anti-deletion constraint Max-V-IO. In sum, we have the following
ranking:
a. + (tGr).vi *
b. (tM.r).vi *!
c. (tM.r).vi *!
183
Metrical structure and parallelism
Finally we must consider in more detail the quantitative shape of the foot, and
try to integrate foot shape constraints into the current ranking. So far we have
assumed that the single foot standing initial in the stem is a binary iamb with its
strong syllable heavy, (H) or (LH). This selection of iambs is due to a set of four
undominated constraints stated in (127), which will be united here into a cover
constraint Ft-Form (for expository reasons).
Note that WSP-Ft serves to exclude the anti-rhythmic iamb (HH) (see Kager
1997a).
Adding up all the subrankings motivated so far, we arrive at:
The rhythmicity of the syncope pattern follows from this ranking there is no
need to set up an intermediate representation of iterative trochees, as in the rule-
based analysis (see section 4.5.3).
Tableaux (129 30) illustrate the full constraint ranking in action.
(129)
Input: /takaarui/ *Complex Ft- All- Red Max- Dep- Parse- Max-
Form Ft-L = C-IO -IO Syl V-IO
a. + (ta.ka).rui *
b. (tk).rui * *!
c. (ta.kar) *! *
d. (ta.ka).(ri) *!*
e. (ta.kaa.ri) *!
f. (tak.ri) *! *
g. (ta.kar) *! *
184
4.5 Case-study: rhythmic syncope in Southeastern Tepehuan
(130)
Input: /tMM-tMrovi/ *Complex Ft- All- Red Max- Dep- Parse- Max-
Form Ft-L = C-IO -IO Syl V-IO
a. + (tGMt).ro.pi ** *
c. (tGMt).pi *! * **
d. (tM.tGr).pi *! * *
e. (tGMt).(ro.p) *! *
f. (tMM.tGr).pi *! * *
g. (tGMt).rop *! * **
Although the analysis derives most forms correctly, it runs into conceptual and
empirical problems that cannot be solved without additional machinery, including
extra rules and even output constraints.
First, the complete lack of surface secondary stress must be accounted for by
a rule of stress conation (Halle and Vergnaud 1987), eliminating secondary
stress feet. This rule obscures the conditioning environment on which syncope
is based, rendering the process opaque. From the viewpoint of the language
learner, the abstractness of this analysis, as well as the extrinsic rule ordering on
which it is based, is problematic. (See chapter 9 for discussion of opacity in OT.)
Second, iterative uneven trochees do not sufce to predict the syncope and
accent pattern. Problematic are words beginning with a sequence #CVVCVV.
Recall that syncope deletes the long vowel in the second syllable, as in /gaa-
gaaga/ [ga.ga]. Quantity-sensitive footing produces a monosyllabic foot
on the heavy second syllable, which must be rst deleted in clash, before syncope
applies, see (133b). Now compare these #CVVCVV cases with those beginning
with a sequence #CVCVV, as in [ta.ka.rui] (133a). These surface with accent
on the second syllable. The quantity-sensitive trochaic parsing results in the inter-
mediary stage [(t).(ka).(ri)], in which the rst foot, rather than the second, is
deleted. The foot deletion rule should be quantity-sensitive in order to make the
proper distinction: if both syllables are equally heavy (#HH, as in 133b), it deletes
the righthand foot, but if the lefthand syllable is lighter (#LH, as in 133a), it
deletes the lefthand foot:
The quantity-sensitive destressing rule that compares the relative weight of the
rst two syllables is a powerful device. Still worse, this analysis misses the gen-
eralization that destressing and syncope conspire toward outputs that begin with
iambs: (H) or (LH).
Third, of the four trochees that the analysis sets up to dene the context of
syncope {(LL), (HL), (H), (L)}, three never surface (only (H) does). This greatly
contributes to the abstractness of the analysis. (Moreover, two of these abstract
trochees, degenerate (L) and uneven (HL), are cross-linguistically marginal; see
Hayes 1995.) In spite of the used trochees, surface stress contours in the stem,
186
4.5 Case-study: rhythmic syncope in Southeastern Tepehuan
#H and #LH, are easily interpreted as iambic, given the fact that foot constituency
is inaudible.
Fourth, the rule-based analysis must be extended by phonotactic output condi-
tions on syncope that block it when it would create a sequence that cannot be
syllabied. For example, the initial light syllable in a word beginning with
#CVCVV (cf. [ta.ka.rui]) must not undergo syncope, even though destressing
places it in a metrically weak position. Another context in which the rule-based
analysis cannot do without an output constraint is that of an initial closed syllable
that is followed by a light syllable, again metrically weak (cf. [vt.vi.rak]):
(134) UR a. /takaarui/ b. /vatvirak/
Syllabify ta.kaa.rui vat.vi.rak
Assign feet (t).(ka).(ri) (vt.vi).(rk)
End Rule L ta.(ka).(ri) (vt.vi).(rk)
Syncopate blocked blocked
Conate (ta.ka).rui (vt.vi).rak
PR [(ta.ka).rui] [(vt.vi).rak]
Clearly this blocking reects an output constraint on syncope: it must not create
syllables with branching onsets or codas (cf. *Complex). Output constraints on
syncope defeat the derivational nature of rule-based theory. But a mixed theory
that has both rules and output constraints might still be acceptable if the rules
were motivated independently of the constraints so as to satisfy output targets,
which is not the case here, as the previous three objections have shown. Without
such independent evidence for separate rules and constraints, the OT analysis
remains conceptually superior.
Let us summarize the results, and make a nal comparison between the rule-
based analysis and the OT analysis. Below I have summed up ve contexts in
which syncope in Southeastern Tepehuan is blocked, and the explanations for
blocking by both analyses:
when a vowel is deleted, its syllable goes, and with it a potential violator of
Parse-Syl. In evaluating this deletion strategy towards exhaustivity, it is helpful
to make explicit the truth conditions of Parse-Syl:
It is not too difcult to imagine under which conditions the deletion strategy may
become optimal. Even though vowel deletion involves the violation of a seg-
mental faithfulness constraint (Max-V-IO), there may be special reasons favour-
ing it over the standard way of achieving exhaustivity (the creation of multiple
feet). Of course, these special reasons have to do with the costs of multiple feet
in terms of metrical well-formedness violations. A major candidate for a con-
straint resisting the assignment of multiple feet is All-Ft-X.
Perhaps the clearest contribution of OT to the eld of prosody resides in captur-
ing parallel interactions of prosodic well-formedness constraints and faithfulness
constraints, allowing for a highly generalizing theory of quantitative phenomena
(vowel shortening, vowel lengthening, gemination, syncope, word minima, etc.).
Parallelism establishes complete communication between all levels of the prosodic
hierarchy. Consequently, changes at lower prosodic levels have effects at higher
levels, and vice versa. In rule-based theory it is not a priori impossible to describe
such chains of effects between prosodic levels. In fact, quantitative rules may
refer to foot structure, while foot assignment rules may refer to quantity. But such
descriptive means leave totally unexpressed the organicity of metrical systems.
The achievement of OT is its elegance of expression: no direction of processes
(upward or downward through the prosodic hierarchy) needs to be stipulated, as
effects of changes at different levels are weighed against each other. If some
action downstairs happens to be too costly in terms of the constraint hierarchy,
then an alternative action in the upstairs region will automatically occur.
4.6 Conclusions
The typology of metrical systems has been a highly fruitful branch of pre-OT
phonology. Theoretical attractiveness of this eld resides mainly in two factors:
on the one hand, the relative autonomy of metrical principles from segmental
phonology; on the other hand, a great deal of cross-linguistic variation in stress
systems. In rule-based theory, this invited an approach based on metrical prin-
ciples and parameters, resulting in a typology that had the dual qualities of com-
pactness and symmetry (though perhaps it was overly symmetric, as Hayes 1995
189
Metrical structure and parallelism
Metrical phonology
Halle, Morris and Jean-Roger Vergnaud (1987) An essay on stress. Cambridge,
Mass.: MIT Press.
Hayes, Bruce (1995) Metrical stress theory: principles and case studies. Univer-
sity of Chicago Press.
(1980) A metrical theory of stress rules. PhD dissertation, MIT, Cambridge,
Mass. (Published 1985, New York: Garland Press.)
Prince, Alan (1983) Relating to the grid. Linguistic Inquiry 14. 19 100.
Selkirk, Elisabeth O. (1984) Phonology and syntax: the relation between sound
and structure. Cambridge, Mass.: MIT Press.
Metrical studies in OT
Cohn, Abigail and John McCarthy (1994) Alignment and parallelism in Indone-
sian phonology. Ms., Cornell University and University of Massachusetts,
Amherst. [ROA-25, http://ruccs.rutgers.edu/roa.html.]
Inkelas, Sharon (forthcoming) Exceptional stress-attracting sufxes in Turkish:
representations vs. the grammar. To appear in Kager, Van der Hulst, and
Zonneveld. [ROA-39, http://ruccs.rutgers.edu/roa.html]
Kager, Ren (1994) Ternary rhythm in alignment theory. Ms., Utrecht University.
[ROA-35, http://ruccs.rutgers.edu/roa.html]
Kenstowicz, Michael (1995a) Cyclic vs. non-cyclic constraint evaluation. Phono-
logy 12. 397436.
Pater, Joe (1995) On the nonuniformity of weight-to-stress and stress preservation
effects in English. Ms., McGill University. [ROA-107, http://ruccs.rutgers.edu/
roa.html]
190
4.64.6
Conclusions
Exercises
EXERCISES
1 Wargamay
Consider the stress pattern of the Australian language Wargamay (Dixon 1981):
(i) bda dog
(ii)
a
ara dilly bag
(iii)
C"awlu freshwater jewsh
(iv) "ur
aymDri Niagara Vale-from
a. State the generalizations governing the position of primary and sec-
ondary stress.
b. What ranking of metrical constraints accounts for this pattern? Sup-
port your analysis by a tableau of Zurway-mri.
2 Manam
Manam stress (Lichtenberk 1983) is exemplied by the set of syllabied words
below:
(i) p.tu stone
(ii) si..ba bush
(iii) ta.np.wa chief
(iv) m.la.b ying fox
(v) m.be.i sacred ute
(vi) ta.np.wa.t.na real chief
a. State the generalizations governing the position of primary and sec-
ondary stress.
b. What ranking of metrical constraints accounts for this pattern? Sup-
port your analysis by tableaux of si.f.ba, m.la.bf, m.be.xi, and
ta.np.wa.t.na.
3 Murinbata
The stress pattern of Murinbata (Street and Mollinjin 1981) is exemplied below:
(i) b march y
(ii) mme I/he/she/ said/did to her
(iii) lmal shoulder
(iv) wlmoma blue-tongue lizard
(v) phJrwJrKn (season just before the dry when grass dries, seeds
fall, etc.)
Street and Mollinjin claim that all non-nal stresses are primary, whereas nal
stresses are secondary. For the purposes of this problem, you can ignore distinc-
tions among stresses.
191
Metrical structure and parallelism
4 Warlpiri
In bare stems, Warlpiri (Nash 1980) has a stress pattern typical of Australian
languages:
193
5
Correspondence in reduplication
5.1 Introduction
A central idea of OT is that the optimal output form arises from competition
of markedness constraints and faithfulness constraints. Markedness constraints
require that output forms match certain segmental or prosodic targets. Faithful-
ness constraints require that outputs be identical to their lexical inputs, each
militating against some type of change segment deletion, segment insertion,
or featural changes. Both constraint types are inherently in conict: markedness
constraints trigger changes, while faithfulness constraints, by their very nature,
oppose changes. Moreover, faithfulness constraints state their requirements about
inputoutput relations in terms of correspondence.
This central idea will be extended in this chapter to a phenomenon that has been
a hotly debated topic in pre-OT phonology (e.g. Wilbur 1973, Marantz 1982,
Broselow and McCarthy 1983, McCarthy and Prince 1986, Shaw 1987, Uhrbach
1987, Steriade 1988a), and continues to be a focus of OT research: reduplication.
From a purely morphological point of view, reduplication is simply a kind of
afxation, both in its morpho-syntactic contribution (it forms morphological
categories, such as plural), and in its linear position with respect to the stem
(preceding it, as a prex, or following it, as a sufx). But from a phonological
viewpoint, the special property of reduplication is that the reduplicative afx is
not fully specied for segmental content. Its segmental content is copied from the
stem that undergoes reduplication. Reduplication is therefore by its very nature a
phenomenon involving phonological identity between the reduplicant and the
base to which it adjoins. (Both terms are used informally here, and will be
dened in section 5.2.)
Segmental and prosodic identity of the reduplicant and the base is obvious in
the case of total reduplication, which involves copying of a complete word. The
following examples of total reduplication in Indonesian (Cohn 1989) show that it
is impossible to tell apart the reduplicant from the base:
194
5.1 Introduction
But other languages have reduplication processes that copy only part of the
segments of the base. This phenomenon is known as partial reduplication. For
example, reduplication in the Wakashan language Nootka (Stonham 1990) copies
the rst sequence of consonant plus vowel (CV or CVV) of the base, and prexes
this material to the base:
Observe that the reduplicant prexes [ 0i-] in (2a) and [wa-] in (2b), both open
syllables, do not match similar open syllables in the base, but copy segments that
stand in closed syllables: [0im] and [was] in the base.
The size of the reduplicant in partial reduplication varies between languages.
This is clear from a comparison of the Nootka pattern (2) with reduplication in
the Australian language Diyari (Austin 1981, Poser 1989, McCarthy and Prince
1994a):
(3) Diyari reduplication (copies initial foot, minus coda of second syllable)
a. wi.2a wi.2a -wi.2a woman
b. ku.ku.a ku.ku -ku.ku.ato jump
c. tjil.par.ku tj il.pa -t jil.par.ku bird species
Here the reduplicant is a disyllabic unit, specically a binary foot, although sur-
prisingly it is not simply a copy of the rst two syllables of the base. The restric-
tion holds that the second syllable of the reduplicant is open, regardless of
whether the second syllable in the base is open or closed. This is shown in (3c),
where the reduplicant [ tj il.pa -] fails to match the rst two syllables of the base,
[tjil.par], the second of which is closed.
reduplicants can be described in terms of prosodic units (syllable and foot). How-
ever, in neither case does the reduplicant exactly match an analogous prosodic
unit in the base.1
1
One reduplication pattern is known which involves copying of an entire prosodic unit. In the
Australian language Yidi (Dixon 1977, McCarthy and Prince 1986) plurals arise by prexing
an exact copy of the rst foot of the base, that is, including its syllabication:
(i) Yidi plural reduplication (copies initial two syllables, or foot)
a. mulari mula-mula.ri initiated men
b. gindalba gindal -gindal.ba lizard species ( plural)
Note that the reduplicant in (a) ends in /a/, matching this segments position at the end of a
foot in the base. And in (b), the reduplicant ends in /l/, matching this segments position in a
closed syllable in the base.
196
5.1 Introduction
This observation will become a focal point of attention in this chapter. The ques-
tion is, what explains it? Steriade, working in a derivational framework, proposed
that marked syllable properties are literally cancelled from the reduplicant. This
proposal assumes that a reduplicant, in a specic stage of its derivation, is a full
copy of its base, including its syllable structure. For example, a derivation of the
Nootka examples (left undiscussed by Steriade) would involve the following two
steps:
b. Elimination of marked
structure disallowed by
the template (=syllable, wa - was-0i$
with codas disallowed)
Steriades proposal maintained the formal distinction between a morphological
operation (afxation, copying) and its construction-specic phonology: the can-
cellation of marked properties. This strict division of labour between morphology
and phonology was indeed assumed by most generative linguists in the 1970s and
1980s (although there were some exceptions; see for example Anderson 1975).
But a fundamental question remains unanswered by Steriades full-copy-plus-
cancellation theory: why is it that cancellations of prosodically marked structure
2
The interesting question of what causes the asymmetry between the rst and second syllable
in the reduplicant in (4b) (in terms of markedness) will be addressed in section 5.4.
197
Correspondence in reduplication
This is not a constraint in the sense of OT: observe the phrasing tendency.
However, it provides the basis of a constraint-based theory of overapplication and
underapplication effects in reduplication, which we will learn about in section 5.4
of this chapter. The basic idea has already been hinted at in the preceding discus-
sion: maximal identity of reduplicant and base increases the transparency of mor-
phological reduplication, but at the cost of a loss of transparency in the phonology
(Anderson 1975). Grammars dene language-specic ways to reconcil both con-
icting forces.
We may summarize the discussion so far by the following three observations:
199
Correspondence in reduplication
proper basis for comparison is not the actual base, but rather the overall prosodic
possibilities of the language.
For example, reduplication in Agta (Healey 1960, Marantz 1982) copies
enough segments from the initial portion of the base to form a heavy syllable:
200
5.2 Reduplicative identity: the constraints
We will address this issue in the context of what McCarthy and Prince (1995a,
forthcoming) call the Basic Model. This model, as depicted in (10), has an input
and an output level. The input of reduplication consists of a segmentally empty
reduplicative afx, which is abbreviated as Afred or red, plus the stem to which
the afx adjoins. Input faithfulness constraints require that the stems input
specications be preserved in the output the base of the basereduplicant
combination. Basereduplicant identity constraints require that both parts of this
output basereduplicant combination be identical in some respect.
Not shown in this model are the two remaining constraint types which come into
play in reduplication. Well-formedness constraints require that the output (base
reduplicant) meet certain unmarked structures. Alignment constraints require that
base and reduplicant be glued together along the edges of specic prosodic
constituents.
done so far. First and foremost, both notions refer to strings of output segments,
rather than to input strings. (In fact, it will be essential that there is no such thing
as the phonological input representation of a reduplicative afx.) Reference to the
output shapes of reduplicant and base is at the heart of the Correspondence
Theory of reduplication.
The denitions of reduplicant and base that are given by McCarthy and
Prince (1994b) are paraphrased in (11):
Note that the reduplicant need not be identical to a unique morpheme, for ex-
ample a root. That reduplication may copy more than just a single morpheme is
shown by examples from the Bantu language Kinande (Mutaka and Hyman 1990,
McCarthy and Prince 1995b):
stress foot in the Polynesian language Samoan (Marsack 1962, Broselow and
McCarthy 1983).
With the preliminary denitions of reduplicant and base, we can now move on
to another notion that requires denition: correspondence in reduplication. In
previous chapters we have seen correspondence relationships between input and
output elements, to which we attributed the term faithfulness. In fact, this notion
of correspondence is all we need to capture the identity relation between the base
and the reduplicant, if only we generalize it a bit. We will see that faithfulness
(or input-to-output correspondence) and reduplicative identity (or base-to-
reduplicant correspondence) are just two aspects of a general relation dened
between elements in two representations. Pairs of representations can be either an
output form and an input form, or a reduplicant and its base.
McCarthy and Prince (1995a: 262) dene this generalized notion of corre-
spondence as follows:4
From here on, we must be somewhat more specic about what it means for
two elements to be correspondents. Following McCarthy and Prince (1995a) we
make the simplifying assumption that elements standing in correspondence are
4
A precursor of the notion correspondence is proposed in Bybee (1988).
203
Correspondence in reduplication
These candidates (and many others) are then submitted to Eval for evaluation by
violable correspondence constraints, interacting with faithfulness constraints and
well-formedness constraints. The forms and functions of basereduplicant corres-
pondence constraints are a topic to which we now turn.
We will extend the set of faithfulness constraints known from previous chap-
ters: Max-IO, Dep-IO, Ident-IO, Linearity-IO, and Anchoring-IO, to the
basereduplicant relation. The rst step is a generalization of the IO-faithfulness
constraints to other kinds of strings, including base and reduplicant. According to
denition (14), correspondence is a relation between elements in two strings: S1
204
5.2 Reduplicative identity: the constraints
and S2. Applying this generalization to the rst three IO-faithfulness constraints
mentioned above, we arrive at the following set:
(17) Max-BR
Every element of B has a correspondent in R.
(No partial reduplication)
This ranking is illustrated by tableau (19). The total reduplication candidate (19d)
is ruled out by No-Coda, since a better candidate (19a) is available which has
fewer violations of this constraint:
a. + 0i-0im.si# ** ****
b. 0im-0im.si# ** *! ***
c. 0im.si-0im.si# ** *! *
d. 0im.si#-0im.si# ** *!*
Violations of No-Coda are marked independently for every coda in every candi-
date, that is, regardless of whether it stands in the reduplicant or the base. Observe
that the base has two closed syllables, hence incurs two violations of No-Coda by
itself. (We will nd out shortly why these violations are unavoidable.) But No-
Coda disallows further violations in the reduplicant, sharply limiting its size to
an open syllable at the expense of violations of Max-BR. In the optimal candidate
(19a) Max-BR is violated four times, once for each base segment missing from
the reduplicant.
Of course, this cannot be the complete story, because the consonants [m] and
[#] that are banned from the reduplicant freely occur as codas in the base. Base
segments are different from reduplicant segments in being subject to input faith-
fulness. Their deletion is penalized by Max-IO. Hence, No-Coda must, in its
turn, be dominated by Max-IO:
reduction of the base back to a monosyllabic format, matching the prosodic shape
of the reduplicant:
a. + 0i-0im.si# ** ****
b. 0im-0im.si# ** *! ***
c. 0im.si-0im.si# ** *! *
d. 0im.si#-0im.si# ** *!*
e. 0i-0i *!***
Candidate (21e) seems to have much in its favour. It is composed of two open
syllables (satisfying No-Coda). Both of its base segments have correspondents in
the reduplicant (satisfying Max-BR). However, it fatally violates faithfulness by
omitting four segments in the base which are present in the input incurring four
marks for Max-IO. Crucially, Max-IO does not militate against the omission of
input segments in the reduplicant. This is because the reduplicant has no input
segments of its own, to which it might potentially be faithful. This is the essence
of reduplication: a reduplicative afx has no input segments, hence escapes from
the gravity forces of faithfulness.
This argument shows that unmarked syllable structure (open syllables) sud-
denly and unexpectedly come to the surface in contexts where input-to-output
faithfulness has no grip. This emergence of the unmarked is a major argument
for OTs assumption that languages are all subject to the same set of universal
markedness constraints. Effects of markedness may remain hidden behind other
factors, in particular preservation of contrast (faithfulness). But any language,
given the chance, will develop unmarked structures in contexts where inuence
of contrast-preserving factors is absent. In reduplication, such cases are easily
dismissed as imperfect copying. This qualication is correct from the viewpoint
that what counts towards perfection is faithfulness. But it seems equally correct
to say that reduplication of the Nootka type involves a kind of unmarked perfec-
tion that is otherwise lacking from the surface phonology of the language.
This analysis exemplies the general line of reasoning to be pursued in the rest
of this chapter. For every pattern of reduplication, we will attempt to reduce it to
interacting constraints of well-formedness, faithfulness, and reduplicative identity.
against any segments in the output which have no correspondents in the input.
Analogously, Dep-BR requires that segments in the reduplicant must have corres-
pondents in the base:
(22) Dep-BR
Every element of R has a correspondent in B.
Observe that epenthesis is blocked at the end of the base, pointing to a strict
enforcement of Dep-IO. We will not present the complete analysis by McCarthy
and Prince, since it is fairly complex, and we refer the interested reader to the
original work.
(24) Ident-BR[F]
Let be a segment in B, and be a correspondent of in R.
If is [F], then is [F].
Thus far we have only seen cases where this constraint was actually satised.
However, it would not be a true OT constraint if it were unviolable. Violations of
Ident-BR are due to differences in feature values of corresponding segments
in reduplicant and base. As we expect, featural deviations in the reduplicant (as
compared to the base) tend to reduce the segmental markedness in the reduplic-
ant. For example, a feature contrast occurring in the base may be disallowed in
the reduplicant. This gives the appearance of neutralization of segmental contrasts
in the reduplicant, as compared to the base.
208
5.2 Reduplicative identity: the constraints
The vowel in the reduplicative CV-prex is a copy of the base vowel in every
respect, except that it is always high. Raising of mid vowels has a striking parallel
in the cross-linguistically common phenomenon of vowel reduction occurring in
unstressed syllables. Reduction amounts to the loss of featural contrasts in met-
rically weak positions, hence a replacement of marked segments by unmarked
segments.5
McCarthy and Prince (1995a) analyse the loss of vowel height contrasts in the
Akan reduplicant as another emergence of the unmarked. Crucially vowels in the
base are exempt from the neutralization of height contrasts taking place in redu-
plicants. Hence the Ident-IO constraint for [high] must dominate the context-free
markedness constraint *[high], which bans [high] vowels:
a. + so *
b. su *!
Next observe that a reduction of the vowel height contrast does occur in the
reduplicant. This is another emergence of the unmarked: the reduplicant contains
5
An analysis by Marantz (1982) was based on a prespecication of the feature [ +high] in the
reduplicant, overriding the copied melody. McCarthy and Prince (1995a) criticize this analysis
for prespecifying an unmarked feature value, [+high]. Underspecication Theory (Kiparsky
1985, Archangeli 1988) predicts that only marked values can be lexically specied.
209
Correspondence in reduplication
segments of lesser markedness than the corresponding base segments. This effect
arises due to the lack of an input correspondent for a vowel in a reduplicant,
which is thus exempt from faithfulness requirements. For unmarked vowels to
arise in the reduplicant, the markedness constraint *[high] must actually dom-
inate the reduplicative identity constraint Ident-BR(high), requiring identity
between the base and reduplicant for the feature [high]. This analysis involves the
type of ranking that we saw earlier for Nootka.
We have now arrived at the rst part of an explanation for the different behaviours
of the reduplicant and base with respect to marked segments.
The second part is to prove that no reduction of markedness can apply to the
base without also applying to the reduplicant. For this purpose, let us turn to
tableau (29):
a. + su-so * *
b. so-so **!
c. su-su *!
d. so-su *! * *
Optimal (29a) preserves the input value [high] in the stem vowel, due to undom-
inated Ident-IO(high), thus violating *[high]. Minimal violation of *[high]
blocks a second occurrence of [high] in the reduplicant, even though this would
yield complete identity between the reduplicant and the base (29b).
Next consider candidate (29d), whose reduplicant vowel copies the inputs
value for [high], while its base vowel is unfaithful to this value. This pattern of
vowel height is precisely the reverse of that in the optimal candidate, where the
unmarked value emerges in the reduplicant. Could this reversed pattern of reduc-
tion in base and reduplicant arise in any language? The correct prediction is that
it cannot, since no constraint ranking can derive it. Candidate (29c) is identical
in its pattern of violation marks to candidate (29d), except for *[high] and
Ident-BR(high), which evaluate (29d) as worse than (29c). Therefore (29d) cannot
be optimal under any possible ranking of these constraints, since in the end it will
210
5.2 Reduplicative identity: the constraints
a. 0i-0im.si# *!*** **
b. I 0im.si#-0im.si# ****
c. 0i-0i *!***
211
Correspondence in reduplication
tj i l p a r ku B ku g u l u B l ofa B
In (33a), the leftmost segment in the reduplicative prex [tjilpa] corresponds with
the leftmost segment in the base [tjilparku]. The corresponding segments [tjilpa]
form a contiguous string of both the base and the reduplicant. In (33b), the
rightmost segment in the reduplicant [-gulu] corresponds with the rightmost base
segment, [kugulu]. The corresponding segments [gulu] form a contiguous string
of both the base and the reduplicant. In (33c), the leftmost segment in the redu-
plicant [lo-] corresponds with the leftmost segment of the base. (Recall that the
base is dened as the segment string to which the reduplicant is adjoined. For
reduplicative prexes, it is the following string of segments: here the foot [lofa]
to which the reduplicant is prexed.) The corresponding segments [lo] are a
contiguous string of both base and reduplicant.
In all three cases, correspondence holds between contiguous strings of seg-
ments which are anchored at an edge. However, this is not a logical necessity in
reduplication. As we will see, partial reduplication need not respect contiguity
6
A more comprehensive exploration of the interactions between both types of correspondence
constraints and well-formedness constraints will take place in section 5.6.
212
5.2 Reduplicative identity: the constraints
and anchoring, which we will state as violable constraints in the following two
subsections.
(34) Anchoring-BR
Correspondence preserves alignment in the following sense: the left
(right) peripheral element of R corresponds to the left (right) periph-
eral element of B, if R is to the left (right) of B.
Convince yourself that all reduplications that we have seen so far satisfy this
constraint: see again the diagrams in (33).
But Anchoring-BR is actually a violable constraint, as can be illustrated by
the perfective prexing reduplication pattern of Sanskrit (Whitney 1889, Steriade
1988a). In all examples below the reduplicant simplies the complex onset of
the base, dropping the initial consonant of a cluster [sk] or [st]:
(35) Sanskrit perfective reduplication, full grade (copies rst CV, drop-
ping /sC/)
a. ka-skand-a leap
b. ta-stambh-a prop
s k a n d -a Base
7
Recall that in chapter 3 we saw its input-faithfulness version, Anchoring-IO, active in the
blocking of consonant deletion at the edge of a stem in Diola-Fogny.
213
Correspondence in reduplication
(38) Contiguity-BR
The portion of the base standing in correspondence forms a contig-
uous string, as does the correspondent portion of the reduplicant.
(39) Sanskrit perfective reduplication, full grade (copies rst CV, drop-
ping C2)
a. pa -prath-a spread
b. ma-mna-u note
c. sa-swar sound
d. da-dhwans-a scatter
214
5.2 Reduplicative identity: the constraints
p r a th -a Base
The preference for low-sonority onset segments coincides with the preference for
abrupt rises of sonority at the beginning of the syllable (Clements 1990).8 We will
not present an analysis of sonority-governed onset simplication, and refer the
reader to Gnanadesikan (1995).
8
We also observe the logically complementary requirement of that made by HNuc (Prince and
Smolensky 1993), that syllable nuclei are maximally sonorous.
215
Correspondence in reduplication
We have already seen three examples of this ranking schema. The rst was redu-
plication in Nootka (20), which produces an open syllable, even though the lan-
guage allows closed syllables in other morphemes than reduplicants. The second
was Akan reduplication (28), which produces high reduplicant vowels, even
where the base contains non-high vowels. Finally, Sanskrit reduplication (37 41)
produces single onsets where the base contains a complex onset. All three rank-
ings (repeated below) are instantiations of the schema (43):
The generalization is that the reduplicant has the size of a heavy syllable, regard-
less of whether the segments which ll it are taken from open or closed syllables
in the base. To account for such shape invariance, Marantz (1982) assumed a
notion of template, a morpheme having the dening property of being melodic-
ally empty. In his template-and-association theory, all prosodic properties den-
ing shape-invariance of reduplicants are stated in the template. The Marantzian
template is a sequence of skeletal segments, for example CVC- in the case of
Agta, to which the melodic content of the base is associated from a fully copied
string. Unassociated melodic elements are deleted:
(48) Red=
The reduplicant is a heavy syllable.
and ranking this above the competing constraints No-Coda and Max-BR (the
OT analogue of full-copying-and-association). A simple tableau illustrates this
ranking:
217
Correspondence in reduplication
a. + bar-ba.ri * *
b. ba-ba.ri *! **
c. ba.ri-ba.ri *!
In early OT, McCarthy and Prince (1993b: 82) construed templates as con-
straints on the prosodymorphology interface, alignment constraints asserting the
coincidence of edges of morphological and prosodic constituents:
The place to look for generalization of the notion of template, we propose,
is in the family of constraints on the prosody/morphology interface, such
as Align. The idea is that the Reduplicant must be in a particular align-
ment with prosodic structure. The strictest such alignments will amount to
classical templates.
The classical template is thus translated into a constraint schema (McCarthy and
Prince 1993b):
(50) Constraint schema for classical templates
Mcat=Pcat
where Mcat Morphological Category Prex, Sufx, Red,
Root, Stem, LexWd, etc.
and Pcat Prosodic Category Mora, Syllable (type), Foot
(type), PrWd (type), etc.
However, recent developments in OT have surpassed this simple translation of
classical templates into constraints. This new approach to templates in OT will
now be illustrated by an analysis of Diyari reduplication, which involves a sharp
reduction of the role of templates, and a correspondingly increased role for gen-
eral prosodic constraints.
From chapter 4, we know that this iterative stress pattern is due to the constraint
ranking in (52). This in fact equals the ranking for Pintupi (see again tableau 74
in chapter 4):
Since each primary stress heads one PrWd, we must conclude that the reduplicant
equals a PrWd itself.
9
This step was anticipated by Steriade (1988a), and more explicitly by Shaw (1991), who
claims that Template = sum of constraints on prosodic weight and constraints on markedness
on its structure (pp. vii1).
10
Poser (1989) observes that the only exception is the monosyllabic function word ya and.
219
Correspondence in reduplication
In classical template theory (McCarthy and Prince 1986) this pattern involves
a reduplicative template that directly encodes the prosodic size of the reduplicant
as a foot, which equals a minimal PrWd. In OT, setting up a templatic constraint
analogous to the classical template is certainly possible, for example Red=Ft.
But a far more interesting approach is possible, which makes the metrical phono-
logy of the language do most of the work, and also eliminates the template in its
classical sense of a prosodic shape invariant associated with a morphological
category. This new approach is known as Generalized Template theory (McCarthy
and Prince 1994b). As stated earlier, its key idea is that the shape invariance
of reduplicative templates is the net result of interaction between prosodic well-
formedness constraints and constraints of reduplicative identity, an approach
which radically simplies the specication of the reduplicative morpheme as
either stem or afx. Recall the important observation made in section 5.1.2,
that reduplicants tend to have unmarked prosodic structures. This is explained by
making well-formedness constraints directly responsible for determining shapes
of reduplicants. Accordingly, we must strip templates of any template-specic
prosodic requirements, reducing them to a bare minimum and specifying them
maximally as the morphological categories afx or stem, differing from their
non-reduplicative counterparts only in having no segmental input specication.
Their prosodic shapes will then emerge from constraint interaction.
In the case of Diyari, all we need to state specically for the reduplicant is that
it equals a stem:
(54) Red==Stem
The reduplicant is a stem.
(55) Stem==PrWd
A stem equals a PrWd.
This is nothing but the minimal stem requirement of Diyari, independently motiv-
ated for non-reduplicative categories. Naturally the reduplicant-as-a-stem is auto-
matically subject to any prosodic limitation that may hold for PrWd. Crucially,
PrWd must be minimally a foot in size, due to the prosodic hierarchy, in which
220
5.3 From classical templates to generalized templates
We have now tracked the chain of effects which follow from a single requirement
that the reduplicant is a stem, resulting in the prediction that the reduplicant is
minimally disyllabic. However, the Diyari reduplicant is not only minimally disyl-
labic, but rather exactly disyllabic. Earlier theories of reduplication took this exact
size to be an indication of its templatic nature, assuming a morphological tem-
plate of the exact size of a metrical category, here a foot (Poser 1989). However,
a more interesting approach is possible, as McCarthy and Prince (1994a, 1995a)
demonstrate. The exact limitation of the reduplicant to a single foot follows from
interactions of metrical constraints which are independently motivated for Diyari.
Observe that the single-foot reduplicant is in most ways metrically perfect
since its single foot is aligned at both edges, while it has no unparsed syllables.
Consider three candidate reduplicants for old woman (53c), of two, three, and
four syllables:
(56) a. [(wC.la)]-
b. [(wC.la).pi.]-
c. [(wC.la).( pD.na )]-
The trisyllabic reduplicant (56b) is less harmonic than a disyllabic one (56a) in
terms of Parse-Syl. In a trisyllabic reduplicant, one syllable must remain
unparsed since feet are strictly binary, while a disyllabic reduplicant can be
exhaustively parsed by a single foot. Moreover, a four-syllable reduplicant (56c)
is less harmonic than a disyllabic one. This is because to parse four syllables it
takes two feet, one of which is necessarily misaligned at the left edge, violating
All-Ft-Left. We nd that a disyllabic reduplicant approximates the metrically
ideal PrWd, one exhaustively parsed by a single, perfectly aligned foot:
This is an emergence of the unmarked in the Diyari reduplicant. Its ideal disyl-
labic size, favoured by the sum of metrical constraints, is not attested in normal
non-reduplicative stems, which exceed disyllabicity in the case of trisyllabic or
quadrisyllabic stems.
221
Correspondence in reduplication
Next we turn to the issue of what constraint interaction limits perfect disyllabicity
to reduplicants, while leaving other stems free to surpass it. Non-reduplicant
stems fail to undergo segment deletion in order to attain a perfect disyllabic size:
IO-faithfulness takes precedence over metrical well-formedness. But for the redu-
plicant, priorities are reversed. Metrical well-formedness takes precedence over
reduplicative identity, and as a result reduplication is partial, approaching the
ideal metrical size. The schematic interaction is:
This analysis is illustrated by the tableaux (60 1). We leave out any candidates
violating undominated Red=Stem, focussing on the effects of the genuinely pro-
sodic constraints. Tableau (60) shows reduplication of a trisyllabic stem.
(60)
Input: /red + tjilparku/ Max- Stem= Ft- Parse- All-Ft- Max-BR
IO PrWd Bin Syl Left
a. + [( tj Cl.pa )]-[(tjCl.par).ku] * r, k, u
j j
b. [( t Cl.par ).ku]-[(t Cl.par).ku] **!
j j
c. [( t C )]-[(t Cl.par).ku] *! * l,p,a,r,k,u
d. [( tj C -tjil).(pr.ku)] *! l,p,a,r,k,u
e. [( tj Cl.pa )]-[(tjCl.pa)] r!,k,u
Candidate (60e) deletes input segments, fatally violating Max-IO. Next, candid-
ate (60d) represents an attempt at prosodically integrating a monosyllabic redu-
plicant with the base at the expense of Stem=PrWd. Remaining candidates differ
in the number of syllables in the reduplicant. A monosyllabic reduplicant (60c)
222
5.4 From circumscription to alignment
(61)
Input: /red + wilapina/ Max- Stem= Ft- Parse- All-Ft- Max-BR
IO PrWd Bin Syl Left
a. + [(wC.la)]-[(wC.la).(pD.na)] p, i, n, a
c. [(wC.la). pi .]-[(wC.la).(pD.na)] *! n, a
d. [(wC)]-[(wC.la).(pD.na)] *! l,a,p,i,n,a
e. [(wC.la)]-[(wC.la)] p!i,n,a
This analysis of Diyari has shown that unmarked prosody in the shape and
size of the reduplicant is indeed due to universal prosodic markedness constraints.
But it takes violable constraints to reach this conclusion: the same universal
markedness constraints which govern the reduplicant are massively violated in the
non-reduplicative forms of the language. This is not an inconsistency, but simply
reects the differences in strength and scope of two sets of correspondence con-
straints: inputoutput and basereduplicant.
In the next section, we will add a nal ingredient to the analysis of reduplica-
tion: the constraints determining the position of the reduplicant.
223
Correspondence in reduplication
Timugon Murut (Prentice 1971) prexes the reduplicant to a part of the stem that
is the residue of subtracting its initial vowel (or initial onsetless syllable):
However, such patterns are remarkably absent from the worlds languages. This
can only be due to the fact that a fully specied afx is not segmentally depend-
ent on its stem, and hence need not immediately precede a consonant in the stem.
But circumscription theory is unable to make this connection, since it totally
separates the circumscription operation from the morphological operation that it
potentiates.
These problems turn out to be serious enough to warrant a new approach, one
in which morphology and prosody apply in parallel and in which alignment
plays a central role. Such an approach is highly compatible with the organization
of the grammar in OT, where prosodic constraints and morphological constraints
are part of the same hierarchy. This approach will now be illustrated for inxing
reduplication in Timugon Murut.
12
Actually, circumscription saw various other ingenious applications in prosodic morphology
(see McCarthy and Prince 1990, 1995b), which also are subject to the same general criticisms.
225
Correspondence in reduplication
(68) Align-Red-L
Align the left edge of the reduplicant with the left edge of the PrWd.
This interaction is illustrated by tableau (69), which also presents a third candid-
ate (69c), showing the activity of Align-Red-L in keeping the inx leftmost in
the word:
a. + u-la-lampoy * u
b. u-ulampoy **!
c. ulam-po-poy * ul!am
13
Undominated input faithfulness constraints, Dep-IO and Max-IO, block consonant epenthesis
and vowel deletion as strategies to avoid onset-less syllables.
226
5.4 From circumscription to alignment
close as possible to the left edge, which is what makes (69a) more harmonic than
(69c).
This nishes the core of the analysis. Its success (as compared to circumscrip-
tion) is due to two factors. First, the fact that prosody and morphology operate
in parallel, rather than serially. The position of the inx (morphology) depends
on the relative prosodic well-formedness of the output. The second key feature of
this analysis is the violability of constraints. The requirement that the reduplicant
is a prex (Align-Red-L) is violable precisely to the extent necessary to avoid
violation of prosodic well-formedness (Onset).
There are some residual issues, to which we now turn. Consider another logically
possible strategy to avoid excessive violation of Onset, while keeping the redu-
plicative afx strictly initial in the word. This strategy is to copy yet another
segment of the base, producing the candidate *ul-ulampoy. It may appear that this
is a genuine improvement over u-la-lampoy: both have one onset-less syllable, but
the former is a perfect prex, while the latter is a near miss. Then what excludes
*ul-ulampoy? Observe that the single improvement of *ul-ulampoy over *u-
ulampoy resides in its lesser violation of Onset, due to its additional onset con-
sonant [l]. But in order to make this [l] a genuine onset, it must syllabify into
the base, thereby blurring the edge between reduplicant and base.
(71) Red=
Align both edges of the reduplicant with the edges of a syllable.
a. + u-la-lampoy u
b. u.l-u.lampoy l!
14
We leave open the consequences of adopting this constraint for Generalized Template theory.
227
Correspondence in reduplication
As noted above, apart from its alignment function, Red= is also responsible for
the size limitation of the reduplicant to one syllable. Therefore it must dominate
Max-BR, ruling out output forms such as *u- lam.poy -lam.poy.
Let us now turn to the interaction between IO-faithfulness constraints and
syllabic well-formedness constraints. Timugon Murut disallows consonant epen-
thesis and vowel deletion as strategies to repair onset-less or closed syllables.
From this we conclude that faithfulness (Dep-IO, Max-IO) dominates prosodic
well-formedness (Onset, No-Coda):
a. + u.lam.poy * **
b. lam.poy *! **
c. u.la.po *!* *
d. Tu.lam.poy *! **
e. u.la.mA.po.yA *!* *
Let us now put all pieces together, and consider the complete analysis. We have
evidence for three undominated constraints: Red=, Dep-IO, Max-IO. These
dominate a pair of syllable well-formedness constraints: Onset and No-Coda,
which in their turn dominate two reduplicative constraints: Align-Red-L and
Max-BR:
15
In fact, one input faithfulness constraint is violated under inxation: Contiguity-IO.
228
5.5 Classical versus OT-based prosodic morphology: conclusions
(76)
Input: /red, ulampoy/ Red= Dep- Max- Onset No- Align- Max-
IO IO Coda Red-L BR
a. + u-la-lam.poy * ** u mpoy
e. la-lam.poy *! ** mpoy
f. Tu-Tu.lam.poy *! ** lampoy
g. u.l-u.lam.poy l! * ** ampoy
Finally, reconsider the serial analysis of this pattern presented in section 5.4.1,
which was based on the circumscription of the initial vowel and prexation of the
reduplicant to the residue of the base. We ended section 5.4.1 by reecting on the
observation, due to McCarthy and Prince (1993a), that a circumscriptional ana-
lysis is principally unable to explain why it is always a reduplicative inx that
skips over the initial onset-less syllable.
Now observe that an OT analyis does make this prediction, for nothing would
be gained (over simple prexation) by the inxation of a segmentally specied
prex /ka-/. Both of the output candidates forms below have one violation of the
constraint Onset:
229
Correspondence in reduplication
In the following sections, we will discuss further evidence that lends support to
the OT-based theory of reduplication. We will rst turn to another central theme
of research in reduplication theory, overapplication and underapplication.
5.6.1 Introduction
As we saw in previous sections, the basic idea behind the OT model of redup-
lication is that reduplicative identity constraints compete with well-formedness
constraints; within the same form, well-formedness constraints compete with
input-faithfulness constraints. Both two-way interactions are summed up below:
The most complex interaction combining all these ingredients that we have seen
thus far is the emergence of the unmarked:
But this interaction does not exhaust the possibilities of the Correspondence
Theory of reduplication. Simple reranking predicts that reduplicative identity may
be promoted to a position in the hierarchy where it produces a more complete
identity between the base and reduplicant than we have seen until here. Particu-
larly, high-ranked basereduplicant identity may cause the transfer of context-
sensitive phonological properties of the base to the reduplicant. Such effects are
known as overapplication and underapplication, and in this section we will
discuss their analysis by McCarthy and Prince (1995a, forthcoming).
The basis of the OT model of overapplication and underapplication resides in
an observation by Wilbur (1973: 58):
The reduplicant prex, a heavy syllable, copies the rst CVC string from the
base. Note that if the base contains a voiced obstruent, this appears as voiceless
in the reduplicant. This is due to the familiar process of coda devoicing, which
applies generally in Washo. In contrast, the intervocalic obstruent in the base
reects its input status, unhampered by coda devoicing. The result is featural non-
identity for [voice] between the corresponding segments in the reduplicant and
the base.
231
Correspondence in reduplication
The Washo pattern of normal application follows naturally from the interac-
tion of the following three constraints:
(84) *Voiced-Coda
No voiced coda.
(85) Ident-IO(voice)
Let be a segment in I, and be a correspondent of in O.
If is [voice], then is [voice].
(86) Ident-BR(voice)
Let be a segment in B, and be a correspondent of in R.
If is [voice], then is [voice].
a. + wet-we.di *
b. wet-we.ti *!
c. wed-we.di *!
232
5.6 Overapplication and underapplication in reduplication
Let us now turn to overapplication and nd out about the ranking schema under-
lying this phenomenon.
Nasality in the underlined vocoids cannot have normal spreading as its source,
as nasal harmony applies exclusively rightwards. This a clear example of a pho-
nological process overapplying to establish complete featural identity between
the reduplicant and the base. Observe that reduplicant and base are featurally
identical; for this reason it is impossible to identify the initial or nal elements
as either the reduplicant or base. However, the identication of the reduplicant
is irrelevant to the argument: all that matters is that these are reduplicated forms,
while nasal harmony overapplies exclusively in this context.
16
Nasality is transcribed in glides by McCarthy and Prince (1995a), but not by Onn (1976), the
source.
233
Correspondence in reduplication
Which constraints are involved? Let us rst take a look at the mechanism that
is responsible for the complementary (allophonic) distribution of oral and nasal
vocoids: nasal vocoids occur in post-nasal position, and oral vocoids elsewhere.
This we recognize as a typical case of complete dominance of markedness con-
straints with respect to [nasal] over IO-faithfulness: see chapter 1, section 1.5.2.
Two markedness constraints govern the distribution of [nasal]. The rst is context-
sensitive, and it excludes a sequence of a nasal and an oral vocoid, see (92).
(92) *NVORAL
*[nas] % [nas, vocalic]
This is undominated in Malay: no oral vocoids ever follow a nasal in the same word.
The second constraint active here is a context-free markedness constraint that
excludes nasal vocoids:
(93) *VNASAL
No nasal vocoids.
(94) Ident-IO(nasal)
Let be a segment in I, and be a correspondent of in O.
If is [nasal], then is [nasal].
a. + waP *
b. SP **!* **
c. wa *! *
The outcome would have been precisely the same if one or both vocoids had had
different input values for [nasal], for example the reverse pattern /S/:
a. + waP * ***
b. SP **!* *
c. wa *! **
The nasalization of the initial vocoids [S] in the base is due to their post-nasal
position (with the triggering nasal as part of the reduplicant), that is, to normal
nasal harmony. The same holds for the last vowel in the reduplicant. But things
are different for the initial vocoids [S] of the reduplicant: being in word-initial
position, these vocoids are outside the scope of normal nasal harmony. They
do undergo nasalization, however, in order to retain featural identity with their
nasalized correspondents [S] in the base.
235
Correspondence in reduplication
a. + SP -SP ****** **
b. waP -waP *!* **
c. waP -SP *!* **** **
a. + SP- SP ****** **
b. waP- waP *!* **
c. waP- SP *!* ****
Note that if prexation were actually sufxation, then Malay nasal harmony
would be an overapplication of phonology to the base, rather than to the redup-
licant. The fact that this effect easily falls out of constraint interaction initially
seems a liability of the parallel OT model, rather than a strength. Does not this
parallel model predict languages in which a phonological property is back-
copied from the reduplicant onto the base? The answer is simple: this is an
empirical issue. There is no a priori reason to assume that back-copying does not
occur in the languages of the world. (It is actually attested, as we will see below
for Southern Paiute.)17
Let us now draw conclusions from the discussion of Malay. First, we have found
strong evidence for the role of basereduplicant identity, hence for the notion of
output-to-output correspondence, which is deeply parallel. Perhaps this argu-
ment gains in depth if we compare the analysis with a serial analysis. McCarthy
and Prince (1995a, forthcoming) point out that the Malay pattern poses severe
problems for a serial theory, in which the surface identity of reduplicant and base
is due to a copy rule. This copies the segmental content of the base onto the
reduplicant. Now consider an analysis of [ SP -SP] in which the reduplicant
is a prex.18 The nasalization of the initial segments [ S] in the reduplicant can
only be understood as being due to the copy rule, as these segments are not in
the proper context for nasalization. (They do not follow a nasal consonant.) The
string [S] must therefore be copied from the nasalized base segments [S],
which, at that point in the derivation, must already have been nasalized. From this
it follows that the copy rule must apply after the rule of nasalization. This is what
it means for a rule to overapply in serial theory: the effects of a phonological
rule in the base are copied onto the reduplicant. But there is a snag: nasalization
of base segments [S] is itself triggered by a preceding nasal but the base itself
17
A precursor of the correspondence analysis of back-copying effects can be found in Russell
(1993).
18
The problems posed to serial theory by a sufxing analysis of Malay reduplication are even
more severe, as this involves back-copying onto the base. However, since there is no way of
knowing which analysis ( prexing or sufxing) is correct, it is only fair to base an argument
on the prex analysis. In section 5.6.5 we will look into a clear case of back-copying.
237
Correspondence in reduplication
contains none! The trigger of nasalization in the base can only be the preceding
nasal segment [], which is part of the reduplicant. There is a paradox: by its very
nature, a reduplicant segment is a result of the copy rule. Hence the copy rule
must also precede nasalization. This mutual dependence of reduplicant and base
is shown by arrows in the diagram in (102):
The basic claim of derivational theory is that rules apply in a strict linear order.
Hence, a reapplication of a rule in a single derivation (within a single domain)
should be allowed under extremely limited circumstances only. More specically,
it has been proposed (see Myers 1991) that some rules reapply whenever their
structural description is met.19 If the Malay copy rule belongs to this class of
persistent rules, then what exactly does it mean for it to apply whenever its
structural description is met? McCarthy and Prince argue that the only reason-
able interpretation is: whenever base and reduplicant are non-identical, which
is, of course, a condition on the surface identity of the base and reduplicant, or
an output-to-output correspondence constraint in disguise.
The second result of the preceding section is a (preliminary) ranking schema for
overapplication. The core property of overapplication, as compared to normal
application (90), is this: a reduplicative identity constraint is promoted to an
undominated position:
19
The standard example of a persistent rule is resyllabication, which reapplies after every
rule that affects syllable structure.
238
5.6 Overapplication and underapplication in reduplication
Let us now evaluate this schema in a broader typological context. As has been
emphasized at various points in this book, a highly suitable way to assess overall
typological predictions of the theory is to construct a factorial typology by per-
mutation of constraint rankings. The central claim of the Basic Model of Corres-
pondence Theory is that reduplication patterns depend on interactions of three
constraint types: well-formedness, BR-identity, and IO-faithfulness. We have now
seen the following three ranking schemata (repeated from 43, 90, and 104 above):
Let us now return to the issue of underapplication. So far, McCarthy and Princes
Basic Model has been able to accommodate normal application and overapplica-
tion. It may seem that the factorial typology has exhausted all logical possibilities,
among which we did not identify underapplication. This conclusion comes as a
mild shock: how does the Basic Model deal with underapplication? This issue
will occupy us in the next section.
Are we on the right track? In fact, this general argument seems to produce noth-
ing but a fatal inconsistency: since how can a change ever apply, if the constraint
that triggers it is itself dominated by a constraint blocking the change?
The answer takes into account the fact that the relevant segments appear twice
in a basereduplicant combination: once in the base, and once in the reduplic-
ant. Moreover, the phonological contexts in which these correspondents occur are
typically different. For example, let us assume that one segment (of a pair of
correspondents) is in a blocking context, while its counterpart is in a trigger-
ing context. By top-ranking BR-identity, the correspondents in reduplicant and
base must be identical. In such a situation, whichever segment wins can only
depend on the pushpull of the blocker- and trigger-constraints. Therefore, in
underapplication there is an undominated constraint blocking the change in either
the base, or the reduplicant. If this argument sounds too abstract, we will now
make it more concrete step by step in the analysis of an actual underapplication
case.
240
5.6 Overapplication and underapplication in reduplication
McCarthy and Prince (1995a, forthcoming) argue that the alternations are trig-
gered by two phonotactic well-formedness constraints. The rst rules out a voiced
velar oral stop:
(108) PostVcls
No voiced velar oral stops.
(109) *[
No word-initial velar nasals.
241
Correspondence in reduplication
(111) Input: /
ara/ *[ PostVcls Ident-IO(nasal)
a. +
ara *
b. ara *! *
a. ka
i *!
b. + kai *
We have just seen a partial ranking in (110) of all constraints except BR-
identity. Arguably it is BR-identity that makes voiced velar stop nasalization
242
5.6 Overapplication and underapplication in reduplication
(115) [
] due to Ident-BR(nasal) PostVcls
ara-
ara
[
] due to *[ PostVcls
(117) Input: /
ara + red/ Ident-BR *[ PostVcls Ident-IO
(nasal) (nasal)
a. +
ara-
ara **
b. ara- ara *! *
c.
ara- ara *! *
To show how the expanded overapplication schema (118b) subsumes the case of
Malay, we repeat it below (from 98):
The ranking schemata (118) summarize the results of our discussion of over-
application and underapplication. As we have seen in the case of Japanese, it is
sometimes not clear whether the special behaviour of reduplicants with respect
to phonological processes is to be referred to as overapplication or underappli-
cation. Whenever the phonology involved has an allophonic character, both terms
seem to t equally well. However, it is not so much the terminology that matters,
but the insights expressed by the analysis: the special behaviour of reduplication
is a kind of identity effect, and the correspondence model takes this identity effect
to be the heart of the matter.
But the ultimate (and most dramatic) consequence of the output correspond-
ence approach to reduplication is yet to be discussed: the case of back-copying
of reduplicant phonology into the base. To this we will now turn.
The analysis of the allophonic pattern resembles that of Japanese: again two
phonotactic constraints dominate an IO-faithfulness constraint. One phonotactic
constraint blocks the nasalization of /w/ in word-initial positions, and is stated as:
(122) *[\w
No word-initial labio-velar nasals.
(123) *VwV
No intervocalic labio-velar glides.
245
Correspondence in reduplication
Next, observe that reduplication deviates from the alternation pattern of (121),
in the sense that roots beginning with [w] unexpectedly retain this glide in an
intervocalic position after a reduplicant.
a. + wV-wVxVA- *
b. w V-w VxVA- *!
w
c. wV- VxVA- *!
246
5.6 Overapplication and underapplication in reduplication
Note that this is precisely the result that is expected under the analysis given
above: since none of the corresponding consonants in reduplicant and base are in
word-initial position, the constraint *[w is never active, so that the next-lower
(trigger-)constraint *VwV determines the outcome.
If this argument is indeed valid, then these data constitute a severe problem for
a derivational theory, which is based on copying. The copy rule always copies a
string of segments of the base, upon the reduplicant. Copying of segments of the
reduplicant into the base is a complete mystery under this theory.
To wind up this section, let us now generalize the ndings for Southern Paiute
to general ranking schemata for back-copying. For the case of underapplication
to the base, the schema is (128):
The overapplication case arises by reversing the ranking of the trigger and
blocker:
247
Correspondence in reduplication
(131) Correspondence
Given two strings S1 and S2, related to one another as input output,
basereduplicant, etc., correspondence is a relation from the ele-
ments of S1 to those of S2. Elements S1 and S2 are referred
to as correspondents of one another when .
(133) Maximality
Every element of S1 has a correspondent in S2.
Domain() = S1
Members: S1 S2 Effect:
Max-IO Input Output No deletion of segments
Max-BR Base Reduplicant Total reduplication
(134) Dependence
Every element in S2 has a correspondent in S1.
Range() = S2
Members: S1 S2 Effect:
Dep-IO Input Output No epenthesis of segments
Dep-BR Base Reduplicant No base-alien segments in the
reduplicant
(135) Identity[F]
Correspondent segments have identical values for feature [F].
If and is [F], then is [F]
Members: S1 S2 Effect:
Ident-IO[F] Input Output No featural changes
Ident-BR[F] Base Reduplicant No featural discrepancy
between R and B
By varying features for [F], different members of the Identity family arise.
Research in progress presents evidence for certain extensions of Identity. In its
current formulation, Identity is symmetrical for S1 and S2. For a pair of corres-
ponding segments, values of [F] are simply compared, without checking whether
discrepancies are due to deletion or insertion of [F]. Pater (forthcoming), as
reviewed in chapter 2, argues for an asymmetrical format of Identity on the
basis of segmental fusions, distinguishing Ident-IO[F] from Ident-OI[F].
Another extension of Identity distinguishes positive and negative values of the
same feature, Ident[+F] and Ident[F] (McCarthy and Prince forthcoming).
Finally, Identity is segment-based in the following sense: featural identity is
evaluated indirectly through corresponding segments, instead of directly through
corresponding features. A strictly segmental view of Identity may have to be
abandoned in favour of a featural view, to account for autosegmental phenomena,
such as oating features and featural stability. This would involve a distinction
between Max[F] and Dep[F] (see Zoll 1996).
Fourth, the constraint militating against medial epenthesis and /or deletion:
(136) (I-, O-) Contiguity
The portion of S1 standing in correspondence forms a contiguous
string, as does the correspondent portion of S1.
I-Contig (No Skipping) Domain() is a single contiguous string
in S1
O-Contig (No Intrusion) Range() is a single contiguous string
in S2
Members: S1 S2 Effect:
Contig-IO Input Output No medial epenthesis or deletion of
segments
Contig-BR Base Reduplicant No medial intrusion or skipping in
reduplicant
McCarthy and Prince (forthcoming) distinguish two forms of this constraint, I-
Contig and O-Contig, differing as to which string (S1 or S2) is taken as basic
with respect to the other. Accordingly violations of Contig are of two types,
250
5.7 Summary of Correspondence Theory
Correspondence Theory
Reduplication
Blevins, Juliette (1996) Mokilese reduplication. Linguistic Inquiry 27. 52330.
Downing, Laura J. (forthcoming) Verbal reduplication in three Bantu languages.
To appear in Kager, van der Hulst, and Zonneveld.
Klein, Thomas B. (1997) Output constraints and prosodic correspondence in
Chamorro reduplication. Linguistic Inquiry 28. 70715.
252
5.7 Summary of Correspondence
5.7 Further Reading
Theory
McCarthy, John and Alan Prince (1994a) The emergence of the unmarked:
Optimality in Prosodic Morphology. In M. Gonzlez (ed.), Proceedings of
the North-East Linguistics Society 24. 33379.
(forthcoming) Faithfulness and identity in prosodic morphology. To appear in
Kager, van der Hulst, and Zonneveld.
Myers, Scott and Troi Carleton (1996) Tonal transfer in Chichewa. Phonology 13.
3972.
Urbanczyk, Suzanne (1996) Morphological templates in reduplication. In K.
Kusumoto (ed.), Proceedings of the North-East Linguistics Society 26. 425
40.
(forthcoming) Double reduplications in parallel. To appear in Kager, van der
Hulst, and Zonneveld. [ROA-73, http://ruccs.rutgers.edu/roa.html]
Coalescence
Lamontagne, Greg and Keren Rice (1995) A correspondence account of coales-
cence. In Beckman, Walsh Dickey, and Urbanczyk. 21123.
Pater, Joe (forthcoming) Austronesian nasal substitution and other Nt effects.
To appear in Kager, van der Hulst, and Zonneveld. [ROA-92,
http://ruccs.rutgers.edu/roa.html]
Metathesis
Hume, Elizabeth (1995) Beyond linear order: prosodic constraints and C/V
metathesis. Proceedings of the Formal Linguistics Society of the Midwest 6.
Bloomington: Indiana University Linguistics Club.
McCarthy, John (1995a) Extensions of faithfulness: Rotuman revisited. Ms.,
University of Massachusetts, Amherst. [ROA-110, http://ruccs.rutgers.edu/
roa.html]
Featural identity
Alderete, John, Jill Beckman, Laura Benua, Amalia Gnanadesikan, John McCar-
thy, and Suzanne Urbanczyk (1997) Reduplication with xed segmentism.
Ms., University of Massachusetts, Amherst. [ROA-226, http://ruccs.rutgers.edu/
roa.html]
Gnanadesikan, Amalia (1995) Markedness and faithfulness constraints in
child phonology. Ms., University of Massachusetts, Amherst. [ROA-67,
http://ruccs.rutgers.edu/roa.html]
Lombardi, Linda (1995b) Why Place and Voice are different: constraint interac-
tions and feature faithfulness in Optimality Theory. Ms., University of Mary-
land, College Park. [ROA-105, http://ruccs.rutgers.edu/roa.html]
253
Correspondence in reduplication
Miscellaneous
Bat-El, Outi (1996) Selecting the best of the worst: the grammar of Hebrew
blends. Phonology 13. 283328.
It, Junko, Yoshihisa Kitagawa, and R. Armin Mester (1996) Prosodic faithfulness
and correspondence: evidence from a Japanese argot. Journal of East Asian
Linguistics 5. 21794.
EXERCISES
Observe that the reduplicant sufx copies all segments of consonant-initial roots
(i). But roots beginning with a vowel (ii) are not copied entirely here the
reduplicant omits the initial vowel. The question then is, what constraint interac-
tion accounts for this pattern.
254
5.7 Summary of Correspondence
5.7 Exercises
Theory
2 Reduplication in Oykangand
The prexing reduplication pattern of Oykangand (Sommer 1981, McCarthy and
Prince 1986) is exemplied below:
Assume that the reduplicants nal consonant syllabies as the onset for the base-
initial vowel (e.d-e.der, i.w -i.wun, al.w -al.wal). This syllabication poses the ana-
lytic challenge.
This is inxing reduplication, very similar to the pattern of Timugon Murut (dis-
cussed in section 5.4.2). The patterns of Pangasinan and Timugon Murut differ
minimally, though.
255
Correspondence in reduplication
The special feature of this inxing pattern is the rst consonant of the root, which
always immediately precedes the reduplicant.
256
6
Output-to-output correspondence
6.1 Introduction
In this chapter we will consider similarities in the shapes of morphologically
related words which are not due to common inputs. We will pursue the idea that
such similarities involve the notion of output-to-output correspondence, the
maximization of phonological identity between morphologically related output
forms.
A theoretical precursor of OO-correspondence, the notion of paradigm uni-
formity, enjoyed a long tradition in pre-generative linguistics (see for example
Kury(owicz 1949). This notion played a modest role in generative phonology (but
see Kiparsky 1982a), where similarities between morphologically related forms
were attributed to derivational means, in particular the phonological cycle.
Recently, paradigm uniformity has been revived in OT by Benua (1995), Flem-
ming (1995), McCarthy (1995a), Burzio (1996), Kenstowicz (1996), Steriade
(1996), and others. Disregarding the technical differences between these pro-
posals (referred to as either paradigm uniformity, uniform exponence, base-
identity, or OO-correspondence), we will subsume all under the general notion
of OO-correspondence.
OO-correspondence elaborates on the notion of reduplicative identity, dis-
cussed in chapter 5. The reduplicant, part of a surface form, is subject to cor-
respondence constraints requiring identity with its base, which is part of the
same surface form. Interactions between reduplicantbase-identity constraints and
markedness constraints turned out to be a variation on the major type of con-
straint interaction in OT: that between faithfulness and markedness.
For example, we discovered a deep similarity between constraints militating
against the deletion of input segments, and those enforcing total reduplication.
Both constraints require that elements in one string (input or reduplicants base)
match elements in another string (output or reduplicant). These (and other) sim-
ilarities were captured by a small set of generalized correspondence constraints:
Maximality, Dependence, Identity, Linearity, Contiguity, and Anchoring.
We also learned that correspondence offers an explanation of underapplication
257
Output-to-output correspondence
The generalization that covers truncation and stem-based afxation is that in both
cases the derived form (the truncated form, or the afxed form) copies a phono-
logical property of its base (the non-truncated output form, or the stem in a
stem-based afxation). In both cases, the base is a free-standing form an output.
This extension of Correspondence Theory to relations between free-standing
output forms is the topic of this chapter. We will learn that OO-identity effects
involve both the underapplication and overapplication of phonology to a morpho-
logically derived (truncated or afxed) form. As we concluded earlier for redupli-
cation, these effects result from a small number of ranking schemata: interactions
of IO-faithfulness, OO-identity, and markedness constraints.
This chapter is organized as follows. First, in section 6.2, we will look into
identity effects in truncation, on the basis of case-studies of English nicknames
and Icelandic truncation. Section 6.3 will extend Correspondence Theory to rela-
tions between an afxed word and the stem on which it is based, considering
English data. Finally, section 6.4 will show how OO-correspondence serves to
258
6.2 Identity effects in truncation
reanalyse data that were analysed by the phonological cycle in derivational theory.
Here we will focus on examples from Palestinian Arabic, keeping an eye on the
advantages of the correspondence model over a serial (cyclic) analysis.
6.2.1 Introduction
Truncation is a general term for any morphological category that is derived by a
systematic phonological shortening of a basic form. A cross-linguistically com-
mon type of truncation is the formation of hypocoristics by shortening a name
(nicknames). It has been observed for various languages that truncations preserve
phonological properties of their base, even though these properties need not be
contextually motivated in the truncated form (Anderson 1975, Benua 1995,
McCarthy 1995a). We will discuss Benuas idea that maximization of phonolog-
ical identity between a truncated form and its base involves OO-correspondence,
a notion that is modelled after base-reduplicant identity.
This section is organized as follows. Section 6.2.2 will outline the analysis of
morphological truncation in Correspondence Theory. Discussion will focus on
examples from American English, analysed by Benua (1995). In section 6.2.3 this
analysis will be generalized into a proposal of a Basic Model, analogous to that
for reduplication in chapter 5. Finally, section 6.2.4 will discuss truncation in
Icelandic, again following the analysis by Benua (1995).
(6) a. *r]
No // before tautosyllabic /r/.
b. *Back-low
Low vowels are front.
c. Ident-IO(back)
Let be a segment in the input, and be a correspondent of
in the output. If is [back], then is [back].
1
Constraints (6ab), in spite of their idiosyncratic appearances, are in fact phonetically
grounded. First, *r] captures the well-known centralization of vowels before [r], here rela-
tivized to the domain of the syllable. Second, *Back-low is not mentioned by Benua (1995),
who gives only a partial analysis of the allophonic pattern. *Back-low functions to support the
lexical contrast in low vowels along the frontback dimension, which is otherwise based on
length (//~// ). This makes sense as a language-specic instantiation of a no-perceptual-
confusion principle.
260
6.2 Identity effects in truncation
The irrelevance of the input is shown in the following tableaux of [kr] and
[l.ri]:
a. [kr] *!
b. + [kr] * *
a. + [l.ri] *
b. [l.ri] *!
(9) Ident-BT(back)
Let be a segment in the base, and be a correspondent of in the
truncated form. If is [back], then is [back].
The truncated form [lr] shows that Ident-BT(back) dominates *r], and by
transitivity, all constraints dominated by it:
(11)
Input: /lri/ Ident-Bt(back) *r] *Back-low Ident-IO(back)
Base: [l.ri]
a. [lr] *! *
b. + [lr] *
If the ordering were reverse (i.e. feeding), then Backness Adjustment would
have a chance to apply to the output of truncation, which is a closed syllable,
incorrectly predicting *[lr]. This ordering of allophonic rules before morpholog-
ical rules is problematic to the standard version of derivational theory according
to which all morphological rules are in the lexicon, and all allophonic rules in the
post-lexical component (Lexical Phonology, Kiparsky 1982b). But even if it were
assumed that Backness Adjustment is a lexical rule (that is, in spite of its allo-
phonic character), the derivational analysis would still face a second problem.
That is, it cannot explain why Backness Adjustment fails to reapply to the output
of truncation. Note that truncation is followed by the automatic resyllabication
of /r/ into the preceding syllable. At that point in the derivation, an automatic
reapplication of Backness Adjustment must be blocked. However, this blocking
must be stipulated by brute-force means.
BT-Identity
Base Truncated form
IO-Faithfulness
Input
The truncated form (T) is a stem, a free-standing form, hence an output. This is
related to a non-truncated form, itself a stem and free-standing form, which
Benua (1995) refers to as the base (B). This base, like any output form, has its own
input (I). Correspondence between elements in the input I and base B (an output)
is evaluated by IO-faithfulness constraints, in a standard way. Correspondence
between the truncated form T and its base B is evaluated by BT-identity con-
straints, militating against any dissimilarities between both.
This Basic Model, when applied to the truncated form [lr], which we dis-
cussed in the previous section, indicates the following correspondence relations
holding between the base, its input, and the truncated form.
BT-Identity
B [lri] T [lr]
IO-Faithfulness
I /lAri/
(16) Correspondence
Given two strings S1 and S2, correspondence is a relation from the
elements of S1 to those of S2. Segments (an element of S1) and
(an element of S2) are referred to as correspondents of one another
when .
(17) Max-BT
Every element in B has a correspondent in T.
Dep-BT requires that every element in the truncated form have a correspondent
in the base.
(18) Dep-BT
Every element in T has a correspondent in B.
Ident-BT[F] requires that correspondents in the base and the truncated form have
identical values for feature [F].
(19) Ident-BT[F]
Let be a segment in the base, and be a correspondent of in the
truncated form. If is [F], then is [F].
Finally, we need to address the constraints that trigger the truncation as such.
These constraints are counterparts of the templatic constraints in reduplication.
Benua (1995) has little to say about this issue, but we may assume an analysis
along the lines of It (1990). The basic idea is that truncated forms are morpho-
logical stems, and accordingly must full all relevant prosodic requirements for
stems. Perhaps the most important requirement is that a stem must equal a PrWd:
(20) Stem=PrWd
A stem equals a PrWd.
From this requirement the minimum size of the truncated form follows, typically
a binary (bimoraic or bisyllabic) foot. PrWd-status entails foot-status by the
prosodic hierarchy, as we saw in chapter 5, section 5.3.2.
The maximum size of the truncated form can then be modelled by morpho-
prosodic alignment constraints. For example, a cross-linguistically common size
2
The term base was chosen so as to reect the strong similarities with other types of OO-
correspondence, for example reduplication and truncation.
264
6.2 Identity effects in truncation
of truncated forms is a heavy syllable (Mester 1990). This equals the smallest
possible foot, hence the minimal PrWd. Analogously to the constraint Red=
from chapter 5, this can be stated as follows:
(21) Trunc=
A truncated form equals a syllable.
It can be argued that deverbal action nouns are derived from innitives by the
truncation of -a (rather than the other way around, deriving innitives by the
sufxation of -a). Deverbal action nouns have two idiosyncratic phonological
properties that set them apart from other forms. First, they may end in a cluster
of consonants that has a rising sonority, such as [tr], [kr], [fr], [mr], or [nj],
whereas word-nal clusters in Icelandic are generally of falling sonority, for
example bjrn bear, folald young foal. The second idiosyncratic property of
deverbal action nouns is that they may contain a long vowel standing before a
consonant cluster, whereas nal consonant clusters are generally preceded by
short vowels; see again bjrn.
265
Output-to-output correspondence
(23) Identity of length and consonant cluster in base and truncated form
s.tra Innitive: to sip
str Deverbal action noun: (the act of) sipping
Vowel length and consonant cluster originate in the innitive, and both are pre-
served in the related deverbal action noun. Deverbal action nouns thus preserve
the phonological shape of the related innitive, although they fail to provide the
prosodic context which normally licenses these shape characteristics. Or to state
it differently, deverbal action nouns copy innitival phonology, but thereby vio-
late otherwise generally respected constraints on the word-level phonology of
Icelandic.
Benua (1995) argues that identity effects are due to OO-correspondence con-
straints which require complete phonological identity between a truncated form
and its base. These identity constraints dominate markedness constraints (which
are responsible for ruling out nal clusters of rising sonority, and long vowels
before consonant clusters). Before we can discuss the precise interactions of
identity constraints and markedness constraints, we must rst nd out how Ice-
landic normally avoids violations of markedness constraints. That is, what pro-
duces the stringent phonotactic restrictions on non-truncated forms?
3
A second repair strategy is the deletion of a word-nal glide /j/ after a consonant, for example
/ bylj/ [byl] snowstorm (nom.sg.). See for details Benua (1995).
266
6.2 Identity effects in truncation
a. + te.kur *
b. tek *!
c. tekr *!
We assume that the position of the epenthetic vowel inside the stem is due to
high-ranking Anchoring-IO, which rules out the candidate [te.kru].
267
Output-to-output correspondence
(29) Stress-to-Weight
If stressed, then heavy.
(30) *3
No trimoraic syllables.
(31) *Final-C-
The nal consonant is weightless.
This is a kind of NonFinality constraint (see chapter 4) at the level of the mora.
For words ending in a consonant cluster, it only affects the nal consonant.
5
Actually Icelandic has word-nal geminate consonants, e.g. [vis] certain, but these are never
preceded by long vowels (behaving like consonant clusters in this respect). Therefore *Final-
C- is dominated by a faithfulness constraint preserving input quantity in consonants. See
Spaelti (1994) and Lorentz (1996) for analyses of similar phenomena in Norwegian and Swiss
German.
268
6.2 Identity effects in truncation
Next consider the question of how to block *CVVCC syllables, that is, a long
vowel before a nal cluster. We explain this blocking by the ban on trimoraic syl-
lables, on the assumption that the rst consonant in the cluster is moraic. This mora
renders vowel length impossible (for trimoraic syllables are ruled out by *3).
Moraic status of coda consonants is due to the following constraint (Hayes 1989):
(32) Weight-by-Position
Coda consonants are moraic.
(34) Syllable weight satised by moraic coda rather than long vowel
[bjrn] [bjrn]
The actual form [bjrn] has a short vowel, from which we infer that the initial
consonant in the cluster is moraic. The suboptimal form [bjrn] has a long
vowel, but none of the coda consonants is moraic. We thus nd a preference for
a moraic coda (Weight-by-Position) to a long vowel.
Since vowel length is an input property, the neutralization of length before a
cluster in CVCC syllables must happen at the expense of a violation of a faith-
fulness constraint militating against changes in input length. This faithfulness con-
straint is Wt-Ident-IO, stated below in the correspondence format (McCarthy
1995a):
(35) Wt-Ident-IO
If Domain(),
if is monomoraic, then () is monomoraic. (no lengthening)
if is bimoraic, then () is bimoraic. (no shortening)
Wt-Ident-IO requires identical quantity of output segments and their input cor-
respondents. This requirement is made in both directions, so that the constraint
militates against both the addition of quantity (lengthening) and loss of quantity
(shortening).
Since surface vowel length entirely depends on stress and syllable structure
in Icelandic, Wt-Ident-IO must be dominated by the length-inducing constraint
269
Output-to-output correspondence
This ranking correctly predicts that underlying vowel length is irrelevant to the
outcome. Regardless of whether an input vowel is long or short, it will be long if
and only if it stands in a stressed open syllable. The tableaux (379) demonstrate
the irrelevance of input length by reversing it (as compared to the output).
The rst tableau is simple: the requirement that the stressed syllable be heavy
means that the vowel of /sko/ is lengthened, regardless of the violation of faith-
fulness to length.
(37)
Input: /sko/ Stress-to- *Final- *3 Weight-by- Wt-Ident-
Weight C- Position IO
a. + skoo *
b. sko *!
The second tableau, of [haas], is slightly more complicated. It shows that the
vowel of a CVC input lengthens to satisfy Stress-to-Weight. Strategies to retain
input shortness of the vowel fail, specically that of making the coda moraic,
which fails on *Final-C-:
(38)
Input: /has/ Stress-to- *Final- *3 Weight-by- Wt-Ident-
Weight C- Position IO
a. + haas * *
b. has *!
c. has *! *
preserving length by keeping both coda consonants weightless (39b) fails on non-
minimal violation of Weight-by-Position:
(39)
Input: /bjrn / Stress-to- *Final- *3 Weight-by- Wt-Ident-
Weight C- Position IO
a. + bjrn * *
b. bjrn **!
c. bjrn *! *
With Son-Seq (from section 6.2.4.2) and Quant-Form available as the con-
straints spelling out the phonotactic laws in the phonology of Icelandic, we can
now return to the original problem of accounting for the violations of these
phonotactics in truncated forms.
(41) Trunc=
A truncated form equals a syllable.
This constraint is undominated, as far as the examples can tell us. (As mentioned
above, the effect may also be due to an emergence of the unmarked, but we will
not pursue this idea.)
Second, a constraint requiring identical quantity between correspondents in the
base and the truncated form:
(42) Wt-Ident-BT
If Domain(),
if is monomoraic, then ( ) is monomoraic. (no lengthening)
if is bimoraic, then ( ) is bimoraic. (no shortening)
271
Output-to-output correspondence
a. + str * * * *
b. st **! *
c. str *! * *
d. s.tra *! *
e. s.tur *! * *
272
6.3 Identity effects in stem-based afxation
6
The sets of tautosyllabic consonants that trigger -tensing vary slightly between the dialects,
but this is irrelevant for the following argument. See Ferguson (1975), Dunlop (1987).
273
Output-to-output correspondence
Next observe that in the same dialects, words which are sufxed by Class 2
sufxes (-ing, -able, and -y) display special behaviour with respect to -tensing
(Dunlop 1987). The stems of (48a) preserve their tense allophone [E] under Class
2 sufxation:
The key difference between Class 1 and Class 2 afxes is that only the latter
require a stem, a free-standing lexical item, as their base (Kiparsky 1985, Inkelas
1989, Borowsky 1993). It has often been observed (starting with Siegel 1974)
that Class 1 afxations behave in many phonological aspects as morphologic-
ally underived words. For example, compare the identical vocalisms of pass-ive
(48b.i) and acid (48c.i). The base of a Class 1 afx need not be a free-standing
stem, but it can be a morpheme which does not occur independently: a root. (For
example, the root aggress- occurs in aggress-ive and aggress-ion; the root pacif-
in pacif-ic and pacif-y.) This difference between Class 1 and Class 2 afxation is
crucial to the observed differences in allophonic distribution between both types
of word formation.
IO-Faithfulness
/ps/(cf. passive)
Benua (1995: 51) argues more generally that Class 2 afxation is derived through
an O/O correspondence with the unafxed word. This OO-correspondence rela-
tion is analogous to that seen in truncated forms in the previous subsection.7
Two constraint interactions are relevant. First, the allophonic distribution of
tense and lax low vowels, once more, points to the allophonic ranking schema of
chapter 1:
(51) Schema for allophonic variation
Contextual markedness Context-free markedness Faithfulness
The contextual markedness constraint is -Tensing, militating against [] in
closed syllables. It outranks a context-free markedness constraint *Tense-low,
requiring low vowels to be lax.
(52) a. -Tensing
*C]
No [] in closed syllables8
b. *Tense-low
Low vowels are lax.
c. Ident-IO(tense)
Let be a segment in the input, and be a correspondent of in
the output.
If is [tense], then is [tense].
This ranking is supported by the following tableaux of [pEs] and [.sd], which
show that input values of [tense] are overruled:
a. [ps] *!
b. + [pEs] * *
7
Benua (1997) argues that Class 1 afxation is subject to its own set of OO-identity constraints.
These constraints are ranked below those for Class 2 afxation: OO2-Identity OO1-Identity.
8
Benua refers to -Tensing as a descriptive constraint, since it must be specic to the
[]~[E] alternation, and not force tensing of other vowels. In contrast, *Tense-low is
grounded to the extent that it reects the cross-linguistically common tendency to avoid tens-
ing in low vowels.
275
Output-to-output correspondence
a. + [.sd] *
b. [E.sd] *!
The second interaction relevant to the afxed form [pE.s] relates to BA-
identity. The relevant BA-identity constraint requires that the tenseness of a vowel
in the base and its correspondent in the afxed form should be identical.
(55) Ident-BA(tense)
Let be a segment in the base, and be a correspondent of in the
afxed form. If is [tense], then is [tense].
(58)
Input: /ps/ Ident- -Tensing *Tense-low Ident-IO(tense)
Base: [pEs] BA(tense)
a. [p.s] *!
b. + [pE.s] * *
Upon comparing this tableau with that of truncation [lr] in (11), it will be clear
that, once more, we witness a domination of a markedness constraint over an OO-
identity constraint. The analysis of stem-based afxation is fully analogous to that
of truncation, and both show that Correspondence Theory elegantly captures rela-
tions between output forms.
Again, a derivational analysis of the pattern is possible, but it encounters prob-
lems that are analogous to those pointed out in section 6.2.4.5 with respect to
truncation. The general idea of a derivational analysis is ordering the allophonic
276
6.4 The cycle versus base-identity
rule which adjusts tenseness in closed syllables before the morphological rule of
Class 2 afxation.
6.4.1 Introduction
Proponents of serial theory have argued for derivational levels which do not
coincide with the input, nor with the output. An important argument for interme-
diate derivational levels was based on phonological properties carried over from
morphologically simplex forms to complex forms. Such transderivational transfer
was modelled as the transformational cycle (Chomsky and Halle 1968), a mode
of rule application in morphologically complex words in which rules apply in an
inside-out fashion, from smaller to larger morphological domains. Cyclic rule
application is intrinsically derivational, as it implies intermediate levels between
the input and output at which phonological generalizations are captured.
Like derivational theory, OT searches for explanation in maximizing general-
izations at some level of the grammar. The output is the privileged level at which
signicant linguistic generalizations are captured. OT grammars map underlying
representations (lexical inputs) into surface forms (outputs) without intermediate
levels, drastically reducing derivations to one-step mappings. The crucial differ-
ence between both theories resides in how interactions between generalizations
9
Most dialects of English offer other examples of underapplication and overapplication in words
derived by Class 2 afxes. Among these are the following two processes (Borowsky 1993):
Simplication of nal /mn / Syllabicity of /r/
hymn /hmn / hinder /hndr/
hymn-al [hmnl] hinder-ance [hndrns]
hymn# [hm] hinder# [hndl]
hymn#ing [hm] hinder#ing [hndl]
Final nasal cluster simplication overapplies in [hm], and /r/-syllabication in [hndl].
277
Output-to-output correspondence
(60) i-Syncope
i
/ __ CV
stress
Verbal forms inected for subject (person, number, and gender) illustrate the
application of i-Syncope:
278
6.4 The cycle versus base-identity
Observe that i-Syncope preserves stressed vowels, hence it must be ordered after
stress. The stress rule of Palestinian Arabic (which we will not state here in rule
notation) places stress on a heavy penultimate syllable, otherwise on the antepe-
nult. Derivations of these forms are presented in (62):
So far, we have not seen any cases of cyclic rule application. The actual examples
on which Brame (1974) rested his case for transderivational preservation of stress
are verbal forms containing accusative sufxes. Accusative sufxes express mor-
phological features of the object. More precisely, verbal forms may be inected
for person, number, and gender of the object by a sufx that is added to a verb
form inected for subject. Observe that bold-face [i] in the forms in (63c) fails
to delete, even though it stands in the context of i-Syncope, an open unstressed
non-nal syllable.
Brame observes that the accusative forms in which [i] fails to delete are all
based on a free form [fhim] (63a) in which this [i] is stressed. The generalization
is that i-Syncope underapplies in any afxed form that has a morphological base
form in which [i] is stressed. Or to state it differently, any [i] having a stressed
correspondent in the base is protected from deletion.
The correctness of this generalization is shown by possessives, nouns which
contain a sufx indicating person and number of the possessor. Observe that
279
Output-to-output correspondence
This analysis was regarded as strong evidence for extrinsic rule ordering, in the
sense that a phonological property (stress) that is acquired in the course of the
derivation blocks a rule that is sensitive to its presence (i-Syncope), even though
it is absent from the surface form due to a subsequent rule that deletes it
(Destressing). This is achieved by linearly ordered rules that are blind to under-
lying representations (no globality), and have access only to the representation
that arises at the point in the derivation at which they apply.
From here on, we will use the notion of base in a specic sense, making explicit
two criteria. First, the base is a free-standing output form of the language, that is,
a word. Second, the base is compositionally related to its derived counterpart (the
afxed form or truncated form). That is, the base contains a proper subset of the
grammatical (semantic, morphological) features of the derived form.
10
The analysis presented below draws on Kager (forthcoming).
281
Output-to-output correspondence
Note that the morphological relation between a truncated form and its base is
included in this denition. Both occur as free-standing independent words. Trun-
cation also matches the second criterion. Consider, for example, the morpho-
semantic status of a truncated form in Icelandic, the deverbal action noun. This
properly contains the morpho-semantic features of the innitive, which is its base.
In fact, the only thing that is subtractive about truncation is phonological: the
truncated form is a segmental reduction of the base. From a morpho-semantic
viewpoint, truncation is an addition, precisely as overt afxation. (Note that the
very terminology truncation correctly suggests that the truncated form results
from a morphological operation on the base.)
By the same criteria, possessive forms have bases, for example [birk-na] our
pools has as its base the word [brak] pools, which contains a subset of its
morpho-semantic features.
282
6.4 The cycle versus base-identity
Keeping these remarks on the notion of base in our minds, we can now return
to the original problem, of how to characterize underapplication of i-Syncope
in object forms and possessives. As we have seen, the generalization is that
i-Syncope underapplies to vowels which are stressed in the base:
From here on, graphic means will serve to indicate the correspondence relations
between an afxed form and (on the one hand) its input and (on the other hand)
its base. These relations will be marked by vertical lines between correspondents
at three levels (input, output, and base). In (69a), bold-face [i] indicates the
underapplication of i-Syncope in the output:
(70) HeadMax-BA
Every segment in the bases prosodic head has a correspondent in the
afxed form.
11
This constraint is modelled after an analogous constraint No [a] in Orgun (1995). An inter-
esting question is whether No [i] can be decomposed into general constraints which, taken
together, produce its effects. Presumably this is possible, if we assume a constraint against
monomoraic syllables (argued for by Broselow 1992: 32), and rank this in between faithful-
ness constraints for specic vowels, for example Ident-IO[a] * Ident-IO[i]. We will
not pursue this issue here, but maintain the formulation of No [i] as it is.
283
Output-to-output correspondence
(71) No [i]
/i/ is not allowed in light syllables.
Note that no reference is made to stress, an aspect that will be conrmed in
section 6.4.4, where we discuss the interaction of syncope, stress, and epenthesis.
No [i] clearly outranks the faithfulness constraint requiring that input segments
have correspondents in the output (McCarthy and Prince 1995a):
(72) Max-IO
Every segment in the input has a correspondent in the output.
This ranking is motivated by the fact that deletion occurs in forms such as
[fhmna] we understood, which satisfy No [i] at the expense of Max-IO.
a. + [.hm.na] *
b. [fhm.na] *! *
a. [.hm.na] *!
b. + [fhm.na] *
This shows that we are on the right track: the basic observation that i-Syncope
underapplies in accusatives with consonant-initial sufxes has now been
accounted for.
284
6.4 The cycle versus base-identity
Next let us consider forms that have vowel-initial sufxes, the accusative
[fh.mu] he understood him (with its base [f.him] he understood), and the
subject form [fh.mu] they understood (lacking a base). The constraint ranking
correctly predicts that i-Syncope applies in both forms, resulting in a pair of
homophonous outputs. In the accusative form, the second occurrence of [i] in the
stem is freely deleted since its counterpart in the base is not stressed. Therefore
HeadMax-BA is not violated in candidate (76b), and the outcome is left to the
markedness constraint No [i]:
a. [f .hi.mu] *!*
b. + [fh.mu] *
c. [fh.mu] *! * *
a. [f .hi.mu] *!*
b. + [fh.mu] *
c. [fh.mu] *! *
In sum, syncope is not blocked by the presence of a counterpart vowel in the base,
but only by the presence of a stressed counterpart vowel in the base.
(arbitrary) assumption that only the latter type invokes cyclicity. However, if
matters had been reverse (with subject morphology invoking cyclicity), this would
have been equally easy to express on the cyclic theory.12
Let us make a more detailed comparison between the base-identity analysis and
the cyclic derivational analysis, based on the subject form [fhmu] they under-
stood. The cyclic analysis (in derivation 65) imposes a condition on i-Syncope
restricting its application to unstressed vowels. This stress condition crucially
protects the vowel in the initial syllable of /him-u/ against i-Syncope, in order
to rule out the incorrect form *[fhmu].
In the base-identity analysis, no need arises for such a stress condition, and
actually it would be impossible to state anything like it. It is impossible to refer
to lack of stress in the target vowel of syncope, as this vowel does not appear in
the output. Nor could blocking of initial syncope be attributed to base-identity,
since subject forms generally lack a base. Instead, the base-identity analysis
blocks candidate (77c) *[fh.mu] by the same constraint that triggers i-syncope in
the rst place: No [i]. If the goal of i-Syncope is the avoidance of light syllables
containing [i], then some progress toward this goal must be made in the output,
due to minimal violation. (Compare optimal [fh.mu] in 77b, which has no open
syllables with [i], with suboptimal *[fh.mu] in 77c, where one open syllable with
[i] is still present.)
Nevertheless, the base-identity analysis does still require some reference to stress
to account for underapplication effects, as in the accusative form [hmna] (74a).
As we have seen, reference to stress is made by HeadMax-BA, a base-identity
constraint requiring that stressed vowels be preserved in morphologically related
forms. The difference in approach between the analyses can be stated as follows:
the OT analysis rationalizes the reference to stress as a case of paradigm uniformity,
involving OO-correspondence. The derivational analysis instead takes the para-
digmatic dimension in blocking to be coincidental, and views blocking as due to
the presence of an abstract stress at an intermediate level of derivation. Which
view is more appropriate?
Arguably, the abstractness of the cyclic analysis, in spite of its striking appear-
ance, constitutes a drawback in terms of learnability. In general, the language
learner is presented with extra difculties in learning a rule whose effects are
obscured at the surface level. The stress that is present at the intermediate level
of representation (where it blocks i-Syncope) is no longer present at the surface
level, and hence has to be inferred or reconstructed by a morphological
12
This objection does not hold for the prosodic theory of Lexical Phonology that was developed
by Inkelas (1989), which links the notion of cyclic category to its prosodic independence.
286
6.4 The cycle versus base-identity
analysis of the relevant word. That is, the abstract stress in [fihmna] must
be related to the fact that it actually appears in [fhim]. Now observe that assum-
ing this morphological reconstruction process is tantamount to establishing a
paradigmatic link between a derived form and its base, precisely as in the OT
analysis. The only difference is that an OT analysis turns this reference to
morphologically related forms into a principle of grammar, taking the form of
OO-correspondence. But this step pays off, since it eliminates abstractness. As
a general strategy, eliminating abstractness is attractive in terms of learnability.
However, it is fair to point out a liability of the OT analysis, one which deriva-
tional theory avoids. The derivational analysis assumes that phonological surface
specications of every output form are derived on the basis of information present
in lexical representations, plus its internal morphological structure. In a way, every
complex form is self-sufcient, which gives a restrictive local theory of trans-
derivational relations. This localism no longer holds under OO-correspondence,
where surface specication of a morphologically complex word becomes depend-
ent upon surface properties of other words. The important question is: to what
extent is Correspondence Theory able to impose restrictions on logically possible
paradigmatic relations?13 Does the elimination of abstractness compensate for
this increase in globality? At present, it is very difcult to answer this question.
However, whatever loss of restrictiveness may occur as a result of the increase in
globality must be compensated for by constraining the notion of paradigmatic
relation. The denition of base, as presented here, is an attempt at constraining
the notion of OO-correspondence.
(78) i-Epenthesis
i / C ___ C
!C #
@# $
13
Various answers to this question were given by Benua (1995), Buckley (1995), Flemming
(1995), Orgun (1994, 1995, 1996), Kenstowicz (1996), Steriade (1996), Kager (forthcoming),
and others.
287
Output-to-output correspondence
This process is the source of opaque stress in possessive examples such as those
in (79a.iii, 79b.iii) below. Epenthetic vowels appear in bold-face:
(79) Epenthesis and opaque stress in Palestinian Arabic
a.i /hm/ f.him understanding
a.ii /hm-u/ f h.mu his understanding
a.iii /hm-na/ f.him.na *.hm.na our understanding
b.i /akl/ .kil food
b.ii /akl-u/ k.lu his food
b.iii /akl-ha/ .kil.ha *a.kl.ha her food
Stress is opaque in the sense that it fails to accord with surface syllabication.
Palestinian generally stresses the penultimate syllable if it is heavy, and otherwise
the antepenult. (Here we disregard nal stress on superheavy syllables.) Never-
theless, forms (79a.iii b.iii) are stressed on their antepenults, in spite of their
closed (heavy) penults.
288
6.4 The cycle versus base-identity
Violations of *Complex can be avoided in two different ways, that is, by epen-
thesis between the rst and the second consonant, or after the second consonant.
(83) a. /f i h m -n a/ b. /f i h m -n a/ Input
[f h i m -n a] [f h m i -n a] Output
[f h i m] [f h i m] Base
Correspondence between base and output is broken in (83b), where the epenthetic
vowel [i] lacks a correspondent in the base. This points to a base-identity con-
straint of the Max type, requiring that base segments have correspondents in the
output (the afxed form):
(84) Max-BA
Every segment in the base has a correspondent in the afxed form.
Max-BA is more general than HeadMax-BA as it does not refer to stress in the
base vowel. Both constraints also differ in their positions in the ranking, crucially
with respect to No [i]. Max-BA outranks No [i], whereas HeadMax-BA ranks
below it, as the following syncope data show:
The next question is: if the (bold-face) vowel in [f.him.na] our understanding
copies the epenthetic vowel in its base [f.him] understanding, then what pre-
dicts the epenthesis site in the base? We must consider two candidates, one
289
Output-to-output correspondence
(86) Align-R
]GrWd = ]
Let us briey consider the featural content of the epenthetic vowel, which
depends on featural markedness (chapter 3). Epenthetic [i] is apparently less
marked than any other vowel. This result follows from the context-free marked-
ness constraint *[high]:
(87) high]
*[
In the tableaux below we will not include this constraint, and tactitly assume it
by including only [i] as an epenthetic vowel.15
After this preliminary analysis, let us now localize the source of metrical opac-
ity. As we have seen, opacity resides in the lack of accordance between stress
and syllabication in surface forms. Palestinian Arabic generally assigns stress to
any heavy penultimate syllable. Then why is epenthetic [i] in [f.him.na] and
[.kil.ha] unstressed even though it stands in a closed penult, a syllable that
normally attracts stress? The rejection of stress by epenthetic vowels is in fact a
cross-linguistically common phenomenon (Piggott 1995, Alderete 1995). To cap-
ture it, Alderete (1995) proposes a head dependence constraint requiring that
stressed vowels must have input correspondents:
(88) HeadDep-IO
Every vowel in the outputs prosodic head has a correspondent in the
input.
15
See Abu-Salim (1980) for data showing that [u] patterns much like [i] in syncope and
epenthesis.
290
6.4 The cycle versus base-identity
(89) a. /f i h m -n a/ b. /b a k a r -n a/ Input
[f h i m -n a] [b a k r -n a] Output
[f h i m] [b k a r] Base
Indirectly, form (89b) rules out an alternative hypothesis about opaque stress in
[f.him.na], according to which a vowel that is stressed in the output must have a
stressed correspondent in the base. This hypothesis is ruled out since the stressed
output vowel of form (89b) has no stressed correspondent in the base.
The reverse ranking would produce penultimate stress, e.g. *[hm-na], rather
than [fhim-na].
The analysis of vowelzero alternations in Palestinian is illustrated by three
tableaux of minimally contrasting output forms: [hm-na] he understood us
in (91), [fhm-na] we understood in (92), and [fhim-na] our understanding
in (93).
(91)
Input: /him-na/ Syll- HeadMax No [i] HeadDep- Max-BA WSP
Base: [f.him] Form -BA IO
a. + [.hm.na] *
b. [f .him.na] * *!
c. [f h.mi.na] * *!
d. [fhm.na] *! *
e. [f hm.na] *! *
291
Output-to-output correspondence
(92)
Input: /him-na/ Syll- HeadMax No [i] HeadDep- Max-BA WSP
Base: none Form -BA IO
a. [.hm.na] *!
b. [f .him.na] *! *
c. [f h.mi.na] *!
d. + [fhm.na]
e. [f hm.na] *!
The nal tableau is the crucial one: it shows the opacity effect with respect to
epenthetic [i]:
(93)
Input: /him-na/ Syll- HeadMax No [i] HeadDep- Max-BA WSP
Base: [f.him] Form -BA IO
a. [.hm.na] * *!
b. + [f.him.na] * *
c. [f h.mi.na] * *!
d. [fhm.na] *! *
e. [f hm.na] *! *
6.4.5 Conclusions
The OT analysis of Palestinian Arabic stress and vowelzero alternations leads to
a number of conclusions with respect to the morphologyphonology interface. On
rst inspection, the opacities in these patterns seem to be problematic to OT, and
292
6.5 Output-to-output correspondence: conclusions
Identity in truncation
Benua, Laura (1995) Identity effects in morphological truncation. In Beckman,
Walsh Dickey, and Urbanczyk. 77136. [ROA-74, http://ruccs.rutgers.edu /
roa.html]
Colina, Sonia (1996) Spanish truncation processes: the emergence of the
unmarked. Linguistics 34. 1199 218.
293
Output-to-output correspondence
Identity in afxation
Burzio, Luigi (forthcoming) Cycles, regularization, and correspondence. To
appear in J. Dekkers, F. van der Leeuw, and J. van de Weijer (eds.), Optimal-
ity Theory: syntax, phonology, and acquisition. Oxford University Press.
It, Junko and R. Armin Mester (1997) Correspondence and compositionality: the
Ga-gyo variation in Japanese phonology. In Roca. 419 62.
Kager, Ren (forthcoming) Surface opacity of metrical structure in Optimality
Theory. To appear in Hermans and van Oostendorp.
Kenstowicz, Michael (1996) Base-identity and uniform exponence: alternatives to
cyclicity. In J. Durand and B. Laks (eds.), Current trends in phonology: models
and methods. CNRS, Paris X, and University of Salford: University of Sal-
ford Publications. 36393. [ROA 103, http://ruccs.rutgers.edu /roa.html]
EXERCISES
1 Spanish
Spanish (Harris 1983) neutralizes place of articulation (to alveolars) in coda
consonants. Neutralization is illustrated by the following alternations, where input
palatals /, / in coda position surface as alveolars [l, n], respectively:
2 Belfast English
In Belfast English (Harris 1990, Borowsky 1993) alveolar non-continuants [t, d,
n, l] are dentalized to [4, 1, 3, 2], respectively, before rhotics [r], [r]:
However, dentalization fails to apply before the comparative and agentive sufxes
/-r/, even though these are phonetically indistinguishable from the endings in
spider etc.:
295
7
Learning OT grammars
7.1 Introduction
Generative theory assumes that the grammars of individual languages are all vari-
ations on a single theme, that of Universal Grammar. By hypothesis, UG is innate
rather than acquired, and hence it denes the range of possibilities within which
natural languages fall. From this viewpoint the study of rst language acquisition
becomes of crucial relevance to the study of natural language, as it may offer a
window onto properties of UG, hence into the human language faculty. The
central issue in rst language acquisition is this: how do principles of UG deter-
mine the acquisition process?
In previous studies, this issue of language acquisition has been approached from
a variety of viewpoints and methods. Some researchers study data from childrens
language, while others consider the preconditions that are necessary to make a
grammar learnable.
One eld of investigation is based on the collection of data from childrens
speech, in the form of corpora of spontaneous speech, or elicited through experi-
mental methods. Researchers study these data in close connection with assump-
tions about UG, and attempt to establish the relevant properties of UG which
guide the child during her acquisition of the target grammar (Nouveau 1994,
Demuth 1995, Gnanadesikan 1995, Goad 1997).
The second eld of investigation, which we will actually focus on in this
chapter, is learnability. Here the central issue is what formal and substantive
properties of universal grammar make it possible that grammars of individual
languages can actually be learned. OT makes a number of assumptions about
UG which are very different from other models, particularly Principles-and-
Parameters Theory (Wexler and Culicover 1980, Hyams 1986, Dresher and Kaye
1990), which denes the learners task as determining values of a set of universally
available binary choices, each corresponding to an inviolate property of the target
grammar. In contrast, OT assumes that UG denes a set of universal and violable
296
7.2 Learning constraint rankings
This chapter is organized as follows. In section 7.2 we focus on the issue of the
learnability of OT grammars. Assuming that languages differ mainly by their
constraint rankings, can it be proved that it is actually possible for the language
learner to infer the correct ranking on the basis of output data? We will discuss
results of a learning algorithm developed by Tesar and Smolensky (1993), which
lead to a positive answer to the above question. The algorithm will be seen in
action in section 7.3. In section 7.4 we will discuss aspects of language acquisi-
tion which are currently not included in this model, and we will review some
attempts to include these. Finally, section 7.5 will sketch an approach to adapt the
algorithm to the complications involved in learning phonological alternations.
297
Learning OT grammars
Starting from this initial unranked state, the algorithm gradually develops a hier-
archy by reranking constraints. Reranking is only allowed if there is positive
evidence in the form of a constraint violation in the optimal output. Reranking
always involves the demotion (rather than promotion) of a constraint below
another constraint. Demotion is minimal in the sense that a constraint is demoted
to a position immediately below the highest-ranking constraint that induces its
violation in the optimal output. See (2), in which constraints are indicated by the
symbol C plus a subscript:
298
7.2 Learning constraint rankings
It is important to bear in mind that the stratied hierarchies which arise in the
course of progress of the algorithm are hypothetical. At each moment during the
learning process, stratied hierarchies represent the current knowledge which
the learner at that moment has accumulated about constraint interactions under-
lying a given output form. This knowledge is dynamic, as it continuously changes
while the learning algorithm processes information from output forms. After all
information has been absorbed from some output form in the form of rankings,
the current hierarchy may already fully match the hierarchy of the target gram-
mar. But it is equally possible that the hierarchy is still incomplete, meaning that
one or more constraints have not yet been assigned to their proper positions.
Crucial evidence required to complete the hierarchy may reside in new output
forms, which the algorithm has not yet considered. In this sense, the learner can
never be sure that the acquisition process has terminated after any output form.
However, any new output form the learner encounters may only serve to rene
the current hierarchy, rather than totally redene it. This is because (by hypothe-
sis) all output forms of the target language consistently reect a single constraint
hierarchy.
We now turn to a demonstration of Tesar and Smolenskys algorithm in action.
299
Learning OT grammars
(7)
Input: /puikltju/ Ft- Left- Parse- Right- All-Ft-L All-Ft-R
Bin most Syl most
The specic task of the algorithm in the Pintupi learning situation is to deduce
the ranking of constraints in (5) which correctly predicts the given output form
[(p.i).(kB.l).tju] on the basis of a given input /puikltju/. To this end, the
learning algorithm is provided with precisely this information:
301
Learning OT grammars
Out of this initial single mother stratum, the learning algorithm will develop a
complete hierarchy by a consecutive demotion of constraints into new lower
strata. Demotion will take place on the basis of information which is deduced
from a comparison of constraint violations in the optimal form and those in
suboptimal candidates. Such comparison of candidates requires some crucial pre-
processing of information, to which we now turn.
As stated earlier, we assume that the learning algorithm is fed with the surface
form [(p.i).(kB.l).t ju], including its metrical structure, and together with the
information that its input is the form /puiklt ju/ we (sat) on the hill.
The task for the learner (in its model form, the algorithm) is to deduce the
grammar which leads to this particular pairing of input and output. Deducing
the grammar means: ranking universal constraints into a hierarchy under which
[(p.i).(kB.l).tju] is the most harmonic output form of /puiklt ju/, out of all
possible output forms. This implies that all possible output forms of /puiklt ju/
are somehow available to the learner, together with violation marks for specic
constraints which render them suboptimal. But are suboptimal forms available? It
has been observed by generative linguists time and again that a child learning her
native language has access to positive evidence only. That is, the ungrammatical-
ity of forms is never directly offered as data to the learner.1
In OT terminology, the child has direct access to optimal outputs of the gram-
mar, while suboptimal output forms (negative evidence) are not part of the
childs linguistic environment. For the sake of the argument, let us reduce the data
available to the learner of Pintupi (who is faced with the task of constructing the
1
Except in cases where the child is explicitly corrected.
302
7.3 Learning the Pintupi grammar of stress
metrical grammar in 6) to only a single piece of positive evidence, that is, the
output form (11). Consequently the learner is deprived of any suboptimal outputs
of /puiklt ju/, such as candidates (7be) in the above tableau. Thus far in this
book, we have built arguments for constraint rankings on the comparison of
suboptimal candidate outputs with the actual optimal output. This is the only
method that produces valid ranking arguments. But if (as we now assume) the
learner has no access to suboptimal forms, then how could the relevant rankings
ever be inferred? It seems that the learner has got stuck before she has even
started. How to break the spell?
The learners strategy is to make maximal use of information which is implicit
in the surface form, but which is nevertheless reconstructable. If [(p.i).(kB.l).t ju]
is the optimal output of the input /puiklt ju/, then any output candidate must
be suboptimal, by denition. The learner may freely posit literally any output can-
didate as a competitor of [(p.i).(kB.l).t ju], and still be sure that this hypothetical
competitor is less harmonic. The algorithm capitalizes on this, and generates a set
of suboptimal candidates,2 which are the competitors for [(p.i).(kB.l).t ju], for
example the following set:
She is then automatically served with information packages of the following kind:
2
There is a procedure for automatically selecting informative suboptimal candidates, which is
called Error-Driven Constraint Demotion (Tesar 1995). See also note 7.
3
Given Freedom of Analysis, Gen will supply the learner with an innite number of such pairs.
Clearly not all such pairs are informative to the learner, due to the presence of a large number
of intrinsically suboptimal candidates (see again chapter 1, section 1.7.5). The issue of how
to deal with such noise in the data will not be discussed here; in any event, no negative effects
arise for the learner by considering intrinsically suboptimal candidates. Moreover, the algo-
rithm does not know beforehand how many mark-data pairs must be considered in order to
arrive at the target grammar, nor is it necessary to know this. The ideal learner will consider
all available information, after which she will positively have acquired the target grammar, as
will be shown below.
303
Learning OT grammars
This is the point at which constraint evaluation comes into play. OT is based
on the central claim that the observed surface form is the most harmonic output
(of all possible output candidates), given some specic ranking of violable con-
straints. The optimal output may violate constraints and in fact it always will.
However, the very fact that the observed output is optimal implies that no other
output is possible which is more harmonic, at least not under the same constraint
ranking. The learner can simply be certain that any constraint violation in the
observed output is forced. That is, if the optimal output violates a constraint C1,
then any suboptimal output which respects C1 must itself violate some higher-
ranking constraint C2 which is unviolated in the optimal output. (For if C1 were
not violated in the optimal form, then this form would have been suboptimal
itself.) The key to the problem of establishing the unknown constraint ranking is
precisely this property of OT grammars. The learner must identify the constraint
violations in the observed output (which is optimal by denition), matching these
against violations of other constraints in suboptimal outputs. From this informa-
tion, she deduces the target constraint hierarchy.
304
7.3 Learning the Pintupi grammar of stress
Observe that every pair of (13) contains the optimal output [(p.i).(kB.l).t ju].
This is a logical necessity, since the optimal candidate is the single one which is
presented to the learner. Since every harmonic comparison involves the optimal
output, every cell winner-marks will contain identical sets of violation marks. In
contrast, the contents of loser-marks differ from row to row.
305
Learning OT grammars
Before we look into the actual statement of Recursive Ranking, we must rst
expand the algorithms work-slate beyond the mark-data pairs table in (17). From
now on the algorithm will register rerankings in the constraint hierarchy, which
will acquire more and more structure until it reaches a point at which no addi-
tional rerankings are motivated on the basis of positive evidence available. At that
point, the learning process will have terminated, and hopefully we will then nd
that the algorithm has established a constraint hierarchy which matches the frag-
ment of the grammar of Pintupi. The current state of the constraint hierarchy is
still identical to its initial state. Recall that this initial state is not a genuine
307
Learning OT grammars
hierarchy, but includes the entire set of universal constraints without any ranking
dened among them. All constraints are lumped together in a single stratum.
308
7.3 Learning the Pintupi grammar of stress
opt (winner) *
subopt (loser) *!
If the constraints were ranked reversely, then the winner would become the
loser, and the loser would become the winner. See tableau (20):
opt (no-longer-the-winner) *!
subopt (no-longer-the-loser) *
(21) Mark-data
subopt opt loser-marks winner-marks
(22) {Closer}
{Cwinner}
The algorithm will achieve this by demoting Cwinner to a stratum below Closer.
A question promptly arises: what happens when more than one constraint occurs
in loser-marks? More specically, to what stratum should a constraint Cwinner be
demoted when the constraints in loser-marks occupy different strata in the hier-
archy? Should all constraints come to dominate Cwinner, as depicted in (23a)? Or
should one of the constraints in loser-marks be selected as dominating Cwinner, for
example the highest-ranked among them, as in (23b)?
309
Learning OT grammars
This issue is not void of empirical content since the rankings in (23a) and (23b)
may give rise to different optimal outputs. Is there a hard-and-fast rule which will
always produce a correct result? To this issue we will now turn.
The second general idea underlying Recursive Ranking is that all constraints are
in the highest possible stratum in the hierarchy which is compatible with the
evidence from mark-data (which has been considered so far). In the initial state
of the hierarchy, this idea is seen in a most exemplary way: no evidence from
mark-data has been considered in that stage, so that all constraints are granted the
status of being undominated. Demotions of a constraint are always triggered by
positive evidence from mark-data, and even then, no constraint is demoted farther
down than can be positively motivated by the marks pattern. This implies that a
constraint assessing a winner-mark (Cwinner) is demoted to the highest possible
stratum in the hierarchy which is still compatible with mark-data. That is, Cwinner
is demoted to a stratum immediately below the highest-ranking constraint Closer in
the current hierarchy. Or to state it differently, we opt for demotion strategy (23b),
rather than (23a). We safely infer that this constraint cannot be ranked higher in
the hierarchy than it should be; for if it were higher-ranked, then it would not be
violated in the optimal output. (See again tableaux 1920.) Each constraint is
given the benet of the doubt: the algorithm considers it to be as high in the
hierarchy as can be, keeping open the possibility that new evidence may eventu-
ally turn up triggering additional demotions of the constraint. This was referred
to as a conservative demotion strategy earlier in this section. The full advantages
of this strategy become apparent only when we consider alternatives.
Suppose that constraints assessing winner-marks (Cwinner) were instead demoted
to a stratum below the lowest-ranked constraint in loser-marks. Chances are fair
that a demoted constraint falls too deep, so that it must later be rehabilitated by
demotions of other constraints which it had passed on its way down. But when
these new demotions also occur at random intervals, a never-ending jumping
over of constraints may start. Consequently the acquisition process will never
converge into the stable state of the target grammar.
This is illustrated schematically in (24), in the form of a cyclic demotion
process of three stages. Observe that the result of the nal stage (Hn+3) is identical
to the input to the initial stage (Hn). Demoted constraints appear in bold-face,
while . . . indicates a site from which a constraint has been demoted. This loop
is eternal since the learner will never reach the stable state in which no more
demotions can be justied by the data. The alternative strategy of minimal demo-
tion, which is part of the Tesar and Smolensky algorithm, serves to guarantee that
the learning process converges into a stable ranking. We will now see that this
indeed works.
310
7.3 Learning the Pintupi grammar of stress
Consider the part of Tesar and Smolenskys algorithm which captures this key
idea, Constraint Demotion:
Observe that Constraint Demotion considers the pairs in mark-data one by one,
extracting information on constraint rankings from their distribution of marks.
Constraint Demotion is recursive.5 That is, it is repeated until no further demo-
tions occur. In our example this stable state of the hierarchy will arise after nine
steps, when the complete hierarchy of six metrical constraints of the target
grammar of Pintupi will have been deduced. Crucially, the order in which mark-
data pairs are examined by Constraint Demotion makes no difference to the nal
result, although it may be necessary to examine some mark-data pairs more than
once. In our test-case below we will actually select the least efcient way to reach
the target grammar, to emphasize the fact that the correct grammar emerges
regardless of the order in which mark-data pairs are examined.
5
We will present the recursive version of Tesar and Smolenskys constraint demotion algorithm,
entirely for expository reasons. It should be mentioned that there is also a non-recursive
version of the algorithm, also presented in Tesar and Smolensky (1993), which produces the
same results in a somewhat different fashion. This version is actually assumed in most of the
literature.
311
Learning OT grammars
This pair embodies the generalization that Pintupi prefers a left-oriented distribu-
tion of feet to a right-oriented one. Constraint Demotion is able to deduce the
correct ranking:
This pair embodies the generalization about Pintupi that metrication of syllables
in feet takes priority over the (left edge and right edge) alignment of feet. Con-
straint Demotion deduces the corresponding rankings as follows:
312
7.3 Learning the Pintupi grammar of stress
Observe that no new stratum is created for All-Ft-L. This is placed in the
stratum already occupied by All-Ft-R, in accordance with the conservative
demotion strategy: no constraint is demoted further down than is justied by the
evidence from mark-data.
This mark-data pair embodies the generalization that left-edge primary stress is
preferred to right-edge primary stress. Constraint Demotion processes the infor-
mation as follows:
313
Learning OT grammars
The fourth mark-data pair to be considered is the one in the bottom row of table
(17), e a or [(p.i).(kB.l).(t j)] [(p.i).(kB.l).t ju]:
This harmonic ranking reects the generalization that degenerate feet are no licit
strategy to improve exhaustivity of parsing. This information is processed as
follows:
In four steps, the algorithm has produced a broad division into two strata. The top
stratum contains both undominated constraints, while the bottom stratum contains
all dominated constraints. However, this hierarchy must be further rened in
order to achieve the status of target grammar. In particular, renements must
be achieved in the mutual rankings of the dominated constraints in the bottom
stratum.
The algorithm does not know that it has not yet nished its reranking opera-
tion, and it steadily goes on considering mark-data pairs. Let us assume that it
works through the pairs once more in the same order. The rst pair b a (which
we will not fully repeat) contains a loser-mark {*All-Ft-L} and a winner-mark
{*All-Ft-R}:
314
7.3 Learning the Pintupi grammar of stress
Next the algorithm reconsiders the second mark-data pair in (17), c a, which
contains the loser-mark {*Parse-Syl} and the winner-marks {*All-Ft-L, *All-
Ft-R}:
In two more steps following the rst round of four, Constraint Demotion has
created the stratum {Rightmost, Parse-Syl} below the topmost stratum, which
is in fact part of the target grammar. The only step to take place is a demotion of
All-Ft-R below All-Ft-L, which requires a third (and nal) round through the
mark-data pairs (it will eventually be triggered by the rst pair b a). But rst
we will see two vacuous steps.
Next, Constraint Demotion reconsiders the pair d a, which contains loser-
marks {*All-Ft-L, *Leftmost, *Parse-Syl} and winner-marks {*All-Ft-R,
*Rightmost}:
315
Learning OT grammars
A similar story holds for the pair e a, which contains the loser-marks {*All-
Ft-L, *Ft-Bin}, and the winner-marks {*Parse-Syl}:
What both previous steps have in common is that in both cases, loser-marks con-
tain a mark which is assessed by an undominated constraint. In the pair d a
this is *Leftmost, and in the pair e a, this is *Ft-Bin. These marks are
identied as Closer, regardless of the content of winner-marks in these pairs. Con-
straint Demotion says that a constraint can be demoted only if it is not already
dominated by Closer. But in fact, no winner-marks in these pairs are assessed by
constraints which are not already dominated by the top stratum of constraints.
Finally, a third round is needed to nish the hierarchy. Once again, the initial pair
b a is considered. It contains a loser-mark {*All-Ft-L} and a winner-mark
{*All-Ft-R}:
This hierarchy precisely matches the target grammar (6). The learning algorithm
has been successful, having accomplished what it should. Interestingly, this hier-
archy cannot be changed by any further rounds of reconsiderations of the mark-
data pairs in table (17). It is a stable ranking, crucially so. Let us see how this
316
7.3 Learning the Pintupi grammar of stress
conclusion follows. We have already seen that the pairs d a and e a cannot
lead to further rerankings of the hierarchy. Their loser-marks contain a mark
which is assessed by an undominated constraint, either Ft-Bin or Leftmost. But
in the nal hierarchy, H9, no constraint occurs which is not already dominated by
either of these constraints. Therefore no constraint can undergo a further demo-
tion which is triggered by either Ft-Bin or Leftmost.
Similar reasoning holds for the two remaining pairs b a and c a. Evidently
the former cannot lead to further demotion, since it was itself the trigger of the
nal demotion in step 9, which led to the current hierarchy. The latter pair c a
contains the loser-mark {*Parse-Syl} and the winner-marks {*All-Ft-L, *All-
Ft-R}. Again the constraint in loser-mark is already dominating both of the
constraints in winner-marks. Therefore this is insufcient to trigger a demotion.
This result is important, as it shows that the learning algorithm, on the basis of
a single output form, converges to a state in which all information from this
output form has been put to its maximal use. All information has been extracted,
and no more can be extracted from the output form under consideration. Regard-
less of how many times the mark-data pairs are reconsidered by the algorithm, no
further changes in the hierarchy will result. The learner is eager, but she knows
where to stop.6
It may occur (and typically does occur) that a single output form is insufcient
to rank completely all constraints. This we have in fact just seen in the Pintupi
ve-syllable example, from which no mutual rankings of constraints within strata
{Ft-Bin, Leftmost} and {Rightmost, Parse-Syl} could be deduced. In fact,
the language may offer no evidence for a complete ranking. But it is equally
possible that when new output forms are fed into the algorithm, new rerankings
will be motivated. This issue will be taken up in sections 7.4 7.5.
6
Bruce Tesar ( p.c.) points out that there is a theoretical limit (an upper bound) on the number
of informative mark-data pairs necessary to determine a correct constraint hierarchy for a
language. An informative mark-data pair is one which contains some information about the
ranking that is not contained in the pairs already observed. The upper bound is on the order
of the square of the number of constraints. More precisely, if N is the number of constraints,
the upper bound on the necessary number of informative mark-data pairs is N(N-1)/2. This is
just a theoretical limit; in practice, the actual necessary number is much, much lower than this,
and in fact it would be quite challenging to construct an optimality theoretic system that
actually could require that many pairs.
317
Learning OT grammars
Let us go through the essential steps once again, now following the new order.
Again, the initial hierarchy has a single stratum only, containing all constraints.
First, consideration of mark-data pair e a demotes Parse-Syl to a new
stratum. Second, consideration of mark-data pair d a demotes All-Ft-R and
Rightmost into the stratum already occupied by Parse-Syl. No new stratum is
created because demotion is minimal (both of the highest-ranking constraints
assessing loser-marks, All-Ft-L and Leftmost, already dominate this stratum).
Third, the mark-data pair c a produces a demotion of All-Ft-L and All-Ft-
R into a new stratum, immediately below that of Parse-Syl. Fourth, the mark-
data pair b a leads to a demotion of All-Ft-R to a new stratum, below that of
All-Ft-L. And that is all! In (40) are the hierarchies which arise after each of
these four steps.
318
7.3 Learning the Pintupi grammar of stress
Here it takes four steps, rather than nine, to arrive at the target grammar. We nd
a rather large variation in length of the trajectory between the initial state and the
target grammar, depending on the order in which mark-data pairs are considered.
But this variation does not affect the outcome: in both cases the algorithm con-
verges into the target grammar.7
7
Yet another issue is that of the generation of informative suboptimal candidates. As mentioned
in note 2, an algorithm was developed by Tesar (1995) to accomplish this task. Error-Driven
Constraint Demotion works by interweaving learning and parsing. The learner uses her current
constraint hierarchy, and computes the description for the underlying form which is best. If it
matches the correct description (the winner), then learning is done for that winner. If it does
not match the winner, then it will make a good loser, so a mark-data pair is made combining
the winner ( pre-determined) with the currently optimal description as the loser. Constraint
demotion can then be applied with that mark-data pair, yielding a new constraint hierarchy.
The learner then applies parsing using the new constraint hierarchy, to see if the winner is
optimal yet. If not, then the constraint which is best under the new constraint hierarchy
becomes the next loser. In this way, learning is stopped for a given winner once a constraint
hierarchy is reached which makes that winner actually optimal.
319
Learning OT grammars
constraint assessing loser-marks. We have seen the success of the minimal demo-
tion strategy in the Pintupi case study. But it is useful to understand that minimal
demotion is crucial to the success of the algorithm. To understand this, we must
consider the alternative strategy of maximal demotion.
By maximal demotion we might understand the following: a constraint assess-
ing winner-marks is demoted to a stratum below the lowest-ranking constraint that
assesses loser-marks. The failure of maximal demotion can be demonstrated in
either of two ways. First, it can be shown that the algorithm continues performing
constraint rerankings even when the target grammar has been reached. Of course
the algorithm does not know that it has reached the target grammar. Therefore
it will continue considering mark-data pairs, and performing rerankings whenever
the mark-data pairs motivate these. It is only when rerankings are no longer justi-
ed that we say that the target grammar has been acquired. Now suppose that
the algorithm would, by chance, arrive at the target grammar. Another demotion
would occur if another mark-data pair (say, e a) were taken into consideration:
320
7.4 The learning algorithm: discussion
H5 e a {Ft-Bin, L-most}
(no demotion justied ) {All-Ft-L, R-most}
{Parse-Syl, All-Ft-R}
H6 d a {Ft-Bin, L-most}
(no demotion justied ) {All-Ft-L}
{Parse-Syl}
{All-Ft-R, R-most}
Minimal demotion arrives at the target grammar in four steps. But maximal
demotion has not reached the target grammar even after ten steps, and it has
actually started reiterating previous stages from H7 onwards. It has run into an
eternal loop. Such an oscillation of demotions offers no hope that this algorithm
will ever acquire the target grammar. In sum, we have found that constraint
demotion must be minimal in order for effective learning to become possible at all.
Therefore, if the model can learn the constraint hierarchy of an OT grammar, then
it means that the problem is logically solvable. Consequently we may assume that
the language-learning child is also able to perform the same task. The learnability
of constraint rankings is a crucial ingredient of the explanation of learnability of
grammars. It is only an ingredient, however, since much more is at stake in
learning a grammar than constraint ranking. To this issue we now turn.
Tesar and Smolensky make a number of simplifying assumptions about the nature
of the acquisition task, which will (ultimately) have to be reconsidered in order
to arrive at a more complete model of the language learner. Let us discuss these
assumptions.
First, Tesar and Smolenskys algorithm works on the assumption that output
forms are available to the learner in the form of (properly structured) linguistic
representations, rather than in a raw phonetic form. Under real-life conditions
in which acquisition takes place, we cannot make this assumption, simply because
linguistic units such as syllables, feet, and distinctive features are not readily
available from the phonetic forms, and must therefore be inferred by the learner.
Underdetermination of the linguistic representation in the phonetic form raises
the problem of how the learner gets around it. This problem has been addressed
recently by Tesar (1996), who has developed an extension of the learning algo-
rithm having the ability to reach progress along two dimensions, by iterative
testing of hypotheses about the outputs representation and the constraint ranking.
Tesar (1996: 1, 7) states the general idea as follows:
the learner can go back and forth between estimating the hidden structure
and estimating the constraint ranking, eventually converging on the correct
forms for both . . . The goal is to nd a ranking such that the interpretation of
each overt form matches the corresponding optimal description, both of
which are determined with respect to the current hypothesis ranking. Chang-
ing the hypothesis ranking may change the optimal description assigned to
the underlying form of the prior interpretation. But, it may also change the
interpretation assigned to the overt form by interpretative parsing.
Tesar demonstrates the feasibility of this approach in an algorithm that is faced
with the task of constructing a ranking of metrical constraints on the basis of
outputs that have no overt metrical structure, but only raw stress markings.
Second, Tesar and Smolenskys learning algorithm assumes that the learner has
already mastered the lexicon, including the correct underlying representations for
each morpheme. Therefore every output form considered by the algorithm will be
paired with its correct input form. But in real-life language acquisition, under-
lying forms are hypothetical and have to be inferred from combined analytic
assumptions about the output and the constraint hierarchy. Of course this problem
322
7.4 The learning algorithm: discussion
Third, Tesar and Smolensky assume that the hierarchy of the target language has
the property of total ranking. The assumption that all constraints are ranked with
respect to the others guarantees that each input corresponds with a single output.
To see this, consider the fact that no two output forms that have distinct violation
marks can both be optimal. Hence if two output forms have different violation
marks for conicting constraints, then these forms must have different harmonic
values, since both constraints are, by denition, ranked with respect to each other.
In close relation to this issue, Prince and Smolensky (1993: 51) remark that the
total ranking hypothesis is no a priori assumption of OT, but an empirical matter:
It is entirely conceivable that the grammar should recognize nonranking of
pairs of constraints, but this opens up the possibility of crucial nonranking
(neither can dominate the other; both rankings are allowed), for which we
have not yet found evidence.
There is potential empirical evidence that bears on this issue. The assumption that
an input has unique output may be problematic in the sense that languages are
known to exhibit widely variability of output forms, even under grammatical con-
trol. Some phenomena to display grammar-governed variability in many languages
are stress patterns, phonological phrase structure, and syntactic phenomena such
as linear order of adjunct phrases (scrambling). See chapter 9 (section 9.4) for
more discussion of variation in OT.
Finally, it is assumed that among the data presented to the learner no incorrect
data (ungrammatical outputs) occur. Again this assumption does not match real-
life conditions under which language acquisition takes place. Tesar and Smolensky
323
Learning OT grammars
show that the learning algorithm is capable of signalling such mists, and make
suggestions about the possible role of this alarm function in acquisition.
But in stems whose nal obstruent is underlyingly voiced, coda devoicing pro-
duces voice alternations, as in the singular and plural of bed, hoed, and breed
(45):
about the underlying forms (deducing those of 445), and a set of universal con-
straints. In this set of universal constraints are included the two well-formedness
constraints (46a b) and the faithfulness constraint (46c):
(46) a. *Voiced-Coda
Coda obstruents are voiceless.
b. Inter-V-Voice
Intervocalic consonants are voiced.
c. Ident-IO(voice)
Let be a segment in the input, and be a correspondent of in
the output. If is [voice], then is [voice].
The task facing the language learner is to nd the proper constraint hierarchy
(47), and also to infer the correct underlying forms which are mapped to the
attested outputs. A priori, the learner may state two hypotheses about the alterna-
tion [bt]~[b.dn] in (45), which involve different markedness constraints. The
rst (correct) hypothesis is that the stem bed has an underlying voiced obstruent
/bd/, which is devoiced at the end of the syllable in the singular. Syllable-nal
devoicing involves domination of the markedness constraint *Voiced-Coda over
the featural faithfulness constraint Ident-IO(voice), as we have seen in chap-
ter 1. The alternative hypothesis is that the stem bed has an underlying voiceless
obstruent /bt/, which is voiced in intervocalic position in the plural. Intervocalic
voicing involves domination of the markedness constraint Inter-V-Voice over
Ident-IO(voice). This hypothesis is demonstrably incorrect, as no constraint hier-
archy that involves this ranking is consistent with the data. But let us rst discuss
the mapping of the correct underlying forms to the attested outputs.
Under the correct hypothesis, the underlying forms /pt/ and /bd/ are mapped
onto surface forms by the ranked constraints of (47), as illustrated by the tableaux
325
Learning OT grammars
a. + pt
b. pd *! *
a. + bt *
b. bd *!
None of these tableaux contain evidence for the ranking of Inter-V-Voice, since
all output candidates which are considered satisfy this constraint. (There is no
intervocalic context.)
a. + p.tn *
b. p.dn *!
a. b.tn *! *
b. + b.dn
Note that tableau (51) of [b.dn] beds gives no information about ranking
whatsoever.
Now consider the (incorrect) alternative hypothesis, under which the voiced [d]
in [b.dn] derives from an input /t/ in /bt-n/ by intervocalic voicing. The
grammar which performs this mapping must crucially rank Inter-V-Voice
326
7.5 Learning alternations and input representations
This ranking actually derives all the forms correctly except one: it predicts
*[p.dn] caps rather than [p.tn]. (The incorrect winner is indicated by a L
symbol.)
a. p.tn *!
b. L p.dn *
The intervocalic voicing contrast has vanished due to the demotion of Ident-
IO(voice).
The argument for the correct grammar (47) over the hypothetical grammar in (52)
is based on the voicing alternation in bedbedden, and lack thereof in petpetten.
This makes a perfectly straightforward argument. However, we must ask whether
the choice in favour of grammar (47) is equally transparent to the learner, who
must determine both the underlying forms and the constraint rankings, on the
basis of only surface forms and a set of universal constraints. What makes a child
learning Dutch eventually select this correct combination of grammar and lex-
icon, rather than one in which the alternation in bedbedden is due to intervocalic
voicing of an underlying /t/? Actually, we will show that the correct grammar and
underlying forms are learnable by the Tesar and Smolensky learning algorithm, if
only this algorithm is extended by iterative learning in the sense of Tesar (1996).
That is, the learner can go back and forth between estimating the underlying
forms and estimating the constraint ranking, and eventually converges on the
correct forms for both. We will argue that Lexicon Optimization plays an import-
ant role in this learning procedure.
underlying forms, and return to this in due course. The initial state of the learner
is the universal set of unranked constraints contained in a single stratum, of which
(54) forms a subset:
Assume that the learner is rst confronted with the surface form [bt], equipped
with the correct underlying form / bd/. The mark-data pairs of the optimal can-
didate [bt] and its major competitor [bd] are given below:
bd bt {**Voiced-Coda} {*Ident-IO(voice)}
Observe that this happens to be the incorrect hypothetical grammar of (52). What
makes the child reject this? It will be clear that no valuable information can be
gathered from the surface forms [pt] and [b.dn], since these violate none of
the three constraints in (56). (See tableaux 48 and 51.) And since there is no
interaction of constraints in these cases, no new rankings can be established.
But sooner or later, the Dutch child comes across the crucial surface form
[p.tn], which will induce a second round of the constraint demotion algorithm.
Again, no cancellation of marks occurs. It is made sure that the constraint which
induces the loser-mark, Ident-IO(voice), does not dominate the constraint induc-
ing the winner-mark, Inter-V-Voice. In accordance with the algorithm the latter
constraint is demoted to a stratum immediately below that of the former con-
straint:
which is the correct mini-grammar of the voicing alternations in (44 5). We leave
it as an exercise to the reader to establish that the learning algorithm would have
yielded the same result when surface forms were presented in the opposite order,
with [p.tn] preceding [bd].
/ bt / bd bt {* *Voiced-Coda,
*Ident-IO(voice)}
Actually this mark-data pair is never considered by the core algorithm since it is
eliminated by provision (16b) of Marks Cancellation even before Constraint
Demotion applies. The constraint ranking therefore remains in its initial state.
Let us assume that the learner is now confronted with the plural form [b.dn],
and (after judicious morphological analysis) attributes this form to the morpheme
/ bt/ which occurs in the singular [bt]. Starting from this incorrect lexical
form /bt /, the following mark-data pairs will be constructed:
8
It is an entirely different question whether the child actually proceeds incrementally on the
way to the target constraint ranking. Evidence presently available strongly suggests that chil-
drens grammars may have different constraint rankings from adult grammars. See the next
section.
330
7.5 Learning alternations and input representations
Next, the child encounters the singular form [pt], which she considers to be on
a par with the singular [bt], currently attributed to the lexical form / bt /. The
child simply registers [pt] under the lexical form /pt/,
(62) IO-pairings after learners exposure to output set {[bt], [b.dn],
[pt]}
a. /pt / [pt]
b. / bt / [bt] ~ /bt-n/ [ b.dn]
At this stage, the learner is completely unaware of its plural [p.tn], which will
induce an important constraint demotion in a later stage of learning. In fact, if the
child were asked to produce the plural of [pt] in this acquisitional stage, she
would have no choice but to reply: [p.dn]!, since this is literally what the
ranking (61) predicts that it should be. The model predicts overgeneralization of
phonology in alternations, which is a widely observed characteristic of childrens
grammars. See section 7.5.4 for Dutch language acquisition data which corrobor-
ate this prediction.
The nal form which the child is confronted with is [p.tn]. This comes as a
shock to the child, as this is the rst surface form she encounters in which
*Inter-V-Voice is violated. A mark-data pair is immediately drawn up:
331
Learning OT grammars
This presents ranking information which conicts with that of the form [b.dn]
beds in (60). However, since [p.tn] is the current form under analysis, the
learner proceeds to track mechanically its consequences for the hierarchy. Let us
carefully consider the steps taken by the Constraint Demotion algorithm.
(64) { . . . *Voiced-Coda . . . }
{Ident-IO(voice)}
{Inter-V-Voice}
The child has actually succeeded in learning the correct target ranking. This
achievement is remarkable, given the fact that it is based on incorrect inferences
about underlying forms. But may we also conclude that the child has now suc-
cessfully acquired the fragment of the grammar which derives the voicing pattern?
Of course we may not, since the underlying forms of the pair [bt] ~ [bdn]
are still misrepresented as /bt / ~ / bt-n/. Once the ranking (64) has been
established, the child will make the incorrect prediction *[b.tn] for the plural
form see tableau (65):
a. L b.tn *
b. b.dn *!
332
7.5 Learning alternations and input representations
The rst strategy, going through another constraint demotion, may in fact produce
a short-term success with respect to the problematic form, but will not converge
into a stable ranking. The mark-data pairs of table (60) reactivate Constraint
Demotion in the hierarchy (64). Concretely, Ident-IO(voice) will be demoted
below Inter-V-Voice:
This hierarchy accounts for [bdn], but of course we run into a loop now, as we
have been in this stage before, at a point prior to the introduction of the form
[ptn]. The learner will go through the entire demotion process once more,
exchanging positions between Inter-V-Voice and Ident-IO(voice), without ever
converging into the target grammar. Note that these stages crucially include the
mark-data pairs (60) and the ranking (61). In sum, the rst option of repairing the
hierarchy by Constraint Demotion produces an eternal loop.
Of all things, eternal loops must be avoided most. Hence the learner must
capitalize on any information warning her that she is entering a loop. Actually, a
signal is given to the learner right at this point: a stratum is vacated. To vacate
a stratum means: to demote a constraint from a stratum in which it was the single
constraint. An empty stratum has been indicated in (66) by { . . . }.
Stated generally, a loop occurs whenever the learner is presented with incon-
sistent information with respect to the ranking of two constraints.9 That is, a pair
of constraints C1 and C2 must be ranked C1 C2 for one set of forms, and as C2
C1 for another set of forms. If the learner encounters both sets of forms, an
9
The same idea that vacating of a stratum points to an inconsistency in the underlying forms
was used by Broihier (1995) to solve the problem of learning grammars with tied constraints.
333
Learning OT grammars
eternal process of ranking and reranking starts that never terminates in a stable
hierarchy. The diagnostic for inconsistency in the data with respect to ranking is
the vacation of a stratum a consistent target ranking never gives rise to a loop.
Since the learner may assume that the target ranking is consistent with the data,
any sign of an eternal loop must be due to another cause an incorrect assump-
tion about input forms.
What causes an incorrect assumption about the input? Clearly the error must
reside in an alternating morpheme, whose alternants are specied as [+F] and
[F], respectively, in different contexts. By Lexicon Optimization, the learner
will be led to analyse the rst occurring alternant of a morpheme to reect its
input value. Hence, if the learner happens to encounter the alternant [F] rst,
she will set up the incorrect input value [F], even when the correct input value
is [+F].
This erroneous assumption on inputs causes the (apparent) inconsistency in
ranking, as follows. The value of the feature [F] in a non-alternating morpheme
always equals the value of [F] in one of the alternants of an alternating mor-
pheme. This is simply due to the neutralizing nature of the processes causing
alternations. (For example, word-nal [voice] occurs in both the alternating form
[bt] and in the non-alternating form [pt].) Alternating and non-alternating mor-
phemes have identical specications for [ F] in a specic context, as is shown
schematically below:
The problem occurs when the learner attributes both types of morphemes to the
same input value, [F]. This causes an apparent inconsistency in the ranking of
faithfulness constraints and markedness constraints in the elsewhere context
(here: bedden versus petten). The loop signals that such a situation occurs.
Once this alarm bell goes, the learner adjusts her underlying representation of the
observed output form in accordance with Lexicon Optimization. Restructuring of
the current input / bt-n/ into the new input /bd-n/ is forced as the single
method of reaching compatibility with the current hierarchy (64). This is achieved
by provision (68b):
At this point, when the learner is confronted with the output form [bt], the
hierarchy (64) still holds. The algorithm
forms are unchanged, since the Anti-Loop Provision is only activated by forms
which pose the threat of vacating a stratum. It is easy to show that such a threat
is not posed by [pt] or [p.tn], though. First, mark-data pairs for [pt] are
trivially uninformative. Second, mark-data pairs of [p.tn] in (63), if anything,
might motivate a demotion of Inter-V-Voice below Ident-IO(voice). However,
this demotion is inapplicable, as Ident-IO(voice) already dominates Inter-V-
Voice in the current ranking (64). In sum, non-alternating forms are incapable of
triggering any demotion, hence the Anti-Loop Provision is never activated, auto-
matically preserving the inputs.
Therefore we may safely conclude that the learning algorithm has converged
into the target grammar of Dutch: the hierarchy (64). But even more importantly,
the learner has succeeded in establishing the correct set of underlying forms for
alternating morphemes. That is, the learner has overcome the handicap that under-
lying forms are not pre-given, but have to be inferred from output forms on the
basis of hypothetical constraint rankings.
10
I wish to thank Martin Everaert for sharing these data with me.
336
7.5 Learning alternations and input representations
During this stage, Emma voices obstruents in intervocalic positions where adult
forms have voiceless ones (72a). The context of voicing is actually more general
than intervocalic. That is, Emma voices obstruents in between approximants and
vowels, as (72b) shows, but not after a nasal (72c) or an obstruent (72d).
Only two months later, the pattern has extended into prevocalic obstruents
following nasals (73c), generalizing the process to post-sonorant obstruents:
7.5.5 Discussion
For expository reasons, the alternation problem discussed has been a simple one,
involving only a single alternation. Yet our success in solving this problem sug-
gests that the Tesar and Smolensky algorithm is extendable to handle more com-
plex alternations. The central idea that we have explored here is that of building
inertness of the hierarchy into the learning algorithm, prohibiting the demotion
of a constraint which forms a stratum on its own. This presents a warning bell
to the learner that current assumptions about input forms may be incorrect, as a
result of which lexical restructuring takes place. Such adjustment of input forms
by the Anti-Loop Provision is always concrete, in the sense that it copies pho-
nological structure of the output (here, a feature value for [voice]), in accordance
with Lexicon Optimization. In chapter 9 (section 9.6) we will re-evaluate the need
for underlying forms in OT, sketching an alternative in terms of allomorphs.
337
Learning OT grammars
Parameters
Dresher, Elan and Jonathan Kaye (1990) A computational learning model for
metrical phonology. Cognition 34. 13795.
Connectionist models
Daelemans, Walter, Steven Gillis, and Gert Durieux (1994) The acquisition of
stress: a data-oriented approach. Computational Linguistics 20. 42151.
Gupta, Prahlad and David Touretzky (1994) Connectionist models and linguistic
theory: investigations of stress systems in language. Cognitive Science 18.
150.
Child phonology
Demuth, Katherine (1995) Markedness and the development of phonological
structure. In J. Beckman (ed.), Proceedings of the 25th North East Linguistic
Society, II: Papers from the workshops on language acquisitions and lan-
guage change. 13 25.
Gnanadesikan, Amalia (1995) Markedness and faithfulness constraints in
child phonology. Ms., University of Massachusetts, Amherst. [ROA-67,
http://ruccs.rutgers.edu/roa.html]
Goad, Heather (1997) Consonant harmony in child language. In S. J. Hannahs and
M. Young-Scholten (eds.), Focus on phonological acquisition. Amsterdam:
John Benjamins. 11342.
Syntactic acquisition
Broihier, Kevin (1995) Optimality theoretic rankings with tied constraints: Slavic
relatives, resumptive pronouns and learnability. Ms., Department of Brain
and Cognitive Sciences, MIT. [ROA-46, http://ruccs.rutgers.edu /roa.html]
EXERCISES
The goal is to nd a ranking of the three constraints such that the winner is more
harmonic than the loser, for both pairs. The question is, why not create a new
stratum containing the demoted constraint Mid by itself?
11
Thanks to Bruce Tesar (p.c.) for suggestions which have inspired this problem.
339
Learning OT grammars
(iii) Demotion steps using stratied hierarchies, from initial state {Low,
Mid, Top}:
Steps Hierarchies after steps 13
H0 {Low, Mid, Top}
H1 b a
H2 c a
H3 b a
Apply the ranking algorithm, including the Anti-Loop Provision, to test the learn-
ability of underlying forms. (Make sure that you present the data to the algorithm
in an order that will trigger the incorrect initial input form / bet /, as in the text of
section 7.5.3.1.) Do you experience any new difculties in learning input forms?
If so, can you propose a remedy?
340
8
Extensions to syntax
8.1 Introduction
In this chapter we will look into results of OT in the domain of syntax. It is
important to emphasize once again that OT is not a theory of phonology proper,
but rather a theory of grammar. Therefore the basic idea underlying OT, that of
hierarchically ranked constraints which are minimally violated, is, in principle,
equally well applicable to non-phonological phenomena. The present chapter should
be read as an attempt at such an extension of OT into syntax, an attempt mainly
based on a recent paper on English auxiliaries by Grimshaw (1997). We will
discuss the syntactic counterparts of constraint types which we have seen active
in previous chapters, and will elaborate the OT architecture of faithfulness and
well-formedness constraints. Besides dening constraints in the domain of syn-
tax, we will also address the nature of the input in syntax, and the denition of
the function of Gen. These are non-trivial matters, that merit discussion in their
own right. Finally we will develop the factorial typology of the core syntactic
constraints of Grimshaws paper.
341
Extensions to syntax
1
Or as Grimshaw (1997: 405) puts it, parameters serve to accommodate language variation in
a system of inviolable constraints.
342
8.2 OT and syntax
A stronger kind of parallelism between standard syntax and OT, and one that will
also play an important role in the discussion below, is that of economy. This
notion stems from recent work in Minimalist syntactic theory (Chomsky 1993,
1995). At the heart of this theory is the assumption that syntactic derivations and
representations must not exceed what is minimally necessary to meet general
well-formedness conditions. For example, no movement must take place without
some general structural requirement forcing it,2 and no projection must be present
without an overt licensing of this amount of structure.
This notion of economy of derivation and representation is highly similar to the
do only when necessary principle of OT.3 That is, outputs will be identical to
inputs (due to faithfulness constraints) except when divergence between them is
forced by a high-ranking well-formedness constraint. But even then, the diver-
gence between input and output will be kept at a bare minimum, that is, to the
extent that is required to meet well-formedness constraints. Such inertness fol-
lows from interactions of faithfulness and well-formedness constraints, as we
have seen on many occasions in earlier chapters of this book, in which we were
dealing with phonological phenomena. In fact, inertness eventually follows from
the general OT idea that constraints are violable, but that violation must be
minimal. Minimalism in syntax is based on theoretical assumptions that are
sufciently parallel to OT notions to warrant an attempt at assimilation.4 The
advantage of modelling economy in OT is, of course, that it is a soft system
by nature, rather than a hard system such as Minimalist syntax. Recently syn-
tacticians have indeed tried to explain economy using OT assumptions, and we
will see some results of this ongoing enterprise below. We will base our discus-
sion on syntactic phenomena of Wh-movement and inversion of subject and aux-
iliary verb in English, as have been analysed by Grimshaw (1997). We will also
sketch some of the typological consequences of an OT analysis of Wh-movement.
From here on, this chapter is organized as follows. Directly below, in section
8.2.1, we will sketch the theoretical assumptions on which OT-based syntax is
founded, developing these as variants on more general assumptions underlying
OT. Here issues will be taken up such as: What denes syntactic inputs?, What
is the function of Gen in syntax?, and What is the inventory of syntactic con-
straints?. This amount of theoretical background will enable us to outline in
2
Compare the ban on unmotivated movement in pre-minimalist syntax.
3
This similarity was pointed out by Prince and Smolensky (1993). See chapter 3 (section 3.3.3),
for a discussion of do only when necessary in phonology.
4
One difference between Chomskys notion of economy and its OT counterpart of minimal
violation is the type of evaluation. Chomsky assumes that economy is evaluated locally, rather
than globally (as in parallel OT). What are compared are not complete derivations, but only the
possibilities arising at specic points in a derivation. Hence a choice made at a particular point
in a derivation cannot be inuenced by any negative consequences that it may have later on.
343
Extensions to syntax
Accordingly, Grimshaw denes the input for the type of syntactic constructions
that she considers in her paper verbal extended projections as follows:
(1) Input
a lexical head plus its argument structure
an assignment of lexical heads to its arguments
344
8.2 OT and syntax
For example, consider the input of the sentence What did Mary say? At the level
of the input, this is dened by the lexical head say, which is a predicate taking
two arguments, plus an assignment of two lexical heads (Mary, what) to these
arguments.
Note that no semantically empty auxiliaries (do, did) are present in the input. The
presence of such elements in the output, and the constraint interactions by which
they appear, will be our main concern in this chapter.
Grimshaw makes two further assumptions about the input that are implicitly
guided by the principle of Containment (Prince and Smolensky 1993),5 which was
briey discussed in chapter 3 (section 3.3.1). This principle requires that no
element be literally removed from the input. This may be stated for the domain
of syntax as follows:
(3) Containment
competing candidates are evaluated as analyses of the same lexical
material
competing candidates to be generated for a single input must be
semantically equivalent
To state it differently, each analysis of the input competes with other analyses of
the same input, and all these analyses must have non-distinct semantic representa-
tions. In fact, we are already committing ourselves to a denition of Gen in syntax,
an issue which will be given special attention in the next subsection.
5
Although Grimshaw does not explicitly mention Containment, her approach is very much
similar to that of Prince and Smolensky (1993) in this respect.
345
Extensions to syntax
Note that this X theory does not require that some head be present in every
projection: such a requirement will in fact be made by a violable constraint,
which is referred to by Grimshaw as Obligatory Heads. (We will nd out why
this is a violable constraint later on when we come to discuss patterns of sub-
ordinate interrogatives.)
By this denition IP and CP are both extended projections of V (the lexical head
which has VP as its minimal projection). The schematic structure in (6) contains
a verb in its own projection VP, upon which a hierarchy of extended projections
are built (here consisting of a Inectional Phrase and a Complementizer Phrase).
(6) CP
XP C
C IP
XP I
I VP
XP V
V ...
346
8.2 OT and syntax
Let us now turn to the types of syntactic operations that Gen may perform on
the input, while keeping within the previously dened limits. These include the
following:
Note that, in keeping with Containment (3), no elements may be literally removed
from the input, and no semantically meaningful elements may be introduced.
Let us now consider a number of candidate analyses of the input of the sen-
tence What did Mary say? as it was dened in (2) above:
(8) Various candidate analyses for {say (x, y), x = Mary, y = what,
tense = past)
a. [IP Mary [VP said what]]
b. [CP what [IP Mary [VP said t]]]
c. [CP what saidi [IP Mary [VP ei t]]]
d. [CP what didi [IP Mary ei [VP say t]]]
These outputs are all extended projections, conforming to the X schema dened
in (45). Evidently these analyses do not all correspond to grammatical sentences
of English: in fact only one does: (8d). This involves Wh-movement, do-support,
and subjectauxiliary inversion. Yet all of the analyses (8ac) correspond to gram-
matical sentences in languages other than English. Analysis (8a), for example, has
no movement of any kind, as in Chinese. Analysis (8b) involves Wh-movement,
but it lacks both subjectverb inversion and do-support (or its analogue), the set
of properties found in Czech and Polish. Finally, analysis (8c) has both Wh-
movement and subjectlexical verb inversion, but it lacks do-support, as in Dutch.
The idea of the OT approach to syntax is that the diversity of syntactic struc-
tures across languages reects differences in the rankings of universal and viol-
able constraints. Each of the analyses in (8) violates one or more constraints, but
each can be considered as maximally harmonic (optimal ) with respect to some
347
Extensions to syntax
(10) CP
Spec-of-CP ...
Wh
Spec-of-CP will be the single available position for a Wh-element to move into
when the specier position of the next-lower projection, Spec-of-IP, is occupied
by the subject. Wh-movement into Spec-of-CP produces a chain of effects in
English syntax, which are known as subjectauxiliary inversion and do-support.
6
Later we will go into the question of what blocks movement of a Wh-phrase to other specier
positions, such as Spec-of-VP or Spec-of-IP. Furthermore, Grimshaw assumes that the option
of base-generating the Wh-phrase in Spec-of-CP is ruled out by the Theta Criterion, which may
be interpreted as a part of Gen, or as a constraint dominating Stay.
348
8.2 OT and syntax
That is, the creation of Spec-of-CP implies the presence of a CP, due to inviolate
X requirements. This CP, in its turn, is an extended projection subject to struc-
tural constraints that, indirectly, trigger the effects mentioned above.
Consider, for example, the following structural constraint, whose function should
be clear from its statement:
For verbal projections, Verb Phrase and its extended projections Inectional
Phrase and Complementizer Phrase, this implies that each must have a verb as
its head. Satisfaction of this constraint may require the movement or insertion of
a verb to become the head of an extended verbal projection. For example, Ob-Hd
may trigger subjectauxiliary inversion, the movement of an auxiliary to become
the head of CP (Den Besten 1983).7
The representation below shows the output of subjectauxiliary inversion in the
sentence What will Mary say?:
(12) CP
whati C
C IP
willj Mary I
I VP
ej V
V ti
say
The auxiliary verb willj undergoes head-movement to CP, from its original posi-
tion in IP, as has been indicated by its trace ei. Crucially, both the auxiliary verb
and its trace function as proper heads in their respective extended projections, IP
and CP.
7
Of course Ob-Hd can also be satised by a complementizer (that, whether, etc.) in the head
of CP.
349
Extensions to syntax
(13) a. CP b. CP
C C
C IP C IP
I will I
I VP I VP
will
Each of these analyses violates Ob-Hd, however, since each has one projection
that is not headed: CP in (13a) and IP in (13b).
350
8.2 OT and syntax
However, the input of the syntax as Grimshaw denes it (see again section
8.2.2) is, strictly speaking, not a (hierarchical) syntactic representation itself. It
only contains lexical heads and their argument structure, but not extended syntac-
tic projections, nor functional heads. This renders a correspondence approach to
economy, in principle at least, problematic.
Nevertheless, we may still conceive of syntactic faithfulness constraints in a
less correspondence-like fashion. First consider the general anti-movement con-
straint Stay:
The function of this constraint is to militate against any movement per se, or in
the case of gradient violation, to select the shortest movement, the one that has
the minimal number of intermediate steps. What we refer to as a movement is
actually construed as a chain of an element plus its traces as this occurs at surface
structure, the level at which Stay is evaluated. For example, the chain of a Wh-
element and its trace ti in (15a) incurs one violation of Stay, while the chain of
an Aux-element and its two traces ei in (15b) incurs two violations:
(15) a. Whi . . . ti
b. Auxi . . . ei . . . ei
Next consider the question of why Stay penalizes traces, rather than divergences
of word order between the input and output. (A correspondence approach to
economy of movement might set up constraints measuring the distance between
some element at surface structure and its input correspondent.) One problem,
already pointed out above, is that the input is not a syntactic representation, so
that the position of input elements cannot be established. Furthermore, under a
denition of the input as a lexical head plus its argument structure, it would
become impossible to penalize any movement of elements that are not present at
the level of the input.9 A third reason why such a correspondence approach
to economy may not be feasible is the following. What matters to economy of
movement is the number of landing sites of an element between its base position
and its position at surface structure, rather than its distance.10 Since every trace
9
A correspondence approach to economy of movement which would circumvent this problem
would involve setting up an intermediate syntactic level of deep structure that is distinct
from Grimshaws input: it is dened as a phrase-marker in which every element occupies its
base-generated position. This level would allow the representation of syntactic elements that
have no counterparts in the input (or lexical conceptual structure).
10
Ackema and Neeleman (forthcoming) propose an evaluation of Stay that is based on the
number of nodes intervening between positions in a movement chain. It remains an empirical
issue which type of evaluation is most adequate.
351
Extensions to syntax
in a chain incurs a violation of Stay, surface structure chains such as (15) are
indispensable in measuring violations.
The effect of this constraint is that a lexical head (for example, a lexical verb)
must stay in the projection that it heads (e.g. the VP). The conguration (17)
presents the typical case of violation of No-Lex-Mvt:
(17) . . . Vi . . . [VP . . . ei . . .]
Finally, consider the constraint that militates against the suppression of semantic
roles of lexical elements, Full-Int:
The key function of this constraint is to ban semantically empty auxiliary verbs,
as in do-support in English. In a sentence such as What did Mary say? the verb
do is semantically empty, functioning merely as an auxiliary for the lexical verb
say. It will be assumed that do in such sentences is lacking from the input, and
inserted from the lexicon into candidate analyses by Gen. Since, as was argued
above, Gen is semantically neutral, any insertion of a lexical element must occur
at the expense of its lexical conceptual structure. Observe that the lexical verb do
is a theta-marker (hence, an argument-taker) in a sentence such as Mary did the
vocal parts. This can be represented as below:
(19) do (x, y)
Under do-support, this lexical conceptual structure of the verb do is not parsed,
hence the sentence What did Mary say? incurs a violation of Full-Int. In
352
8.3 The structure of extended verbal projections in English
Each projection, the lexical projection VP and its extended projection IP, is
headed by an appropriate head. The VP is headed by the lexical verb (say), while
the IP is headed by the auxiliary verb (will). Since no heads are missing from this
353
Extensions to syntax
structure, there is no need for an additional CP plus inversion of the subject and
auxiliary verb, as in (22):
(23) {say (x, y), x = Mary, y = too much, Op- Ob- Stay
tense = future, auxiliary = will} Spec Hd
11
Under the hypothesis that the subject is base-generated in the VP (Zagona 1982), an additional
candidate merits consideration: [IP will [VP Mary say too much]]. This would even be optimal,
since, as compared to (23a), it avoids movement of the subject into Spec-of-IP. Grimshaw
rules this candidate out by the constraint Subject a clause must have a subject, in which
subject is dened as the highest A(rgument) specier in a clause. If Subject dominates
Stay, the subject is driven out of VP into IP, which would otherwise remain subject-less:
{say (x, y), x = Mary, y = too much, Op-Spec Ob-Hd Subject Stay
tense = future, auxiliary = will}
354
8.3 The structure of extended verbal projections in English
(23a), which is awless with respect to all three constraints. A more general predic-
tion is that no language has subjectauxiliary inversion in simple declaratives.
Next consider interrogatives, where Wh-movement is obligatory, in combina-
tion with inversion, as in (24a):
(25) Generalization
Subjectauxiliary inversion occurs if and only if Wh-movement
applies.
12
Inversion is triggered also by yes/no interrogatives, as in Will Mary say anything? See Grim-
shaw (1997) for analysis of this construction.
355
Extensions to syntax
a proper head for CP. At the same time, its trace ei in IP still functions as the
head of IP. Crucially, both lexical heads and traces can serve as heads of a
projection.
We thus arrive at the following scenario: Wh-movement serves to place the Wh-
element, an operator, in specier position of CP (as forced by Op-Spec); con-
sequently the auxiliary verb must also move into CP to provide a head for this
extended projection (due to Ob-Hd). Both movements naturally take their toll as
they occur at the expense of violations of Stay, the general anti-movement con-
straint. This motivates the following ranking:
Op-Spec must dominate Stay in order for Wh-movement to take place; with the
reverse ranking movement would be blocked by Stay. And Ob-Hd must also
dominate Stay in order for head movement of the auxiliary verb to take place.
This ranking is shown to be appropriate in the following tableau:
The optimal candidate (28d) is the only one which satises both Op-Spec and Ob-
Hd. Its representational perfection is purchased at the expense of two violations
of economy of movement (Stay), one for the trace t left by Wh-movement, and
another for the trace ei left by head movement. But (28d) is optimal precisely for
the reason that it cannot be improved over by other candidates. To improve (28d)
could only mean to avoid violations of Stay, hence to reduce movements. This,
however, cannot be achieved without violating higher-ranked constraints, Op-
Spec or Ob-Hd. For example, no improvement is made over (28d) by candidates
(28ab), which totally avoid movements, but consequently run into fatal viola-
tions of Op-Spec (28a), or even worse, of both Op-Spec and Ob-Hd (28b).
Next, candidate (28c) has the apparent virtue of avoiding head movement to CP.
356
8.3 The structure of extended verbal projections in English
Let us now see how the property of economy follows from the OT analysis. For
the sake of the argument, we distinguish derivational and representational eco-
nomy. Derivational economy (no unnecessary movement) is enforced directly
by Stay. Head movement of the auxiliary occurs whenever necessary (that is,
in interrogative sentences) to meet the top-ranking structural constraint Ob-Hd
even though movement violates Stay. Naturally any movement of the auxiliary
that yields no gains with respect to Ob-Hd will be blocked by Stay (that is,
in declarative sentences). Representational economy (no empty projections) is
achieved without a constraint explicitly militating against unnecessary projec-
tions. Instead, exclusion of superuous extended projections such as CP is
achieved indirectly, by cooperation of two constraints, Ob-Hd and Stay. To posit
a projection is to accept responsibility for its structural well-formedness. But
doing so may cause problems of derivational economy: an extended projection
left unheaded is ruled out by Ob-Hd. Alternatively, an extended projection sup-
plied with a proper head by head movement will be ruled out by Stay (except
when it yields an improvement with respect to Ob-Hd).
13
Again it may be interesting to consider the consequences of base-generating the subject in VP.
The candidate left out of consideration in tableau (28) is [CP what will [VP Mary say t ]], which
lacks an IP altogether. The subject Mary occupies Spec-of-VP, and the Wh-element is moved
to Spec-of-CP. This structure is more economical than optimal (28d = b below) since it has
no movement of auxiliary to IP. See the following tableau:
Grimshaw does not discuss this option, presumably because she assumes that auxiliaries
always head the IP, either in situ, or as a trace. Moreover, this additional candidate does not
affect the main result that inversion is obligatory in this case, due to the ranking Op-Spec,
Ob-Hd Stay. That is, the non-reversing candidate (c) is ruled out in the same way as it is
in (28c).
14
Peter Ackema (p.c.) points out that this analysis requires modications in order to account for
double Wh-constructions. In languages like English, only one Wh-element may move into CP,
while all others remain in situ (Who has given what to whom yesterday?). Here Grimshaws
analysis, which has undominated Ob-Hd and Op-Spec, predicts that every Wh-element will
be moved to a new CP, with the auxiliary verb moving upward through the head position of
each CP (*Who has what to whom given yesterday?).
357
Extensions to syntax
This analysis is unifying in the sense that both types of economy are, either
directly or indirectly, reduced to a single economy constraint, Stay. Economy
requires no separate constraints for derivation and representation. Stay directly
enforces derivational economy, while it indirectly enforces representational eco-
nomy, assisted by Ob-Hd.
In sum, given the pair Ob-Hd and Stay, both movement and extended pro-
jections are kept at a bare minimum. No movement will occur, and no extended
projection will be constructed, unless it is necessary. This warrants the conclusion
that economy is enforced by every grammar containing Ob-Hd and Stay hence
that economy is universal.
8.3.2 Do-support
15
A third logical possibility, that of inversion involving the lexical verb (cf. What said Mary?),
will be discussed in section 8.3.2.2.
358
8.3 The structure of extended verbal projections in English
Positive declarative sentences are structured in a way that renders addition of the
auxiliary do superuous. As expected under economy, superuity entails pro-
hibition. (In section 8.3.2.2 we will return to the structure of such sentences.)
This reminds us of generalizations found earlier in this book, all having the gen-
eral form do only when necessary. Then do referred to some change imposed
on the input, for example an epenthesis or deletion of a segment. Here, do
literally refers to do-support.
Grimshaw goes on subsume generalization (34) under the standard OT account
for generalizations of the do only when necessary type: a domination of well-
formedness over faithfulness.
not present in the input). Again the parallelism extends to the syntactic analysis:
do-support is triggered by the well-formedness constraint (Ob-Hd), at the expense
of violations of the syntactic faithfulness constraint Full-Int.
Once we have spotted the main idea behind the analysis, its execution becomes a
fairly simple matter. Evidently Full-Int must be dominated by Ob-Hd, since
violations of Full-Int (in the form of do-support) are tolerated to avoid viola-
tions of Ob-Hd.
(35) Ob-Hd Full-Int
Turning now to an actual example, this ranking is supported by the comparison
of two candidates for an interrogative, one with do-support (36a), another without
it (36b):
(36) a. What did Mary say?
b. *What Mary said?
Thus far we have not seen any evidence bearing on the ranking of Full-Int with
respect to Stay. Lacking this evidence, we arrive at a partial hierarchy in (37),
which inserts the ranking Ob-Hd Full-Int (35) into the earlier hierarchy
Op-Spec, Ob-Hd Stay (27):
(37) do-support only when necessary
Op-Spec, Ob-Hd Full-Int, Stay
In tableau (38), both candidates (36ab) are represented as (38a b). The former
candidate is optimal, as it has no violations of either highest-ranking constraint
Op-Spec and Ob-Hd, while all other candidates violate at least one of these. In
(38a) the auxiliary verb did heads CP, while its trace ei properly heads IP. Since
all its extended projections are headed, (38a) fully satises Ob-Hd. This happens
at the expense of violations of lower-ranked Full-Int (due to do-support) and
Stay (due to Wh-movement and head movement of did to CP).16
16
If subjects are base-generated in VP, a possibility mentioned in notes 1113, the optimal can-
didate would be [CP what did [VP Mary say t ]], leading to the same word order. Movement of
Mary out of VP is not necessary to provide a subject for the clause (cf. Subject in note 11),
hence this would violate Stay without reason. Avoidance of IP brings yet another advantage:
the auxiliary need not move to become head-of-CP, but can be simply inserted in that position:
361
Extensions to syntax
(38)
{say (x, y), x = Mary, y = what, Op- Ob-Hd Full- Stay
tense = past} Spec Int
Apparently the lexical verb is not allowed to move (due to No-Lex-Mvt, intro-
duced in section 8.2.4). We postpone discussion of this construction, including its
typological status, to section 8.4, and now continue our survey of the distribution
of the auxiliary do in English.
362
8.3 The structure of extended verbal projections in English
(41)
{say (x, y), x = Mary, y = what, Op- Ob- Full- Stay
tense = future, auxiliary = will} Spec Hd Int
This tableau adduces evidence that Full-Int dominates Stay.17 This resides in
the fact that candidate (41a) has more violations of Stay than (41b), but is
nevertheless optimal as it has no violations of Full-Int.
The next tableau evaluates candidates for simple declarative sentences that lack
an auxiliary (Mary said little). Economy (no do-support) follows from the same
17
Grimshaw (1997) does not discuss this ranking.
363
Extensions to syntax
(42) {say (x, y), x = Mary, y = little, Op- Ob- Full- Stay
tense = past} Spec Hd Int
Consider how this result follows. A matrix clause that lacks auxiliaries in the
input is, in a way, self-supporting. Specically it has no need for IP, an extended
projection canonically headed by auxiliaries, nor is there any need for CP, due to
the lack of Wh-elements. As we have seen often before, when extended projec-
tions are unnecessary, syntactic faithfulness rules them out. The economy mech-
anism is essentially the same as before: introduction of extended projections
triggers the well-formedness constraints for projections. Here Ob-Hd requires that
IP be headed, thereby excluding candidate (42c). Moreover, no head of IP can be
supplied by movement of an auxiliary as no auxiliary occurs in the input. (The
option of moving the lexical verb will be discussed in section 8.4.2.) The single
remaining option to provide a head for IP is do-support, as in (42b). But this
option crashes into Full-Int. In sum, all attempts at postulating an IP have
resulted only in losses, and no gains, as compared to the structurally simpler
candidate (42a). Again, representational complexity never wins unless it brings a
bonus in terms of lesser violations.
Finally, the observation that do-support never cooccurs with itself gives additional
evidence that Full-Int dominates Stay.
(43)
{say (x, y), x = Mary, y = what, Op- Ob- Full- Stay
tense = past} Spec Hd Int
364
8.3 The structure of extended verbal projections in English
In fact, this observation readily follows from the analysis as it stands now. The
difference between Wh-objects and Wh-subjects is that the latter can satisfy Op-
Spec by staying in Spec-of-VP, a legitimate specier position for a syntactic
operator. In contrast a Wh-object must move out of VP to nd a proper specier
position, in particular when Spec-of-VP is already occupied by the subject or its
trace.
The following tableau of sentence (44a) shows that without structural necessity
for Wh-subjects to move, their movement is blocked:
(45) {say (x, y), x = who, y = that, Op- Ob- Full- Stay
tense = past} Spec Hd Int
18
The fronted position of the subject Wh-element in Who will say that? is due to the constraint
Subject, which was previously mentioned in notes 11 and 16. Structure (b) with the auxiliary
in I, and the Wh-element in Spec-of-VP, would violate Subject since this constraint requires
that the highest A(rgument) specier in a clause have a subject, in this case Spec-of-IP. Hence
Wh-movement becomes obligatory:
{say (x, y), x = who, y = that, Op-Spec Ob-Hd Subject Full-Int Stay
tense = future, auxiliary = will}
365
Extensions to syntax
366
8.4 Typological consequences
Working our way through this typology from top to bottom, we rst arrive at the
rankings in (46a b). Here Stay dominates both well-formedness constraints Op-
Spec and Ob-Hd. When violations of Stay are avoided at the expense of viola-
tions of well-formedness, a grammar arises lacking Wh-movement as well as
inversion. Languages of this type are attested, for example Chinese (Ackema and
Neeleman forthcoming).
Next, ranking (46c), where Stay still dominates Op-Spec, produces a similar
lack of Wh-movement; nor is there movement of auxiliaries into head positions
of extended projections due to Wh-movement. Therefore ranking (46c) leads to
the same inert picture as both rankings in (46ab).
We now move on to ranking (46d), which merits some discussion. Here Op-
Spec dominates Stay, hence Wh-movement is forced. But Stay, in its turn, dom-
inates Ob-Hd, so that inversion cannot be used to ll the head position of
extended functional projections which are the result of Wh-movement. In sum,
this represents a language that has Wh-movement, but not inversion. Such a
language is French (Ackema and Neeleman forthcoming).
Finally, the rankings (46ef) are apparently equivalent since both have Op-
Spec and Ob-Hd on top of Stay. As in English, both Wh-movement and inversion
occur in violation of Stay, to satisfy both top-ranking constraints. However, as
Grimshaw points out, there is a potential empirical difference between the rank-
ings (46e) and (46f) which arises when a fourth constraint comes into play.
We must now consider the cause of its ungrammaticality. This structure seems to
have a lot in its favour. Wh-movement satises Op-Spec, and the projection thus
created (a CP) satises Ob-Hd due to the lexical verb, which has moved out of
the VP. On top of all this, structure (47b) avoids do-support. Then why should it
be ruled out? The answer resides in the undominated constraint No-Lex-Mvt that
was introduced in (16) of section 8.2.4, but has been left out of consideration thus
far because it was not crucial to any other examples which were previously dis-
cussed. No-Lex-Mvt blocks head-movement of a lexical verb out of VP. We may
thus extend tableau (38) with the new candidate (47b = 48e) in the following way:
367
Extensions to syntax
(48)
{say (x, y), x = Mary, y = what, No-Lex- Op- Ob- Full- Stay
tense = past} Mvt Spec Hd Int
When movement of the lexical verb to the head position of CP is blocked, while
this head position must be lled by some verb, then there is nothing better than
to insert a form of do. English thus prefers violations of Full-Int to violations
of No-Lex-Mvt.
Now we return to the typological aspects of this analysis. Surely one would expect
that languages occur in which No-Lex-Mvt takes less priority than it does in
English, and even ranks below Full-Int, so that subjectverb inversion involves
the lexical verb. Such a language is Dutch:19
(50)
{say (x, y), x = Marie, y = wat, Op- Ob- Full- Stay No-Lex-
tense = past} Spec Hd Int Mvt
19
The verb moves from a VP-nal position, since Dutch has a basic Subject ObjectVerb order.
368
8.5 Conclusions
Grimshaw points out that languages of this type (which allow movement of lex-
ical verbs) are incompatible with a semantically empty auxiliary: there is always
a better option than (the analogue of) do-support, which is moving the lexical
verb. This conclusion follows naturally from the analysis developed, in which
minimal violation plays a crucial role.
Importantly, the typology does not predict the following situation: do-support in
a sentence containing a Wh-element, but left unaccompanied by Wh-movement.
No possible ranking of constraints will produce this (logically possible) situation,
as will be clear from the following argument. First, for Wh-movement to be
prohibited, it must be the case that Stay dominates Op-Spec. Second, for do-
support to occur, it must be the case that Ob-Hd dominates Full-Int. That is,
do-support is triggered by the requirement that (extended) projections be properly
headed. But an extended projection never occurs without structural necessity, in
particular Wh-movement. But when Wh-movement is absolutely prohibited, this
situation simply cannot arise.
8.5 Conclusions
In this chapter we have demonstrated that OT is a theory of grammar, rather than
a theory of phonology proper, since it is applicable to linguistic phenomena
outside phonology. The empirical domain was syntactic in nature: we considered
interactions between the patterns of Wh-movement, subjectauxiliary inversion,
and do-support in English. It was demonstrated that inversion and do-support
have economical distributions: they occur if and only if the construction has
properties which make inversion and/or do-support necessary. Necessity, stated in
terms of independently motivated terms, was then translated into well-formedness
constraints (such as Op-Spec and Ob-Hd); while syntactic effects (movement,
inversion, do-support, etc.) were translated into faithfulness constraints (such as
Stay, Full-Int, and No-Lex-Mvt). This set of syntactic constraints, in combina-
tion with general principles of constraint interaction (such as strict domination and
minimal violation), sufce to explain the observed syntactic patterns, as well as
the economy of movements and representations.
The observed economy follows as the natural result of constraint interaction.
Movement necessarily involves domination of a syntactic well-formedness con-
straint over a syntactic faithfulness constraint (Stay). Since any movement incurs
a violation of Stay, movement is kept to the bare minimum necessary to obey
higher-ranking well-formedness constraints. Any movement in excess of this min-
imum will serve no purpose in satisfying the higher-ranking constraints, and
therefore incurs an unnecessary violation of Stay. This explanation requires no
369
Extensions to syntax
stipulation that movement be minimal, but simply follows from general OT prin-
ciples: that constraints are violable, but violation must be minimal.
Similarly, the explanation for economy of representation is based on the same
principle of minimal violation. Any (extended) projection postulated in the ana-
lysis of an input is subject to the general well-formedness constraints pertaining
to syntactic structure. To satisfy well-formedness constraints, some movement or
other effect (for example, do-support) may be required. But this, in its turn, incurs
violations of (faithfulness) constraints militating against these effects. The explana-
tion for economy of representation is thus reducible to economy of movement.
In the nal section we have shown that this OT theory of the interactions
of Wh-movement, subjectverb inversion, and do-support produces a factorial
typology which is adequate in terms of what is currently known about syntactic
typology.20
Minimalist syntax
Chomsky, Noam (1993) A minimalist program for linguistic theory. In K. Hale
and S. J. Keyser (eds.), The view from Building 20. Cambridge, Mass.: MIT
Press. 4158.
(1995) The minimalist program. Cambridge, Mass.: MIT Press.
Radford, Andrew (1997) Syntax: a minimalist introduction. Cambridge University
Press.
OT syntax
Ackema and Neeleman (forthcoming) Optimal questions. To appear in Natural
Language and Linguistic Theory 16:3. [A prenal version of the paper can
be found in ROA-69, http://ruccs.rutgers.edu/roa.html]
Barbosa, Pilar, Danny Fox, Paul Hagstrom, Martha McGinnis, and David Pesetsky
(eds.) (1998). Is the best good enough? Optimality and competition in syntax.
Cambridge, Mass.: MIT Press.
Bresnan, Joan (forthcoming) Optimal syntax. To appear in J. Dekkers, F. van der
Leeuw, and J. van de Weijer (eds.), Optimality Theory: phonology, syntax,
and acquisition. Oxford University Press.
Grimshaw, Jane (1997) Projection, heads, and optimality. Linguistic Inquiry 28.
373 422.
20
Other works pursuing issues of syntactic typology in OT are Ackema and Neeleman (forth-
coming) and Legendre, Raymond, and Smolensky (1993).
370
8.5 8.5
Further
Conclusions
reading
Keer, Edward and Eric Bakovic (1997) Have Faith in syntax. Proceedings
of the West Coast Conference on Formal Linguistics 16. [ROA-200,
http://ruccs.rutgers.edu/roa.html]
Legendre, Graldine, William Raymond, and Paul Smolensky (1993) An Optimality-
Theoretic typology of case and grammatical voice systems. Proceedings of
the Berkeley Linguistics Society 19. 46478.
Mller, Gereon (1997) Partial Wh-movement and Optimality Theory. The Lin-
guistic Review 14. 249 306.
Pesetsky, David (forthcoming) Some Optimality principles of sentence pronun-
ciation. To appear in Barbosa et al.
Syntaxphonology interaction
Golston, Chris (1995) Syntax outranks phonology: evidence from ancient Greek.
Phonology 12. 343 68.
371
9
Residual issues
9.1 Introduction
The previous eight chapters of this book have offered an overview of Optimality
Theory, with an emphasis on areas in which the theory has proved successful.
This chapter will add an overview of issues that have not yet been successfully
resolved, and developments and modications in the theory that are currently
taking place. The issue that is perhaps most urgently in need of a solution is
opacity, to be discussed in section 9.2. Remaining sections each deal with a major
theme in ongoing research. First, absolute ungrammaticality will be addressed in
section 9.3. Section 9.4 will evaluate strategies to deal with optionality and free
variation. Next, section 9.5 will discuss positional faithfulness in relation to func-
tional approaches to phonology. Finally, section 9.6 will re-evaluate the role of
underlying forms in OT, linking this issue with phonologically driven allomorphy.
Conclusions and a perspective on future developments in OT will be presented in
section 9.7.
9.2 Opacity
9.2.1 Introduction
Opacity refers to the phenomenon that output forms are shaped by generalizations
that are not surface-true. Opaque generalizations lurk at a level deeper than the
output, which becomes apparent by peeling off effects overlaid by other surface-
true generalizations. Opacity is predicted by any theory allowing non-surface
levels of description (the input, or any level mediating between input and output).
However, opacity presents a potential problem for surface-oriented OT, a theory
disallowing reference to preoutput levels by well-formedness constraints. (Of
course, the fact that a generalization is not surface-true is, by itself, not immedi-
ately problematic for OT. Output forms are always in violation of some con-
straints.) Before we look into strategies for dealing with opacity in OT, we will
rst discuss its varieties. That is, opaque generalizations are either non-surface-
apparent or non-surface-true, following McCarthys (1998) terminology.
372
9.2 Opacity
c. Interaction
/ hCpu-ki/ hCpki she dances
/nAi-ki/ nAki she leads (someone)
Vowel harmony copies the colour (backness and rounding) of the rightmost stem
vowel onto the vowel of the 3 sg. f. sufx /-ki/.1 Syncope deletes unstressed
vowels standing immediately before //. The output form [hCpki] she dances
is opaque with respect to vowel harmony, since the stem vowel /u / that triggers
the back and rounded quality of the sufx vowel cannot be recovered from the
surface. (It is indirectly recoverable, of course, precisely because of the sufx
vowels quality.)
A generalization is non-surface-true if it has cases of non-application at the
surface that are controlled by a non-surface level. This is the logically opposite
situation of the previous case. A set of forms fail to undergo a process even
though their surface forms match its structural description. An example comes
from Isthmus Nahuat (Law 1958, Kenstowicz and Kisseberth 1979). A process of
apocope (optionally) deletes a word-nal unstressed vowel. A second process
devoices approximants /l, w, j/ at the end of a word:2
1
Glottal stop // is transparent to harmony.
2
Syllable-nal approximants may also be devoiced, under conditions that are irrelevant here.
374
9.2 Opacity
Opacity has received much attention in rule-based serial phonology since it offers
a major argument for this theory. Therefore let us rst take a look at opacity from
a serial viewpoint. For a rule to apply, all that matters is whether its structural
context is satised at the point of the derivation at which the rule applies.3 For
this reason serial theory easily captures generalizations that are not surface-true
or not surface-apparent, thus predicting opacity on principled grounds. The two
types of rule interactions that produce opacity are known as counterbleeding and
counterfeeding, respectively (Kiparsky 1973).
Counterbleeding arises when a rules structural context is potentially destroyed
or removed by the application of a prior rule, but the ordering is such that both
rules apply. The second rule, which might have destroyed the context of applica-
tion for the rst rule, applies too late to actually do so. In the Tunica example,
harmony rst copies rounding and backness of the rightmost stem vowel onto the
sufx vowel. This triggering vowel is then deleted by syncope:
3
At the same time, this output-blindness is a serious disadvantage of serial theory, as we have
seen in chapter 2, since it frustrates an account of conspiracies.
375
Residual issues
Apocope misses its chance to establish the context for devoicing, which does not
apply.4
Interactions such as those in (45) seem to motivate strongly abstract inter-
mediate levels of representation between input and output. OT recognizes no such
intermediate levels, in line with standard assumptions stated earlier in this book.
In standard OT, the mapping from input (Lexical Representation) to output
(Phonetic Representation) is direct. Moreover, well-formedness constraints state
requirements on output forms only, ignoring the input. This assumption is another
cornerstone of OT, essential to explanation of segment inventories, conspiracies,
and the Duplication Problem (see chapters 12).
Let us rst consider the problem in more detail, focussing on the Turkish case.
The two processes involved, both of which can be independently motivated for
Turkish, are stated as constraint interactions below:
*VkV and *Complex never conict, and cannot be ranked with respect to one
another. The rankings (6a) and (6b) are integrated in tableau (7), considering
all logically possible combinations of k-deletion and epenthesis, for the input
/jk-m/:
a. .jkm *!
b. .j.km *! *
c. .j.m * *!
d. L .jm *
Candidate [.j.m] (7c) is the actual output, but it is not the most harmonic
candidate. The transparent form [.jm] (7d) has one fewer violation of Dep-IO,
obeying the OT adage do-only-when-necessary: why epenthesize if there is no
4
Kiparsky (1973) proposes the hypothesis that grammars avoid orderings of rules that produce
opacity. That is, the ordering of rules will tend toward a relation that maximizes the transpar-
ency of the rules involved. The cost of opaque interactions clearly resides in the abstractness
they involve, which increases learnability difculties. On the other hand, opacity may also be
functionally motivated as contributing to learnability since it makes lexical representations
recoverable from output representations (Kisseberth 1973, Kaye 1974).
376
9.2 Opacity
need for it? Note that the case for [.jm] is robust enough to be independent of
constraint ranking. A comparison of the violation patterns of both candidates
shows that violation marks incurred by (7d) form a proper subset of those
incurred by (7c). This nding destroys all hope that the problem is solvable
without the help of additional constraints (or even new theoretical machinery).
But no matter how we integrate the subrankings into a total ranking, the opaque
candidate (9b) will never become optimal. Instead the transparent candidate (9c)
is predicted:
a. ikkCli *!
b. ikkCl * *!
c. L ikkC6 * *
Opaque (9b) and transparent (9c) only differ in their violation marks for *Voiced-
Coda and Ident-IO(voice). However, the mutual ranking of these constraints is
forced, since it is independently motivated by approximant devoicing in words
such as [tjo6] shelled corn (3b). The incorrect prediction crucially depends on
constraint ranking (rather than being independent of it, as in overapplication).
This is a clear ranking paradox.
To illustrate the basic idea, let us consider the Tunica example. Opacity of vowel
harmony is accounted for if harmony is triggered by input vowels, but takes effect
in the output. This can be achieved by a well-formedness constraint that refers to
the input and output simultaneously, for example:6
(10) Harmony-IO
If input V1 . . . V2 then V1 and V2 agree in backness and rounding.
output V2
5
In its original form, Containment Theory was never used as a framework for analysing opacity.
Yet the idea that input features are abstractly represented in the output has been elaborated by
Cole and Kisseberth (1995) in Optimal Domains Theory. The innovative aspect of this theory
is its assumption that input features occur in the output in special constituents, or F(eature)-
domains, which largely coincide with (autosegmental) harmony domains. Relations between
F-domains and input features are enforced by violable faithfulness constraints.
6
A complete analysis should account for the joint reference to backness and rounding (colour),
and also explain the directionality of harmony: rightward, or more likely, stem to afx.
378
9.2 Opacity
(12) Lowering-IO
Any output correspondent of an input long vowel must be [high].
Lowering has the format of a correspondence constraint, but with one crucial
difference: correspondents in the input and output are not required to agree with
respect to the same feature (as in Ident-IO[F]). Like (12), Lowering-IO is not
an IO-faithfulness constraint, since feature-cooccurrence is required for different
features (here, length and height), and for unrelated values. In Archangeli and
Suzukis analysis of Yokuts, Lowering triggers a featural change from the input
value of [high]. Therefore, it functions as a well-formedness constraint, although
it has the IO-format of standard correspondence constraints. A theory allowing
for constraints such as (10) and (12) essentially gives up the distinction between
well-formedness constraints and faithfulness constraints.
7
Nevertheless, Harmony-IO interacts with IO-faithfulness constraints in a standard way it
dominates Ident-IO(round) and Ident-IO( back).
379
Residual issues
structure. (So far we have not seen such cases.) For example, an opaque gen-
eralization referring to prosody cannot be analysed by reference to the input,
assuming that prosody is not present in input forms.
A well-studied case is compensatory lengthening (CL), a situation where a
vowel is lengthened to compensate for the quantity of a deleted consonant
(Hayes 1989). An example comes from Oromo (Lloret 1988, Sprouse 1997):
A serial derivation shows the origin of the long stem vowel in [feena] we wish.
A mora is assigned to the coda consonant closing the rst syllable (by Weight-
by-Position, chapter 4). This consonant is then deleted before a consonant-initial
sufx, but its mora is preserved in the form of an extra element of length on the
preceding vowel. Opacity is explained by a counterbleeding rule order (Weight-
by-Position Pre-consonantal deletion):
(14)
/f e-na/ f e na f e na f e na
As Sprouse (1997) points out, the mora that triggers the lengthening cannot be
part of the input. If faithfulness to input moras were to trigger CL, and the
consonant // be specied as moraic in the input, then CL should occur in any
context in which // cannot hold on to its mora. This is incorrect; see *[feea]
(13b), where // surfaces as an onset. Instead CL is restricted to the context of
Weight-by-Position. Moreover, if input consonants were contrastively specied as
moraic (so that weight of CVC syllables would lexically vary), then certain stems
would undergo CL, while other stems would simply undergo deletion. Such con-
trasts are apparently not found in Oromo. Finally, as McCarthy (1998) points out,
input specication of moras runs into a general problem: it is at odds with Rich-
ness of the Base, a cornerstone of OT. In sum, the length-triggering mora cannot
be part of the input, ruling out a two-level analysis of CL. The best a two-level
analysis can achieve is to encode the context of Weight-by-Position into a two-
level constraint:
(15) -Projection
Project an output for every input C followed by a C.
380
9.2 Opacity
...
Output
Stratum 2: I2 /.j.km/
*Complex, *VkV Dep-IO, Max-IO
O2 [.j.m]
The output of S1, [.j.km], is due to the ranking *Complex, Max-IO Dep-
IO, *VkV:
a. .jkm *!
b. + .j.km * *
c. .j.m *! *
d. .jm *!
This S1 output is then fed as an input into S2. Ranking at S2 is such that intervo-
calic /k/ is deleted (*VkV Max-IO), giving an S2 output [.j.m], which is
the surface form.
a. .jkm *! *
b. .j.km *!
c. + .j.m *
d. .jm **!
In sum, both strata have minimally different rankings, involving only reranking
of a well-formedness constraint and a faithfulness constraint.8
Let us now briey discuss a case of underapplication, which is captured
in serial theory by counterfeeding. Approximant devoicing in Isthmus Nahuat is
opaque, as shown earlier in this chapter. Here intermediate outputs are [ ikkili]
and [tajo6], respectively:
383
Residual issues
a. + ikkili *
b. ikkil *! *
c. ikki6 *! *
a. tajol *!
b. + tajo6 *
The reverse rankings hold at Stratum 2, where apocope applies (Final-C Max-
IO), but devoicing is blocked (Ident-IO(voice) *Voiced-Coda):
a. ikkili *!
b. + ikkil * *
c. ikki6 *! *
a. tajol *! *
b. + tajo6
384
9.2 Opacity
Consequently each form undergoes only one process, either devoicing or apo-
cope, but not both. ( Note that values for [voice] as these occur in the output of
Stratum 1 are preserved at Stratum 2, regardless of their values in the original
lexical input.)
In contrast to two-level well-formedness theory, an intermediate-levels the-
ory of opacity holds the promise of accounting for types of opacity that are not
controlled by the input. Compensatory Lengthening in Oromo (13), for example,
may be accounted for by an intermediate level at which Weight-by-Position has
applied, but consonant deletion is still blocked. CL becomes an identity effect
preserving quantity occurring at intermediate levels. In sum, multi-stratal evalu-
ation has the advantage of a broad empirical coverage of opacity effects, being
equivalent to serial theory in this respect.
But does it preserve OTs advantages over serial theories, which are largely
based on direct mapping and evaluation of output forms? If OT is not to be
reduced to a notational variant of serial theory, one major question should be
answered: Can we have the best of both worlds? That is, can intermediate levels
be restricted in a way that captures opacity, but also preserves OTs advantages?
Can the number of strata be restricted to a universal maximum? At present, it is
not clear what the ultimate answers to these questions will be, due to a lack of
experience with multi-stratal models. We foresee two problems, however.
Firstly, the problem of nding independent motivation for strata. Motivation
must be independent in the sense that it goes beyond the desire to capture opaque
interactions. If such (presumably morphological) evidence cannot be produced,
then multi-stratal OT is reduced to a variant of serial theory, differing in having
two mechanisms (constraint interaction and derivation) instead of one (derivation).
Considerations of generality of explanation would then favour the serial model.
Secondly, multi-stratal evaluation implies that multiple rankings are active
within a grammar. This predicts that stratal rankings (hypothetically, at least) can
differ as widely as those of different languages. But cases under discussion show
that such radically different rankings for strata do not occur. On the contrary,
rankings differ only in minimal ways, typically by the reranking of a pair of
constraints (a well-formedness constraint and a faithfulness constraint), or per-
haps two pairs, but not by massive rerankings.
Thirdly, multi-stratal models are not learnable by Tesar and Smolenskys algo-
rithm, discussed in chapter 8, and it is doubtful whether they are learnable at
all, due to the large increase in complexity. However, future research will have to
answer this question.
385
Residual issues
9.2.4 OO-correspondence
A third approach to opacity is based on OO-correspondence (McCarthy 1995a;
Benua 1995, chapter 6). Opacity involves underapplication and overapplication
effects, as noted in section 9.2.1. Hence, it seems logical to extend the apparatus
of OO-identity constraints to opacity. If successful, this approach would have the
advantage of preserving two core principles of standard OT: direct mapping and
strictly output-based well-formedness constraints.
An identity-based approach to opacity requires the following pair of conditions.
First, for each opaque output, there must be an output form compositionally
related to it. Second, this base must be transparent with respect to the generali-
zation. Both conditions hold for the analysis of i-Syncope in Palestinian Arabic
(chapter 6, section 6.4).
i-Syncope normally deletes unstressed /i/ in open syllables (25b). It under-
applies in (25c), where unstressed /i/ corresponds with a stressed vowel in the base.
Two-level well-formedness fails here since the abstract stress blocking application
of i-Syncope (rendering it opaque in 25c) is not present in the input.
However, an OO-correspondence analysis works, because the blocking stress
is recoverable from the base. A BA-identity constraint HeadMax-BA refers to it:
(26) HeadMax-BA
Every segment in the bases prosodic head has a correspondent in the
afxed form.
9.2.5 Sympathy
The most recent attack on opacity is due to McCarthy (1998), and it is called
Sympathy. Its core feature is an extension of the correspondence relation to
pairs of candidate forms. Faithfulness constraints require the output form to re-
semble another candidate of Gen, the sympathetic form, which is analogous to the
abstract intermediate representation in serial theory. Sympathy preserves the key
features of standard OT: direct mapping of inputs to outputs and the output-based
format of well-formedness constraints. However, it implies a vast increase in the
correspondence relations involved in selecting the optimal output.
a. .jkm *!
b. .j.km *! *
c. .j.m * *!
d. L .jm *
Let us rst consider an intuitive (and informal) way of picking the sympathetic
candidate to which [.j.m] is faithful. Focussing on the candidate pair [.j.m]
and [.jm], we nd that whatever advantage of faithfulness the former may have,
this must reside in its epenthetic []. We deduce that the yet-to-be-identied sym-
pathetic candidate shares this vowel with [.j.m]. Such a candidate form is
[.j.km] (27b). This happens to be the form in tableau (27) that is otherwise
maximally faithful to the input this observation will be taken up directly below.
This sympathetic form will be indicated by the ower {.
The {-candidate [.j.km] matches the intermediate form in the serial ana-
lysis (4), arising after vowel epenthesis (the input to intervocalic k-deletion). In
the OT analysis, [.j.km] is more faithful to the input /jk-m/ than opaque
[.j.m], taking an intermediate position between both. Thus the serial analysis
and OT analysis share an insight: both set up an abstract intermediate form
connecting the opaque output to the input.9
(28)
Input: /jk-m/ *Complex *VkV Max-{O Max-IO Dep-IO
{-Candidate: .j.km
a. .jkm *! *
b. { .j.km *! *
c. + .j.m * * *
d. .jm **! *
The opaque candidate (28c), which would normally lose to the transparent
candidate (28d) because of its extra violation of Dep-IO, now becomes optimal
due to its maximal faithfulness to the {-candidate. Note that one violation of
Max-{O is incurred by each segment of the {-candidate that lacks a correspond-
ent in the output. Therefore, opaque (28c) is unfaithful to the {-candidate
by one segment (deleted /k/), whereas transparent (28d) is unfaithful by two
9
McCarthy points out that such parallelism is not always exact, particularly in cases involving
multiply opaque generalizations.
388
9.2 Opacity
segments (deleted /k / and //), with the additional violation being fatal. Finally,
the {-candidate itself fatally violates *VkV.10
Next we turn to a case of overapplying opacity that is not controlled by the input
(which is problematic to reference-to-the-input models). Again, the {-candidate
matches the intermediate representation in a serial analysis, which arises after
Weight-by-Position and is the input to consonant deletion. This is [fe.na]
(29b). The opaque output (29c) is faithful to it by satisfying Max--{O, a con-
straint demanding that each mora of the {-candidate have a correspondent in the
output.
(29)
Input: /fe-na/ *Weight-by- Coda- Max-- Max-IO Dep-
{-Candidate: fe.na Position Cond {O -IO
a. fe.na *! * *
b. { fe.na *! *
c. + fee.na * *
d. fe.na *! *
a. { ikkili *!
b. + ikkil * *
c. ikki6 *! * *
10
Another plausible output candidate, [j.km], is equally faithful to the sympathetic candidate.
The difference is that an input vowel is deleted in [j.km] but an input consonant in [.j.m]
(the actual output). We assume that this contrast correlates with a distinction between Max-
C and (higher-ranking) Max-V. (See the analysis of Southeastern Tepehuan in chapter 4.) This
assumption is shared by McCarthy (1998), who does not discuss the Turkish case, though.
389
Residual issues
Candidate (30a), perfectly faithful to the input and to itself (in its quality of {-
candidate), is nevertheless rejected for its fatal violation of Final-C. Opaque
(30b) is optimal due to Ident-{O(voice) *Voiced-Coda, ruling out trans-
parent (30c).
Observe that this tableau contains two faithfulness constraints of the format
Ident(voice), a low-ranking one evaluating IO pairs (Ident-IO(voice)), and a
top-ranking one evaluating {-O pairs (Ident-{O(voice)). Since the {-candidate
happens to be identical to the input, both faithfulness constraints produce the
same evaluation marks, at different positions in the hierarchy. We will return to
this observation shortly below, in connection with the issue of how the choice of
the {-candidate is made.
The {-candidate is not a priori given, and it should be determinable on the basis
of positive evidence. How can this aim be achieved? In all cases of opacity
discussed thus far, the {-candidate satises an IO-faithfulness constraint that is
violated in the opaque form. In all three cases, this is Max-IO:
We noted in section 9.2.1 that opaque generalizations are overlaid by other gen-
eralizations of the language. Now we see how the {-candidate is related to the
opaque form by peeling off a structural change (here, undoing a segment
deletion). The relation between the opaque form and the {-candidate is such that
the latter obeys an IO-faithfulness constraint that is violated by the former. This
special IO-faithfulness constraint is called the selector.
McCarthy claims that the choice of the {-candidate is uniquely determined by
the selector, given the (independently motivated) constraint ranking of the lan-
guage. That is, the {-candidate is the most harmonic candidate of all candidates
that satisfy the selector. For this purpose, we may think of candidate space as
divided into two mutually exclusive subsets, one of candidates that satisfy the
selector, and another of candidates violating it. Within the former subset, the {-
candidate is the optimal candidate, given the constraint hierarchy of the language.
syllabic root ending in /k/ loses /k/ in intervocalic contexts. Therefore *VkV must
be crucially dominated by some constraint enforcing root-minimality, whose
exact nature is irrelevant to our discussion.
The dominated position of *VkV is conrmed by the selection of the {-
candidate [.j.km]. Tableau (32) shows four candidates which obey the selector
constraint Max-IO (omitting candidates that violate this constraint, which do not
qualify by denition). The independently motivated constraint ranking indeed
selects (32c) as the {-candidate:
a. .jkm *! 3
b. .jk.m *! 3 *
c. { .j.km * 3 *
d. .j.k.m *! * 3 **
This is not the tableau selecting the actual output form but only the part that is
relevant to the selection of the {-candidate. In a fully edged tableau, the choice
of the {-candidate is actually made in parallel with the choice of the optimal
output form. That is, (32) is a subtableau of (28). Note that tableau (32), unlike
(28), does not include Max-{O, the Sympathy constraint. McCarthy argues that
the Sympathy constraint must indeed always be invisible to the selection of the
{-candidate, to avoid circularity in selection.
The choice of the selector is critical, since this determines the {-candidate,
hence indirectly the choice of the opaque output. But how is the selector itself
being chosen? The selector is always an IO-faithfulness constraint, violable in
actual output forms of the language (crucially so, in the opaque output itself).
Since most faithfulness constraints of a language are undominated, this narrows
down its choice. But the bottom line is that any positive evidence regarding the
choice of the selector can only reside in the opaque form itself. The learner must
infer the choice of the selector from the opaque form. This may seem an unsatis-
factory conclusion which has a whiff of circularity. However, an analogous conclu-
sion holds for a serial theory of opacity: any evidence pertaining to rule ordering
(bleeding or counterbleeding, feeding or counterfeeding) can only come from the
opaque form itself.
Let us now briey discuss this proposal, starting with its virtues. First, Sympathy
preserves two cornerstones of standard OT direct mapping and the output-based
391
Residual issues
The complex constraint [C1 & C2] (the conjunction of constraints C1 and C2) is
violated if and only if both of its components are violated. Moreover, for a viola-
tion of [C1 & C2] to occur, both separate violations must arise within a single
domain (a segment, morpheme, etc.). Evidently some domain is needed for
conjunction: the severity of output ill-formedness is never increased by combina-
tions of violations in random positions in the output. Finally, a conjoined con-
straint does not replace its components, but it is separately ranked. It is generally
assumed that a conjoined constraint is universally ranked above the component
constraints.
We will rst look at evidence for conjunction from opacity (chain shifts), and then
at its wider applications.
That is, A reoccupies the position left vacant by B, which itself occupies C,
etc.
A striking example of a chain shift is vowel raising in Western Basque (De Rijk
1970, Kenstowicz and Kisseberth 1979, Kirchner 1996). Mid vowels and high
vowels that precede another vowel are raised by one degree (mid to high and high
to raised):
393
Residual issues
Kirchner assumes the following specications for vowels for [low], [high], and
[raised]:
(In the Etxarri dialect, on which Kirchner focusses, low vowels are not raised in
hiatus. The raising of clitic vowels /bat/ [bet] is conditioned by a high vowel
in the stem, and we will ignore it.) First we will see that chain shifts are not
problematic to serial theory, while they do pose problems to standard OT.
In serial theory the analysis is straightforward: it is a case of counterfeed-
ing on the focus. Two counterfeeding rules raise high vowels and mid vowels,
respectively:11
(39) Hiatus-Raising
In V1 V2, maximize height of V1.
Kirchner argues that this constraint is evaluated gradiently, and that different
values of V1 incur the following violations marks: low ***, mid **, high *,
and raised none. The IO-faithfulness constraints involved are:
11
A third rule raises the sufx vowel from /-a / to [-e] if it is preceded by a high vowel.
394
9.2 Opacity
(40) a. Ident-IO(high)
If an input segment is [high], then its output correspondent is
[high].
b. Ident-IO(raised)
If an input segment is [raised], then its output correspondent is
[raised].
For raising to take place at all, Hiatus-Raising must be ranked above both
faithfulness constraints. That is, e i shows that Ident-IO(high) is dominated,
while i ij shows that Ident-IO(raised) is dominated. This is summarized in the
following tableau (which, however, gives only a subset of the output candidates
to be nally considered for /e/):
a.i ee *!*
a.ii + e i * *
b.i ii *!
b.ii + i ij *
Note, however, what happens if we add a third output candidate, [ij], to the tableau
of /e/. This ranking incorrectly predicts that /e/ is raised to [ij], going two steps
rather than one:
c.i ee *!*
c.ii ei *! *
c.iii L e ij * *
395
Residual issues
The reasoning behind Kirchners Local Conjunction analysis is this: the change
e ij involves violation of two faithfulness constraints, while each of the indi-
vidual steps i ij and e i involves only one violation. Moreover, the faithful-
ness violations incurred by i ij reoccur separately in the individual steps i
ij and e i. Then what is needed is the conjunction of both faithfulness con-
straints into a composite constraint. This must be ranked above Hiatus-Raising
in order to restrict raising to a one-step process:
(42) a. High vowel raising: Hiatus-Raising Ident-IO(raised)
b. Mid vowel raising: Hiatus-Raising Ident-IO(high)
c. Interaction: [Ident-IO(raised) & Ident-IO(high)]
Hiatus-Raising
The composite constraint [Ident-IO(raised) & Ident-IO(high)] is violated if and
only if Ident-IO(high) and Ident-IO(raised) are violated with respect to a given
segment. The domain is equal to the segment for which both faithfulness
constraints are evaluated.
Tableau (43a) illustrates how the fell swoop candidate e ij is eliminated by
the composite constraint:
(43)
[Ident-IO(high) & Hiatus- Ident-IO Ident-IO
Ident-IO(raised)] Raising (high) (raised)
a.i ee **!
a.ii + e i * *
a.iii ei j
*! * *
b.i ie **! *
b.ii ii *!
b.iii + i i j *
But in tableau (43b), the same output i i j is allowed as it involves only a single
step, hence the composite constraint is not violated.
Finally, let us briey discuss why Sympathy theory cannot deal with chain shifts.
To account for opacity of raising in e i, the output must be maximally faithful
to a {-candidate that is [raised] itself. Therefore Ident-IO(raised) must be the
selector, and [i] the {-candidate (which also happens to be the output). Assum-
ing Ident-{O(raised) as the undominated {O-faithfulness constraint, we arrive
at tableau (44a):
396
9.2 Opacity
a.i ee *!*
a.ii + { e i * *
a.iii e ij *! * *
b.i ie *!* *
b.ii L { i i *
b.iii ii j
*! *
In (44b), however, we see that the same ranking predicts that [i] is the {-
candidate, hence the (incorrect) output. Reversing the ranking of Ident-
{O(raised) and Hiatus-Raising may account for i ij, but will spoil the correct
outcome for input /e/, predicting e ij. This ranking paradox cannot be resolved.
Local Conjunction has seen wider applications (outside chain shifts) in a range
of phenomena, including dissimilation and Obligatory Contour Principle (OCP)
effects (Alderete 1997, It and Mester 1998) and word stress (Kager 1994, Crow-
hurst and Hewitt 1997). The shared property of all these phenomena is that
multiple violations of basic constraints within some domain are banned, while
a single violation of each of the constraints individually is tolerated. A specic
case is that where multiple violations of one constraint within a domain are
banned: self-conjunction.
Here we will illustrate this approach for OCP effects. It and Mester (1998)
discuss various restrictions on the cooccurrence of segments within Japanese morph-
emes, which ban cooccurring segments sharing the same marked value of some
feature. One of these restrictions is known as Lymans Law:
(45) Lymans Law: Stems must not contain more than one voiced
obstruent.
Lymans Law is exemplied by the minimal pairs (46ac) and systematic gaps
(46d):
(49) VOP2
No cooccurrence of voiced obstruency with itself.
In order to full its function of positional neutralizer, VOP2 must be ranked
above the basic sequence Ident-IO(voice) VOP. Considering a hypothetical
input that has a dual occurrence of [+voice, son], one of these is erased, while
12
The OCP was originally proposed for tonal systems (Leben 1973, Goldsmith 1976), and later
generalized into a wider principle governing dissimilations (McCarthy 1986).
398
9.2 Opacity
the other is preserved. Which of them is erased cannot be determined here, given
the fact that there are no alternations:
(50) Input: /
a
i/ VOP2 Ident-IO (voice) VOP
a.
a
i *! **
b. + ka
i * *
c. +
aki * *
d. kaki **!
a. bd *! * **
b. + bt * * *
c. pt **! *
d. b *! *
mode, it offers a highly elegant implementation of the insight that multiple viola-
tions of a constraint are worse than a single violation (Mohanan 1993). This extends
to OCP effects, as we saw above. However, Local Conjunction also has some
negative sides.
Firstly, although banning the worst-of-the-worst is undeniably in the spirit of OT,
conceptual problems do arise. Local Conjunction seems to stipulate what should
come for free in OT, given the architecture of the theory. OT is designed to deal
with forms which have more-than-necessary violations, against the principle of
minimal violation. However, minimal violation by itself, as a standard property
of interactions of basic constraints, should sufce to exclude the worst-of-the-
worst, rather than an extra mechanism of constraint conjunction. Accepting it
means that the theory has two means to rule out excessive violations of faithful-
ness: (a) minimal violation of basic constraints, and (b) Local Conjunction.
A second conceptual problem is that Local Conjunction seems to undermine
strict domination, a core principle of OT. Under strict domination, violation of
higher-ranked constraints cannot be compensated for by satisfaction of lower-
ranked constraints. (See chapter 1.) But under Local Conjunction, two con-
straints A and B, each of which is ranked too low to force the violation of C, can
nevertheless dominate C by joining forces in a conjoined constraint [A & B].
Such a situation, in which two constraints team up against a third constraint,
conicts with the intuition behind strict domination (even though Local Conjunc-
tion and strict domination are not formally inconsistent).
Finally, questions arise with respect to the huge increase of possible constraints
in Gen which is implied by Local Conjunction. For example, can any pair of
constraints be conjoined? This predicts constraints of a typologically doubtful
status, such as [Onset & NoCoda] or [*[+round] & Parse-Syl]. Can faithful-
ness constraints be conjoined with markedness constraints?13 If so, this predicts
even more bizarre constraints, such as [*Nt & Ident-IO(Place)]. Can any
number of constraints be conjoined, or is there a (binary?) upper limit? Without
any upper limit, the number of constraints in Gen becomes innite, with fatal
effects on learnability. But even under maximally restrictive assumptions about
Local Conjunction, a vast increase occurs in the amount of constraint interaction.
13
It and Mester (1998) exclude this, but see section 9.5 below.
400
9.3 Absolute ungrammaticality
lexical input, some grammatical output exists the optimal output, which minim-
ally violates the conicting constraints in a xed hierarchy. Nevertheless, languages
do not strictly conform to this picture, since cases of absolute ungrammaticality
occur. A specic input has no grammatical output:
Note that -ize is a stressed sufx (it has secondary stress wherever it appears),
and that its attachment to a stem with nal stress would create a stress clash, a
situation of adjacent stresses. Intuitively, clash avoidance takes priority over
afxation. But how can this be captured in OT, a theory of violable constraints?
If word formation were simply blocked if its optimal output violated any phono-
logical constraint, then no word formation would be possible at all. To avoid
wholesale nullication of morphology, the lexical input must be realized by the
grammar, that is, be mapped onto some output. Instead of blocking the input, the
grammar selects its optimal output analysis, possibly by a repair. In the case in
hand, repair may involve violation of accentual faithfulness (Max-Ft-IO input
stresses occur in the output), or well-formedness (*Clash). In sum, absolute
ungrammaticality poses a challenge to OT. In contrast, a theory of inviolate con-
straints has no problems: an output lter (with nullifying power) will reject any
outputs violating *Clash.
(54) Candidates
C1
C2
Input ... Output
...
Cn
The question then is, how can the Null Parse be optimal? Due to its lack of
phonological and morphological word status, it has one substantial advantage over
all other candidates: it cannot violate any well-formedness constraints pertain-
ing to the word level. However, the Null Parse violates the following constraint
(McCarthy and Prince 1993b):
(55) MParse
Morphemes are parsed into morphological constituents.
a. kI.rp.tz *!
b. k.rmp.tz *!
c. + {krmpt, -z} *
The Null Parse (56c) is optimal since all its competitors violate undominated con-
straints. Hence it is better to have no (tangible) output at all than an ill-formed output.
Orgun and Sprouse (1997: 4) point out empirical problems for MParse theory.
They argue that . . . there are cases of ungrammaticality in which the ungram-
matical candidate could be repaired by violating a constraint independently
known to be violable in other (grammatical) output forms in the language. That
is, the constraint ranking required to make the Null Parse win is demonstrably
inconsistent with the ranking required for non-null forms of the language. If these
objections (and the analyses on which they are based) are valid, then they pose
serious challenges to MParse theory.
402
9.3 Absolute ungrammaticality
Yet another unsatisfactory aspect of the MParse model is the assumption that
the Null Parse, in spite of its lack of phonetic realization, violates no faithfulness
constraints. This assumption is required to prevent the undesired result that the
Null Parse is rejected for violating the same constraints that exclude its non-null
(ungrammatical) competitors. For example, adding a violation mark for Ident to
the Null Parse (56c), penalizing its lack of phonetically realized stress, would
render it less harmonic than all its competitors. Alternatively, it might be stipu-
lated that identity constraints are only activated for outputs that are phonetically
interpreted, but that seems equally ad hoc.
Alternatives to MParse have been proposed, changing the basic design of the
OT grammar, by introducing inviolate constraint components. Orgun and Sprouse
(1997) argue that a component of inviolate constraints (Control) is serially
ordered after Gen and Eval as an output ltering device. As in standard OT, Eval
selects an optimal candidate, which is submitted to Control. Unlike Eval, Control
has the power of marking as ungrammatical any outputs violating its constraints.
Under this conception the grammar contains two sets of undominated constraints:
those whose violation is avoidable by repairs (these are part of Eval ), and those
whose violation is beyond repair (these are part of Control). In the case in hand,
the output [k.rmp.tz], optimal under Eval, is submitted to Control, which lters
it out, leaving the input /krmpt, -z/ without an output.
However, this proposal has its own specic problems. Firstly, it is essential that
constraints in Control, as output lters blocking afxations, be inviolate in all
outputs of the language. But for English, most researchers would agree that
*Clash is violable even within a Prosodic Word, as forms like Chnse reveal.
Secondly, Control is a rather blunt tool, which is principally unable to account for
different types of blocking within a single language. For example, a language may
have two defective afxations, each of which is blocked in a separate phono-
logical context. Here Control would be of no value because it predicts that the
afxations share gaps in the same contexts. In contrast, MParse theory may deal
with such cases by splitting up MParse into different afx-specic versions. In
sum, absolute ungrammaticality is another challenge which OT has not yet
completely mastered.14
14
Broekhuis (forthcoming) argues that absolute ungrammaticality can be dealt with by a com-
ponent of inviolate constraints preceding Eval. This proposal is comparable to the assumption
that Gen contains universally inviolable constraints (Prince and Smolensky 1993), ltering out
candidates even before they are submitted to Eval. Broekhuis deviates from this idea, however,
in his denition of input. In syntax, as we have seen in chapter 8, the input is less clearly
dened than in phonology. Broekhuis, for example, denes the input to Gen as a complete syn-
tactic representation developed in a component preceding Gen, whose requirements (check-
ing) are inviolable. Whether such a model can deal with absolute ungrammaticality in phonology
remains to be seen, however.
403
Residual issues
The fact that variation is free does not imply that it is totally unpredictable, but
only that no grammatical principles govern the distribution of variants. Never-
theless, a wide range of extragrammatical factors may affect the choice of one
variant over the other, including sociolinguistic variables (such as gender, age, and
class), and performance variables (such as speech style and tempo). Perhaps the
most important diagnostic of extragrammatical variables is that they affect the choice
of occurrence of one output over another in a stochastic way, rather than determin-
istically. Here we will focus on the consequences of free variation for the grammar.
Why does free variation pose a challenge to OT? An OT grammar is essentially
an input output mapping device. The grammar is deterministic, in the sense that
each input is mapped onto a single output the most harmonic candidate for a
constraint hierarchy. Given a single deterministic competition, how can two can-
didates ever both be optimal? If two output candidates O and O are different in
grammatical terms, then this difference must be relevant to some constraint(s) in
the hierarchy. This implies that O and O do not share the same violations marks,
hence one is more harmonic than the other with respect to the hierarchy. The
question is: how can free variation be reconciled with the deterministic nature of
the grammar?15
15
It has been argued that some cases of free variation indeed derive from inability on the part
of the constraint inventory to distinguish different outputs (Hammond 1994, Smolensky
1996). That is, the constraint inventory simply lacks constraints discriminating between two
outputs O1 and O2. However, even if this approach is feasible for the particular cases for which
it has been proposed, it is clearly not generalizable to all cases of free variation. Most involve
presence or absence of grammatical structure which is visible to some constraint (ultimately
to *Struc no phonological structure).
404
9.4 Free variation
(59)
Co-phonology 1 Output1
Input
Co-phonology 2 Output2
possibility that constraints were crucially unranked. Free ranking was observed
as a purely theoretical option by Prince and Smolensky (1993: 51), and has since
been argued to be the OT counterpart of optional rule application (Kiparsky
1993b, Kager 1994, 1997b, Reynolds 1994, Anttila 1995). When two constraints
C1 and C2 are freely ranked, the evaluation procedure branches at that point. In
one branch, C1 is ranked above C2, while in the other branch the ranking is
reversed.
Note that free ranking preserves strict domination, which holds within each sub-
hierarchy.
A (slightly simplied) example of free ranking is given below for English
vowel reduction. The conict between Reduce (vowels lack quality) and Ident-
IO is resolved in favour of either the latter (61a) or the former (61a):
a.i + sentim[en]tality *
a.ii sentim[n]tality *!
Reduce Ident-IO
b.i sentim[en]tality *!
b.ii + sentim[n]tality *
In what way(s) does free ranking differ from parallel co-phonologies? Is what
we call subhierarchy just another name for co-phonology? To some extent the
answer is yes, since free ranking entails evaluation of candidate forms by paral-
lel competitions. There is a substantial difference between the approaches, however.
Subhierarchies differ only in constraints whose ranking is not stipulated by the
grammar. One may think of a grammar with free rankings as underdetermined.
Variable ranking remains consistent with the hard rankings stated in the grammar,
a limitation explaining the observed similarities between variable outputs. Radical
differences between outputs are possible, but this entails a large amount of free
ranking, with a corresponding increase in the number of outputs. In a free ranking
model, two factors are positively correlated: the degree of dissimilarity between
406
9.5 Positional faithfulness
variable output forms and the number of variable outputs. In contrast, the
co-phonologies approach fails to predict such a correlation, since rankings of
different co-phonologies are intrinsically unrelated. A grammar with two co-
phonologies may select only two variable outputs of radically different shapes.
A nal point in favour of free ranking is that it offers a fairly accurate estimate
of the frequency of occurrence for each output (Anttila 1995).
The free ranking approach to variation looks promising, but a number of poten-
tial problems merit attention in future research. First, it is unclear whether OT
grammars with free ranking are learnable at all. (If so, free ranking is likely to
require major adaptions of Tesar and Smolenskys learning algorithm.) Second,
not necessarily on a negative note, the notion of free ranking may have conse-
quences for the concept of OT grammar which are sharply at odds with Prince
and Smolenskys (1993) principle of strict domination. Fine-tuning of free varia-
tion may be achieved by associating a freely ranked constraint with a numerical
index indicating its relative strength with respect to all other constraints. This may
pave the way to a probabilistic view of constraint interaction, replacing the doc-
trine of strict domination and moving into the direction of connectionism. Such
a development is already apparent in functionally oriented OT (Boersma 1997),
with precursors in Goldsmith and Larson (1990) and Mohanan (1993).
16
The notion of licensing originates in pre-OT phonology (Goldsmith 1990, Kaye, Lowenstamm,
and Vergnaud 1990, Steriade 1995a).
407
Residual issues
In most cases it is simply impossible to nd evidence for one view or the other,
due to the fact that the contexts of neutralization and faithfulness are both posit-
ively characterized by mutually exclusive labels (onset, coda, etc.). In current
literature both views have been adopted. Regardless of the issue of whether one
or both views are adequate, two general arguments for positional faithfulness can
be put forward.
Some researchers (Steriade 1995b, Flemming 1995, Jun 1995, Kirchner 1995,
1997) have argued that perceptual principles should be directly stated in gram-
mars, thus allowing reference to gradient and non-contrastive phonetic features.
Others (Selkirk 1995, Lombardi 1995b, Beckman 1997a, b) maintain a strict separa-
tion of phonology and phonetics, in the sense of avoiding reference to gradient
features.
The second (empirical) argument for positional faithfulness is that it captures and
unies a number of phonological patterns in different languages. More specic-
ally, there is an overwhelming typological tendency for neutralizing assimilation
to preserve feature values of segments in salient positions (onsets, initial syl-
lables, root segments, etc.), at the expense of segments in other positions (codas,
408
9.5 Positional faithfulness
medial syllables, afx segments, etc.). In this section we will look into one of
these cases the licensing of the feature [+round] by initial syllables drawing
on non-OT work by Steriade (1995a) and inspired by the OT analysis of Shona
vowel harmony by Beckman (1997a).
A typologically common restriction regarding [+round] is that it occurs on
vowels in specic positions. For example, several Altaic languages allow rounded
vowels only in the initial syllable of the word. This is a case of contextual neutral-
ization: the rounding contrast is suppressed in segments in non-initial syllables.
However, an analysis of this pattern by a contextual markedness constraint ban-
ning [+round] from non-initial syllables is awkward, as the context of neutraliza-
tion (non-initial syllables) is not a natural class. This defect is avoided by a
positional faithfulness analysis. A constraint Ident-IO(round, [) militates
against the loss of [round] in initial syllables:
(64) Ident-IO(round, [)
An output segment standing in the initial syllable has the same value
for [round] as its input correspondent.
(65) Ident-IO(round)
An output segment has the same value for [round] as its input
correspondent.
This installs the faithfulness part of the interaction. Let us now look into the
markedness part, which is very simple. The faithfulness constraints compete with
a general, context-free markedness constraint *[+round], which penalizes round
vowels. In Altaic, rounding is lost in all vowels except those that are licensed by
an initial syllable. This is expressed in the following ranking:
Let us assume a hypothetical input with rounding in both of its vowels. Candidate
(68c) fatally violates positional faithfulness in its initial syllable. Of the two
remaining candidates, (68b) is optimal since it minimally violates *[+round]:
a. u-o **!
b. + u-i * *
c. i-i *! **
However, an even better argument can be made for positional faithfulness on the
basis of rounding harmony. In Yokuts (Newman 1944), [+round] is contrastive in
the rst syllable only, as in Altaic, but it also spreads beyond its directly licensed
position, into afx vowels.17
17
We abstract away from the interaction with vowel height, as well as from opacity (section 9.2).
410
9.5 Positional faithfulness
a. + dub-hun ** *
b. dub-hin *! *
c. dib-hin *! *
Harmony is satised in both (71a) and (71c) but only the latter violates posi-
tional faithfulness in its initial syllable. This analysis is highly elegant, and it also
captures the relation with the direct licensing of rounding in the Altaic languages
by a simple reranking. (In Altaic, *[+round] dominates Harmony.) Finally, a posi-
tional faithfulness analysis is superior to one based on contextual markedness.
With only a general faithfulness constraint Ident-IO(round) to penalize changes
of [round], the inertness of the initial syllable must be due to contextual marked-
ness. Even if we assume a constraint militating against [+round] in non-initial
syllables (ranking it above *[+round]), its interaction with Harmony is highly
problematic. For example, Harmony *[+round] Ident-IO(round) predicts
a harmony pattern *dib-hin, regardless of where we rank the contextual marked-
ness constraint. This empirical argument for positional faithfulness complements
the typological argument that was discussed earlier.
Steriade (1995a: 162) points out extensions of the idea of indirect licensing to
the cases of local assimilation in which onsets spread place or laryngeal features
onto adjacent coda consonants. In many languages, codas cannot carry independ-
ent values for [voice] (as in Dutch, chapter 1) or place of articulation (recall the
discussion of the Coda Condition in chapter 3). In a subset of these languages,
coda neutralization is accompanied by coda-to-onset assimilation, resulting in an
indirect licensing of features by the onset.
Let us now evaluate the notion positional faithfulness by criteria that have played
a major role earlier in this chapter. These are constraint format and factorial
typology.
First, does positional faithfulness maintain the strict separation between faith-
fulness constraints and markedness constraints? Recall that in section 9.2.2 we
criticized two-level well-formedness for blurring this distinction, and giving con-
straints rule-like power. Positional faithfulness constraints resemble two-level
well-formedness constraints in their reference to prosodic positions of output seg-
ments. Unlike two-level well-formedness constraints, they cannot be violated if
the output segment fails to occupy the relevant position, and so cant trigger
changes. In this respect, compare (73) and (74) stated in their correspondence
formats:
What is lacking from this factorial typology, as compared to the one of chapter
1, is the case of allophonic variation. This arises under a complete domination
of faithfulness for a feature [F] by markedness constraints for [F], with contextual
412
9.6 Underlying Representations versus allomorphy
IO-Faithfulness
Input UR (afxed) UR
On the standard view, the input equals an abstract UR, which is mapped onto the
output, an actual surface representation. UR is abstract as it need not surface in
its input form, but serves to supply phonotactically unpredictable shape aspects
413
Residual issues
Let us now extend this checking view to cases in which alternations do exist, that
is, cases for which the standard model uses an abstract UR. We start by making
the major assumption that each surface alternant of a morpheme has its own
input, which is simply identical to its output under Lexicon Optimization. (That
is, we temporarily ignore the fact that alternants are systematically related in their
shapes.) The assumption of multiple inputs for each morpheme (allomorphs) thus
allows the grammar to continue to function as a checking device.
In the Dutch example, the input of the singular [bt] bed is simply {bt},
while that of the plural [bdn] is simply {bdn}. (We will use the notation
{ . . . } for inputs to avoid confusion with the standard UR notation / . . . /.) Still,
under Richness of the Base, an alternative singular input {bd} might have been
proposed, but this would not have been able to make it to the surface due to a
constraint interaction (*VoicedCoda Ident-IO(voice)) neutralizing it into the
output [bt]. Therefore the optimal lexical input for [bt] is {bt}, due to Lexicon
Optimization. The grammar does not impose such a neutralization on the input
{bdn}, which makes it to the surface without change:
In this UR-less model, the input (lexical shape) simply equals the output (surface
shape). IO-faithfulness maintains its original function of reinforcing parts of the
input, protecting it against the neutralizing forces of markedness.
414
9.6 Underlying Representations versus allomorphy
IO-Faithfulness
415
Residual issues
voice in very simple paradigms which consist of the singular stem and the plural.
Therefore we assume that the input is a mini-paradigm, a set of allomorph pairs,
each containing one base allomorph (for insertion into the singular stem) and one
contextual allomorph (for insertion into the afxed plural). As usual, Gen supplies
a set of candidate output forms for each input pair, that is, a paradigm consisting
of an actual singular stem and an actual afxed plural.
First we will look at the evaluation of an input paradigm {bt ~ bd-n}, which
the grammar should approve of without changes, producing [bt] ~ [bd-n]. Gen
proposes an innite set of candidate output paradigms, of which four are shown
in (79).
All four are submitted to Eval, which selects output paradigm (80a), indeed
identical to the input:
a. + bt ~ bd-n *
b. bt ~ bt-n *!
c. bd ~ bd-n *! *
d. bd ~ bt-n *! ** *
a. + bt ~ bd-n * *
b. bt ~ bt-n **!
c. bd ~ bd-n *!
d. bd ~ bt-n *! * *
Up to this point, no activity of uniform exponence has been visible. But of course
the grammar must allow for such activity, so as to restrict the difference in shape
between allomorphs in a paradigm. Without constraints enforcing uniform expon-
ence, any pair of input allomorphs would be able to surface (with the only restric-
tion imposed by high-ranked well-formedness constraints).
For example, Dutch allows allomorph pairs such as [bt] ~ [bd-n], whereas
pairs such as *[bt] ~ [pt-n], with voice alternations in word onset position, are
systematically excluded. Such candidate output paradigms are rejected for viola-
tion of an undominated positional faithfulness constraint:
paradigm respecting uniform exponence with respect to word onset voicing. Since
this neutralization could occur at the expense of the voicing value of either the
base or the afxed form, a tie-breaking constraint is required. In tableau (84),
this is the low-ranked constraint VOP:
(84)
Input: {bt ~ pt-n} Ident-OO *Voiced Ident-IO Ident-OO VOP
(voice, [C) Coda (voice) (voice)
a. bt ~ pt-n *! * *
b. bt ~ bt-n * *!*
c. + pt ~ pt-n *
d. pt ~ bt-n *! ** * *
This example demonstrates the interaction of the three major types of constraints in
an allomorphy model: OO-identity, IO-faithfulness, and well-formedness.
This is the second example of a lexical paradigm being overruled by the gram-
mar, the case of an oversized paradigm that is shrunk to match the requirements
of uniform exponence.
An extension of this model may be considered under which the distribution of the
allomorphs is also brought under control of the grammar. The Dutch lexicon
supplies the set of two allomorphs {bt ~ bd}, without marking one for insertion
into stem and the other for insertion into afxed form. The distribution of allo-
morphs is fully predictable from well-formedness constraints, primarily *Voiced-
Coda but possibly also Inter-V-Voice, which, in spite of its low ranking in
Dutch, may still exert its inuence as an emergence of the unmarked:
418
9.6 Underlying Representations versus allomorphy
a. + bt ~ bd-n
b. bd ~ bt-n *! *
It is simply too early to evaluate the results of a theory that seeks to eliminate
URs. However, some major points can be made even on the basis of the simple
model outlined above. As usual, the model has pros and cons.
On the positive side, this model reduces the abstractness of lexical repres-
entation by eliminating the UR. This is a noteworthy result, since reduction of
abstractness entails an increase in cognitive plausibility, reducing the role of the
learner in inferring patterns that are remote from actual surface patterns. While
it has been claimed in the classical generative literature that such abstractness
is just what it takes to shape an explanatory theory of alternations, any reduction
of abstractness that leaves the generalizing power of the theory unaffected is very
welcome. (Of course it has to be determined whether such a model indeed
matches or even exceeds the explanatory power of UR theory, a point that we will
return to below.)
The second point in favour of the allomorphic model is that it presents a
uniform analysis of all types of alternations, productive and non-productive alike.
The lexicon is the place where idiosyncratic properties of a language are listed,
so nothing guarantees that every morpheme will indeed exhibit the full range of
allomorphs as compared to other morphemes. For example, English is known
to have exceptions to a process of trisyllabic laxing (op[e]que ~ op[]city, but
ob[i]se ~ ob[i]sity, Kiparsky 1982b). On an allomorphic model the difference
between both morphemes is simply this: opaque has two allomorphs alternating
in vowel length, while obese has only one, hence no length alternation. There are
no high-ranked well-formedness constraints, nor OO-identity constraints pertain-
ing to vowel length to enforce this allomorphy. Thus complete symmetry is not
expected. Or to state it differently, the grammar allows space for lexical variation,
but the lexicon allots this space in the form of allomorphy. The grammar partly
controls allomorphy, but does not fully predict it. (Richness of the Base was never
intended to ll all the accidental gaps in the lexicon of a language.)
419
Residual issues
severe pressure from OT analysts (starting with Smolensky 1993, and elaborated
by Inkelas 1995, It, Mester, and Padgett 1995, and Steriade 1995b) who argue
that constraint interactions offer superior accounts. Similar reductionist arguments
were made against representational assumptions of feature geometry (Padgett
1995, N Chiosin and Padgett 1997) and syllable structure (Steriade 1995b).
An issue closely related to that of representations concerns the boundary be-
tween phonology and phonetics. In work by Steriade, Flemming, Kirchner, Hayes,
and others, it is argued that constraints should be able to refer to much more phon-
etic detail (including non-contrastive features and numerical values of acoustic
parameters) than is allowed on classical generative assumptions, which maintain
a strict separation between phonology and phonetics. (An illustration of this
development is the title of Flemmings 1995 UCLA dissertation: Auditory repres-
entations in phonology.) This blurring of the phonologyphonetics boundary
goes hand in hand with an increased role for functional explanations. For ex-
ample, Jun (1995) and Steriade (1995b), in the footsteps of phoneticians such as
Lindblom, Kohler, and Ohala, argue that speakers make more effort to preserve
features in contexts where they are most salient. The articulatory and perceptual
basis of phonological constraints is emphasized by Archangeli and Pulleyblank
(1994), Gafos (1996), Hayes (1996a), Myers (1997b), and others. No doubt, real
progress can be made by this approach. An increased role for functional explana-
tions in grammatical theory matches well with a major goal of OT, which is to
encode directly markedness in the grammar, an enterprise that has been crucial
to OTs typological achievements. The merging of the phonetic and phonological
components into a single hierarchy of constraints comes tantalizingly close to a
single-step mapping, another authentic goal of OT.
However, freely mixing phonology and phonetics comes at a certain cost. There
is overwhelming support for a level coinciding with the output of phonology and
the input to phonetic interpretation. First, while phonological specications are
categorical (that is on or off), phonetic specication of non-distinctive features
is gradient and based on interpolation (Keating 1988, Cohn 1993a; see Kirchner
1997 for a theory of contrast in a one-step mapping model). Second, there is sur-
prisingly little evidence that grammatical generalizations refer to non-distinctive
feature specications. Third, a relatively abstract (phonetically underspecied)
output level of the phonology is conrmed as a cognitive reality by various kinds
of independent evidence (language games, speech errors, second language acqui-
sition, etc.: Fromkin 1971, Stemberger 1991). Apart from the evidence for levels,
there is yet another potential stumbling block for a direct reductionist approach.
A theory reducing phonology to interactions of raw functional (perceptual and
articulatory) factors has difculties in accounting for symmetry as a property of
phonological systems, since such factors, by denition, interact in a gradient
421
Residual issues
fashion. (But see Hayes 1996a for a theory of learning of symmetrical patterns
on the basis of gradient information.) In sum, a theory which gives up the sep-
aration of phonology and phonetics holds much explanatory potential, but also
faces two fundamental problems in dealing with cognitively plausible levels of
representation.
When numerical values (of phonetic parameters) are incorporated into phono-
logy, it seems only logical to take another step into numerical (gradient) types of
interaction, so that constraints exert inuence according to their relative strength,
expressed in an index. In several constraint-based models (for example, Harmonic
Grammar, Legendre, Miyata, and Smolensky 1990), numerical ranking indeed re-
places the principle of strict domination, partly bridging the gap with connection-
ism (Rumelhart and McLelland 1986, Goldsmith and Larson 1990). It is not clear
at all whether an OT model based on numerical ranking can preserve the advan-
tages of standard OT. For example, the phenomenon of the emergence of the
unmarked depends on strict domination. For discussion see Prince and Smolen-
sky (1993, chapter 10).
In sum, in the foreseeable future phonology may look quite different from what
it is today. It has been suggested that there are some striking resemblances
between OT and Structuralism (with respect to views of allophonic patterns and
contrast, surface patterns, functional considerations, and allomorphy), the domin-
ant framework in the pre-generative era. Is history circular? Perhaps, but if so,
there are important differences from the earlier days. Due to the generative legacy,
there remains a strong emphasis on formal precision in grammatical analysis,
combined with the necessity to restrict the descriptive power of linguistic theory.
Both theoretical priorities are solidly integrated into OT. Moreover, in-depth
phonological analyses of many languages have given us a much better insight
into cross-linguistic tendencies and typology than we had half a century ago.
The emphasis on formal accuracy and explanatory adequacy, coupled to a still
expanding typological basis, provides the background that is necessary to move
successfully forward into areas that were previously considered to be too surface-
oriented for phonologists to deal with. The concept of grammar is strong enough
to survive this continuing enterprise.
Opacity and OT
Archangeli, Diana and Keiichiro Suzuki (1997) The Yokuts challenge. In Roca.
197226.
422
9.7 Conclusion:9.7
future
Further
perspectives
reading
Local Conjunction
Alderete, John (1997) Dissimilation as Local Conjunction. In K. Kusumoto (ed.)
Proceedings of the North East Linguistic Society 27. 1731. [ROA-175,
http://ruccs.rutgers.edu/roa.html]
Kirchner, Robert (1996) Synchronic chain shifts in Optimality Theory. Linguistic
Inquiry 27. 34150.
Absolute ungrammaticality
Orgun, C. Orhan and Ronald Sprouse (1997) From M-Parse to Control: deriv-
ing ungrammaticality. Ms., University of California, Berkeley. [ROA-224,
http://ruccs.rutgers.edu/roa.html]
Raffelsiefen, Renate (1996) Gaps in word formation. In U. Kleinhenz (ed.), Inter-
faces in phonology. Studia Grammatica 41. Berlin: Akademie Verlag. 194209.
Free variation
Anttila, Arto (1995) Deriving variation from grammar: a study of Finnish genit-
ives. Ms., Stanford University. [ROA-63, http://ruccs.rutgers.edu/roa.html]
Kager, Ren (1997b) Generalized alignment and morphological parsing. Rivista
di Linguistica 9. 24582.
Positional faithfulness
Beckman, Jill (1997a) Positional faithfulness, positional neutralization and Shona
vowel harmony. Phonology 14. 146.
Lombardi, Linda (1995b) Why Place and Voice are different: constraint inter-
actions and feature faithfulness in Optimality Theory. Ms., University of
Maryland, College Park. [ROA-105, http://ruccs.rutgers.edu/roa.html]
Allomorphy
Burzio, Luigi (forthcoming) Cycles, regularization, and correspondence. To
appear in J. Dekkers, F. van der Leeuw, and J. van de Weijer (eds.), Optimal-
ity Theory: syntax, phonology, and acquisition. Oxford University Press.
423
Residual issues
424
REFERENCES
425
References
426
References
Borowsky, Toni and Mark Harvey (1997) Vowel length in Warray and weight identity.
Phonology 14. 16175.
Boxwell, Helen and Maurice Boxwell (1966) Weri phonemes. In S. A. Wurm (ed.), Papers
in New Guinea linguistics, V. Linguistic Circle of Canberra Publications, Series A,
No. 7. Canberra: Australian National University. 7793.
Brame, Michael (1974) The cycle in phonology: stress in Palestinian, Maltese, and
Spanish. Linguistic Inquiry 5. 39 60.
Bresnan, Joan (forthcoming) Optimal syntax. To appear in J. Dekkers, F. van der Leeuw,
and J. van de Weijer (eds.), Optimality Theory: phonology, syntax, and acquisition.
Oxford University Press.
Broekhuis, Hans (forthcoming) Against feature strength. To appear in R. van Bezooijen
and R. Kager (eds.), Linguistics in the Netherlands 1998. Amsterdam: John
Benjamins.
Broihier, Kevin (1995) Optimality theoretic rankings with tied constraints: Slavic relatives,
resumptive pronouns and learnability. Ms., Department of Brain and Cognitive
Sciences, MIT. [ROA-46, http://ruccs.rutgers.edu/roa.html]
Bromberger, Sylvain and Morris Halle (1989) Why phonology is different. Linguistic
Inquiry 20. 5170.
Broselow, Ellen (1992) Parametric variation in Arabic dialect phonology. In E. Broselow,
M. Eid, and J. McCarthy (eds.), Perspectives on Arabic linguistics IV: Papers from the
fourth annual symposium on Arabic linguistics. Amsterdam and Philadelphia: John
Benjamins. 7 45.
(1995) Skeletal positions and moras. In Goldsmith. 175205.
Broselow, Ellen, Su-I Chen, and Marie Huffman (1997) Syllable weight: convergence of
phonology and phonetics. Phonology 14. 47 82.
Broselow, Ellen and John McCarthy (1983) A theory of internal reduplication. The
Linguistic Review 3. 25 89.
Buckley, Eugene (1995) Cyclicity and correspondence. Handout of paper presented at the
Tilburg conference The derivational residue in phonology, Fall 1995. [ROA-93c,
http://ruccs.rutgers.edu/roa.html]
Burzio, Luigi (1994) Principles of English stress. Cambridge University Press.
(1995) The rise of Optimality Theory. Glot International 1:6. 37.
(1996) Surface constraints versus Underlying Representation. In J. Durand and B. Laks
(eds.), Current trends in phonology: models and methods. CNRS, Paris X, and
University of Salford. University of Salford Publications. 97122.
(forthcoming) Cycles, regularization, and correspondence. To appear in J. Dekkers,
F. van der Leeuw, and J. van de Weijer (eds.), Optimality Theory: syntax, phonology,
and acquisition. Oxford University Press.
Bybee, Joan L. (1988) Morphology as lexical organization. In M. Hammond and
M. Noonan (eds.), Theoretical morphology. San Diego: Academic Press. 119 41.
(1995) Regular morphology and the lexicon. Language and Cognitive Processes 10.
425 55.
427
References
Bye, Patrik (1996) Correspondence in the prosodic hierarchy and the grid: case studies in
overlength and level stress. Cand. Philol. thesis, University of Troms.
Chomsky, Noam (1957) Syntactic structures. The Hague: Mouton.
(1965) Aspects of the theory of syntax. Cambridge, Mass.: MIT Press.
(1981a) Markedness and core grammar. In A. Belletti, L. Brandi, and L. Rizzi (eds.),
Theory of markedness in generative grammar. Proceedings of the 1979 GLOW
conference. Pisa: Scuola Normale Superiore di Pisa. 123 46.
(1981b) Lectures on government and binding. Dordrecht: Foris.
(1991) Some notes on economy of derivation and representation. In R. Freidin (ed.),
Principles and parameters in comparative grammar. Cambridge, Mass.: MIT Press.
4158.
(1993) A minimalist program for linguistic theory. In K. Hale and S. J. Keyser (eds.),
The view from Building 20. Cambridge, Mass.: MIT Press. 4158.
(1995) The minimalist program. Cambridge, Mass.: MIT Press.
Chomsky, Noam and Morris Halle (1968) The sound pattern of English. New York: Harper
and Row.
Churchward, C. Maxwell (1953) Tongan grammar. Oxford University Press.
Clements, George N. (1985a) The problem of transfer in nonlinear morphology. Cornell
Working Papers in Linguistics 7. 38 73.
(1985b) The geometry of phonological features. In C. Ewen and E. Kaisse (eds.),
Phonology Yearbook 2. Cambridge University Press. 225 52.
(1986) Syllabication and epenthesis in the Barra dialect of Gaelic. In K. Bogers,
M. Maus, and H. van der Hulst (eds.), The phonological representation of
suprasegmentals. Dordrecht: Foris. 31736.
(1990) The role of the sonority cycle in core syllabication. In J. Kingston and M.
Beckman (eds.), Papers in laboratory phonology I: Between the grammar and physics
of speech. Cambridge University Press. 283 333.
Clements, George N. and Samuel J. Keyser (1983) CV phonology: a generative theory of
the syllable. Cambridge, Mass.: MIT Press.
Cohn, Abigail (1989) Stress in Indonesian and bracketing paradoxes. Natural Language
and Linguistic Theory 7. 167216.
(1993a) Nasalisation in English. Phonology 10. 4381.
(1993b) The status of nasalized continuants. In Huffman and Krakow. 329 68.
Cohn, Abigail and John McCarthy (1994) Alignment and parallelism in Indonesian
phonology. Ms., Cornell University, Ithaca, N. Y. and University of Massachusetts,
Amherst. [ROA-25, http://ruccs.rutgers.edu/roa.html]
Cole, Jennifer and Charles Kisseberth (1995) Restricting multi-level constraint evaluation:
opaque rule interactions in Yawelmani vowel harmony. Ms., University of Illinois,
Urbana-Champaign. [ROA-98, http://ruccs.rutgers.edu/roa.html]
Colina, Sonia (1996) Spanish truncation processes: the emergence of the unmarked.
Linguistics 34. 1199 218.
Crowhurst, Megan and Mark Hewitt (1995) Prosodic overlay and headless feet in Yidi,
Phonology 12. 39 84.
428
References
429
References
Frank, Robert and Giorgio Satta (1998) Optimality Theory and the generative
complexity of constraint violability. Computational Linguistics 24. 30715.
[ROA-228, http://ruccs.rutgers.edu/roa.html]
French, Koleen M. (1988) Insights into Tagalog: reduplication, inxation, and stress from
nonlinear phonology. Dallas: Summer Institute of Linguistics and University of Texas
at Arlington.
Fromkin, Victoria (1971) The non-anomalous nature of anomalous utterances. Language
47. 2752.
Furby, Christine (1974) Garawa phonology. Canberra: Australian National University.
Gafos, Adamantios (1996) The articulatory basis of locality in phonology. PhD
dissertation, Johns Hopkins University.
Gnanadesikan, Amalia (1995) Markedness and faithfulness constraints in child
phonology. Ms., University of Massachusetts, Amherst. [ROA-67,
http://ruccs.rutgers.edu/roa.html]
Goad, Heather (1997) Consonant harmony in child language. In S. J. Hannahs and
M. Young-Scholten (eds.), Focus on phonological acquisition. Amsterdam: John
Benjamins. 113 42.
Goldsmith, John (1976) Autosegmental phonology. PhD dissertation, MIT. [Published
1979, New York: Garland.]
(1990) Autosegmental and metrical phonology. Oxford: Blackwell.
(1993a) Harmonic phonology. In Goldsmith (1993b). 21 60.
(ed.) (1993b) The last phonological rule: reections on constraints and derivations.
University of Chicago Press.
(ed.) (1995) The handbook of phonological theory. Oxford: Blackwell.
Goldsmith, John and Gary Larson (1990) Local modeling and syllabication. In M.
Ziolkowski, M. Noske, and K. Deaton (eds.), Papers from the Chicago Linguistic
Society 26:2. 129 41.
Golston, Chris (1995) Syntax outranks phonology: evidence from ancient Greek.
Phonology 12. 343 68.
(1996) Direct Optimality Theory: representation as pure markedness. Language 72.
713 48.
Greenberg, Joseph (1978) Some generalizations concerning initial and nal consonant
clusters. In J. Greenberg (ed.), Universals of human language, II: Phonology. Stanford
University Press. 243 80.
Grimshaw, Jane (1991) Extended projection. Ms., Brandeis University, Waltham, Mass.
(1997) Projection, heads, and optimality. Linguistic Inquiry 28. 373 422.
Gupta, Prahlad and David Touretzky (1994) Connectionist models and linguistic theory:
investigations of stress systems in language. Cognitive Science 18. 150.
Haas, Mary (1940) Tunica. Handbook of American Indian languages, IV. Washington, D.C.:
Smithsonian Institute, Bureau of American Ethnography.
Haas, Wim de (1988) A formal theory of vowel coalescence: a case study of Ancient Greek.
PhD dissertation, University of Nijmegen. Dordrecht: Foris.
430
References
Hale, Mark and Charles Reiss (1997) Grammar optimization: the simultaneous acquisition
of constraint ranking and a lexicon. Ms., Concordia University, Montreal. [ROA-231,
http://ruccs.rutgers.edu/roa.html]
Halle, Morris and George N. Clements (1983) Problem book in phonology. Cambridge,
Mass.: MIT Press.
Halle, Morris and Jean-Roger Vergnaud (1987) An essay on stress. Cambridge, Mass.: MIT
Press.
Hammond, Michael (1984) Constraining metrical theory: a modular theory of rhythm and
destressing. PhD dissertation, University of California, Los Angeles. [Published 1988,
New York: Garland.]
(1994) An OT account of variability in Walmatjarri stress. Ms., University of Arizona.
[ROA-20, http://ruccs.rutgers.edu/roa.html]
(1997) Parsing syllables: modeling OT computationally. Ms., University of Arizona.
[ROA-222, http://ruccs.rutgers.edu/roa.html]
Hansen, K. C. and L. E. Hansen (1969) Pintupi phonology. Oceanic Linguistics 8.
153 70.
Harris, James (1983) Syllable structure and stress in Spanish: a nonlinear analysis.
Cambridge, Mass.: MIT Press.
Harris, John (1990) Derived phonological contrasts. In S. Ramsaran (ed.), Studies in the
pronunciation of English: a commemorative volume in honour of A. C. Gimson.
London: Routledge. 87105.
Hawkins, John and Anne Cutler (1988) Psycholinguistic factors in morphological
asymmetry. In J. Hawkins (ed.), Explaining language universals. Oxford: Blackwell.
280 317.
Hayes, Bruce (1980) A metrical theory of stress rules. PhD dissertation, MIT. [Published
1985, New York: Garland.]
(1985) Iambic and trochaic rhythm in stress rules. In M. Niepokuj, M. VanClay, V.
Nikiforidou, and D. Jeder (eds.), Proceedings of the Berkeley Linguistics Society 11.
429 46.
(1986) Inalterability in CV phonology. Language 62. 32151.
(1987) A revised parametric metrical theory. In J. McDonough and B. Plunket (eds.),
Proceedings of the North East Linguistic Society 17. 274 89.
(1989) Compensatory lengthening in moraic phonology. Linguistic Inquiry 20. 253 306.
(1995) Metrical stress theory: principles and case studies. University of Chicago Press.
(1996a) Phonetically driven phonology: the role of Optimality Theory and inductive
grounding. Ms., University of California, Los Angeles. [ROA-158,
http://ruccs.rutgers.edu/roa.html]
(1996b) Constraint ranking software. Ms., University of California, Los Angeles.
[Manual of computer program ranking OT constraints, on line available from
http://www.humnet.ucla.edu/humnet/linguistics/people/hayes/otsoft/otsoft.htm]
(forthcoming) Anticorrespondence in Yidi. To appear in B. Hermans and M. van
Oostendorp (eds.), The derivational residue in phonology. Amsterdam: John Benjamins.
431
References
Hayes, Bruce and May Abad (1989) Reduplication and syllabication in Ilokano. Lingua
77. 33174.
Hayes, Bruce and Tanya Stivers (1995) A phonetic account of postnasal voicing. Ms.,
University of California, Los Angeles.
Healey, Phyllis M. (1960) An Agta grammar. Manila: Summer Institute of Linguistics.
Hjelmslev, Louis (1935) La Catgorie des Cas I. Acta Jutlandica 7:1. Aarhus. [Reissued
1972, Copenhagen and Munich.]
Hooper [Bybee], Joan L. (1976) An introduction to Natural Generative Phonology.
New York: Academic Press.
Hore, Michael (1981) Syllable length and stress in Nunggubuyu. In B. Waters (ed.),
Australian phonologies: collected papers. Work Papers of SIL-AAB, A5. Darwin:
Summer Institute of Linguistics.
Huffman, Marie K. (1993) Phonetic patterns of nasalization and implications for feature
specication. In Huffman and Krakow. 303 27.
Huffman, Marie K. and Rena A. Krakow (eds.) (1993) Phonetics and phonology V: Nasals,
nasalization, and the velum. San Diego: Academic Press.
Hulst, Harry van der (1984) Syllable structure and stress in Dutch. Dordrecht: Foris.
Hulst, Harry van der and Ellis Visch (1992) Iambic lengthening in Carib. In R. Bok-
Bennema and R. van Hout (eds.), Linguistics in the Netherlands 1992. Amsterdam:
John Benjamins. 113 24.
Hume, Elizabeth (1992) Front vowels, coronal consonants and their interaction in nonlinear
phonology. PhD dissertation, Cornell University, Ithaca, N.Y.
(1995) Beyond linear order: prosodic constraints and C/V metathesis. Proceedings of the
Formal Linguistics Society of the Midwest 6. Bloomington: Indiana University
Linguistics Club.
Hung, Henrietta (1994) The rhythmic and prosodic organization of edge constituents.
PhD dissertation, Brandeis University, Waltham, Mass. [ROA-24,
http://ruccs.rutgers.edu/roa.html]
Hyams, Nina (1986) Language acquisition and the theory of parameters. Dordrecht:
Reidel.
Hyman, Larry (1985) A theory of phonological weight. Dordrecht: Foris.
Idsardi, William J. (1997) Phonological derivations and historical changes in Hebrew
spirantization. In Roca. 367 92.
Inkelas, Sharon (1989) Prosodic constituency in the lexicon. PhD dissertation, Stanford
University.
(1995) The consequences of optimization for underspecication. In J. Beckman (ed.),
Proceedings of the North East Linguistic Society 25. 287302.
(1996) Dominant afxes and the phonologymorphology interface. In U. Kleinhenz
(ed.), Interfaces in phonology. Studia Grammatica 41. Berlin: Akademie Verlag.
128 54.
(forthcoming) Exceptional stress-attracting sufxes in Turkish: representations vs.
the grammar. To appear in Kager, Van der Hulst, and Zonneveld. [ROA-39,
http://ruccs.rutgers.edu/roa.html]
432
References
Inkelas, Sharon and C. Orhan Orgun (1995) Level ordering and economy in the lexical
phonology of Turkish. Language 71. 763 93.
Inkelas, Sharon, C. Orhan Orgun, and Cheryl Zoll (1997) The implications of lexical
exceptions for the nature of grammar. In Roca. 393 418.
It, Junko (1986) Syllable theory in prosodic phonology. PhD dissertation, University of
Massachusetts, Amherst. [Published 1988, New York: Garland.]
(1989) A prosodic theory of epenthesis. Natural Language and Linguistic Theory 7.
21760.
(1990) Prosodic minimality in Japanese. In M. Ziolkowski, M. Noske, and K. Deaton
(eds.), Papers from Chicago Linguistic Society 26:2. 213 39.
It, Junko, Yoshihisa Kitagawa, and R. Armin Mester (1996) Prosodic faithfulness and
correspondence: evidence from a Japanese argot. Journal of East Asian Linguistics 5.
21794.
It, Junko and R. Armin Mester (1992) Weak layering and word binarity. Ms., University
of California, Santa Cruz. Linguistics Research Center Report No. 92 09.
(1995) The core-periphery structure of the lexicon and constraints on reranking. In
Beckman, Walsh Dickey, and Urbanczyk. 181210.
(1997) Correspondence and compositionality: the Gagyo variation in Japanese
phonology. In Roca. 419 62.
(1998) Markedness and word structure: OCP effects in Japanese. Ms., University of
California, Santa Cruz. [ROA-255, http://ruccs.rutgers.edu/roa.html]
(forthcoming) Realignment. To appear in Kager, Van der Hulst, and Zonneveld.
It, Junko, R. Armin Mester, and Jaye Padgett (1995) Licensing and underspecication in
Optimality Theory. Linguistic Inquiry 26. 571 614.
Jacobsen, William (1964) A grammar of the Washo language. PhD dissertation, University
of California, Berkeley.
Jakobson, Roman (1941) Kindersprache, Aphasie und allgemeine Lautgesetze. Uppsala.
[Reissued in Jakobson 1962. 328 401.]
(1962) Selected writings. The Hague: Mouton.
Jun, Jongho (1995) Perceptual and articulatory factors in place assimilation: an Optimality
Theoretic approach. PhD dissertation, University of California, Los Angeles.
Kager, Ren (1989) A metrical theory of stress and destressing in English and Dutch.
Dordrecht: Foris.
(1992a) Shapes of the generalized trochee. In J. Mead (ed.), Proceedings of the West
Coast Conference on Formal Linguistics 11. 298 311.
(1992b) Are there any truly quantity-insensitive systems? In L. A. Buszard-Welcher,
L. Lee, and W. Weigel (eds.), Proceedings of the Berkeley Linguistics Society 18.
12332.
(1993) Alternatives to the iambic-trochaic law. Natural Language and Linguistic Theory
11. 381 432.
(1994) Ternary rhythm in alignment theory. Ms., Utrecht University. [ROA-35,
http://ruccs.rutgers.edu/roa.html]
(1995) Review of Hayes 1995. Phonology 12. 437 64.
433
References
434
References
435
References
436
References
437
References
438
References
Odden, David (1986) On the role of the Obligatory Contour Principle in phonological
theory. Language 62. 35383.
Ohala, John J. (1983) The origin of sound patterns in vocal tract constraints. In
P. F. MacNeilage (ed.), The production of speech. New York: Springer. 189216.
(1990) The phonetics and phonology of aspects of assimilation. In J. Kingston and
M. Beckman (eds.), Papers in laboratory phonology I: Between the grammar and
physics of speech. Cambridge University Press. 25875.
Ohala, John J. and H. Kawasaki (1984) Phonetics and prosodic phonology. In C. Ewen and
E. Kaisse (eds.), Phonology Yearbook 1. Cambridge University Press. 11327.
Ohala, John J. and Manjari Ohala (1993) The phonetics of nasal phonology: theorems and
data. In Huffman and Krakow. 225 49.
Onn, Farid M. (1976) Aspects of Malay phonology and morphology: a generative
approach. PhD dissertation, University of Illinois, Urbana-Champaign.
Orgun, C. Orhan (1994) Monotonic Cyclicity and Optimality Theory. In M. Gonzlez (ed.),
Proceedings of the North East Linguistic Society 24. 46174.
(1995) Correspondence and identity constraints in two-level Optimality Theory. In J.
Camacho, L. Choueiri, and M. Watanabe (eds.), Proceedings of the West Coast
Conference on Formal Linguistics 14. 399 413.
(1996) Sign-Based Morphology and Phonology: with special attention to
Optimality Theory. PhD dissertation, University of California, Berkeley. [ROA-171,
http://ruccs.rutgers.edu/roa.html]
Orgun, C. Orhan and Ronald Sprouse (1997) From M-Parse to Control: deriving
ungrammaticality. Ms., University of California, Berkeley. [ROA-224,
http://ruccs.rutgers.edu/roa.html]
Orr, Carolyn (1962) Ecuador Quichua phonology. In B. Elson (ed.), Studies in Ecuadorian
Indian languages. Norman, Okla.: Summer Institute of Linguistics. 60 77.
Osborn, Henry (1966) Warao I: phonology and morphophonemics. International Journal
of American Linguistics 32. 108 23.
Padgett, Jaye (1995) Feature classes. In Beckman, Walsh Dickey, and Urbanczyk. 385 420.
Paradis, Carole (1988) On constraints and repair strategies. Linguistic Review 6. 7197.
Paradis, Carole and Franois Prunet (eds.) (1991) The special status of coronals: internal
and external evidence. San Diego: Academic Press.
Pater, Joe (1995) On the nonuniformity of weight-to-stress and stress preservation effects
in English. Ms., McGill University. [ROA-107, http://ruccs.rutgers.edu/roa.html]
(1996) *Nt. In K. Kusumoto (ed.), Proceedings of the North East Linguistic Society 26.
22739.
(forthcoming) Austronesian nasal substitution and other Nt effects. To appear in Kager,
Van der Hulst, and Zonneveld. [ROA-160, http://ruccs.rutgers.edu/roa.html]
Payne, David L. (1981) The phonology and morphology of Axininca Campa. Arlington:
Summer Institute of Linguistics Publications in Linguistics.
Pesetsky, David (1998) Some optimality principles of sentence pronunciation. In P.
Barbosa, D. Fox, P. Hagstrom, M. McGinnis, and D. Pesetsky (eds.), Is the best good
enough? Optimality and competition in syntax. Cambridge, Mass.: MIT Press. 33783.
439
References
Piggott, Glyne L. (1993) The geometry of sonorant features. Ms., McGill University,
Montreal.
(1995) Epenthesis and syllable weight. Natural Language and Linguistic Theory 13.
283326.
Popjes, Jack and Jo Popjes (1986) Canela-Krah. In D. C. Derbyshire and G. K. Pullum
(eds.), Handbook of Amazonian languages, I. Berlin: Mouton De Gruyter. 12899.
Poser, William (1989) The metrical foot in Diyari. Phonology 6. 117 48.
Prentice, D. J. (1971) The Murut languages of Sabah. Pacic Linguistics, series C, no. 18.
Canberra: Australian National University.
Prince, Alan (1980) A metrical theory for Estonian quantity. Linguistic Inquiry 11. 511 62.
(1983) Relating to the grid. Linguistic Inquiry 14. 19 100.
(1984) Phonology with tiers. In M. Aronoff and R. Oehrle (eds.), Language sound
structure. Cambridge, Mass.: MIT Press. 234 44.
(1990) Quantitative consequences of rhythmic organization. In M. Ziolkowski, M. Noske,
and K. Deaton (eds.), Papers from the Chicago Linguistic Society 26:2. 35598.
(1994) Optimality: constraint interaction in generative grammar. Handout of lectures at
Utrecht University, January 1994.
Prince, Alan and Paul Smolensky (1993) Optimality Theory: constraint interaction in
generative grammar. Ms., Rutgers University, New Brunswick and University of
Colorado, Boulder. [To appear as Technical report no. 2, Rutgers University Center
for Cognitive Science. Cambridge, Mass.: MIT Press.]
(1997) Optimality: from neural networks to universal grammar. Science 275.
1604 10.
Radford, Andrew (1997) Syntax: a minimalist introduction. Cambridge University Press.
Raffelsiefen, Renate (1996) Gaps in word formation. In U. Kleinhenz (ed.), Interfaces in
phonology. Studia Grammatica 41. Berlin: Akademie Verlag. 194 209.
Rehg, Kenneth L. and Damien G. Sohl (1981) Ponapean reference grammar. Honolulu:
University of Hawaii Press.
Reynolds, William T. (1994) Variation and phonological theory. PhD dissertation,
University of Pennsylvania, Philadelphia.
Riad, Tomas (1992) Structures in Germanic prosody: a diachronic study with special
reference to Nordic languages. PhD dissertation, Stockholm University.
Rice, Curtis (1992) Binarity and ternarity in metrical theory: parametric extensions. PhD
dissertation, University of Texas, Austin.
Rice, Keren (1993) A reexamination of the feature [sonorant]: the status of sonorant
obstruents. Language 69. 308 44.
Rizzi, Luigi (1991) Residual verb second and the Wh Criterion. Technical Reports in
Formal and Computational Linguistics 2. Facult des Lettres, University of Geneva.
Roca, Iggy (1994) Generative phonology. London and New York: Routledge.
(ed.) (1997) Constraints and derivations in phonology. Oxford University Press.
Rosenthall, Sam (1994) Vowel/glide alternation in a theory of constraint interaction.
PhD dissertation, University of Massachusetts, Amherst. [ROA-126,
http://ruccs.rutgers.edu/roa.html]
440
References
(1997) The distribution of prevocalic vowels. Natural Language and Linguistic Theory
15. 139 80.
Rumelhart, D. E. and J. L. McLelland (1986) On learning the past tenses of English.
In D. E. Rumelhart and J. L. McLelland (eds.), Parallel Distributed Processing:
explorations in the microstructure of cognition. Cambridge, Mass.: MIT Press.
216 71.
Russell, Kevin (1993) Morphemes as constraints: the case of copy-back reduplication. In
K. Beals, G. Cooke, D. Kathman, S. Kita, K.-E. McCullough, and D. Testen (eds.),
Papers from the Chicago Linguistic Society 29. 37589.
Sapir, Edward (1930) Southern Paiute, a Shoshonean language. Proceedings of the
American Academy of Arts and Sciences 65:13.
(1965) A grammar of Diola-Fogny. Cambridge University Press.
Schachter, Paul and Victoria Fromkin (1968) A phonology of Akan: Akuapem, Asante, and
Fante. Los Angeles: University of California.
Scobbie, James (1991) Attribute-value phonology. PhD dissertation, University of
Edinburgh.
Selkirk, Elisabeth O. (1980) The role of prosodic categories in English word stress.
Linguistic Inquiry 11. 563 605.
(1981) Epenthesis and degenerate syllables in Cairene Arabic. In H. Borer and J. Aoun
(eds.), Theoretical issues in the grammar of Semitic languages. Cambridge, Mass.:
Department of Linguistics and Philosophy, MIT.
(1984) Phonology and syntax: the relation between sound and structure. Cambridge,
Mass.: MIT Press.
(1986) On derived domains in sentence phonology. Phonology 3. 371 405.
(1995) The prosodic structure of function words. In Beckman, Walsh Dickey, and
Urbanczyk (eds.). 439 69.
Selkirk, Elisabeth and Tong Shen (1990) Prosodic domains in Shanghai Chinese. In
S. Inkelas and D. Zec (eds.), The phonology syntax connection. University of Chicago
Press. 31338.
Sezer, Engin (1981) The k / alternation in Turkish. In G. N. Clements (ed.),
Harvard studies in phonology. Bloomington: Indiana University Linguistics Club.
354 82.
Shaw, Patricia (1987) Non-conservation of melodic structure in reduplication. In A. Bosch,
B. Need, and E. Schiller (eds.), Papers from the Chicago Linguistic Society 23:2.
291306.
(1991) Ling 253: morphology. Handout of LSA Linguistic Institute 1991.
Sherer, Tim (1994) Prosodic phonotactics. PhD dissertation, University of Massachusetts,
Amherst. [ROA-54, http://ruccs.rutgers.edu/roa.html]
Sherrard, Nicholas (1997) Questions of priorities: an introductory overview of Optimality
Theory in phonology. In Roca. 4389.
Siegel, Dorothy (1974) Topics in English morphology. PhD dissertation, MIT.
Smith, Neilson V. (1973) The acquisition of phonology: a case study. Cambridge University
Press.
441
References
Smolensky, Paul (1993) Harmony, markedness, and phonological activity. Handout to talk
presented at Rutgers Optimality Workshop 1, 23 October 1993, New Brunswick,
N. J. [ROA-87, http://ruccs.rutgers.edu/roa.html]
(1995) On the internal structure of the constraint component Con of UG. Handout
to talk presented at University of California, Los Angeles, 7 April 1995. [ROA-86,
http://ruccs.rutgers.edu/roa.html]
(1996) On the comprehension/production dilemma in child language. Linguistic Inquiry
27. 720 31.
Sommer, Bruce (1981) The shape of Kunjen syllables. In D. L. Goyvaerts (ed.), Phonology
in the 1980s. Ghent: E. Story-Scientia.
Spaelti, Philip (1994) Weak edges and nal geminates in Swiss German. In M. Gonzlez
(ed.), Proceedings of the North East Linguistic Society 24. 57388.
Spencer, Andrew J. (1994) Syllabication in Chukchee. In R. Wiese (ed.), Recent
developments in Lexical Phonology. Theorie des Lexikons. Arbeiten des Sonder-
forschungsbereichs 282, No. 56. Dsseldorf: Heinrich Heine University. 20526.
Spring, Cari (1990) Implications of Axininca Campa for prosodic morphology and
reduplication. PhD dissertation, University of Arizona, Tucson.
Sprouse, Ronald (1997) A case for Enriched Inputs. Handout of a presentation at TREND,
3 May 1997. [ROA-193, http://ruccs.rutgers.edu/roa.html]
Stahlke, Herbert (1976) Segment sequences and segmental fusion. Studies in African
Linguistics 7. 44 63.
Stampe, David (1972) How I spent my summer vacation (a dissertation on Natural
Phonology). PhD dissertation, University of Chicago. [Published 1979, New York:
Garland.]
Steinbergs, Aleksandra (1985) The role of MSCs in OshiKwanyama loan phonology.
Studies in African Linguistics 16. 89 101.
Stemberger, Joseph P. (1991) Radical underspecication in language production.
Phonology 8. 73112.
Steriade, Donca (1982) Greek prosodies and the nature of syllabication. PhD dissertation,
MIT.
(1987) Redundant values. In A. Bosch, B. Need, and E. Schiller (eds.), Papers from the
Chicago Linguistic Society 23:2. 339 62.
(1988a) Reduplication and syllable transfer in Sanskrit and elsewhere. Phonology 5.
73155.
(1988b) Review of G. N. Clements and S. J. Keyser (1983). Language 64. 118 29.
(1993) Closure, release, and nasal contours. In Huffman and Krakow. 40170.
(1995a) Underspecication and markedness. In Goldsmith (1995). 114 74.
(1995b) Positional neutralization. Ms., University of California, Los Angeles.
(1996) Paradigm uniformity and the phoneticsphonology boundary. Paper presented at
the 5th Conference in Laboratory Phonology, Evanston, Illinois, July 1996.
Stonham, John (1990) Current issues in morphological theory. PhD dissertation, Stanford
University.
442
References
Street, Chester S. and Gregory Panpawa Mollinjin (1981) The phonology of Murinbata. In
B. Waters (ed.), Australian phonologies: collected papers. Work Papers of SIL-AAB,
A5. Darwin: Summer Institute of Linguistics.
Tesar, Bruce (1995) Computational Optimality Theory. PhD dissertation, University of
Colorado, Boulder.
(1996) An iterative strategy for learning metrical stress in Optimality Theory. In
E. Hughes, M. Hughes, and A. Greenhill (eds.), The proceedings of the 21st annual
Boston University Conference on Language Development, November 1996. 61526.
[ROA-177, http://ruccs.rutgers.edu/roa.html]
Tesar, Bruce and Paul Smolensky (1993) The learnability of Optimality Theory: an
algorithm and some basic complexity results. Technical Report CU-CS-678-93,
Computer Science Department, University of Colorado, Boulder. [ROA-2,
http://ruccs.rutgers.edu/roa.html]
(1998) Learnability in Optimality Theory. Linguistic Inquiry 29. 229 68.
Trigo, R. Lorenza (1993) The inherent structure of nasal segments. In Huffman and
Krakow. 369 400.
Trommelen, Mieke and Wim Zonneveld (1979) Inleiding in de Generatieve Fonologie.
Muiderberg: Coutinho.
Trubetzkoy, Nicolai S. (1939) Grundzge der Phonologie. Travaux du Cercle Linguistique
de Prague 7. [English translation: Principles of phonology. Berkeley and Los Angeles:
University of California Press, 1969.]
Uhrbach, Amy (1987) A formal analysis of reduplication and its interaction with
phonological and morphological processes. PhD dissertation, University of Texas,
Austin.
Urbanczyk, Suzanne (1996) Morphological templates in reduplication. In K. Kusumoto
(ed.), Proceedings of the North East Linguistic Society 26. 425 40.
(forthcoming) Double reduplications in parallel. To appear in Kager, van der Hulst, and
Zonneveld. [ROA-73, http://ruccs.rutgers.edu/roa.html]
Vance, Timothy J. (1987) An introduction to Japanese phonology. Albany, N.Y.: SUNY
Press.
Vijver, Ruben van de (1998) The iambic issue: iambs as a result of constraint interaction.
HIL dissertations 37. Leiden: Holland Institute of Generative Linguistics.
Vogel, Irene (1976) Nasals and nasal assimilation patterns, in the acquisition of Chicano
Spanish. Papers and Reports on Child Language Development 15. 20114.
Walther, Markus (1996) ot simple: a construction-kit approach to Optimality
Theory implementation. Ms., Heinrich Heine University, Dusseldorf. [ROA-152,
http://ruccs.rutgers.edu/roa.html]
Wexler, Kenneth and Peter W. Culicover (1980) Formal principles of language acquisition.
Cambridge, Mass.: MIT Press.
Whitney, William D. (1889) Sanskrit grammar. Cambridge, Mass.: Harvard University Press.
Wilbur, Ronnie (1973) The phonology of reduplication. PhD dissertation, University of
Illinois, Urbana-Champaign.
443
References
444
INDEX OF LANGUAGES
445
Index of languages
Oromo 3801, 385, 389, 390 Tepehuan, Southeastern 177 88
OshiKwanyama 836, 87 Timugon Murut 2249, 255
Oykangand 95, 255 Toba Batak 81
Tongan 175 7
Paiute, Southern 2447 Totonac 97
Pangasinan 255 6 Tunica 94, 97, 3734, 375, 378
Pintupi 144, 145, 1645, 188, 192, 300 1, 302, Turkish 373, 374, 3767, 3823, 386, 3879,
303, 308, 312 390 1
Piro 168, 170
Polish 347
Venda 79
Ponapean 93, 133 4, 136, 137, 138
Quechua, Puyu Pungo 801, 84, 85, 87 Warao 144, 145, 164
Wargamay 191
Samoan 203, 204, 205, 212, 224 Warlpiri 192
Sanskrit 197, 21315, 216, 217, 251 Washo 2312
Sedang 97 Weri 144
Sibutu Sama 144
Spanish 79, 97, 294
Yidi 145, 196
Swahili 79
Yokuts 58, 97, 104, 379, 41011
Tagalog 121 4, 141, 197
Temiar 93 Zoque 80
446
INDEX OF SUBJECTS
447
Index of subjects
deletion 67 language acquisition 1, 296, 3367
consonant deletion 134, 380 learnability 296
vowel deletion (see syncope) of serial grammar 186, 2867
derivation 57 8, 1857, 238, 280 of lexical representations 322, 329, 334
derivational theory 57 8 of OT grammar 2967, 407
derived environment effect 75 of output representations 322
distinctive feature 3, 36, 71, 127, 408 lexical representation 33, 413, 415
do-only-when-necessary (see economy) lexicon 19, 32 4, 415
domination 13 Lexicon Optimization 323, 32930, 334,
strict domination 223, 344, 400, 405 414
Duplication Problem 56, 84, 381 licensing 409 11
linguistic theory 13
economy 21, 74, 104 7, 343, 357 goals of 1
emergence of the unmarked 130, 206 7, Local Conjunction 392400
209 10, 21516, 222
epenthesis 68, 98 100, 124 5 Mark Cancellation 306
consonant epenthesis 105 Mark-Data pairs 304
vowel epenthesis 106, 112, 126, 133, 287 markedness 2 3, 45, 44
subminimal epenthesis 144, 166 markedness constraint 910 (see also Index of
Evaluator (Eval) 19, 205 constraints)
extrametricality 149, 166 context-free markedness constraint 28, 125
extraprosodicity 124 context-sensitive markedness constraint
28, 125
markedness scales 44
factorial typology 35, 171, 239, 366, 412
metathesis 63
faithfulness 5 6, 10, 55, 74, 200, 211, 414
Minimalism 343
faithfulness constraint 10, 14, 200, 350
Morpheme Structure Constraint 20, 56
positional faithfulness 407 13
morphology 3, 19, 115, 194, 274
root faithfulness 76
morphological category (constituent) 118 19
fallacy of perfection 16
morphological constraint 122, 21718
foot 142, 145, 147
morphological edge 75, 115, 135
foot distribution (parsing) 1625, 16770
morphological feature 282
foot well-formedness 161, 172 4
morphological rule (process, operation) 197,
free variation (see optionality)
223 4, 262, 273, 282
Freedom of Analysis 20, 25, 535, 344, 417
morphological truncation (see truncation)
functional motivation 6 7, 10, 421
morphologically related 263, 2812, 415
functionally related processes 56, 87, 139, 177
morphology-phonology interface 25, 118,
122 4, 197, 2235, 262
Generative Grammar 1, 296
Generator (Gen) 19, 20, 545, 204, 303, neutralization 14, 29, 30, 36
3457 complete neutralization 36
grammar 1, 8, 422 positional neutralization 389, 4078
components of 19
structure of 18 21, 382 opacity 3724
grammatical word 118, 152, 166 optimality 1213
grounding of constraints 5, 11, 61, 94, 144, 241, Optimality Theory
381, 408 and goals of linguistic theory 34
basic ideas of 3 4, 8 13
harmony 3, 8 9, 1617, 151, 344 comparison with derivational (rule-based)
harmony scale 44, 409 theory 52 8, 86 8, 1389, 187 8,
237 8, 262, 273, 285 7
identity (see base identity and reduplicant) optionality 4047
implicational universal 93 4 output 3, 8, 1213, 56, 58, 87, 401, 404, 420
inxation 121 4, 2245 nonunique output 405
input 8, 1920, 33, 57 8, 322, 324, 344 5, output candidate 20
378 81, 413 14 candidate set 8, 257
intermediate levels 57 8, 280, 376, 3815 faithfulness to (see Sympathy)
448
Index of subjects
output constraint (see constraint) reduplicative template (see template)
output-to-output correspondence total reduplication 195, 205
(see correspondence) rewrite rule (see rule)
overapplication Richness of the Base 19, 29, 31, 34, 414
in opacity 373 rule 523
in reduplication 1989, 2338 optional (see optionality)
in stem-based afxation 274 6 rewrite rule 1, 53
rule ordering 1, 57
paradigm 415 18 counterbleeding 375
paradigmatic relation 287 counterfeeding 375
paradigm uniformity 6, 257 structural change of 53
parallelism 25 structural description of 53
in reduplication 2447 rule-based theory 523
of base identity and faithfulness 292 comparison with OT (see Optimality Theory)
of evaluation of candidates 55
of morphology and prosody 122 3, segment inventory 434
225, 227 stem-based afxation 273 4
of prosodic levels 188 9 Basic Model 275
parameter 2, 296, 3412 structural change of rule (see rule)
Persistent Rule Theory 56 structural description of rule (see rule)
phonetics 5, 11, 61, 408, 421 2 Structuralism 2, 422
phonetic grounding (see grounding) syllable 917
phonology 5 6 coda 91, 94, 96, 130
autosegmental phonology 138 9 nucleus 91
Declarative Phonology 12 onset 91, 93, 96
Generative Phonology 2, 52, 413 syllable template 98
Harmonic Phonology 4, 382 syllable weight 147, 155
Lexical Phonology 2, 262, 277, 382 Sympathy 38792
metrical phonology 142, 1467 syncope 177 8, 278
Natural Phonology 2 syntax 2, 341, 3447
positional faithfulness (see faithfulness) syntactic constraint 34852
positional neutralization (see neutralization)
positive evidence 302 tableau 13
Principles-and-Parameters Theory 2, 3, 296, 341 template 217
prosodic circumscription 2245, 229 classical template 21617
prosodic morphology 217, 230 decomposition of 21819
prosody Generalized Template 218, 220
prosodic categories 119, 146 reduplicative template 196, 230
prosodic head 146, 167 truncation template 2645
prosodic hierarchy 146 violability of template 227, 230
prosodic word 111, 136, 146, 220 1 truncation 259, 265
Basic Model 263
quantity-sensitivity 145 6, 1715 truncation template (see template)
typology 1, 11, 34
Recursive Ranking 308, 311 of structural changes 645, 78
robustness of 31719
reduplicant 194, 201, 202 underapplication
constraint on 218, 220, 227 in opacity 374
identity with base 1989 in reduplication 198, 240 4
shape invariance of 195 6, 199 in stem-based afxation 27885
unmarkedness of 196 8, 199 in truncation 2601
reduplication 194 5 Underlying Representation (see lexical
as inxation 203, 212, 2249 representation)
as prexation 195, 202, 212 underspecication 33, 70, 127, 209, 398,
as sufxation 202, 212 4201
Basic Model 201 ungrammaticality 3, 23
partial reduplication 195, 205, 222 absolute ungrammaticality 4003
449
Index of subjects
Universal Grammar 1 well-formedness
universality 12, 18 output-based nature of 878
two-level well-formedness 378 81
violation (see constraint violation) well-formedness constraint 93, 104
450
INDEX OF CONSTRAINTS
451
Index of constraints
*VoralN 28 Uneven-Iamb 151
*VwV 245 Weight-by-Position 147, 269
*r] 260 WSP 155, 172
*[ 241 WSP-Ft 184
*[W 245
-Tensing 275 Various phonological constraints
Coda-Cond 131 *Struc 404
Cor-high 128 Harmony-IO 378
Harmony 410 Fill 99
Hiatus-raising 394 Lowering-IO 379
Inter-V-Voice 325 MParse 402
No [a] 283 Parse 100
No [i] 284 -Projection 380
OCP 56
PostVcls 241 Alignment constraints
Reduce 406 Align-L 111
VOP (Voiced Obstruent Prohibition) Align-Morph-L 115, 136
40, 340, 398 Align-R 113, 290
VOP 2 398 Align-Red-L 226
Align-Stem-R 119
Prosodic markedness constraints Align-Syllable-R 119
*Clash 165 Align-um-L 122
*Complex (cover constraint) 288 Align-Wd-Left 169
*ComplexCod 97 Align-Wd-Right 169
*ComplexOns 97 All-Ft-Left 157, 163, 300
*Final-C- 268 All-Ft-Right 163, 300
*3 268 Edgemost 122, 167
* 283 GrWd=PrWd 152, 166
Final-C 377 Leftmost 167, 300
Ft-Bin 156, 161, 184, 300 Red=Stem 220
Ft-Form (cover constraint) 184 Red= 227
HNuc 215 Red= 182, 217
No-Coda 94, 112 Rightmost 167, 300
[NoCoda & VOP]Segment 399 Stem=PrWd 220, 264
NonFinality 151, 165 Trunc= 265, 271
Onset 93, 110
Parse-Syl 153, 162, 300 Syntactic constraints
Quant-Form (cover constraint) 271 Economy of Movement (Stay) 351
Rh-Contour 174, 184 Full-Interpretation (Full-Int) 352
RhType=I 172, 184 No Movement of a Lexical Head
RhType=T 172 (No-Lex-Mvt) 352
Son-Seq 267, 288 ObligatoryHeads (Ob-Hd) 349
Stress-to-Weight 268 Operator in Specier (Op-Spec) 354
Syll-Form (cover constraint) 288 Subject 354
452