Boethius On The Supreme Good PDF
Boethius On The Supreme Good PDF
Since in every kind of being there is a supreme possible good, and since man too is a certain
species or kind of being, there must be a supreme possible good for man, not a good which
is supreme in the absolute sense, but one that is supreme for man. The goods which are
accessible to man are limited and do not extend to infinity. By means of reason we will seek
to determine what the supreme good is which is accessible to man.
The supreme good for man should be his in terms of his highest power, and not accord-
ing to the vegetative soul, which is also found in plants, nor according to the sensitive
soul, which is also found in animals and from which their sensual pleasures arise. But mans
highest power is his reason and intellect. For this is the supreme director of human life
both in the order of speculation and in the order of action. Therefore, the supreme good
attainable by man must be his by means of his intellect. Therefore, men who are so weighed
down by sense pleasures that they lose intellectual goods should grieve. For they never attain
their supreme good. It is insofar as they are given to the senses that they do not seek
that which is the good of the intellect itself. Against these the Philosopher protests, saying:
Woe to you men who are numbered among beasts and who do not attend to that which
is divine within you!1 He calls the intellect that which is divine in man. For if there is
anything divine in man, it is right for it to be the intellect. Just as that which is best among
all beings is divine, so also that which is best in man we call divine.
Moreover, one power of the human intellect is speculative and the other is practical. This
is clear from this fact, that man theorizes concerning certain objects of which he is not the
active cause, e.g., eternal things, and about others he acts under the direction of the intel-
lect in choosing some fitting means whenever any human act is in question. From this, then,
we know that these two intellectual powers are present in man. But the supreme good acces-
sible to man in terms of the power of his speculative intellect is knowledge of what is true
and delight in the same. For knowledge of what is true gives delight. An intelligible object
gives delight to the one who knows it. And the more wondrous and noble the intelligible
1 M. Grabmann, Die Opuscula De Summo Bono sive De Vita Philosophi und De Sompniis des Boetius
von Dacien, Mittelalterliches Geistesleben, II (1936), 20024: 209, n. 18, notes that this statement cannot
be found in the writings of Aristotle.
MP_C43.qxd 11/23/06 2:41 AM Page 354
354
PRACTICAL PHILOSOPHY
object and the greater the power of the apprehending intellect to perfectly comprehend,
the greater the intellectual delight. One who has tasted such delight spurns every lesser
pleasure, such as that of sense. The latter is, in truth, less, and is more base. And the man
who chooses such pleasure is, because of that pleasure, more base than one who chooses
the former.
It is because of this, because the object known gives delight to the one who knows, that
the Philosopher [Aristotle] in Book XII of the Metaphysics maintains that the first intellect
enjoys the most pleasurable life.2 For since the first intellect is the most powerful in under-
standing and the object which it knows is the noblest, its essence itself for what nobler
object can the divine intellect have than the divine essence? therefore, it has the life of
greatest delight. No greater good can befall man in terms of his speculative intellect than
knowledge of the universality of beings, which come from the first principle and, by means
of this, knowledge of the first principle insofar as such is possible, and delight in it. Therefore,
our conclusion above follows: that the supreme good accessible to man by means of his
speculative intellect is knowledge of what is true in individual cases, and delight in the same.
Likewise, the supreme good accessible to man in terms of his practical intellect is the doing
of good, and delight in the same. For what greater good can befall man in terms of his
practical intellect than to choose the fitting means in human action and to delight therein?
For no man is just unless he takes delight in acts of justice. The same must be said of the
acts of the other moral virtues. From what has been said one can evidently conclude that
the supreme good open to man is to know the true, to do the good, and to delight in both.
And because the highest good possible for man is happiness, it follows that human
happiness consists in knowing the true, doing the good, and taking delight in both. The
military profession is prescribed in a state by the lawmaker for this reason, that when
enemies have been expelled, citizens may devote themselves to intellectual virtues in con-
templating the true, and to moral virtues in doing good, and thus live a happy life. For the
happy life consists in these two. This then is a greater good, which man can receive from
God and which God can give to man in this life. With reason does a man desire a long life
who desires it for this, to become more perfect in this good. He who shares more perfectly
in that happiness which reason tells us is possible for man in this life draws closer to that
happiness which we expect in the life to come on the authority of faith. And since so great
a good is possible for man, as has been said, it is right for all human action to be directed
toward that good, so as to attain it. For just as all actions as regards a certain law are right
and proper when they tend toward the end of the law, and better the more closely they
approach the end of the law, while actions which are opposed to the end of the law or which
are weak or indifferent without either being opposed to the end of the law or in accord with
it, while all such actions sin against the law to a greater or lesser degree as is clear from what
has been said, the same is true in man himself. All designs and deliberations, all actions and
desires of man which tend to this supreme good which is accessible to man according to the
above, these are right and proper. When man so acts, he acts in accord with nature. For he
acts for the sake of the supreme good, to which he is ordered by nature. And when he so
acts he is properly ordered. For then he is ordered to his best and his ultimate end. But all
actions of man which are not ordered to this good, or which are not such as to render man
stronger and better disposed for actions which are ordered to this good, all such actions in
man are sin.
355
356
PRACTICAL PHILOSOPHY
of the value of beings. This delight is greater than that of sense. Therefore, he despises sense
pleasures. But many sins and vices consist in excessive sense pleasure. Thirdly, because there
is no sin in understanding and theorizing. There is no possibility of excess and of sin in the
order of supreme goods. But the action of the philosopher is such a contemplation of truth.
Therefore, it is easier for the philosopher to be virtuous than for another. So it is that the
philosopher lives as man was born to live, and according to the natural order.
Since in him the lower powers and their operations are for the sake of the higher powers
and their operations, and all taken together for the highest power and that highest action,
which is contemplation of truth and delight in the same, above all, the first truth, the desire
to know will never be satisfied until the uncreated being is known. As the Commentator
says, all men naturally desire to know about the divine intellect.
Desire for any knowable object is a kind of desire for the first knowable object. This is
the proof. The closer beings are to the first knowable being, the more we desire to know
them and the more we delight in thinking of them.
Therefore, by studying the caused beings which are in the world and their natures and
relationships to one another, the philosopher is led to consider the highest causes of things.
For a knowledge of effects leads to a knowledge of the cause. And in noting that higher causes
and their natures are such that they must have another cause, he is led to a knowledge of
the first cause. And because there is pleasure in speculative knowledge, and all the more so
the nobler the object known, the philosopher leads a life of very great pleasure. The philo-
sopher also knows and observes that it is necessary for this cause to be its own cause of being,
that is to say, not to have another cause. For if there were nothing in the universe which
was not caused by another, then there would be nothing at all. He also notes that this cause
must be eternal and unchangeable, always remaining the same. For if it were not eternal
then nothing whatsoever would be eternal. And again, since certain things in the world have
begun to be, and since one being which begins to be cannot be a sufficient cause of another
being which begins to be, as is evident, it clearly follows that all things in this world which
begin to be must derive from an eternal cause. This cause is also unchangeable and always
remains the same. For change is possible only in imperfect things. And if there is some most
perfect being in the universe, it is right for this to be the first cause. The philosopher also
notes that the entire being of the universe, with the exception of this first cause itself, must
come from it and thus, that this first cause is the cause which produces beings and orders
them to one another and maintains them in existence certain ones in terms of their
individual identity and without any kind of change (as the separated substances); certain ones
according to their individual identity, but as subject to change (as the heavenly bodies); and
certain ones in terms of their species alone (as those which are below the heavenly orbit,
such as the lowest levels of beings). He also notes that just as all things derive from this first
cause, so too, all things are ordered to it. For that being is the beginning of all things, the
end of all things, and that through which all things are joined to their end, that being is
the first being according to the philosophers and God the Blessed according to the holy
men. Nevertheless, in this order there is great range. Those beings which are closest to the
first principle are nobler and more perfect. Those which are farther removed from the first
principle are lower and less perfect.
This first principle is to this world as the father of a family is to his household, as a com-
mander to his army, and as the common good to the state. Just as the army is one because
of the unity of its commander, and just as the good of the army is essentially in the com-
mander and in others in terms of their relationship to him, so too, from the unity of this
MP_C43.qxd 11/23/06 2:41 AM Page 357
357