Alexander An - Pr. 1.1-7 PDF
Alexander An - Pr. 1.1-7 PDF
Aphrodisias
On Aristotle Prior
Analytics 1.1-7
Translated by
Jonathan Barnes, Susanne Bozien,
Kevin Flannery S. J.,
Katerina lerodiakonou
B L O O M S B U R Y
LONDON NEW DELHI NEW YORK SYDNEY
Bloomsbury Academic
An imprint of Bloomsbury Publishing Pic
www.bloomsbury.com
Jonathan Barnes, Susanne Bobzien, Kevin Flannery and Katerina lerodiakonou, 1991
The translators have asserted their right under the Copyright, Designs and
Patents Act, 1988, to be identified as Author of this work.
Acknowledgements
The present translations have been made possible by generous and imaginative funding
from the following resources: the National Endowment for the Humanities, Division of
Research Programs, an independent federal agency of the USA; the LeverhulmeTrust;
the British Academy; the Jowett Copyright Trustees; the Royal Society (UK); Centra
Internazionale A. Beltrame di Storia della Spazio e delTempo (Padua); Mario Mignucci;
Liverpool University.The editor is grateful to Ian Crystal and Paul Opperman for their help
in preparing the volumes for press.
Preface vii
Introduction 1
Alexander of Aphrodisias 1
Commentaries 4
Alexander, On the Prior Analytics 7
The translation 14
Logical terminology 17
Translation 35
1. Preface 41
2. Introductory explanations 53
3. Conversions 83
4. The First Figure 101
5. The Second Figure 138
6. The Third Figure 166
7. Further reflections 184
Oxford JB
August 1990 SB
KF
KI
Introduction
Alexander of Aphrodisias
Alexander addressed his essay On Fate to the Emperors Septimius
Severus and Caracalla. The address dates the work between the
years 198 and 209 AD.1 Alexander explains that in the essay he will
present and discuss Aristotle's views on fate and human freedom;
for
1
2 Introduction
Alexander 'of Aphrodisias', but more than one town went by that
name and it is at best a reasonable conjecture that he was born in
the rich and flourishing Aphrodisias in Caria.5 As for his personal
features and foibles, we learn nothing - unless we may believe that
he was 'lean and pale'.6
His teachers included Sosigenes and Herminus - whom he
criticises at some length in his commentary on the Prior Analytics.1
We know little about these scholars. Their pupil emerged as a
learned philosopher; but we cannot tell to what extent and in what
ways the pupil's ideas were shaped and formed by his teachers.
His writings contain critical and polemical passages, many of
them directed against the Stoics.8 It is easy to suppose that he was a
controversialist, engaged in living dispute with his contemporaries.
There is indeed evidence that he broke a lance or two with Galen,
his senior by some years and a leading intellectual figure of the day.9
Yet it may be suspected that some, at least, of Alexander's attacks
were bookish - delivered in the calm of the study or the lecture-room
against dead or hypothetical opponents.10
Bookish he certainly was. A dozen major works survive, in
addition to several collections of shorter pieces. And much more has
been lost than survives. Although Alexander did not rival the
productive energy of Galen, his collected works would have occupied
an impressive amount of shelf space.11 Moreover, they had some
influence:12 on his contemporaries (such as Galen), on the later
Greek philosophers (on Plotinus13 and on the Neoplatonic
commentators), and also on Arabic philosophy.14
5
On Aphrodisias see e.g. Reynolds. The name 'Alexander' is found on Aphrodisian
inscriptions (e.g. Monumenta Asiae Minoris Antigua VIII 414, 574); but it is an
extremely common name.
6
See [Alexander], in Metaph. 531,25-6 (cf. 532,7-19) -but this part of in Metaph. is
not from Alexander's own feather.
7
See Moraux (1973/84), II, pp. 335-60 (Sosigenes) and pp. 361-98 (Herminus). On
the controversial figure of Aristotle of Mytilene see Moraux (1973/84), II, pp. 399-425;
Accattino; Goulet, pp. 411-12; and esp. Thillet, pp. XI-XIX.
8
See Todd (1976); Sharpies (1987), p. 1178.
9
For the evidence see esp. Thillet, pp. XXXII-XLIX; cf. von Muller, pp. 424-5;
Pines; Zimmermann, p. Ixxxi n. 2; Nutton (1984), pp. 318-24; Nutton (1987), pp.
45-51; Sharpies (1987), p. 1179.
10
The evidence for living and contemporary debate in Alexander's school is sifted
by Sharpies (1990), pp. 90-2,104-10.
11
For a general characterization and a full catalogue see Sharpies (1987), pp.
1179-99; cf. Thillet, pp. LII-LXXIII; Goulet, pp. 128-39.
12
See, in general, Cranz, pp. 79-82; Sharpies (1987), pp. 1220-4.
13
See Porphyry, Vit. Plot. 14; and the Index Fontium to the Henry-Schwyzer
edition of Plotinus. Note that Eusebius cites Alexander (Fat.) at PE VI ix.
14
See esp. Maroth. Many of Alexander's writings were translated into Arabic, and
some have survived only in their Arabic versions: see Badawi (1987), pp. 109-14;
Strohmaier; Sharpies (1987), pp. 1187-8, 1192-4. For Alexander's influence on
mediaeval thought see Ebbesen (1981b), (1982), (1990).
Introduction 3
15
In philosophy, he was thoroughly Aristotelian. Indeed, his
philosophical activity can be roughly characterised as an attempt to
organise and present a comprehensive, consistent and contemporary
Aristotelianism. This being so, it is unsurprising to discover that
much of his writing took the form of commentaries on Aristotle's
works; and although there is a substantial body of material, always in
Aristotelian vein, which is less closely tied to the words and works of
the Master, the Aristotelian commentaries constitute the core of his
philosophical achievement.
He wrote commentaries on all the constituent works of Aristotle's
Organon or logical corpus: the commentaries on the Categories, On
Interpretation, Prior Analytics 2, Posterior Analytics,16 and the
Sophistical Refutations11 are lost. But in addition to the work on
Prior Analytics 1, we possess a substantial commentary on the
Topics.18 There were also independent books on logical matters: an
essay on the conversion of propositions,19 and an essay on utterances,
both preserved in Arabic versions;20 several brief discussions on
questions to do with the concept of possibility, found among the
so-called Quaestiones and closely related to Alexander's interest in
determinism;21 a lost essay on hypothetical syllogistic;22 a one-
volume work on syllogisms with modally mixed premisses, and some
Scholia Logica or Logical Notes, both referred to in the commentary
on the Prior Analytics and both lost.23
The chronology of Alexander's writings cannot be established.24
The only absolute date is given by the opening of On Fate - and even
that is not precise. For the internal or relative chronology, we must
rely on occasional cross-references. Thus we know that the essay on
conversions, and perhaps the commentary on the Topics, were
15
For a sketch see Donini, pp. 220-48; Sharpies (1987), pp. 1199-220; the account
in Zeller, III i, pp. 817-31, is still worth reading.
16
For fragments, testimonies and discussion see Moraux (1979).
17
The commentary preserved under his name and published in CAG II 3 is a much
later work: see Ebbesen (1981a), I, pp. 242-4; Sharpies (1987), p. 1184.
18
Edited by Wallies in CAG II2.
19
Arabic text in Badawi (1971); referred to below by 'Alexander, Conu.'.
20
See Sharpies (1987), p. 1193. An Arabic source refers to a second, shorter,
commentary on Are. Pr.: see Badawi (1987), p. 113.
21
See Sharpies (1982), (1983).
22
Known to Avicenna: see Mardth, pp. 7,139.
23
For the peri mixeon see in An. Pr. 125,30; 127,16; 207,35; 213,26; 238,37; 249,38
(cf. Philoponus, in An. Pr. 126,20-3); for the Scholia see 250,2 (cf. Sharpies (1987),
p. 1196). Zeller, III i, p. 820 n. 2, asserts that the reference to the Scholia Logica at in
An. Pr. 250,2 is a later gloss; but he offers no reason for this opinion. Perhaps there
was also an essay on affirmations: see our note to in An. Pr. 36,6 below. Note also the
indeterminate cross-references at in An. Pr. 188,16; 191,17; 284,17; 390,9; and the
prolepticreferences atinAn. Pr. 70,20; 110,20; 193,21; 328,6.
24
See Sharpies (1987), p. 1181.
4 Introduction
written after the commentary on the Prior Analytics;25 and we know
that the commentary on the Prior Analytics had itself been preceded
by two shorter writings on logical matters. Such results are meagre
and unsatisfying. But in any case, chronological questions are
probably of little significance.26 For the commentaries presumably
represent the substance of Alexander's lectures on Aristotle;27 the
lectures were presumably delivered year in year out; and the passing
years presumably brought revisions of various sorts. In such circum-
stances it makes little sense to speak of a relative chronology: in a
way, we might rather suppose that Alexander wrote his commen-
taries concurrently, and perhaps over a decade or more.
Commentaries
Numerous ancient commentaries on Aristotle have survived. And
many more have perished. Alexander's commentaries are, by
general consent, among the best: modern scholars praise him - and
so did some of the ancients.28 But he was not the first in the field: on
the contrary, he was writing in a tradition already some centuries
old.
Aristotle's immediate successors, Theophrastus and Eudemus,
wrote on the same subjects as their master had done; and, to some
extent at least, they conceived of their task as correcting, expanding
and completing Aristotle's work.29 Their works can no doubt be
26
See Conu. p. 60; in Top. 7,11. (But note that cross-references in the
commentaries are primarily concerned with the order in which the readers or the
audience will read or hear the works - they do not necessarily provide evidence for
the order of composition.)
26
The same may be said for the chronology of some of Aristotle's writings: see e.g.
Barnes (1981).
27
But note the doubts expressed by Sharpies (1990), p. 97.
28
See e.g. Simplicius, in Phys. 80,15-16; 795,33-5; in DA 52,27-8. It is regularly
asserted that Alexander was later known simply and honorifically as 'The
Commentator'. The passages adduced to support this claim include: Simplicius, in
Phys. 707,33; 1170,13; 1176,32; Philoponus, in An. Pr. 126,21; Olympiodorus, in
Meteor. 263,21. In all these texts Alexander is indeed referred to by phrases such as
'the commentator' or 'Aristotle's commentator'; but these phrases are not honorific
titles - they are ordinary referring expressions. (If, at the end of a book review, you
read The author deserves our thanks', you will rightly take this for praise - but you
will not think that the author has been honoured as The Author par excellence.)
Alexander is also said to have been called 'the second Aristotle'; but the two relevant
texts ('Ellas' [i.e. David], in Cat. 128,13; Syrianus, in Metaph. 100,6) are peculiarly
difficult (and 'Elias' is certainly corrupt): for opposing views see Moraux (1973/84), II,
p. 401; Thillet, pp. XX-XXXI. Note, too, that Alexander was often criticised (e.g.
Plutarch of Athens, apud Philoponus, in DA. 21,20-3; Philoponus, in An. Post.
111,31-112,6) and sometimes accused of bias (e.g. 'Elias', in Cat. 123,4-8).
29
See Boethius' comment on Theophrastus at in Int. ed. sec. 12,3-16; cf. Barnes
(1985a) for an attempt to reconstruct one such Theophrastean supplement.
Introduction 5
30
called interpretations or exegeses of Aristotle, in a loose sense; but
there is no reason to believe that they wrote commentaries on his
writings;31 and it seems unlikely that any Aristotelian work
received a commentary before the renascence of Aristotelian studies
in the late first century BC.32 By then the tradition of literary
commentaries, which had been consolidated in Alexandria in the
third century BC,33 was well established, and the hupomnema or
commentary was a recognised genre.34 There were already
commentaries on scientific texts - namely, on the medical writings
in the Hippocratic corpus.35 Perhaps, too, there were commentaries
on philosophical texts, and in particular on Platonic texts. According
to Proclus, Grantor was 'the first interpreter of Plato';36 and whether
or not Proclus means that Grantor wrote commentaries on Plato,37 it
is likely that such commentaries were written during Grantor's
life-time - for two papyri dating from the third century BC preserve
small fragments of what seems to have been a commentary on the
Phaedo.38 The earliest philosophical commentary of which we can
form any general impression is the anonymous commentary on the
Theaetetus, partly preserved on papyrus.39 The papyrus itself is
dated to the first century AD, but the text it contains may go back to
30
Compare the way in which later Epicureans interpreted the works of their
master: see esp. Sedley; Puglia.
31
Pace Geffcken, pp. 406-7: Geffcken's study is a useful survey of the antecedents
of philosophical commentaries; but he fails to distinguish essays in interpretation
from commentaries proper.
32
On this renascence see most recently Moraux (1973/84), I, pp. 1-94; Gottschalk
(1987), pp. 1083-97.
33
See e.g. Pfeiffer, pp. 210-33; Fraser, pp. 447-79; Turner, pp. 112-24; and esp. del
Fabbro, who gives lucid accounts of the forms and varieties of early commentaries
(pp. 70-2; 93-5), of commentatorial style (pp. 97-100), and of the sorts of topics which a
commentary standardly covered (pp. 106-23).
34
For the history of the term see e.g. Bomer.
35
See Fraser, pp. 363-7. Our MSS of Galen ascribe a commentary on Hippocrates'
Aphorisms to Herophilus (in Hipp. Aph. XVIIIA 186-7K); but the text should be
emended to ascribe the commentary to Herophilus' pupil, Bacchius: see now von
Staden, pp. 75-6.
36
See in Tim. I 75,30-76,10 (cf. II 276,31-277,14).
37
See most recently Dorrie, pp. 328-38. The use of the word exegesis does not in
itself imply a commentary: thus we should not suppose that the pleistoi ... hosoi
exegentai the book of Heraclitus, and who included the shadowy Antisthenes (not,
pace Geffcken, p. 399, the celebrated Antisthenes but the Herakleiteios mentioned at
Diogenes Laertius, VI19) and Heraclides of Pontus (Diogenes Laertius, IX 15), wrote
commentaries (even though Heraclides' work was entitled Herakleitou exegeseis:
Diogenes Laertius, V 88).
38
Namely PMon 91 [Carlini (1986), pp. 10-14] and PHeid 28 [Carlini (1978), pp.
201-9]; see also Carlini (1975).
39
See Diels-Schubart; Praechter (1909b) (a new text is being prepared for the
Corpus dei Papiri Filosofici). Note that the anonymus had also written commentaries
on the Timaeus (XXXV 10-12), on the Phaedo (XLVIII 7-11), and on the Symposium
(LXX10-12).
6 Introduction
40
the first century BC. There are scattered references to other
commentatorial activity on Platonic texts.41
The earliest surviving commentary on Aristotle is Aspasius'
commentary on the Nicomachean Ethics.42 Aspasius was a gener-
ation senior to Alexander. Earlier Peripatetics had written earlier
commentaries: Andronicus, Boethus and Ariston in the first century
BC; Sotion, Apollonius, Achaicus and Alexander of Aegae in the first
century AD.43 Of these scholars, Boethus and Ariston are known to
have written about syllogistic;44 and Boethus had indeed proposed
substantial modifications to Aristotle's theories.45 But it is not
explicitly said that they wrote commentaries on the Prior Analytics.
Sotion wrote a commentary on the Topics; and a papyrus preserves
part of a commentary on the Topics dating from the first century AD.46
Contemporary with Aspasius were Adrastus, who was perhaps
Alexander's compatriot,47 and Alexander's teachers, of whom Hermi-
nus almost certainly had written a commentary on the Prior
Analytics.48 In addition, thinkers outside the Peripatetic school had
addressed themselves to Aristotelian logic; and the two earliest
logical handbooks to have survived Galen's Introduction to
40
So Tarrant; but see Glucker (1989).
41
See e.g. Diogenes Laertius, III 65-6; POxy 1609 (a reference to a commentary on
the Timaeus); Suetonius, apud Eustathius, in Od. I 107; Porphyry, Vit. Plot. 14;
Proclus, in Rep. II 96. On Albinus' commentaries see Diels-Schubart, pp.
XXVIII-XXX; on Adrastus' commentary on the Timaeus see Moraux (1973/84), II, pp.
296-313; on Posidonius' alleged commentary on the Timaeus see Kidd, pp. 338-40 (on
PGen 203 see Burkert (1987)). In general see Gudeman, cols. 687-91; Untersteiner,
pp. 205-22; Dillon, pp. 54-7; Westerink (1976), I, pp. 7-19.
42
Edited by Heylbut in CAG XIX1 (see Mercken; cf. Goulet, pp. 635-6).
43
See esp. Moraux (1973/84), I, pp. 97-142 (Andronicus), 143-80 (Boethus), 181-96
(Ariston); II, pp. 211-14 (Sotion), 216-17 (Apollonius), 217-21 (Achaicus), 222-5
(Alexander of Aegae); also Moraux (1986b); Gottschalk (1987), pp. 1097-121 (who also
refers to Platonists, such as Eudorus, and to Stoics, such as Athenodorus, who
discussed but did not compose commentaries upon Aristotle's logical ideas).
44
For Ariston see esp. Mariotti, pp. 59-74.
46
Notably in his thesis that all categorical syllogisms are 'perfect': Themistius,
Max. 190-1; Ammonius, in An. Pr. 31,11-32,7; scholiast to Aristotle, 156b43-157b9
(see our note to 23,14 below). Note too Boethus' claim that hypothetical syllogistic is
prior to categorical: Galen, Inst. Log. vii 2.
46
PFayum 3: see Moraux (1973/84), I, pp. 215-16.
47
For his presence in the surviving commentary on Books II-V of EN (edited by
Heylbut in CAG XX) see Moraux (1973/84), II, pp. 323-30; Gottschalk (1987), p. 1155;
Mercken; Goulet, pp. 56-7. Note too the fragmentary commentary on GC preserved in
'Ocellus Lucanus', 20-35: the date of this work is uncertain, but it may be as early as
the first century BC (see Moraux (1973/84), II, p. 606; (1986b), pp. 133-4).
48
For commentaries on An. Pr. see also Ebbesen (1981b); Lee, pp. 9-12, 36, 128.
(POxy 3320 may possibly come from an early commentary on An. Pr.) For early
commentaries on Cat. see Galen, Lib. Prop. XIX 42K; Simplicius, in Cat. 1,3-2,29;
159,23-33 (cf. Moraux (1973/84), II, pp. 519-27; Gottschalk (1987), pp. 1101-12); for
commentaries on de Int. see Zimmermann, pp. Ixxx-xcii.
Introduction 1
49 50
Dialectic and the On Interpretation ascribed to Apuleius both
contain accounts of Peripatetic syllogistic.51
Alexander thus had at his disposal a wealth of scholarly work on
Aristotelian logic in general and on the Prior Analytics in particular;
and at least some of this work had been expressed in the form of
commentaries. Alexander rarely names his predecessors.52 But it is
clear from his own commentary that he was thoroughly familiar with
their work. It is clear, too, that the tradition had produced interpreta-
tions of considerable detail and ingenuity. And it is clear that the
tradition was not uniform or univocal: Alexander reports deviant
interpretations; and he also reports the views of logicians who wished
to modify or even reject some parts of Aristotle's logical system.
Alexander's commentary was influential in its turn. Two later
commentaries on the Prior Analytics survive: one, truncated, by
Ammonius,53 and the other by Ammonius' pupil, John Philoponus.54
Ammonius and Philoponus were intimate with Alexander's work,
and each draws upon it. Indeed, there are substantial passages in
Philoponus' commentary which paraphrase, with or without acknow-
ledgment, the corresponding passages in Alexander's work. The two
later commentators were Platonists, and they did not share
Alexander's general philosophical stance. But their differences from
Alexander in matters of logic were relatively trifling; and their
commentaries provide us with interesting, and sometimes illuminat-
ing, parallels to Alexander's discussion.55
Alexander, On the Prior Analytics
The later commentators were conservative creatures. They worked
to a standard form; and they borrowed shamelessly - or perhaps
49
Note also Galen's commentaries on An. Pr., An. Post, and Cat.: Lib. Prop. XIX
47K (see Moraux (1973/84), II, pp. 688-91).
50
For the latest surveys of the long-standing controversy over the authorship of
this work see Hijmans, pp. 408-11; J.-M. Flamand, in Goulet, pp. 298-317.
51
Note also the brief description in Albinus, Didasc. 158-64H.
52
In the first part of in An. Pr. Herminus is the only commentator named (72,27;
89,34; 91,21); but note the several anonymous references to exegetes and critics of
Aristotle: 20,31; 23,3; 65,18; 68,21; 75,11; 81,17; 95,29; 100,17. Sometimes other
evidence allows us to name these people (see e.g. our note to 95,29; and compare in
An. Pr. 125,3-6 with [Ammonius], in An. Pr. 39,31).
53
Edited by Wallies in CAGIV 6.
54
Edited by Wallies in CAG XIII 2: the commentary was taken from Ammonius'
seminars on An. Pr. There is also an Armenian version of David's commentary on An.
Pr., and a fragment of the commentary by Elias (see Westerink (1961)). We perhaps
have references to lost commentaries by Porphyry (see Ammonius, in An. Pr. 31,15),
lamblichus (Philoponus, in An. Pr. 26,5), Themistius ([Ammonius], in An. Pr. 39,2),
Syrianus ([Ammonius], in An. Pr. 39,2), Eutocius (Elias, in An. Pr. 134 Westerink),
Proclus ([Ammonius], in An. Pr. 43,30-1), Marinus (Leo Magentinus: Ebbesen
(1981b), p. 10). For Byzantine commentaries see Benakis.
55
On the substantial issues see Lee, passim. We draw attention to the more
interesting parallels in our notes to the translation.
8 Introduction
reverentially - from their predecessors.56 Moreover, they had
reflected upon the obligations and duties of a commentator, and they
had established certain canons of procedure.57 Earlier scholars had
also thought about the matter. Thus Galen:
The translation
Book 1 of the Prior Analytics divides into three main sections: first,
in 1.1-7, Aristotle introduces his syllogistic theory and expounds the
non-modal syllogisms; then, in 1.8-22, he discusses modal
syllogisms; and thirdly, in 1.23-46, he offers a loosely organized
series of metalogical observations. The first part can sensibly be
read on its own; for, apart from the discussion of modal conversions
in 1.3, it is entirely self-contained. Alexander's commentary also,
and unsurprisingly, divides into three parts. This translation is of
the first part - that is to say, the commentary on 1.1-7. This
accounts for about one third of the total bulk of Alexander's work.
We have endeavoured to do Alexander into plain and intelligible
English. Our readers, we suppose, will be primarily interested in the
history of logic and in Aristotelian syllogistic; and the translation is
designed for such readers. It will be of little interest to anyone
whose main concern is with Alexander's prose style - not that such
people are common.
Our English is sometimes clumsy or ambiguous or obscure. In
principle these failings are deliberate: they reflect failings in
Alexander's Greek, failings which an English reader should be
aware of. We have not, however, attempted to match Alexander's
stylistic inelegancies with analogous inelegancies of our own: mere
bad writing - as opposed to bad thinking - has been effaced. (But we
have no doubt introduced some bad writing of our own.) In
particular, we have consciously striven to break down Alexander's
long and contorted periods into ordinary English sentences. This
betrays Alexander's style, but it does service to his argument. And
Alexander's style merits no loyalty.
We have added a few things of our own. Occasionally we have
interpolated numerals to indicate the division of an argument into
its parts. These numerals have no counterpart in the Greek, and we
have added them only where the train of thought seemed
78
See in An. Pr. 8,19-29.
Introduction 15
disagreeably obscure without them. The Chapter and Section
headings are also our addition. They too have no counterpart in the
Greek, which is broken only by the Aristotelian lemmata.79 But they
should not be misleading; and they may serve any reader who
wishes to scan through the pages looking for matters of particular
interest - and also any hardened spirit who may determine to read
the book from cover to cover.
As far as vocabulary is concerned, we have not affected a rigorous
purism. Different Greek words are often given the same English
translation if they are synonyms or used synonymously. Conversely,
a single Greek word will get different English renderings if it is
ambiguous - or even if normal English idiom requires or suggests a
variation. (It should be unnecessary to state these elementary
principles of translation; but in recent years a foolish purism, based
on a false conception of fidelity, has become fashionable.) Where
logical terminology is involved, we have, however, been a little more
scrupulous. Here we have allowed ourselves a few barbarisms; for
here it is - or it may be - important to know that Alexander used the
same word in this sentence as in that. The next section of the
Introduction says something about Alexander's logical terminology
and our attempts to translate it. The Greek-English Index and the
English-Greek Glossary offer a more extensive view of our linguistic
decisions.
It will surprise some readers that we have altogether avoided
logical symbolism. There is a temptation to employ modern logical
notation (or at least the standard symbols deployed in modern
treatments of Aristotle's syllogistic) in the translation, or at any rate
in the notes. For symbolism is both concise and precise. But
Alexander himself was no symbolic logician. Like Aristotle, he uses
a technical and semi-technical vocabulary. But he writes in Greek,
and the 'mathematical' aspect of modern logic is entirely foreign to
him (as indeed it is to Aristotle himself).80 Hence (and also for other
reasons) we have dispensed altogether with symbols. We write 'A
holds of every B' rather than 'AaB'. We write 'If P, then Q' rather
than'P-^Q'.
The annotations are mere notes: they do not, and are not intended
to, amount to a commentary (or metacommentary). They are of five
kinds. (1) They provide precise references and cross-references to
ancient texts which Alexander cites or alludes to. Where Alexander
simply remarks "X says' (or 'I have said'), we pedantically supply the
appropriate numbers. Sometimes Alexander's allusions are covert
79
On our treatment of the lemmata see below, p. 17.
80
Alexander follows Aristotle in using letters (A, B, C; M, N, O; P, R, S) to express
syllogistic forms; but these letters are not variables in the modern sense (see note to
53,30).
16 Introduction
(for he knew Aristotle and Plato backwards and his language often
echoes them): we have sometimes made such allusions explicit - but
we cannot pretend to have hunted all of them down. (2) The notes
also record parallel passages in other ancient texts: in Alexander's
other works; in the later commentaries of Ammonius and
Philoponus; and occasionally in other authors. These records, again,
make no claim to completeness; rather, they suggest starting-points
to anyone who wishes to look further into the ancient history of the
issues which Alexander discusses. (3) There are references to the
modern literature. This literature is not in fact vast; for Alexander's
logic has not been a favourite topic among modern scholars. Even so,
there is more than we have looked at, and our notes are selective. (4)
From time to time, Alexander's arguments appear to us to be
obscure and difficult to follow. In such cases we have provided a
paraphrase: some of the paraphrases are no more than tentative
attempts to articulate one possible interpretation of a puzzling text;
and although we have (of course) picked the interpretation which we
think is least bad, we do not suppose that our interpretation is the
only interpretation worth considering. (5) Finally, there are some
textual notes - but they require a fresh paragraph.
The only critical edition of Alexander's commentary on the Prior
Analytics is the text published by Maximilian Wallies in volume II1
of the Berlin series of Commentaria in Aristotelem Graeca. Wallies
relied mainly on three manuscripts (BLM) and on the early Aldine
edition, which he took to represent an inferior manuscript tradition.
There are several manuscripts which Wallies did not consult; and
some of those which he did consult he consulted briskly: a full
critical edition of the commentary would have demanded far more
time than the Berlin Academy allowed its editors.81 And a properly
scholarly edition is yet to be done. (We have looked idly at a few
pages in a late Florentine manuscript;82 this has, unsurprisingly,
brought only one small improvement to Wallies' text - and Wallies'
error was perhaps due to a minor lapse at the proof-reading stage.83)
We have ventured to depart from Wallies' text at some eighty
places. The departures are signalled in notes of the fifth sort.
81
For an enthusiastic account of the origins and the progress of CAG see Usener,
pp. 199-202. Wallies signed the Preface to in An. Pr. on 1 September 1883: the Berlin
Academy had given its formal approval to the CAG project on 9 May 1878.
82
Laurent LXXII11, which Wallies calls C.
83
At 17,4 Wallies prints e en tei entolei e en tei klesei; and his critical apparatus
records no variants. Laurent LXXII 11 has e en tei erotesei after entolei. It is likely
that this is the correct text (for it is hard to imagine a scribe's being moved to
interpolate the words). But we should not infer that the Laurentian MS uniquely
preserves Alexander's text. In fact, the same text is printed in the Aldine edition; and
we suspect that the words in question are to be found in all the MSS - they have been
lost from Wallies' text by some nineteenth-century oversight.
Introduction 17
(These textual notes are collected in Appendix 3.)
As a matter of fact, Alexander's text seems to be in pretty good
order; and we do not suppose that a new critical edition would often
differ substantially from Wallies. But there is one point where
some uncertainty might be felt. It concerns the lemmata or snippets
of Aristotelian text which punctuate the commentary. There are two
problems here. First, the lemmata run to different lengths in
different manuscripts: it seems likely that different copyists (or their
paymasters) chose to copy more or less of the Aristotelian text; and it
is not clear that we know how extensive the lemmata were in
Alexander's own copy of his commentary. Secondly, the proper
wording of the lemmata is sometimes a matter of doubt. Alexander's
text of the Prior Analytics often differs (usually in trifling particulars)
from more recent texts;84 and copyists would sometimes take their
lemmata from a manuscript of Aristotle rather than from the
manuscript of Alexander which they were reproducing. (This is
proved by the fact that the text of a lemma will sometimes disagree
with the text cited in the course of the commentary.85) Thus we
cannot always be sure that the text which we read in the lemmata
was the text which Alexander himself had before him.
In the translation we have adopted the following policy: in every
case, we have translated all of the lemma which Wallies prints; but
we have often continued the citations beyond the text in Wallies, and
we have occasionally interpolated new lemmata on our own ini-
tiative. All such additions are clearly marked, being enclosed by
angle brackets. They are made, solely for the convenience of the
modern reader, when Alexander's subsequent comments bear speci-
fically on a part of the text which does not appear in the lemma which
Wallies prints.
Logical terminology86
Alexander had at his service a rich and developed logical
84
See notes to Appendix 1.
85
There is a trivial example of this in the part of in An. Pr, which we have
translated: at Are. Pr. 26al5 our texts of Aristotle read ontos te, and so does the lemma
at in An. Pr. 58,24 (except that the Aldine edition prints tou for te); when Alexander
cites the same line of Aristotle in the body of the commentary, he writes ontos ge
(58,9: the manuscripts havege, the Aldine has nothing - and Wallies prints te). For a
more interesting case compare in An. Pr. 282,14-15 (the lemma, agreeing with our
text of Aristotle) with 283,3 (and 284,20.29), which cites a variant text. Note that the
lemmata in the Aldine edition have often (but not invariably) been written to fit the
current text of Aristotle (e.g. 9,4; 13,27; 23,20 - further references in the notes to
Appendix 1).
86
The Greek-English Index contains references to discussions in this section.
18 Introduction
87
vocabulary. Many of his Greek terms are difficult to translate; and
any translation is certain to break some of the semantic connexions
which link the different Greek terms. In this section we survey
Alexander's logical vocabulary, stating and sometimes explaining
our choice of translation. We do not discuss every word which might
be deemed logical in a broad sense of the term; and we are primarily
interested in Alexander's syllogistic vocabulary.88 The section is
written as a continuous narrative: we begin with a few terms of very
general application; then we turn to arguments and syllogisms;
thirdly, we deal with words connected with propositions and their
interrelations; and finally we discuss the terminology for the parts
and internal structure of propositions.89
Alexander insists that the logician should attend not to words but
to what words mean;90 nonetheless, the objects of his study are, of
course, essentially expressed in words: phone, which we normally
translate 'word' and lexis, which is normally 'expression', pick out
parts of language - words, phrases or sentences. These linguistic
items have a semantic force - they mean something.
Alexander's semantic repertoire includes the following words:
semainein (with semantikos and the associated semeion); deloun
(with delotikos); menuein (and menutikos); endeiknunai. It is
initially tempting to suppose that these different words must have
different senses, and so to establish different English versions for
them. But there is no evidence of any subtle semantic distinctions
among the words, whether in Alexander or in any other Greek
author. (Greek philosophers were scarcely interested in theories of
meaning; Greek grammarians did not develop any semantic
theory.91) Accordingly, we have been content to use 'mean' as a
standard translation for the first three of these four verbs. For the
fourth, endeiknunai, we do reserve a special translation, 'indicate';
but we do so only because the word is used elsewhere in a technical
sense, and an English reader might be interested to see how
Alexander uses it in a non-technical way. (In addition, the four verbs
may have a slightly different meaning in certain contexts. Thus
deloun means 'make delos or clear';92 and 'make clear' may
87
Little work has been done on Alexander's style and language; but see Todd
(1974).
88
For a brief account of syllogistic see Appendix 2.
89
But a desire to group together words from the same stem has occasionally
interfered with this general scheme. 90 See 84,15-19 and note.
91
The grammarian Apollonius Dyscolus has an extensive semantic vocabulary (see
e.g. the opening section of Conj.); but he makes no systematic distinctions among the
words he uses, all of which can usually be translated by the one word 'mean'.
92
'Clear' is always delos: 'obvious' renders enargSs, 'plain' gives saphes, and
'evident' translates phaneros. The Greek words are in fact synonyms. But it is useful
to signal occurrences of phaneros, since the word has a vital role in the account of
Introduction 19
sometimes carry the sense not of 'mean', i.e. 'make clear in
language', but rather of 'betoken' or 'show'. Similarly, menuein may
be 'mark'; andsemainein is sometimes 'signify'.)
Two different lexeis may be said isodunamein or ison dunasthai
they may be equal in power or capacity to one another. We have
used the English 'equivalent' for this. (The etymology of'equivalent'
is exactly that of isodunamos.) A modern philosopher will ask
whether isodunamein amounts to synonymy (sameness of meaning),
or whether some weaker equivalence is intended.93 The question
cannot be answered: the important distinction between synonymy
and logical equivalence seems not to have been observed by any
ancient logician.
Lexis comes from legein, which is one of several verbs we translate
by 'say'. (Sometimes 'mean' is better, and we have used it.) Legein
also breeds logos, a word often cited as a paradigm of the
untranslatable. It is true that no one English word will pick out the
range of meaning of logos. But that does not make logos a puzzling,
let alone a metaphysically exciting, term. The central idea is
perfectly simple: a logos is what you say. There is no noun in English
which means precisely 'what is said'. We have followed custom and
taken 'account' as our normal rendering. But there are contexts in
which this translation would be pointlessly misleading: first, the
logos in question is sometimes an argument; and secondly, it is
sometimes a mere utterance. In these cases the word logos does not
mean 'argument' or 'utterance'. But clarity and the exigencies of
English demand that we translate logos by 'argument' or by
'utterance'. Sometimes a translator should be content to preserve
reference and let sense go.
Logoi which are arguments are the subject of Aristotle's work. The
kind of argument with which he is concerned in the Prior Analytics
is taken by Alexander to be a species ofpistis.9* Apistis is a way of
warranting or justifying something; and we use 'justification' for
pistis, with 'justify' and 'justified' for the cognate verbs (pisteuein,
pistousthai) and adjective (pistos). (The adjective pistos sometimes
rather has the force of 'justifiable', 'warrantable'. More generally, to
call something pistos is sometimes to say that you are entitled to
believe it. But in the commentary 'justified' will normally do, and we
have stuck by it.)
Arguments yield conclusions. Alexander most often says that an
argument sunagei its conclusion. We translate sunagein by
'perfect' syllogisms.
93
Note that there are also very weak uses of the word: e.g. Philoponus, in An. Pr.
63,12; 98,6 (cf. Ammonius, in Int. 114,22-3; 122,20-26; 246,9; 257,30-258,4; and note
Apuleius,/ret 181,6).
94
See 43,11 note.
20 Introduction
'deduce'. ('Infer' would do as well, but we keep this for another verb,
epipherein, where it is used as a synonym for sunagein.) A sunagoge
is a deducing or, more naturally, a deduction; and we use
'deduction'.
An argument will also perainein, or more often sumperainein,
something. We use 'conclude' for both verbs. And the noun,
sumperasma, is 'conclusion'. The conclusion hepetai or akolouthei
the premisses: we use 'follow (from)' for both verbs - which both
carry the spatial and temporal sense of 'follow' (i.e. 'come after') in
non-logical contexts. Akolouthia is the cognate noun: there is no
good English noun from 'follow', so we use 'implication' for
akolouthia and lose the transparency of its connexion with
akolouthein.
The arguments in which Alexander is interested can be
systematized or subsumed under general rules: there is a methodos
- a method - in their case; and they contrast in some passages with
arguments said amethodosperainein, to conclude unmethodically.
An argument, or an arguer, may establish and prove, or refute
and disprove. 'Disprove' gives diaballein and 'refute' elenkhein?5
(An elenkhos is a refutation.) 'Establish' is kataskeuazein. Trove' is
normally deiknunai - and the associated noun, deixis, comes out as
'proof. In ordinary Greek, deiknunai means, quite generally, 'show';
and in some Alexandrian contexts it is clear that 'show', rather than
the more specific 'prove', is required. You might use 'show'
throughout for deiknunai; but then, since 'show' has no appropriate
noun, the connexion between deixis and deiknunai, self-evident in
Greek, will be lost in the English version. Hence we use both 'prove'
and 'show' for deiknunai, as the context suggests. (In using 'prove'
we are again attending to the reference rather than to the sense of
the Greek verb.) The adjective deiktikos is sometimes 'probative';
but it is more often paraphrased by way of'prove'.96
Apodeiknunai always has the specific sense of'prove' rather than
the generic sense of 'show'. Since we have arrogated 'prove' for
deiknunai, we take 'demonstrate' for apodeiknunai. The translation
is well established in the tradition. 'Demonstration' and 'demon-
strative' are used for the cognates apodeixis and apodeiktikos. An
argument may be demonstrative, in which case it is an argument
which functions as a proof and it stands in contrast to dialectical or
sophistical (dialektikos, sophistikos) arguments.97 Again, Alexander
frequently speaks of demonstrating an argument, i.e. of proving it to
95
But where Greek idiom uses elenkhein English will sometimes demand 'prove'
rather than 'refute': elenkhein to asullogiston is 'to prove to be non-syllogistic'.
96
There is an odd Aristotelian use of the adjective which Alexander explains at
112,13-16 (cf. in An. Pr. 256,11-14).
97
See 7,8 note.
Introduction 21
be valid. By contrast, certain arguments, which are taken as basic,
are called anapodeiktoi. We translate this by 'indemonstrable'. The
word was used by the Stoics of the basic arguments in their logical
system, and it is generally supposed that the Peripatetics came to
adopt the Stoic terminology. We are told that the Stoics used the
word anapodeiktos in the sense of 'not needing demonstration';98
and it is likely that it should be construed in the same way in
Alexander. But 'indemonstrable' is established as the orthodox
translation in Stoic texts; and in any case there is no convenient
alternative.
The special sort ofpisteis to which the Prior Analytics is devoted
are called sullogismoi. Some translators of Aristotle render the word
as 'deduction' - in the sense in which deductions contrast with
inductions. There is much to be said for the rendering. (Aristotle,
and Alexander after him, contrasts sullogismoi with epagogai or
inductions.99) But there is also one fatal objection: Alexander,
following Aristotle, recognizes the existence of deductive arguments
which are not sullogismoi. This point is not a casual aside: it is
central to Alexander's understanding of sullogismoi.100 Hence we
prefer to align ourselves with an older practice, and to transliterate
rather than translate: sullogismoi are syllogisms.
The noun carries a verb, sullogizesthai. The word 'syllogize' is
ugly, but it exists. Similarly, sullogistikos is 'syllogistic'. But note
that 'syllogistic' in Alexander has two different uses. First, and
generally, it means 'concerned with syllogisms', so that syllogistic is
the science of syllogisms - just as arithmetic is the science of
arithmoi or numbers. (Sullogistike in effect means 'logic', and is
more or less synonymous with logike and dialektike. But note that in
some authors and contexts these three terms are sharply distinct.)
Secondly, Alexander will regularly describe a pair of premisses as
syllogistic: in this sense, to say of something that it is syllogistic is to
say that it can syllogize something, i.e. to say that it will yield a
conclusion by a syllogism.101 'Non-syllogistic' or asullogistos is the
opposite of'syllogistic' in this second use. A synonym of asullogistos
is adokimos, 'unreliable'.
Some syllogisms are teleioi or 'perfect' (in the sense of 'complete',
'lacking nothing1): the term is technical - roughly speaking, it picks
out a class of syllogisms which are basic inasmuch as their validity
is evident. Other syllogisms are ateleis or imperfect. These can,
98
See e.g. Sextus, PHII156; Af VIII 223; Galen, Inst. Log. viii 1; cf. Frede (1974a),
pp. 127-9.
99
And also with 'paradigms',paradeigmata: see 43,11 note.
100
See Barnes (1990a).
101
Note too the technical term huposullogistikos, which we give as 'subsyl-
logisticaP.
22 Introduction
however, be perfected - the verb is teleioun or epitelein. To perfect a
syllogism is in effect to prove it valid: Alexander also uses
apodeiknunai in these contexts, as we have already noted; and like
Aristotle he will speak of analysing or reducing an imperfect
syllogism into or to a perfect syllogism.
'Analyse' translates - or rather transliterates - analuein. There is
a cognate noun, analusis; and an adjective, analutikos, from which
Aristotle's work took its title. Alexander has a short essay on the
notion of analusis.102
'Reduce' represents both anagein and apagein; and 'reduction' is
anagoge or apagoge (the latter noun being by far the more common,
and always occurring in the phrase 'reduction to the impossible'). In
some texts there may be a difference between anagein and apagein;
but we discern none in Alexander and hence do not scruple to use a
single English word.
There are various ways in which syllogisms may be perfected,
analysed, or reduced; each of them involves certain operations - to
which we shall return - on the syllogism or on its component parts.
For a syllogism is a compound item - it is composed of a
conclusion and a pair of premisses. Each of these three components
is a proposition. Where the word 'proposition' occurs in our
translation it represents protasis. (Andproteinein, the cognate verb,
comes out as 'propound'.) A proposition is not a linguistic item nor
yet a psychological event - it is neither a sentence nor an uttering of
a sentence. Rather, it is what you propound when you utter a
sentence of a certain sort. Alexander notes103 that the word protasis
also has a more specific sense: it is used for a premiss of an
argument i.e. it refers specifically to what you propound when you
put forward propositions from which a conclusion is to be deduced.
For this sense of protasis we reserve the word 'premiss'. It is not
always clear when protasis means 'premiss' rather than 'proposi-
tion'; and sometimes our translation depends on the toss of a coin.
But since both 'proposition' and 'premiss' are exclusively used for
protasis, the reader will always know when the Greek text presents
the word protasis .104
Propositions, orprotaseis in the general sense, are true (or false),
alethes (orpseudes). Equivalently, they 'hold' (huparkhein) or fail to
102 103
See 7,11-33 and notes. See 44,19-21.
104
One particular point deserves notice. Alexander frequently speaks of pairs of
protaseis from which no syllogistic conclusion can be deduced. It is natural to suppose
that in such passages protasis means 'proposition' rather than 'premiss'; for it is odd
to speak of premisses which generate no conclusion. Nonetheless, it emerges that in
Alexander's view these protaseis are indeed premisses - premisses which yield now
one conclusion and now another (see above, pp. 12-13). Hence we have supposed that
'premiss' is the correct translation in all these texts.
Introduction 23
hold. The verb huparkhein is also used with two argument-places,
when the arguments are terms rather than propositions. For A
huparkhei toi B we say 'A holds of B'.105 (A huparkhei toi B, or A
holds of B, just in case A is truly predicated of B. Animal holds of
man: man is an animal.)106 Again, propositions (whether true or
false) are either simple or complex. Alexander occasionally mentions
complex propositions, for which his general name is 'hypothetical
(hupothetikos) proposition'.107 Thus he sometimes refers to
conditionals (sunemmena), which the Peripatetics called 'conti-
nuous' (sunekhe), and to disjunctions (diezeugmena), which the
Peripatetics called 'disjoint' (diairetika). But Aristotelian syllogisms
contain only simple propositions, and we may forget about complex
propositions. From now on, when we refer to propositions we shall
have non-complex propositions in mind.
Alongside protasis, in the general sense, we find apophansis. We
use 'assertion' for apophansis, 'assert' for apophainein, 'assertoric'
for apophantikos. Alexander makes a technical distinction between
& protasis and an apophansis, which our English terms do not well
reflect. But the distinction is explained in the text;108 and in any
case, apophansis is rare in the commentary, while apophainein is
normally used as a mere synonym for legein, 'say".109
Protaseis in the special sense, or premisses, come in pairs. A pair
of propositions is called a suzugia or a sumploke: etymologically, the
words mean 'co-yoking' and 'co-weaving1. We use 'combination' for
the first expression and 'conjunction' for the second.
The word protasis is only one of several devices by dint of which
Alexander refers to the premisses of an argument. Two verbs are
widely used - and each has several compound forms.
First, an arguer will lambanein a proposition. The verb is the
normal Greek word for 'take'; and in many contexts (especially when
it is terms which you must lambanein) this is how we translate it.
But in the case of'taking' a proposition, we need a word to express to
lambanomenon or to lephthen, 'what is taken'; and there is no
suitable noun from 'take'. The right noun for the passive participle
seems to be 'assumption'. (We have also used 'assumption' for the
105
huparkhein in this usage is normally translated as "belong to'; but 'belong to' has
no advantage over 'hold of, and it disguises the connexion with the one-place use of
huparkhein.
106
huparxis is 'existence', and is thus distinguished from hupostasis or
'subsistence': in Alexander there seems to be no difference in sense between the two
words; but the distinction is important in some Stoic contexts. On huparkhousa see
below, p. 30.
107
See esp. in An. Pr. 256,12-14 (cf. 258,24; 261,25-6; in Top. 2,6; Ammonius, in Int.
3,7-15); see e.g. Volait, pp. 24-7.
108
See 10,17 and note.
109
'Statement' at 1,19 represents axioma; elsewhere in Alexander this ambiguous
word is 'axiom'.
24 Introduction
noun lemma and - once - for the abstract noun lepsis, which is
usually paraphrased.) Hence it seems sensible to use 'assume' for
the verb when its object is a proposition or premiss.
Lambanein a proposition is sometimes contrasted with erotan, to
request, a proposition. Dialectical arguers must 'request', i.e. they
may argue from P only if an interlocutor 'grants' (didonai) a request
(erotesis) or gives an affirmative answer to the question 'P?'.
Demonstrative reasoners on the other hand are not thus dependent
on an interlocutor - they should simply 'take', without asking, what
appears to be true. But this contrast between lambanein and erotan
is not always present in Alexander: in particular, when he uses the
word 'assumption' he does not usually have demonstrative
syllogisms specifically in mind.
Of several compounds of lambanein, the most important are
proslambanein, metalambanein and paralambanein. Proslam-
banein is used as a term of art. (We also find proslepsis and
aprosleptos.) It applies specifically to the assumption of the second
premiss of a syllogism: you assume one premiss; and then you
assume in addition, or 'co-assume', a second. We translate
'co-assume'; and proslepsis is 'co-assumption'.
Metalambanein is once used in a technical sense as a synonym for
proslambanein: we there use 're-assume'.110 Normally the word
(which has a cognate noun metalepsis) means 'take ... instead of...':
we sometimes use 'transform' and sometimes paraphrase.
(Paralambanein does not seem to be technical. Alexander uses it
of introducing material - a term or a proposition - into a given
context. And so 'introduce' is apposite enough.)
The second verb is tithenai. Its general meaning is 'put' or 'place'.
It, its cognates, and its compounds are widely used by Alexander in
technical and semi-technical senses. You may tithenai a proposition,
and in particular you may tithenai a proposition as a premiss for an
argument. Here we use 'posit': the verb is unattractive (and its
normal English overtones are inapposite); but nothing preferable
presents itself. We use 'posit', the noun, for to tethen or to tithemenon
(passive participles). The abstract noun thesis, cognate with
tithenai, is normally used in connexion with terms rather than with
propositions. Here too we sometimes use 'posit' - but we also use
'position' and paraphrase.111
In normal Greek, keisthai ('lie') is often used as a perfect passive
of tithenai. For it we use 'be supposed', thus preserving a link with
'posit'. The participle, to keimenon, is frequently applied to what has
been posited or what is supposed - i.e. to a putative premiss; hence
110
See 19,5 and note.
111
On the thesis of terms, and the related notion of taxis ('order' or 'ranking'), see
47,22 note.
Introduction 25
'supposition'. (The verb also has other, less technical, uses.)
There are five important compounds oftithenai, four of which it
seems best to discuss here, although they are not directly connected
to the concept of a proposition or a premiss.112
Alexander commonly uses paratithenai and parathesis in connex-
ion with the production of specific concrete terms, especially of terms
designed to provide counterexamples to a putative syllogism.113 We
use 'set down' for this verb.
Protithenai and prothesis connote a putting forward; what you
protithes is what you aim at or purpose. For example, Alexander will
explain the prothesis of the Prior Analytics, i.e. what Aristotle
intends or purposes to do in the work. We normally use 'purpose' or
'propose'; but the words are not technical, and we have chosen
different renderings as idiom suggests. There is, however, one
semi-technical use of the verb - or rather of the associated passive
verb and participle, prokeisthai and prokeimenon. In the context of a
syllogism, to prokeimenon is, as it were, what the syllogism or the
syllogizer is aiming at: it is the putative conclusion of the syllogism. If
you say to yourself'I want to find an argument to show X', then X is to
prokeimenon. We have found no simple word for to prokeimenon in
this usage: we generally make do with the clumsy paraphrase 'the
point at issue'.
Hupotithenai and hupokeisthai have three distinct uses. First, to
hupokeimenon is regularly the subject-term of a proposition - it is, as
it were, what 'lies under' or 'is placed under' the predicate. For this
use we keep the traditional word 'subject'; and for the verb: 'be subject
for'. Secondly, the verbs, and also the associated noun hupothesis, are
often used in the context of a particular type of argument, namely a
reductio. In a reductio you make a hupothesis and then show that
something absurd or impossible follows. As a result of this you reject
the hupothesis and thereby establish its negation.114 Here we
transliterate^ with the tradition, to 'hypothesis' and 'hypothesize'.
Thirdly - and relatively rarely - Alexander will use hupokeisthai of
the premisses of an argument. Here it is a synonym ofkeisthai, and
we translate 'suppose', thereby obliterating the distinction between
the compound and the simple verb.
Finally there is ektithenai, ekthesis and ekkeisthai. The words are
not uncommon in a non-technical sense, where they denote the
setting out of a term or a proposition or a problem. And we use 'set
out'. But there is also an important technical usage (but not, strictly
speaking, a technical sense): one of the methods of analysing or
112
For the fifth, antitithenai, see below, p. 26.
113
See below, p. 30.
114
See 24,18 note.
26 Introduction
reducing a syllogism employs what Aristotle calls ekthesis.115 We
retain 'set out' for the verbs in this usage. The translation is
adequate. But there is no corresponding noun; hence for ekthesis in
this usage we have adopted the traditional Latinism 'exposition'.
Propositions stand in a variety of relations to one another. If two
propositions are both true, they are said to be true together with one
another (sunaletheuein)116 or to hold at the same time as one
another (sunuparkhein). Again, there is akolouthia, the relation of
following or implication, which we have already mentioned.117 One
proposition may yield another by akolouthia, and it may also
anairein it. X anairei Y when the truth of X determines the falsity of
Y. The verb literally means 'destroy'; but 'destroy' is too dramatic a
metaphor in English, and we prefer 'cancel'. (But when the verb has
a personal subject we use 'reject'; for then 'destruction' is simply
denial.) Similarly for the cognates anairesis, anairetikos; and for the
compound sunanairein. If X destroys Y and Y destroys X, then X and
Y 'fight', makhontai: they conflict, we shall say (and there is a
conflict, makhe, between them). More soberly - and more frequently
- they are said to be opposed, antikeisthai.
We normally translate antitithenai, antikeisthai, antithesis and
antikeimenon by 'oppose', 'be opposed', 'opposition' and 'opposite': X
and Y are opposed when they conflict, i.e. when they cannot both
hold at the same time. There are different varieties of opposition. In
particular, there is a distinction between enantia ('contraries') on
the one hand and items which are opposed antiphatikos
('contradictorily') on the other. X and Y are opposed antiphatikos
just in case X and Y cannot both hold at the same time and also
cannot both fail to hold at the same time. (For example, and most
obviously, a proposition and its explicit negation are contradictorily
opposed.) If X and Y are opposed antiphatikos, then they are or form
an antiphasis.116 We usually translate this word by 'contradictory
pair'; but sometimes the abstract term 'contradiction' is more
appropriate.
In Stoic logic antikeisthai has the specific sense of 'be
contradictorily opposed',119 and sometimes Alexander uses ta
antikeimena, without any qualification, to refer to a contradictory
pair of opposites. Does he use antikeisthai in the Stoic sense in these
passages? Sometimes it is certain that he does, and there we
translate the word by 'contradictories'. But in many passages it is
115
See 32,33 and note.
116
But sunaletheuein is also used non-symmetrically: see 29,18 note.
117
antistrophd or conversion will be discused later, p. 31.
118
See the discussion of antiphasis at Ammonius, in Int. 81,13-84,25 (cf. 77,13-15),
which depends on Aristotle, Int. 17a33.
119
Note also Aristotle, ATI. Pr. 59b8-10.
Introduction 27
plain that Alexander uses ta antikeimena to refer to contradictories
but unclear whether he uses it in the sense of 'contradictories'; and
in these passages we have preferred 'opposites'. (It is always clear
from the context whether the opposites in question are in fact
contradictories.)
Enantia or contraries cannot be true together but can be false
together; paradigm contraries in the context of Aristotelian
syllogistic are propositions of the form 'Every A is B' and 'No A is B'.
The pair 'Some A is B' and 'Some A is not B' are not contraries: they
may both be true but they cannot both be false. The relation in
which they stand is known as 'subcontrariety' and hupenantios is
rendered by 'subcontrary'.120 Further, 'Some A is B' is 'subaltern'
(hupallelos) to 'Every A is B', and 'Some A is not B' to 'No A is B'.
These various relations are the constituents of the so-called 'square
of opposition'.121
In addition to standing in these relations, the members of a pair of
propositions may also be 'similar in form' or 'dissimilar in form',
homoioskhemon or anomoioskhemon. These are terms of art and
their explanation demands a detour. Every proposition is either
affirmative or negative. 'Affirmative' gives kataphatikos: 'affirm' is
kataphaskein, 'affirmation1 kataphasis. 'An affirmative' is katapha-
tikon. (Aristotle - and hence Alexander - sometimes uses
kategorikos as equivalent to kataphatikos. We render this word by
'predicative', for reasons to be given later.122) 'Negative', 'negation'
and 'a negative' are apophatikos, apophasis, apophatikon. But for
the verbs apophaskein and apophanai 'negate' will not work, and we
use 'deny'. (Aristotle and Alexander sometimes use steretikos as a
synonym for apophatikos. We translate 'privative' the root verb
sterein means 'deprive'; but the intended sense of 'privative' is no
different from that of 'negative'.) The status of a proposition as
affirmative or negative is called by Alexander its quality, poiotes.
Propositions differ in quality, kata to poion, when one is affirmative
and the other negative. If the propositions in a pair differ in quality,
they are anomoioskhemones or dissimilar in form; if they are of the
same quality, they are homoioskhemones or similar in form.123
A proposition has a quantity as well as a quality: propositions
may differ or agree kata to poson, in quantity. For in every
120
Alexander appears to mean that 'Some A is B' is subcontrary to 'Some A is not
B', so that 'subcontrary' means something like 'quasi-contrary'. (The prefix
hupo- often has this semantic force.) Note, however, that Ammonius (in Int. 92,21-24)
supposes that 'Some A is B' is subcontrary to 'Every A is B', and that 'Some A is not B'
is subcontrary to 'No A is B': the particular propositions are 'subcontraries' inasmuch
as they fall under the universals, which are contraries.
121
See e.g. Ammonius, in Int. 91,4-93,18; Boethius, Syll. Cat. 800AC.
122
See below, pp. 30-1.
123
The terms do not seem especially apposite, but they are Aristotle's own.
28 Introduction
proposition, the predicate is predicated (or denied) of all or of some
of its subject; and differences in 'all' and 'some' are differences kata
to poson. A proposition which has the 'all' quantity is called
katholou, the word being used as an undeclinable adjective. In
Greek 'A holds of the whole of B' is 'A holds kath' holou tou B'; the
preposition kata (kath') and the quantitative adjective holos then
coalesce, giving katholou. We translate by 'universal'.
For 'some'-propositions Aristotle and Alexander use epi merous,
kata meros or en merei. For all three expressions, which do not differ
in sense, we use the adjective 'particular'. Corresponding to en merei
for 'some'-propositions, there is a use of en holdi - 'in a whole' - for
'all'-propositions. Now you might expect 'A is en holdi toi B' to mean
'A is in the whole of B', i.e. A is found everywhere in B, or A holds of
every B. But in fact the Greek means exactly the opposite: A is en
holdi toi B if B is true of every A. B is, as it were, a whole for A. To
make this reasonably clear, we have followed the customary - and
awkward - translation, writing 'A is in B as in a whole'.12*
(Meros occurs in other contexts, and is always translated 'part'. In
normal Greek, the diminutive morion is synonymous with meros.
And we have usually translated it too by 'part'. But morion
sometimes means 'subpart' - one of the few places being the opening
pages of Alexander's commentary.125)
Propositions are complex items: they sunkeitai ('are compounded':
suntithenai is 'to compound', sunthesis is given by the noun
'compounding'); they have a sustasis or 'construction' (the verb is
sunistanai, 'to construct'); in them, one element is linked
(sunaptein) or connected (suntattein) to another. (Suntattein gives
the noun suntaxis, from which derives the English 'syntax'; but in
Alexander 'syntax' is not strictly a linguistic notion: it is parts of
propositions, not parts of sentences, which are connected.)
The chief components of a proposition are terms or horoi. But a
proposition may also contain a diorismos, or a sign to mark its
quantity,126 and a tropos, or a sign to mark its modality. A
proposition with no specific indication of quantity, such as 'Pleasure
is good', is called adioristos. The best English for this is
'indeterminate'. Hence we use 'determination' for diorismos (and
'determine' for diorizein). Strictly speaking, there are only two
determinations of propositions, a universal and a particular; but the
124
For a clear account of the locution see Boethius, Syll. Cat. 810B. In Greek, as in
English, it is natural to take part and whole as mutually exclusive things; hence if A
is en holoi tdi B, it might seem to follow that A is not en merei toi B. But in Aristotle's
logic, 'Every A is B' entails 'Some A is B'; hence in this context wholes and parts are
not mutually exclusive. (In the modern jargon, 'part' here does not mean 'proper
part').
125 126
See Barnes (1988), pp. 240-2. Later authors preferprosdiorismos.
Introduction 29
commentators all speak of four - 'Every', 'Some', 'No' and 'Some ...
not'. Hence the determination in effect gives the quality as well as
the quantity of the proposition. Thus in the determinate proposition,
'Every pleasure is good', 'Every' is or marks the diorismos. (We say
'is or marks'; for it is unclear in Alexander whether a diorismos is a
sign of quantification, i.e. a quantifying particle, and hence part of a
sentence; or whether it is, so to speak, the quantity signified by the
sign.)
Note that the word adioristos is also used in a different context,
involving the truth-conditions of particular propositions. We use
'indeterminate' here too - Alexander himself explains what he
means by this sort of indeterminacy.127
Tropos has a wide non-technical use: 'way', 'method', 'mode' are
variously appropriate, and we have used them as the context
suggests. In addition, there is a technical use of the word: here we
always use 'mode' (some might prefer 'mood'). If you say 'ex anankes,
A is B' then 'ex anankes' is or marks a mode.128 ('is or marks': the
same uncertainty arises.) We always translate ananke as 'necessity'
and ex anankes as 'by necessity'. Anankaios is usually 'necessary'.
Dei also marks necessity: we render it by the word 'must'. And for
the occasional opheilein we use 'should'. (In our part of the
commentary modal issues occupy a minor place; but elsewhere they
are of central importance, and we have therefore been uncharacter-
istically pedantic in translating modal words.)
A second tropos is that of possibility. Here there are familiar
difficulties for the translator. For Aristotle distinguishes different
sorts of possibility, and he also has two different words (or families
of words) to designate possibility, namely dunasthai and endek-
hesthai.129 Dunasthai and dunatos are always translated as 'be
possible' and 'possible' where Alexander is explicitly discussing
modal propositions. (And adunatos is 'impossible'.) Elsewhere we
often use 'can', rather than the cumbersome 'be possible', for
dunasthai. Endekhesthai, in normal Greek, is virtually a synonym
for dunasthai; and in contexts which are certainly non-technical we
use 'be possible' or 'can' for it too. But where Alexander is discussing
modal propositions, it is important to mark the difference between
endekhesthai and dunasthai. Accordingly, we have used 'be
contingent' for endekhesthai. This works well in some places. (For
example, 'A is B endekhomenos' comes out as 'A is contingently B',
127
See 66,1-10 and notes; cf. e.g. Ammonius, in Int. 94,7-24; 118,7-8; Philoponus, in
An. Pr. 82,1-84,11; 98,4-12. For a further type of indeterminacy see Ammonius, in Int.
90,19-20.
128
Hence the modern phrase 'modal logic' - but tropos embraces far more than the
modalities treated in standard modal logic (see Barnes (1991)).
129 There are also other words enkhorei, exesti, esti, and so on.
30 Introduction
i.e. 'A is B, but not by necessity' - and that is exactly the intended
sense.) But whereas in English 'It is contingent that A is B' suggests
that A is indeed B, it is not clear that the Greek carries the same
suggestion - 'endekhetai that A is B' may be true when A is not B. To
this extent our translation is unhappy. But we see no alternative
which is not at least equally bad.
Alexander holds that the 'plain' proposition 'A is B' also has a
modality:130 he has no special term for it, but (following Aristotle) he
refers to such propositions by the participle huparkhon, 'holding'.131
We might say that 'A is B' is taken to say that A is actually B, as
opposed to being necessarily or possibly B. And so we have used
'actual' for huparkhon in this usage. (The translation disguises
connexions which are patent in the Greek; and the expression 'an
actual proposition' is vaguely comic. But, again, alternatives seem
worse.)
Terms constitute the hule or 'matter' of a proposition (and hence,
indirectly, of a syllogism). And they contrast with its eidos or 'form',
which - in effect - is determined by its logical structure, or its
quality, quantity and mode. Aristotle and Alexander regularly use
'dummy letters' - ABC, MNO, PRS - in formulating syllogisms.132
Thus they will represent the form of a proposition by such a formula
as 'A holds of every B'. When he wants to give a genuine proposition,
with genuine terms, Alexander will talk of setting down133 hule.
(Here we translate hule as 'material instance'.) When Aristotle gives
a material instance or concrete term, he uses either a common noun
('man', 'swan') or a mass term ('snow') or an adjective in the neuter
singular ('wild', 'rational'). We translate these straightforwardly
into English. The result is usually barbarous; for in ordinary
English such a formula as 'No wild is man' is ill-formed. Yet it is
clear what those formulae are intended to express; and the Greek
formulae which they represent are also barbarous.
In a simple proposition, one term is predicated of (kategoreisthai)
another; and it is called 'the predicate' (to kategoroumenon) of the
proposition. The other term is the subject (hupokeimenon, as we
have already remarked). The verb kategorein has compounds,
antikategorein, 'counterpredicate', and proskategorein, 'co-
predicate'. There is also an adjective kategorikos: as we have said, it
is used specifically to designate affirmative propositions; but it is
also used generically to designate simple propositions,134 and hence
130
The point later aroused controversy: see Barnes (1991).
131
The participle is usually in the feminine, huparkhousa, agreeing with an
unexpressed protasis.
132
See 53,30 note.
133
paratithenai: above, p. 25.
134
As opposed to complex or hupothetikoi propositions: above, p. 23.
Introduction 31
to pick out those syllogisms whose component propositions are all
simple.135 We use the adjective 'predicative', to preserve the trans-
parent connexion with kategorein. (Latin authors regularly use
praedicativus.) It is true that 'predicative' does not transparently
designate these items - but then the same holds for kategorikos.136
To express the predicative tie, Aristotle also uses legesthai, 'be said
of, and huparkhein, 'hold of (and especially in schematic formulae,
he often omits a verb altogether). 'B is A', 'A holds of B', 'A is said of B',
'A is predicated of B' - all these are equivalent.137 Note in particular
that 'A is said (or: predicated) of B' does not mean 'Someone says: "A is
B"'.
Subjects and predicates are alike terms: they belong to the same
logical category. (In this they are fundamentally different from the
subjects and predicates of modern 'Pregean' logic.138) Hence they may
exchange places in a proposition. Alexander's technical term for this
exchange is antistrophe, with the verb antistrephein. Antistrophe
may denote either an operation on a proposition, viz. 'conversion', or
else the result obtained by performing the operation, i.e. a converse.
Thus if you operate on 'No B is A' to reach 'No A is B', you perform a
conversion (antistrophe) and you get a converse (antistrophe). It is not
always clear whether antistrophe means 'conversion' or 'converse'.
We have chosen what in each context seems the more plausible option
- in point of fact little turns on the issue.
The verb antistrephein sometimes takes a personal subject: the
logician converts a proposition. More often the subject is a proposi-
tion. Then there are two grammatical constructions: antistrephein +
dative, antistrephein + pros + accusative. There is a difference in
usage here.139 Antistrephein pros marks a symmetrical relation: if X
antistrephei pros Y, then Y antistrephei pros X. We talk here of
'converting with'. Antistrephein + dative, on the other hand, is
non-symmetrical: if X antistrephei toi Y, then Y may or may not
antistrephei toi X. Moreover if X antistrephei toi Y, then X may be
derived from Y by a process of 'prepositional conversion'. Hence we
use 'convert from' for antistrephein + dative. (Prepositional antistro-
phe, as Alexander explains, is simply an interchange of terms which
preserves truth.140)
IBS por ancient explanations of the Aristotelian use of the term see Dexippus, in
Cat. 12,29; Ammonius, in Int. 70,7; 87,13.
136
kategorikos is usually transliterated to 'categorical'; hence Aristotle's logic is
known as 'categorical syllogistic'.
137
Note that, according to Apuleius (Int. 192,30-193,5) the Peripatetics prefer the
expression 'A holds of B', whereas he normally uses 'B is A' (cf. below, 54,25-29;
Albinus, Didasc. 158-9H).
138
On this see esp. Barnes (1983).
139
The difference emerges most clearly at in An. Pr. 392,19-26.
uo
See 29,1-29 and notes.
32 Introduction
Two terms may stand in various relations to one another. If every
B is A, then A 'includes' or 'encompasses' B, periekhei or
perilambanei. (There is a nounperilepsis.) A is 'over', huper, B, and
B is 'under', hupo, A. A may, in addition, hold of things which are not
B. Then A is of wider extension, epi pleon, than B, and it (or some
part of it) 'falls outside' B (piptein ektos). Again, if no A is B, then A
and B are 'disjoined' (apezeugmenon).
Asuzugia or combination of premisses contains three terms in all:
its two constituent propositions 'share', koinonein, a term.
(Koinonia, and the adjective koinos, are also used in this connexion.)
The shared term or the term taken twice - once in each proposition -
is the middle term, meson; and the other two unshared terms are
'extremes', akra. Any further term which may be invoked to show
that the combination is syllogistic is said to be taken 'from outside',
exothen. (And Alexander also speaks of operations, such as
antistrophe, being introduced 'from outside', a locution which is not
illuminating.)
The extremes are distinguished in two ways: first, one of them
may be called 'first' (prdtos) and the other 'last' (eskhatos). Secondly,
and more importantly, one may be called meizon and the other
elation. The standard translations are 'major' and 'minor'; and we
have retained these English words, not without misgiving. Literally
the words mean 'greater' and 'less'. They are comparative adjectives.
A is greater than B if and only if B is less than A; and A is greater
than B if A is more extensive (or holds epi pleon) than B. In English,
'major' and 'minor' do not carry such evident implications of relative
extension; nor, of course, are they genuine comparatives. This
means that our translation suppresses an important idea present in
the Greek. In addition, in some passages Alexander speaks
expressly of A being meizdn than B. In these passages we hedge by
using phrases such as 'A is major in extension with respect to B'.
(The notion of relative extension is important in certain contexts.
Thus it is connected with definitions (horismoi), which standardly
analyse the definiendum into genus (genos) and differentia
(diaphora) and which may do so by the method of 'division'
(diairesis).141)
Finally, the terms in a combination have an order and a position
(taxis, thesis)142 The order and position of the middle term
determines the type or 'figure' (skhema) of a combination.143
141
Hence diairein is normally 'divide'. The compound verb antidiairein is used
when you pick out items at the same level in a division: we use 'co-ordinate' here,
losing the connexion with diairein.
142
On these notions see 47,22 note.
143 For the figures see Appendix 2.
Introduction 33
Most readers will find some of our translations misguided. There
is nothing much to be done or said about this. All translators are in a
pickle, and logical texts are no easier to deal with than texts in
ethics or metaphysics.
This page intentionally left blank
Alexander of Aphrodisias
On Aristotle Prior Analytics 1.1-7
Translation
This page intentionally left blank
Contents
1. Preface
1.1 The status of logic 41
1.1.1 Instrument or part of philosophy? 41
1.1.2 Useless parts of logic? 43
1.1.3 The value of logic 46
1.2 The Prior Analytics 48
1.2.1 Contents and title 48
1.2.2 Procedure 50
2. Introductory Explanations
2.1 ThegoaloftheAraaZyics 53
2.2 Propositions 54
2.2.1 The general account 54
2.2.2 Demonstrative and dialectical propositions 57
2.3 Terms 61
2.3.1 Subjects and predicates 61
2.3.2 The copula 61
2.4 Syllogisms 63
2.4.1 The premisses 63
2.4.2 The conclusion 66
2.4.3 Necessitas consequentiae 71
2.4.4 Non-syllogistic arguments 71
2.4.5 'Positing' 75
2.4.6 Perfect syllogisms 75
2.5 Kinds of proposition 77
2.5.1 Universal Propositions 77
2.5.2 Modality 79
2.5.3 Quality and quantity 80
2.5.4 Modes 81
3. Conversions
3.1 Conversions in general 83
3.2 Non-modal conversions 84
3.2.1 General remarks 84
37
38 Translation
3.2.2 Universal negatives 86
3.2.3 Other propositions 90
3.3 Modal conversions 91
3.3.1 Necessary propositions 91
3.3.1.1 Necessary universal negatives 91
3.3.1.2 Other propositions 93
3.3.2 Contingent propositions 95
3.3.2.1 Contingent affirmatives 95
3.3.2.2 Contingent negatives 96
7. Further Reflections
7.1 Syllogisms with non-standard conclusions 184
7.2 Reduction 187
7.2.1 All syllogisms reduced to the first figure 187
7.2.2 All syllogisms reduced to Barbara and Celarent 189
7.3 Final remarks 195
This page intentionally left blank
1
Preface
41
42 Translation
6
10 Now those who say that it is a part were led to their view by the
following consideration. Just as philosophy concerns itself with the
other items which are universally agreed to be parts of philosophy,
making it its business to discover and order and construct them, so
too it concerns itself with the study before us. But although this
study is the product of philosophy, it is not a subpart of either of the
other parts of philosophy - neither of the theoretical nor of the
15 practical part. For its subject matter is different from theirs, and the
purposes of the three are distinct. The theoretical and the practical
parts differ from each other in certain ways, and in virtue of these
differences they are co-ordinate with one another: logic differs from
each of them in the same ways, and therefore it may reasonably be
taken as co-ordinate with them. It differs from them both in
subject-matter (for its subject-matter consists of statements and
20 propositions7) and also in its end and purpose (for its purpose is to
prove that, when propositions are compounded with one another in
2,1 certain ways, something may be deduced by necessity from what is
posited or conceded - and this is not the end of either of the other
parts).
Those who claim that logic is not a part but an instrument of
philosophy reply as follows. For something to be a part of an art or
5 science it is not enough that the art or science is concerned with it8
in the same way as it is concerned with each of the other parts which
it studies. For something is judged to be a part not merely because it
is an object of attention and study, but when, in addition, its end and
construction do not make reference to anything other than those
10 very things which the science in question studies, i.e. when it is not
investigated and constructed for the sake of these other items. For if
something makes reference to the needs of other items which fall
under the same science or art, then it cannot properly be taken as
co-ordinate with them, since it is for their sake that it exists and
comes into being; nor can it be a part in the way in which they are,
since it exists for their sake. For if something makes reference to
15 certain items, and if its end is given attention insofar as it
contributes to the discovery and construction of other items, then it
is the instrument of those items. With distinct arts, the product of
one is the instrument of another if its end makes reference to the
needs of what is made by the art whose instrument it is: similarly, if
the things made by a single science or art have such a ranking in
philosophy; but Top. 163b9-ll, which uses the word organon in a pertinent context,
may have been in Alexander's mind (cf. in Top. 584,9-12).
6
1,9-2,2 = SVF II 49a.
7
cf. Ammonius, in An. Pr. 9,26-7. Note that here Alexander uses axioma
('statement') in the Stoic sense: see e.g. Frede (1974a), p. 32 n. 1.
8
Omittingtomorion.
1. Preface 43
relation to each other, then one will be an instrument and the other 20
- the higher one - will be both the product and a part of the science.
A hammer and anvil are not precluded from being an instrument of
the smith's art by the fact that they are its product.9
Moreover, those who call logic a part of philosophy must admit
that a part of philosophy is an instrument of those other sciences
and arts which use syllogisms and demonstrations to establish and
construct the objects of their own concerns. For they use them, but 25
not as parts of themselves (since it is impossible for the same thing
to be a part of different sciences, nor does any of these sciences study
the construction and discovery of syllogisms); hence they will be
using them as instruments. But if so, and if one art or science
dominates another whenever it uses in its own production the
product and end of the other art, whose own product makes 30
reference to its needs (as bridle-making in relation to the art of
riding and ship-building in relation to the pilot's art),10 then
according to these people there will be other sciences and arts more
perfect than philosophy, namely those which have a part of
philosophy as their instrument.
1.2.2 Procedure
When you are giving instruction it is always63 very useful to state
53
The main texts on geometrical analysis are Pappus, 634-6, and a scholium to
Euclid XIII1-5 (printed in Heiberg's Euclid, IV 363-6); see also e.g. Albinus, Didasc.
157H; Philoponus, in An. Post. 162,16-28. Geometrical analysis is said to have been
encouraged by Plato: Diogenes Laertius, III 24; Proclus, in Eucl. 211,18-212,4. See
e.g. Hintikka and Remes; lerodiakonou, pp. 173-90.
64
See e.g. Aristotle, Gael. 300a7-ll; GC 329a20-4.
55
7,22-7 = FDS 1106.
56
See e.g. Apollonius Dyscolus, Synt. 265,9-10; 326,11-327,12.
57
cf. e.g. Ammonius, in An. Pr. 6,2-4; in Porph. /sag. 36,7-9; Philoponus, in An.
Post. 334,25-335,3; see lerodiakonou, pp. 166-73.
58
e.g. by Galen (Inst. Log. ix 1, 2; x 2). Aristotle does not use 'analyse' in precisely
this sense in An. Pr.; but he does use it in a closely related way, of reducing a
syllogism in one figure to a syllogism in another (e.g. 51a2, 3,18,22).
59
i.e. at An. Pr. 46b40-47bl4 (for analusis see 47a4): see Alexander, in An. Pr.
340,5-21 (with a reference to Theophrastus" work On the Analysis of Syllogisms: F 31
Graeser).
60
i.e. at An. Pr. 47bl5-50a4 (for analusis see 49al9); see Alexander, in An. Pr.
372,26-373,9. (At 7,30-31 we follow the punctuation proposed by Wallies on p. 711 of
his edition of in Top.)
61
Reading pou auton (Aldine) for tina autdn.
62
See An. Pr. 50a5-15 (but Aristotle does not use the word 'compound' of
syllogisms); Alexander, in An. Pr. 381,28-386,2; cf. lerodiakonou, pp. 21-3.
63
Reading aei (cj. Wallies) for dein.
1. Preface 51
64
the aim and purpose of what you are going to say; for those who
know what each thing you say refers to learn more easily than those
who do not know. (The difference between such learners is like that 5
between people walking along the same road, when some know the
destination to be reached and others are ignorant of it: those who
know walk with more ease and accomplish their purpose without
exhaustion, whereas those who are ignorant tend to tire. In all cases
ignorance is like a sort of inexperience.65) Since this practice is 10
useful, Aristotle usually follows it in his other studies - and he does
so here too. At the very beginning he states what his purpose is; and
having done so quickly and briefly, he next tackles the items which
lead up to this purpose.66 For just as 'that for the sake of which' is a
starting-point for things which come about, so too is it for things
which are said; for that for the sake of which certain things are said, 15
i.e. their aim, is the explanation for the things said for its sake. And
if this is a starting-point, we should use it as a starting-point and
start from it. Moreover, if the aim is recognized, it will help those
who speak to judge what to say and those who learn to judge what
they hear.
At the same time, by saying that the purpose of his study of
syllogisms is to speak about demonstrations, he tells us that the 20
account of demonstration must be considered the primary product of
syllogistic method as a whole. For the study of the other forms of
syllogism is a matter for philosophers only to the extent that dealing
with them is useful for demonstration and for the discovery of what
is true: if you have exercised in dialectical syllogisms and can 25
recognize what is plausible and what lies close to what is true, then
you can more easily discover what is true, not being deceived by the
similarity of the plausible to the true but being aware of their
difference;67 and if you know how sophistical arguments come about
you will be able to guard against falsehood - and avoiding this helps
very greatly in the discovery of what is true.68
Aristotle does the same in the Ethics as he does here. There he 30
first says that 'our method aims at these things, being in a sense
political',69 and he states that his purpose has to do with
64
Alexander's general comment, and also the specific analogy with walking, allude
to Aristotle's celebrated remarks on Plato's lecture On the Good (see Aristoxenus, -II
30; cf. Aristotle, Metaph. 995a33-b2).
65
'Inexperience' gives apeiria. The word may also mean 'infinity'; and Alexander
may be punning. At Probl. 955b9-21, [Aristotle] asks why a road seems longer if we do
not know how long it is; and he replies that it is in a sense infinitely long (apeiros).
66
See An. Pr. 24alO-15; cf. below 10,9-23.
67
See Aristotle, Top. 101a27; Alexander, in Top. 27,24-31.
68
See Alexander, Conv. 59. Note the practice of the Stoic Zeno (Plutarch, Stoic.
Rep. 1034E); and cf. Ebbesen (1981a), I, pp. 88-9.
69
SeeAT1094blO-l.
52 Translation
constitutions or political power. But only after ten books does he
give an account of these things,70 thereby suggesting that it is
9,1 necessary first of all to speak of human character and to say which
characters are required in those who are to make up a State, since
they are the primary parts of a State.71
70
i.e. at EN 1179a33-1181b23? Or does Alexander rather mean that the whole of
EN is, so to speak, a preface to Pol.?
71
See e.g. Aristotle, Pol. 1290b38-1291a8 (cf. Plato, Rep. 552A).
2
Introductory Explanations
53
54 Translation
20 given an appropriate reply to each of the questions he proposed.
A demonstration is a demonstrative syllogism; and demonstrative
science is the disposition by means of which it is possible to syllogize
demonstratively - for to speak about demonstrations7 is the mark of
demonstrative science and of someone who possesses it.
2.2 Propositions8
41
i.e. it refers back to An. Pr. 24al7.
42
Top. 100b21-3: 'Reputable opinions are those held by everyone or by most people
or by the wise (and either by all the wise or by most of them or by the best known and
most reputable)'.
43
An. Pr. 24a30-bl.
44
An. Post. 71b21-2.
45
An.Pr. 24blO-12.
46
Omitting kai before endoxou with LM: see Aristotle, Top. 100b23-5.
47
i.e. it is relatively easy to discern that the propositions are merely plausible.
2. Introductory Explanations 61
2.3 Terms
2.4 Syllogisms62
r. 24al2-13.
144
24,1-12 =FDS 1100.
145
See above, 21,31 and note.
146
i.e. in his account of second and third figure syllogisms in An. Pr. 1.5-6.
147
If the text is right, 'impossibles' here must be shorthand for 'reductions to the
impossible".
2. Introductory Explanations 77
the point at issue. That is why we say that it is proved not by a
syllogism but from a hypothesis - the syllogism yields something
else.148
149
See above, 14,25-15,4.
iso por 'as jn a wnoie' see Introduction, p. 28.
151
Contrast Philoponus, in An. Pr. 39,15-24, who maintains that 'A is in B as in a
whole' implies that A has a smaller extension than B.
152
See above, 10,2-9; below, 53,19-25; 54,2-29; Ammonius, in An. Pr. 33,28-34,5;
Philoponus, in An. Pr. 12,5-12. See e.g. Mignucci (1969), pp. 216-17; 224-7.
153
See An. Post. 73b26-7; above, 12,2-3. (The words at 25,11-13 are exactly the
same as those at 12,2-3: it is difficult to avoid the suspicion that their second
occurrence is not due to Alexander.)
154
Omitting eipein peri tou kata mgdenos (with the Aldine).
2. Introductory Explanations 79
2.5.2 Modality
Now every proposition is either of holding or of holding by
necessity or of holding contingently. [1.2,25al-2] 25
With 'every proposition' one has to understand 'predicative'. For
Aristotle is here dealing only with propositions and syllogisms of
this sort - they are the ones of which he has given an account.155
Now in every predicative proposition a term is predicated of a term
either affirmatively or negatively, i.e. as holding of the subject or not 26,1
holding of it. Of those terms which hold of something, some hold
always while others sometimes hold and sometimes do not hold. If
what is said to hold holds always and is taken as holding always,
then the proposition is a true necessary affirmative. A true 5
necessary negative is a proposition in which what by nature never
holds of something is taken never to hold of it. If the predicate does
not always hold of the subject, then if it holds of it at the present
moment, the proposition which marks this is a true actual156
affirmative; and in the same way, a true actual negative is a
proposition which says that what does not now hold does not hold. If 10
the predicate does not hold of the subject at the present moment,
although it is possible for it to hold, and if it is taken in this way, i.e.
as being possible, then the proposition is a true contingent
affirmative; and a proposition which says of something which either
holds or does not hold but can both hold and not hold, that it is
contingent for it not to hold, is a true contingent negative.157
155 156
See above, 11,17-20; 17,5-8. For our use of'actual' see Introduction, p. 30.
157
(1) Aristotle normally operates with three (or four) different modalities:
necessity, possibility, contingency (or 'two-sided' possibility) and, as an optional
extra, impossibility. It is contingent that P if and only if it is possible that P and also
possible that not-P (see e.g. Int. 23a7-26; An. Pr. 32al8-b2; cf. A. Becker, pp. 11-16;
Hintikka (1973), pp. 27-30, 47-51). See also below, 41,10 note. (2) The later
Peripatetics regularly gloss these modalities in temporal terms (see e.g. Ammonius,
in Int. 153,13-15; 215,11-14), so that 'Necessarily P' is equivalent to 'Always P' and
'Possibly P' to 'Sometimes P'. Hence 'Contingently P' becomes equivalent to
'Sometimes P and sometimes not-P', and 'Impossibly P' to 'Never P'. Traces of these
equivalences are to be found in Aristotle, but it is disputed how thoroughly
Aristotelian they are (see e.g. Hintikka (1973), pp. 93-113; Barnes (1977)). (3)
Alexander's account in the present text (cf. e.g. in An. Pr. 183,19-24) is clearly based
on some idea of temporal equivalences; but it is muddled. He preserves the equations
between 'Necessarily P' and 'Always P' and between 'Necessarily not-P' (i.e.
'Impossibly P') and 'Never P'. But for 'Contingently P' he offers the curious 'Possibly P
and now not-P' (which he finds in Aristotle at An. Pr. 29b29-32; cf. in An. Pr.
119,22-8). For 'Contingently not-P' he offers the odder 'Possibly P and possibly not-P
and (either now P or now not-P)'. And, what is oddest of all, the accounts he gives of
'Contingently P' and 'Contingently not-F evidently do not run parallel. We can find
no way of explaining - let alone of justifying - this muddle. In addition, Alexander
glosses the non-modal 'P', or 'Actually P', in temporal terms: 'P' is equivalent to 'Now
P and not always P'. This has some strange consequences. Thus 'Necessarily P' does
not entail 'F; 'P or not P' is not logically true\ It also fails to consist with Aristotle's
remark at An. Pr. 34b7-18 (cf. An. Post. 73a29; 75b25-6), according to which 'you must
80 Translation
15 Such propositions are false when they mark something as having
a mode which it does not in fact have. For since propositions make
clear that what is meant by them holds, the propositions
themselves, if they are assimilated to the mode of what they mean,
correspond to the way in which those items hold.
Further, everything which holds of something either is
inseparable from it and holds of it in its own right or else is
20 separable. If it is inseparable, the proposition which means this is
necessary, and if it is separable, contingent. If a contingent
proposition means what is already present, it is actual; if it means
either what has been separated or what is not yet present but can
hold, then it is contingent in the specific sense.158
2.5.4 Modes164
It seemed to me worth asking why, when he is dealing in these books
with syllogisms and figures, he also introduces material differences
among propositions.165 For the fact that a predicate belongs in this
way rather than in that way is a material difference. Differences of
this sort among propositions will seem to bear not on an argument's 28,1
being a syllogism simpliciter but on its being this or that kind of
syllogism - demonstrative, say, or dialectical.166
161
Alexander must mean: 'some actual [i.e. non-modal] affirmative propositions'.
162
cf. 24al7.
163
Not all, since some can only be reduced by using reduction to the impossible.
164
cf. Barnes (1990a), III.3-4; (1991).
165
Note that 27,1-5 has effectively answered this question, by distinguishing
between propositions which say that P, where it is necessary that P (where necessity
introduces a 'material' difference) and propositions which have the form 'Necessarily
P' (which introduces a formal difference). The present section breaks the flow of the
argument: Alexander perhaps incorporated it into his commentary at a late stage.
166
See above, 7,9 and note.
82 Translation
Or are these differences among propositions in general necessary
5 for the method and study of syllogistic? For since propositions which
differ in respect of the modes we have mentioned do not convert in
the same way, and since most of the syllogisms in the figures other
than the first are proved to be deductive by means of conversions, it
is indeed necessary for him to divide propositions according to the
modes. For it is by converting in one way in the case of the necessary
and the actual and in another way in the case of the contingent, that
10 the propositions will produce syllogisms. Moreover, when proposi-
tions which differ in respect of these modes are mixed167 with one
another, they produce different syllogisms: for this reason too, the
difference among propositions in respect of these modes is necessary
for the study of syllogistic.
Thus, ignoring the material aspect, he annexes the modes
themselves to the propositions and produces universal proofs for
them; and he thereby shows that the difference among the
15 syllogisms depends not on there being this or that matter, but
rather on the annexed mode. So the proofs, being universal, are a
proper object of syllogistic study.
Aristotle mentions these modes insofar as they are useful for
syllogistic method - as is clear from the fact that there are
20 differences among propositions in respect of other modes too. If'well'
or 'badly' or 'at length' or 'briefly' or 'fast' or 'slowly' is annexed, these
are modes and differences among propositions (e.g. in 'Socrates
talks well' or 'at length' or 'concisely').168 But Aristotle does not
mention any of these when he makes his division of propositions,
since they do not bear on the generation or differentiation of
syllogisms.
25 Now these different modes are useful for the generation and
construction of syllogisms, but not for the generation of the species of
syllogism. For the different kinds of syllogism (i.e. the demon-
strative, the dialectical and the sophistical) depend not on this
division but on the one which Aristotle discusses in the studies
30 appropriate to them. For there he says much about this theory and
makes it splendidly plain.169
167
For such 'mixing* see 123,28-124,7: mixis was the standard term for 'mixed'
modal syllogisms (cf. the title of Alexander's work on the subject: Introduction, p. 3).
168
cf. Ammonius, in Int. 214,31-215,3 (see Barnes (1991), XI). For other modes in
Alexander see in An. Pr. 270,10-28; 329,30-330,5; 411,35-7 (with reference to
Aristotle, Int. 22al3, where 'truly' is implicitly taken as a mode).
169
See above, 7,9 note (and cf. 14,18-21).
3
Conversions
1
cf. e.g. below, 45,14-46,16; Alexander, in Top. 191,6-12; 582,23-6; and esp. Cow.;
also Galen, Inst. Log. vi 3-7; Apuleius, Int. 181,19-183,6; Ammonius, in An. Pr.
35,7-36,15; Philoponus, in An. Pr. 39,32-42,34; Boethius, Int. Syll. Cat. 785B-790C
(cf. Syll. Cat. 804A-809A). See Lee, pp. 79-94; Mardth, pp. 140-3.
2
See above, 27,22-6 (or perhaps 23,21-24,7, if the previous section is a later
addition).
3
29,7-13 =FDS 1163.
4
See An. Pr. 2.8-9. On conversion of syllogisms see also Alexander, Conv. 60;
Galen, Inst. Log. vi 5; Patzig, pp. 152-3.
5
cf. below, 46,6-8; Alexander, in Top. 190,26-193,7 (on Aristotle, Top. 113bl5-26,
whence Alexander's example in in An. Pr. is taken); Conv. 60-1; Galen, Inst. Log. vi 4;
[Ammonius], in An. Pr. 68,28; Lee, pp. 86-7.
83
84 Translation
6
is true together with the corresponding negation. In this sense a
contingent affirmative is said to convert from a contingent negative.
20 For example, if it is true (as a contingency) that it is contingent that
every man is walking, then it is also true that it is contingent that
no man is walking.
Conversion of terms when the items are true together is also
called conversion of propositions. Conversion of terms occurs when
we interchange and make the subject term the predicate term and
25 what was the predicate7 the subject, preserving the quality of the
converted proposition. The interchange of terms in the manner
described is called conversion simpliciter^ - for example:
Every man is an animal.
Every animal is a man.
Here the terms have been converted. When in addition to the
conversion, the propositions which are converted, being assumed in
the same way,9 are also true together, then the propositions are said
to convert from themselves.
syllogisms Cesare and Camestres cannot be reduced to Celarent and must therefore
be treated as perfect (Alexander, Corey. 69; Themistius, Max. 180): see above, 23,14
note. Themistius explicitly and Alexander implicitly ascribe the rejection to the
Megaric philosopher Eubulides; and Alexander explicitly says that he defended,
against Aristotle, the thesis that particular negatives convert (see below, 30,26 note).
Eubulides is known from Greek texts as an enemy of Aristotle's (e.g. Diogenes
Laertius, II 109: see Giannantoni II B, 8-11); but the two Arabic texts provide the
only evidence thus far discovered that Eubulides attacked Aristotle's philosophical
position rather than his life and person. (It must be added that the attacks show no
logical refinement at all.) The two texts'also provide evidence that thinkers outside
Aristotle's immediate circle knew the contents of his Analytics.
12
cf. Alexander, Corey. 61; Boethius, Syll. Cat. 805B-806A; in Cic. Top. 1133BC. In
Conv. Alexander goes on to remark that 'Eubulides argued against Aristotle's view
that particular negatives do not convert from any proposition, saying that they convert
sometimes from particular negatives and sometimes from universal affirmatives' (66:
on 66-8 Alexander rightly scouts this suggestion). See above, 30,7 note.
86 Translation
syllogisms and because they are equivalent to particular propo-
sitions.13
<The particular privative does not convert for the same reason
as we gave earlier.> [1.3, 25a34-6]
He says that no proposition converts from a necessary particular
negative, because none converted from an actual particular
negative; i.e. because it is proved in the same way - by way of terms
and material instances - that they do not convert. The refutation
uses the same terms:
By necessity man does not hold of some animal,
25 and
By necessity animal holds of every man.
47
Reading endekhetai (with LB2: endekhesthai M) for ananke.
48
See above, 36,11 note, for the argument.
49
And rightly, since from 'It is not necessary for A to belong to some B' we may
infer 'It is not necessary for A to belong to every B'.
50
Reading endekhetai for ananke. Note that Philoponus, in An. Pr. 57,24-58,27,
knows - and rejects - a variant reading in Aristotle's text: endkhetai medeni for me
anank.
51
Reading tautei for tautSs (aphelon here has the same sense as anelon at 36,16).
52
Above, 36,20-3.
3. Conversions 95
53
3.3.2 Contingent propositions
67
Alexander has in effect summarized the argument of .An. Pr. 36b35-37a31: cf. in
An. Pr. 221,16-227,9.
68
F 15 Graeser; cf. Alexander, in An. Pr. 219,35-221,5 [= Eudemus, F 16 Wehrli];
anon, in Int. An. Pr. 100 Mynas [= Eudemus, F 15 Wehrli]; cf. A. Becker, pp. 65-7;
Bochenski (1947), p. 74 (see above, 41,10 note).
69
i.e. at in An. Pr. 219,35-221,5.
70
So too Philoponus, in An. Pr. 63,19-64,7; Ross, pp. 299-300. For a contrary view
see Maier, Ila, p. 27 n. 1; see also Mignucci (1969), pp. 209-10.
71
Reading apophatikei (Aldine) for kataphatikSi.
4
The First Figure
4.1 Introductory
101
102 Translation
<We must discuss syllogisms before demonstration because
syllogisms are more universal: a demonstration is a syllogism,
but not every syllogism is a demonstrations [1.4,25b28-31]
Here he plainly presents the reason why, after having proposed to
discuss demonstration, he first deals with syllogisms: it is because
20 syllogisms are 'more universal'. And he tells us in what sense they
are universal by showing that there is no conversion: 'a
demonstration is a syllogism, but not every syllogism is a
demonstration.' Since syllogisms stand in this relation to
demonstrations they are primary with regard to them. This indeed
is the explanation of the titles Prior and Posterior Analytics which
25 have been given to these studies, as we have said.3 For in order to
define demonstrations and to place them in the genus of syllogisms,
one must learn first what a syllogism is, and by what means it comes
about, and when, and how these means must relate to each other.
He has added 'every syllogism',4 although he discusses only
predicative syllogisms, because he thinks that only these are
30 syllogisms in the strict sense, as he will show later on. For he thinks
that no syllogism from a hypothesis syllogizes the point at issue.5
3
See above, 6,32-7,11.
4
i.e. in An. Pr. 25b27, in the previous lemma.
5
See An. Pr. 50al6-b4; Alexander, in An. Pr. 386,5-30 (cf. above, 24,18 note); on
syllogisms 'from a hypothesis' in Aristotle see Striker; Lear, ch. 3. Alexander is no
doubt alluding, generally, to 'hypothetical' syllogisms: a hypothetical syllogism is a
syllogism in which at least one premiss is a hypothetical proposition (on hypothetical
propositions see above, 11,20 note). For the stock contrast between categorical and
hypothetical syllogistic see e.g. the little essay in [Ammonius], in An. Pr. IX 22-XI36;
cf. e.g. Mueller (1969); Frede (1974b); Barnes (1983), (1985); Maroth.
6
cf. Aristotle, Are. Pr. 68b8-14.
4. The First Figure 103
7
better known.
Now anyone who justifies something or wishes to make it known,
justifies it on the basis of some other item or items. Nothing is
proved and justified on its own basis, otherwise everything would be
justified. Since, then, justification is based on some other item,
either you prove the point at issue on the basis of what is whole and
universal and inclusive (the point at issue is either some part of that 15
by means of which the justification is effected or, more generally, is
something of it; and it is proved by means of it), or you prove the
whole on the basis of its parts or a part on the basis of some part
falling under the whole.
When a part is proved or justified on the basis of a part, such a
proof (and the justification so conducted) is called a paradigm.8 For
instance, someone opposes Dionysius' demand that the Syracusans
give him a bodyguard on the grounds that if he gets it he will aim at 20
a tyranny; and he justifies this by observing that when Pisistratus
got the bodyguard he demanded from the Athenians, he became a
tyrant; and that Theagenes did the same to the Megarians. Each of
the items - both what is being proved and that by means of which
the proof is effected (and the demand opposed) - are parts of a
whole: the whole being the fact that all those who demand a
bodyguard aim at tyranny.9 So he produces a justification10 by way 25
of the one part, which he uses to establish the other; and the
argument proves an unknown and disputed part by means of a
known and justified part.
When the whole is justified and proved on the basis of the parts,
such a proof is called an induction.11 For instance: men move their
7
Aristotle says that 'a justification is a sort of demonstration; for we take
something to be justified par excellence when we deem it to have been demonstrated'
(Rhet. 1355a4-6: cf. Grimaldi, pp. 349-56; Sprute, pp. 58-67); and he analyses
justifications by way of the part/whole relation (Rhet. 1357b26-30; cf. An. Pr.
49b37-50al; 64al5-17, bll-13; 69al3-16; see Introduction, p. 28, on 'in as in a whole',
and in general Barnes (1988)). Usually he distinguishes two varieties of justification:
syllogisms (the rhetorical version of which is the enthymeme) and inductions (the
rhetorical version of which is the paradigm) see Rhet. 1356a35-blO; An. Pr. 68b8-14;
Top. 103b3-7; SE 165b27-8 (followed by Alexander, in Top. 62,6-13; Apuleius, Int.
185,10-20). But at An. Pr. 69al6-19 he implicitly marks three varieties of
justification, inasmuch as there he distinguishes between inductions and paradigms;
and the later tradition generally adopts this three-fold division (e.g. Alexander in the
present passage; Galen, Simp. Med. Temp. XI 470K; Sem. IV 58 IK; Ammonius, in
An. Pr. 28,21-29,19; Philoponus, in An. Pr. 34,12-30; David, in Porph. hag.
88,12-89,10). Note that here Alexander, following Aristotle, confounds the notion of
an argument with the notion of a proof: see esp. 44,14, where syllogisms are simply
saidtobeproo/s.
8
The definition and the example of Dionysius (for whom see Diodorus Siculus, XIII
91-5) are taken from Aristotle, Rhet. 1357b25-1358a2 (cf. 1393a25-1394al8).
9
See Plato, .Rep. 566B.
10
Reading ho de [with the MSS: ho de Wallies]pism [piston MSS].
11
cf. e.g. Aristotle, Top. 105al3-16; 108blO-ll; see Ross, pp. 481-5; Hintikka
104 Translation
lower jaw, as do horses, dogs, cows and sheep; therefore every
animal does.12 Induction is a path by way of known and justified
44,1 particulars toward the universal which is unknown. Both these
things (induction and paradigm) contain plausibility but not
necessity.13
Aristotle discusses these types of justification at greater length in
the second book,14 showing how they differ from syllogistic
justification, that they too are useful, and how15 they are subsumed
5 under syllogistic justification. Thus for present purposes what we
have said about them is enough.
When a part is justified from the whole, such a justification is
called a syllogism; and this is the most compelling16 type of
justification. For anything which applies to or holds of a universal
and a totality, by necessity also holds of what is within it and is
10 included in it. If you assume that all justice is noble and that
everything noble is good, then it is by means of the whole and the
universal - that is, by means of the fact that everything noble is
good - that you prove justice to be good, this being a part of the fact
that everything noble is good, since justice is indeed noble. (Aristotle
has already given an account of what a syllogism is.17)
4.1.3. Problems
15 Now since a syllogism is a proof, by means of agreed items, of
something disputed, and since what is disputed and proposed for
proof is called a problem, let us say a little about problems.18
Problems belong to the genus of propositions;19 for problems and
assumptions and agreements and conclusions and axioms are all the
same in genus - they are all propositions, differing from one another
in aspect.20 When a proposition is put forward for proof as not being
20 known, it is called a problem; when it is assumed in order to prove
(1980); Burnyeat, pp. 200-1.
12
The example is a stock one: e.g. Sextus, PH II 185; Apuleius, Int. 185,10-20;
Ammonius, in An. Pr. 28,32-29,2; Philoponus, in An. Pr. 34,21-6. The usual point of
the example is that the induction is misleading - for the crocodile does not move its
lower jaw (Herodotus, II68; Aristotle, HA 492b23-6; PA 691b5-16).
13
See above, 18,8-12; cf. Apuleius, Int. 185,10-20; Ammonius, in An. Pr. 28,23-5;
Philoponus, in An. Pr. 34,10-14.
14
Paradigms at An. Pr. 68b38-69al9, inductions at 68bl3-37.
15
Reading kaipos forpos.
16
anankastikdtatos: cf. Aristotle, Top. 105al6-19 (cf. An. Pr. 68b35-7); Alexander,
in Top. 86,21-87,6; cf. Long, pp. 137-9.
17
i.e. at An. Pr. 24bl8-22.
18
cf. Aristotle, Top. 101bl6-36 (cf. Alexander, in Top. 40,13-41,16): a 'problem' has
the form of a question: 'Is it the case that P, or not?' (see e.g. below, 46,25).
19
On protasis as a genus see above, 11,4 note.
20
cf. Apuleius, Int. 183,22-6; Ammonius, in Int. 10,2-4; in An. Pr. 26,34-27,4;
Philoponus, in An. Pr. 11,25-36; 22,4-15; in Cat. 11,20.
4. The First Figure 105
21
something else, it is an assumption or an agreement (as Plato calls
it22) or a proposition in the special sense;23 it is an axiom if it is true
and known through itself; and if it has been proved, it is a conclusion
(for anything which has been proved is a conclusion from the items by
means of which it was proved).
Thus problems belong to the genus of propositions, and every
proposition consists of a subject term and a predicate term - the
subject being that about which something is said, the predicate that 25
which is said about it;24 and again, the subject is that to which the
quantitative determination of the proposition is annexed ('every' or
'no' or 'some' or 'not every')25 and the predicate is that to which is
annexed 'is' or something equivalent to 'is' which includes 'is'
potentially in itself.26 Well then, since there are two terms in a
problem - the subject, and the predicate, which must be proved to 30
hold or not to hold of the subject - there must be some third term to
prove it, a term which, when it is co-assumed, will either bring the 45,1
terms in the problem together or else separate and part them. This
term which is co-assumed from outside must stand in a certain
relation to the two terms in the problem. When it is taken, it becomes
a middle term for them both, dividing the problem and making the
one proposition two. It is itself introduced into each of the two 5
premisses, being compounded with each of the terms of the problem
in turn, now with the subject and now with the predicate. You can
recognize the middle term, which has been introduced from outside,
inasmuch as it is taken twice and is present in both the premisses.
A conjunction of propositions of this sort is called a combination:
there is a combination when two propositions share one term, which 10
is a middle term. For when propositions differ from one another, then
either they share nothing at all with each other (e.g. 'Everything just
is noble' and 'Every pleasure is good'), or else they share something;
and if they share something, then either they share one term or else
they share the two terms.
21
cf. e.g. in Top. 23,21.
22
See Theaetetus 155AB; cf. Mardth, pp. 25-32.
23
i.e. a premiss: see Introduction, p. 22.
24
See above, 14,27-15,4.
25
For the four 'quantitative determinations' or quantifiers see e.g. below, 65,26-7;
100,11-14; Galen, Inst. Log. ii 5; Ammonius, in Int. 89,2-36. The quantifiers are taken
to modify the subject term (cf. Alexander, in An. Pr. 297,22-3; Philoponus, in An. Pr.
277,29-31; in An. Post. 155,24-5): the predicate term is not quantified (see below,
58,29 note). See also Introduction, pp. 28-9.
26
On the copula see above, 15,23-16,17 and notes. For the thought that it is
annexed to the predicate see above, 16,8-10 (cf. e.g. Alexander, in An. Pr. 406,32-5).
Ammonius says, more persuasively, that 'is' is added to 'the terms' and serves to 'bind
them together' (in Int. 165,10-16).
106 Translation
4.1.4 Propositions which share two terms27
Now it is among propositions which share the two terms that
15 oppositions and conversions of propositions are found.28 For when
they share their terms in such a way that the terms preserve the
same order in both propositions but differ either in quality or in
quantity or in both, then we find the oppositions, i.e. the different
types of opposition.29
When their terms are supposed in the same way and the quantity
20 is the same in both, but they differ in quality, then if they are
universal they are contraries. For universal affirmatives and
universal negatives, when they have the same terms in the same
order and differ only in respect of being affirmative and negative,
are contraries. When both are particular, they are called
subcontraries (these seem to stand in opposition to one another but
30
25 are not in fact opposed ). When their quality and also the order of
their terms are the same but they differ in quantity, then they are
subalterns (and these are not in any way opposed). Universal
affirmatives stand in this relation to particular affirmatives, and
universal negatives to particular negatives. When they differ both
30 in quantity and in quality and have the same terms ordered in the
same way, then they are contradictories. Universal affirmatives and
particular negatives stand in this relation to one another, as do
46,1 universal negatives and particular affirmatives - these are
contradictorily opposed to one another.
When propositions share their two terms with one another but the
terms in them are not in the same order but are taken inversely - it
is among propositions which share in this way that prepositional
31
5 conversions are found. For the conversion of propositions is a
matter of their sharing their two terms, inversely posited, and in
addition being true together. When they differ in quality, such
prepositional conversions require an opposition - and they are
called 'conversions with opposition'. When they are the same in
quality, the conversions which are taken in this way and are true
10 together come about without an opposition. Of those which convert
in this way, some preserve their quantity as well as their quality -
27
On this and the following section see Lee, pp. 65-74.
28
On the koinonia of terms see e.g. Ammonius, in An. Pr. 36,8; Philoponus, in An.
Pr. 42,22; Boethius, Syll. Cat. 798C-799A. Galen calls such pairs of propositions
sunoroi or 'co-terminal': Inst. Log. vi 3.
29
On the different types of opposition, which produce the so-called 'square of
opposition', see Introduction, pp. 26-7; cf. e.g. Apuleius, Int. 179,16-181,17;
Ammonius, in Int. 91,4-93,18. The terminology is Aristotelian, apart from the words
'subcontrary' and 'subaltern', which we find as logical terms first in Alexander.
30
Note that Aristotle counts them as opposites at An. Pr. 59b8-ll; but at 63b23-30
he remarks that they are opposites only kata ten lexin, in expression.
31
See above, 29,1-30,6.
4. The First Figure 107
as was proved in the case of universal negatives, both actual and
necessary (and similarly for particular affirmatives). Others have
the same quality but disagree in quantity, namely those which
convert with universal affirmatives (they are particular affir-
matives), and similarly those which convert with contingent 15
universal negatives (it is contingent particular negatives which
convert with them).
57
See Apuleius./rct 186,5-10.
4. The First Figure 113
Further, in this way it turns out that the conclusion is similar to
the inferior assumption.58
4.3.2 Ranking59
When both premisses are universal and affirmative, the conclusion
too is such. And it is reasonable for this syllogism to hold the first 10
rank; for in its conclusion it possesses both what is superior in
quantity and what is superior in quality.60 When the major premiss
changes to a universal negative, we get the syllogism which holds
the second rank. For this syllogism again possesses what is superior
in the proper characteristic of syllogisms (but not both types of
superiority); for it is universal. If the minor premiss changes and 15
becomes particular, then since the major is a universal affirmative
and the minor a particular, the conclusion will be affirmative. This
syllogism is third in rank; for it excels the next syllogism by being
superior in quality: it is affirmative, whereas the other is negative.
When the minor premiss is a particular affirmative and the major is
a universal negative, the conclusion is a particular negative. This 20
syllogism is the last in the first figure, being excelled by its
predecessors - by one with respect to quantity, by one with respect
to quality, and by one with respect to both.
Now when three terms so stand to one another that the last is
in the middle as in a whole and the middle is or is not in the
first as in a whole, <it is necessary for there to be a perfect
syllogism of the extremes.' I call a term middle when both it is
in another and another is in it - it is middle by position too.>
[1.4,25b32-6]
These are examples, one the first and the other the second
syllogism. He next gives the account of the first figure, which he is 53,1
discussing, in his remarks about the middle term: the first figure is
that in which the middle term 'both ... is in another and another is
in it'. For in this figure the middle is predicated of one of the terms
and is subject for the other. He does not give a general account of the 5
middle term but one which holds for the first figure. In general, the
middle term in a combination is the one which is taken twice, which
occurs in both premisses, and which the premisses in the
combination share with each other.66
The expression he uses also makes clear the reason why this is the
first figure. (He says: 'it is necessary for there to be a perfect 10
syllogism of the extremes.') For it is reasonable that the figure with
the perfect syllogisms should be the first figure.67
He does not mean that combinations in which the middle term
'both ... is in another and another is in it' and in which the middle
holds the middle position, are always syllogistic or that a perfect
syllogism always comes about from them. For in that case all the
combinations in this figure would be syllogistic. Rather, he means 15
that this is so when the terms stand in the way he has just
described. He sets down this way by saying: 'so ... that the last is in
the middle as in a whole and the middle is or is not in the first.' For
when the premisses stand in this way, there is then a perfect
65
The terms 'reliable' and 'unreliable' are not used in this logical sense by Aristotle,
and Alexander's explanation perhaps implies that they are new (or at least
unfamiliar). Galen knows them: Inst. Log. xi 6.
66
On the middle term see above, 44,29-45,10; 46,21-32.
67
See above, 47,24-7.
116 Translation
syllogism of the extremes in relation to one another. (Here he calls the
conclusion a syllogism.68)
20 He begins his exposition of the syllogisms now with 'as in a whole'
and now with 'of every', since each of these items is a sort of principle
and is primary.69 'As in a whole' is primary and a principle in relation
to us. For things which are 'as in a whole' and subjects are better
known to us than things said with a wider extension; for they are
closer to perceptible things. On the other hand, 'of every' is primary
25 by nature; for it is more common and more general, and common
items are primary by nature and thus are also principles.70
68
For the word sullogismos used in the sense of 'conclusion' see e.g. Galen, Inst.
Log. i 5; cf. Patzig, pp. 95-6.
69
See above, 25,9-11 note.
70
On the primacy of universals in Alexander see Tweedale.
71
For other comments on Aristotle's use of letters see below 77,32-78,5; 98,20-3;
Alexander, in An. Pr. 125,26-8; 379,14-380,27; 414,9-10; 415,10-12; in Top. 2,16-29;
Conv. 61; Philoponus, in An. Pr. 46,25-47,11; Boethius, Syll. Cat. 810CD. Cf.
Bochenski (1956), p. 157; Lukasiewicz, pp. 7-10 (but the letters should not be
construed as variables: Frede (1974b), p. 113).
72
See An. Pr. 24b26-8; above, 24,26-25,11.
4. The First Figure 111
supposed and taken in the premisses, is sufficient for the proof of the
deduction.73
This74 is why syllogisms of this kind are perfect and indemon-
strable in the strict sense.75 Let A be the major extreme, B the
middle term, and C the minor extreme. If C is in B as in a whole,
B is said of every C. For these formulae convert from each other.
Therefore it is not possible to take any of C of which B is not said. 15
Again, if B is in A as in a whole, A is said of every B. Hence it is not
possible to take76 any of B of which A is not said. Now, if nothing of B
can be taken of which A is not said, and C is something of B, then by
necessity A will be said of C too. The deduction in syllogisms of this
sort is thus directly obvious, being justified by means of the 20
suppositions - by means of'of every' and 'of none' - and not needing
anything else from outside.
He77 uses 'of every1 and 'of none' in his exposition because by
means of these formulae the deduction becomes known, and because
when they are stated in this way the subject and the predicate are
better known, and because 'of every' is primary by nature in relation
to 'in it as in a whole', as I have already said.78 (But syllogistic usage 25
is normally the other way about. Virtue is not said of every justice,
but the other way about - 'All justice is virtue'. This is why we have
to train ourselves in both types of formulation, so that we can follow
both normal usage and Aristotle's exposition.79)
5 Nor when the first holds of none of the middle and the middle of
none of the last will there be a syllogism in this case either.
<Terms for holding: science, line, medicine. For not holding:
science, line, unit.> [1.4, 26a9-13]
He has moved on to the combination of two negative universals in
the first figure, and he proves that this too is non-syllogistic. Again,
he sets down terms such that, in the different cases, A evidently
10 holds of every C and also of no C. The reason why nothing is deduced
syllogistically in this combination is that the middle bears no
relation to either of the extremes (it is as if a middle had not been
taken at all - and syllogisms depend on the middle term); and when
it stands thus, C may fall under A and also not fall under A. If A is
15 science, B line, and C medicine, both universal negative premisses
are true and science will hold of all medicine. But if unit or stone is
posited instead of medicine, the premisses are true in the same way,
but science will hold of no unit and of no stone.
92
An. Pr. 26al3-14 (see also below, 60,9).
93
See An. Pr. 27a5-14; cf. below, 78,21-2; 79,7-8.
122 Translation
94
the other particular. (That is why the converses of such propositions
are particular.) Thus it was in order to make it clear that the
universality and particularity of the terms occur in the conjunction of
5 the premisses and not in a single premiss nor yet in a converse of a
premiss, that he added 'in relation to the other': i.e. 'when one term is
predicated universally, and this is predicated particularly of some-
thing else'; or, more simply, 'when the same term is universal in
relation to one term and particular in relation to the other in the
conjunction described'. For it is when it is taken particularly in this
10 way that we get a combination or conjunction of premisses.
Having discussed combinations in the first figure with two uni-
versals, he turns next to combinations in which one premiss is
particular and the other universal, showing which and how many
they are and which of them are syllogistic. First, he sets them out. Of
15 these combinations, two again are reliable, viz. the combination of a
universal affirmative major premiss and a particular affirmative
minor, and the combination of a particular affirmative minor and a
universal negative major. He mentions both of them together when
he says:
94
A puzzling passage; for in what sense can we talk about the terms in a
proposition being universal or particular? It might seem that Alexander is supposing
that the proposition 'Every man is an animal' predicates some animal of every man, so
that man is universal and animal particular. And it might then further seem that
Alexander is here admitting - or even insisting - that the predicate as well as the
subject bears a quantifier. But quantification of the predicate was rejected by
Aristotle (Int. 17bl2-16; An. Pr. 43bl7-22; An. Post. 77b30), and the commentators
followed him: e.g. Alexander, in An. Pr. 297,4-23 (cf. above, 44,28 note); Philoponus,
in An. Pr. 277,26-32; and esp. the long essay in Ammonius, in Int. 101,14-108,36, on
which see Mignucci (1983). Rather, Alexander has the following simple fact in mind:
in some cases where A holds of every B, only some As are Bs, and in other cases all As
are Bs. In the former cases A is 'particular', in the latter 'universal'. (And this has
nothing to do with quantifying the predicate.)
4. The First Figure 123
But when it is on the minor or the terms stand in any other
way, it is impossible. [1.4, 26a20-l]
Having referred to the major premiss and said that there will be a
syllogism when it is privative, he continues 'But when it (sc. the
privative) is (sc. posited instead) on the minor' so that it is a 30
particular negative and the major is universal, either affirmative or
negative. 'Stand in any other way' means 'If the major is instead 60,1
assumed as a particular and the minor as a universal'. For when
they stand so, there is no syllogism.
'But when it is on the minor' may also have the force of 'when the
universal is instead assumed on the minor' - and to judge by what
comes next, this is indeed rather what he is saying.95 Then 'or the
terms stand in any other way' will be said in reference to the minor 5
premiss 'if this is not assumed instead as a universal but remains
particular and is assumed as a negative'.
I call the major extreme the one in which the middle is, and the
minor the one under the middle. [1.4, 26a21-3]
Everything he says must be understood to be said of the first figure.
For what he says here is this: 'In the first figure, the major term is 10
the one which the middle is in and the minor the one under the
middle.' For in this figure, as we saw, the middle term is subject for
one term and predicate of the other. In the second figure both the
major and the minor are in the middle term - the middle is under no
term. Conversely, in the third figure the middle is not only under the 15
major but also under the minor - no term is in the middle term.96
He has shown plainly that the term predicated in the conclusion is
the major term in the premisses and that the major premiss is major
because of it.97
who suggested that 'not of every' implies that the predicate holds of several of the
subject and that 'not of some' implies that it holds of one (scholium to Aristotle,
145a30-7 = F 5 Graeser - but the sense of the passage is uncertain); cf. Bochenski
(1947), p. 43.
107
'Deductive' translates sunaktikos (from sunagein, 'to deduce'): it is here used as
a synonym for 'syllogistic'.
108
See above, 61,24-9.
109
See above, 30,31 note.
110
See above, 62,11-12.
4. The First Figure 127
Having first proved non-syllogistic the combinations in which the
major is particular, he now proves non-syllogistic those in which the
major remains universal, whether affirmative or negative, and the 10
minor is a particular negative. (He thereby shows what he meant
when he said above: 'But when it is on the minor or the terms stand
in any other way.'111) These combinations are non-syllogistic
because of the minor, which is negative.
His proof112 that these combinations are non-syllogistic uses the
part of C of which it is supposed that B does not hold. For taking 15
this, he proves, again by setting down terms, that A holds of all and
also of none of it. He intended in this way to give an appropriate
proof of the fact that the combination set out is non-syllogistic; for if
the proof used every C, it would no longer be suitable in the same
way. When B held of no C, the combination was proved to be
non-syllogistic inasmuch as A could hold both of all and also of none 20
of that of none of which B held:113 in the same way, when B is
supposed not to hold of some C, the combination would be proved
non-syllogistic, if it were proved that A could hold of all and also of
none of that part of C of which B does not hold.114
Again, since the minor is a particular negative, the same premiss
can also be a particular affirmative in the same respect;115 for 25
nothing prevents that which does not hold of some so-and-so from
holding of some of it as well. But when the minor is a particular
affirmative, there is a syllogism if the major is universal, whether
affirmative or negative - a syllogism which is either a particular
affirmative or a particular negative, as has been proved116 (for each
of the premisses possesses its proper characteristic, the minor being 30
affirmative and the major universal). And since this combination is
syllogistic, it was not possible for him to take terms both for which A 64,1
holds of every C and also for which it holds of no C. Hence, since it is
supposed that B does not hold of some C, then if it also holds of some
C, it will not be possible to take terms for which A holds of every C
and also for which it holds of no C. For in that case we should also
disprove and reject the syllogistic combinations in which B holds of
111
An. Pr. 26a20-l; see above, 59,28-60,6.
112
On this see Maier, Ha, p. 87; Ross, p. 304; Patzig, pp. 177-80.
113
See Are. Pr. 26a2-9; above, 55,20-56,1.
114
Alexander's thought seems to be this: since 'B does not hold of some C' only
concerns some C (some white things), a disproof of the combination which invoked all
C would be too general and hence not appropriate. This is a confused thought; and it
is intended to justify a procedure which is unjustifiable. (Aristotle's argument fails
because, in Alexandrian terms, he does not take that part of C of which B does not
hold: he takes two different parts of C.)
115
Alexander must mean: 'The particular affirmative, "B holds of some C", may be
true when the particular negative premiss is true.'
116
i.e. Darii and Ferio: Aristotle, An. Pr. 26al7-29. (Note that here 'syllogism' is
used in the sense of'conclusion': see above, 53,19 note.)
128 Translation
5 some C and A of every B, and in which B holds of some C and A of no
B. For in the case of the combination which deduces an affirmative,
it is impossible to take terms for which A holds of no C, since it holds
syllogistically of some C; and in the case of the combination which
syllogizes a particular negative, it is impossible to take terms for
which A holds of every C, since it is syllogistically proved that A does
10 not hold of some C. Each of these combinations would be rejected if,
in the case of the combination before us, terms were found for A's
holding of every C and also for A's holding of no C.117
For this reason, since it is not possible, he does not give the proof
in terms of C simpliciter, but rather takes from C those parts of
which B does not hold (for it is supposed that B does not hold of some
C); and by setting down material instances he proves that there are
15 parts of C (of which B does not hold) of all of which A holds, and
parts of none of which A holds.
It is also possible to prove that the conjunction we have set out118
is non-syllogistic by predicating B universally and negatively of the
parts of C, assuming the minor as a universal negative. For suppose
that A is said of every B and B of none of the parts of C which have
20 been taken: since A may have a wider extension than B (for it is
possible that A is such as to exceed B), it may include the parts of C
of which B does not hold, and also not include them.119 Such a
combination is unreliable.120
The terms which Aristotle sets down are animal for A, man for B,
and white for the whole C, of some of which man holds and of some
25 of which man does not hold. Next, since BC is a particular negative
and it is impossible to prove and deduce a universal negative of C
when the terms are so taken (or a universal affirmative if AB is
taken as a universal negative), let us take some parts of white, of
none of which man is said - let them be swan and snow. (Man is said
117
This is false: the valid combinations would be rejected only if we could find
terms to verify 'A belongs to every B and B does not belong to some C and B belongs to
some C" as well as 'A belongs to every C' or 'A belongs to no C'.
118
Reading ekkeimenen for eirSmenen (Wallies, from the Aldine: the MSS have
antikeimenen).
119
See above, 56,8-27.
120
Alexander's procedure in this paragraph is correct, but his exposition is
compressed. The argument depends on the fact that 'B does not hold of some C' is true
if and only if there is some D such that C holds of every D and B holds of no D. (See
above, 32,20 note, for the corresponding fact about 'B holds of some C'.) Hence if a
syllogism of the form 'P, B does not hold of some C: therefore, Q' is valid, then so too is
the corresponding syllogism of the form 'P, B holds of no D: therefore, Q'. Hence a
counterexample to the latter will refute the former. According to Alexander, this
train of reasoning, although probative, was not Aristotle's (see below, 65,16-32:
Alexander implies that some critics had both ascribed it to Aristotle and found it
wanting). Later Philoponus expresses the line of thought more clearly - and reads it
into Aristotle (in An. Pr. 82,21-7; cf. 82,34-83,4; and note metalambanein at
109,20-1).
4. The First Figure 129
neither of swan, which is white, nor of snow.) Now animal is said of
every swan but of no snow. In this way such a combination is proved 65,1
unreliable and non-syllogistic in terms of a part of C to which B does
not belong.
(As for conjunctions with two particulars,121 when he sets down
the terms by which he proves that such conjunctions are
non-syllogistic, he no longer argues in terms of a part of C of some of
which it is supposed that B does not hold, but rather in terms of the 5
whole of C; for a conjunction with two particulars is non-syllogistic,
both if B does not hold of some C while also holding of some C and
also if B holds of no C. Now inasmuch as there is no syllogistic
combination to set alongside such a conjunction of premisses, it is
possible to take the whole of C and obtain terms both for A's holding
of every C and also for its holding of none. And if something holds of
the whole of C, clearly it also holds of each of its parts - and hence of 10
the part of which B does not hold.)
<Again, let A hold of no B and let B not hold of some C; and let
the terms be inanimate, man, white. Then of the whites of
which man is not predicated, take swan and snow. Inanimate
is predicated of all the one and of none of the other.> [1.4,
26blO-14]
The refutation is similar if AB is taken as a universal negative. Let
the terms be inanimate for A, man for B, white for C; and let us
again take swan and snow as whites of which man is not predicated.
For inanimate holds of all snow and of no swan. (The same terms,
swan and snow, were used to prove that the combination is 15
non-syllogistic when the major is a universal affirmative.)
He does not, as some think, invoke a universal negative in setting
out the terms, transforming the particular negative of the minor
proposition into a universal negative. (Nor, if someone does invoke
it, should one therefore deem him not to prove the given 20
combination to be non-syllogistic.) For you invoke what is universal
if you prove 'of every' and 'of none' for all C rather than for some part
ofC.122
Again, if it were not possible to take any parts of the last term of
which the middle did not hold universally, then the objectors would
be right in objecting to the transformation. This would be the case if
C were indivisible and did not have parts. But if it is indivisible, it 25
cannot be true that the middle does not hold of some of it. For if the
determinations - namely 'of every' and 'of none' and 'of some' and
121
Aristotle, An. Pr. 26b21-5; below, 68,9-21.
122
See above, 64,15-24 and note.
130 Translation
123
'not of some' - are annexed to the universal, as has been shown in
On Interpretation,12* it is clear that the last term is universal and
not indivisible;125 and sometimes there will be not only some thing
but some things of which it is predicated, if the middle has been
30 taken not to hold of some of it - as in the examples Aristotle sets
down. If it is of this sort, then both the exposition126 and the
transformation into the universal are correct, and the proof by way
of the universal that the given combination is non-syllogistic is
sound.
... and that all problems are proved by means of this figure ...
[1.4,26b30-l]
This is the main reason why this figure is the first.151 This is why
Aristotle, having said this, continues: 'I call this the first figure',152
suggesting that he has given the reasons why this figure is rightly 25
called the first.
Aristotle153 has proved that the four syllogisms which have been
set out are the primary syllogisms in the first figure. To these four
Theophrastus adds five more, which are no longer perfect or
indemonstrable. Aristotle, too, will mention these, some at a later
point in this book and some at the beginning of the next, i.e. the 70,1
second, book. Three of them, which come about from the first three
indemonstrables by conversion of the conclusion, he will mention at
the beginning of the second book, where he is investigating whether
it is possible for there to be several conclusions from the same
suppositions.154 The other two he will mention in this book, where 5
he says that of the non-syllogistic combinations those similar in
form are perfectly155 non-syllogistic, while in non-syllogistic
combinations which have a universal negative and are dissimilar in
form something can be deduced with the minor term said of the
major.156 These two conjunctions are in the first figure, one with a
universal affirmative major and a universal negative minor and the 10
other with a particular affirmative major and a universal negative
minor. (The remaining combinations are either syllogistic or similar
149
Aristotle, Are. Pr. 24b23-4.
150
See above, 32,11 note.
151
See above, 48,21-49,6.
152
Are. Pr. 26b33.
153
69,26-9 =FDS 1101.
154
Are. Pr. Bl,53a3-14.
155
Reading teleon for teleioi with Wallies (see his corrigenda on p. 426).
156
Are. Pr. 29al9-27.
136 Translation
in form or do not have a universal negative minor.) Theophrastus
calls one of them the eighth and the other the ninth. When both
15 their premisses are converted, a particular negative conclusion is
deduced with the minor term said of the major. If particular
negatives converted, then each of the two combinations would be
syllogistic necessarily and primarily, proving the point at issue by
conversion of the conclusion. But since they do not convert, the
combinations are non-syllogistic with regard to the point at issue -
20 but something else can be deduced syllogistically by means of them.
We will say something about these syllogisms when we come to the
passages in question.157
157
See below, 109,4-111,27, on An. Pr. 29al9-27. (Alexander's commentary on An.
Pr.'B- and hence his discussion of 53a3-14 - is lost). On the 'additional' syllogisms
see e.g. Volait, pp. 30-6; Bochenski (1947), pp. 56-61; Rose, pp. 57-79; 109-32; Patzig,
pp. 112-14; Thorn, pp. 52-5 (also Appendix 2, pp. 213-15). (1) Aristotle says at An. Pr.
53a3-14 that whenever the conclusion of a syllogism converts, then there is a further
syllogism to hand. He thus recognizes - but only implicitly and in entirely general
terms - eight further syllogisms; for we may convert the conclusions of Barbara,
Celarent and Darii in the first figure, of Cesare and Camestres in the second figure,
and of Darapti, Disamis and Datisi in the third figure. Let us call these new
syllogisms Group A. (2) At An. Pr. 29al9-27 Aristotle remarks that, of the
combinations which he has rejected as non-syllogistic, some will in fact yield a
conclusion in which the minor term is predicated of the major: the combinations are
those which consist of a universal negative and a universal or particular affirmative.
Aristotle thus recognizes - but only implicitly and in entirely general terms - five
further syllogisms, namely Fapesmo and Frisesomorum in the first figure, Firesmo in
the second figure, and Fapemo and Frisemo in the third figure. (There are, in all,
twelve combinations - four in eachfigure- which contain a universal negative and a
universal or particular affirmative. Seven of these combinations are recognised as
syllogistic in An. Pr. 1.4-6.) Let us call these new syllogisms Group B. (3)
Theophrastus added five syllogisms to the first figure (F 17 Graeser: in addition to the
present text see below, 109,29-110,21; Alexander, Corey. 60; Apuleius, Int. 193,7-13
[but the text is corrupt: see the discussion in Sullivan, pp. 155-7]; Martianus Capella,
IV 411; Boethius, Syll. Cat. 813BC, 814C-816C [Boethius mentions Eudemus - and
Porphyry - alongside Theophrastus]; scholium to Aristotle, 188a4-12). The five are
Baralipton, Celantes and Dabitis, from Group A, and Fapesmo and Frisesomorum,
from Group B. Theophrastus seems to have described these syllogisms in detail and
to have shown how they can be reduced to the four direct syllogisms in the first figure.
No text hints that Theophrastus made any additions to the other figures. Later
logicians refer to these syllogisms as 'reflected' (kat anaklasin or antanaklomenoi:
Boethius, Syll. Cat. 815A; Philoponus, in An. Pr. 79,10); the terminology was in use
before the time of Apuleius, who translates it by reflexim, and it may go back to
Theophrastus. (4) According to Apuleius, 'Ariston and some of the more recent
Peripatetics' added a further five syllogisms (Int. 193,16-20; see Sullivan, pp. 165-6).
(Note that the best MSS give Aristoteles instead of Aristo. At Int. 193,24 the MSS
again give Aristoteles; but here the text should not be changed to Aristo: see Moraux
(1973/84), I, pp. 190-1.) They are the so-called subaltern moods, i.e. Barbari,
Celaront, Celantos, Cesaro, and Camestrop. (Any combination which yields a
universal conclusion will also yield the particular proposition which falls under the
universal.) Call them Group C. Apuleius regards the addition of Group C as 'very
silly'. (5) At Inst. Log. xi 3-7 Galen enumerates certain additional syllogisms. (The
text is desperate: we follow here the version suggested by Jonathan Barnes and
Michael Frede in their forthcoming edition.) To the first figure Galen adds the five
4. The First Figure 137
Theophrastean syllogisms (three from Group A, two from Group B) and the two
Aristonian syllogisms (from Group C). To the second figure he adds Cesaro and
Camestrop from Group C (he omits Celantop). To the third figure he adds Daraptis
from Group A. (6) At in An. Pr. 109,4-111,27 Alexander adds Firesmo to the second
figure and Fapemo and Frisemo to the third, all from Group B. (7) Philoponus accepts
the three first figure syllogisms from Group A (in An. Pr. 79,10-20); he accepts the five
syllogisms from Group B (in An. Pr. 112,21-113,20); and he implicitly endorses all
eight syllogisms from Group A (in An. Pr. 388,18-399,9). (8) The general disregard for
Group C is not, perhaps, surprising; for (as Apuleius in effect remarks) the subaltern
moods do not add anything to the probative power of categorical syllogistic. But why
are Group A syllogisms not added to the second and third figures? The explanation is
to be found in Galen; for he observes that the reflected form of Cesare is simply
Camestres, and vice versa, and that the reflected form ofDisamis is simply Datisi and
vice versa (Inst. Log. xi 7). (Convert the conclusion of Cesare and you get: B holds of no
A; B holds of every C: therefore, C holds of no A. And this is Camestres, with the
premisses in reversed order.) It is, then, strange that Galen allows the reflected form
ofDarapti; for Daraptis is in fact identical with Darapti, as Apuleius observes (Int.
189,23-5). Here Galen seems to be following Theophrastus (see below, 95,30 note).
5
The Second Figure
138
5. The Second Figure 139
it comes to be predicated of both terms once the major has been
converted. And as predicated, it has a superior place in the second
figure since being predicated is more important than being subject.5
Reasonably, therefore, this is the second figure, since the middle
(because of which syllogisms come about), having lost the position
appropriate to it (which it had in the first figure), has the nobler of the 20
two remaining positions.
A combination is syllogistic in the second figure when the major
premiss is universal. When it is particular there will be no syllogism
in the second figure - and with good reason. For the syllogistic 25
combinations in the second figure preserve the proper characteristic
of the proposition by the conversion of which the second figure was
generated from the first.6 The second premiss, the minor, must be
either particular or universal (it is syllogistic both when it is
universal and when it is particular). And it must by necessity be
opposite in quality to the major, i.e. dissimilar in form: if the latter is 30
affirmative, it must be negative; if negative, affirmative. For if they
are similar in form a syllogism does not come about in the second
figure: neither from two negatives (because in no figure is such a
combination syllogistic), nor from two affirmatives, as will be proved.
The syllogistic premisses standing thus, in this figure too there will 72,1
be four syllogistic combinations: if the major premiss is affirmative, it
is connected either to a universal or to a particular negative minor; if
the major is assumed as negative, the minor is either a universal or a
particular affirmative. 5
I say that in it the middle term is the one predicated of both ...
[1.5, 26b36-7]
This is actually the account of the second figure: it is the figure in
which the middle is predicated of both the extremes for which the
deduction must be made.
... and the major extreme is the one supposed on the middle.
The middle is posited outside the extremes and first in 10
position. [1.5,26b37-9]
By the diagram of the terms7 and the expression8 he uses he has
made clear to us that it is when the major premiss in the first figure
5
See above, 48,25-7.
6
cf. below, 95,14-19; Themistius, Max. 182-3.
7
For other references to diagrams see e.g. below, 78,4; Alexander, in An. Pr.
301,9-19; 381,8-12; Philoponus, in An. Pr. 65,20-3; 87,8; Boethius, Syll. Cat. 814B.
For illustrative examples see [Ammonius], in An. Pr. VTII.20-1, 24-5; X.10-XI.1; 39,9
app. crit. See Rose, pp. 133-6.
8
Reading lexeos (with LM and the Aldine) for taxeos.
140 Translation
is converted that the second figure comes about. For the position and
order of the terms which he describes - the fact that the middle is
put first in order and the major supposed after it - make clear that it
9
15 is the major premiss which was converted.
46
The first reduction uses Darii, the second Ferio; Alexander presumably thinks
that the second is better because it does not require us to convert the hypothesis.
Both proofs are, of course, equally 'good'.
47
Reading ara for gar.
150 Translation
5.4.2 Non-syllogistic combinations
81,1 If M is predicated of every N and O, there will not be a
syllogism. <Terms for holding: substance, animal, man. For
not holding: substance, animal, number. (Substance is the
middle.)> [1.5, 27al8-20]
Having proved the syllogistic combinations with two universal
premisses in the second figure, he sets down the non-syllogistic
5 combinations and shows that they are non-syllogistic, setting down
material instances to prove that in them the major extreme may
hold of all and also of none of the minor. The remaining
combinations with two universal premisses are the ones which are
similar in form, i.e. the combination with two universal affirmatives
and the combination with two universal negatives.
First, then, he tackles the combination with two universal
10 affirmatives, in which M holds of every N and O. For the case that N
holds of every O, he sets down the terms substance for M, animal for
N, man for O. For substance holds both of every animal and of every
man. And animal, which was N, holds of every man, which was
supposed for O.
For the case in which N holds of no O he posits number for O.
15 What he says would be more evident if stone had been posited. For
the premisses are again true in the same way (substance holds both
of every animal and of every stone), and animal holds of no stone.
Either he took number to stand for unit - for they say48 that units
are substances. (They say that units are not quantities inasmuch as
they are neither continuous nor determinate.49 They are substances
inasmuch as they are capable of receiving contraries50 - for a
20 beginning and an end are contraries, and numerical units possess
both.) But if a unit is what is undivided in quantity, a point what is
undivided in magnitude, and an instant what is undivided in time,51
then they will have one genus52 - they will be quantities. Further,
the unit is a part of number. For numbers are compounded from
units.53 But what is a part of a quantity is a quantity.
25 It is better to say that he uses the example rather loosely - in
other cases too we shall find him using examples without deliberate
48
Who? According to Philoponus, the view is Pythagorean (in An. Post. 301,26-8);
but Alexander's 'they' are no doubt earlier scholars who have in mind Aristotle's own
remark that 'a unit is a substance without position' (An. Post. 87a36).
49
Quantities are either continuous or determinate: Aristotle, Cat. 4b20.
50
This is the proper characteristic of substances: Cat. 4alO-ll.
51
See e.g. Aristotle, An. Post. 77a22-3 (units); Metaph. 1016b24-6 (points); Phys.
233b33 (instants).
52
Reading hen genos for en genei (Wallies' emendation of en genesi, which the MSS
present).
53
See e.g. Aristotle, Metaph. 1053a30; cf. Cat. 4b23 for number as a quantity.
5. The Second Figure 151
54
precision - since the doctrine is Pythagorean. For according to the
Pythagoreans numbers are substances since they are principles of
substances.55
The reason why there is no syllogistic combination from two
universal affirmatives in the second figure is that the middle is
predicated of both extremes, and the predicate is the major term. 30
Thus, being major in relation to both, it may be predicated of one
extreme term in virtue of one of its parts, and of the other in virtue of
another. And in this way there is nothing which the extremes share
with each other, if they each share with the middle term in virtue of
different parts of it. For the extremes must share in one and the same
thing if there is to be a syllogism.56 82,1
5.5.1 Festino
If the middle is universal in relation to one term ... [1.5, 27a26]
54
We follow LM and the Aldine: after paradeigmasin B has all'hosper with te writ-
ten above -per and Wallies prints allos te.
65
So Philoponus, in An. Pr. 92,9-12 (for the evidence about Pythagorean number
metaphysics see Burkert (1972), pp. 28-52). Cf. Aristotle, Are. Pr. 27b6-8; below, 86,5-6.
56 57
For the style of argument see above, 56,27 note. See above, 57,10-14.
58
Alexander is paraphrasing Are. Pr. 27a23-5. In modern texts Aristotle continues
as follows: '... if there is a syllogism when the terms are universal', i.e. 'if there is a
syllogism with universal premisses'. It is unlikely that Alexander should have
misunderstood this, so we suppose that he had a different text before him.
59
See above, 71,29-31.
152 Translation
Having discussed the combinations with two universal premisses,
15 and having proved some of them to be syllogistic and the others
non-syllogistic, he now discusses those which are compounded from
a universal and a particular. He shows which they are, and which of
them are syllogistic and which non-syllogistic. He shows that here
too the combinations dissimilar in form are syllogistic - provided
that the universal is preserved for the major premiss. There are two
20 syllogistic combinations: one in which the major is a universal
negative and is compounded with the minor which is a particular
affirmative; the other in which the major is a universal affirmative
and the minor a particular negative.
5.5.2 Baroco
10 Again if M holds of every N and not of some O, it is necessary
for N not to hold of some O. For if it will hold of every O, <and
M is predicated of every N, it is necessary for M to hold of every
O. But it was supposed not to hold of some.> [1.5,27a36-bl]
97
Retaining mede (medenos Wallies).
98
Aristotle, Are. Pr. 27a26-b2.
99
Aristotle, An. Pr. 27b3-36.
164 Translation
same examples, just as he did in the first figure.100 And he counts
the indeterminates along with the particulars as being, like them,
non-syllogistic - they are equivalent to them101 and are refuted by
the same terms.
93,1 Having said, 'Nor if it holds of some of each or does not hold (sc. of
some of each)', he adds 'or of all of neither'. This differs only in
expression from 'does not hold of some of each'. For both expressions
betoken particular negatives.102
5 Terms for holding of every: white, animal, man. For holding of no:
white, animal, inanimate. For white holds of some animal and of
some man, and also does not hold of some; and it holds of some of one
of them and does not hold of some of the other; and it holds of each
indeterminately, and also does not hold (and complementarily); and
indeterminately of the one and as a determinate particular of the
10 other. And animal holds of every man. Again, white similarly holds
of animal and inanimate - through all the particular and
indeterminate permutations; and animal holds of no inanimate.
<... they are all perfected when certain items are co-assumed
20 which> either inhere by necessity in the terms or are posited
as hypotheses <- i.e. when we prove by means of the
impossible ....> [1.5,28a5-7]
What 'inhere by necessity in the terms' (or in the premisses
supposed) are the converses, which we have invoked for the
perfecting of those syllogisms where the proof is by way of
100
Aristotle, Are. Pr. 26b21-5; above, 68,9-21.
101
See above, 30,31 note.
102
See above, 62,12 note.
103
i.e.'as we did at Are. Pr. 27a23': see above, 82,8, where the point is not explicit
but is implicit in Alexander's paraphrase. (See above, 58,10 and 60,9, on the first
figure, and below, 108,22 on the third.)
104
i.e. Celarent and Ferio (and also, in the third figure, Bocardo and Ferison).
5. The Second Figure 165
conversion. For the converses of the premisses inhere in the 25
premisses which are assumed.105
What are 'posited as hypotheses' are the hypotheses we use for the
proof of imperfect syllogisms in reductions to the impossible, as
Aristotle has made clear. For we take as an hypothesis the opposite
of what we are proving and thus produce a syllogism and a
deduction of the impossible. Then by means of this we reject the
hypothesis and establish its opposite, which was the point at issue. 30
106
cf. above, 58,13-22.
6
The Third Figure
166
6. The Third Figure 167
8
particulars. ) But there are more syllogistic combinations in this
figure - there are six, whereas each of the earlier figures contained
four syllogistic combinations.
The reason is this. In the third figure the minor premiss must
again9 by necessity be affirmative if there is to be a syllogism (if it is
negative, there is no syllogism in the third figure); but so long as it is 25
affirmative, there is a syllogism no matter how the major is
assumed, provided only that we ensure that the premisses are
neither both negative nor both particular. For in no figure is there a
syllogism from two particulars or from two negatives.10 (The major
and the minor premisses will be grasped in the same way in this
figure as they are in the second.11) Now if these conditions are 30
observed, there are six syllogistic combinations. Hence this is the
number of syllogistic combinations in this figure. If the minor is a
universal affirmative, there will be four syllogistic combinations, the
major being taken either as universal, whether affirmative or 95,1
negative, or as particular, whether affirmative or negative; and if
the minor is a particular affirmative, there are two further
syllogistic combinations, the major being universal and either
affirmative or negative.
The reason why there are more syllogistic combinations in the 5
third figure is this. In the other figures more features were
determined, and these had to be preserved in order for there to be a
syllogistic conjunction. Both in the first and in the second figure two
features were determined. In the first figure, the major premiss was
determined (it had to be universal) and so was the minor (it had to
be affirmative).12 In the second figure the major was determined (it
had to be universal), and it was also determined that the two 10
premisses must not be similar in form (it is the proper characteristic
of the second figure that nothing is deduced from two affir-
matives).13 But in the third figure only the minor premiss is
determined - it must be affirmative. (The fact that the premisses
may not be both particular or both negative is common to the three
figures and not a proper characteristic of the third.) And what is less
determined is more general and has a wider extension.
Given that the first figure has both its premisses determined, the
major in quantity (it is universal) and the minor in quality (it is
affirmative), it stands to reason that the other figures (I mean the 15
second and the third) should preserve the proper characteristic of
8
See above, 30,31 note; 51,25 note.
9
i.e. as well as in the first figure: above, 49,25.
10
See above, 71,32-3.
11
i.e. the major premiss is the premiss containing the major term, and the major
term is the term which is predicate in the problem: see above, 75,19-34.
12
See above, 49,19-50,14.
13
See above, 71,22-33.
168 Translation
the premiss by the conversion of which each of them was
14
20 generated. The second figure was generated by conversion of the
major, and it preserves the proper characteristic of that premiss in
syllogistic combinations15 - in the second figure, too, the major
premiss is universal in the syllogistic conjunctions. The third figure
was generated by conversion of the minor and retains its proper
characteristic16 - for in this figure the minor is again determined, as
we said, inasmuch as it is affirmative.
20
i.e. Baroco: Aristotle, An. Pr. 27a36-b3; above, 83,12-84,3.
21
Alexander follows Theophrastus in placing Datisi before Disamis and Ferison
before Bocardo (see Philoponus, in An. Pr. 105,28-106,2; Boethius, Syll. Cat.
819A-821A; scholium to Aristotle, 155b8-19: - F 21 Graeser; cf. Bochenski (1947),
p. 65; Sullivan, pp. 123-6). The later tradition generally took the Theophrastean line
(e.g. Apuleius, Int. 190,25-191,5; Martianus Capella, IV 413). Galen (Inst. Log. x 1-6)
follows Aristotle in placing Disamis before Datisi, but like Theophrastus he has
Ferison before Bocardo.
22
Or 'is generated': see below, 97,30 note.
23
See above, 78,25-79,19. Here Alexander seems to treat the proof of Camestres as
consisting simply in the application of Celarent, which yields the conclusion 'O holds
of no N'. The conversion of this conclusion is then superadded to the proof proper.
6. The Third Figure 171
and reduced to the first figure - and by the analysis they are proved 30
to be syllogistic.24
... the major is the extreme further from the middle, <and the 98,1
minor is the one nearer.> [1.6,28al3-14]
Since the major premiss in the first figure was converted, the middle
term came to be posited before the major extreme in the second
figure.25 In the same way, since the third figure has been generated
by converting the minor premiss in the first figure, the middle term 5
in the third figure comes to have position after the minor extreme.
For by the conversion of each premiss the middle term falls in the
position near the extreme with which it is combined in the converted
premiss. In the third figure the middle term comes to be near the
minor extreme and becomes subject for both terms: for the minor
because of the conversion of the minor premiss, for the major 10
because it was supposed from the beginning in the first figure to be
its subject. Being subject for both, it reasonably holds the last
position.26
6.3.1 Darapti
... but there will be a potential one both when the terms are
universal and when they are not universal in relation to the
middle. [1.6, 28al6-17]
'Not universal' does not mean 'neither of them being universal' (for it 15
24
On the generation of the figures see above, 47,27 note. Here Alexander, in trying
to correlate generation with analysis, conflates figures with syllogisms: the figures,
properly speaking, are generated but not analysed or proved (it makes no sense to
speak of proving a figure); the syllogisms, properly speaking, are analysed or proved
but not generated (cf. Themistius, Max. 184).
26
See above, 72,15 note.
26
Alexander tacitly alludes to the standard diagrams (see above, 72,11 note). In
the first figure the terms are set out thus:
A-B-C.
By converting the minor premiss, i.e. by inverting the order of B and C, we get:
A-C-B.
And A, the major term, is further from B than C is.
172 Translation
is impossible, as we have already said,27 to get a syllogism from two
particular propositions). It means 'not both being universal'.
6.3.2 Felapton
And if R holds of every S and P of none, <there will be a
syllogism that P does not hold of some R by necessity. There is
the same mode of demonstration, the premiss RS being
converted. It can also be proved by way of the impossible, as in
the earlier cases.> [1.6,28a26-30]
He has turned to the second combination, which has a universal
negative major and a universal affirmative minor. This too he
30 proves syllogistic by conversion of the minor, RS, which is a
universal affirmative. He takes RS as a particular affirmative and
reduces the syllogism to the fourth syllogism in the first figure. (This
was the syllogism which deduces a particular negative conclusion
from a universal negative major and a particular affirmative
minor.39)
It is clear that one can also prove this syllogism by reduction to
101,1 the impossible, as he says; and it is plain what impossibility is
V deduced. For if you hypothesize that P holds of every R, then since R
was supposed to hold of every S, it will be deduced that P holds of
every S - but it was supposed to hold of no S.
36
Aristotle also uses exposition for a second figure syllogism, viz. Baroco with two
necessary premisses (An. Pr. 30a5-14); but Alexander argues that this is a different
type of exposition (in An. Pr. 121,15-123,9).
37
Who are these people and what is their view? The style of reference leads us to
think that Alexander is mentioning a rival interpretation of exposition; but we are
unable to find anything here incompatible with what Alexander himself says. (It is
possible that Alexander has Boethus in mind: see Themistius, Max. 191-2 - but the
text is obscure.)
38
See above, 31,27-32,32.
39
Ferio: Aristotle, An. Pr. 26a25-8.
6. The Third Figure 175
And, once again, you can also prove it by invoking exposition,
although Aristotle does not mention this. If we take some perceptible 5
item of S, then inasmuch as it is obviously in R and participates in it
but does not share with P, it will be evident that P does not hold of
some R. For it will not hold of what has been taken and set out, and
this is some item of R.
40
See Aristotle, An. Pr. 26a2-9; above, 56,7-27.
176 Translation
syllogistic (he says which they are41) and two will be non-syllogistic.
6.4.2 Bocardo
If one is predicative and the other privative <and the
predicative is universal, then when the minor is predicative
there will be a syllogism. For if R holds of every S and P does
not hold of some S, it is necessary for P not to hold of some R.
For if of every, and R of every S, then P will hold of every S. But
it did not hold. It is also proved without the reduction if
something of S is taken of which P does not hold.> [1.6,
28bl5-21]
From premisses similar in form he moves on to premisses dissimilar
in form and the combinations constructed from them, first 10
preserving one of the premisses as a universal affirmative. He shows
which of these conjunctions are syllogistic combinations. Thus, if the
minor is universal and affirmative, it is clear that the major will be
particular and negative and the combination syllogistic. For if R
holds of every S and P does not hold of some S, it can be deduced that 15
P does not hold of some R. The proof can no longer proceed by
conversion; for the particular negative does not convert, and if we
convert the universal affirmative we will produce two particulars -
and from two particulars nothing necessary can be deduced in any
figure.46 Rather, he proves by reduction to the impossible that we 20
get a particular negative conclusion with this combination. For if,
when the premisses are supposed in the way we have said, someone
should not concede that P does not hold of some R, then let the
opposite be hypothesized, i.e. let P hold of every R. But it is supposed
that R holds of every S. Thus it will be deduced that P holds of every
S. But this is impossible; for it was supposed that P does not hold of 25
some S.
44
See above, 96,26-32.
45
It is hardly true that Aristotle 'made this clear'; but see below, 106,21.
46
Compare the similar remarks about Baroco, above 83,12-24.
178 Translation
He says that you can prove this same conclusion to be deducible
even without reduction to the impossible, 'if (he says) something of S
is taken of which P does not hold'. He means again the method of
exposition. Quite rightly he has not taken one of the Ss of which R
holds but rather one of them of which P does not hold. For, since R
30 holds of every S and P does not hold of some, R will certainly hold of
any item of S of which P does not hold; but it is not necessary for P
not to hold of any item of S of which R holds - for it is possible to take
something of S of which P will hold. (It was supposed not that it
holds of no S but that it does not hold of some S; and what does not
104,1 hold of some may also hold of some.) But if you take one of the Ss47
(an individual thing) of which P does not hold, then since this is
certainly in R (for R was said of every S), P will not hold of some R.
It is possible to conduct the proof for this combination if you take
5 not some perceptible and individual item of S but rather some of S of
none of which P will be predicated. For then P will be predicated of
none of it and R of all, and it has been proved that such a
combination deduces syllogistically that P does not hold of some R.48
Note that he uses the method of exposition for negatives too.
10 We made this the final syllogistic combination since it is not
possible to prove its conclusion by conversion.49
6.4.4 Ferison
If the privative is the universal term, <then when the major is
privative and the minor predicative, there will be a syllogism.
For if P holds of no S and R holds of some S, P will not hold of
some R. For again there will be the first figure, the premiss RS
being converted.> [1.6,28b31-5]
He is still discussing premisses dissimilar in form and combinations
5 which contain only one universal. Having discussed those in which
the universal is affirmative, he now discusses those which have the
negative universal (and the particular, of course, affirmative). In
combinations of such premisses he says that if the major is a
universal negative, there will be a syllogism, but not in the converse
case.
10 He proves that there is a syllogism when the major is a universal
negative and the minor a particular affirmative, setting out the
combination with letters. If P holds of no S and R of some S, P will
not hold of some R. For when the minor premiss, RS, is converted,
15 we get the first figure and its fourth syllogism, which deduces a
particular negative from a universal negative major and a
particular affirmative minor.
We said that this syllogism was the fifth, inasmuch as it is proved
by way of conversion, whereas the syllogism which Aristotle placed
51
See above, 66,1-10.
52
See Aristotle, An. Pr. 28a30-3; above, 101,11-22.
6. The Third Figure 181
53
fifth cannot be proved by conversion. For proof by conversion is
more authoritative and more appropriate than proof by means of the
impossible, as Aristotle himself will say.54 It is possible to use 20
reduction to the impossible and the method of exposition for this
syllogism too; but he does not say so since it is well known and has
already been said.55
Nor when both are posited as privative <and one is universal 107,1
and the other particular^ [1.6, 28b38-9]
He assumes both premisses as negative with one of them universal,
and he proves that the combinations of these premisses are
non-syllogistic, whichever is the universal. Now, if the minor is a
universal negative, the terms he sets down for 'of every' are animal, 5
man, wild. For animal does not hold of some wild, man holds of no
wild, animal of every man. For 'of none': animal, science, wild. For
animal does not hold of some wild, science holds of no wild, and
animal of no science.
When the major, <for not holding: raven, snow, white. It is not
possible to take terms for holding if R holds of some S and does
not hold of some S. For if P holds of every R and R of some S, P
63
See above, 96,34-97,3.
64
Aristotle nowhere says exactly this. Alexander is probably thinking of ATI. Post.
87al-30, where Aristotle argues that a direct proof of a proposition is 'superior' to a
proof by reduction to the impossible (see Barnes (1975), pp. 180-1). (But note that
Themistius, Max. 192, says that Aristotle makes the point in the second book of
An.Pr.)
56
Aristotle has not in fact said this; but Alexander wrongly takes him to have done
so at ATI. Pr. 28bl5 (see above, 103,4-7).
182 Translation
holds of some S. But it was supposed to hold of none. It must be
proved from the indeterminacy. > [1.6,29a2-6]
10 He is trying to prove that the combination in which the major is a
universal negative and the minor a particular negative is
non-syllogistic. Now for 'P holds of no R' the terms he sets down are
raven, snow, white; for raven holds of no white, snow does not hold
of some white, raven holds of no snow.
15 He says again that it is not possible to take terms for T holds of
every R' when R does not hold of some S in such a way that it also
holds of some S. (This was the case with the terms he set down, snow
and white.56) The reason is this. We again get a syllogistic
combination which has a universal negative major and a particular
affirmative minor; and as we have proved,57 this deduces a
particular negative, the opposite of which is impossible. Thus if we
20 hypothesize that P holds of every R, then given that R does not hold
of some S in such a way that it also holds of some S, our hypothesis
will be impossible. For it will be cancelled, since it was proved
syllogistically that P does not hold of some R. But since the truth of
particulars is indeterminate, if we take the particular negative to be
true inasmuch as the universal negative is true, we will then obtain
25 terms for 'of every', and we will prove that the combination is
non-syllogistic. For it is potentially the same as the combination of
two universal negatives.58 Aristotle proved by reduction to the
impossible that it is not possible to obtain terms for 'P holds of every
R', given that the particular negative RS is true in its own right. For
if it is hypothesized that P holds of every R and it is also the case
30 that R holds of some S, then P will also hold syllogistically of some of
the Ss. But this is impossible - for it is supposed that P holds of no S.
59
See above, 93,16 note.
7
Further Reflections
184
7. Further Reflections 185
and all negatives; in the third figure the particular affirmatives and 15
all negatives. These conjunctions of premisses, then, prove nothing
syllogistically at all.
Of conjunctions dissimilar in form (i.e. differing according to their
quality) and having a universal negative, the following were
non-syllogistic: in the first figure, the combination of a universal
affirmative major and a universal negative minor and that of a
particular affirmative major and a universal negative minor; in the 20
second figure, the combination having a particular affirmative
major and a universal negative minor; and in the third figure those
having an affirmative major, either universal or particular, and a
universal negative minor.
It has been proved that these combinations do not syllogize the 25
point at issue.4 Yet something else can be syllogized from them,
either by converting both premisses and interchanging the terms5
(in the first figure), or by converting only one premiss (in the other
two figures), so that the minor extreme becomes the major and is
predicated in the conclusion.
Take first the non-syllogistic combination in the first figure with 30
'A holds of every B' and 'B holds of no C'. In this combination there is
no deduction from A to C. This is why the combination is
non-syllogistic, being of no use with regard to the point at issue. Yet
something can be deduced syllogistically from the minor to the 110,1
major term. For if both premisses are converted, we get 'C holds of
no B' and 'B holds of some A' (since the universal affirmative
converts with the particular). From these premisses it can be
deduced that C does not hold of some A, where C takes the place of
the major term in the conclusion and A that of the minor, conversely 5
to how they were supposed. (The particular negative does not
convert, so that we cannot convert and have the conclusion we
proposed. In that case the conjunction would deduce the point at
issue, though not indemonstrably.) From this combination, then,
this is what can be proved and this is the way in which it is proved.
The other combination - with a particular affirmative major and a 10
universal negative minor - also proves by conversion of both
premisses that C does not hold of some A, taking the terms
conversely to how they were supposed.
These are the last two syllogisms of the five which Theophrastus -
who says that there are nine syllogisms in the first figure - adds to
the four laid down in the first figure.6 They are last because they do 15
that the text yields these six cases: either Alexander has made a trivial error or else
his scribes have miscopied.
4
See Aristotle, An. Pr. 26a2-9,36-9; 27b6-8; 28a30-3,36-8.
5
i.e. making the major term minor and the minor major.
6
Theophrastus, F17 Graeser (see above, 70,21 note).
186 Translation
not prove the point at issue at all, unlike the three before them in
which the conclusion is converted. (The remaining three, which come
about by conversion of the conclusions of the first, second, and third
syllogisms in the first figure, are also mentioned by Aristotle, at the
20 beginning of the second book of the Prior Analytics .7 We will remark
on them again in our notes there. In Theophrastus they are ranked
before the other two.)
The non-syllogistic conjunction in the second figure with a parti-
cular affirmative major and a universal negative minor is indeed
non-syllogistic with regard to proving that something is deduced from
25 the major to the minor term; but it deduces something from the minor
to the major if the universal negative minor is converted and the
minor term takes instead the major place. For if the order is changed8
and the minor converted, then the premiss which was the minor is the
major and a universal negative and the premiss which was the major
is the minor and a particular affirmative, the terms remaining in the
30 same order. From these premisses it can be deduced that the term
originally hypothesized as minor does not belong to some of the one
originally posited as major.
Again, the two combinations in the third figure - one with a
111,1 universal affirmative major and a universal negative minor and the
other with a particular affirmative major and a universal negative
minor - are non-syllogistic with regard to the point at issue. Again,
both of them syllogize a particular negative from the minor to the
5 major term, again by conversion of the affirmative major premiss.
These and thus many are the conjunctions in combinations which
are non-syllogistic with regard to the point at issue but syllogistic
with regard to something else. They all deduce their conclusions in
the first figure. Aristotle shows how the deduction comes about and
what is deduced in one of the combinations in the first figure: he omits
the other combinations which syllogize something in a way similar to
10 the one he mentions. He makes only this one clear because these
syllogisms are generated and proved in the same way in all the
figures. This is so because they all yield the fourth indemonstrable.
7.2 Reduction
<... and when the terms are taken as particulars, they are
perfected by means of the particular syllogisms in the first
figure - but these were reduced to the former: hence so too are
the particulars in the third figure.> [1.7,29b21-4]
As for the next three - two of them with a universal major, either
affirmative or negative, and a particular affirmative minor, and the
20 other with a particular affirmative major and a universal
affirmative minor - these no longer seem to derive from two
universals by way of reduction to the impossible. For the premiss
hypothesized in their case must certainly be universal, since it is
taken as opposite to the conclusion, which is particular; but the
co-assumption is particular.
Or does this hold only of the two cases in which the minor is a
25 particular affirmative?26 For it is this which is assumed together
with the hypothesis, which was universal; and when it is assumed it
produces the first figure - not one of the syllogisms with two
universals but one with one particular premiss. Hence, since they
reduce by reduction to the impossible to the same syllogisms to
which they reduce by conversion, he reasonably used proof by
conversion in their case.27
30 It is possible, however, to reduce them by reduction to the
impossible to the syllogisms in the second figure with two universal
premisses; and these are reduced by conversion of the negative
25
sc. despite the fact that he says 'immediately', which here means not 'by using
one or more conversions' but 'without first being reduced to some other syllogism'.
26
For the third case, Disamis, can be treated by reduction to the impossible using
Celarent since the co-assumption is universal: below, 116,20-9.
27
Datisi is reduced by conversion to Darii (An. Pr. 28bll-14; above, 102,27-103,3)
and by reduction to the impossible using Ferio. Ferison is reduced by conversion to
Ferio (An. Pr. 28b31-5; above, 106,9-16) and by reduction to the impossible using
Darii.
7. Further Reflections 193
premiss to the second syllogism in the first figure. For if it is
supposed that A holds of every C and B of some C, then I say that A
holds of some B. For if not, then A holds of no B. But it is supposed
that it also holds of every C. The proof is similar if AC is a universal 35
negative.28
The reduction by way of the second figure to the first syllogisms in
the first figure will seem easier than the proof which reduces them 116,1
by conversion to the two in the first figure which have a particular
minor premiss, inasmuch as these in turn must first be reduced by
reduction to the impossible to the syllogisms in the second figure in
which both premisses are universal.29
Again, it is possible to say that these syllogisms too are reduced to
the first syllogism in the first figure by conversion. In the case of the 5
syllogism with a universal affirmative major, we must hypothesize
not the opposite of what is deduced but the converse of the opposite.
For if it is supposed that A holds of every C and B of some C, it can
be deduced that A holds of some B. If not, then its opposite, that A
holds of no B, is the case. But since this converts, B will hold of no A. 10
But it was supposed that A holds of every C. And from this it can be
deduced that B holds of no C, which is impossible.
If AC is a universal negative, what is deduced is that A does not
hold of some B. For if not, then let its opposite, that A holds of every
B, be the case. If this is assumed, and if the universal negative AC is
converted so that C is taken to hold of no A, then again we get the 15
second syllogism in the first figure.30
But if in a reduction to the impossible you must hypothesize the
opposite of what is being proved and co-assume the other
supposition, the first syllogism I stated will seem not to satisfy the
suppositions, because it hypothesizes not the opposite of what is
being proved but the converse of the opposite; nor will the second,
because it co-assumed not one of the suppositions but the converse 20
of a supposition.31
The syllogism with a particular affirmative major and a universal
affirmative minor can be reduced by conversion to the third
syllogism in the first figure, which does not contain two universals.32
However, it can also be reduced by reduction to the impossible to the
28
i.e. Datisi may be treated by a reduction to the impossible using Cesare, and
Ferison by a reduction using Camestres.
29
Thus Aristotle reduces Datisi to Celarent by way of first Darii and then
Camestres. Alexander reduces Datisi to Celarent by way of Cesare alone.
30
The combination is: A holds of no C, B holds of some C. Hypothesize that A holds
of every B. Convert the first premiss to: C holds of no A. From this and the hypothesis,
infer that C holds of no B (by Celarent). Convert the conclusion to: B holds of no C -
and this is inconsistent with the second premiss of the original combination.
31
A trifling objection to a sound procedure.
32
cf. Aristotle, An. Pr. 28b7-ll; above, 102,6-24.
194 Translation
second syllogism in the first figure which has a universal negative
25 major and a universal affirmative minor, to which the first
syllogism, with two universal affirmatives, was also reduced.33
Hence this too, like the first two with two universal premisses, is
also immediately perfected by means of the universal syllogisms in
the first figure. (Those syllogisms reduce by conversion to the third
and fourth34 just as this reduces to the third.)
30 Now this case was overlooked in what Aristotle said and still
more the case of the syllogism with a particular negative major and
a universal affirmative minor. For this is not reduced in any way to
the particular syllogisms in the first figure - it is not proved by
conversion at all, as he said when he discussed it,35 but only by
35 reduction to the impossible, by which it is reduced to the first
syllogism of the first figure.
In this way,36 then, the syllogisms with two universal premisses
are directly reduced to the syllogisms in question, according to
117,1 Aristotle. The other four, he says, which have a particular premiss,
are reduced by conversions to the two particular syllogisms in the
first figure. These were proved to reduce to the first two syllogisms
by way of the first two in the second figure. Hence the syllogisms in
the third figure will be reduced to them by the same means. For the
5 syllogisms in the third figure reduce by conversion to the particular
syllogisms in the first figure, and the particular syllogisms in the
first figure reduce to the first two in the second figure by reduction to
the impossible, and the first two in the second figure reduce to the
second in the first figure by conversion. Hence the syllogisms in the
third figure with one particular premiss will be reduced to this same
syllogism.
But perhaps, as I said,37 this is so not for the four syllogisms but
10 only for the three which are proved by conversion. The syllogism
with a particular negative major and a universal affirmative minor
was neither proved by conversion nor reduced to one of the
particular syllogisms in the first figure. Rather, it too was directly
reduced by reduction to the impossible to the first syllogism in the
first figure, as has been proved.38 But the same is true of one of the
33
See above, 114,33-115,12.
34
Darapti to Darii (An. Pr. 28al8-22); Felapton to Ferio (An. Pr. 28a26-9).
35
See An. Pr. 28bl5-20 - but Aristotle does not say this. Alexander himself does, at
103,16-19. Should we change eipe Che said') to eipon ('I said')?
36
This paragraph does not fit. We suspect that in the original version of
Alexander's discussion, 115,17 was immediately followed by 116,36-117,9. When he
considered the matter again, Alexander added some new thoughts in 115,17-116,36.
Having done so, he re-read 116,36-117,9 which he corrected and supplemented by
appending 117,9-25. (See, in general, Introduction, p. 9.)
37
Above, 116,30-5.
38
Aristotle, Are. Pr. 28bl5-20; above, 103,9-25.
7. Further Reflections 195
other three: the syllogism with a universal affirmative minor and a 15
particular affirmative major can indeed be reduced by conversion to
the third syllogism in the first figure - but by reduction to the
impossible it too can be reduced directly to the second syllogism.39
And if in this case we must use proof by conversion because it is
more authoritative,40 then we must do the same in the case of the
syllogisms with two universal premisses. And in that case they too
will no longer be perfected immediately by means of the first two 20
syllogisms in the first figure but will also be reduced to the two
particular syllogisms, the one to the third and the other to the
fourth.
Perhaps, then, with 'when the terms are taken as particulars' we
should understand 'if they cannot be directly perfected by means of
the syllogisms in question' inasmuch as they are reduced to the
particular syllogisms in the first figure. For this is surely missing, 25
and when it is added there is no longer anything to investigate.
- both in their own right, when they are from the same figure
...[1.7,29b27-8]
10 This depends on Thus it is evident'.43 For it is evident from what he
has said that all syllogisms will be reduced to the first two
syllogisms in the first figure, and how each syllogism is syllogistic in
its own figure, and why each of them is syllogistic. All this has been
proved.
... and in relation to one another, when they are from different
figures... [1.7, 29b28]
44
15 This too still depends on 'Thus it is evident'. For it is also evident
from what he has said how the figures, and the syllogisms in the
different figures, differ in relation to one another - the difference
depends on the position of the middle term and on the different ways
in which they are reduced to the first two syllogisms in the first
20 figure. For some are reduced directly and some by reduction to one
another (i.e. the two syllogisms in the first figure and the three in
the third with particular propositions); and of the latter again, some
inasmuch as they are reduced to the first syllogisms in the second
figure (i.e. the two in the first figure), and others inasmuch as they
are reduced to those in the first figure which prove particular
premisses (i.e. the three syllogisms in the third figure which are
25 reduced to these by conversion). The difference in their reductions
shows the differences among these syllogisms.
43
At An. Pr. 29b24; but unless Alexander's text of An. Pr. was even further from
ours than we suppose, his construal is impossible.
44
Again, at An. Pr. 29b24; and again, Alexander's construal is impossible.
7. Further Reflections 197
some by conversion and some by reduction to the impossible. So too
with the syllogisms in the third figure: some are reduced by
reduction to the impossible and some by conversion first to the 5
particular syllogisms in the first figure.
Appendix 1
Translation of Prior Analytics 1.1-7
1
See Introduction, p. 17.
2
On this question see Wallies; Ross, pp. 90-2.
3
We have consulted Williams for corrections and additions to the OCT's critical
apparatus.
4
24all: epistemen apodeiktiken Alexlc; epistemes apodeiktikes OCT, Alex: Aldina.
198
Translation of Prior Analytics 1.1-7 199
this to be or not be in that as in a whole, and what we mean by being
predicated of every or of none. 15
Now a proposition is an utterance affirming or negating something of
something. It is either universal or particular or indeterminate. By
universal, I mean holding of all or of none, by particular holding of some or
not of some or not of all, by indeterminate holding or not holding, without 20
being universal or particular (e.g. that of contraries there is the same
science, or that pleasure is not a good).
A demonstrative proposition differs from a dialectical proposition in that
a demonstrative proposition is the assuming of one part of a contradictory
pair (for if you are demonstrating you do not request but assume), while a
dialectical proposition is a request for one of a contradictory pair. There will 25
be no difference with regard to there being a syllogism in each case. For
whether you are demonstrating or requesting, you syllogize by assuming
that something holds of something or that something5 does not hold. Hence
a syllogistic proposition simpliciter affirms or negates something of
something in the way already mentioned.6 It is demonstrative if it is true
and is assumed by way of the initial hypotheses. It is dialectical if it is a 24blO
request for one of a contradictory pair (if you are inquiring) or an
assumption of what is apparent and reputable (if you are syllogizing) - as
has been said in the Topics. In what follows we shall say with precision
what a proposition is and how7 syllogistic and demonstrative and dialectical
propositions differ; but for present purposes let what we have determined 15
be enough.
I call a term that into which a proposition resolves - i.e. the predicate and
that of which it is predicated (when you add or remove8 'is' or9 'is not').
A syllogism is an utterance in which, certain things being posited,
something different from the suppositions comes about by necessity
inasmuch as they are the case. By 'inasmuch as they are the case' I mean 20
that it comes about because of them; and to come about because of them is to
need no external term for the generation of the necessity.
I call a syllogism perfect if it needs nothing else apart from the
assumptions in order for the necessity to be evident; and imperfect if it
needs one10 or more items which are necessary by way of the terms 25
supposed but have not been assumed by way of premisses.
For one thing to be in another as in a whole and for the other to be
predicated of all the one are the same thing. We say that one thing is
predicated of all another when it is not possible to take any of it11 of which 30
the other is not said. And similarly for of none.
(2) Now every proposition is either of holding or of holding by necessity or of 25al
holding contingently. Of these some are affirmative and others negative, in
respect of each adjunct. Again, of affirmatives and negatives, some are
5
24a28: kai ti Alexc (13,27); e codd Arist, Alexc (13,17).
6
24a29: proeiremenon Alexc; eiremenon OCT.
7
24bl3: tini Alex1; ti OCT.
8
24bl7: e diairoumenou Alexc, codd Arist; del OCT.
9
24bl8: e Alexc, OCT; kai Arist: ABdA.
10
24b25: henos Alexc; e henos OCT, Alex: Aldina.
II
24b29: labein + ton hupokeimenou codd Arist; del OCT, non habet Alexc (sed cf.
24,29.32; 54,7).
200 Appendix 1
5 universal, some particular, some indeterminate. And in the case of proposi-
tions of holding, it is necessary for the12 universal privative to convert in its
terms - e.g. if no pleasure is a good, no good will be a pleasure. Predicative
propositions necessarily convert, but to a particular and not to a universal -
10 e.g. if every pleasure is a good, then some good is a pleasure. Of particulars, it
is necessary for the affirmative to convert to a particular (if some pleasure is a
good, then some good will be a pleasure), but the privative does not
necessarily convert (it is not the case that if man does not hold of some
animal, then animal does not hold of some man).
15 First, then, let the proposition AB be a universal privative. Now if A holds
of no B,13 B will hold of no A.14 For if of some, e.g. of C, it will not be true that A
holds of no B. For C is something of B.
If A holds of every B, then B will hold of some A. For if of none, A will hold of
no B. But it was supposed to hold of every B.
20 Similarly if the proposition is particular. For if A holds of some B, then it is
necessary for B to hold of some A. For if of none, then A will hold of no B.15
If A does not hold of some B, it is not necessary that B should not hold of
25 some A. E.g. if B is animal and A man: man does not hold of every animal, but
animal holds of every man.
(3) The case will be the same for necessary propositions. For the universal
privative converts to a universal, and each of the affirmatives to a particular.
30 For if it is necessary for A to hold of no B, it is necessary for B to hold of no A.
For if it is contingent that it holds of some, then it will be contingent that A
holds of some B.16
If A holds by necessity of all or of some of the Bs,17 then it is necessary for B
to hold of some of the As.18 For if it is not necessary, A will not hold of some B
by necessity.
35 The particular privative does not convert for the same reason as we gave
earlier.
As for contingent propositions, since19 being contingent is meant in several
ways (we say that the necessary and the non-necessary and the possible are
40 contingent), in affirmatives the case will be similar in respect of conversion in
all instances.
25bl If it is contingent for A to hold of every or of some B, then it will be
contingent for B to hold of some A. For if of none, then A of no B (this has been
proved earlier).
In negatives it is not the same. With those which are said to be contingent
5 inasmuch as it is by necessity that they do not hold20 or inasmuch as it is not
by necessity that they do hold,21 the case is indeed similar. E.g. if someone
12
25a5: ton men en toi huparkhein ten men Alex1; ten men en toi huparkhein OCT;
ten men oun en toi huparkhein Alex: Aldina.
13
25al5: toi B Alexcl, OCT; ton B Arist: ABC2d, Alexc: LM.
14
25al5: tdi A Alexcl, OCT; tbn A Arist: ABCdrO; to B Arist: n2.
15
25a22: toi B Alexc, OCT; tbn B Arist: ABCdm.
16
25a31 tini toi B Alex1; t6i B tini OCT, Alex: Aldina.
17
25a32: ton B Alex1, Arist: A2C; toi B OCT. Alex: Aldina.
18
25a33: ton A Alex1, Arist: A2C; toi A OCT, Alex: Aldina.
19
25a37: epei Alex1; epeide OCT, Alex: Aldina.
20
25b4: ex anankes me huparkhein Alex ut videtur, Arist: A2B2CdFA; ex
anankes huparkhein OCT.
21
25b5: me ex anankes huparkhein Alex0, Arist: AB1CdrAri; me ex anankes
Translation of Prior Analytics 1.1-7 201
were to say that it is contingent for man not to be a horse or that it is
contingent22 for white to hold of no cloak. In the one case it is by necessity
that it does not hold, and in the other it is not necessary that it does hold.
And the proposition converts in the same way. For if it is contingent for
horse to hold of no man, then it may be that man holds of no horse; and if it 10
may be that white holds of no cloak, then it may be that cloak holds of no
white. For if it is necessary for it to hold of some, then white will hold of
some cloak by necessity - this was proved earlier. (Similarly too for
particular negatives.)
But as for those which are said to be contingent inasmuch as they are for
the most part23 and by nature - this is the way in which we determine the 15
contingent - here the case will not be similar for negative conversions.
Rather, the universal privative proposition does not convert whereas the
particular does convert.
This will be evident when we discuss the contingent. For the moment, in
addition to what we have said, let it be24 clear that 'It is contingent that it 20
holds of none or not of some' has an affirmative figure. For 'It is contingent'
is ranked in the same way as 'is', and 'is' (where it is co-predicated) always
and in every case makes an affirmation - e.g. 'It is not good' or 'It is not
white' or generally 'It is not such-and-such' (this too will be shown in what
follows). And in respect of conversions the case will be similar to that of the 25
others.
(4) Having determined these issues, let us now say25 by what means and
when and how every syllogism comes about. We must discuss
demonstration later. (We must discuss syllogisms before demonstration
because syllogisms are more universal: a demonstration is a syllogism, 30
but26 not every syllogism is a demonstration.)
Now when three terms so stand to one another that the last is in the
middle as in a whole and the middle is27 or is not in the first as in a whole, it
is necessary for there to be a perfect syllogism of the extremes. I call a term 35
middle when both it is in another and another is in it - it is middle by
position too. Extremes are both that which is in something else and that in
which something else is.
If A is said of every B and B of every C, then it is necessary for A to be
predicated of every C. For we have earlier said what we mean by 'of every'.
Similarly, if28 A is said of no B and B of every C, A will hold of no C. 26al
But if the first follows29 all the middle and the middle none of the last,30
there will not be a syllogism of the extremes. For nothing necessary follows
inasmuch as they are the case. For it is possible for the first to hold of all 5
m22huparkhein OCT.
23
25b6: leukon + endekhesthai
cl
Alexc; non habet1 OCT.
24
25bl4: to polu Alex , OCT; to om Arist: ABd , Alex: Aldina.
25bl9: pros tois eirSmenois estd Alex1; estd pros tois eirSmenois OCT, Alex:
Aldina.
25
26
25b26: legdmen Alex1, OCT; legomen Arist: ABCd.
27
25b30: ho de sullogismos Alexc;1ho sullogismos de OCT.
28
25b34: protdi + e OCT;
1
om Alex bis [52,29 e praebet L, 53,17 & praebet Aldina].
29
25b40: d'ei kai Alex ; de kai ei OCT.
30
26a2: akolouthei Alexcl, OCT; huparkhei codd1Arist.
26a3: toi de eskhatoi to meson medeni Alex ; to de meson medeni toi eskhatoi
huparkhei OCT [huparkhei om Arist: A].
202 Appendix 1
and also of none of the last. Hence neither the particular nor the universal is
necessary. And if nothing is necessary by way of these items, there will not
be a syllogism. Terms for holding of every: animal, man, horse. For holding
of none: animal, man, stone.
10 Nor when the first holds of none of the middle and the middle of none of
the last will there be a syllogism in this case either. Terms for holding:
science, line, medicine. For not holding: science, line, unit.
Thus when the terms are universal it is clear when there will be a
31
15 syllogism in this figure and when there will not be one; and that if there is
a syllogism it is necessary for the terms to stand as we have said, and that if
they stand in this way there will be a syllogism.
If one of the terms is universal and one particular in relation to the other,
then when the universal is posited on the major extreme (whether it is
predicative or privative) and the particular on the minor is predicative, it is
20 necessary for there to be a perfect syllogism. But when it is on the minor or
the terms stand in any other way, it is impossible. (I call the major extreme
the one in which the middle is, and the minor the one under the middle.32)
For let A hold of every B and B of some C. Then if being predicated of
25 every is what we said at the beginning, it is necessary for A to hold of some
C.
And if A holds of no B and B of some C, it is necessary for A not to hold of
some C. For we have also denned what we mean by 'of none'. Hence there
will be a perfect syllogism. (Similarly too if BC is indeterminate, being
30 predicative. For there will be the same syllogism, whether it is assumed as
indeterminate or as particular.)
If the universal, either predicative or privative, is posited on the minor33
extreme, there will not be a syllogism, whether the indeterminate or
particular is affirmative or negative. I.e.34 if A holds or does not hold of some
35 B and B holds of every C. Terms for holding: good, disposition, sagacity. For
not holding: good, disposition, ignorance. Again, if B holds of no C and A
holds35 of some B or does not hold (or does not hold of every), in this case too
there will not be a syllogism. Terms: white, horse, swan; white, horse,
raven. The same terms serve if AB is indeterminate.
26bl When the term on the major extreme is universal, either predicative or
privative, and the term on the minor is privative and36 particular, there will
not be a syllogism (whether it is assumed as indeterminate or as
particular).37 I.e. if A holds of every B and B does not hold of some C (or if it
5 does not hold of every C). For the first will follow all and also none of that of
some of which the middle does not hold. Suppose the terms to be animal,
man, white. Then of the whites of which man is not predicated, take swan
and snow. Then animal is predicated of all the one and of none of the other.
10 Hence there will not be a syllogism. Again, let A hold of no B and let B not
hold of some C; and let the terms be inanimate, man, white. Then of the
whites of which man is not predicated, take swan and snow. Inanimate is
31
26al5: ontos ge Alexc \ge om Aldina]; ontos te OCT, Alex1.
32
26a22: to meson + on OCT, Alexc: L, Aldina, Alex1: Aldina; om Alex01.
33
26a30: ton elassona Alex1 [to elasson Aldina]; to elation OCT.
34
26a33: to men A OCT, Alex: Aldina; men om Alex1.
35
26a36: toz B + e OCT; om Alex1.
36
26b2: steretikon + kai Alex1; om OCT, Alex: Aldina.
37
26b3: adioristou te kai en merei lephthentos Alex1, codd Arist; del OCT.
Translation of Prior Analytics 1.1-7 203
predicated of all the one and of none of the other. Again, since 'B does not hold 15
of some C' is indeterminate and it is true both if it holds of none and if it does
not hold of all (because it does not hold of some), and since there is no
syllogism if terms are taken such that it holds of none (this has been said
earlier), it is evident that there will not be a syllogism inasmuch as the terms
stand in the way we are considering. For then there would be one in this case 20
too. (And38 it will be proved in the same way if39 the universal is posited as
privative.)
Again, if both the intervals are40 particular, either predicatively or
privatively (or one is said predicatively and the other privatively), or one
indeterminate and the other determinate, or both indeterminate, in none of
these cases will there be a syllogism. Terms common to all cases: animal, 25
white, horse; animal, white, stone.
Thus it is evident from what has been said that if there is a particular
syllogism in this figure, it is necessary for the terms to stand as we have said;
for if they stand in any other way, there is not. It is clear, too, that all the
syllogisms in it are perfect (for they are all perfected by means of the initial 30
assumptions), and that all problems are proved by means of this figure
(holding of every and of none and of some and not of some). I call this the first
figure.
(5) When the same item holds of all the one and of none of the other, or of all or 35
none of each, I call this the second figure. I say that in it the middle term is the
one predicated of both, the extremes are those of which this is said, and the
major extreme is the one supposed on the middle.41 The middle is posited
outside the extremes and first in position.
Now there will not be42 a perfect syllogism in this figure, but there will be a 27al
potential one both when the terms are universal and when they are not
universal. When they are universal, there will be a syllogism when the
middle holds of all the one and of none of the other, on whichever the privative 5
may be; and in no other case.
Let M be predicated of no N and of every O. Since the privative converts, N
will hold of no M. But M was supposed to hold of every O. Hence N of no O (this
has been proved earlier).
Again, if M holds of every N and of no O, O will hold of no N. For if M holds of 10
no O, O holds of no M. But M held of every N. Therefore O will hold of no N. For
we have got the first figure again. And since the privative converts, N will
hold of no O. Hence there will be the same syllogism. (It is also possible to
prove these by reduction to the impossible.) 15
Thus it is evident that there is a syllogism when the terms stand thus - but
not a perfect one. For the necessity is perfected not only from the initial
assumptions but also from other items.
If M is predicated of every N and O, there will not be a syllogism. Terms for
holding: substance, animal, man. For not holding: substance, animal, 20
number. (Substance is the middle.) Nor when M is predicated of no N and of
38
26b20: homoids de Alexcl, OCT; homoiosgar cj. Alex.
39
26b20: kai ei Alex1, OCT; kan Arist: ABd.
40
26b21: meros + ii Alex1, Arist: C; om OCT.
41
26b38: keimenon + elation de to porroterd tou mesou OCT; om Alex1, Arist: B1.
42
27al: sullogismos + oudamos OCT; om Alex1.
204 Appendix 1
no O. Terms for holding: line, animal, man. For not holding: line, animal,
stone.
Thus it is evident that if there is a universal syllogism,43 it is necessary
25 for the terms to stand as we said at the beginning. For if they stand in any
other way, the necessity does not come about.
If the middle is universal in relation to one term, then if it is universal in
relation to the major, either predicatively or privatively, and particular in
relation to the minor and in an opposite way to the universal (by 'in an
30 opposite way' I mean that if the universal is privative the particular is
affirmative, and if the universal is predicative the particular is privative), it
is necessary for there to be a particular privative syllogism. For if M holds of
no N and of some O, it is necessary for N not to hold of some O. For since the
35 privative converts, N will hold of no M. But M was supposed to hold of some
O. Hence N will not hold of some O. For we get a syllogism by way of the first
figure. Again, if M holds of every N and not of some O, it is necessary for N
not to hold of some O. For if it will hold of44 every O, and M is predicated of
27bl every N, it is necessary for M to hold of every O. But it was supposed not to
hold of some. (And if M holds of every N and not of every O, there will be a
syllogism that N does not hold of every O. The demonstration is the same.)
5 If it is predicated of every 0 and not of every N, there will not be a
syllogism. Terms: animal, substance, raven; animal, white, raven. Nor
when of no O and of some N. Terms for holding: animal, substance, unit. For
not holding: animal, substance, science.
10 Thus when the universal is opposite to the particular, we have said when
there will be a syllogism arid when not. When the premisses are similar in
form - i.e. both privative or affirmative - there will in no case be a syllogism.
Let them first be privative, and let the universal be supposed on the major
15 extreme. I.e. let M hold of no N and not of some O. Now it is possible for N to
hold of every O45 and also of no O. Terms for not holding: black, snow,
animal. It is not possible to take terms for holding if M holds of some O and
not of some 0. For if N holds of every O and M of no N, M will hold of no O;
20 but it was supposed to hold of some. Thus in this case it is not possible to
take terms - it must be proved from the indeterminacy. For since 'M does
not hold of some O' is true even if it holds of none, and since there was no
syllogism when it held of none, it is evident that there will not be one in the
present case either.
Again, let them be predicative and let the universal be supposed in the
25 same way. I.e. let M hold of every N and of some O. Now it is possible for N
to hold of every O and also of no O. Terms for holding of none: white, swan,
stone. It is not possible to take terms for holding of all (the explanation is
the same as before) - it must be proved from the indeterminacy.
30 If the universal is on the minor extreme, and M holds of46 no O and not of
some N, it is possible for N to hold of every O and also of no O. Terms for
holding: white, animal, raven. For not holding: white, stone, raven.
If the premisses are predicative, terms for not holding are white, animal,
snow; for holding, white, animal, swan.
35 Thus it is evident that when the premisses are similar in form and one is
43
27a23: katholou + tdn hordn onion OCT; om Alex ut videtur.
44
27a38: huparxei Alex1, Arist: C; huparkhei OCT.
46
27bl5: toNtdiXMex!; tdiXtoNOCT, Alex: Aldina.
46
27b28-30: ean ...ei... huparxei Alex1; el... esti... huparkhei OCT, Alex: Aldina.
Translation of Prior Analytics 1.1-7 205
universal and the other particular, in no case is there a syllogism.
Nor if it holds of some of each, or does not hold, or of some of one and not of
some of the other, or of all of neither, or indeterminately. Terms common to
all cases: white, animal, man; white, animal, inanimate.
Thus it is evident from what we have said that if the terms stand to one 28al
another in the way we have said, there is a syllogism by necessity, and that if
there is a syllogism it is necessary for the terms to stand in this way. It is
clear too that all the syllogisms in this figure are imperfect (for they are all 5
perfected when certain items are co-assumed which either inhere by
necessity in the terms or are posited as hypotheses - i.e. when we prove by
means of the impossible), and that there is no affirmative syllogism by
means of this figure but that all of them, both the universal and the
particular, are privative.
(6) When47 one term holds of all and the other of none of the same term, or 10
both of all or none, I call this the third figure; and I say that in it the middle
is that of which both are predicated, the extremes are the predicates, the
major is the extreme further from the middle, and the minor is the one
nearer. The middle is posited outside the extremes and is last in position. 15
There is no perfect syllogism in this figure either, but there will be a
potential one both when the terms are universal and when they are not
universal in relation to the middle.
If they are universal, then when both P and R hold of every S, P will hold
of some R by necessity. For since the predicative converts, S will hold of 20
some R. Hence since P holds of every S and S of some R, it is necessary for P
to hold of some R. For we get a syllogism by way of the first figure. It is also
possible to effect the demonstration by means of the impossible and by
exposition. For if both hold of every S, then if something of S - say N - is 25
taken, both P and R will hold of this. Hence P will hold of some R.
And if R holds of every S and P of none, there will be a syllogism that P
does not hold of some R by necessity. There is the same mode of
demonstration, the premiss RS being converted. It can also be proved by
way of the impossible, as in the earlier cases. 30
If R holds of no S48 and P of every S,49 there will not be a syllogism. Terms
for holding: animal, horse, man. For not holding: animal, inanimate, man.
Nor when both are said of no S will there be a syllogism. Terms for holding:
animal, horse, inanimate. For not holding: man, horse, inanimate. 35
(Inanimate is the middle.)
Thus it is evident in this figure too when there will be a syllogism and
when not, the terms being universal. When both the terms are predicative
there will be a syllogism that the extreme holds of some of the extreme; and
when they are privative there will not be one. When one is privative and the 28bl
other affirmative, then if the major is predicative and the other affirmative,
there will be a syllogism that the extreme does not hold of some of the
extreme; if they are the other way about, there will not be.
If one term is universal in relation to the middle and the other particular, 5
then if both are predicative, it is necessary for there to be a syllogism,
whichever of the terms is universal. For if R holds of every S and P of some
47
28alO: hotan Alex1; ean OCT.
48
28A30: medeni + tdi S Alex1, Arist: Cn2; om OCT
49
28a31: tdi S huparkMi Alex1 [tdi S om Aldina]; huparkhei tdi S OCT.
206 Appendix 1
S, it is necessary for P to hold of some R. For since the affirmative converts, S
10 will hold of some P. Hence since R holds of every S and S of some P, R will hold
of some P. Hence also50 P of some R. Again, if R holds of some S and P of every
S,51 it is necessary for P to hold of some R. There is the same mode of
demonstration. It is also possible to demonstrate by means of the impossible
15 and by exposition, as in the earlier cases.52
If one is predicative and the other privative and the predicative is
universal, then when the minor is predicative there will be a syllogism. For if
R holds of every S and P does not hold of some S, it is necessary for P not to
20 hold of some R. For if of every, and R of every S, then P will hold of every S. But
it did not hold. It is also proved without the reduction if something of S is
taken of which P does not hold.
When the major is predicative, there will not be a syllogism - i.e. if P holds
of every S and R does not hold of some S. Terms for holding of every: animate,
25 man, animal. It is not possible to take terms for holding of none if R holds of
some S and does not hold of some. For if P holds of every S and R of some S,
then P will hold of some R. But it was supposed to hold of none. We must take
terms as in the earlier cases. For 'does not hold of some' is indeterminate, and
30 it is true to say of what holds of none that it does not hold of some. But if it
holds of none, there was no syllogism. So it is evident that there will not be a
syllogism.
If the privative is the universal term, then when the major is privative and
the minor predicative, there will be a syllogism. For if P holds of no S and R
35 holds of some S, P will not hold of some R. For again there will be the first
figure, the premiss RS being converted.
When the minor is privative, there will not be a syllogism. Terms for
holding: animal, man, wild. For not holding: animal, science, wild. (Wild is
middle in both cases.) Nor when both are posited as privative and one is
29al universal and the other particular. Terms when the minor is universal in
relation to the middle: animal, science, wild; animal, man, wild. When the
major, for not holding: raven, snow, white. It is not possible to take terms for
5 holding if R holds of some S and does not hold of some S. For if P holds of every
R and R of some S, P holds of some S. But it was supposed to hold of none. It
must be proved from the indeterminacy.
And if each holds of some of the middle, or does not hold of some, or if one
holds and the other does not hold, or one of some and the other not of all, or
indeterminately - there will not be a syllogism in any of these cases. Terms
10 common to all cases: animal, man, white; animal, inanimate, white.
Thus it is evident in this figure too when there will be a syllogism and when
there will not - that53 when the terms stand as has been said there is a
syllogism by necessity, and that if there is a syllogism it is necessary for the
15 terms to stand thus. It is evident too that all the syllogisms in this figure are
imperfect (for they are all perfected when certain things are co-assumed),
and that it is not possible to syllogize a universal, whether privative or
affirmative, by means of this figure.
20 (7) It is clear too that in all the figures, when there is no syllogism, if both the
50
28bll: hoste + kai Alexc, Arist: BC2A; om OCT.
51
28bl2: huparkhei + toiSMex1; om OCT.
52
28bl5: proteron Alexc, OCT; proteron Alex: M, Aldina, Arist: ACd.
53
29al2: ekhontdn + te OCT; om Alexc.
Translation of Prior Analytics 1.1-7 207
54
terms are predicative or privative nothing necessary comes about at all; but
if they are predicative and privative, then if the privative is taken as
universal there is always a syllogism of the minor extreme in relation to the
major. E.g. if A holds of every or of some B and B of no C. For if the premisses 25
are converted, it is necessary for C not to hold of some A. Similarly in the
other figures too: there is always a syllogism by means of conversion.
It is clear too that if an indeterminate is posited instead of a particular
predicative, it will effect the same syllogism in all the figures.
It is evident too that all the imperfect syllogisms are perfected by means of 30
the first figure. For they are all brought to a conclusion either probatively or
by means of the impossible, and in both ways we get the first figure - when
they are perfected probatively, because they are all brought to a conclusion by
means of conversion and conversion produces the first figure; when they are 35
proved by means of the impossible, because when the falsity is posited the
syllogism comes about by means of the first figure. (E.g. in the last figure, if A
and B hold of every C, A holds of some B. For if of none and B of every C, then A
of no C. But it held of every C. Similarly in the other cases too.)
It is also possible to reduce55 all the syllogisms to the universal syllogisms 29bl
in the56 first figure. For the second figure syllogisms are evidently perfected
by them (though not all in the same way: the universals by conversion of the
privative, each of the particulars by means of reduction to the impossible). 5
The particular syllogisms in the first figure are indeed perfected by means of
themselves; but it is also possible to prove them by means of the second figure
by reducing them to the impossible. E.g. if A holds of every B and B of some C,
then A of some C. For if of none and of every B, then B will hold of no C - we 10
know this by means of the second figure. The demonstration will be similar in
the case of the privative syllogism. For if A holds of no B and B of some C, A
will not hold of some C. For if it holds of every C and of no B, B will hold of no C.
(This was the middle figure.) Hence since all the syllogisms in the middle 15
figure are reduced to the universal syllogisms in the first figure, and the
particular syllogisms in the first figure to the syllogisms in the middle figure,
it is evident that the particular syllogisms will be reduced to the universal
syllogisms in the first figure. The syllogisms in the third figure, when the 20
terms are universal, are perfected immediately by means of those syllogisms;
and when the terms are taken as particulars,57 they are perfected by means
of the particular syllogisms in the first figure - but these were reduced to the
former: hence so too are the particulars in the third figure. Thus it is evident
that all will be reduced to the universal syllogisms in the first figure. 25
Thus we have said how syllogisms which prove that something holds or
does not hold stand - both in their own right, when they are from the same
figure, and in relation to one another,58 when they are from different figures
(either by the middle term or inasmuch as they are reduced to the first
figure).59
54
29a21: ton horon ontdn Alex1; onton ton horon OCT.
55
29bl: anagein Alex1; anagagein OCT.
56
29b2: en + toi OCT; om Alex1.
57
29b21: epi merous Alex0; en merei OCT.
58
29b28: allelous Alex"1, OCT; allous Arist: ABd.
59
29b28: heteron + skhematon e toi mesdi e tdi anagesthai eis to prdton Alexcl; om
OCT [+ skhematon Arist: ABCn2].
Appendix 2
Aristotelian Syllogistic
I
The interpretation of Aristotle's syllogistic is controversial, and not only in
its details. Here we do not discuss the various rivals: we simply set down a
sketch of the system, without argument or defence - and also without any
attempt at technical sophistication.1
A syllogism, then, is a sort of argument; and an argument may be
represented as a sequence of propositions, one the conclusion and the rest
the premisses. Any argument, we may say, has the form:
Pi,P2 Pn: therefore, Q
- where the PIS are the premisses and Q is the conclusion. And an argument
is valid if its conclusion follows from its premisses.
An Aristotelian syllogism is a valid argument of a particular sort. First, a
syllogism is an argument which has exactly two premisses. In other words,
it has the form:
PI, P2: therefore, Q.
Moreover, the conclusion, Q, must be a different proposition from each of
the premisses; and the premisses must be different from each other.
Each of the three component propositions of a syllogism must exhibit a
particular structure; for each must be a 'subject-predicate' proposition. A
proposition is a 'subject-predicate' proposition if it contains two terms, A
and B, one of which (the predicate term) is said of the other (the subject
term). Thus 'Horses are animals' predicates animal of horses;2 and 'Dogs
are not cats' predicates cats (negatively) of dogs. If we use'... holds of ' to
1
For fuller versions of the account we outline, see e.g. Smiley; Corcoran. In
adopting this account we implicitly reject the interpretation advanced by
Lukasiewicz and elaborated by Patzig: it is nevertheless true, as our notes to the
translation suggest, that Lukasiewicz and Patzig have contributed more than any
other scholars to our understanding of Aristotle's syllogistic.
2
Or should we rather say that it predicates 'animal' of horses, or 'animal' of
'horses'? The ancients rarely saw any need for precision on this and allied points; and
we shall imitate them. Modern readers will think this a frightful muddle - rightly.
But it is a muddle which, or so we think, does not affect the presentation of the
syllogistic.
208
Aristotelian Syllogistic 209
express the predicative tie, we may say that the component propositions of a
syllogism all have at their heart the form:
A holds of B
- where A and B are terms, A the predicate and B the subject.
Subject-predicate propositions also have a 'quality' and a 'quantity' and a
'mode'. Their quality consists in the fact that they are either affirmative or
negative: either A holds affirmatively of B or A holds negatively of B. Their
quantity consists in the fact that they are either universal or particular:
either A holds of every B or A holds of some B.3 Their mode consists in the
fact that the predicate is said to be tied to the subject either necessarily or
actually or possibly: either A holds necessarily of B or A holds actually of B
or A holds possibly of B.
Putting these three features together, we may say that an Aristotelian
subject-predicate proposition has a form which could be clumsily
represented thus:
8[A holds+/-of e/sB]
- where 8 marks the mode,'+/' indicates the quality, 'e/s' stands for the
quantity ('every', 'some').
In An. Pr. 1.4-7 Aristotle investigates syllogisms in which all the
component propositions have the neutral mode marked by 'actually1. Hence
in the rest of this Appendix we shall ignore modal differences and drop the
modal sign from our representation of the form of subject-predicate
propositions.
That being so, it is clear that there are exactly four sorts of
subject-predicate proposition: universal affirmatives, of the form:
A holds of every B;
universal negatives, of4 the form:
A holds of no B;
particular affirmatives, of the form:
A holds of some B;
and particular negatives, of the form:
A does not hold of some B.
Three distinct propositions are involved in any syllogism; but the three
propositions must be interrelated. In particular, the two premisses must
have a term in common (the so-called 'middle' term); and the two terms in
the conclusion (the 'extremes') must each appear in one of the premisses.
Thus the three propositions of any syllogism exhibit altogether precisely
three distinct terms.
It is plain that the middle term may collaborate with the other two terms
in the premisses in any one of three different ways: it may be subject for one
extreme and predicate for the other; it may be predicate for both extremes;
or it may be subject for both. In other words, the premisses may, as a pair,
show any one of the following core structures:
I A holds of B,B holds of C.
II B holds of A, B holds of C.
III A holds of B, C holds of B.
3
Aristotle sometimes also refers to 'indeterminate' propositions, i.e. to propositions
which mark no quantity. Since such propositions are treated as equivalent to
particular propositions, we may ignore them here. See 30,31 note.
4
Note that the word 'no' here combines two functions: it indicates at once the
quality - negative - and the quantity - universal - of the proposition.
210 Appendix 2
These three structures determine the three 'figures' of Aristotelian
syllogistic: a syllogism belongs to the first figure if its premisses exhibit
structure I, to the second figure if its premisses exhibit structure II, and to
the third figure if its premisses exhibit structure III.5
Since each premiss may have any of four subject-predicate forms, there
are sixteen premiss pairings with each structure. Of the sixteen with
structure I, four are shown in An. Pr. 1.4 to yield conclusions, so that the
first figure contains four syllogistic forms. Of the sixteen pairings with
structure II, An. Pr. 1.5 establishes that four yield syllogistic conclusions, so
that the second figure also contains four syllogistic forms. The third figure,
analysed in An. Pr. 1.6, has six syllogisms.
The first figure syllogisms are 'perfect'; that is to say, their validity is
evident. Thus the first syllogistic form in this figure, which is known as
Barbara6, looks like this:
(1) A holds of every B
(2) B holds of every C
(3) A holds of every C
And it is, or so we are invited to think, evident that (3) follows from (1) and
(2).
The syllogisms in the other figures are 'imperfect'; but they can be
'perfected' inasmuch as they can be reduced to first figure syllogisms.
Aristotle employs three methods of perfection or reduction - in effect, he has
three ways of proving that a given syllogistic form is valid. One method
relies on 'conversion', a second on reduction to the impossible, and the third
on 'exposition'.
Conversion is an operation on propositions. To convert a proposition of
the form 'A holds of B', you interchange the terms A and B to get 'B holds of
A'. Aristotle recognises three conversion rules, which he establishes in
An.Pr. 1.2. They may be set out thus:
(CD From 'A holds of no B' infer 'B holds of no A'.7
(C2) From 'A holds of some B' infer 'B holds of some A'.
(C3) From 'A holds of every B' infer 'B holds of some A'.
A perfection by way of conversion works in the following way. Suppose as
premisses that:
(1)A holds of no B,
and:
(2) A holds of every C.
Then from (1), by (CD, infer:
(3) B holds of no A.
And now, by the second syllogism in the first figure (Celarent), we may infer
from (3) and (2) to:
(4) B holds of no C.
B
Later versions of syllogistic produce four figures; and there is a large - and largely
futile - literature on the origin and value of the fourth figure. See 47,12 note.
6
For the 'names' of the syllogistic forms see below, pp. 212-15.
7
Strictly speaking we should write:
(Cl*) From a proposition of the form 'A holds of no B' infer the corresponding
proposition of the form 'B holds of no A'.
But here and hereafter we shall follow the harmlessly inaccurate custom of citing
prepositional forms as though they were propositions and syllogistic forms as though
they were syllogisms.
Aristotelian Syllogistic 211
Thus we have shown that (4) follows from (1) and (2). A syllogism with
premisses of the forms (1) and (2) and with a conclusion of the form (4) is in
the second figure - it is a syllogism of the form Cesare.8
The method of reduction to the impossible works as follows. Suppose as
premisses:
(1) A does not hold of some B.
(2) C holds of every B.
Hypothesize in addition that:
(3) A holds of every C.
Then, by Barbara, we may infer from (3) and (2) to:
(4) A holds of every B.
But (4) is 'impossible'; or rather, (4) is inconsistent with premiss (1). Hence
if both (1) and (2) are true, (3) cannot be true. Hence if both (1) and (2) are
true, it follows that the contradictory of (3) is true, i.e. that:
(5) A does not hold of some C.
Thus we have shown that (5) follows from (1) and (2). A syllogism with
premisses of the forms (1) and (2) and with a conclusion of the form (5) is in
the third figure it is a syllogism of the form Bocardo.9
The third method, the method of exposition, is more controversial.10
Alexander's interpretation, which has been generally rejected on
inadequate grounds, is roughly this.11 Suppose as premisses that:
(1)A holds of every B.
(2) C holds of every B.
Now 'expose' or set out some particular B, say b. Then from (1) we may infer:
(3) A holds of b,
and by (2) we may infer:
(4) C holds of b.
But from (3) and (4) it follows that A holds of something of which C also
holds. Hence that:
(5) A holds of some C.
Thus we have shown that (5) follows from (1) and (2). A syllogism with
premisses of the forms (1) and (2) and with a conclusion of the form (5) is in
the third figure - it is a syllogism of the form Darapti.12
8
Some mav prefer a more formal presentation of the argument, thus:
1(1) A holds of no B prem
2(2) A holds of every C prem
1(3) B holds of no A 1,(C1)
1.2(4) B holds of no C 3,2Celarent
9
More lormally:
1(1) A does not hold of some B prem
2(2) C holds of every B prem
3(3) A holds of every C hyp
2,3 (4) A holds of every B 3,2 Barbara
1,2(5) A does not hold of some C 1,2,3,4 reductio
10
11
See 32,33 note.
In fact Alexander thinks that Aristotle uses two distinct types of exposition: see
100,17
12
note.
The formal version requires the interpolation of of few steps:
1(1) A holds of every B prem
2(2) C holds of every B prem
1(2*) B holds something 1
2+(2+) B holds of b exp
1,2+(3) A holds of b 1,2+
212 Appendix 2
Of the forty-eight possible premiss pairings, An. Pr. 1.4-6 proves fourteen
syllogistic. Moreover, Aristotle also proves that none of the remaining
thirty-four pairings yields a conclusion of the form 'A holds of C'. (The
method by which he proves pairings to be non-syllogistic has been described
in the Introduction.13) In 1.7, Aristotle signals two further developments.
He indicates a way of reducing all syllogisms to the first two syllogisms of
the first figure (i.e. to Barbara and Celarent); and he observes that there are
certain other syllogistic forms in addition to the fourteen which have been
set out in 1.4-6. For the former development it should be enough to con
Alexander's close commentary; for the latter we may refer to the long note
to 70,21 and to the descriptions in the second part of this Appendix.
II
Against each syllogistic form in the following list we have set its standard
mediaeval name. (Like most writers on syllogistic, we have found it
convenient to refer to the syllogistic forms by their traditional names.) The
names, which were collected into halting hexameters, are significant.14 The
first three vowels in each name indicate the quantity and quality of the
premisses and conclusion of the syllogism. (A marks a universal affirmative,
E a universal negative, I a particular affirmative, O a particular negative.)
The initial consonant indicates to which first figure syllogism a derived
syllogism may be reduced: a syllogism beginning with 'B' reduces to
Barbara, with 'C' to Celarent, with 'D' to Darii, with 'F' to Ferio. 'S' indicates
that the syllogism can be reduced if the premiss marked by the preceding
vowel is converted by an application of rule (Cl) or (C2); 'P' indicates a
conversion by rule (C3). A 'C' - except an initial 'C' - indicates the need for
reduction to the impossible. The other letters in the names have no
significance.15
We give first the standard fourteen syllogisms, in their three figures and
in the order in which Aristotle gives them.16
First figure
Barbara Darii
A holds of every B A holds of every B
B holds of every C B holds of some C
A holds of every C A holds of some C
The list has a double purpose: it expands the various abbreviations which
appear in the notes to the Introduction and the Translation; and it indicates
which editions of the ancient texts we have taken as standard.
Albinus
Didasc. Didascalicus [ed. Hermann, in vol. VI of the
Teubner Plato]
Alexander
in An. Pr. Commentary on Aristotle's Prior Analytics [ed.
Wallies, CAG III]
Conv.1 On Conversion [ed. Badawi (1971)]
DA On the Soul [ed. Bruns, CAG suppt II1]
Fat. On Fate [ed. Bruns, CAG suppt II2]
in Metaph. Commentary on Aristotle's Metaphysics [ed. Hay-
duck, CAG I]
Quaest. Questions [ed. Bruns, CAG suppt II2]
in Top. Commentary on Aristotle's Topics [ed. Wallies, CAG
112]
[Alexander]2
in Metaph. Commentary on Aristotle's Metaphysics [ed. Hay-
duck, CAG I]
inSE Commentary on Aristotle's Sophistical Refutations
[ed. Wallies, CAG II3]
Ammonius
in An. Pr. Commentary on Aristotle's Prior Analytics [ed.
Wallies, CAG IV 6]
in Int. Commentary on Aristotle's On Interpretation [ed.
Busse,CAGIV5]
in Porph. Isag. Commentary on Porphyry's Introduction to Philo-
sophy [ed. Busse, CAG IV 3]
[Ammonius]
in An. Pr.3 Commentary on Aristotle's Prior Analytics [ed.
Wallies, CAG IV 6]
1
We have used an English translation generously made for us by Mr. Robert
Hoyland of Pembroke College, Oxford.
2
Square brackets around an author's name mark inauthenticity: the pseudo-
Alexandrian commentary on SE is rightly ascribed to Michael of Ephesus.
3
References using upper case roman numerals pick out texts printed in the
Introduction to Wallies' edition.
219
220 Texts and Abbreviations
anonymous
in Int. An. Pr. Commentary on Aristotle's On Interpretation and
Prior Analytics [ed. Mynas (Paris, 1844)]
in Theaet. Commentary on Plato's Theaetetus [edd. Diels-
Schubart]
Logica Logic and the Quadrivium [ed. Heidberg (Copen-
hagen, 1929)]
Apollonius Dyscolus
Conj. On Conjunctions [ed. Schneider, Grammatici Graeci
III]
Synt. Syntax [ed. Schneider, Grammatici Graeci II2]
Apuleius
Dog. Plat. On Plato and his Doctrines [ed. Beaujeu, Bud6]
Int. On Interpretation [ed. Thomas, Teubner]
Aristotle
An. Pr. Prior Analytics [ed. Ross, OCT]
An. Post. Posterior Analytics [ed. Ross, OCT]
Gael. On the Heavens [ed. Allan, OCT]
Cat. Categories [ed. Minio-Paluello, OCT]
DA On the Soul [ed. Ross, OCT]
EE Eudemian Ethics [edd. Walzer-Mingay, OCT]
EN Nicomachean Ethics [ed. Bywater, OCT]
GC On Generation and Corruption [ed. Joachim (Oxford,
1922)]
HA History of Animals [ed. Dittmeyer, Teubner]
Int. On Interpretation [ed. Minio-Paluello, OCT]
Metaph. Metaphysics [ed. Ross (Oxford 1924)]
Meteor. Meteorology [ed. Fobes (Cambridge Mass., 1918)]
PA Parts of Animals [ed. Peck, Loeb]
Phys. Physics [ed. Ross, OCT]
Pol. Politics [ed. Dreizehnter (Munich, 1970)]
Rhet. Rhetoric [ed. Kassel (Berlin, 1976)]
SE Sophistical Refutations [ed. Ross, OCT]
Top. Topics [ed. Brunschwig, Bud6; Ross, OCT]
[Aristotle]
Probl. Problems [ed. Bekker (Berlin, 1831)]
Aristoxenus Harmonics [ed. da Rios (Rome, 1954)]
Boethius
in Cic. Top. Commentary on Cicero's Topics [edd. Orelli-Baiter, in
vol. V ofCiceronis Opera (Zurich, 1833)]
in Int. Commentary on Aristotle's On Interpretation [ed.
Meiser, Teubner]
Int. Syll. Cat. Introduction to Categorical Syllogisms [ed. Migne,
Patrologia Latina 64]
Syll. Cat. Categorical Syllogisms [ed. Migne, Patrologia Latina
64]
CAG Commentaria in Aristotelem Graeca
Cassius Dio Histories [ed. Boissevain (Berlin, 1895-1901)]
Cicero
Nat. Deorum On the Nature of the Gods [ed. Ax, Teubner]
CMG Corpus Medicorum Graecorum
Texts and Abbreviations 221
David
in Porph. Isag. Commentary on Porphyry's Introduction to Philo-
sophy [ed. Busse, CAG XVIII2].
Dexippus
in Cat. Commentary on Aristotle's Categories [ed. Busse,
CAG IV 2]
Diodorus Siculus History [ed. Dindorf, Teubner]
Diogenes Laertius Lives of the Philosophers [ed. Long, OCT]
Elias
in. An. Pr. Commentary on Aristotle's Prior Analytics [ed. West-
erink(1961)]
in Cat. Commentary on Aristotle's Categories [ed. Busse,
CAG XVIII1]
Proleg. Prolegomena [ed. Busse, CAG XVIII1]
Epictetus
Diss. Discourses [ed. Schenkl, Teubner]
Euclid Elements [ed. Heidberg/Stamatis, Teubner]
Eudemus
FnWehrli fragment n in Wehrli
Eusebius
PE Preparation for the Gospel [ed. Mras/des Places, Die
griechischen Christlichen Schriftsteller VIII1-2]
Eustathius
inOd. Commentary on Homer's Odyssey [ed. Stallbaum
(Leipzig, 1825/6)]
Eustratius
in An. Post. Commentary on Aristotle's Posterior Analytics [ed.
Hayduck, CAG XXII]
FDS Fragmente zurstoischen Dialektik [see Bibliography:
Hiilser]
Galen
Anat. Admin, Anatomical Procedures [ed. Kiihn (Leipzig, 1821-33)]
in Hipp. Aph. Commentary on Hippocrates' Aphorisms [ed. Kiihn
(Leipzig, 1821-33)]
in Hipp. Fract. Commentary on Hippocrates' On Fractures [ed. Kuhn
(Leipzig, 1821-33)]
in Hipp. Off. Commentary on Hippocrates' On the Surgery [ed.
Kuhn (Leipzig, 1821-33)]
Inst. Log. Introduction to Logic [ed. Kalbfleisch, Teubner]
Lib. Prop. On My Own Books [ed. von Miiller, Teubner]4
Meth. Med. On Therapeutic Method [ed. Kuhn (Leipzig, 1821-33)]
Opt. Sect. On the Best Sect [ed. Kuhn (Leipzig, 1821-33)]
PHP On the Doctrines of Hippocrates and Plato [ed. de
Lacey, CMG]5
Sem. On Semen [ed. Kuhn (Leipzig, 1821-33)]
Simp. Med. Temp. On the Mixture and Powers of Simple Drugs [ed.
Kuhn (Leipzig, 1821-33)]
Gellius Attic Nights [ed. Marshall, OCT]
Herodotus Histories [ed. Hude, OCT]
4
References are given by Kiihn numbering.
5
References are given by Kuhn numbering.
222 Texts and Abbreviations
lamblichus
Comm. Math. Sc. On the Common Science of Mathematics [ed. Festa,
Teubner]
Martianus Capella The Marriage of Philosophy and Mercury [ed. Dick,
Teubner]
Ocellus Lucanus On the Nature of the Universe [ed. Harder (Berlin,
1926)]
OCT Oxford Classical Texts
Olympiodorus
in Gorg. Commentary on Plato's Gorgias [ed. Westerink,
Teubner]
in Meteor. Commentary on Aristotle's Meteorology [ed. Stuve,
CAGXII2]
Pappus Collection [ed. Hultsche (Berlin, 1976-8)]
Papyri
PFayum Fayum Towns and their Papyri [edd. Grenfell-Hunt-
Hogarth (London, 1900)]
PGen Les Papyrus de Geneve [ed. Nicole (Geneva,
1896-1900)]
PHeid [see Bibliography: Carlini, 1978]
PMon [see Bibliography: Carlini, 1986]
POxy The Oxyrhynchus Papyri [edd. Grenfell-Hunt, et al.
(London, 1898-)]
Philodemus
Rhet. Rhetoric [ed. Longo Auricchio (Naples, 1977)]
Philoponus
in An. Pr. Commentary on Aristotle's Prior Analytics [ed.
Wallies,CAGXIII2]
in An. Post, Commentary on Aristotle's Posterior Analytics [ed.
Wallies,CAGXIII3]
in Cat. Commentary on Aristotle's Categories [ed. Busse,
CAGXIII1]
in DA Commentary on Aristotle's On the Soul [ed.
Hayduck,CAGXV]
Plato6
Rep. Republic [ed. Bury, OCT]
Plutarch
Ser. Num. On God's Slowness to Punish [edd. Pohlenz-
Sieveking, Teubner]
Stoic. Rep. On Stoic Self-contradictions [ed. Cherniss, Loeb]
Porphyry
Vit. Plot. Life ofPlotinus [edd. Henry-Schwyzer, in vol. I of the
OCT Plotinus]
Posidonius
FrcEK fragment n in Edelstein-Kidd
Proclus
inEucl. Commentary on the First Book of Euclid's Elements
[ed. Friedlein, Teubner]
in Rep. Commentary on Plato's Republic [ed. Kroll,
Teubner]
8
For all Plato's works we have used Bury's OCT.
Texts and Abbreviations 223
in Tim. Commentary on Plato's Timaeus [ed. Diehl,
Teubner]
Ptolemy
Synt. Almagest [ed. Heiberg, Teubner]
scholia to Aristotle [ed. Brandis, in vol IV of Aristotelis Opera, ed.
Bekker (Berlin, 1836)]
Seneca
Ep. Letters [ed. Reynolds, OCT]
Sextus
M Against the Mathematicians [ed. Mutschmann/Mau,
Teubner]
PH Outlines of Pyrrhonism [ed. Mutschmann/Mau,
Teubner]
Simplicius
in Cat. Commentary on Aristotle's Categories [ed. Kalbflei-
sch, CAG VIII]
in DA Commentary on Aristotle's On the Soul [ed.
Hayduck.CAGXI]
in Phys. Commentary on Aristotle's Physics [ed. Diels, CAG
IX-X]
SVF Stoicorum Veterum Fragmenta [see Bibliography:
von Arnim]
Syrianus
in Metaph. Commentary on Aristotle's Metaphysics [ed. Kroll,
CAG VII]
Themistius
Max. Reply to Maximus [ed. Badawi (1971); French trans.
inBadawi(1987)]
Theophrastus
F n Graeser fragment n in Graeser
Bibliography
The bibliography lists all the books and articles referred to in the
Introduction and in the notes to the translation. A full bibliography on
Alexander, up to 1986, can be found in Sharpies (1987); new items may be
tracked down in the regular bibliographical sections of the journal Elenchos.
Paolo Accattino: 'Alessandro di Afrodisia e Aristotele di Mitilene', Elenchos
1,1985,67-74
J. L. Ackrill: review of Patzig, Mind 71,1962,107-117
Allan Back: 'Philoponus on the Fallacy of Accident', Ancient Philosophy 7,
1987,131-146
Abdurrahman Badawi: Commentaires sur Aristote perdus en grec (Beirut,
1971)
La transmission de la philosophic grecque au monde arabe (Paris,
19872)
Jonathan Barnes: 'Aristotle's Theory of Demonstration', Phronesis 14,1969,
123-152 [reprinted in J. Barnes, M. Schofield and R. Sorabji (edd.),
Articles on Aristotle I (London, 1975)]
Aristotle's Posterior Analytics (Oxford, 1975)
review of Hintikka (1973), Journal of Hellenic Studies 1977, 97,
183-186
[1980a]: 'Proof Destroyed', in M. Schofield, M. F. Burnyeat and J.
Barnes (edd.), Doubt and Dogmatism (Oxford, 1980)
[1980b]: 'Aristotle and the Methods of Ethics', Revue Internationale de
Philosophic 133,1980,490-511
'Proof and the Syllogism', in E. Berti (ed.), Aristotle on Science: the
Posterior Analytics (Padua, 1981)
'Terms and Sentences', Proceedings of the British Academy 69, 1983,
279-326
[1985a]: Theophrastus and Hypothetical Syllogistic', in J. Wiesner
(ed.), Aristoteles: Werk und Wirkung I (Berlin, 1985)
[1985b] 'Uma terceira espcie de silogismo: Galeno e a logica das
relacdes', Andlise 2,1985,35-61
'Peripatetic Negations', Oxford Studies in Ancient Philosophy 4,1986,
201-214
'Bits and Pieces', in J. Barnes and M. Mignucci (edd.), Matter and
Metaphysics (Naples, 1988)
[1990a]: 'Logical Form and Logical Matter', in A. Alberti (ed.), Logica,
Mente e Persona (Florence, 1990)
[1990b]: 'Galen and the Utility of Logic', in J. Kollesch (ed.),
Proceedings of the Fourth International Galen Congress (Berlin, 1990)
[1990c]: The Toils of Scepticism (Cambridge, 1990)
224
Bibliography 225
[1991]: 'Ammonius and Adverbs', in H. Blumenthal and H. M.
Robinson (edd.). Aristotle and his Successors, Oxford Studies in Ancient
Philosophy, supplementary volume 1991
Albrecht Becker: Die aristotelische Theorie der Moglichkeitsschlufle (Berlin,
1933)
Oskar Becker: 'Uber die vier Themata der stoischen Logik', in his Zwei
Untersuchungen zur Antiken Logik (Wiesbaden, 1957)
Linos G. Benakis: 'Commentaries and Commentators on the Logical Works of
Aristotle in Byzantium', in R. Claussen and R. Daube-Schackat (edd.),
Gedankenzeichen: Festschrift fur Klaus Oehler zum 60. Geburtstag
(Tubingen, 1988)
I. M. Bochenski: La Logique de Theophraste (Fribourg, 1947)
Ancient Formal Logic (Amsterdam, 1951)
Formale Logik, Orbis Academicus III 2 (Freiburg/Munich, 1956)
F. Bomer: 'Der Commentarius', Hermes 81,1953, 210-250
Jacques Brunschwig: 'Observations sur les manuscrits parisiens des Topi-
ques', in G. E. L. Owen (ed.), Aristotle on Dialectic (Oxford, 1968)
'La proposition particuliere et les preuves de non-concluance chez
Aristote', Cahierspour I'Analyse 10,1969,3-26 [reprinted in A. Menne and
N. Offenberger (edd.), Zur modernen Deutung der aristotelischen Logik I
(Hildesheim, 1982)]
'L'objet et la structure des Seconds Analytiques d'apres Aristote', in
E. Berti (ed.), Aristotle on Science: the Posterior Analytics (Padua, 1981)
' "Indetermine" et "Indefini" dans la logique de Theophraste', Revue
philosophique de la France et de I'Etranger 172,1982,359-370
Walter Burkert: Lore and Science in Ancient Pythagoreanism (Cambridge
Mass., 1972)
- "Xenarchos statt Poseidonios: zu Pap. Gen. inv. 203', Zeitschrift fur
Papyrologie und Epigraphik 67,1987, 51-55
Myles Burnyeat: The Origins of Non-deductive Inference', in J. Barnes, M. F.
Burnyeat and M. Schofield (edd.), Science and Speculation (Cambridge,
1982)
Antonio Carlini: 'Su alcuni papiri "platonici"', Proceedings of the XlVth
International Congress ofPapyrologists (London, 1975)
(ed.): Papiri letterari greci (Pisa, 1978)
(ed.): Papiri letterari greci della Bayerische Staatsbibliothek di Monaco
di Baviera (Stuttgart, 1986)
John Corcoran: 'Aristotle's Natural Deduction System', in J. Corcoran (ed.),
Ancient Logic and its Modern Interpretations (Dordrecht, 1974)
F. Edward Cranz: 'Alexander Aphrodisiensis', in P. O. Kristeller (ed.),
Catalogus Translationum et Commentariorum I (Washington D.C., I960)
Marina del Fabbro: 'II commentario nella tradizione papiracea', Stadia
Papyrologica 18,1979,69-132
H. Diels and W. Schubart (edd.): Anonymer Kommentar zu Platans Theaetet,
Berliner Klassikertexte 2 (Berlin, 1905)
John Dillon: lamblichi Chalcidiensis in Platonis dialogos commentariorum
fragmenta, Philosophia Antiqua 23 (Leiden, 1973)
Pierluigi Donini: Le scuole, I'anima, I'impero (Turin, 1982)
William E. Dooley: Alexander of Aphrodisias: on Aristotle, Metaphysics 1
(London, 1989)
Heinrich Dorrie: Der Platonismus in derAntike I (Stuttgart, 1987)
226 Bibliography
Sten Ebbesen [1981a]: Commentators and Commentaries on Aristotle's
Sophistici Elenchi, Corpus Latinum Commentariorum in Aristotelem
Graecorum VII (Leiden, 1981)
[1981b]: 'Analyzing Syllogisms, or Anonymous Aurelianensis HI - the
(presumably) earliest extant Latin commentary on the Prior Analytics,
and its Greek model', Cahiers de I'Institut du Moyen-Age Grec et Latin 37,
1981,1-20
'Ancient scholastic logic as the source of mediaeval scholastic logic', in
N. Kretzmann, A. J. P. Kenny and J. Pinborg (edd.), The Cambridge
History of Later Mediaeval Philosophy (Cambridge, 1982)
- 'Philoponus, "Alexander", and the origins of mediaeval logic', in Sorabji
(1990b)
Theo Ebert: 'Zur Formulierung pradikativer Aussagen in den logischen
Schriften des Aristoteles', Phronesis 22,1977,123-145
'Warum fehlt bei Aristoteles die 4. Figur?', Archiv fur Geschichte der
Philosophic 62,1980,13-31
L. Edelstein and I. G. Kidd: Posidonius: I The Fragments, Cambridge
Classical Texts and Commentaries 13 (Cambridge, 1972)
Kevin Flannery: 'A Rationale for Aristotle's Notion of Perfect Syllogisms',
Notre Dame Journal of Formal Logic 28,1987,455-471
P. M. Fraser: Ptolemaic Alexandria (Oxford, 1972)
Michael Frede [1974a]: Die stoische Logik (Gottingen, 1974)
[1974b]: 'Stoic vs. Aristotelian Syllogistic', Archiv fiir Geschichte der
Philosophie 56, 1974, 1-32 [reprinted in his Essays in Ancient Philosophy
(Oxford, 1987)]
J. Geffcken: 'Zur Entstehung und zum Wesen des griechischen wissenschaft-
lichen Kommentars', Hermes 67,1932, 397-412
Gabriele Giannantoni: Socraticorum Reliquiae (Naples, 1983)
John Glucker: Antiochus. and the Late Academy, Hypomnemata 56 (Got-
tingen, 1978)
review of Tarrant (1985), Journal of Hellenic Studies 109,1989,272-273
H. B. Gottschalk: 'Aristotelian Philosophy in the Roman World from the time
of Cicero to the end of the second century AD', in W. Haase (ed.), Aufstieg
und Niedergang der Romischen Welt II 36.2 (Berlin, 1987)
'The earliest Aristotelian Commentators', in Sorabji (1990b)
Richard Goulet: Dictionnaire des Philosophes Antiques I (Paris, 1989)
Andreas Graeser: Die logischen Fragmente des Theophrast (Berlin, 1973)
William M. A. Grimaldi: Aristotle, Rhetoric I: a commentary (New York,
1980)
A. Gudeman: 'Scholien', Pauly-Wissowas Realencyclopaedie IIA (Stuttgart,
1923), 625-704
Ilsetraut Hadot: 'Les introductions aux commentaires ex6getiques chez les
auteurs n^oplatoniciens et les auteurs Chretiens', in M. Tardieu (ed.), Les
regies de ^interpretation (Paris, 1987)
Pierre Hadot: 'Les divisions des parties de la philosophic dans 1'antiquite',
Museum Helveticum 36,1979,201-223
B. J. Hijmans: 'Apuleius, Philosophus Platonicus', in W. Haase (ed.), Aufstieg
und Niedergang der Romischen Welt II 36.1 (Berlin, 1987)
Jaakko Hintikka: Time and Necessity (Oxford, 1973)
'Aristotelian Induction', Revue Internationale de la Philosophie
133/134,1980,422-439
and U. Remes: The Method of Analysis (Dordrecht, 1974)
Bibliography 227
Karlheinz Hiilser: Die Fragmente zur Dialektik der Stoiker (Stuttgart,
1987-88)
Katerina lerodiakonou: Analysis in Stoic Logic (diss. London, 1990)
Werner Jaeger: review of Merki, in his Scripta Minora II (Rome, 1960)
E. Kapp: 'Syllogistic', in J. Barnes, M. Schofield and R. Sorabji (edd.), Articles
on Aristotle I (London, 1975)
I. G. Kidd: Posidonius: II The Commentary, Cambridge Classical Texts and
Commentaries 14 (Cambridge, 1988)
John S. Kieffer: Galen's Institutio Logica (Baltimore, 1964)
William and Martha Kneale: The Development of Logic (Oxford, 19848)
Erich Lamberz: 'Proklos und die Form des philosophischen Kommentars', in
J. Pepin and H. D. Saffrey (edd.), Proclus, lecteur et interprete des anciens
(Paris, 1987)
Jonathan Lear: Aristotle and Logical Theory (Cambridge, 1980)
Tae-Soo Lee: Die griechische Tradition der aristotelischen Syllogistik in der
Spatantike, Hypomnemata 79 (Gb'ttingen, 1984)
A. C. Lloyd: Form and Universal in Aristotle (Liverpool, 1981)
The Anatomy ofNeoplatonism (Oxford, 1990)
A. A. Long: 'Reply to Jonathan Barnes: "Epicurean Signs"', Oxford Studies in
Ancient Philosophy, supplementary volume 1988
Jan Lukasiewicz: Aristotle's Syllogistic (Oxford, 19572)
John Lynch: Aristotle's School (Berkeley, 1972)
Henry Maconi: 'Late Greek Syllogistic', Phronesis 30,1985,92-98
Heinrich Maier: Die Syllogistik des Aristoteles (Tubingen, 1899/1900)
Italo Mariotti: Aristone d'Alessandria (Bologna, 1966)
Miklos Maroth: Ibn Sina und die Peripatetische 'Aussagenlogik' (Budapest,
1989)
Benson Mates: Stoic Logic (Berkeley, 19612)
H. P. F. Mercken: 'The Greek Commentators on Aristotle's Ethics', in Sorabji
(1990b)
H. Merki: Homoiosis Theoi (Fribourg, 1952)
Mario Mignucci: Aristotele: gli Analitici Primi (Naples, 1969)
'Hos epi to polu et necessaire dans la conception aristotelicienne de la
science', in E. Berti (ed.), Aristotle on Science: the Posterior Analytics
(Padua, 1981)
'La teoria della quantificazione del predicate nell'antichita classica',
Anuario Filosofico 16,1983,11-42
Paul Moraux: Der Aristotelismus bei den Griechen, Peripatoi 5 and 6 (Berlin,
1973/1984)
Le Commentaire d'Alexandre d'Aphrodisie aux 'Seconds Analytiques'
d'Aristote, Peripatoi 13 (Berlin, 1979)
[1986a]: 'Diogene Laerce et le Peripatos', Elenchos 7,1986,245-294
[1986b]: 'Les debuts de la philologie aristotelicienne', in G. Cambiano
(ed.), Storiografia e dossografia nella filosofia antica (Turin, 1986)
Ian Mueller: 'Stoic and Peripatetic Logic', Archiv fur Geschichte der Philos-
ophie 51,1969,173-187
'Greek Mathematics and Greek Logic', in J. Corcoran (ed.), Ancient
Logic and its Modern Interpretations (Dordrecht, 1974)
Iwan von Mueller: Uber Galens Werk vom wissenschaftlichen Beweis,
Abhandlungen der koniglichen Bayerischen Akademie der Wissenschaf-
ten 20 (Munich, 1897)
228 Bibliography
Vivian Nutton: 'Galen in the Eyes of his Contemporaries', Bulletin of the
History of Medicine 58,1984, 315-324
'Galen's Philosophical Testament: "On My Own Opinions"', in J.
Wiesner (ed.) Aristoteles: Werk and Wirkung II (Berlin, 1987)
J. H. Oliver: Marcus Aurelius - Aspects of Civic and Cultural Policy in the
East, Hesperia supplement 13 (Princeton, 1970)
Dominic O'Meara: Pythagoras Revived (Oxford, 1989)
Giinther Patzig: Aristotle's Theory of the Syllogism (Dordrecht, 1968)
R. Pfeiffer: A History of Classical Scholarship (Oxford, 1968)
Shlomo Pines: 'Omne quod movetur necesse est ab aliquo moveri: A
refutation of Galen by Alexander of Aphrodisias and the Theory of
Motion', Isis 52,1960,21-54 [reprinted in his Studies in Arabic Versions of
Greek Texts and in Mediaeval Science (Jerusalem, 1986)]
Karl Praechter [1909a]: review of CAG, Byzantinische Zeitschrift 18, 1909,
516-538 [reprinted in his Kleine Schriften (Hildesheim, 1973); English
translation in Sorabji (1990b)]
[1909b]: review of Diels-Schubart, Gdttinger Gelehrter Anzeiger 171,
1909, 530-547 [reprinted in his Kleine Schriften (Hildesheim, 1973)]
Carl Prantl: Geschichte derLogik imAbendlande (Leipzig, 1855)
E. Puglia: 'La filologia degli Epicurei', Cronache Ercolanesi 12,1982,19-34
Nicholas Rescher: Galen and the Syllogism (Pittsburgh, 1966)
Joyce Reynolds: Aphrodisias and Rome, Journal of Roman Studies mono-
graph 1 (London, 1982)
Marcel Richard: 'Apo Phones', Byzantion 20,1950,191-222
Lynn E. Rose: Aristotle's Syllogistic (Springfield, 1968)
W. D. Ross: Aristotle's Prior and Posterior Analytics (Oxford, 1949)
D. M. Schenkeveld: 'Stoic and Peripatetic Kinds of Speech Act and the
Distinction of Grammatical Moods', Mnemosyne 37,1984,291-353
D. N. Sedley: 'Philosophical Allegiance in the Greco-Roman World', in
M. Griffin and J. Barnes (edd.), Philosophia Togata (Oxford, 1989)
R. W. Sharpies: 'Alexander of Aphrodisias: Problems about Possibility I',
Bulletin of the Institute of Classical Studies 29,1982,91-108
'Alexander of Aphrodisias: Problems about Possibility II', Bulletin of the
Institute of Classical Studies 30,1983, 99-110
'Alexander of Aphrodisias: Scholasticism and Innovation', in W. Haase
(ed.),AufstiegundNiedergangderRomischen Welt II 36.2 (Berlin, 1987)
-The School of Alexander?', in Sorabji (1990b)
Ineke Sluiter: Ancient Grammar in Context (Amsterdam, 1990)
Timothy Smiley: 'What is a Syllogism?', Journal of Philosophical Logic 2,
1973,136-154
Robin Smith: 'What is Aristotelian Ecthesis?', History and Philosophy of
Logic 3,1982,113-127
Aristotle: Prior Analytics (Indianapolis, 1989)
Richard Sorabji [1990a]: The ancient commentators on Aristotle', in Sorabji
(1990b)
:(ed.) [1990b]: Aristotle Transformed (London, 1990)
Jiirgen Sprute: Die Enthymemtheorie der aristotelischen Rhetorik (Got-
tingen, 1982)
Gisela Striker: 'Aristoteles iiber Syllogismen "aufgrund einer Hypothese" ',
Hermes 107,1979,33-50
G. Strohmaier: 'Al-Iskander al-Afrudisi', in G. van Donzel (ed.), Encyclo-
paedia of Islam W (Leiden, 19782)
Bibliography 229
Eleonore Stump: Dialectic and its Place in the Development of Mediaeval
Logic (Ithaca, 1989)
M. W. Sullivan: Apuleian Logic (Amsterdam, 1967)
Leonardo Taran: 'Amicus Plato sed magis arnica veritas', Antike und
Abendland 30,1984,93-124
Harold Tarrant: 'The Date of anon. In Theaetetum', Classical Quarterly 33,
1983,161-187
Scepticism or Platonism ? (Cambridge, 1985)
Pierre Thillet: Alexandre d'Aphrodise: Traite du Destin (Paris, 1984)
Paul Thorn: The Syllogism (Munich, 1981)
E. Thouverez: 'La IVme figure du syllogisme', Archiv fur Geschichte der
Philosophic 15,1902, 49-110
Robert B. Todd: 'Lexicographical Notes on Alexander of Aphrodisias'
Philosophical Terminology', Glotta 52,1974, 207-215
Alexander of Aphrodisias on Stoic Physics, Philosophia Antiqua 28
(Leiden, 1976)
E. G. Turner: Greek Papyri (Oxford, 1968)
Martin M. Tweedale: 'Alexander of Aphrodisias' Views on Universals',
Phronesis 29,1984,279-303
Mario Untersteiner: Problemi della filologia filosofica (Milan, 1980)
Hermann Usener: review of CAG, in his Kleine Schriften III (Stuttgart,
1913)
G. Volait: Die Stellung des Alexander von Aphrodisias zur aristotelischen
Schlufilehre (Bonn, 1907)
Hans von Arnim: Stoicorum Veterum Fragmenta (Leipzig, 1903-1905)
Heinrich von Staden: Herophilus: the art of medicine in early Alexandria
(Cambridge, 1989)
Maximilian Wallies: 'Zur Textgeschichte der Ersten Analytik', Rheinisches
Museum 72,1917/1918,626-632
Fritz Wehrli: Eudemos von Rhodos, Die Schule des Aristoteles 8 (Basel,
1955)
L. G. Westerink: 'Elias on the Prior Analytics', Mnemosyne 14, 1961,
126-139 [reprinted in his Texts and Studies in Neoplatonism and
Byzantine Literature (Amsterdam, 1980)]
The Greek Commentaries on Plato's Phaedo (Amsterdam, 1976)
'The Alexandrian commentators and the introductions to their
commentaries', in Sorabji (1990b)
Wolfgang Wieland: 'Die aristotelische Theorie der Konversion von
Modalaussagen', Phronesis 25,1980,109-116
Mark F. Williams: Studies in the Manuscript Tradition of Aristotle's
Analytics, Beitrage zur klassischen Philologie 161 (Konigstein, 1984)
Eduard Zeller: Die Philosophie der Griechen III i (Leipzig, 19235)
F. W. Zimmermann: Al-Farabi's Commentary and Short Treatise on
Aristotle's de Interpretatione, Classical and Mediaeval Logic Texts 3
(London, 1981)
Indexes
English-Greek Glossary
The Glossary lists all and only those English words which occur in the Greek- English
index.
absurd: atopos clear: delos
accidentally: kata sumbebekos clear, make (v.): deloun [deldtikos]
account: logos co-assume (\.)\proslambanein
accusative: aitiatikos [aprosleptos]
actual: huparkhousa co-assumption: proslpsis
add (v.): prostithenai coincide with (v.): sumpiptein
addition: prosthesis, prosthSke combination: suzugia
adjunct: prosrSsis combine (v.): suzeugnunai
affirm (v.): kataphaskein common: koinos
affirmation: kataphasis common usage: sunetheia
affirmative: kataphatikos common use, in: suneth&s
agree (v.): homologein complementarily: enallax, parallax
agreement: hotnologema compound (v.): suntithenai
aim: skopos compounded, be (v.): sunkeisthai
alter together with (v.): summetaballein compounding: sunthesis
analyse (v.): analuein concede (v.): sunkhdrein
analysis: analusis conclude (v.):perainein, sumperainein
analytic: analutikos conclusion: sumperasma
annex (v.): prostithenai conditional: sunGmmenon
apply to (v.): harmozein, epharmozein conflict: makM
appropriate: oikeios conflict (v.): makhesthai
argument: logos congruous: katalUlos
art: tekhne conjectural: stokhastikos
aspect: skhesis conjunction: sumploke
assert (v.): apophainein connect (v.): suntattein
assertion: apophansis connection: suntaxis
assertoric: apophantikos construct (v.): sunistanai
assume (v.): lambanein [lepsis] construction: sustasis
assumption: Umma contingent, be (v.): endekhesthai
authoritative: kurios continue (v.): epipherein
axiom: axioma continuous: sunekMs
contradiction: antiphasis
beginning: arkhS contradictory: antikeimenon, anti-
betoken (v.): d&loun phatikos
contradictory pair: antiphasis
cancel (v.): anairein [anairetikos] contrary: enantios
case: ptosis contribute (v.): suntelein
change (v.): metapiptein [summeta- converse: antistrophe
piptein, summetaskhematizein] conversion: antistropM
230
English-Greek Glossary 231
convert from (v.): antistrephein + pros external: exothen
convert with (v.): antistrephein + dative extreme: akron
co-ordinate (v.): antidiairein
co-predicate (v.Y.proskategorein fal\(v.):piptein
counterpredicate (v.): antikategorein fall in (v.): peripiptein
false -.pseudes
deduce (v.): sunagein figure: skhema
deduction: sunagdge find (v.): heuriskein
deductive: sunaktikos follow from (v.): akolouthein, hepesthai
define (v.): horizein form: eidos [eidopoiein]
definition: horismos
definitional: horistikos general: koinos
demand: attests genus :genos
demand (v.): apaitein give (an account oO (v.): apodidonai
demonstrate (v.): apodeiknunai [.apodosis]
demonstration: apodeixis greater length, at: epi pleon
demonstrative: apodeiktikos
deny (v.): apophanai, apophaskein help: boetheia
destroy (v.): anairein hold (of) (v.): huparkhein [sunuparkhein,
determination: diorismos asunuparktos]
determine (v.): diorizein homonymous: homonumos
diagram: katagraphe homonymy: homonumia
dialectical: dialektikos hypothesis: hupothesis
difference: diaphora hypothesize (v.): hupotithenai
differentia: diaphora hypothesized, be (v.): hupokeisthai
directly: autothen hypothetical: hupothetikos
discovery: heuresis
disjoin (v.): apozeugnunai, diazeugnunai immediately: eutheos, euthus
disjoint: diairetikos imperfect: ateles
disjunctive: diazeuktikos implication: akolouthia
disposition: hexis impossible: adunatos
disprove (v.): diaballein include (v.)-.periekhein
dispute (v.): amphisbetein incongruous: akatallelos
dissimilar in form: anomoioskhemon indemonstrable: anapodeiktos
distinguish (v.): diairein, khorizein indeterminate: adioristos
divide (v.): diairein indicate (v.): endeiknunai
doctrine: doxa indifferent: adiaphoros
duplicated: diphoroumenos individual: atomos
indivisible: adiairetos, atomos
encompass (v.): perilambanein [perilep- induction: epagoge
sis, sumperilambanein] infer (v.): epipherein
end: telos inferior: kheiron
equal: isos inseparable: akhoristos
equivalent: isos instrument: organon
equivalent, be (v.): ison dunasthai, intelligible: noetos
isodunamein introduce (v.): paralambanein [sum-
establish (v.): kataskeuazein paralambanein]
example: paradeigma investigate (v.): zetein
exceed (v.): huperballein, huperek-
piptein, huperekhein, huperpiptein justification: pistis
excel (v.): pleonektein justified: pistos
existence: huparxis justify (v.):pisteuein,pistousthai
explanation: aitia
explanatory: aitios keep (v.): terein
exposition: ekthesis [ekthetikos] knowledge: gnosis, episteme
expression: lexis known: gndrimos
232 Indexes
laid down, be (v.): keisthai position: thesis
last: eskhatos possible: dunatos
link (v.): sunaptein possible, be (v.): dunasthai, endekhesthai
logic: logike predicate: kategoroumenon
logical: dialektikos predicate (v.): kategorein
predication: kategoria
major: meizon predicative: kategorikos
mark (v.): menuein [menutikos] prefix (v.): protattein
material: hulikos premiss: protasis
material instance: hule present (v.): apodidonai [apodosis]
matter: hule preserve (v.): phulattein
mean (v.): deloun, menuein, semainein primary: proegoumenos
[deldtikos, semantikos} principle: arkhe
metaphor: metaphora privative: steretikos
method: methodos problem: problema
middle: mesos proof: deixis, elenkhos
minor: elation proper characteristic: to idion
mode: tropos propose (v.): protithenai
proposition: protasis
name: onoma propound (v.): proteinein
necessary: anankaios prove (v.): deiknunai [deiktikos],
necessity: ananke elenkhein
need(v.):endem purpose: prothesis
negation: apophasis purpose (v.): protithenai
negative: apophatikos put(v.): tithenai
non-different: adiaphoros
non-syllogistic: asuilogistos quality: poion,poiotes
quantity: poson
object (v.): enistastkai question, be in (v.): prokeisthai
obtain (v.): euporein
obvious: enarges rank: taxis
opposed to, be (v.): antikeisthai rank(v.): tattein
opposite: antikeimenon reason: aitia
opposition: antithesis re-assume (v.): metalambanein
order: taxis reduce (v.): anagein, apagein
order (v.): tattein reduction: anagoge, apagoge
outside, from: exothen redundant, be (v.): parelkein
own: oikeios reference: anaphora
refutation: elenkhos
paradigm: paradeigma [para- refute (v.): elenkhein
deigmatikos] reject (v.): anairein [anairesis, sun-
part: meros, morion anairein]
participate (v.): metekhein relation: skhesis
particular: enmerei, epi merous, kata reliable: dokimos
meros remain (v.): menein
perception: aisthgsis [aisthetos, reputable: endoxos
aisthetikos] request: erotesis
perfect: teleios request (v.): erdtan
perfect (v.): epitelein, teleioun reveal (v.): ekkaluptein
perfection: teleiosis right, in its own: kath' hauto
permutation: metathesis
place (v.): tithenai same genus, of the: homogenes
plausible: pithanos say (v.): legein
point at issue: prokeimenon science: episteme
posit: thesis seek (v.): zetein [zgtesis]
posit (v.): tithenai separate (v.): khdrizein
English-Greek Glossary 233
separated: khoristos superior: beltion
separative: khoristikos suppose (v.): hupotithenai
set down (v.Y.paratithenai [parathesis] supposed, be (v.): keisthai, hupokeisthai
set out (v.): ektithenai supposition: keimenon
set out, be (v.): ekkeisthai syllogism: sullogismos
share (v.): koinonein [koinonia] syllogistic: sullogistikos
shared: koinos syllogize (v.): sullogizein
show (v.): deiknunai [deiktikos]
sign: sGmeion take (v.): lambanein
signify (v.): semainein [semantikos] term: horos
similar in form: homoioskhemon theorem: theorema
single-assumption: monolemmatos theoretical: theor&ikos
sophist: sophistes theorise (v.): theorem
sophistical: sophistikos theory: thedria
sound: hugies transform (v.): metalambanein
species: eidos transformation: metalepsis
starting-point: arkM 'tropic': tropikon
statement: axioma true: alethes [sunaUtheuein]
strict: kurios
study: pragmateia unclear: ad&los
study (v.):pragmateuesthai universal: katholikos, katholou
subaltern: hupallelos unmethodical: amethodos
subcontrary: hupenantios unreliable: adokimos
subject for, be (v.): hupokeisthai utterance: logos
subject for, make (v.): hupotithenai
subordinate (v.): hupotattein verb: rhema
subpart: morion
subsistence: hupostasis wider extension, of: epipleon
substance: ousia whole: holokleros
subsume (v.): hupagein whole, in as in a: en holoi
s\Aayl\ogistical:huposullogistikos word: onoma,phdnS
Greek-English Index
Wallies' edition of in An. Pr. contains an adequate index verborum, and we have not
thought it necessary to duplicate his work: this Index limits itself, with a few
exceptions, to Alexander's logical terminology (but it understands the word 'logical' in
a generous sense). We have not listed every occurrence of every logical term in our
portion of in An. Pr. Where a word occurs more than about twenty-five times, we have
given the first six or seven occurrences and then indicated (by a figure printed in bold
type and between square brackets) approximately how many examples of the word a
complete list would contain. (The listings exclude occurrences in lemmata or citations
from Aristotle's text.) The Ibycus system, which we used in making this Index, is
widely available; and any reader who wishes to scan all the occurrences in our text of,
say, the word 'sullogismos' will find it far easier to consult Ibycus than to contemplate
a sequence of 290 numerical references.
For each Greek word we have given the English translation or translations which
we have normally used. (Note that the translations are normal and not invariable.) In
a few cases we have indicated that a word is normally paraphrased rather than
translated: we set between angle brackets the word or words normally used in the
paraphrase.
adelos, unclear, 5,29.31; 18,24 akolouthein, to follow, 17,31; 20,32;
adiairetos, indivisible, 81,21.22 21,7; 35,16; 55,10.10; 87,13;
adiaphoros, non-different, indifferent, 112,12.30
18,17; 72,18 akolouthia, implication, 7,1; 11,20;
adioristos, indeterminate, 11,19; 13,30; 17,30
27,18; 30,29; 49,14.15; 51,25 [70] akron, extreme, 33,27; 46,19.21;
adokimos, unreliable, 52,24.24; 56,25; 47,3.4.11.15 [50]
62,5; 64,21; 65,1; 85,22; 104,19.20 alettes, true, 5,13; 6,9.10;
adunatos, impossible, 22,11; 24,6.12.16; 8,24.25.26.27.29 [130]
31,10.11; 33,11 [125] amethodos, unmethodical, 21,30;
aisthesis, perception, 4,4; 5,7; 33,1; 22,18.24; 24,1.9; 68,23.32
99,32; 100,1 amphisbetein, to dispute, 43,8.26;
aisthetikos, perceptual, 32,33; 33,14; 44,14.15
113,1 anagein, to reduce, 7,18.25; 24,5; 58,21;
aisthetos, perceptible, 4,3.6.9; 32,33; 77,4; 98,26; 100,31 [65]
33,2.3; 53,23; 100,4.5.7.12.17.22.23; anagoge, reduction, 7,12.26.31; 97,29;
101,5; 104,4 113,16; 115,14.17.36; 118,20.25.28
aitesis, demand, 14,2; 43,21 anairein, to destroy, to reject, to cancel,
aitia, reason, explanation, 5,8; 17,24; 22,27.27.28.28; 24,16; 31,13.14;
21,13.13.15.16 [30] 50,31; 55,31; 56,2.5.30; 57,2; 64,3.9;
aitiatikos, accusative, 9,7.8 87,25; 88,25; 90,10.26.28; 91,9; 105,6;
aitios, explanatory, 8,16; 10,29; 14,13; 107,21; 112,29
21,17.21; 23,2; 24,2.16; 42,23; 47,22; anairesis, rejection, 30,24; 36,5; 77,24;
55,18; 67,17; 68,16; 75,18; 83,14; 84,26
87,20; 94,6.22; 95,4; 96,9; 101,19; anairetikos, <cancel>, 55,26; 90,8.12;
104,32; 106,30; 107,16 91,25.32
akatallelos, incongruous, 15,24 analuein, to analyse,
akhdristos, inseparable, 4,13; 26,19.20 7,15.20.22.22.23.25
234
Greek-English Index 235
analusis, analysis, 6,28; 53,2.5; 54,6; 69,24
7,12.13.14.19.26.27; 58,19; 97,29.30 apodosis, <apodidonai>, 9,8; 10,7;
analutikos, analytic, 4,30; 14,28
6,15.30.32.33; 7,11.27; 8,1.2; 9,6; apophainein, to assert, 5,22
11,9; 12,3.23; 14,13.19; 25,12; 42,24; apophanai, to deny, 91,22
110,20 apophansis, assertion,
anankaios, necessary, 4,11.18; 8,33; 10,13.16.17.27.27; 11,7.8.28
9,25; 12,24; 17,27.28 [115] apophantikos, assertoric, 10,19.30;
ananke, necessity, 2,1; 7,3; 17,26.31.32; 11,12; 14,2; 27,8
20,32; 21,2 [50] apophasis, negation, 10,6.25.30;
anaphora, reference, 2,10.12.14.17.35; 11,5.13.15.23.23.27.27; 13.22.26;
3,16.24; 8,5 14,3; 15,11.13.27.28.32.34; 16,2.4;
anapodeiktos, indemonstrable, 6,25; 22,16.16; 37,7; 41,14; 72,22
24,4.11; 49,5; 54,12; 55,3; 60,21.25; apophaskein, to deny, 73,13.18;
69,28; 70,3; 77,5.16; 79,7; 83,13; 74,1.2.10.11.15.18.19.21.22
102.30; 110,7; 111,12.18; 113,7 apophatikos, negative, 10,18; 11,26.31;
anomoioskhemon, dissimilar in form, 13,24; 14,9; 15,10.30 [405]
70,8; 71,29; 76,21.23; 82,9.18; 86,12; apozeugnunai, to disjoin, 31,7.8.8.9;
96,5; 104,13; 106,3; 108,4; 109,9.17 34,14.14
antidiairein, to co-ordinate, 1,16.18; aprosleptos, <co-assume>, 20,18
2,12; 11,2 arkhe, principle, beginning, starting-
antikategorein, to counter-predicate, point, 4,12; 7,14.14.15.17; 8,12.14
72,23 [30]
antikeisthai, to be opposed to [anti- asullogistos, non-syllogistic, 6,22;
keimenon, opposite, contradictory], 20,14.19.23; 42,13; 47,18; 52,19 [120]
12,32.33; 15,13; 19,11.12.16.18 [95] asunuparktos, not holding at the same
antiphasis, contradictory pair, contra- time, 90,2
diction, 11,10.11; 12,28; 13,5; 14,5; ateles, imperfect, 6,25.25; 7,24; 10,1;
18,28.29.29; 19,3; 31,17; 36,5.6.12; 23,19.21.23.24 [30]
45,31; 56,1.5; 57,1; 80,1; 89,33.34; atomos, indivisible, individual,
90,15 65,24.25.28; 73,23.28; 100,14
antiphatikos, contradictory, 30,1; 31,23; atopos, absurd, 16,15; 20,27; 34,20
46,1; 99,14 autothen, directly, 6,24; 13,9; 54,18;
antistrephein, to convert [+pros, con- 116,36; 117,12.17.23; 118,19
vert from; + dative, convert with], axidma, axiom, statement, 1,19;
6,35; 28,9; 29,2.8.9.10.13 [160] 44,18.21
antistrophe, conversion, converse,
24,3.5.14; 27,23.26; 28,5.6 [140] beltion, superior, 3,6.7; 51,11.13.18;
antithesis, opposition, 29,10.16; 71,17
45,15.18.24; 46,8.9 boetheia, help, 24,10; 77,8.20.28; 78,22
apagein, to reduce, 6,4
apagoge, reduction, 24,6; 31,10.11.15; deiknunai, to prove, to show, 2,2;
34,5.17; 76,11 [55] 4,27.32.33; 5,27; 12,9.16 [345]
apaitein, to demand, 4,24; 9,7 deiktikos, <prove, show>, 34,13; 43,25;
apodeikiiunai, to demonstrate, 54,2; 75,18; 79,20; 104,23; 109,17;
12,25.32.34; 13,16; 49,9 111,18; 112,16
apodeiktikos, demonstrative, 1,4; deixis, proof, 4,22.26; 7,17; 18,21; 23,28;
9,19.21.21.22.23; 12,8.22.27; 28,14.16; 31,6 [80]
13,14.22; 14,11.19; 18,24; 20,26; delos, clear, 3,20; 5,2; 13,5; 15,12; 16,23;
28,2.27; 49,6.7.9 18,31; 28,19 [35]
apodeixis, demonstration, 2,25; deldtikos, <deloun>, 11,24; 13,30;
4,21.24.25.33; 6,10.12 [35] 15,9.11; 16,24; 18,8; 20,31; 21,4.13;
apodidonai, to give (an account of), to 26,16; 42,9.17; 59,32; 62,12; 71,6;
present, 10,14; 11,21; 76,13; 93,3
12,3.9.11.14.18; 13,13.18; 16,22; deloun, to make clear, to mean, to
23,18; 25,13.17.28; 41,5; 42,19; 44,13; betoken, 11,5; 12,16; 13,26.29; 14,23;
236 Indexes
15,28; 17,6 [40] 65,10; 68,25; 90,10; 111,26
diaballein, to disprove, 30,23; 64,3; enallax, <complementary>, 61,14;
66,27; 68,24; 88,25; 89,1.29.32; 109,14
91,3.21 enantios, contrary, 20,3; 25,15; 45,20.23;
diairein, to divide, to distinguish, 4,9; 55,25; 61,20; 81,19.19; 87,16; 90,2
7,21; 15,6.10.11.28.31; 16,2.4.5.6; enarges, obvious, 13,9; 23,12; 30,28;
36,21; 45,4; 68,31 31,13.14; 34,11.15; 54,19; 55,24;
diairetikos, disjoint, 19,4.7.12.20.29.32; 100,6; 101,5
20,3 endeiknunai, to indicate, 9,30; 12,25;
dialektikos, logical, dialectical, 1,4; 3,30; 14,25; 16,7; 17,2; 52,27; 53,28; 54,8
4,28; 7,8; 8,24; 11,21; 12,4 [30] endein, to need, 22,5; 24,9; 117,25
diaphora, difference, differentia, 4,15; endekhesthai, to be possible, to be con-
6,16.19.22; 8,6.27; 12,7 [70] tingent, 21,1.2; 25,7.8; 26,12.13.14
diazeugnunai, to disjoin, 19,22 [110]
diazeuktikos, disjunctive, 19,21.25.26 endows, reputable, 12,14.31.32; 14,5.17;
diorismos, determination, 36,26; 44,26; 18,27
65,26; 67,4; 100,13.13 en holdi, in as in a whole, 10,7; 24,22.23;
diorizein, to determine, 38,10; 51,24; 25,2.4.5.5 [30]
66,11; 67,4.6; 81,19; 93,9 enistasthai, to object, 12,29; 65,23.24
diphoroumenos, duplicated, 18,17; en merei, particular, 11,19; 13,30; 45,6;
20,11 58,27.28; 59,2.4; 93,11; 116,2;
dokimos, reliable, 52,19; 55,15; 59,14 117,1.24
doxa, doctrine, 81,27; 86,5 epagoge, induction, 20,28; 43,27.29; 44,1
dunasthai, to be possible, 4,9.11.14.17; epharmozein, to apply, 13,14.21; 34,6;
7,29.31; 8,26 [105] 111,31
dunatos, possible, 25,15; 38,7.13.19.29; epi merous, particular, 27,18;
39,17.21.24.28 30,2.3.7.8.15.16 [410]
epipherein, to infer, to continue, 13,5;
eidopoiein, to impose a form, 56,25 15,2; 18,14.24; 19,1.3.5.11.25.27.28;
eidos, form, species, 4,13; 6,17.19; 20,23.28; 33,22; 56,29; 58,12; 59,29;
7,2.3.4.4.5.20; 8,22; 11,1; 18,22.23; 60,3; 69,24; 78,25; 82,7; 102,22; 105,8
19,1.2; 22,17; 27,21; 28,26; 51,21; epipleon, at greater length, of wider
73,23.28 extension, 12,1.21; 17,29; 25,7; 41,24;
ekkaluptein, to reveal, 18,25 44,2; 47,31; 48,1; 53,23; 56,12; 61,28;
ekkeisthai, to be set out, 55,18; 56,8; 62,19; 64,19; 72,25; 74,14; 95,14
63,17; 66,1; 69,26; 75,2; 78,18; 80,10; episteme, science, knowledge, 1,6;
83,14; 85,23; 90,24; 99,21; 100,10; 2,4.5.9.11.19.23.26 [40]
101,7 epitelein, to perfect, 69,17; 115,3;
ekthesis, exposition, 32,33; 116,27; 117,20.23
33,1.13.26.30; 34,1; 54,4; 65,17.30; erotan, to request, 12,25.28.30.34;
67,11; 78,1; 89,13.15; 96,17; 99,22.32; 13,6.21; 14,1; 49,14
100,7.14.16; 103,4.6.27; 104,8; erdtesis, request, 11,22; 12,12.14.27.27;
106,20; 113,1 13,3.5.6.7; 14,4
ekthetikos, <exposition>, 34,7 eskhatos, last, 48,19; 49,20.21; 51,21;
ektithenai, to set out, 12,1; 32,30; 33,2; 65,22.28; 67,13; 77,27; 78,5;
34,21; 54,31; 55,15; 59,14; 61,18; 94,6.7.10.17; 97,8; 98,12; 113,28
98,23; 101,4.11; 102,13; 104,28; euporein, to obtain, 6,27; 12,31; 65,8;
106,11; 109,4 66,17; 75,25; 87,8.19.25;
elation, minor, 3,9; 4,31; 22,3; 39,22.26; 88,4.10.17.24.28; 89,7.30; 90,14.19;
47,29; 48,1 [230] 91,14.30; 105,5.21; 106,1.1; 107,24,27
elenkhein, to refute, to prove, 20,20; euthus (andeutheds), immediately, 5,8;
31,15; 65,3; 66,1.27; 67,23; 68,27; 8,12; 19,32; 115,2.4; 116,27; 117,19
81,6; 82,1.11; 85,23; 87,2; 89,13; exdthen, from outside, external, 16,8.9;
91,22; 92,10.30.33; 101,14; 104,19.20; 21,26; 22,2; 23,27; 24,2.7.13.13;
105,22; 107,10; 108,6; 109,26 45,2.7; 46,25; 54,8.21; 76,6; 77,21;
elenkhos, refutation, proof, 14,20; 37,24; 80,30; 84,29.22
Greek-English Index 237
genos, genus, 4,15.17; 7,2.2.3.4; supposed, to be hypothesized,
11,1.3 [35] 1,15.18.19; 4,17; 9,16.17.17 [80]
gnorimos, (well) known, 4,25; 6,24; hupostasis, subsistence, 4,10.13
10,2.6; 12,24; 13,9; 14,13 [30] huposullogistikos,subsy\logistica\,
gnosis, knowledge, 3,13.18.21.23.25; 4,1; 84,12
5,1.8.10.13.13; 6,10.10 hupotattein, to subordinate, 4,16; 10,31
hupothesis, hypothesis, 13,1.7.10; 24,17;
harmozein, to apply to, 13,27; 58,15; 42,30; 80,7.15.20.22; 83,6;
100,12 84,20.25.27.28; 93,28.29; 99,12.13;
hepesthai, to follow, 7,1.3; 13,10; 14,21; 105,13.15; 107,21; 112,17.30
17,28.29.31 [30] hupothetikos, hypothetical, 11,19; 17,8
heuresis, discovery, 1,7.12; 2,15.27.34; hupotithenai, to make subject for, to
3,11; 6,26; 8,24.29 suppose, to hypothesize, 13,11;
heuriskein, to find, 5,15; 6,27; 7,31; 8,26; 31,12.14.24; 34,9; 38,20.22 [30]
31,16; 45,18; 51,24.26; 61,29; 62,20;
64,10; 75,2.5; 81,25; 90,15; 91,25 idion, to, proper characteristic, 18,1;
hexis, disposition, 5,27; 9,18.21; 61,30; 21,15; 47,33; 48,4.5.13; 49,1; 55,22;
62,1.2.4.8; 89,17.17.18.20.21.23.23.24 63,29; 71,25; 95,10.13.19.20.23
holokleros, whole, 48,24 isodunamein, to be equivalent to, 41,12;
homogenes, of the same genus, 16,29.30; 84,13.15
72,28; 73,3.19 ison dunasthai, to be equivalent to,
homoioskhemon, similar in form, 15,18.20; 30,30; 37,8; 41,14; 44,27;
70,6.12; 71,31; 81,8; 86,19.22.23.26; 49,15; 84,7; 92,33; 94,20; 111,30;
92,3.5.8.14; 95,10; 103,9; 109,7.12 112,1
homologein, to agree, 1,10; 5,24; 18,14; isos, equal, equivalent, 11,6.9; 13,3;
31,13.14; 32,3.5.8.28.29; 33,12; 36,12; 22,4.5.6.7 [30]
44,15; 79,25; 90,14; 113,12
homologema, agreement, 44,17.20 katagraphe, diagram, 72,11; 78,4
homonumia, homonymy, 37,28 katallelos, congruous, 16,13; 67,1
homonumos, homonymous, 38,10 kata meros, particular, 49,31; 61,21;
horismos, definition, 11,21; 16,31 86,21; 109,23
horistikos, definitional, 23,6.7 kataphasis, affirmation, 10,5.23.25;
horizein, to define, 10,15.28; 11,5.13.15.26 [35]
11,15.26.30; 12,13; 14,30 [30] kataphaskein, to affirm, 73,14.19;
fcoros.term, 3,28; 6,6; 9,27; 11,9.17.23: 74,1.20.22
14,25 [205] kataphatikos, affirmative, 10,18;
hugies, sound, 17,31; 65,32; 90,6 11,24.25.31; 13,24; 14,9; 19,8 [365]
hule, material instance, matter, 4,13; kataskeuazein, to establish, 93,29;
6,17.18.20; 7,20; 12,23; 13,13 [40] 112,30
hulikos, material, 27,29 kata sumbebSkos, accidentally, 112,19
hupagein, to subsume, 44,5 kat&gorein, to predicate [kategorou-
hupallelos, subaltern, 45,26; 87.131 menon, predicate], 10,24.32;
huparkhein, to hold (of) [huparkhousa, 11,1.4.5.24.25 [120]
actual], 5,23; 20,1.1; 21,1; 22,12; katdgoria, predication, 6,35; 26,30
26,1.2 [440] kategorikos, predicative, 11,18.29; 15,3;
huparxis, existence, 4,11; 26,16.17; 38,5 17,6; 24,30; 25,26.28; 27,17.21; 42,28;
hupenantios, subcontrary, 45,24; 59,25
87,11.15; 88,32; 89,6; 91,29.31.32; kath'hauto, in its own right, 4,20; 15,17;
92,13; 105,24 17,9; 26,19; 66,15; 67,9.10.11.14;
huperballein, to exceed, 62,19 73,13.19; 74,30; 105,3; 107,28
huperekhein, to exceed, 64,20; 67,20 katholikos, universal, 22,10; 28,14.17;
huperekpiptein, to exceed, 56,21 30,28; 35,9; 74,3
huperpiptein, to exceed, 56,15.15 katholou, universal, 6,28; 10,5.5; 11,18;
hupokeisthai, to be subject for, to be 12,3.15; 13,30 [510]
keisthai, to be supposed, to be laid down
1
See also 63,13. [keimenon, supposition], 12,17; 16,20;
238 Indexes
17,28; 18,9.10.14.23 [135] metapiptein, to change, 51,12.15; 52,11
kheiron, inferior, 43,9; 51,7.31; metaphora, metaphor, 23,6.7.9.10.12
94,12.15.16; 99,3 metathesis, permutation, 93,11
khoristikos, separative, 16,31 metekhein, to participate, 5,16; 101,6
khoristos, separated, 26,19.20 methodos, method, 1,5.17; 3,14; 7,28;
khdrizein, to separate, to distinguish, 8,21; 28,3.18; 75,2.6
4,16; 15,10; 16,10.25.27.30; 18,9; monolemmatos, single-assumption,
26,21; 31,7; 45,1; 56,10; 67,14.19; 17,12.18; 18,4; 21,25; 22,24
100,18 morion, subpart, part, 1,14; 2,5;
koinonein, to share, 13,20; 16,28; 42,5; 3,7.13.32; 11,8; 15,22.30; 31,17.25;
45,11.12.12.13.14.16; 46,2.4.17.18; 33,2.3.4.5.6.7.21.22; 80,1
53,7; 68,18; 81,33; 82,1; 100,7; 101,6
koinonia, <to share>,45,9; 46,5.20.29; noetos, intelligible, 4,5.6.15
47,3.4; 56,22; 85,28; 94,7; 100,22
koinos, common, general, shared, 6,17;
10,32; 11,12.32; 12,7.9.16 [35] oikeios, appropriate, own, 2,24.25.29;
kurios, strict, authoritative, 1,7; 3,31; 3,26.27; 4,26; 5,1 [30]
22,25; 23,4.10; 36,30; 39,11; 42,29; onoma, name, word, 3,20; 9,28; 14,25.29;
47,23; 48,12.15.16; 49,9; 54,12; 17,13; 38,34; 48,3
106,18; 117,17 organon, instrument, 1,9;
2,3.15.17.18.20.21.23.28.33;
lambanein, to take, to assume,1,6; 3,4.5.8.9.12; 4,30.31; 18,20
4,13.28; 5,11; 7,17; 12,17.27 [240] ousia, substance, 3,32; 4,6.10.17; 17,1;
legein, to say, 1,9; 2,3.21.23.33; 3,4.31 22,27.27 [40]
[435]
lemma, assumption, 44,17.20 paradeigma, example, paradigm, 39,2;
lepsis, <assume>, 12,25.26; 13,19; 43,18; 44,1; 52,26.30; 68,23.24.27;
14,16; 47,13; 68,31 69,1; 71,4.5; 81,25.26; 92,30; 94,3
lexis, expression, 13,26; 16,13.16; 18,2.6; paradeigmatikos, paradigmatic, 18,11
19,19; 20,4; 21,4; 32,23; 38,6; 39,8.9; paralambanein, to introduce, 11,30;
53,8; 62,12; 66,29; 84,7.10.11.16.18; 18,21; 27,28; 45,5.7; 46,25; 77,21
93,2 parallax, complementarity, 93,8; 108,14
logike, logic, 1,3; 2,33; 3,3.7.14 parathesis, <to set down>, 55,22; 57,9;
logos, account, utterance, argument, 61,19; 63,16; 65,2; 66,28; 81,5; 86,30;
4,4.8.9.16; 6,31; 7,10.20 [130] 91,23; 92,7; 101,15; 104,19; 105,29;
106,25
makhe, conflict, 11,20 paratithenai, to set down, 39,5.19;
makhesthai, to conflict, 17,16; 52,23 53,15; 55,12; 64,14.22; 65,30 [30]
meizdn, major, 47,28.29.30; 48,4.4.6.7 parelkein, to be redundant, 23,1
[395]2 perainein, to conclude, 18,17; 21,31;
menein, to remain, 50,19; 60,6; 61,13; 22,18.24; 24,1.9; 68,23.32
63,9; 75,29; 83,16; 99,30; 115,15 periekhein, to include, 23,26; 25,3;
menuein, to mean, to mark, 26,8.15; 43,14; 44,9.28; 56,21; 64,20.21; 67,19;
55,33 85,28.29
menutikos, marking, 21,5 perilambanein, to encompass, 49,31;
meros, part, 1,8.8.9.11.14; 2,3.4 [75]3 50,5; 56,14.16.16; 62,20; 67,21.22
mesos, middle, 33,28; 45,3.7.10; perilGpsis, <encompass>, 56,15
46,19.21.23 [105] peripiptein, to fall in, 75,26
metalambanein, to transform, to re- phone, word, 84,16.17
assume, <instead>, 19,4; 22,26.30; phulattein, to preserve, 5,4; 8,29; 23,9;
54,4; 60,1.6; 65,17; 67,1; 68,6; 41,7; 45,16; 46,11; 52,22; 71,26;
84,7.10; 110,26 82,18; 94,26; 95,6.19.21; 103,10
metalepsis, transformation, <instead>, piptein, to fall, 25,4; 57,13.14; 98,7;
65,23.31; 74,28; 84,19 100,1
2
Excluding the few occurrences in which meizdn means 'greater'.
3
Excluding occurrences which form part of the phrases en merei, epi merous and kata meros.
Greek-English Index 239
pisteuein, to justify, 4,23; 43,8 9,12.20.30; 23,24; 41,33; 42,18; 44,19;
pistis, justification, 43,7.9.10.11.15.18; 99,11; 110,6
44,3.4.4.6.7.8; 48,13; 49,3; 68,20; pseudes, false, 8,28; 10,17.19; 11,20;
77,31; 84,24; 113,10 26,15; 27,5.6.9.10.11.11; 31,15.16.17;
pistos, justified, 4,25; 43,8.13.24.26.30; 41,16; 68,26; 80,7.7.11.15.19; 83,6;
84,27 84,2; 87,14; 99,12.13; 111,25
pistousthai, to justify, ptosis, case, 9,7.7.8.10
43,7.11.12.13.17.20.27; 54,19; 68,20;
77,25; 104,16 rhema, verb, 14,29
pithanos, plausible, 8,25.27; 14,17; 44,1
pleonektein, to excel, 48,28; 49,4.5; semainein, to mean, to signify, 3,21;
51,17 7,27; 10,3.5; 12,1; 15,8; 17,5.15.17;
poion, quality, 10,26; 11,10.30.31; 18,3; 36,22; 38,7.8.19.23.31.34;
45,17.20.25 [30] 39,10.15.17; 67,5; 84,17.17; 86,13
poiotes, quality, 11,32; 29,25; 42,6; semantikos, <semainein>, 11,7; 25,4;
49,18; 68,10; 73,22; 89,23.24.24 38,33; 39,3; 42,3; 98,15.21
poson, quantity, 11,30.32; 44,26; semeion, sign, 5,7; 21,14.20; 55,24;
45,17.19.26.29; 46,10.13; 48,26.27.29; 81,21; 100,8
50,9.11.25; 51,11.21.32; 85,18; semeioun, to infer, 12,2; 25,11; 38,5;
86,13.23; 95,16 62,25; 104,8
pragmateia, study, 1,3.13; 2,7.34; 3,4.6; skMma, figure, 6,16.17.19.20.21.23.27
6,29; 8,11.20.22; 14,21.23; 20,25.27; [335]
28,4.11.17.29; 29,15; 42,24 skhesis, aspect, relation, 17,30; 21,5;
pragmateuesthai, to study, 2,6.9.27; 44,18; 45,2; 47,14.21; 57,11
6,14; 8,1 skopos, aim, 8,4.15.18; 9,5; 20,25
problema, problem, 7,18; sophistes, sophist, 49,14
44,16.16.17.19.23.29; 45,1.3.4.5; sophistikos, sophistical, 1,4; 7,8; 8,28;
46,29.22.23.24.31.32; 47,6.29; 48,22; 14,16.18.20; 28,28; 49,7.8; 94,8.10
70,28; 75,23.27.33 ster&ikos, privative, 31,6; 35,23; 37,5;
proegoumenos, primary, 2,20; 8,20; 59,28.30; 67,2; 78,5.12
19,14; 69,27; 70,16; 112,14.18 stokhastikos, conjectural, 39,31
prokeisthai, to be in question [pro- sullogismos, syllogism, 2,24; 4,21;
keimenon, the point at issue], 1,3; 6,12.13.15.23.24 [290]
4,22.24; 8,9.12.13; 18,29 [55] sullogistikos, syllogistic, 1,3;
proskategorein, to co-predicate, 15,6; 6,11.16.20.22.29; 8,21 [200]
27,3; 40,19.25; 41,13 sullogizein, to syllogize, 9,22; 12,17.30;
proslambanein, to co-assume, 13,7.17; 14,3; 17,3; 21,15.19; 42,30;
19,5.6.9.24.24.26.28; 20,19.24; 21,6; 43,7.8; 64,8; 75,24.31; 77,26; 108,27;
22,2.12; 23,27; 29,11; 31,12; 34,10; 109,12.25.26; 111,3
44,2.31; 80,22; 113,24; summetaballein, to alter together with,
115,9.23.25.25; 116,13.16.20 52,20
proslepsis, co-assumption, 19,13.17.21; summetapiptein, to change together
20,9.9.14.15.21; 21,29; 22,10 with, 52,22; 56,25
prosresis, adjunct, 27,13 summetaskhematizein, to change confi-
prostheke, addition, 23,1; 24,7; 26,30; guration with, 52,22
27,3 sumparalambanein, to introduce
prosthesis, addition, 15,25.26; 21,24 together with, 11,13
prostithenai, to add, to annexe, 9,6; sumperainein, to conclude, 18,30; 21,3;
11,9; 12,7; 13,12.28; 15,5.8 [40] 49,10; 94,9
protasis, proposition, premiss, 1,19.20; sumperasma, conclusion, 7,16.17; 14,14;
6,26.27; 7,24.30; 9,26 [420] 17,23.24.27; 18,10 [120]
protattein, to prefix, 47,23; 49,4; 72,14 sumperilambanein, to encompass
proteinein, to propound, 44,15 together with, 50,6
prothesis, purpose, 1,16.20.20; sumpiptein, to coincide with, 19,15.28;
8,4.19.32; 9,5; 75,33 20,4
protithenai, to propose, to purpose, 6,31; sumploke, conjunction, 17,14; 19,22.26;
240 Indexes
42,13; 45,9; 47,11; 50,17 [65] suzeugnunai, to combine, 98,7
sunagein, to deduce, 2,1; 19,8; 21,28; suzugia, combination, 6,21; 10,7; 18,19;
22,6.9; 23,32; 24,8 [155] 21,3; 33,27; 42,4.5 [240]
sunagdge, deduction, 24,2; 35,7;
54,8.11.19.22; 55,3; 61,1.5; 72,8; tattein, to order, to rank, 14,26; 45,31;
76,11; 91,3.12; 93,28; 109,32; 111,8; 75,31; 77,6; 102,14.32
115,12 taxis, order, rank, 1,12; 2,19; 7,16; 10,30;
sunaktikos, deductive, 62,14 14,22; 41,7; 42,11 [35]
sunaletheuein, to be true together with, tehhne, art, 1,6;
29,18.22.28; 30,21.25; 41,7; 46,6.9; 2,4.5.11.16.16.17.18.19.23.29.30.33.
66,13; 88,20; 104,30; 105,30 35; 3,8.19; 39,23.31
sunanairein, to reject together with, teleios, perfect, 2,32; 6,23; 7,25; 10,1;
84,26 15,30; 16,1.5 [30]
sunaptein, to link, 56,11 teleiosis, perfection, 93,23
sunekhes, continuous, 6,1.2; 17,30; teleioun, to perfect, 78,22; 112,6.7.10;
20,14.14; 81,18 113,6
sunemmenon, conditional, 17,30; 20,17; telos, end, 1,19; 2,2.8.14.17.29; 3,13;
100,18 7,15.28; 20,25; 22,29
sunetheia, common usage, 23,10.11; terein, to keep, 16,1; 29,25; 61,2; 94,30;
54,25 97,25; 102,28
sunethes, in common use, 14,25 theorem, to theorise, 3,1.1.20.24.28;
sunistanai, to construct, 2,10; 3,23; 9,17.18
4,12; 29,5 theorema, theorem, 29,4
sunkeisthai, to be compounded, 6,15; thedretikos, theoretical, 1,14; 3,13.22;
9,26; 15,1.4.14; 81,23; 82,16; 117,32 4,7; 5,19
sunkhorein, to concede, 2,1; 3,2; 17,3.23; thedria, theory, 3,14.28; 4,1.5.12.29.34;
18,26.27; 31,22; 33,8; 50,30.30.31; 5,6.21; 6,2.6.9; 28,30
51,1.3; 90,6; 103,22 thesis, posit, position, 13,11; 16,26; 23,4;
suntattein, to connect, 15,21; 46,22; 24,16; 46,23.28; 47,22; 53,12; 57,27;
48,7.9; 51,27; 72,3.19 71,19.21; 72,13.19; 94,3; 96,9.12;
suntaxis, connection, 15,30 98,6.7.12; 105,4; 118,8.18
suntelein, to contribute, 2,15; 4,28; 8,17; tithenai, to posit, to place, to put, 2,1;
20,27; 28,1.24 4,25; 7,1.3.26; 13,9; 17,4 [40]
sunthesis, compounding, 7,12.13.14; tropikon, 'tropic', 20,7
15,8; 17,13.14.15.17.18; 42,2.14.17 tropos, mode4,26,15.18.30; 27,13;
suntithenai, to compound, 17,1; 27,22; 28,5.7.10.12.13.18.20.21.25; 40,12;
42,6.10.16; 45,5; 50,20; 52,1.7.7.14; 47,14; 53,30; 117,28
82,20
sunuparkhein, to hold at the same time, zetein, to investigate, to seek, 2,10.34;
90,11 3,1.2.11; 17,17; 23,24; 41,3; 46,33;
sustasis, construction, 1,7.12; 47,6; 70,4; 72,17; 73,25; 74,5.29
2,8.15.24.27.34; 28,25; 43,4 zetesis, <seek>, 74,28; 75,8
Numbers in bold type refer to the works cited; numbers in ordinary type refer to the
pages of this book.
ALBINUS
Didasc. 153,47n.40; 158H, 108n.36; 158-64H, 7n.51; 156-7H, 49n.50; 157H, 50
n.53; 158-9H, 31 n.137; 158-60H, 73 n.129; 158H, 49 n.49,56 n.25; 161H, 45
n.22; 179-80H, 47 n.40
ALEXANDER
inAn.Pr. 121,15-123,9,174n.36; 121,15-123,24,88n.24; 123,28-124,7, 82n.l67;
124,8-30,113 n.58; 125,3-6,7 n.52; 125,30,3 n.23; 126,1-8,87 n.20; 125,26-8,
116 n.71; 126,29-127,2,113 n.58; 127,16,3 n.23; 129,9,133 n.140; 136,1-2,109
n.41; 140,14-141,6,93 n.45; 144,4-6,53 n.3; 151,14-16,53 n.3; 155,20-25,93
n.45; 156,27-157,2,93 n.45; 158,24-161,2,99 n.66; 164,17-165,15,98 n.60;
164,23-165,6,43 n.ll; 164,30,66 n.87; 165,8-15,98 n.61; 165,10,98 n.62;
168,31-169,10,98 n.60; 173,32-174,19,113 n.58; 188,16,3 n.23; 191,17,3 n.23;
193,21,3 n.23; 199,7-10,99 n.66; 201,21-24,93 n.45; 203,3-5,133 n.140;
203,15-35,132 n.137; 207,35,3 n.23; 210,30-2,53 n.3; 213,11-27, 9 n.60;
213,26,3 n.23; 214,12-18,9 n.60; 218,20-4,99 n.66; 219,35-221,5,100 nn.68,
69; 219,35-221,13,98 n.63; 221,6,133 n.140; 221,16-227,9,100 n.67; 236,8-11,
9 n.60; 238,22-38,9 n.60,10 n.65; 238,37,3 n.23; 240,32-241,9,9 n.60;
249,15-250,2,10 n.65; 249,25-32,9 n.60; 249,38,3 n.23; 250,2,3 n.23;
256,12-14,23 n.107; 256,32-258,25,108 n.36; 257,1-4, 70 n.112; 257,6-12,64
n.71; 257,8-13,64 n.72; 258,24,23 n.107; 259,8-260,6, 77 n.148; 260,23-261,2,
73 n.127; 261,25-6,23 n.107; 262,5-9,67 n.93; 262,29-31,69 n.103; 262,32-5,65
n.79; 263,11-12,69 n.103; 263,26-36,67 n.93; 266,8-267,27,133 n.143;
266,8-270,8,101 n.l; 268,7-8,73 n.127; 270,6-8,9 n.60; 270,10-28,82 n.168;
271,16-272,10,108, n.37; 271,2-6,145 n.26; 275,32-7,49 n.50; 282,14-15,17
n.85; 283,3,17 n.85; 284,17,3 n.23; 284,20,17 n.85; 284,29,17 n.85; 297,4-23,
122 n.94; 297,22-3,105 n.25; 300,3,98 n.61; 301,9-19,139 n.7; 317,31-318,10,
77 n.148; 326,31-2,118 n.83; 328,6,3 n.23; 328,10-30,13 n.77; 329,30-330,5,82
n.168; 331,12-24,49 n.49; 340,11-12,48 n.42; 343,21-344,6, 71 n.118; 344,9-13,
65 n.78; 344,9-346,6,72 n.125; 344,27-31,65 n.78; 345,18-20,134 n.135;
346,10-14, 74 n.133; 348,29-32,64 n.67; 349,5-7,107 n.34; 350,11-16, 71 n.118;
350,30-352,26,130 n.125; 372,26-373,9,50 n.60; 372,29-30,154 n.65;
373,16-30,154 n.65; 379,20-1,65 n.78; 379,14-380,27,116 n.71; 381,8-12,139
n.7; 381,28-386,2,50 n.62; 386,5-30,67 n.93,77 n.148,102 n.5; 388,18-399,9,
136 n.157; 390,3-4,65 n.79; 390,9,3 n.23; 392,19-26,31 n.139; 406,32-5,62
n.55,105 n.26; 411,35-7,82 n.168; 414,9-10,116 n.71; 415,10-12,116 n.71
Coreu. 83 n.l; 56,48 n.43; 56-7,108 n.36; 57-9,49n.49; 59,51 n.68; 60,4 n.25,83
n.4,136 n.157; 60-1,83 n.5; 61,85 n.12,116 n.71; 63,84 n.10,89 n.27,90 n.34;
64-5,87 n.19; 65,86 n.14,90 n.33; 65-6,91 n.38; 66-8,85 n.12; 69,84 n.ll;
69-74,84 n.ll; 76-7,92 n.41
DA 2,4-9,9 n.62; 90,2-9,67 n.90; 90,10-91,6,47 n.40
Fat. 164,1-3,1 n.l; 164,14-15,1
in Metaph. 1,10-2,3,46 n.29; 2,3-21,47 n.34; 2,24-5,13,46 n.31; 17,5-18,14,47 n.34;
241
242 Indexes
18,5-13,44 n.18; 260,1-20,49 n.49; 72,9-12,45 n.21; 103,5-104,18,44 n.16;
208,28-209,34,55 n.17; 351,9-15,72 n.122; 415,29-31,1 n.3; [531,25-6], 2 n.6
Quaest. 4,4-7,49 n.50; 61,1-28, 98 n.61; 141,2-4,47 n.34.
in Top. 2,6,23 n.107; 2,15-3,24,49 n.49; 2,16-29,116 n.71; 2,20-23,41 n.3; 2,23-25,
41 n.3; 2,25-26,41 n.3; 7,10-15,14,63 n.62; 7,11,4 n.25; 8,8-14,65 n.67;
8,14-9,19, 64 n.72,65 n.75; 8,29-9,5,74 n.136; 9,5-8,65 n.78; 9,17-19,64 n.74;
9,20-10,16,43 n.ll; 10,7-10, 66 n.88; 10,8-13,66 n.87; 10,14-16, 70 n.112;
10,26-8,49 n.49; 10,28-30, 70 n.lll; 10,30-13,10, 67 n.92; 11,23-7,69 n.104;
12,10-24,55 n.14; 12,31-13,10,66 n.81,68 n.96; 13,25-8,65 n.75; 13,28-14,2, 74
n.136; 14,17-15,14, 72 n.125; 22,10-14, 41 n.3; 23,21,105 n.21; 27,7-31, 44 n.14;
27,24-31,51 n.67; 32,12-34,5,98 n.61; 40,13-41,16,104 n.18; 62,6-13,103 n.7;
69,13-70,11, 58 n.32; 74,29-75,3,41 n.5; 86,21-87,6,104 n.16; 174,5-176,26,131
n.128; 190,26-193,7,83 n.5; 191,6-12,83 n.l; 257,22-3,80 n.158; 264,19,84 n.8;
288,13-289,8,86 n.13; 302,23-304,6,67 n.89; 321,26-8,67 n.90; 367,16-20,49
n.47; 421,3-34,63 n.64; 425,16-426,5,75 n.139; 566,25-7,66 n.87; 566,25-31,
70 n.112; 568,18-23, 74 n.136; 574,10-15,65 n.75; 582,23-6,83 n.l; 584,9-12,41
n.5
[ALEXANDER]
inSE 50,8-52,28, 74 n. 137
AMMONIUS
in An. Pr. 1 n.53; 2,18-3,30,49 n.49; 4,36-7,53 n.l; 5,5-7,25,48 n.42; 5,10-6,2-4,50
n.57; 7,6-14,108 n.36; 7,25,49 n.50; 8,15-11,21,41 n.l; 9,26-7,42 n.7;
9,37-10,1,43 n.9; 12,6-10, 53 n.4; 13,17-14,4,55 n.12; 14,13-22, 61 n.48;
15,30-16,9,55 n.12; 17,10-32,57 n.28; 19,3-21,30, 58 n.32; 22,12-30,61 n.51;
22,34-24,24,61 n.52; 23,25-24,5,61 n.54; 26,2-6,64 n.74; 26,6,65 n.76; 26,30-3,
64 n.66; 26,34-27,4,104 n.20; 27,6-14,64 n.67; 27,14-33, 64 n.72,65 n.75;
27,34-28,20,66 n.83; 27,35-28,5,66 n.88; 28,5-9,66 n.87; 28,21-29,19,103 n.7;
28,23-5,104 n.13; 28,32-29,2,104 n.12; 29,20-34, 71 n.116; 31,11-32,7,6 n.45;
31,14-32,7,75 n.141; 31,15,7 n.54; 31,22-3, 75 n.141; 32,12-14,66 n.87; 32,13,
66 n.88; 32,30-3, 75 n.141; 33,28-34,5, 78 n.152; 35,7-36,15,83 n.l; 36,8,106
n.28
in Int. 2,9-3,6,64 n.66; 2,21-5,55 n.13; 3,7-15,23 n.107; 3,19-20, 67 n.93; 5,1-23,64
n.66; 7,32-8,4,61 n.51; 9,7-10,59 n.37; 10,2-4,104 n.20; 14,18-26,62 n.56;
14,22-5, 61 n.49; 15,16-30, 56 n.18; 22,18-24,61 n.49; 27,1-3, 61 n.53; 44,11-19,
62 n.59; 57,29-32,62 n.56; 62,10-12,62 n.59; 64,26-65,2,64 n.66; 66,14-28,56
n.18; 67,30-68,9,56 n.18; 70,7, 31 n.135; 77,13-15,26 n.118; 80,15-35, 56 n.18;
80,31-5, 57 n.28; 81,13-84,25,26 n.118; 87,13,31 n.135; 88,12-28,80 n.160;
89,2-36,105 n.25; 90,19-20,29 n.127; 91,4-93,18,27 n.121,106 n.29; 94,7-24,
29 n.127; 100,21-3,86 n.13; 101,14-108,36,122 n.94; 106,13-16,86 n.13;
111,10-120,12,86 n.13; 114,22-3,19 n.93; 118,7-8,29 n.127; 122,20-26,19
n.93; 153,13-15,79 n.157; 153,13-26,93 n.45; 161,11-16,84 n.6; 165,4-30,61
n.54; 165,10-16,105 n.26; 181,5-7,45 n.26; 185,14-18,86 n.14; 194,15,84 n.8;
214,31-215,3,82 n.168; 215,7-28,80 n.160; 221,11-229,11,99 n.64; 240,7-13,93
n.45; 246,9,19 n.93; 249,1-25,45 n.26; 251,31,189 n.17 257,10-13,133 n.140;
257,30-258,4,19 n.93; 272,3,83 n.6
in Porph. Isag. 36,7-9,50 n.57; 37,7-13,49 n.52
[AMMONIUS]
in An. Pr. VIiI.20-21,139 n.7; VIII.24-5,139 n.7; IX.22-XI.36,102 n.5; X.10-XI.1,
139 n.7; XII.10-16,134 n.144; XIII, 191 n.23; 38,38-39,2,113 n.58; 39,2,7 n.54;
39,9 (app.crit), 139 n.7; 39,31,7 n.52; 40,2-40,113 n.58; 43,30-1, 7 n.54;
45,42-46,1, 99 n.66; 68,8-13, 70 n.lll; 68,6-7,69 n.103; 68,7-13,67 n.93; 68,28,
83 n.5; 70,11-13, 72 n.125; 70,20-22,134 n.145; 71,3-4,134 n.145
ANONYMOUS
in Int. An. Pr. 100,100 n.68
in Theaet. 7,14, 47 n.40; 66,12-43, 73 n.129
Logica62, 74n.l37
Index of Passages 243
APOLLONIUS DYSCOLUS
Synt. 265,9-10,50 n.56; 326,11-327,12,50 n.56
APULEIUS
Dog. Plat. 126,3-6,47 n.40
Int. 1 n.50; 176,1-3,41 n.4; 176,13-14,62 n.59; 177,3-10,56 n.25; 177,15-17,86
n.13; 178,1-18,61 n.49; 179,16-181,17,106 n.29; 181,6,19 n.93; 181,19-183,6,
83 n.l; 183,15-21,110 n.47; 183,22-6,104 n.20; 184,19-23,65 n.75; 184,23-31,
66nn.87,88; 185,10-20,103 n.7,104nn.l2,13; 185,23-186,10, 111 n.54; 186,5,
12 n.75; 186,5-10,112 n.57; 188,4-11,48 n.45; 189,19-27,168 n.18; 189,23-5,
136 n.157; 190,15-191,5,145 n.30; 190,25-191,5,170 n.21; 192,30-193,5,31
n.137; 193,7-13,136 n.157; 193,9-16,113 n.62; 193,16-20,136 n.157; 194,23,12
n.75
ARISTOTLE*
An. Pr. 24alO-ll, 71 n.113; 24alO-15,51 n.66; 24al2-13, 76 n.143; 24al7,60 n.41,
81 n.162; 24a30-bl, 60 n.43; 24blO-12,60 n.45; 24bl8-22,75 n.142,104 n.17,
154 n.67; 24b20,134 n.147; 24b22-6,144 n.25; 24b23-4,135 n.149; 24b26-8,
116 n.72; 25al4-17,147 n.40; 25a20-22, 88 n.22; 25a29-34,92 n.41; 25a38-9,
93 n.43; 25bl4-15, 95 n.55; 25bl9-25,99 n.64; 25b22, 61 n.54; 25b27,102 n.4;
25b29,49 n.48; 25b30,48 n.41; 25b32-5,107 n.34; 26a2-9,124 n.113,131
n.131,175 n.40,185 n.4; 26a9-12,12 n.76; 26al3-14,121 n.92; 26al5,17 n.85;
26al7-29,127 n.116; 26a20-21,127 n.lll; 26a25-8,174 n.39; 26a28-30,113
n.62; 26a29-30,86 n.13; 26a30-31,123 n.95; 26a36-9,185 n.4; 26blO-16,159
n.86; 26bll-13,132 n.139; 26bl4-20,159 n.85; 26b21-5,129 n.121,164 n.100;
26b33,135 n.152; 27a5-9,145 n.32; 27a5-14,121 n.93,169 n.19,189 n.19;
27a9-14,146 n.34; 27al8-20,159 n.84; 27a20,156 n.76; 27a20-23,158 n.82;
27a23,164 n.103; 27a23-5,151 n.58; 27a26-b2,163 n.98; 27a32-6,157 n.81,
189 n.20; 27a36-bl, 190 n.21; 27a36-b3,170 n.20,173 n.30; 27b3-36,163 n.99;
27b4-6,154 n. 70; 27b6-8,151 n.55,185 n.4; 27b20-3,132 n.137; 27b27-9,132
n.137; 28al6,145 n.26; 28al7-23,191 n.24; 28al8-22,194 n.34; 28al8-23,188
n.12; 28a22-26,89 n.26; 28a22-26,89 n.28; 28a26-9,194 n.34; 28a26-30,178
n.48,191 n.24; 28a30-33,180 n.52,185 n.4; 28a33-6,182 n.58; 28a36-8,185
n.4; 28a37-b4,176 n.41; 28b7-ll, 193 n.32; 28bll-14,192 n.27; 28bl5-20,194
nn.35,38; 28b31-5,182 n.57,192 n.27; 28bl5,181 n.55; 28bl5-20,155 n.71;
28b22-4,155 n.72; 28b24-31,132 n.137; 29al9-27,135 n.156,136 n.157;
29a27-9,86 n.13,113 n.62; 29b24,196 nn.43,44; 29b29-32,79 n.157; 30a5-14,
174 n.36; 30b35-40,93 n.45; 32al8-b2, 79 n.157; 32a29-bl, 99 n.66; 32a31-b3,
99 n.64; 32bl8-22,98 n.60; 34al6-19,64 n.72; 34b7-18, 79 n.157; 36b35-37a31,
98 n.63,100 n.67; 38a29-31,12 n.75; 38bl8-20,12 n.75; 39b3-6,12 n.75;
40b30-7,64 n.72; 40b36,67 n.93; 41a2-20,108 n.36; 41a23-32, 77 n.148;
41a39,67 n.93; 41b6-22,133 n.143; 41b6-31,101 n.l; 41b33,145 n.26;
41b36-42a40,64 n.71; 41b36-42b26,108 n.37; 44al3,118 n.83; 43b3,118 n.83;
43bl7-22,122 n.94; 43b32-6,98 n.60; 43b43-44a2,88 n.21; 46b40-47bl4, 50
n.59; 47al6-20,74 n.136; 47a22-3,65 n.75; 47a22-31,74 n.133; 47bl5-50a4,50
n.60; 49b37-50al, 103 n.7; 50a5-15,50 n.62; 50al6-28,64 n.69; 50al6-b4,102
n.5; 51a2,3,18,22,50 n.58; 51b3-52b34, 99 n.64; 53a3-14,135 n.154,136
n.157,186 n.7; 53bl6-23,64 n.72; 59b8-10,27 n.119; 59b8-ll, 106 n.30;
61al8-33, 77 n.148; 62a9-10,125 n.106; 63b23-30,106 n.30; 64al5-17,103 n.7;
64bll-13,103 n.7; 64b28-65a37, 70 n.112; 65a38-b40, 74 n.137; 68b8-14,102
n.6,103 n.7; 68bl3-37,104 n.14; 68b35-7,104 n.16; 68b38-69al9,104 n.14;
69al3-16,103 n.7; 69al6-19,103 n.7; 70a2-b38, 72 n.119
An. Post. 71b20-72a24,58 n.34; 71b21-2,60 n.44; 71b22, 72 n.120; 72a8-9,56 n.21;
72al3-14,56 n.22; 73a7-ll, 64 n.72; 73a29, 79 n.157; 73b26-7, 57 n.30;
73b26-7, 78 n.153; 75b25-6, 79 n.157; 77a22-3,150 n.51; 77b30,122 n.94;
79al7-32,110 n.52; 79a29-32,109 n.40; 79b23-5,125 n.104; 85al3-86b39,110
n.48; 87al-30,181 n.54; 87a36,150 n.48; 87bl9-27,98 n.60; 96a8-19,98 n.60;
97b37-9, 75 n.139; 99bl5-17,53 n.6
Fragmente zur Stoischen Dialektik (FDS) 691, 75 n.138; 1051, 64 n.70; 1084, 153
n.61; 1087, 72 n.121; 1090, 133 n.142; 1099, 48 n.44; 1100, 76 n.144; 1101,
117n.74, 117 n.81, 135 n.153, 189 n.15; 1106, 50 n.55; 1118, 74 n.134; 1163, 83
n.3; 1171, 66 n.83; 1184, 86n.l5
Stoicorum Veterum Fragmenta (SVF) II 49a, 42 n.6; II 260, 72 n.124, 73 n.131, 133
n.142; II 261, 66 n.83, 67 n.91, 68 n.97, 69 n.105; II 264, 153 n.61, 154 n.64; II
265, 69 n.101; III Ant 27, 65 n.75
SYRIANUS
in Metaph. 100,6, 4 n.28
THEMISTIUS
Max. 75 n.141; 180, 84 n.ll; 180-3, 109 n.41; 181-2, 108 n.38, 140 n.ll; 182-3, 139
n.6; 184, 109 n.41, 171 n.24; 186, 84 n.ll; 190-1, 6 n.45, 86 n.14; 191-2, 174
n.37; 192, 181 n.54
THEOPHRASTUS
[F n Graeser] 4, 131 n.128; 5, 125 n.106; 13, 86 n.14; 14, 93 n.46; 15, 100 n.68; 16, 99
n.66; 17, 136 n.157, 185 n.6; 19, 168 n.18; 21, 170 n.21; 24-5, 113 n.58
Index of Persons
248
Index of Persons 249
n.93,75 n.141,78 n.151,92 n.41,93 Sosigenes, 2
n.44,94 n.50, 111 n.54,113 n.62, Sotion, 6
128 n.120,129-30,136 n.157,140 Stoics, 2,6 n.43,21,26,41 n.4, n.12,43
n.ll n.12,44 n.18,62 n.59,68,69 n.103,
Tisistratus', 103 72,134,153 n.63,154 n.64, n.65
Plato, 5,16,47 n.33,50 n.53,73,73 Syrianus, 7 n.54
n.129, 75,75 n.140,105
Platoniats, 6, n.43,7,99 Theagenes', 103
Plotinus, 2 Themistius, 7 n.54,75 n.141,85 n.ll,
Porphyry, 7 n.54,56 n.18, 75 n.141,168 181 n.54
n.17 Theo', 88
Posidonius, 41 n.l Theophrastus, 4,4 n.29,56,56 n.18,
Proclus, 5,7 n.54,8 n.57,9 n.61, n.62,46 n.24,74 n.141,86,87 n.19,89,93,
n.27 99 n.66,100,109 n.41,113 n.58,125
Pythagoreans, 150-1,150n.48,156 n.106,130,131 n.128,135-6,136
n.157,137 n.157,168 n.17,170
Septimius Severus, 1 n.21,185-6
Sextus Empiricus, 10
'Socrates', 62-3,82,173 Zeno (Stoic), 51 n.68
Index of Subjects
250
Index of Subjects 251
dialectical arguments, 24,51,67,81,82, hypothetical syllogisms, 3,6 n.45,102,
110 102 n.5
dialectical propositions, 57,57-60
dictum de omni et nullo, 87,87 n.20, imperfect syllogisms, 21,50, 75-6,135,
116-17,117 n.35,124,135 146,149,183,210
differentia, 63-4 indemonstrables, 21,76,117,189
Disami, 214 indeterminacy, 28-9,29 n.127
Disamis, 136n.l57,176,192-3,213 = absence of quantifier, 85-6,86 n.13,
disjoint arguments, 67-9,67 n.92 111, 113-14,113n.62,124,125,126,
disjunction, 131 n.128 164,167-8,187,209 n.3
disproof, 12-13,85,91,159,160 of particulars, 130-1,131 n.128,132-3,
dissimilar in form, 27,156 n.77,184-5 157,158,159,162,163,164,180,
double negation, 66 n.81 182
duplicated arguments, 66-7,66 n.88, induction, 66,71,103-4,103 n.7,104
69-70 n.12
is, 62,105
enthymeme, 103 n.7 justification, 19,102-4,103 n.7,109,110
eristic arguments, 67
etymologies, 44 n.17,64 n.74 knowledge, 46
every, of, 54,77-8
existence, 23 n. 106,62 lemmata, 8,8 n.58,15,17,17 n.85
explanation, 72,72 n.122 letters, 16,116 n.71,146,172
exposition, 26,88,88 n.24,130 n.126, logic, 41-3,67
159,169,173,174n.36,175,177, Stoic [see Index of Persons, s.v. Stoics]
178,189,211 utility of, 41,43,43 n.ll, 46 n.27,66,
70,82,97-8,104
Fapemo, 136 n.157,214 value of, 46-8
Fapesmo, 136 n.157,214 logoi, kinds of, 64,64 n.66
Faresmo, 215
Felapton, 174-5,178,191,213 major term, 32,109,109 n.43,140-4,167
Ferio, 124,127,149,161 n.93,191,213 n.ll, 176
Ferison, 180-1,192-3,213 major premiss, 109,167,167 n.ll
Festino, 152,157,189,213 matter, 30,45,48,50,58,59,81-2,81
figures, 32,48,91,101,107-8,209-10 n.165,85,114,116,119
first, 108-16,212-13 meaning, 154
fourth, 108,108 n.36,210 n.5 medicine, 98,98 n.62
ranking of, 108-10 metaphor, 74
second, 110,138-9,154,213 middle term, 32,105,107-8,115,138,
third, 110,154,166-8,213 146,166,171,209
Firesmo, 136 n.157,214 minor term, 32,109,109 n.43,140-4,
form, 30,45,48,50,114,119 166,167 n.ll
for the most part, 97-8,98 n.60 minor premiss, 109,167,167 n.ll
Frisemo, 136 n.157,214 mixed modes, 9 n.60,82 n.167
Frisesomorum, 136 n.157, 214 modal propositions, 79-80,79 n.157,80
n.158
modal syllogisms, 9 n.60,29 n.128,82
generation of figures, 108-10,109 n.41, modes, 29-30,80-1,81-2,116,195,209
138-9,166,168,170-1,171 n.24,186
genus, 45,49,55-6,56 n.18,63-4,67, nature, 97-8
140-2,140 n. 13 necessity, 29,79-80, 79 n.157,80 n.160,
geometry, 44-6,49-50,50 n.53,59, 73, 81 n.165
86-7 of the consequence, 71
gods, 44,47,47 n.40 kinds of, 93
Xsyllogism, 21,65,66,134,162
hypotheses, 25,59,179 negative, 27,55,57,59,143-4,187
hypothetical propositions, 23,56,56 non-differently concluding arguments,
n.25,64 66,66 n.87
252 Indexes
reduction of syllogisms, 11-12,22,50,76,
not of some/every, 125,125 n.106, 177,187-95
126,132,153,164 reliable, 114-15,114 n.65
nouns, 61 reputable propositions, 58,60,60 n.42
numbers, 150 requests, 58
opposition, 26,106,106 n.29 separability, 80,80 n.158,86,86 n.14
signs, 72
paradigms, 66,103,103 n.7 single-assumption arguments, 64,65-6,
parts, 28,88,103,103 n.7,111-12,125, 71,73
126,128,132,15i; 155 singular terms, 130 n.125
particles, 131-2,132-3,133 n.140 sophistical arguments, 51,74,82,
peiorern rule, 113 n.58 110-11,166
perception, 45,46,88-9,173,175,189 sophistical propositions, 60
perfect syllogisms, 6 n.45,21-2,50, 75-6, speech, parts of, 50
75 n.141,84 n.ll, 86 n.13,102, subalterns, 106,131,157
108-9,115-16,117-18,124,135, subaltern moods, 136 n.157
144,188,189,190,210 subcontraries, 27,27 n.120,106,157,
philosophy, parts of, 41-6,41 n.4 159,162,163,180
practical, 42 subject, 25,61,61 n.49,105,208
theoretical, 42,44 subpart, 28,42
Porphyrean tree, 140 n.13 subsyllogistic arguments, 153-4,153
possibility, 3,29,97-8 n.63
potential, 121,145,145n.26,146,164-5, superfluous arguments, 73,73 n.136, 73
179 n.137
predicate, 30-1,57,61,61 n.49,105,105 syllogisms, 21,63-4,104,208
n.15,118,122 n.94,208,208 n.2 additional, 134-7,184-7,212,213-15
predicative propositions, 27,30,56,56 kinds of, 49 n.49,67,82,110-11
n.25,64,78 ranking of, 113,145,145n.30,168-70,
kinds of, 81 176,177,178,180 2D1
premisses, 22 n.104,104-5 reflected, 136 n.157
principles, 59
Prior Analytics, title of, 48-50,48 n.42, terminology, 10,11-12,17-33,136 n.157
102 terms, 28,61-2,208
priority, 49,49 n.46,55-6, 71,145 universalXparticular, 121-2,122 n.94
problems, 104-5,110,144 text of Alexander's commentary, 16-17
property, 91 text of Prior Analytics, 53,53 n.3,195
propositions, 22,54-60,62,104-5,208-9 n.41,198
time, 56,56 n.22
quality, 27,56,56 n.22,57,110,112, and modality, 79-80, 79 n.157
167-8,209 truth, 22-3,26,46,55,79,80-1,84 n.6
quantification of the predicate, 105 n.25,
122 n.94 unmethodically concluding arguments,
quantifiers, 28-9,105,105 n.25,129-30, 11 n.68,20,72-4,72n.l25, 76,134,
130 n.125,173,209 134n.l44,134n.l48
quantity, 27-8,57,105,110,112,167-8, units, 150
209 universals, 28,57
unreliable, 114-15,114 n.65,119
reciprocal proof, 87,92 variables, 15 n.80,116 n.71
reduction to the impossible, 25, 70 n.109, verbs, 61
74 n.137,76-7,77n.l48,86,89,146, virtues, 47
154,158,161-2,179,187,193
used in reduction of syllogisms, 148-9, whole, in as in a, 28,28 n.124,54,77-8,
152,153,172,174,177,188,191, llln.55,112,116,123n.98
211