Restorative Justice, Intersectionality Theory
Restorative Justice, Intersectionality Theory
by
MASTER OF LAWS
in
The Faculty of Graduate Studies
This thesis problematizes the use of feminist intersectionality theory within the
context of the restorative justice social movement as applied in cases of violence against women
in some intersectional approaches to restorative justice (RJ) and domestic violence that slides
and critical stances of that feminist analytical tool for understanding racialized womens needs
communities applying RJ as remedial justice, i.e., intra-group gender inequality and allows co-
some RJ interventions like alienation, exclusion and the silencing of victims' individual histories,
reinforcing the fact that the representation of the individual female victim within the RJ
movement has not been adequately resolved and remains deeply problematic. To illustrate my
arguments, I focus on sentencing circles that are used ostensibly as state-sanctioned alternative
criminal justice responses designed to ameliorate the systemic racism and over-incarceration
rates that Aboriginal peoples experience in postcolonial jurisdictions such as Canada and
Australia. I argue that these restorative-like experience are especially vulnerable to intersectional
ii
Table
of
Contents
Abstract.................................................................................................................................. ii
Table
of
Contents .................................................................................................................. iii
Acknowledgements ................................................................................................................ v
Dedication ............................................................................................................................. vi
Introduction ........................................................................................................................... 1
1.
Topic:
Restorative
justice,
intersectionality
theory
co-optation
and
violence
against
women ..... 1
2.
Thesis
structure ................................................................................................................................................................ 5
3.
Caveat,
topic
developments
and
literature
review............................................................................................ 7
4.
A
brief
word
on
the
co-optation
of
the
feminist
anti-violence
movement
by
political
interests 16
5.
Theoretical
framework:
Intersectionality
theory ............................................................................................17
6.
Intersectionality
and
restorative
Justice..............................................................................................................22
7.
Thesis
preliminary
critique
and
defense .............................................................................................................28
iii
c)
The
critique
revolving
around
RJ
as
an
appendage
of
the
justice
system........................................... 111
d)
Feminist
critique
of
RJ:
Deferring
the
discussion .......................................................................................... 112
iv
Acknowledgements
I offer my enduring gratitude to the faculty, staff and my fellow students at UBC,
who have inspired me to continue my work in this field despite all the adversities that life and
language barriers imposed on me. I owe particular thanks to Professor Janine Benedet, whose
keen intelligence and penetrating knowledge about womens studies are a reflection of her
v
Dedication
vi
Introduction
This thesis explores the affinities and tensions that arise between the restorative
justice social movement (hereafter RJ) and feminist intersectionality theory within the context
of violence against women.1 Basically, I contend that a theoretically ideal intersectional feminist
analysis of the problem of the use of RJ as a remedy for cases of violence against women should
bear in mind analytical criteria which meet all the intersectional inequality categories in a
balanced way without losing the focus on the final purpose of any feminist analytical tool worthy
of the name: to serve, above all, womens interests. A possible failure of some intersectional
feminists in giving balance to claims of gender injustice with various other intersectional
inequality markers like culture; social class; religion; and ethnicity may have been silencing
critical objections to RJ as a tool for dealing with the problem of violence against women,
some RJ advocates that in general restorative experiences ---in their various models and forms
1
Although
throughout
this
paper
I
may
refer
to
the
expression
violence
against
women
which
is
as
a
catch-all
phrase
to
any
kind
of
violence
that
is
directed
against
a
woman
because
she
is
a
woman
or
that
affects
women
disproportionately,
my
emphasis
is
on
intimate
partner
violence
also
known
as
domestic
violence,
battering
or
family
violence.
These
terms
will
be
used
in
this
paper
generically
and
interchangeably
as
forms
of
gender-based
violence;
notwithstanding,
distinctions
among
them
can
be
found
in
the
literature
over
violence
against
women.
Definitions
of
intimate
partner
violence
or
domestic
violence
can
vary
according
to
jurisdiction,
but
in
general
they
refer
to
a
range
of
often
repetitive
and
meaningful
violent
and
abusive
behaviours
that
reflect
patterns
of
conduct
characterised
by
the
misuse
of
power
and
control
by
one
person
over
another
who
are
or
have
been
in
an
intimate
relationship.
It
can
occur
in
heterosexual
and
same
sex
relationships
and
has
profound
negative
impacts
in
the
lives
of
children,
individuals,
families
and
communities.
It
may
also
involve
physical,
sexual,
emotional
and/or
psychological
abuse.
1
are egalitarian, gender-friendly and victim-oriented forms of justice that are suitable to any
empirical and cultural context, no matter how disparate womens socioeconomic and ethnic
realities are structured.2 I challenge this assumption throughout this study by arguing that there
are epistemic problems with the intersectional approach of RJ in Indigenous settings: mainly
Furthermore, I hope to reveal that in some cases the underlying cause of this
advocacy discourse and other ethnocultural political agendas. I argue that this appropriation of a
Martin a backfire is what happens when an action is counterproductive to its originators, and
recoils against them. In a backfire dynamic, outcomes and processes can be worse than
anticipated and in some cases worse than having done nothing.3 I use the expression
intersectional backfire in this same sense. These are intuitive insights for a very particular
niche of feminist analysis on RJ that in general does not overlook the problems regarding RJs
doctrine and its scope. Nevertheless, I am aware of no study theoretical or empirical that
2
Feminists,
however,
have
been
made
a
critique
of
the
RJ
movement
that
revolve
around
three
main
themes:
womens
safety,
offender
accountability,
and
the
politics
of
gender
and
race.
See,
e.g.,
Angela
Cameron,
Restorative
Justice:
A
Literature
Review
(Paper
presented
to
the
British
Columbia
Institute
Against
Family
Violence,
2005)
[unpublished]
at
18-22.
(Noting
and
citing
sources
in
a
comprehensive
literature
review
on
RJ
and
domestic
violence).
Furthermore,
here
I
make
one
more
remark
on
terminology.
Although
I
make
casual
use
of
the
terms
Indigenous
and
Aboriginal
throughout
this
paper,
in
order
to
refer
generically
to
autochthonous
peoples
from
North
America
(United
States
and
Canada)
and
Australasia
(Australia
and
New
Zealand).
I
do
not
have
the
intention
to
strip
them
of
their
particularities,
ethnic
diversity
or
to
the
right
of
designating
and
retaining
their
own
names
for
communities,
places
and
persons.
For
the
sake
of
simplicity,
I
will
use
those
terms
interchangeably
and
as
a
neutral
replacement
instead
of
giving
specific
names.
Nevertheless,
when
suitable
for
the
purposes
of
this
paper
I
may
mention
a
specific
group
or
ethnicity
by
their
self-indentified
name.
3
See
Brian
Martin,
Justice
Ignited:
The
Dynamics
of
Backfire
(Lanhan,
Maryland:
Rowman
&
Littlefield
Publishers,
2007).
(Discussing
through
case
studies
theoretical
implications
of
a
backfire
dynamic).
See
also
Dana
Greene,
Repeat
Performances:
Why
Good
Reforms
Go
Bad
&
Testing
the
Next
Wave,
RJ
(Ph.D.
Thesis,
The
city
University
of
New
York,
2005)
[unpublished].
(Describing
a
backfire
dynamic
concerning
RJ
as
a
benevolent
penal
reform
initiative).
2
attempts directly to connect the (mis)use of an intersectional approach and the validation of RJ
practices through the co-optation of the former.4 In fact, the literature proceeds as if there are no
intersectionality theory as a research tool within the context of RJ, domestic violence and
about certain emancipatory effects for women. This usually means that the intersection of the
inequality categories (or social identities) brings into light the structures of domination and
oppression embedded in womens lives, and has the potential to expose existing detrimental
power relations. However, in my opinion, some feminists and activists on RJ may reflect, at
especially in Indigenous settings are developed with an explicit connection with collectivist RJ
values and anti-racist political claims which do not coincide necessarily with Aboriginal
womens primary interests. For this reason, it is possible that an imbalanced intersectional
approach does not benefit its intended particular beneficiaries (in our main focus of study:
Indigenous women), because it cannot assure them of a sense of security and empowerment in
4
I
do
not
want
to
suggest
that
RJ
and
feminist
scholars
have
ignored
this
topic
completely.
Intersectional
themes
have
been
openly
considered
in
a
great
deal
of
feminist
studies
on
restorative
justice.
In
fact,
almost
the
totality
of
them
used
somehow
intersectional
insights.
However,
none
of
them
explored
the
problems
and
prospects
of
the
methodology
itself,
or
asked
whether
it
might
be
co-opted
by
other
political
interests
present
in
the
RJ
field.
Most
of
the
scholarly
commentaries
are
laudatory
front-page
endorsements
of
an
intersectional
approach
and
do
not
engage
in
debate
regarding
possible
procedural
problems
due
to
the
presence
of
competing
inequality
categories.
That
is
my
original
take
on
the
issue.
3
ethnocentrism and cast doubts over the real achievements of outstanding members of the
"benefited" group since they can create an unhealthy preoccupation with other political claims,
generating a kind of intellectual myopia. It may serve to reproduce and reinforce those
approach may not capture the internal and external flaws and vulnerabilities of the RJ rhetoric
since it might be conflated with them. Instead of providing an explanation or critical evaluation
of RJ insights from this imbalanced intersectionality approach might become more like a claque,
than enlighten policy-makers about possible dangers. One could argue that almost any action can
generate unforeseen adverse consequences. The relevant issue is to determine what is the cost of
an intersectional backfire for Aboriginal women versus the cost of not using intersectional
the most relevant feminist theory scholarship about RJ and domestic violence, my thesis
establishes as a working hypothesis positive links between the existence of competing inequality
markers in an intersectional approach, and dissonant voices among feminist scholars about RJ
effectiveness to cope with violence against women, especially regarding RJ models used in
Aboriginal communities in Canada and Australia (mainly sentencing circles models). I seek to
demonstrate that an excessive reliance on other intersectional inequality categories rather than a
gender-oriented approach may result, paradoxically, in a feminist analytical tool that turns out
to be divisive, uncritical and far from being in any way emancipatory to oppressed Aboriginal
4
women. As a matter of fact, I contend that an intersectional approach might function as a
double-edged sword with the potential to address how other forms of inequality and
oppression, such as racism, colonialism, ethnocentrism, and class privilege affect Aboriginal
women victimized by violence, but at the same time it has the potential to be co-opted to serve as
resonates with a political agenda of diverse (and sometimes conflicting) interest groups where
tend to impact directly on some intersectional approaches of RJ interventions. The reason for
that is a pattern of identification and divided loyalty by a number of intersectional feminists with
RJ tenets and other movements historical struggles like those represented by the battered
womens movement, victims and offenders rights advocates, and ethnic or racial minorities
category of analysis provides the epistemological frailty for intersectionality analysis. In this
sense, the heart of my study is to test whether or not intersectionality theory is vulnerable to be
tamed as a critical feminist analytical tool by the militant advocacy of restorative proponents.
In sum, intersectional feminists epistemological (in)ability to deal with the messiness of these -
most of the time - overlapping interests will be the central topic of my thesis.
2. Thesis
structure
within the context of RJ and violence against women will be presented in the body of this thesis
in three chapters: In the first chapter, I sketch out the foundational assumptions and main features
of RJs theoretical framework. In addition, a brief general critique of the RJ movement from
various perspectives will be provided. The objective is to bring them into focus providing a solid
restorative justice. In this chapter, the aim is to explore the relationship between feminism and
RJ, by addressing the contributions of several schools of feminist thinking. This leads to
positioning feminist intersectionality theory within the context of feminist criminology, RJ and
political claims. Whereas some intersectional feminists employ a feminist theory that focuses
analytical category, I contend that intersectionality needs a more balanced approach ---
strategically focused on individual gender equality concerns --- in which the forces shaping and
obstructing intersectional analysis can be properly taken into consideration. Finally, this chapter
will focus on the mainstream feminist contribution on the debate regarding the suitability of RJ
first two chapters regarding the interplay between intersectionality theory, domestic violence and
RJ will be contextualized in Indigenous settings and further developed. This last chapter ---
which also incorporates the conclusion --- seeks to develop insights into the use of intersectional
thinking that reveal a lack of understanding from some intersectional feminists of particular
cooptive structures (e.g., the impact of postcolonial multicultural theory on RJ and intersectional
feminism) and other political (e.g., ethnocultural postcolonial claims) and epistemic processes
(e.g., prospects of intersectional disempowerment) that point to the necessity of a more cautious
interests.
6
3.
Caveat,
topic
developments
and
literature
review
cannot be applied to all intersectional feminist views on RJ and domestic violence. Actually, the
prevailing perception of feminists (intersectional or not) over the use of models of RJ to cope
with violence against women is highly critical and markedly hinders its use in several
scholars have been playing an influential role in the adoption or otherwise of RJ models to cope
with cases of violence against women to the extent that their objections or approval is, at times,
thought on this important public policy issue and to understand better the conflicting stances
among feminist scholars, especially those that can be labelled as intersectional feminists or at
least inspired by its methodology within the context of Indigenous women. I take this very
particular niche of research concerning Aboriginal communities and the long term relationship
between feminist theory and violence against women as a starting point for my study about how
the feminist theory of intersectionality interacts with RJ in ways that can produce a backfire,
especially in relation to Aboriginal women. As stated in the last section, I hope to emphasize the
5
Daly
and
Stubbs,
for
instance,
observed
that,
with
the
exception
of
circle
sentencing,
RJ
has
largely
been
kept
off
the
agenda
for
partner
and
sexual
violence,
in
part
due
to
feminist
or
victim
advocacy.
See
Kathleen
Daly
&
Julie
Stubbs,
Feminist
Engagement
with
RJ
(2006)
10:1
Theoretical
Criminology
9-28
at
11.
More
recent
literature,
however,
suggests
that
this
tide
may
be
turning
with
several
ongoing
RJ
programmes
particularly
in
Canada
and
the
United
States
coping
with
domestic
violence.
See
James
Ptacek,
ed.,
Restorative
Justice
and
Violence
Against
Women
(New
York,
NY:
Oxford
University
Press,
2009).
7
I will focus my analysis mainly in two empirical contexts. Firstly, the access to
and use of sentencing circles in Canada by Aboriginal communities.6 I start with scholarly
commentaries on the relationship between RJ and Indigenous justice particularly the adoption of
RJ practices by Indigenous communities. That will permit us to get insights about the existence
specific models of RJ, and how Aboriginal women are affected by it empirically. Secondly, I ask
whether we might not expand upon those insights by analyzing the effects of the use of similar
models of RJ by Aboriginal people mainly in Australia. I use data collected by feminist scholars
to explore whether or not there is a pattern of repetition concerning how Aboriginal women are
impacted by RJ experiences.
predominantly within particular political and socio-legal feminist mindsets. Thus, for instance,
cultural and ethnic justice arguments found especially within the context of Indigenous Justice
and RJ such as that domestic violence occurs because the community is still suffering from the
6
As
Stubbs
points
out,
There
are
problems
in
conflating
Indigenous
justice
with
RJ,
but
no
agreement
on
how
to
differentiate
between
the
two.
Circle
sentencing
is
commonly
designated
as
an
example
of
RJ
but
Marchetti
and
Daly
disagree
and
classify
it
as
an
Indigenous
justice
practice.
See
Julie
Stubbs,
Restorative
Justice,
Gendered
Violence,
and
Indigenous
Justice
in
James
Ptacek,
ed.,
Restorative
Justice
and
Violence
Against
Women
(New
York,
NY:
Oxford
University
Press,
2009)
at
1656-1659
in
a
kindle
e-book
version.
Emma
Cunliffe
and
Angela
Cameron
also
resist
to
the
idea
of
considering
Aboriginal
sentencing
circles
a
form
of
RJ
since,
in
their
words,
This
endorsement
is
risky
because
categorizing
judicially
convened
sentencing
circles
as
restorative
justice
acts
as
a
frame
by
which
the
circle
practice
is
interpreted
as
helping
to
secure
restorative
objectives,
regardless
of
the
fact
that
circles
actually
operate
more
ambivalently.
The
categorization
also
accords
the
practice
legitimacy
within
the
Canadian
criminal
justice
system.
See
infra
note
8,
Cameron
&
Cunliffe,
Writing
the
Circle
at
14
.
Angela
Cameron
also
articulates
several
distinctions
between
Indigenous
Justice
and
RJ,
but
at
the
same
time
she
notes
that:
Other
scholars,
as
well
as
the
Supreme
Court
of
Canada,
have
noted
the
striking
similarities
between
Aboriginal
justice
and
other
restorative
justice
practices
in
Canada
(R
v.
Gladue,
1999;
Doulis,
1996;
LaPrairie,
1992).
See
note
2
at
6.
But
see
Ann
Skelton,
Tapping
indigenous
knowledge:
traditional
conflict
resolution,
restorative
justice
and
the
denunciation
of
crime
in
South
Africa
(2007)
Acta
Juridica
228-246
at
230.
(Observing
that
African
writers
are
more
open
to
making
the
linkages
between
modern
restorative
justice
and
Indigenous
justice
than
are
their
counterparts
from
Australia,
New
Zealand
and
North
America).
For
the
purposes
of
my
thesis
I
will
treat
Aboriginal
sentencing
circles
as
consistent
with
RJ
experiences
since
the
general
perception
is
that
both
are
conflated.
8
acclaimed by some intersectional feminists and RJ advocates, while womens safety and
autonomy are neglected. Emphasizing some inequality categories may hamper the pursuit of
others. In fact, advocacy of political goals through RJ and Indigenous justice may have a
profound negative impact on the achievement of a safe environment for Indigenous women in
restorative conferences, both ignoring and silencing the victim.7 Recently, a number of scholarly
works have given considerable attention to this focus of study. They highlight the potential perils
of the way in which conflicting inequality markers and disparate political goals have been
fostering the debate among and between Indigenous and non-Indigenous women on the
appropriateness of restorative justice and Indigenous justice in response to partner, sexual and
7
Giving
voice
to
victims
is
of
paramount
importance
in
any
RJ
conference
since
it
is
considered
part
of
the
healing
process
to
allow
victims
to
tell
their
stories
to
the
community
and
to
the
ones
who
caused
the
harm
in
order
to
have
them
understand
the
impact
of
their
actions.
8
See,
e.g.,
Angela
Cameron
&
Emma
Cunliffe,
Writing
the
Circle:
Judicially
Convened
Sentencing
circles
and
the
Textual
Organization
of
Criminal
Justice
(2007)
19:1
Canadian
Journal
of
Women
and
the
Law
1-35;
Elizabeth
Adjin-Tettey,
Sentencing
Aboriginal
Offender:
Balancing
Offender's
Needs,
the
Interests
of
victims
and
Society,
and
the
Decolonization
of
Aboriginal
Peoples
(2007)
19:1
Canadian
Journal
of
Women
and
the
Law
179;
Carol
LaPrairie
&
Jane
Dickson-Gilmore,
Will
the
Circle
be
Unbroken?
Aboriginal
Communities,
Restorative
Justice
and
the
Challenges
of
Conflict
and
Change
(Cullompton,
UK:
Willan
Publishing
2005);
Angela
Cameron,
Sentencing
Circles
and
Intimate
Violence:
A
Canadian
Feminist
Perspective
(2006)
18:2
Canadian
Journal
of
Women
and
the
Law
479-512
and
Rashmi
Goel,
No
Women
at
the
Center:
The
use
of
the
Canadian
Sentencing
Circles
in
Domestic
Violence
Cases(2000)
15
Wiscosin
Womens
Law
Journal
293-3334.
(Addressing
specifically
the
issue
of
the
use
of
sentencing
circles
in
Indigenous
settings
and
its
consequences
for
Indigenous
women).
See
generally
the
following
books:
James
Ptacek,
ed.,
Restorative
Jutice
and
Violence
Against
Women
(New
York,
NY:
Oxford
University
Press,
2009)
and
Heather
Strang
&
John
Braithwaite,
eds.,
Restorative
Justice
and
Family
Violence
(Cambridge,
UK:
Cambridge
University
Press,
2002).
(In
these
collections
of
essays
over
the
theme
RJ
and
violence
against
women
several
several
contributors
have
used
a
perspective
of
Aboriginal
women).
9
See
Kathleen
Daly
&
Julie
Stubbs,
Feminist
Theory,
Feminist
and
anti-racist
politics
and
Restorative
Justice
in
Gerry
Johnstone
&
Daniel
W.
Van
Ness,
eds.,
Handbook
of
Restorative
Justice
(Portland,
Oregon:
Willan
Publishing,
2007)
at
161.
9
Although the intersectional approach addresses multiple discrimination categories
(or inequality markers) --- gender; religion; ethnicity; culture; social class, etc.--- and helps us
understand how different sets of social identities impact Indigenous womens interactions with
RJ there is the tangible risk in considering a given inequality category or marker, for example,
culture, as more important than others and by so doing neglecting essential features of the
traditional feminist thought like security and empowerment.10 Just to take one example of how a
dynamic like that can function, I single out for demonstration an insight drawn from the work of
the Canadian feminist scholar Angela Cameron. She points out the existence of asymmetric
approaches by Indigenous women and feminist scholars concerning how they see RJ
their primary goal --- clearly a cultural and political agenda. Others focus more on gender to
the quest to incorporate an appropriate cultural and gender perspective in the debate about
restorative justice is a difficult one. The scholars discussed in this segment, in many cases,
prioritize a cultural agenda over an agenda that incorporates gender equality and culture in the
10
As
Barbara
Hart,
an
historical
militant
in
the
battered
womans
movement,
argues:
In
the
context
of
domestic
violence,
there
are
six
primary
goals.
The
first
and
overarching
goal
is
safety
for
battered
women
and
children.
Every
intervention
should
be
measured
against
the
yardstick
of
safety.
(According
to
her,
safety
is
followed
by
stopping
the
violence
(the
second
goal);
holding
perpetrators
accountable
(the
third
goal);
divesting
perpetrators
of
control
(the
fourth
goal);
restoring
women
who
have
been
battered
(the
fifth
goal),
and
enhancing
agency
in
women
who
have
been
battered
(the
sixth
goal)
making
them
able
to
make
decisions
without
interference
by
the
batterer).
See
Barbara
J.
Hart,
Arrest,
Whats
the
Big
Deal
(1997)
3
Wm.
&
Mary
J.
Women
&
L.
at
207-209.
Goodmark
defines
empowerment,as
consistent
with
autonomy
or
agencyas
self-direction,
self-determination,
enabling
the
woman
who
has
been
battered
not
only
to
make
choices,
but
to
define
the
options
for
herself,
regardless
of
how
others
would
evaluate
those
options.
(I
adopt
her
same
view
on
womens
empowerment).
See
Leigh
Goodmark,
Autonomy
Feminism:
An
Anti-essentialist
Critique
of
Mandatory
Interventions
in
Domestic
Violence
Cases,
This
article
will
be
adapted
as
a
chapter
in
A
Troubled
Marriage:
Domestic
Violence
and
the
Legal
System
publication
forthcoming
(NY:
New
York
University
Press,
2011)
at
48.
11
See
Angela
Cameron,
Gender,
Power
and
Justice:
A
Feminist
Perspective
on
Restorative
Justice
and
Intimate
Violence
(LL.M.
Thesis,
University
of
British
Columbia,
2003)
[unpublished]
at
136.
12
Ibid.
10
Defenders of the primacy of community interests over gender issues often argue
that women should put the community before themselves as a political assertion of their
autonomy and self-governance. However, other Indigenous women and feminist scholars have
criticized claims like those arguing that womens choices are, in that context, constrained by
political forces. These forces are objectionable since they re-victimize Indigenous women
undermining their freedom of choice --- even using state-based coercive sanctioning schemes --
and reinforcing gender subordination. They deprive individual Indigenous women of the self-
determination and self-direction that are essential for their autonomy and empowerment. As
Rashmi Goel, another Canadian scholar observes: this dynamic is complicated when
community members also see themselves as victims of the mainstream system interactions
might simply shift to one in which the community and the offender stand as victims of the
state.13 She adds, This could work to excuse the offender or to blame the victim for bringing
safety and offenders accountability is only one example consistent with a strand of feminist
thought that I contend has permeated some imbalanced intersectional approaches. Those
intersectional feminists do not focus on womens subordinated and victimized statuses believing
they believe that other inequality loci are most significant, such as, cultural or ethnical political
claims or even RJ advocacy interests. Doing so they might be giving validation to those RJ
experiences as culturally sensitive while in truth womens security and empowerment are
neglected. Cameron observes that although culture really matters, (...) we need to move away
13
See
Rashmi
Goel,
Aboriginal
Women
and
Political
Pursuit
in
Canadian
Sentencing
Circles:
At
the
Cross
Roads
or
Cross
Purposes?
in
James
Ptacek,
ed.,
Restorative
Jutice
and
Violence
Against
Women
(New
York,
NY:
Oxford
University
Press,
2009)
at
1048-1051
in
a
kindle
e-book
version.
14
Ibid.
11
from romanticized, abstract notions of what can be achieved by western RJ or Aboriginal justice
and turn our attention to the actual experiences of victims and offenders. Their experiences,
whether positive or negative (or both) need to be grounded in a more adequate theorization of the
intersection of culture and gender in post-colonial societies.15 From my point of view this
adequate theorization means to combine and balance a commitment to womens interests with
constructive hybridization. Daly, citing Blagg, defined the term constructive hybridization:
Blagg (2005, p. 3) terms this constructive hybridization, and it refers to the ways in
which Aboriginal values and principles can be incorporated into the non-Aboriginal
justice system. Constructive hybridization reveals intersectional thinking. However, it
must include Indigenous womens interests and avoid inappropriate uses of cultural
arguments. Restorative justice practices typically work within a dominant white
perspective, but they could benefit by using constructive hybridization. Indigenous justice
practices can be improved by bringing the voice or perspective of the victim into the
process. This is especially important so that an offender does not take up the position of
offender and a victim of colonial society, which has the effect of obscuring the victim. It
may also serve to break the common ground of male interests (that is, those comprising
16
white justice and black community leaders).
The question is how to balance values based on alternative forms of justice like
RJ with values like gender empowerment. Part of the answer certainly includes studies that
address fairness concerns regarding RJ conferences; that females and victims interests are not
properly protected, and that feminist scholars are more likely to engage in dissent when they
15
See
Angela
Cameron,
Stopping
the
Violence:
Canadian
Feminist
Debates
on
Restorative
Justice
and
Intimate
Violence
(2006)
10
Theoretical
Criminology
at
56-57.
16
See
Kathleen
Daly,
Seeking
Justice
in
the
21st
Century:
Towards
an
Intersectional
Politics
of
Justice
in
H.
E.
Ventura
Miller,
ed.,
RJ:
From
Theory
to
Practice.
Sociology
of
Crime,
Law,
and
Deviance
Series,
Vol.
11
(Amsterdam:
Emerald
Group
Publishing
Ltd.,2008)
at
27.
See
also
Harry
Blagg,
A
new
way
of
doing
justice
business?
Community
justice
mechanisms
and
sustainable
governance
in
Western
Australia
(2005)
State
Solicitor's
Office,
Background
Paper
No.
8.
Perth:
Law
Reform
Commission
of
Western
Australia
at
3.
12
The uncertainty concerning who should play the major role in RJ thinking, or
victims, offenders and community interests, provides another opportunity to examine the
complex relationships and contradictions inherent but latent in the RJ rhetoric. Many RJ
proponents embrace (and defend) that restorative conferences have the capacity to benefit
victims in a wide range of symbolic, material, therapeutic, and moral outcomes.18 For example,
as Stubbs observes: Proponents typically point to the opportunity for victims to participate and
have a voice and receive validation, and for offenders to take responsibility, for a communicative
and flexible environment and relationship repair (if that is a goal; Daly and Stubbs 2006)19.
Moreover, victims have allegedly reported reduced levels of fear, anxiety, and anger and show
less interest in seeking revenge. There are also claims of potential benefits concerning the
However, the worry of many critics is that the capacity of RJ to advance victims interests is
17
The
most
common
practices
of
restorative
justice
include
family-group
conferences,
peace-making
circles/
sentencing
circles,
and
a
variety
of
victim-offender
mediation
processes
depending
on
the
legal
jurisdiction.
In
chapter
1
these
models
of
RJ
will
be
presented
in
more
details.
18
Stubbs,
supra
note
6
at
1551-1554.
19
Ibid.
at
1560-1564.
20
Ibid.
See
also
Heather
Strang,
Repair
or
Revenge:
Victims
and
RJ
(Oxford:
Oxford
University
Press,
2002)
(Discussing
the
RJ
promises
to
victims
and
offenders.
There
are
allegedly
benefits
to
the
community
like,
for
example,
participation
in
their
own
problems
reinforcing
participatory
democracy).
13
that the threat of violence may be ongoing and not reducible to discrete incidents (Cocker
2002; Stubbs 2002).21
In fact, the link between the mis(use) of the intersectional approach and the
uncertain status of victims interests in some RJ models is less obvious than the link between the
RJ claim of RJ to bring together victims, offenders and community and the desire to reform the
overlooked connection between the mis(use) of intersectionality theory and the equivocal role of
among the various RJ stakeholders is identifying which RJ model will adequately capture all the
subtle shades of meaning within the RJ realm, while not excluding the richness and diversity of
feminist scholars. By examining the literature I hope to identify problematic RJ models that
victim-oriented feminist scholars would be willing to engage like sentencing circle experiences
in Aboriginal communities in Canada and Australia. Key authors like Kathleen Daly; Julie
Stubbs; Rashmi Goel; Elizabeth Adjin-Tettey, and Angela Cameron are particularly pertinent in
this sense because they address the subject-matter in a way that privileges a victim-oriented
analysis of the appropriateness of RJ to cope with violence against women without losing well-
These scholars and others have summarized the current RJ theoretical framework
under a feminist perspective, and at the same time either conducted or investigated several
empirical studies on RJ, especially based on ongoing actual experiences in Canada and
21
Stubbs,
supra
note
6
at
1552-1556.
14
Australasia (Australia and New Zealand) with white and non-white subjects.22 According to
them, domestic violence offences and other manifestations of violence against women cannot be
subsumed within existing generic restorative practices without significant risks to victims
interests. Furthermore, the extensive research data allowed them to identify a group of feminists
who do not apply a balanced approach in using inequality categories which generates distortions
largely inspired and influenced by their findings and intends to complement their work adding
my own perspective on the issue, especially regarding the (mis)use of an intersectional approach
and a possible co-optation of it by RJ advocacy arguments and other political claims that become
is especially striking when one considers that the UN Basic Principles on RJ fundamentally aim
to provide an opportunity for victims to obtain reparation, feel safer and seek closure (...)
(Preamble).23 This pledge for the protection of victims and victims rights as absolute priority is
a key feature that cannot be ignored when implementing any RJ program. If the restorative
approach fails in delivering reparation, security or even empowering the victim, it also fails as a
remedy and, therefore, as a viable practice to cope with cases of gender violence. Under that
premise, any RJ legislation, program or policy must unquestionably assure the women victims of
violence that their safety and autonomy will be preserved whether Indigenous or not; otherwise it
cannot be deemed a viable approach. Likewise, I argue that if an intersectional approach to the
discourses and other political agendas --- being diverted from its purpose as a methodology that
22
See,
e.g.,
note
8.
23
UN
Economic
and
Social
Council,
Declaration
of
Basic
Principles
on
the
use
of
Restorative
Justice
Programmes
in
Criminal
Matters,
ECOSOC
Res.
2002/12,
UN
Doc
A/40/881
(1999).
15
furthers womens interests --- the whole idea of intersectionality may also become seriously
compromised.
As noted in the previous sections the main impetus for my thesis is my perception
that an intersectional feminist approach to RJ may be co-opted by other interests rather than
those committed to womens empowerment and autonomy. There are good reasons to hold such
fears. The history of the feminist anti-violence movement suggests that its co-optation by other
political interests in ways that could be misused to create policies to further alienate and
disempower battered women, is by no means a novelty. Indeed, as James Ptacek put it, the
history of how feminism has transformed state responses (to domestic violence) is the story of
how the state has sought to co-opt feminist activism24 Ptacek of course is concerned about the
appropriation of the feminist movement by the conservative right in order to legitimise and
validate get tough policies such as mandatory pro-arrest policies for police and no-drop
prosecution policies.25 In truth, Ptaceks concerns are not very different from mine. While Ptacek
24
See
James
Ptacek,
ed.,
Restorative
Jutice
and
Violence
Against
Women
(New
York,
NY:
Oxford
University
Press,
2009)
at
155-158
in
a
kindle
e-book
version.
Parentheses
added
by
me.
25
The
impact
of
tough
on
crime
or
zero
tolerance
policies
on
domestic
violence
cases
was
subjected
to
harsh
criticism
by
some
feminist
scholars
who
found
that
these
policies
operate
in
ways
that
may
further
state
control
of
women,
particularly
women
who
are
marginalized
by
race,
class,
and
immigrant
status.
Mandatory
arrest
and
prosecution
policies,
for
instance,
may
result
in
increased
numbers
of
arrests
of
non-citizen
women
who
may
then
be
deemed
deportable
under
immigration
law;
my
aggravate
racist
and
abusive
police
behaviors;
result
on
overincarceration
of
men
of
color;
reinforce
pathological
notions
that
battered
women
do
not
want
to
assist
prosecution
and
that
they
accept
violence
staying
with
the
offender;
unwarranted
removal
by
the
state
of
children
from
women
who
have
been
battered;
prosecution
of
battered
women
involved,
even
peripherally,
in
criminal
conduct,
and
limits
womens
ability
to
use
the
criminal
justice
system
strategically
to
gain
greater
control
over
their
lives,
but
did
not
necessarily
complete
legal
processes.
Nevertheless,
many
feminists
aligned
themselves
with
those
policies.
See
Donna
Coker,
Transformative
Justice:
Anti-Subordination
Processes
in
Cases
of
Domestic
Violence
in
John
Braithwaite
&
Heather
Strang,
eds.,
Restorative
Justice
and
Family
Violence
(Cambridge,
UK
:Cambridge
University
Press,
2002)
at
133.
(summarizing
the
literature
on
this
point).
See
also
Donna
Coker,
"Crime
Control
and
Feminist
Law
Reform
in
Domestic
Violence
Law:
A
Critical
Review"(2001)
4
Buffalo
Criminal
Law
Review
801-860.
16
would ask: how is feminism affected by conservative political agendas? I would ask: How is
feminism --- especially intersectionality theory --- affected by informal alternative justice
practices like restorative justice? As we shall see, those alternative forms of justice practices are
also capable of assimilating feminist theoretical approaches in their own terms, especially within
the context of specific models used in Indigenous justice such as sentencing circles.
At this point it should come as no surprise that this study will draw on insights
from intersectionality theory. But what does intersectionality mean? Intersectionality theory also
known as feminist critical race theory, integrative feminism, anti-essentialist feminist theory, and
multiracial (or multicultural) feminism may be defined as a feminist theory with the purpose of
acknowledge that there is no unitary or monolithic experience for women. Feminists who take an
intersectional approach to questions of power and subordination among women are highly
critical of descriptions of inequality that tend to homogenize their experiences into experiences
and political claims of white, middle-class women. For example, the experiences of Black
women may be vastly different than those of white women, or those of poor women distinct
from those more socially advantaged.27 In fact, Kimberl Crenshaw, who originally devised this
26
See
Alison
Bailey,
On
Intersectionality
and
White
Feminist
Philosophy
SSRN
(29
September
2008),
online:
Available
at
SSRN:
http://ssrn.com/abstract=1334786
at
4.
27
See
Kimberl
Crenshaw,
Mapping
the
Margins:
Intersectionality,
Identity
Politics,
and
Violence
against
Women
of
Color
(1991)
43:6
Stanford
Law
Review
1241-1299.
See
also
Kimberl
Crenshaw,
Demarginalizing
the
Intersection
of
Race
and
Sex:
A
Black
Feminist
Critique
of
Antidiscrimination
Doctrine,
Feminist
Theory,
and
Antiracist
Politics
(1989)
14
University
of
Chicago
Legal
Forum,
538-54.
But
see
Amanda
Burgess-Proctor,
Intersections
of
Race,
Class,
Gender,
and
Crime:
Future
Directions
for
Feminist
Criminology
(2006)
1
Feminist
Criminology
7
at
44.
(Arguing
that,
in
her
words:
intersectionality
actually
emerged
during
the
1970s.
That
is,
at
the
beginning
of
the
second
wave
of
the
feminist
movement,
women
of
color
(as
well
as
White
antiracist
women
17
approach in the 1980s, employed the term intersectionality to address specifically a black
feminist perspective in contrast to the sameness of mainstream white feminism in the United
States. Furthermore, intersectionality has been a fruitful analytical resource for feminist scholars
working in a variety of fields. For example, history; feminist criminology; feminist theory;
critical legal studies; and international human rights have been using intersectionality theory to
emphasize the interactions between inequality markers and complex systems of domination or
privilege.28 The term intersectionality itself has its roots in the word intersection which lead
us to the metaphor of crossroads and traffic used by Kimberl Crenshaw to explain her insights
Intersectionality is what occurs when a woman from a minority group tries to navigate
the main crossing in the city. The main highway is racism road. One cross street can
be Colonialism, the [other] Patriarchy Street She has to deal not only with one form of
oppression, but with all forms, those names as road signs, which link together to make a
double, a triple, multiple, a many layered blanket of oppression.29
understanding and responding to the ways in which gender intersects with other inequality
markers or social identities and how these intersections can raise concerns about womens
and
others
who
felt
marginalized
by
mainstream
feminism)
began
calling
for
scholarship
that
simultaneously
attended
to
issues
of
race,
class,
gender,
and
sexuality.
However,
the
concept
of
intersecting
inequalities
first
appeared
in
criminology
during
the
1980s,
corresponding
to
feminisms
third
wave).
28
Supra
note
26.
29
This
quotation
was
extracted
from
Baileys
paper
On
Intersectionality
and
White
Feminist
Philosophy
and
according
to
her
is
originated
from
a
paper
Crenshaw
gave
at
the
World
Conference
Against
Racism
(WCAR)
in
South
Africa.
She
adds
that
the
paper
is
no
longer
available,
but
it
is
cited
by
Nira
Yuval-Davis
on
her
paper
Intersectionality
and
Feminist
Politics.
Supra
note
16
at
31.
See
also
Nira
Yuval-Davis,
Intersectionality
and
Feminist
Politics
(2006)
13:3
European
Journal
of
Womens
Studies
at
196.
(Yuval-Davis
cites
Crenshaws
metaphor
as
a
passage
of
a
report
of
the
WCAR
meeting
as
presented
by
Indira
Patel
to
a
day
seminar
in
London
in
November
2001).
See
also
Kathy
Davis,
Intersectionality
as
Buzzword:
A
Sociology
of
Science
Perspective
on
What
Makes
a
Feminist
Theory
Successful
(2008)
9:1
Feminist
Theory
67-85
(Observing
incidentally
that
Crenshaw
expanded
her
conceptualization
of
intersectionality
to
address
domestic
violence
in
order
to
show
how
feminists
have
been
primarily
concerned
with
getting
the
issue
of
domestic
violence
on
the
political
agenda
as
a
womens
issue,
and
have
tended
to
downplay
differences
among
women).
18
term intersectionality refers to both a normative theoretical argument and an approach to
conducting empirical research that emphasizes the interaction of categories of difference ---
including but not limited to race, gender, class, and sexual orientation.30 Under an intersectional
theory approach, therefore, women are usually divided along multiple inequality categories or
social identities such as class, race, religion, ethnicity, sexual orientation, and nationality. As
constitutive relationship among these categories and the way in which race (or ethnicity) and
gender (or other relevant categories) play a role in the shaping of political institutions, political
actors, the relationships between institutions and actors, and the relevant categories
strategy for bringing out the tensions and connections between feminism, anti-racism, anti-
For this reason, one of the often heralded attributes of intersectionality theory has
been its capacity to reflect critically upon the objects of study vis--vis the existence of
inequality categories that would help us to identify how different sets of identities impact on
intersectional approach and RJ where intersectionality theory acts more like a validation tool
than a critical instrument of analysis. Although I recognize the importance of other inequality
also cannot ignore the potential negative effects of overemphasizing certain aspects to the
detriment of others. For this reason, dividing the attention of feminists among so many and
30
See
Ange-Marie
Hancock,
When
Multiplication
Doesnt
Equal
Quick
Addition:
Examining
Intersectionality
as
a
Research
Paradigm
(2007)
5:1
Perspectives
on
Politics
at
63-64.
31
Ibid.
32
See
note
26
at
7
19
sometimes conflicting inequality categories may have come with a price, namely an imbalance
among them.
Knudsen recognized this issue and argued that multiple inequality perspectives are
turned into a problem, because any category may be considered as the most significant one. She
depicted this problem using Crenshaws metaphor of the crossroad, writing: the ethnicity may
be chosen in favour of gender as the one road chosen, while the other road is left behind.33
Another insight pointed out by Knudsen that I also share is that inequality categories may be
was the case in the 1970s where, for example, class and race gained more significance than
gender. In the context of RJ, I contend that some intersectional feminists and RJ advocates ---in
practice. More specifically, an overemphasis on the offender in some programs which have
contributed to a great suspicious among some feminists about RJ is really committed to victims
directly from imbalanced intersectionality theory, and has led to a variety of stances in the
feminist community regarding the appropriateness of the use of restorative justice models in
cases of violence against women. Some enthusiastically support it, while others vehemently
oppose it. By looking at the multifaceted, sometimes contradictory inequality markers and social
movements that influence these points of view, I contend that we can better deal with the
33
Susanne
Knudsen,
Intersectionality
-
A
Theoretical
Inspiration
in
the
Analysis
of
Minority
Cultures
and
Identities
in
Textbooks
on
line:
(2008)
Caught
in
the
Web
or
Lost
in
the
Textbook,
<www.caen.iufm.fr/colloque_iartem/pdf/knudsen.pdf+intersectionality+theory&hl=en&ct=clnk&cd=3&client=firef
ox
firefox-a>
at
63.
Retrieved
on
20
March
2008
(In
the
transversal
intersectional
perspective
the
categories
intertwine,
pervade
and
transform
each
other).
20
problem of the divergence between feminists revealing which inequality categories have more
weight in an intersectional analytical perspective of RJ and how this might affect the feminist
judgement and appraisal of restorative justice practices. For example, in Canada, Angela
Cameron calls for a moratorium on new RJ and Indigenous justice practices for addressing
violence against women under the argument that they do not provide necessary security and
empowerment to victimized women, while in the USA Dona Cocker believes that it would be
postmodern feminism epistemic positions), and Cocker is more concerned with other inequality
and against restorative justice. For this reason my thesis also argues that there is a need for a
more thoughtful and integrated intersectional approach within the context of RJ concerning its
ability to cope with violence against women. After all, it is at least odd that the same analytical
tool turns out to have such diametrically opposing appraisals of experiences inspired by the same
RJ tenets. Of course, I acknowledge that the diversity of RJ models and practices also
contributes to those conflicting results, but my point is that the existence of competing values in
the intersectionality theory are left out of the picture. I suggest that great caution should be
tool, since contradictorily they can address adequately the use of RJ in relation to violence
against women, and can also take the restorative claims on their own terms and without further
investigations.
34
See
Donna
Coker,
Restorative
justice,
Navajo
Peacemaking
and
domestic
violence
(2006)
10:1
Theoretical
Criminology
67-85.
See
especially
Cameron,
supra
note
10.
See
also
note
14.
21
6. Intersectionality
and
restorative
Justice
the multiple and shifting identities of people (e.g., Maher, 1997; see also McCall, 2005) and
politically and analytically to critique categorical thinking in law, social theory, and social
movement groups (Crenshaw, 1989, 1991; Marchetti, 2008).35 Daly uses the latter sense more
specifically, to address the conflicting interests of victims and offenders, social movement
groups, and individuals and collectivities in responding to crime.36 I use her insights to analyse
the interplay between intersectionality theory and RJ. To do so when using an intersectional
those usually found in the intersectionality doctrine, such as gender; ethnicity; social-economic
status; sexual orientation; immigration status; religion, and age. Daly, for example, identifies
three not so self-evident loci of inequality that she names sites of contestation between and
among feminists and anti-racist groups, because these relate to alternative justice practices like
RJ. They are the inequalities caused by crime (victims and offenders), social divisions (race and
gender politics), and individuals and collectivities (rights of offenders and victims).
The picture that emerges from Daly's new categories of inequality is of a division
of loci, in which those sites of contestation (e.g. inequality caused by crime) and associated
actors (e.g. victims and offenders) are marked by a pursuit of disparate goals which are in
constant conflict with one another. For this reason, the political agendas of the actors belonging
to each locus of inequality tend to focus on their own interests, even within a group that is
already suffering from some kind of power imbalance or oppression. In other words, even within
systemic dilemma for Indigenous women: in an intersectional context, for example, they may
find themselves forcibly situated in one of two camps of sometimes conflicting political agendas.
interventions, they may be categorized either as individualists or as people who do not embrace
community interests, even though these may be more aligned to offenders interests. Crenshaw,
since women are forced to split their political energies between two sometimes-opposing groups
while men of color and white women seldom deal with this problem.37 My fear is that a form of
communities, especially concerning the emphasis given to male offenders as surrogates for
For example, critics of Indigenous womens organizations say they are too closely
aligned with feminist interests (or what is termed womens or individual rights), not with
the collective interests or rights of Aboriginal people. In response, Indigenous women say
they are being asked (unfairly) to put community interests ahead of their interests as
women. Relating this to criminal justice, Emma LaRocque (1997, p. 81), a Canadian
Indigenous woman, says it remains a puzzle how offenders, more often than victims,
have come to represent collective rights. She argues that in the interests of social
harmony, (...) the pendulum has swung way too far to the advantage of [offenders] within
Native communities. 38
37
See
note
27,
Crenshaw,
Mapping
the
Margins.
38
See
note
16
at
6.
23
Following this line of reasoning Daly contends that, If we want to do justice
differently, we must find ways to align race and gender justice politics, and not permit the
implications of using an intersectional approach within the context of RJ and violence against
women draws on those insights from Daly. She uses what she terms sites of contestations in
order to describe, the different positions that feminist and anti-racist groups have taken toward
justice practices.40 Daly thinks that those loci of inequality, as a I prefer to name them,
encapsulates the different emphases that Indigenous (or racialized political minority groups)
and feminist groups take in seeking justice.41 According to Daly, that is the reason why racial
and ethnic minority groups claims commonly centre on treatment of offenders, while feminist
claims more likely convey the needs of victims. As she puts it:
Race and gender politics can be viewed as a group-based overlay on the positional
interests of offenders and victims: Indigenous (or racialized minority) groups emphasize
offenders interests; feminist groups, victims interests. In light of relations of Indigenous
(or racialized minority) groups to the state, which are grounded in distrust spawned by a
history of white racism, racial prejudice, and discrimination, taking the positional interest
of an offender is logical and expected. Likewise, for feminist groups, who awakened
consciousness to the problem that has no name (sexual and physical abuse by men
toward women, particularly in the home), taking the positional interest of a victim is
logical and expected.42
She concludes by arguing that this can create problems in finding common ground
39
See
note
16.
40
Ibid.
at
14.
41
Ibid.
42
See
note
16
at
18.
24
As a consequence, the emerging feminist socio-legal analysis of the problem of
using RJ in Indigenous settings has its roots in other developments besides solely gender. Issues
like race, class, ethnicity, sexuality, age, religion, colonization, and other key markers or
categories of inequality have emerged to compete at times against gender as a primary feminist
category of analysis and, sometimes against each other. Razack was the first to capture this
tension between inequality markers when she argued that culture, community, and colonization
can be used to compete with and ultimately prevail over gender-based harm.43 Daly argues that
in order to address conflicts and competing interests that emerge in those sites of contestation
knowledge and capacities of victims, offenders, community people; and state support);
movement of group-based interests to other positional interests; and positive rights for victims
and offenders that are not compromised by collectivities.44 Unfortunately, I believe that this is
not the case of some RJ models applied within the context of Aboriginal communities in Canada
Before advancing to the next sections, I must pause and temporarily turn away
from intersectionality theory. As stated in the previous paragraphs the main question to be raised
in my thesis is the connection between the (mis)use of procedural values (inequality categories)
in intersectionality theory, on the one hand, and the convenience of using RJ practices to cope
with violence against women cases on the other hand. Although I had highlighted the importance
of intersectionality theory in this connection, the relevance of RJ was not yet fully clarified. In
this sense it is crucial to determine whether RJ interventions can do any better than the solutions
found in the conventional criminal justice system (hereafter CJS) as feasible remedies to gender-
43
See
Sherene
Razack,
What
Is
to
be
Gained
by
Looking
White
People
in
the
Eye?
Culture,
Race,
and
Gender
in
Cases
of
Sexual
Violence,
(1994)
19
Signs
894-923
at
910.
44
See
note
29
at
24.
25
based violence. I point out two reasons which support the relevance of studying RJ within this
context.
First, scholarly literature either defends or refutes the use of RJ to cope with
violence against women which leaves an inconclusive answer among scholars concerning this
problem of public policy.45 I hope to draw my own conclusions about the topic from the debate
among scholars. In order to do this, my research looks into RJ to explore what the current
literature says or infers about the problem, either in terms of imposing constructive criticism
(telling policy-makers what they should not do) or offering positive guidance (telling policy-
makers what they should do). It is important to mention that the exploration of literature will be
preceded by an outline of the conceptual and theoretical framework of RJ that should be helpful
in addressing some of the complexities, promises and internal deficiencies of the RJ movement
itself.
For example, at first sight it may seem difficult to go against the noble aspirations
combined with character transformation, and a more meaningful role for victims in the criminal
justice system. However, some critics of RJ question whether it is possible to achieve those
45
There
is
a
considerable
amount
of
scholarly
work
asserting
the
positive
effects
of
RJ
concerning
violence
against
women
while
there
is
an
equal,
if
not
greater,
amount
of
scholars
criticizing
those
stances
and
presenting
serious
concerns,
especially
regarding
autonomy
and
security
of
victimized
women
in
RJ
conferences.
See,
e.g.,
Stopping
Violence,
note
15
at
56-59.
(Angela
Cameron
classifying
feminist
stances
on
the
use
of
RJ
to
deal
with
gender-
based
violence
into
groups
for
and
against
the
idea).
See
also
note
2,
Cameron,
Restorative
Justice:
A
literature
Review.
(Here
Angela
Cameron
identified
an
intermediary
position
where
detractors
of
the
use
of
RJ
to
deal
with
violence
against
women
are
willing
to
reconsider
their
position
if
restorative
justice
processes
were
better
framed).
See
also,
Feminist
Engagement,
supra
note
5
at
18
(
Daly
and
Stubbs
listing
the
potential
problems
and
benefits
mentioned
in
the
literature
regarding
the
usability
of
RJ
to
cope
with
gender-based
violence).
26
aspirations.46
In the literature, for instance, there is constant criticism regarding lack of clarity
and coherence of the RJ goals; doubts about whether or not there is an artificial dichotomy
between victims advocates and offender-oriented programmes, and the paradox inherent in the
restorative aspiration to offer a distinctive alternative to the conventional criminal justice system
while simultaneously co-existing and adopting fundamental concepts within the very framework
it seeks to challenge.47 The study of RJ aspirations and its limitations will offer guidance not
only to understand the fundamental interactions between these and violence against women, but
may also help to explain how such models might set priorities among the various sites of
contestation proposed by Daly. This is particularly the hope concerning individual interests
where victims and offenders positive rights seem not be clearly articulated in contrast to
collectivistic interests which may be acquiring primacy over others, mainly in Aboriginal models
of RJ.
46
The
extent
to
which
RJ
can
achieve
these
aspirations
is
hotly
debated.
Compare,
e.g,
Howard
Zehr,
The
Little
Book
of
Restorative
Justice
(Intercourse,
PA:
Good
Books,
2002;
Howard
Zehr,
Changing
Lenses:
A
New
Focus
for
Crime
and
Justice
(Scottdale,
Pennsylvania:
Herald
Press,
1990);
Allison
Morris,
Critiquing
the
Critics:
A
Brief
Response
to
Critics
of
Restorative
Justice
(2002)
42:3
British
Journal
of
Criminology
596;
John
Braithwaite,
Principles
of
Restorative
Justice,
in
A.
Von
Hirsch,
et.al.,
eds,
Restorative
Justice:
Competing
or
Reconcilable
Paradigms?,
(Portland,
OR:
Hart
Publishing,
2003)
and
John
Braithwaite,
Crime,
Shame
and
Reintegration
(New
York,
NY:
Cambridge
University
Press,
1989).
(Claiming
that
RJ
has
potential
to
achieve
its
aspirations),
with
Annalise
E.
Acorn,
Compulsory
Compassion:
A
Critique
of
Restorative
Justice
(Vancouver,
BC:
UBC
Press,
2004);
Kathleen
Daly,
Mind
the
Gap:
Restorative
Justice
in
Theory
and
Practice
in
A.
Von
Hirsh
et.
al,
eds.,
Restorative
Justice
and
Criminal
Justice
(Oxford:
Hart
Publishing,
2004);
Kathleen
Daly,
The
Limits
of
Restorative
Justice
in
Dennis
Sullivan
&
Larry
Tifft
,eds.,
The
Handbook
of
Restorative
Justice:
A
Global
Perspective
(New
York,
NY:
Routledge,
2006);
Joanna
Shapland
&
et.
al,
Situating
Restorative
Justice
Within
Criminal
Justice
(2006)
10:4
Theoretical
Criminology
505-532
(Critiquing
work
seeking
to
reveal
flaws
in
the
RJ
theory
and
practice).
47
See
Margarita
Zernova,
Aspirations
of
Restorative
Justice
Proponents
and
Experiences
of
Participants
in
Family
Group
Conferences
(2007)
47
:3
Britihs
Journal
of
Criminology
491-509
at
491.
(Referring
to
fundamental
problems
in
the
RJ
philosophy
found
in
the
literature).
27
7. Thesis
preliminary
critique
and
defense
inequality caused by crime - i.e., one which occurs between victim and offender - may give
credit to certain detrimental internal power relations relevant to Aboriginal women. According to
my view, this happens simply because those power relations emerge from cultural and
philosophical practices that somehow resonate with the aspirations of RJ proponents, e.g., a
community pro-active role on conflict resolution, which can also mean --- in an Aboriginal view
of justice --- an alternative justice intervention that conveys political autonomy and self-
governance.48 However, as stated before victimized women may feel that their interests are not
exactly the same as those of their own community and that the majority of the community
restorative conferences. For example, a major untested assumption in the RJ discourse is that
when a conference is successfully undertaken, there are positive effects to all participants. It is
thought that if offenders learn from an RJ encounter they develop more empathetic feelings
about the impact of crime on victims, and they may be deterred from future offending. It is also
believed that RJ processes may assist in victims emotional and trauma recovery.49 However,
there is no guarantee that victims, offenders and community supportive members will come to
RJ conferences with equal power, equally able to assert their positions and to discuss and
negotiate the terms of a restorative agreement among them in order to benefit according to
48
As
observed
by
Cheon
and
Regehr,
Perhaps
the
most
distinguishing
characteristic
of
RJ
is
its
reliance
on
communities
of
care
to
carry
out
the
weighty
tasks
of
changing
offenders
behavior,
supporting
victims
in
healing,
enforcing
agreements,
and
doing
their
best
to
prevent
further
offending
(Dodd,
2002;
Presser
&
Gaarder,2000).
To
achieve
these
multiple
goals
simultaneously
is
not
an
easy
task
since
they
demand
juggling
several
interests,
at
times,
contradictory.
See
Aileen
Cheon
&
Cheryl
Regehr,
RJ
Models
in
Cases
of
Intimate
Partner
Violence:
Reviewing
the
Evidence
(2006)
1:4
Victims
&
Offenders
369-394
at
374.
49
See
generally
Elmar
G.
M.
Weitekamp
&
Hans-Jrgen
Kerner,
eds.,
RJ:
Theoretical
Foundation
(Mill
Street,
Uffculme:
Willan
Publishing
2002);
Eugene
McLaughlin
et
al.,
eds.,
Restorative
Justice:
Critical
Issues
(Thousand
Oaks,
CA:
Sage
Publications,
2003).
28
expectations. Some critics argue that all women are at a disadvantage in RJ conferences because
of their unequal moral, economic and social power; most agree that women who have been
battered are at a disadvantage in RJ as a result of the coercion and violence they have faced. As a
women when there is an imbalance amongst the various loci of inequality, creating more
problems than solutions and jeopardizing the very notion of it as an emancipatory feminist
research methodology. For this reason, I contend that it is better to insist on a more cautious
intersectionality as a well-proven tool for feminist critical analysis. On the contrary, I intend to
strengthen it by reflecting how under certain circumstances that invaluable feminist analytical
tool can be diverted by the restorative rhetoric and practice in ways that may even be considered
interventions as a remedy to deal with violence against women. Consequently, those feminist
scholars who are using an intersectional approach without considering the balance needed among
the various inequality categories embedded in this theory might be inclined to rush to approval
of policies committed to RJ models. Lamentably, this may occur without further investigation
concerning whether or not interventions based on RJ practices meet the needs of abused
Aboriginal women.
beneficial effects for women as a subject of inquiry. Indeed, it might be a disservice to them
because it neutralizes the best of intersectionality theory (its critical approach) and provides
29
legitimization and validation to RJ experiences not fully committed to gender awareness.50 The
term co-optation, as used in this paper, refers exactly to a process of neutralization and
intersectional approach must produce results functionally committed to womens interests and
essentially with them in sight. Representation of other interests like those present in RJ
discourses, even when theoretically noble and legitimate --- like the assertions of autonomy and
self-governance by Aboriginal people --- can be diversionary and overlook RJ faults concerning
approach as a strategy to foster a gender-centered perspective on the debate over the use of RJ to
cope with violence against women in Indigenous settings. This may be seen as a paradoxical
goal since the intersectionality methodology seeks departure from gender essentialism as I
stressed before.51 I am fully aware that recurring to gender as an inequality category that
deserves special attention may be considered a superseded idea. In fact, nowadays the use of
gender as a universal subject matter in inequality analysis is not held in esteem by new
labelled as monolithic and finally dismissed. At the center of these concerns is the danger of a
gendered analysis that is unable to attend to differences among and between racialized women as
intersectional feminists are constantly reminding us. Their critique has reinforced the scepticism
51
Angela
Harris
explains
the
notion
of
gender
essentialism
as
the
assumption
that
a
unitary,
essential
womens
experience
can
be
isolated
and
described
independently
of
race,
class,
sexual
orientation,
and
other
realities
of
experience.
See
Angela
P.
Harris,
Race
and
Essentialism
in
Feminist
Legal
Theory
(1990)
42
Stanford
Law
Review
at
581.
(Intersectional
feminists
argue
that
descriptions
of
inequality
located
in
one
category,
for
example,
gender
often
falsely
homogenizes
the
diverse
experiences
of
racialized
women).
30
about the unity apparent in the category gender by highlighting the intersectionality of
identities like race, class, immigration status and sexual orientation, etc. Hence, the weak point
in my line of reasoning would be not considering the fragmentation of the category gender and
perspectives and the different needs and interests among them. I also do not see gender in
isolation from other inequality categories. Rather, I seek to shift some territory to gender
questions --- using the concept of strategic essentialism --- in the midst of other competing
commonality amongst victims of intimate violence. After all, it would be impossible within the
context of violence against women to not give some privilege to gender as an analytical category
simply because this particular inequality category --- among others --- arises as an important
catalyst that precipitates violence and contributes significantly to the power imbalance in RJ
encounters in Indigenous communities. In addition, the fact that women in different social loci
may experience sexism differently does not mean that they have nothing in common since they
still can suffer the consequences from sexism, patriarchal oppression and from other general
effects of violence because they are women. Even when alternative justice practices like RJ are
either applied or heralded as committed to intersectional thinking it does not take too much to
misuse an intersectional approach regarding gender and race politics, especially when
Indigenous women are kept marginalized and silenced instead of being the center of all
attentions. For this reason, the effort of creating a balanced intersectional critical theory that
advances womens interests demands awareness of the ways that, paradoxically, intersectional
thinking can interact with forces that keep individuals into traditional patterns of oppression ---
31
Chapter
I
Restorative
justice
Chapter
outline
foundations and theoretical framework. In the first part, I present an account of the birth and
emergence of the RJ movement taking into consideration several areas of scholarship and social-
political activism that have apparently informed it. In order to do that, I rely heavily on previous
studies by Kathleen Daly; Russ Immarigeon; Julie Stubbs; Angela Cameron, and Theo
Gavrielides who were able to accumulate a considerable amount of data on RJ literature and
practice going back to its foundations and up to current developments. These scholars not only
collected data, but also put some order in the scholarly production on RJ establishing an outline
of what comprises the RJ movement in its standard criminal justice manifestation. They did it
through an extensive literature review on RJ of which I hope to make good use in this thesis as a
light of the foundational accounts to be developed in the first segment. Furthermore, I identify
some definitional problems concerning RJ; notably, because it is often regarded essentially as a
contested concept in the literature, or explained in the vaguest generalities.52 It is not rare to find
52
See
Gerry
Johnstone
&
Daniel
W.
Van
Ness
eds.,
Handbook
of
Restorative
Justice
Handbook
of
Restorative
Justice
(Mill
Street,
Uffculme:
Willan
Publishing,
2007)
at
5.
(Arguing
that
RJ
is
an
appraisive,
internally
complex
and
open
concept
that
continues
to
develop
with
new
practices.
For
this
reason,
it
cannot
accommodate
a
single
accepted
conception
otherwise
the
movement
could
be
impoverished
or
be
seen
as
misleading
since
might
be
presented
as
more
unified
and
coherent
than
it
actually
is).
See
Katherine
Doolin,
But
What
does
it
mean?
Seeking
Definitional
Clarity
in
Restorative
Justice
(2007)
71
J.
Crim.
L.
427-440.
(For
a
discussion
over
the
definitional
problems
of
RJ;
particularly,
whether
it
should
be
defined
in
terms
of
the
processes
to
be
used,
or
rather,
the
outcomes
to
be
achieved).
See
generally
William
B.
Gallie,
Essentially
Contested
Concepts
(1956)
56
Proceedings
of
the
Aristotelian
Society
167.
(Arguing
that
essentially
contested
concepts
are
in
nature
concepts
that
we
would
never
reach
agreement
about
the
criteria
for
its
application
because
they
combine
a
general
32
people even in academic and practitioner circles who use the term restorative justice
frequently in their everyday lives, but simply do not feel comfortable when confronted with
requests to explain what the concept of RJ really means.53 In this subsection, therefore, I hope to
shed some light on the problems regarding the lack of clarity of a RJ definition. M. Kay Harris
was amongst the first to suggest that we must have more definitional clarity in the field of RJ.
As Harris stresses above one, of the reasons for the lack of definitional clarity in
RJ is the multiplicity and ambiguity of meanings that cluster around the term restorative
justice. Actually, as pointed out by Zernova and Wright: It may not be an exaggeration to
agreement
on
the
abstract
notion
that
they
represent
with
endless
disagreements
about
what
they
might
mean
in
practice).
53
This
claim,
of
course,
is
not
entirely
anecdotal.
An
empirical
research
conducted
by
Theo
Gravielides
among
more
than
one
hundred
RJ
theorists
and
practitioners
around
the
world
provides
support
for
it.
The
study
reports
that
the
survey
participants
have
highlighted
that
conceptual
conflicts
and
different
practical
dimensions
of
RJ
have
affected
negatively
the
understanding
and
implementation
of
it.
Concerning,
for
instance:
a)
the
level
of
collaboration
and
communication
between
them
and
other
practitioners
working
either
in
the
same
or
different
RJ
programmes/organisations;
b)
the
outcomes
of
their
funding
applications
to
governmental
or
private
bodies;
c)
the
outcomes
of
the
RJ
processes;
d)
the
procedure
that
was
followed
by
RJ
facilitators;
e)
the
evaluation
of
restorative
programmes
and
their
outcomes;
f)
the
parties
willingness
to
participate;
g)
the
parties
motives
to
participate;
h)
the
level
of
communication
among
the
parties,
and
i)
the
genuineness
of
the
restorative
processes.
According
to
Theo
Gravielides,
the
study
shows
that
there
is
a
division
between
sources
of
a
theoretical
nature
and
sources
that
originate
from
the
field
of
practice.
This
separation
seems
to
have
affected
the
way
the
RJ
conception
was
received.
See
Theo
Gavrielides,
RJ
Theory
and
Practice:
Addressing
the
Discrepancy
(Monsey,
New
York:
Criminal
Justice
Press,
2007)
at
133.
(For
a
comprehensive
study
about
the
gaps
between
theory
and
practice
in
the
field
of
RJ)
54
See,
e.g.,
M.
Kay
Harris,
Reflections
of
a
Skeptical
Dreamer:
Some
Dilemmas
in
Restorative
Justice
theory
and
practice(1998)
1:1
Contemporary
Justice
Review
at
59.
33
suggest that each proponent has his or her own vision of restorative justice.55 So as we can see,
the fact is that RJ means many things to many people, and therefore is effectively without any
universal meaning or established standardizing procedures. This poses a challenge for employing
feminist analysis on RJ and intimate violence, since one perspective often has to be reframed in
different ways depending on proponents opinions on RJ. As a matter of fact, this can become a
serious epistemological problem since a conclusive description of what RJ really is may end up
in the eye of the beholder, i.e., what one observer might recognize as a textbook example of RJ
experience, another might recognize as something else that is not RJ in any way, and vice-versa.
potential tasks and roles for restorative justice, such that different schemes or commentators can
stress the importance of different aspects, and continue to disagree about what is its essence.56
to specific models accepted as being more accurate and authoritative in the literature.
Nonetheless, wherever there is considerable disagreement among scholars over whether or not a
certain practice really is RJ, I will address it in particular as I will do with the Indigenous
sentencing circles that will be engaged in a separate chapter. By referring throughout this chapter
to well known examples of RJ --- sketched in the work of several RJ scholars --- I put some flesh
on the theoretical bones that will be discussed in this chapter. My goal is to avoid equivocal
points surrounding the use of definitions in RJ, although I acknowledge that this strategy is not
cannot define a term due to the circularity of reasoning embedded in the act of exemplifying.
55
See
Margarita
Zernova
and
Martin
Wright,
Alternative
Visions
of
Restorative
Justice
in
Gerry
Johnstone
and
Daniel
W.
Van
Ness,
eds.
Handbook
of
Restorative
Justice
(Mill
Street,
Uffculme:
Willan
Publishing,
2007)
91
(Discussing
how
RJ
should
be
conceive
and
practised,
especially
raising
questions
over
the
debate
concerning
the
process-
oriented
concept
of
RJ
and
the
outcome-focused
RJ
concept).
56
See
note
47,
Shapland
et
al.,
Situating
Restorative
Justice,
at
506.
34
This approach is only an interim arrangement to justify the absence of a better definition of what
constitutes restorative justice. Having acknowledged that, I will use exemplification more as a
convenience tool than anything else; at least until a more consistent conceptualization of RJ is
reached by the literature and RJ doctrine. Another important point to be stressed here is that the
working definition to be provided in this chapter is only a limited theoretical concept of RJ that
clearly does not retain all its features and hence does not support a claim to be definitive.
There is yet one other factor complicating the conceptualization of RJ. The term
justice such as therapeutic justice; transformative justice; community justice; relational justice,
and peacemaking justice to the extent necessary to make a fine-grained analysis in order to
distinguish one from another. A good example of this difficulty are the continuities and
similarities between RJ and Indigenous justice that make them almost indiscernible from each
other to the point that one is often understood and explored in the literature through the other. In
this paper then, any unqualified reference to RJ means the inclusion of other experiences that
may fall under the rubric RJ unless specified otherwise. To complicate matters even further, RJ
principles, values and practices are also employed in other fields besides adult criminal justice;
youth justice being the most significant from which many general scholarly commentaries on RJ
were originally conceived and targeted. Where necessary I will situate RJ ideas in the specific
context of its usage and in conformity with the language and jargon articulated by the group or
particular program to which I am referring. I took this valuable lesson from Angela Cameron
who successfully used the same scheme in several of her studies on restorative justice.
differing fundamental assumptions about what aspirations; roles; responsibilities, and promises
exist for lay actors in RJ theory and practice. As a consequence, different versions of restorative
35
thinking may imply different focus on RJs stakeholders, i.e., offenders, victims and
community.57 Thus, there is clearly some logic to use a stakeholder approach when addressing
RJ. It can help in a quick assessment of the collective key issues for the lay actors of RJs theory
and practice while at the same time providing a stage where is possible to discern what is
acceptable to each as individuals. After all, a specific RJ program can give more emphasis to a
specific stakeholder, while deemphasizing others with whom it also interacts. This thesis
addresses the doubtful claim of some RJ advocates that it is possible to create a model of
alternative criminal justice which in ideal terms would equally empower all the stakeholders in
While one of the tenets of RJ theory is that all stakeholders matter and that
restorative models should integrate their responsibilities to the various stakeholders uniformly,
this balancing exercise has proven difficult to enact in practice. Bearing this in mind, this chapter
also provides a brief overview on substantial divergences in emphasis that can be found in the RJ
field regarding orientation in favour of victims, offenders and community and its reflects in
practical experiences. Still in accordance with that approach, my thesis adopts a framework
proposed by Angela Cameron in which she engages the problem of the ability of RJ models to
57
As
Howard
Zehr
and
Barb
Toews
point
out
the
term
stakeholders
is
widely
used
in
the
RJ
jargon
and
normally
refers
to
victims,
offenders
and
communities
which,
in
their
words,
make
the
heart
of
restorative
justice.
In
contrast,
they
also
consider
the
term
stakeholders
offensive
to
colonized
indigenous
people
since
in
its
origins
it
refers
to
European
settlers
of
North
America
driving
a
stake
into
the
ground
to
claim
land
that
originally
belonged
to
Indigenous
people.
See
Howard
Zehr
&
Barb
Toews,
eds.,
Critical
Issues
in
Restorative
Justice
(Monsey,
New
York:
Criminal
Justice
Press,
2004)
at
61-63.
(Although
I
have
found
quite
interesting
this
colourful
account
of
that
term
etymology,
mainly
because
I
am
an
Old
West
movies
fan,
I
believe
that
a
more
prosaic
meaning
applies
for
the
term
stakeholders,
i.e,
a
person
or
persons
with
an
interest
or
concern
in
something.
For
this
reason,
I
will
use
the
term
in
this
paper
without
any
reservations).
See
also
David
Cornwell
&
Heather
Strang,
The
Penal
Crisis
and
the
Clapham
Omnibus:
Questions
and
Answers
in
Restorative
Justice
(Hampshire,
UK:
Waterside
Press,
2009)
at
83
(Proposing
a
quadripartite
stakeholder
approach
where
besides
victims,
offenders
and
community
the
state
government
also
plays
a
role
in
the
RJ
movement).
36
cope with intimate violence, primarily through the lens of the needs of female victims of
interests, but realizing that without placing victims interests as a priority it is not possible to
achieve justice for all stakeholders. As will be discussed in another chapter, since victims ---
especially Indigenous women --- tend to have less influence on the dynamics of RJ interventions
than offenders and communities claims, mainly due to power imbalances and deep colonizing
effects, their claims and needs should be more carefully weighed than others stakeholders. As
Cameron put it, This is not intended to indicate that the interests of the offender are
unimportant; ending violence against women can only be accomplished by ensuring that those
who commit these crimes become whole, non violent beings.59 Likewise, a community
perspective will not be downplayed, although I argue in this paper that the cumulative effect of a
certain degree of cultural tolerance for violence in intimate relationships in conjunction with the
has been undermining the confidence in communities ability or willingness to take domestic
violence seriously enough. Finally, the acknowledgment of the primacy of victims interests is in
consonance with RJs general pledge for the protection of victims and victims rights. For this
reason, the perspective of victims will be a constant in this chapter as in the followings.
Finally, another part of this chapter considers a brief critique of the RJ movement
in the hope of providing a better portrait of it. Notably, concerning several points of tension in
the RJ movement identified mainly by Theo Gavrielides, Richard Delgado, R. London, and
Raymond Koen. These scholars invite us to take a critical look at several fault-lines in RJ theory,
58
See
note
11
at
15.
59
Ibid.
37
advocacy rhetoric and practice under historical, philosophical, sociolegal, and psychological
points of view. In addition, their line of critical analysis reveals a deep understanding of the main
themes of disagreement in the RJ movement, and sets out other themes for analysis as they may
evolve to other reflections like, for instance, the usability of RJ to deal with domestic violence
and the potential harms and benefits associated with it. Their findings will be succinctly
philosophy, and law, RJ --- as theory and practice --- also evolved from distinct and sometimes
political claims. For this reason, keeping track of all of these influences can be a difficult and
bewildering task. However, Daly and Immarigeon identified that the RJ movement mainly took
advantage of the following strands of ideas and activism: community, offender, and victim
disenchantment with the criminal justice system; concerns with the rising costs of punitive
policies, especially the costs of imprisonment; enthusiasm on the part of citizens and
governments to use informal processes whenever possible; and the popularity of metaphors of
reconciliation, healing, and restoration.60 They translated those strands of RJ ideology into a
three-fold categorization of the theoretical and empirical roots that have informed the
development of RJ thinking. According to these authors the core insights of RJ theory entail a
commitment to a set of ideas and practices that more or less include the following ideological
60
See
Kathleen
Daly
&
Russ
Immarigeon,
"Restorative
Justice:
Origins,
Practices,
Contexts,
and
Challenges"
(1997)
August
ICCA
Journal
on
Community
Corrections
1-17
at
2.
(Other
references
to
the
multi-layered
origins
of
RJ
appear
within
general
summaries
of
several
other
RJ
scholars).
See
also
Kathleen
Daly
&
Russ
Immarigeon,
The
Past,
Present,
and
Future
of
Restorative
Justice:
Some
Critical
Reflections
(1998)
1:1
The
Contemporary
Justice
Review
21-45
at
14.
(Refining
the
characterization
of
the
origins
of
the
RJ
movement).
38
and political sources: social movements of the 1960s and 1970s; particular practices and
grouped above do not coexist harmoniously. RJ theory and practice may encompass ---
depending on its empirical manifestation --- one or more of the aforementioned foundational
principles, and even when some RJ experience is consistent with one set of ideas it may be
inconsistent with others. The inevitable result is a fragmented theoretical and empirical
movement that somehow puts together cohorts of stakeholders --- victims, offenders and
community --- with distinct and sometimes conflicting interests. Thus, none of the following
ideological sources of the RJ movement made by Daly and Immarigeon are a perfect portrait of
its foundations. They rely on simplifying assumptions and only provide a first cut at
demonstrating how RJ has drawn from one foundational input to another. As Angela Cameron
The proliferation of the use of this term [Restorative Justice] has led to some confusion
and often to the conflation of disparate historical and political underpinnings that inform
varied visions of restorative justice. When discussing restorative justice it is vital that
the historical, political and cultural basis of the model or program in question be made
clear. This facilitates evaluation of whether a restorative initiative meets the needs of
victims of violence by framing the discussion of a particular model, with particular
attributes or problems.62 Brackets added.
In addition, their analysis was based on experiences carried out in North America
(Canada and United States) or Australasia (Australia and New Zealand) and does not reflect the
prominence and where it is currently applied as a first response to endemic social injustices
61
Ibid.
Daly
&
Immarigeon,
Origins,
at
7.
62
See
note
11
at
46.
39
found within the conventional criminal justice system that have a particular impact on ethnic
minorities and Aboriginal peoples. At the same time, they shed light on the underlying causes of
the difficulty of providing a unifying concept of restorative justice. In the following segments, I
refer directly or indirectly to many insights and schematizations initially devised by Daly and
Immarigeon in conjunction with other scholars contributions like Angela Cameron, and Theo
Gavrielides.
be traced back to the civil rights and womens movements of the turbulent 1960s and 1970s in
the United States and other countries.63 According to them the civil rights movement was based,
parallel, feminists perceived that conventional criminal justice institutions had been excluding
women --- who also found their partners routinely marginalized by incarceration --- ensured
feminist activists were, in the words of Daly and Immarigeon, also involved in prisoners rights
campaigns.64
viewed as antagonists in the justice system - ended up sharing common ground in their
63
See
note
61,
Daly
&
Immarigeon,
The
Past,
Present
at
5.
(Issues
such
as
overcriminalization
and
imprisonment
of
racial
and
ethnic
minority
groups
---
particularly,
African
Americans
and
Indigenous
People
---
and
the
mistreatment
of
victims
in
the
criminal
justice
process
were
of
crucial
importance
to
catalyze
the
RJ
movement
in
the
United
Sates.
Likewise,
anti-colonial
movements
in
Canada,
Australia
and
New
Zealand
embraced
those
perceptions
and
echoed
them
in
their
own
settings.
For
example,
the
struggle
of
the
Maori
people
against
their
overrepresentation
in
the
criminal
justice
system
in
New
Zealand
and
similar
concerns
of
Aboriginal
and
First
Nations
people
in
Australia
and
Canada
fuelled
the
discussions
for
alternatives
to
the
conventional
criminal
justice
system
in
the
mid-1970s
and
following
decades).
64
Ibid.
at
5-6.
40
experiences with conventional justice system practices usually seen as unfair and unresponsive
to their particularities and needs. Those perceptions were crucial in triggering decarceration
actions, including prisoners rights campaigns and alternatives to confinement. As a result, a new
line of feminist reasoning made a case for challenging existing remedies for violence against
women around ideas such as alternatives to prisons, methods of alternative dispute resolution
and informal justice. Some strands of RJ practice are a direct result of that criticism of the
traditional justice system and turning to alternative processes for resolving disputes; to
alternative sanctioning options, or as Daly and Immarigeon put it, to a distinctively different,
new mode of criminal justice organized around principles of restoration to victims, offenders,
and the communities in which they live.65 In contrast, during the 1970s the battered womens
movement also pursued reforms in the criminal justice system that also superficially aligned
many feminists with conservative retributive-based get tough policies. These reforms, with the
goal of providing greater victim safety and increased offender accountability, were eventually
put into effect in the mid-1980s and resulted in actions such as mandatory pro-arrest policies for
police, no-drop prosecutorial policies (mandatory policies that do not allow victims to determine
whether or not arrest and prosecution takes place), and restraining orders (also known as
protective orders). This movement is also credit with a myriad of non-punitive victim-oriented
services like battered women's shelters and safe-houses; emergency hotlines; counselling and
support groups; financial assistance; transportation; job and housing locator services; civil relief
legal assistance; and children's programs.66 However, gradually feminist scholars started to
express ambivalence about the more conservative and harsh conformation of the conventional
65
Ibid.
at
2.
66
See
Kim
Cook,
A
Restorative
Justice
Critique
of
Shelters
for
Battered
Women
in
the
American
Deep
South
Center
Prison
Fellowship
International
Centre
for
Justice
and
Reconciliation,
on
line
(26
August
2006):
Restorative
Justice
On
line:
<http://www.restorativejustice.org/10fulltext/cook/view/>
Retrieved
on
March
2010.
(Contending
that
shelters
cannot
be
deemed
a
community
of
care
in
the
restorative
justice
sense
of
the
expression).
41
criminal system that generated a desire for less-punitive and non-state-based interventions. There
were concerns that some non-white, non-middle-class, and immigrant women simply did not
want to see their partners arrested or prosecuted and were negatively impacted by these
Such feelings were part of a larger set of concerns and criticisms that have run
through feminist theorizing since the 1970s when racialized-women started to question the very
notion that the conventional criminal justice system itself could deliver justice to women
victimized by intimate violence. The fact is that RJ theoretical language was profoundly
victims in courts derived from social movements in the 1960s and 1970s. However, tracking the
influence of all these elements in the RJ discourse is complicated by practical experiences that
also emerged spontaneously almost at the same time in response to similar claims. In the
following subsection I address these practical experiences according to Daly and Immarigeons
previous categorizations.
Feminist scholars like Daly and Immarigeon also share the view that RJ practical
models had important inputs in the RJ movement. In fact, citing Tony Marshall they suggest that,
67
The
impact
of
tough
on
crime
or
zero
tolerance
policies
on
domestic
violence
cases
was
subjected
to
criticism
by
some
feminist
scholars
who
found
that
these
policies
operate
in
ways
that
may
further
state
control
of
women,
particularly
women
who
are
marginalized
by
race,
class,
and
immigrant
status.
Mandatory
arrest
and
prosecution
policies,
for
instance,
may
result
in
increased
numbers
of
arrests
of
non-citizen
women
who
may
then
be
deemed
deportable
under
immigration
law;
my
aggravate
racist
and
abusive
police
behaviors;
result
on
overincarceration
of
men
of
color;
reinforce
pathological
notions
that
battered
women
do
not
want
to
assist
prosecution
and
that
they
accept
violence
staying
with
the
offender;
unwarranted
removal
by
the
state
of
children
from
women
who
have
been
battered;
prosecution
of
battered
women
involved,
even
peripherally,
in
criminal
conduct,
and
limits
womens
ability
to
use
the
criminal
justice
system
strategically
to
gain
greater
control
over
their
lives,
but
did
not
necessarily
complete
legal
processes.
See
note
25,
Coker,
Transformative
Justice,
at
133.
(summarizing
the
literature
on
this
point).
See
also
note
25,
Coker,
Crime
Control.
42
the practice of restorative justice came first, born of the exigencies of needing to do justice
differently, and that the theory came later.68 As Daly and Immarigeon point out, since the 1970s
many programs and practices have been implemented that could be labeled as restorative justice
experiments. These pioneers experiments almost functioned on a trial and error basis with no
prior guidelines apart from practitioners dissatisfaction with the fact-finding adversarial in-court
process and in earnest desire for a more humane, informal conflict resolution.69 According to
Daly and Immarigeon, early efforts focused on moderated meetings between victims and
offenders, adapting or drawing from traditional mediation models.70 According to Daly and
Immarigeon, early efforts focused on moderated meetings between victims and offenders,
adapting or drawing from traditional mediation models.71 Later, they concluded, these
68
See
note
61,
Daly
&
Immarigeon,
The
Past,
Present,
at
11.
See
also
Tony
F.
Marshall,
The
Evolution
of
Restorative
Justice
in
Britain
(1996)
4
European
Journal
on
Criminal
Justice
and
Research
21-43.
69
A
good
example
is
the
acknowledgement
of
pioneer
work
by
practitioners
initiatives
like
the
Victim
offender
reconciliation
programs
(VORP)
format
that
can
be
traced
to
Kitchener,
Ontario
where
in
1974
Mark
Yantzi
and
Dave
Worth,
both
members
of
the
Mennonite
Church,
working
with
the
Kitchener
Probation
Department
and
with
the
help
of
a
local
judge
successfully
established
a
restitution
and
reconciliation
program
based
in
face-to-face
mediation
addressing
emotional
and
informal
needs
of
offenders
and
victims.
A
few
years
later
in
1978
the
first
American
program
was
established
in
Elkhart,
Indiana
also
under
the
auspices
of
Mennonite
Church
representatives;
the
local
judge;
probation
officers,
and
a
community
corrections
organization
called
PACT
(Prisoner
and
Community
Together).
These
programs
were
quickly
replicated
in
other
parts
of
North
America
and
gained
the
status
of
being
considered
the
first
RJ
practical
experiences
in
North
America.
See
Dean
E.
Peachey,
The
Kitchener
Experiment
in
Gerry
Johnstone,
ed.,
A
Restorative
Justice
Reader:
Texts,
Sources,
Contexts
(Devon,
UK:
Willan
Publishing,
2003)
at
178.
70
A
good
example
is
the
acknowledgement
of
pioneer
work
by
practitioners
initiatives
like
the
Victim
offender
reconciliation
programs
(VORP)
format
that
can
be
traced
to
Kitchener,
Ontario
where
in
1974
Mark
Yantzi
and
Dave
Worth,
both
members
of
the
Mennonite
Church,
working
with
the
Kitchener
Probation
Department
and
with
the
help
of
a
local
judge
successfully
established
a
restitution
and
reconciliation
program
based
in
face-to-face
mediation
addressing
emotional
and
informal
needs
of
offenders
and
victims.
A
few
years
later
in
1978
the
first
American
program
was
established
in
Elkhart,
Indiana
also
under
the
auspices
of
Mennonite
Church
representatives;
the
local
judge;
probation
officers,
and
a
community
corrections
organization
called
PACT
(Prisoner
and
Community
Together).
These
programs
were
quickly
replicated
in
other
parts
of
North
America
and
gained
the
status
of
being
considered
the
first
RJ
practical
experiences
in
North
America.
See
Dean
E.
Peachey,
The
Kitchener
Experiment
in
Gerry
Johnstone,
ed.,
A
Restorative
Justice
Reader:
Texts,
Sources,
Contexts
(Devon,
UK:
Willan
Publishing,
2003)
at
178.
71
See
note
61,
Daly
&
Immarigeon,
Origins,
at
2.
43
meetings expanded to include family members and friends of both parties, as well as
practitioners influence on the foundations of RJ has a relationship with others strains of socio-
political justice reform. For example, many RJ practices and its decarceration aims were clearly
prisoners rights projects since its originators felt offenders were victims of societal neglect,
impoverished communities, and racial and gender discrimination. Accordingly, advocates hoped
to change prison conditions, minimize the use of incarceration, and even abolish jails and
prisons.73 Daly and Immagerion also suggested that practitioners were driven by victim
advocacy influences since Victims rights groups focused efforts on restitution for crime, on
victims having a formal voice in the court process, and on community safety.74. Although RJ
practices focus on differing interests, Alliances between victim advocacy groups and criminal
justice reform groups began to grow in the 1990s, as members recognized some common
interests.75
by Kathleen Daly in several countries, but especially in North America and Australasia include
As Daly accounts, RJ practices seem to rely on the following premises (at least in
As Angela Cameron warns, the format, scope and agenda of RJ models are
extremely diverse in their jurisdiction, display and subjects implicated. She writes: Restorative
justice interventions are used at various stages of an offenders involvement in the criminal
justice system including: 1. Police (pre-charge) 2. Crown (post charge) 3. Courts (pre-
76
See
Kathleen
Daly,
Restorative
Justice
in
Diverse
and
Unequal
Societies,
(2000)
17:1
Law
in
Context
at
4.
77
See
Kathleen
Daly
&
Sarah
Curtis-Fawley,
"Gendered
Violence
and
Restorative
Justice:
The
Views
of
Victim
Advocates"
(2005)
11
Violence
Against
Women
603
at
606.
45
78
2001). Daly adds that all these practices may be presented, as diversion from the formal
court process, actions taken in parallel with court decisions, meetings between offenders and
victims at any stage of the criminal process (from arrest, presentencing, and prison release), or
meetings held for child protection cases.79 It is important to remind the reader that the examples
listed before are only a sample of experiences commonly associated with RJ values, processes
and outcomes. The diversity of the RJ movement cannot be contained solely in such practical
models. As Angela Cameron notes, While the term restorative justice is used to refer to
academic research and theory occupied pivotal roles for the development of the RJ movement as
well. After this brief overview of pragmatic influences on RJ the next paragraphs will survey
precursory theoretical debates amongst scholars on the subject; it will concentrate on social-legal
scholars, feminist views and justice theorists who from academia have given shape and
Informal Justice and Abolitionism are ideas that are strongly associated with RJ
ideological discourse. Daly and Stubbs note, for example, that informal justice along with
victim-offender mediation and community conflict resolution in the 1970s and 1980s were
78
See
note
2
at
8
[unpublished].
(Noting
and
citing
sources
in
a
comprehensive
literature
review
on
RJ
and
domestic
violence.
Though
leaving
aside
other
dimensions
as
youth
justice;
corrections;
peacebuilding,
and
other
constituents
of
RJ
practice)
79
See
note
61,
Daly
&
Immarigeon,
The
Past,
Present
at
2.
80
Supra
note
77
at
4.
46
precursors to RJ interventions.81 However, they warn that many feminists, after an initial
endorsement, have become disillusioned with the ability of informal negotiated processes --- like
family mediation --- to tackle violence against women. The mediation or conciliation model was
criticized for defining battering and other offences as trivial disputes. Another critique was the
pressure put on women to obtain reconciliation. Furthermore, fear for womens safety and
and violence patterns made feminists condemn those experiences for erasing victimization. Later
those same critiques were influential in curbing feminist enthusiasm for RJ practices. In
discussing this issue, Stephen Hooper and Ruth Busch included this comment:
On the other hand, Daly and Stubbs observe that RJ and mediation practices are
not the same.83 They argue that in their ideal form RJ practices recognize victims and offenders
and hold the latter accountable for wrongdoing. There is no push to reconcile, nor is
victimization erased. In addition there is the presence of symbolic members of the community or
family supporters of victims and offenders. The presence and interaction of these agents ensure
that the nature of the offence is wrong (denunciation); that the victim was injured (empathy); and
that the offender is considered responsible (accountability). Allegedly, the offender is also
81
See
note
9
at
154.
See
also
Lisa
G.
Lerman,
Mediation
of
Wife
Abuse
Cases:
The
Adverse
Impact
of
Informal
Dispute
Resolution
on
Women
(1984)
7
Harvard
Womens
Law
Journal
57.
(Criticizing
the
use
of
mediation
for
domestic
violence
cases).
See
also
Lois
Presser
&
Emily
Gaarder,
Can
Restorative
Justice
Reduce
Battering?
Some
Preliminary
Considerations
(2000)
27
Social
Justice
175.
See
also
note
61.
See
generally
Richard
L.
Abel,
ed.,
The
Politics
of
Informal
Justice.
(New
York:
Academic
Press,
1982)
Vol.
I
&
II.
82
See
Ruth
Busch
&
Stephen
Hooper,
Domestic
Violence
and
Restorative
Justice
Initiatives:
The
Risks
of
a
New
Panacea.
Waikato
Law
Review
(1996)
4
:
188.
83
See
note
81,
Daly
&
Julie
Stubbs,
Feminist
Theory
at
154.
47
confronted with the full consequences of the crime. Finally, in the same dialogue-based process,
family, neighborhood and society are benefited by the reintegration of the offender and victim to
There were also important implications in the findings that emerged from
informal justice investigations like empirical and theoretical studies of informal and formal
Several of those studies advocated that criminal justice could be administered in a consistent and
efficient way without the restraints of court formalities so that the subjects involved in a crime
matter could cope with it by themselves with very low or no state intervention and without
professionals like lawyers, judges, etc. A good example is the work by Nils Christie who is
considered a leading proponent of Informal Justice and also an important penal abolitionist. He
Christie argued that the State had stolen the conflict between citizens, and this
had deprived society of entertaining non-state-based solutions for conflicts, including crimes.84
Instead of enabling those in conflict to resolve troubles, he argued that the State had taken
control of the matter translating it into the professionalized context of the criminal justice system
in which neither victim nor offender is allowed any meaningful role. According to him we
should seek to eliminate the concept of crime from our social vocabulary. We should talk and
think not in terms of crimes, but of conflicts or troubles. Thus, conflicts and troubles are
inevitable parts of everyday life, and therefore should not be delegated to professionals and
specialists claiming to provide solutions. Christie believed that by restricting criminal procedure
and law to the narrow legal definition of what is relevant and what is not, the victim and the
84
See
Nils
Christie,
Conflicts
as
Property
(1977)
17:1
British
Journal
of
Criminology
1-15.
48
offender could not explore the degree of their culpability and the real effects of the event. The RJ
advocacy argument of being an anti-State participatory and democratic form of justice that
involves victims, offenders and community is clearly articulated in Christies precursory study
Bianchi. Bianchi claimed that there are better ways of dealing with society's criminals than
putting them behind bars, arguing that the current criminal justice system is based on a view of
points out, justice in Bianchis view is not a set of scales to be balanced, or a form of moral
accounting. It is a relational experience.86 Here another core insight motivating the RJ theory
relationships.
Martin Wright, another penal abolitionist, also led the construction of the RJ
theoretical framework.87 It is in Wright's work that some of the questions that later motivated
many RJ thinkers on the conception of RJ are for the first time explicitly considered. Wright
proposed that the offender or the community should help the victim, and that the offender should
be required to make amends to both. Only this way, he argued, the offender would demonstrate
respect for a victims feelings and offer them practical help, while treating offenders in a non-
punitive way would draw them back into society rather than increase their isolation. The concept
85
See
Herman
Bianchi,
Tsedeka
Justice
(1973),
Review
for
Philosophy
and
Theology
306-317.
Herman
Bianchi,
Justice
as
Sanctuary:
Toward
a
New
System
of
Crime
Control
(Bloomington:
Indiana
University
Press,
1994).
86
See
note
54
at
21.
87
See
Martin
Wright,
Nobody
Came:
Criminal
Justice
and
the
Needs
of
Victims
(1977)
Howard
Journal
16:1
22.
See
generally
T.
Mathiesen,
Prison
on
Trial.
(London:
Sage,
1990)
and
L.
Hulsman,
The
Abolitionist
Case:
Alternative
Crime
Policies
(1991)
25
Israel
Law
Review
681-709.
49
of victim and offender participating in a non-retributive, non-adversarial process that pursues
and using concepts like shame and trauma recovery seeking to reinforce the benefits of RJ
approaches were also relevant to the construction of the RJ ideological language. The most
prominent of them is John Braithwaite who formulated one of the most famous
introduced the idea of reintegrative shaming to argue for an integrative rather than stigmatizing
response to crime and its effects. Braithwaite's theory of reintegrative shaming was extensively
put into practice in RJ models in New South Wales, Australia. Most notably the police led
Braithwaite believes that shaming is the key to controlling all types of crime. In
particular, he distinguishes two kinds of shame. The first is, what he calls, stigmatising
shame, as it disintegrates the moral bonds between the offender and the community. The
second is the reintegrative shame, which strengthens the moral bonds between the
offender and the community. Stigmatisation (bad shaming) increases crime, but
reintegrative shaming decreases it. Braithwaite embraces the idea of hating the sin but
loving the sinner, claiming that offenders should be given the opportunity to re-join their
community as law abiding citizens. However, in order to earn this right to a fresh start,
offenders must express remorse for their past conduct, apologize to their victims and
repair the harm caused by the crime.89
88
See
especially
note
47,
Braithwaite,
Crime,
Shame
and
Reintegration.
See
also
Nathan
Harris,
Lode
Walgrave,
John
Braithwaite,
"Emotional
Dynamics
in
Restorative
Conferences"(2004)
8:2
Theoretical
Criminology
191-210.
See
generally
John
Braithwaite
&
Philip
Petit,
Not
Just
Deserts:
a
Republican
Theory
of
Criminal
Justice
(Oxford:
Clarendon
Press,
1990).
89
See
note
54
at
25.
50
As also noted above, the role of trauma recovery in RJ interventions has also
emerged as an especially important feature in its theoretical framework. More recently RJ has
been seen by many of its proponents as a kind of cognitive behavioral therapy able to relieve
crime victims from post-traumatic stress disorder (PTSD) symptoms and other pathologies
associated with victimization. For instance, Paul McCold points out that RJ conferences provide
opportunities for victims to hold offenders accountable, tell their story to offenders and others,
and receive new information that may have been missing; all of which are also components of
most situations of conflict and wrongdoing. RJ can acknowledge and address this sense of
victimization and the resulting needs often for everyone involved, including those who have
offended. (Indeed, it can be argued that much offending perhaps most or all violence grows
psychoanalytic frameworks employed by Braithwaite and others, such ideas have proven to be
illustrate, scholars listed several dimensions of the use of RJ outside the criminal justice field.
For example; youth justice; corrections; school discipline; workplace management; corporate
disputes, and employment/trade union disputes have been mentioned as practical dimensions of
90
See
Interview
of
Paul
MacCold
by
Abbey
J.
Porter,
Restorative
Conferences
reduce
Trauma
from
Crime,
Study
shows
from
the
International
Institute
of
Restorative
Practices
(15
August
2006)
on
Restorative
Practices
EForum
online:www.iirp.org
retrieved
on
January
10,
2009.
See
also
David
L.
Gustason,
Exploring
Treatment
and
Trauma
Recovery
Implications
of
Facilitating
Victim
Offender
Encounters
in
Crimes
of
Severe
Violence:
Lessons
from
the
Canadian
Experience
in
Elizabeth
Elliott
&
Robert
G.
Cullomptom,
eds.,
New
Directions
in
Restorative
Justice:
Issues
,
Practice,
Evaluation
(Portland,
OR:
Willan
Publishing,
2005)
at
193.
51
the RJ movement.91 All of them benefited from the allegedly curative properties of RJ
interventions.
contemporary feminist theorists on justice practices like Carol Gilligan, Frances Heidensohn and
Kay Harris. According to Daly and Immarigeon, Gilligan has asked whether and, if so, to what
extent our vision for understanding criminal justice is distorted in a way that privileges a
masculine view of justice --- named ethics of justice--- to the detriment of moral reasoning
and decision-making guided by a feminine ethic of care.92 This works in the following way, as
Daly and Stubbs put it: the ethic of care centres on moral concepts of responsibility and
relationship; it is a concrete and active morality. The ethic of justice centres on moral concepts
of rights and rules; it is a formal, universalizing and abstract morality.93 In criminology, some
have found the ethic of care useful, for example, Kay Harris and Frances Heidensohn who
developed a care/justice dichotomy of the criminal justice system, drawing on Gilligans work.
Heidensohn articulated two models of justice. The first is a Portia model, which values
values caring and personal relations.94 Harris also emphasised values associated with the
91
See
Declan
Roche,
Dimensions
of
Restorative
Justice
(2006)
62:2
Journal
of
Social
Issues
217-238
(Describing
various
other
dimensions
of
restorative
justice
situated
outside
and
alongside
the
criminal
justice
field)
92
See
note
61
Daly
&
Immarigeon,
The
Past,
Present,
at
13.
93
See
note
9,
Daly
&
Stubbs,
Feminist
Theory
at
153.
See
especially
Carol
Gilligan,
A
Different
Voice:
Psychological
Theory
and
Women's
Development
(Cambridge,
MA:
Harvard
University
Press,
1982).
94
See
Frances
Heidensohn,
Models
of
justice:
Portia
or
Persephone?
Some
thoughts
on
equality,
fairness
and
gender
in
the
field
of
criminal
justice
(1986)
14
International
Journal
of
the
Sociology
of
Law
287308.
52
care/response approach rather than a justice/rights orientation, although she acknowledges that a
continued to use Gilligans different voice associating this variety of care-focused feminist
approach to RJ discourse. As Daly and Stubbs observed, Guy Masters and David Smith
(1998) invoke Gilligans work in their attempt to compare retributive justice and RJ, and they
argue that RJ offers a more caring response to crime (see the critique in Daly 2002a).96
However, Daly and Stubbs also pointed out that Gilligans different voice construct was
superseded by more complex analyses of ethics and moral reasoning, especially due to the influx
of ideas from critical race and postmodern feminism in the 1990s that addressed the multiple
influences of inequality markers like class, race, ethnicity and gender on social intereactions. In
time, as noted by Daly, these reading strategies came to be known as intersectionality analysis
or simply intersectionality theory. Nevertheless, Daly and Immarigeon observed that some
current RJ practices remained inspired by the ethic of care approach. To illustrate this point they
mention the work of Pennel and Burford on current family group conferencing in domestic
violence cases in Canada.97 The feminist project concerning RJ will be further explored in the
second chapter of this paper; notably, from the point of view of intersectionality theory.
95
M.
Kay
Harris,
Moving
into
the
new
millennium:
Toward
a
feminist
view
of
justice
in
H.
E.
Pepinsky
&
R.
Quinney
,
eds.,
Criminology
as
peacemaking
(Bloomington,
IN:
Indiana
University
Press,
1998)
83-97.
96
See
note
9
at
154.
97
See
note
61
Daly
&
Immarigeon,
The
Past,
Present
at
13..
See
also
J.
Pennell
&
G.
Burford,
Widening
the
Circle:
The
Family
Group
Decision
Making
Project
(1994)
9
Journal
of
Child
&
Youth
Care
1-12.
53
arguments for alternatives to the conventional justice system. According to Daly and
Immarigeon peacemaking criminology corresponds to the idea that crime and criminal justice
are violence and suffering. The idea finds substantial support in different traditions, including
spiritualism and feminism. The most striking concept of peacemaking criminology is provided
by Pepinsky and Quinney. Daly and Immarigeon delineated their new criminology by way of
Quinney's definition of it as a criminology that seeks to alleviate suffering and thereby reduce
crime.98 Quinney argues that, The ending of both suffering and crime, which is the
establishing of justice, can only come out of peace, peace that is spiritually grounded in our very
being."99
philosophical justifications and calling for restricting the use of penal sanctions and for non-
retributive modes of response to criminal offences. Theo Gavrielides chronicled the work of
these early RJ ideologists. He starts with the work of Philip Pettit and John Braithwaite who
advanced the RJ ideological framework based on republican ideals. They have sought to reframe
what they regard as the key normative questions in the conventional criminal justice system in
compare a full retributivist position with a full republican position and conclude that a full just-
deserts policy would increase injustice while a republican policy would reduce it. As Gavrielides
noted, arguably their Not Just Deserts theory now constitutes the strongest proof of theoretical
work on RJ.100
98
See
note
61
Daly
&
Immarigeon,
The
Past,
Present
at
13.
See
especially
H.
E.
Pepinsky
&
R.
Quinney,
eds.,
Criminology
as
Peacemaking
(Bloomington:
Indiana
University
Press,1991).
99
Ibid.
100
See
note
54
at
25.
See
especially
note
88,
Braithwaite
and
Philip
Pettit,
Not
Just
Deserts.
54
Others drew on philosophical inquiries which try to revisit some basic problems
that are associated with the role and use of punishment, criticizing the traditional punishment
theories. For example, Wesley Cragg, as Gavrielides noted, argued in favour of formal
justice, which according to his opinion is not antithetical to the restorative values of forgiveness,
philosophical standpoint, looks to ethics in restorative processes and the issue of how to
develop and maintain mediation practice that respects ethical principles, and is of good quality
for victims and offenders.102 Aleksandar Fatic was another scholar who tried to establish a
philosophical justification for RJ. Gavrielides wrote that he based his theory on the moral
principle of refraining from the deliberate infliction of pain, as well as on the functional principle
of maximization of trust as a social commodity. and in the creation of a pacifist society, where
traditional legitimists accounts of justice. In fact, traditional legitimist accounts are prevalent in
RJ literature, where they typically come in the form of associations made by practitioners and
theorists between RJ and Indigenous or Christian Religious practices. RJs roots are
conceptualized on the basis of its spiritual or moral legitimacy, drawing on Indigenous forms of
101
Supra
note
at
26.
See
also
Robert
Mackay,
Reparation
and
the
Debate
about
Justice,
(Edinburgh:
University
of
Edinburgh,
1992)
102
Ibid.
103
See
note
54.
See
also
Aleksandar
Fatic,
Punishment
and
Restorative
Crime-Handling:
A
Social
Theory
of
Trust,
(Aldershot,
UK:
Avebury
Ashgate
Publishing,
1995).
55
g) Indigenous
justice
and
religious
roots
Justice. According to Daly, Indigenous justice refers to a variety of justice practices, normally
focused on sentencing, in which Indigenous people have a central role in responding to crime.
They include urban sentencing courts, community justice groups advice to judges in sentencing,
Elders participation in sentencing, and a variety of forms and contexts of sentencing circles.104
These approaches aim directly as Daly puts it, to rebuild Indigenous communities and to redress
the destruction of Indigenous peoples culture and social organization brought about by
colonialism and state violence (Marchetti & Daly, 2004, 2007)105. These attempts to increase
determination means to use wherever possible alternatives to the non-Indigenous criminal justice
system in order to open space to alternatives to incarceration that are normally used in the
conventional criminal justice. This is particularly true because Aboriginal groups are known to
be over-represented in the criminal justice systems of Canada and Australia (our main focus of
interest) both as victims and offenders and resent by the lack of political autonomy and
104
See
note
16,
Kathleen
Daly,
Seeking
Justice,
at
8.
105
Ibid.
106
A
full
discussion
of
the
implications
of
this
claim
would
require
much
more
investigation.
However,
the
empirical
evidence
speaks
by
itself.
In
the
case
of
Canada,
for
example,
according
to
data
originally
compiled
by
Statistics
Canada,
in
2007/2008,
Aboriginal
people
are
being
imprisoned
at
a
disproportionate
rate
when
compared
to
non-Aboriginal
people.
Although
Aboriginal
people
represent
only
three
percent
of
the
Canadian
population,
they
made
up
22
percent
of
individuals
sentenced
to
custody
in
the
provincial
or
federal
correctional
system.
The
figures
are
even
more
impressive
in
some
provinces.
For
example,
Aboriginal
people
accounted
for
81
percent
of
admissions
to
sentenced
custody
in
Saskatchewan
and
69
percent
in
Manitoba,
but
represented
only
11
percent
and
12
percent
of
the
provincial
populations,
respectively.
In
2004
(the
latest
year
for
which
data
is
56
Many RJ proponents and practitioners like to characterize RJ experiences as
suitably rooted within Indigenous Justice traditions, describing it --- as noted by Angela
Cameron as modeled on these cultures which practiced restoration and healing following
anti-social behaviour rather than punishment.107 Although Cameron has acknowledged the
analogous to Indigenous or Aboriginal Justice, she also asserted that Indigenous Justices true
identity cannot be mixed up with RJ due to the unique role of Aboriginal spirituality and culture
Furthermore, she points out that Indigenous Justice practices should not be
identified with RJ, since in her words, the contemporary restorative justice movement is not
grounding.109 Moreover, citing Kent Roach, a Canadian scholar, Cameron notes that
Indigenous Justice developed a specific perspective focusing on renewing collective identity and
creating community rather than individual reparation notions, which is precisely a point of
available),
Aboriginal
people
were
also
three
times
more
likely
than
non-Aboriginal
people
to
be
the
victim
of
sexual
assault,
robbery
or
physical
assault
(319
versus
101
incidents
per
1,000
populations).
See
The
Environics
Institute,
The
Urban
Aboriginal
Peoples
Study
(2010)
online:
Urban
Aboriginal
People
Study
<
http://uaps.ca/>
retrieved
on
11
April
2010.
See
also
Statistics
Canada,
Incarceration
of
Aboriginal
people
in
adult
correctional
services
(Otawa:
Statistics
Canada
Catalogue
no.
11-001-XIE,
2009).
See
also
Jodi-Anne
Brzozowski
et
al.
Victimization
and
offending
among
the
Aboriginal
population
in
Canada.
(2006)
26:3
Juristat.
Statistics
Canada
Catalogue
no.
85-002-XIE.
In
Australia
the
figures
are
not
much
different.
In
Western
Australia,
for
example,
in
2004,
Aboriginal
people
comprised
40
per
cent
of
the
prison
population
although
they
only
represent
3
percent
of
that
state
population.
Aboriginal
people
in
Western
Australia
are
also
overrepresented
as
victims.
In
2003
Aboriginal
people
were
eight
times
more
likely
than
non-Aboriginal
people
to
be
victims
of
violence.
For
Aboriginal
women
the
figures
are
appalling;
they
are
45
times
more
likely
than
non-Aboriginal
women
to
be
victims
of
domestic
violence
by
spouses
or
partners.
See
Austl.,
W.A.,
Law
Reform
Commission
of
Western
Australia,
Aboriginal
Customary
Laws:
The
interaction
of
Western
Australian
law
with
Aboriginal
law
and
culture
(Final
Report
No.94)
by
Commissioner AG
Braddock
(Perth:
Quality
Press,
2006)
at
95-96.
See
generally
Roy
Walmsley,
World
Prison
Population
List,
8th
ed.
(London:
International
Centre
for
Prison
Studies,
2009).
107
See
note
16,
Kathleen
Daly,
Seeking
Justice,
at
6.
108
See
note
2
at
6
109
Ibid.
57
departure from RJ conventional practices.110 Kathleen Daly summarizes this point of sharp
For restorative justice, the focus of the interaction and relationship building is between
offenders, victims, their supporters, community members, and the community (a non-
racially specified community),9 along with professionals such as a police officer and
coordinator. For Indigenous sentencing courts, the focus is between offenders, their
supporters, Elders, the Indigenous community (including service providers), and white
justice (typically, embodied in the legal roles of the magistrate, prosecutor, and defense
attorney).10 Doing justice in a restorative process gives attention to victims and to re-
building relationships between a victim, an offender, and their community; whereas doing
justice in Indigenous sentencing courts gives attention to changing relationships between
white justice and Indigenous people, including the offender. Relatively less attention is
currently given to addressing the needs of victims in Indigenous sentencing courts,
although this may change (Marchetti & Daly, 2007).111
Accordingly, only recently and perhaps because of the efforts of scholars like
Angela Cameron and Kathleen Daly, has the literature on RJ started to make distinctions
between white-based RJ and Indigenous Justice in a way that makes it possible to discern clearly
between the two informal justice alternatives. Increasingly, however, Indigenous Justice and
certain models of white-based restorative justice (mainly conference-based) have been more
difficult to distinguish from one another since their inspiration and modes of operation are
basically the same. Daly, for instance, describes the similarities between them. According to her
rely on lay actors (for restorative justice, victims and their supporters, an offenders
supporters, and other community members; for Indigenous justice, an offenders
supporters, Elders, and other members of the Indigenous community); and
110
Ibid.
111
Ibid.
at
13.
58
improved communication between legal authorities, offenders, victims, and community
members, using plain language and reducing some legal formalities;
procedural justice, i.e., treating people with respect, listening to what people have to
say, and being fair to everyone; and
relationships between victims, offenders, and their communities (a tenet of RJ), with the great
deal of attention given in Indigenous Justice practices to changing relationships between white
justice and Indigenous justice - where more emphasis is placed on the offender - is a sensitive
point in my thesis. Clearly, the issue here is that Indigenous justice can be considered an
movements that is more centered in potential short-term communal political benefits of making
use of their own cultural norms, holistic values, and customary legal institutions in order to avoid
the challenges they may face within the conventional justice system, whereas the white/western
RJ movement is more centered, as Daly writes, with changing justice practices to become more
victims.113 This proposition raises some questions: Is it Indigenous political claims that shape
the RJ movement? Or is the relationship the reverse? Does RJ shape those assertions of political
self-empowerment in ways that motivate people to act and give broader support for their cause?
More importantly: What is the role of victimized Indigenous women in this interplay?
through the language and methods of the so-called white RJ, may be seen by many as
advancement of the political assertion of rights by Indigenous people. Notably, by the institution
112
Ibid.
113
Ibid.
59
of self-determining parallel structures of justice (e.g., sentencing circles) that are devised to play
an active role in the administration of justice as well as empower community rules and sanctions
to deal with law and order problems. Nevertheless, it may also create specific problems for
Indigenous women who may find themselves cornered by the conflicting expectations of the
aspirations on both justice systems. For this reason, despite the alleged advances prompted by
the merger of RJ language with Indigenous justice, scholars like Chris Cunneen argue that
gendered power imbalances still exist in both formats --- RJ and Indigenous Justice --- and
operate in the context of a background system of colonial injustice where the process prioritizes
mens knowledge over womens knowledge as particular and sectional.114 As Cunneen puts it,
Gender interests impact on the ability of indigenous women to develop and use restorative
justice programs. There is no inherent reason to believe that restorative justice practices will
reinstate the voices of indigenous women.115 Rather, this way of intersectional thinking or
constructive hybridization may use the moral authority of Aboriginal justice practices to generate
a model where sets of communitarian moral norms or political interests can silence Aboriginal
Analyzing the origins of restorative justice Kathleen Daly pointed out the
following:
In looking around the world, one finds many histories of restorative justice; most are
ethnocentric. For example, the "history" of restorative justice as reported by Australians
and New Zealanders begins where? In the Antipodes. The "history" as reported by North
Americans begins, where else? In North America. The "history" as reported by some
Christian-oriented North Americas begins in biblical texts.117
114
See
Chris
Cunneen,
What
are
the
Implications
of
RJs
Use
of
Indigenous
Traditions?
in
Howard
Zehr
&
Barb
Toews,
eds.,
Criticial
Issues
in
Restorative
Justice
(Monsey,
New
York:
Criminal
Justice
Press,
2004)
345-353
at
352.
115
Ibid.
116
See
note
16.
117
See
note
61,
Immarigeon
&
Daly,
Origins.
60
Indeed, these ethnocentric manifestations of restorative justice often refer
cultural manifestations of justice that are used by restorative justice proponents as a spearhead to
obtain legitimacy (in the sociological meaning) and a good public image. A blatant example of
the co-optation of cultural elements to reinforce restorative justice rhetoric can be found, as
stressed before, in the recurrent association made by practitioners and theoreticians, particularly
in North America and Australasia, concerning the Indigenous roots of restorative justice.
Likewise, to a certain extent the same association can be made concerning the RJ claims over the
notion of Christian biblical justice which is directly related to the long pacifist and prison
movement. In fact, this latter religious group influenced enormously the first steps of restorative
justice, as we stressed in our account of the first RJ experiences in Canada and United States by
justice proponents seem to identify a trait of restorativeness in the context of their own culture
of study. For example, in Africa restorative justice advocates have established a connection
between it and the local concept of ubuntu or utu.118 In Asia, particularly in China, restorative
justice scholars have claimed that the concept is deeply embedded and rooted in Asian heritage,
albeit they have also recognized there are variations that deviate from the Western standard, like,
for example, the coercive, arbitrative nature of Chinese mediation and undesirable outcomes
related to punishment in tribal justice such as public ignominy, labour service, re-education,
118
See,
e.g.,
note
6,
Skelton,
Tapping
indigenous
knowledge.
(For
a
full
discussion
on
RJ
experiences
in
south
Africa
and
its
similarities
with
traditional
African
models
of
community
justice).
61
letters of repentance, banishment, imprisonment, the death penalty and in the past even burying
However, all these attempts to associate restorative justice with traditional justice
practices in the context of diverse cultures and places must be seen critically as incarnated in
particular modern realities that, albeit more culturally sensitive, sometimes do not have any
proximity to the very traditions by which they claim to be inspired. In these cases, as Daly
observes, they just represent a caricature of those cultural practices that both ignores
improprieties, internal contradictions and --- in the case of RJ models applied in Indigenous
settings --- a gender perspective. These caricatures as Daly properly named them, often
group conferences that, I believe, are oversimplified for basically two reasons. Firstly: to allow a
generic identification with familiar practices to provide a prompt understanding by the targeted
audience. This perspective explains how RJ was so readily accepted in Aboriginal communities
in Australasia and by Indigenous people in North America although the diversity among these
people is enormous. Secondly: the restorative justice movement made itself more visible and
persuasive due to an aura of contestation of the status quo (represented by the conventional
justice experiences. In this sense, I believe that much of the throwback arguments concerning RJ
and traditional justice cultural manifestations have been operating in the hope of arousing public
opinion in favor of the restorative justice cause. This RJ advocacy, I assert, has potential to
conceal negative influences of other political interests in Indigenous settings (mainly community
autonomy and self-determination) that often precede in influence the needs of vulnerable
119
See,
e.g.,
Ping
Wang
et
al.,
Regional
Review
Asia
in
Gerry
Johnstone
&
Daniel
W.
Van
Ness,
eds.,
Handbook
of
Restorative
Justice
(Portland,
Oregon:
Willan
Publishing,
2007)
477-487.
62
stakeholders like Indigenous women, perpetuating harmful power relations of oppression and
privilege within Aboriginal communities. Restorative justice proponents aimed, especially at the
justice system by proposing a paradigmatic shift. In order to achieve this goal they sought to
create a political space of contestation using a language that co-opted the discourse of other
social movements, which also were critical concerning the conventional justice system. For
example, Indigenous movements in North America and Australasia have always been critical of
the conventional justice systems due to disproportionate incarceration rates of Indigenous people
in those systems. Restorative justice proponents associated their own discourse of contestation
about the retributive-punitive conventional system with the political struggle of indigenous
activists, who were also trying to mobilize public opinion in recognition of their political rights
by asserting their own justice systems based on their cultural values. This conferred legitimacy
on the restorative justice claims boosting the potential appeal of its discourse. However, this kind
of tactic came with a price. It imposed serious costs on the foundation of a conclusive and
definitional level because of concessions made to adjust the RJ discourse to specific cultural
into a local image and values in order to be more readily accepted. Nonetheless, the vantage of
being perceived as culturally appropriate in the eyes of the public and policy makers was crucial
to the enormous success of the restorative justice proposals. The cultural sensitivity of RJ
63
Indeed, that strategy proved to be very efficient. In less than thirty years RJ had
become a new international trend in the field of criminal justice. However, the adoption of a
body of universal practices and the framing of a conclusive conceptualization became unfeasible
since the adaptation to local cultural conditions implied the sacrifice of organizational features
that could be held as a constant in the idea of restorative justice. In addition, some RJ proponents
(and intersectional feminists among them), driven either by a colonial sentiment of guilt or by a
non-critical appreciation of those cultural practices seemed not to recognize the dangers that an
unplanned adherence to traditional cultural justice practices might bring when no conclusive
stance is taken towards political standpoints and cultural practices that ignore or silence
manifestations of RJ has been raised by mainstream feminists who single out the case of
indigenous women who are victims of domestic violence. On this theme Kathleen Daly, for
experiences, particularly in the North American model of sentencing circles which involves
several cultural elements familiar to indigenous people such as mediation involving extended
family members; the moral authority exercised by community Elders; storytelling; and other
ritualistic ceremonies. Furthermore, Daly stresses that indigenous women see these experiences
conventional justice system on their own terms.120 A paradox is that feminist scholars have
detected indigenous women who are also concerned with the prevalence of a communitarian
interest discourse detrimental to their own security and empowerment. In addition, those
scholars, particularly socio-legal feminists, have raised questions about the misuse of cultural
120
See
note
9
at
161.
64
arguments in the context of restorative justice. As mentioned in the introduction to this thesis,
Daly observed that: Concerns have been raised that the subordination of women in some
Canadian First Nations communities means that they do not enter the circle on an equal basis
(Goel 2000; Stewar et al. 2001) and that women have sometimes been excluded, silenced or
harmed because power relations were not recognized, or gendered violence not taken
seriously.121
context of RJ does not ensure per se a desirable level of credibility, accountability and
empowerment to all the stakeholders (especially to women victims of intimate violence). On the
contrary, the tendency detected in the RJ discourse to assimilate cultural elements into its
perspective, may end up as a potential danger to the people who experience RJ interventions
since it can perpetuate community acceptance of violence against women. For this reason, it is
discourses (as Indigenous justice for instance) are a double-edged sword that can serve as a
powerful tool to draw attention and acceptance to an intersectional way of thinking about
criminal justice, i.e., giving an opportunity to reconfigure the justice system with culturally
sensitive values, but it may also impose heavy costs on vulnerable stakeholders and even on an
epistemological level (as seen in the definitional problem of restorative justice). A better
intersectional approach to RJ and violence against women must ensure these problems are
addressed properly.
121
Ibid
at
162.
65
2. Defining
restorative
justice
Up to this point I have tried to clarify some foundational issues with the goal of
providing an abstract framework that could be used to schematize the diverse ideological roots
that have informed RJ thought, without telling us exactly what RJ might be. In this subsection I
hope to give a face to the multi-tonal world of restorative justice. Unfortunately, however, the
phrase restorative justice has been defined in the most broadly based way; from the narrow
perspective of a promising way to redress problems within the criminal justice system to
grandiose plans to reform the world creating a more just society.122 But neither of these two
perspectives is able to provide alone a conclusive definition of restorative justice. In his book
The little book of Restorative Justice, Howard Zehr, a seminal thinker in RJ, suggests that: Even
though there is general agreement on the basic outlines of restorative justice, those in the field
have been unable to come to a consensus on its specific meaning.123 Depending on the
may be quite contestable. Johnstone and Van Ness, for example, have observed:
There is widespread agreement among proponents that the goal [of restorative justice] is
to transform the way contemporary societies view and respond to crime and related forms
of troublesome behaviour. However, there are a range of views as to the precise nature of
the transformation sought. These are to some extent in tension with one another,
suggesting that restorative justice is best understood as a deeply contested concept.
Brackets added.124
proponents to define the term conclusively. Susan Sharpe, for example, points out that many
122
See,
e.g.,
Margarita
Zernova,
Restorative
justice:
ideals
and
Realities
(Hampshire,
UK:
Ashgate
Publishing
Ltd.,
2007)
at
2-3.
(For
an
account
on
the
various
perspectives
about
RJ.
She
observes
that
RJ
is
popular
both
with
conservatives
and
liberals.
The
formers
have
an
interest
in
promoting
and
maintaining
RJ
because
it
allegedly
advances
family
values
and
the
interests
of
victims
and
promises
cost
saving
and
reduction
of
re-offending,
the
latters
view
RJ
as
an
individually
empowering
and
less
repressive
response
to
crime).
123
See
Howard
Zehr,
The
Little
Book
of
Restorative
Justice
(Intercourse,
PA:
Good
Books,
2002)
at
36.
124
See
note
54,
Johnstone
&
Van
Ness
eds.,
Handbook
of
Restorative
Justice,
at
1.
66
theorists are reluctant to establish firm definitions of RJ for fear of closing off innovations or
responsiveness to local needs.125 In other words, the effort to capture an adequate meaning for
restorative justice encounters the problem of many proponents simply denying the necessity or
opportunity to provide a definition for it. Gerry Johnstone, a renowned RJ advocate, observes
that when RJ is defined only by its most visible manifestations, there is a danger that the idea can
become over-identified with a particular practice or set of practices which reduces the scope of
the movement.126 He singles out the tendency to think about RJ as being mainly or even
even experiences associated with reparation schemes. Likewise, Declan Roche argues that this
tendency to see RJ as only a criminal justice initiative impoverishes the concept since restorative
processes (which encourage citizens to negotiate among themselves, rather than rely on
professionals to adjudicate), and restorative values (which emphasize the importance of repairing
and preventing harm), can be found across a wide range of regulatory fields. In this sense,
according to him, teachers dealing with bullying in schools; social workers; corporate regulators;
civil mediators members of truth commissions; diplomats; and peacekeepers all to a certain
extent practice a variety of restorative justice. As a consequence, the label restorative justice is
more easily associated with a set of principles and values which makes the phrase itself an
expression that serves as an umbrella term for a large spectrum of experiences and
interventions.127 This paper proceeds, as noted above, on the premise that there is no consensus
125
See
Susan
Sharpe,
How
Large
Should
The
Restorative
Justice
Tent"
be?
in
Howard
Zehr
&
Barb
Toews
eds.,
Critical
Issues
in
Restorative
Justice
(Monsey,
New
York:
Criminal
Justice
Press,
2004)
at
18.
Dana
Greene
stated
in
a
good-humoured
remark
paraphrasing
the
United
States
Supreme
Court
that
restorative
justice,
is
a
bit
like
pornography,
people
know
it
when
they
see
it.
See
note
3,
Dana
Greene,
Repeat
Performances
at
245
unpublished.
126
See
Gerry
Johnstone,
ed.,
A
Restorative
Justice
Reader:
Texts.
Sources
,
Context
(Mill
Street,
Uffculme:
Willan
Publishing,
2003)
at
21.
127
In
the
restorative
justice
literature,
for
example,
we
can
find
studies
associating
it
with
problems
as
diverse
as
medical
malpractice
and
school
bullying.
67
on a RJ definition although it is possible to establish a working definition. In the next subsection
Howard Zhers book Changing Lenses laid the foundations for the scholarly
model of informal justice that encourages and expects active involvement by all stakeholders ---
offenders, victims, affected community --- in the event of a crime, as an integral part of the full
continuum of healing the harm caused by the wrongdoing. Crime in the RJ realm is seen
fundamentally as a violation of people and inter-personal relationships. In addition, its basic idea
promotes the potential value and goodness of human beings, emphasizing communitarian and
participatory values. In general, RJ practices aim at reintegration of the offender and victim in
the community, offender rehabilitation, and victim closure through informal and non-adversarial
from a retributive criminal justice and its recurring themes (over reliance on punishment and just
deserts theory; special and general deterrence; incapacitation; rehabilitation; retribution, and
and offenders with the assistance of facilitators. In addition, these encounters may involve
members of the community. Depending on the RJ format the term community can mean either
For example, Elders (in an indigenous setting), neighbours, supportive friends and anyone
128
See
note
47,
Zehr,
Changing
Lenses.
68
affected by the crime. In some RJ models even designated court agents or police officers are
For the sake of clarity this section will provide a working definition within the
context of criminal justice. Therefore, it does not include any subsequent dimension that
restorative justice advocates may propose in practice or theory in some other context. In any
case, as Theo Gavrielides has observed, the lack of precise aims and limits is not exclusive to RJ,
in the field of criminology. Many argue that there is even disagreement as to what constitutes
However, whether it is true that this open concept can offer flexibility and
adaptability in a myriad of factual situations that may arise and that closing the doors to new
approaches may inhibit the movement evolution and scope is open to analysis. It is also true that
bewilderment, especially when one or more of the constituent human factors (offender, victim or
facilitator) of RJ interventions may be imbalanced or misguided. Zernova sounded the alert when
she stated, Restorative reforms may go astray as a result of being co-opted and diverted from
the original vision. There are historical precedents of criminal justice interventions which got
sidetracked, resulting in undesirable consequences and serving functions rather different from
find practitioners operating a program, even for a long time, without knowing exactly whether or
129
See
also
Theo
Gavrielides.
"Restorative
Justice:
The
Perplexing
Concept:
Conceptual
Fault-Lines
and
Power
Battles
within
the
Restorative
Justice
Movement"(2008)
8
Criminology
and
Criminal
Justice
165-183.
130
See
note
48
at
492.
69
not what they are doing is really restorative justice until somebody shows up and labels it as
being so. On the other hand, someone may claim to operate a RJ programme without in reality
employing restorative justice values and principles.131 Commonsense dictates that we must
establish reasonable limits to the still uncertain goals and objectives of restorative justice. A
good starting point would be to provide a working definition of the term itself that encompasses
the most desirable principles and values, at least in the field of criminal justice which seems to
be the original vocation of restorative justice. In doing so, we expect to provide a working
Even aware of the risk that a definition of RJ may always be incomplete, in this
section we use data collected by Theo Gavrielides who, whilst acknowledging this limitation,
also observed that consistent attempts for a conclusive definition were already being made. In his
meticulous research, Gavrielides listed a comprehensive set of working definitions and principles
for restorative justice. For the purpose of this paper, however, we will only focus on those with a
more favourable reception. The first in Gavrielides list is that one provided by Tony Marshall
where, Restorative Justice is a process whereby all the parties with a stake in a particular
offence come together to resolve collectively how to deal with the aftermath of the offences and
132
its implications for the future.
for the personal involvement of those mainly concerned (particularly the offender and the victim,
but also their families and communities); 2) seeing crime problems in their social context; 3) a
attend fully to victims needs (b) to prevent re-offending by reintegrating offenders into the
community (c) to enable offenders to assume active responsibility for their actions (d) to recreate
a working community that supports rehabilitations of offenders and victims, and is active in
preventing crime and (e) to provide a means of avoiding escalation of legal justice and the
Gavrielides concluded that this definition and principles, albeit still subjected to
criticism because of its limitations regarding scope, was endorsed by the Working Party on
Restorative Justice; a working group of notable restorative justice advocates and scholars that
worked under the auspices of the Alliance of NGOs on Crime Prevention and Criminal Justice
in preparation for the 10th United Nations crime congress in 2000134 Gavrielides also reported
that this same group endorsed Ron Claassens principles regarding restorative justice. According
to Claassens principles: (a) Crime is primarily an offence against human relationships; (b)
Restorative justice is a process to make things as right as possible; (c) As soon as immediate
victim, community and offender safety concerns are satisfied, Restorative justice views the
situation as a teachable moment for the offender; (d) Restorative justice prefers responding to
the crime at the earliest point possible and with the maximum amount of voluntary cooperation
and minimum coercion since healing in relationships and new learning are voluntary and
cooperative; (e) Restorative justice recognises that not all offenders will choose to be
cooperative, and that those who pose significant safety risks should be placed in settings where
the emphasis is on safety, values, ethics, responsibility, accountability and civility; (f)
133
Ibid.
134
This
working
group,
according
to
Gavrielides,
was
comprised
of
the
following
notable
restorative
justice
scholars,
practitioners
and
theoreticians:
Gordon
Bazemore,
John
Braithwaite,
Ron
Claassen,
James
Consedine,
Peter
Cordella,
Frank
Dunbaugh,
Burt
Galaway,
Julia
Hall,
Kay
Harris,
Virginia
Mackey,
Tony
Marshall,
Gabrielle
Maxwell,
John
MacDonald,
Paul
McCold,
Fred
McElrea,
Harry
Mika,
David
Moore,
Ruth
Morris,
Allison
Morris,
Wayne
Northey,
Dean
Peachey,
Joan
Pennell,
Kay
Pranis,
Barry
Stuart,
Daniel
Van
Ness
and
Howard
Zehr.
71
Restorative justice recognises and encourages the role of community institutions, and requires
follow-up and accountability structures. The definitional efforts of Marshall and Claassen when
taken in conjunction are widely considered the most convincing definition in the restorative
justice field.
justice also includes one devised by the United Nations through the Economic and Social
Council. On the 24th of July 2002, the Council adopted Resolution E/CN.15/2002/L.2/Rev.1
Basic principles on the use of Restorative.135 However, this document in particular did not
provide an accurate definition of the term itself. In fact, it only referred to the repetition of the
describing what would be restorative processes/outcomes and other restorative jargon like
parties, facilitator and community. In practical terms that effort has not added anything
substantial to the debate about whether a conclusive definition of RJ is possible. Once more this
advocates to use prescriptive or narrow definitions that might impede further development of
to delimit the field, but where the line is drawn is ultimately an arbitrary choice that might be as
good as any other. Bearing this in mind, our working definition of choice is one provided by
Kathleen Daly which is marked by a descriptive approach to the essential elements of RJ. She
wrote:
135
See
note
23.
136
Ibid.
72
First, a person has admitted responsibility for offending, either explicitly or implicitly.
Although crucial, this is a commonly overlooked feature. RJ does not adjudicate or
mediate facts, but is part of the post-adjudication (or penalty) phase of the criminal
process. Secondly, an offender typically (but not always) has a face-to-face meeting with
a victim (or a representative for a victim, say, a parent for a young child victim), along
with other supporters or relevant community members. Thirdly, it is an informal process
that relies on the knowledge and decision-making capacities of lay actors, but it is linked
to and constrained by established criminal justice (CJ) practices. There are ground rules
for participants behaviour and what can be said, and there are upper limits on penalties,
which depend on the legal context. Fourthly, the aims of RJ are to hold offenders
accountable for their behaviour and to make up for what they did. It is hoped that the
process and outcome will deter offenders from further lawbreaking and provide some
form of reintegration into the community, although neither may be achieved.137
cannot take the space in this paper to account the great deal of information necessary in a
would include, as the most authoritative examples of RJ interventions, the following models:
sentencing circles. In fact, according to Paul McCold, these three practices are the purest
forms of RJ and the only practices that meet the requirements of a face-to-face meeting between
victims and offenders along with their communities of care.138 As he also observes, These
examples all follow similar processes. However they differ in who runs the programmes, how
cases are referred, who conducts the mediation, how much pre-mediation counselling is
involved, the length of the process, the types of offences addressed, and the primary goal of the
137
Kathleen
Daly,
Restorative
Justice
and
Sexual
Assault:
An
Archival
Study
of
Court
and
Conference
Cases
(2006)
46:2
The
British
Journal
of
Criminology
at
335.
138
See
Paul
McCold,
Primary
Restorative
Justice
Practices
in
Allison
Morris
&
Gabrielle
Maxwell,
eds.,
Restorative
Justice
for
Juveniles:
Conferencing,
mediation
and
circles
(Oxford,
UK:Hart
Publishing,
2001)
at
41.
73
process.139 For this reason, I will narrow down my illustration of practical models of RJ to those
three experiences that emerged independently, but that have greatly influenced one another.
Although others models of RJ may be as important as those, I will refrain from mentioning them
in this paper.140
popular and well established formats of RJ. In order to do that I reviewed the research findings
of RJ scholars like Margarita Zernova; Paul McCold; Loretta Frederick; Kristine C. Lizdas;
Mark Umbreit; Howard Zehr; and Angela Cameron. In the following subsections, I will largely
ignore empirical uses of those models since my main concern is with sentencing circles which
will be empirically explored in the next chapter of this paper. Anyway, where it is indispensable
I may mention only in passing a specific RJ program in North America and Australasia to
are the oldest forms of restorative justice practice.141 The practice of RJ in the form of dialogue-
based encounters evolved basically from two distinct programs: faith-based victim-offender
programmes. These programmes gained impetus in the 1970s and 1980s with victims
139
Ibid.
140
For
example,
victim
impact
panels;
Navajo
peacemaking;
community
justice
sanction;
community
boards
or
panels;
victim
compensation,
arbitration,
etc.
See,
e.g.,
Paul
MacCold,
The
Recent
History
of
Restorative
Justice
Mediation,
Circles
and
Conferencing
in
Dennis
Sullivan
&
Larry
Tifft
,
eds.,
The
Handbook
of
Restorative
Justice:
A
Global
Perspective
(New
York,
NY:
Routledge,
2006)
141
Zernova
has
observed
that
early
programs
were
named
victim-offender
reconciliation
programmes,
or
VORP,
however,
some
objected
to
the
term
reconciliation,
because
it
was
value-laden.
Victim's
rights
advocates
believed
that
the
term
implied
that
victims
need
to
reconcile
with
their
offender.
They
preferred
the
term
mediation.
Today
most
programmes
adopt
the
terminology
victim-offender
mediation.
See
note
122
at
8.
74
organizations, religious campaigners for non-custodial sentences and community activists
involved in diverting young offenders from the conventional criminal justice system. To be more
in the early 1970s in Canada and the United States, having emerged even before the concept of
restorative justice was fully realized.142 As Zernova points out, Victim-offender reconciliation
is based on the idea that following a criminal offence, the victim and the offender have a shared
interest in righting the wrong. The emphasis is placed on reconciliation, assisting victims in the
aftermath of an offence, helping offenders to change their lives and more, generally, humanizing
victim and offender with the help of a neutral trained facilitator primarily for the purpose of
giving the offender an opportunity to make reparations, express remorse and if possible reconcile
with the victim.144 Victims are supposed to have the opportunity to talk about what happened and
ask questions to the offender in a respectful and controlled atmosphere in order to mitigate
feelings of anger; fear; shame; frustration and vengeance. The idea is that these negative and
punitive inner attitudes and emotions can be channelled in more constructive ways in the
restorative encounter that ideally would function as a powerful cathartic release. According to
Heather Strang, It seems that this expression of feelings by victims is essential for the
experience of empathy by offender towards their victims. It may be that empathy is the engine
that drives remorse on the offenders part and discharge of retributive feelings on the victims
142
U.S.
Department
of
Health
and
Human
Services,
The
Role
of
Restorative
Justice
in
the
Battered
Womens
Movement,
by
Loretta
Frederick
&
Kristine
C.
Lizdas,
(Washington:
Battered
Women's
Justice
Project,
2003).
143
See
note
122
.
144
If
victims
or
offenders
do
not
feel
for
any
reason
comfortable
to
meet
face-to-face
with
their
counterparts.
They
either
may
choose
a
surrogate
to
represent
themselves
or
use
the
facilitator
as
an
intermediary
to
carry
information
back
and
forth
between
the
parties
until
a
restorative
agreement
is
achieved.
Another
common
forms
of
indirect
dialogue
like
those
are
to
exchange
letters,
videos,
emails
or
to
meet
with
an
unrelated
offender
or
victim.
75
part.145 In sum, by appealing to the psychological and moral mechanisms of empathy, RJ
practitioners intend to trigger inner processes in victims and offenders that give rise to a search
Then the parties may decide together what needs to be done about what happened and reach a
mutually satisfying agreement. An agreement may involve the offender making financial
restitution, working for the victim (or the community), undertaking to behave in a particular way
or attending some rehabilitation programme, such as anger management.146 The facilitator helps
the mediation process, but does not impose any outcome upon the parties. The aim is to promote
a dialogue and empower victims and offenders to solve the conflict the best way they can within
certain procedural constraints. It is crucial to understand that restorative mediation processes are
not necessarily apologetic, i.e., the restorative dialogue does not suppose that the offender will
ask or receive forgiveness from the victim although this outcome may reasonably be expected in
protocols by the parties the facilitator normally would interrupt the encounter and refer the case
again to court for the adoption of conventional criminal justice measures when it is suitable.
Moreover, Frederick and Lizdas suggest --- citing Mark Umbreit --- that VORPs and VOMs can
have positive effects on victims and on offenders as well. For example: a) increasing the
satisfaction levels of victims with the justice systems response to their case rather than going
through the normal court procedures; b) after meeting the offender, victims are significantly less
145
See
Heather
Strang,
Is
Restorative
Justice
Imposing
its
Agenda
on
Victims?
in
Howard
Zehr
&
Barb
Toews
eds.,
Critical
Issues
in
Restorative
Justice
(Monsey,
New
York:
Criminal
Justice
Press,
2004)
at
101.
(Arguing
that
RJ
processes
must
recognize
that
victims
are
entitled
to
convey
retributive
and
bitter
emotions
as
a
valuable
element
of
restorative
transformation
of
both
offenders
and
victims).
See
also
note
88,
Harris
et
al.,
Emotional
Dynamics.
(Arguing
that
emotions
like
empathy,
remorse
and
guilt
will
spill
over
into
feelings
of
shame,
that
are
consistent
with
the
approach
advocated
by
Braithwaites
reintegrative
shaming
theory).
146
See
note
122.
76
fearful of being revictimized; c) more compliance with restitution obligations in regard to
offenders; and d) offenders that agreed to meet their victims are rarely recidivist.147 However, RJ
critics argue these claims are in need of further empirical confirmation and theoretical
clarification.148
North America, but now also in other parts of the world like Germany, Finland, Belgium, and the
United Kingdom.149 She also helps to clarify a number of distinctions which can be drawn
VOMs rely on a similar grouping of participants, but place more emphasis on reparation
and restitution to the victim than on reconciliation of the parties (Strang, 2002). Further,
Tim Roberts, a consultant who evaluated a British Columbia VOM, states that they deal
with more serious and violent offences, while VORPs deal mainly with minor offences
committed by juveniles. According to Roberts, VOMs are more rare than VORPs; the
mediators are trained professionals rather than volunteers; they may not result in a face-
to-face meeting; they are likely to require more preparation and counselling work for
victims and offenders; and are more focused on healing rather than reconciliation
(1995)150
presented and used in a number of configurations depending on the structure of the criminal
justice system in which it is used, as well as the level of acceptance coming from public opinion,
147
See
note
140
at
8-9.
148
See
note
21.
(In
this
note
I
quote
Stubbs
who
provides
examples
of
criticism
regarding
the
promises
of
RJ
to
victims
and
community)
149
See
note
2
(For
an
account
of
examples
of
use
of
victim-offender
mediations
in
Canada
and
other
countries).
See
also
note
70
for
an
account
on
pioneer
experiences
on
VORP
promoted
by
the
Mennonite
Community,
especially
the
Kitchener
experiment
in
Ontario.
(The
Mennonites
are
a
Christian
denomination
or
community
who
adherents
have
become
known
as
deeply
committed
to
pacifism,
nonviolence
and
prison
abolition.
The
Mennonite
church
is
one
of
the
so-called
Peace
churches
like,
the
Quakers
and
the
Brethren
in
Christ.
Several
RJs
prominent
scholars
and
practitioners
are
members
either
of
the
Mennonite
church
or
Quaker
community,
for
instance,
Daniel
Van
Ness,
Howard
Zehr
and
Joan
Pennell.
Basically
they
see
RJ
as
a
form
of
Biblical
Justice.
The
Mennonite
church,
for
example,
is
a
leading
sponsor
of
RJ
initiatives
in
North
America).
150
See
note
2
at
16.
77
policy-makers and the cultural and historical background of the country. According to
Gavrielides, the first configuration is of independent programmes, when they are offered as real
alternatives for criminal litigation, diverting the criminal case totally out of the formal process of
the conventional criminal justice at a very early stage --- normally pre-charge.151 The second
reviewed and evaluated within a formal criminal proceeding.152 At any stage of that proceeding,
according to court or prosecutorial discretion, the case can be referred to a mediator or facilitator
(I prefer the term facilitator to avoid allusive references to civil mediation) who takes charge of
accomplished successfully, it will have an impact on the outcome of the criminal proceedings.
Normally, a positive outcome takes the form of a shortened sentence time, although there have
been cases where charges were dropped altogether. The third configuration is of dependent
programs which take place when the offender is already incarcerated or after sentencing. Finally,
distinctions concerning operational styles that are noteworthy to quote in length. In his words:
The first is between programmes that are primarily oriented towards the needs of the
offender, and those that also take account of the needs of the victim. The second
distinction is made between projects where victims meet their offenders and projects
where groups of victims take part in discussions with unrelated offenders. Although this
type of mediation does not preclude bringing the individuals together to consider how
offenders can make amends, their main goal is to help both victims and offenders to
challenge each others prejudices. The third distinction concerns mediation programmes
that may include face-to-face meeting of the victim with the offender, and those that have
mediators act only as go-betweens. The fourth category depends on the cases that the
mediation programmes accept.
For instance, a project may take cases below or above a
certain level of seriousness, or only juvenile cases. Lastly, there are victim-offender
mediation programmes that are carried out by paid professional staff or by trained
volunteers.153
151
See
note
54
at
31.
152
Ibid.
153
See
note
54
at
301.
78
In the next subsections I will describe family group conferencing and sentencing
circles. Nevertheless, it is important to understand that many of the features ascribed to VORPs
and VOMs are also shared by family group conferencing and sentencing circles because in its
origins RJ was virtually synonymous with VORPs and VOMs. Paul McCold, for example, noted
that: In the beginning, mediation was restorative justice, and restorative justice was
mediation.154 However, as A.W. Roberts observed: Within a short time, VOM become more
flexible, and often was multi-part, with several victims and/or offenders, family members and/or
supporters. Next, this VOM model of practice became several models and them a family of
models.155 Family group conferences and sentencing circles are, therefore, the result of the
natural expansion of RJ dialogue-based encounters like VORPs and VOMS. For this reason, they
The central idea behind family group conferencing (hereafter FGC) is the
recognition that victims and offenders by themselves may be unable to deal with the
consequences of a crime since it also affects their families and communities as a whole. In other
words, FGC depends not only on the agency of dialogue-based processes between victim and
offender but also on the contributions of supportive family members of both of them; respected
community members, and public officials like police and probation officers. As Frederick and
Lizdas put it, A wider circle of people is recognized as being victimized by the offense
154
See
note
138
at
24.
155
See
Ann
Wamer
Roberts,
Is
Restorative
Justice
Tied
to
Specific
Models
of
Practice?,
in
Howard
Zehr
&
Barb
Toews
eds.,
Critical
Issues
in
Restorative
Justice
(Monsey,
New
York:
Criminal
Justice
Press,
2004)
at
242.
156
The
term
encounter
encapsulates
in
one
word
one
of
the
most
important
tenets
of
the
RJ
movement:
that
victims,
offenders
and
the
affected
community
should
be
allowed
to
encounter
one
another
outside
highly
formal,
professional-dominated
settings
like
a
courtroom
to
deal
with
their
own
problems.
See
note
53
Johnstone
&
Van
Ness,
Handbook
of
RJ,
at
9.
79
identified as primary and secondary victims in FGC. Victims are more likely to receive
RJs principle of participatory democracy and holistic justice. As a matter of fact, the strongest
connection between FGC and RJ is formed by one of the fundamental assumptions that underlies
RJ theory, i.e., that the wrongdoers behaviour and its consequences are only part of something
that is intimately interconnected with other stakeholders which can be only understood by
reference to them as a whole.158 In this sense, although the primary victims are those most
directly affect by the offense, other lay actors, such as family members of victims and offenders,
witnesses, and members of the affected community, are also considered victims. Bearing this
interconnection in mind, it makes sense to seek an offenders reinclusion into the circle of
community belonging and support through the application of social pressure and collective
FGC involves the acknowledgment of a wider range of people as being victimized by the
wrongdoing and at the same time requires collective responsibility in the task of reintegrating the
offender and victim into the community, thus contributing to the empowering and healing of the
overall community.
157
See
note
142
at
9.
158
Zehr
and
Mika
stress
that
any
restorative
programme
must
be
applied
in
the
light
of
the
following
principles:
1)
Recognition
that
crime
is
a
violation
of
one
person
by
another
and
not
against
the
state;
2)
Recognition
that
crime
is
harmful
to
interpersonal
relationships
and
to
communities;
3)
The
focus
is
on
problem
solving
and
restoration
of
social
harmony;
4)
Restitution,
reconciliation
and
vindication
are
used
as
a
means
of
restoration;
5)
The
community
acts
as
a
facilitator
in
the
restorative
process,
and
6)
The
holistic
context
of
an
offence
is
taken
into
consideration
including
moral,
social,
economic,
political
and
religious
aspects.
In
addition,
there
are
four
procedural
pillars
for
RJ
practical
models.
Firstly,
the
restorative
encounter
which
creates
a
window
of
opportunity
for
victims,
offenders
and
community
members
who
want
to
do
so
to
meet
to
discuss
the
crime
and
its
aftermath.
Secondly,
the
seek
for
reintegration
which
means
to
restore
victims
and
offenders
as
contributing
members
of
society.
Third,
the
inclusiveness
that
provide
opportunities
for
parties
with
a
stake
in
a
specific
crime
to
participate
in
its
resolution.
Finally,
making
amends
that
requires
from
offenders
to
take
decisive
steps
to
repair
the
harm
they
have
done.
See
note
131.
80
According to Umbreit and Zher, FGC first developed in New Zealand in the late
1980s as a way to address the failures of conventional juvenile justice and as an attempt to
incorporate traditional justice values of the Maori People --- the Indigenous group of New
Zealand --- that emphasised the role of family and community in addressing wrongdoing.159 In
accordance with that intersectional thinking initiative, FGC was institutionalized in 1989
through, The Children, Young Persons and their Families Act, as an alternative to formal court
proceedings for young offenders.160 As Umbreit has observed, FGC is now the standard for
processing juvenile cases in New Zealand and also in Australia that adopt the concept a short
period later.161 Since then, several countries such as Canada, United States, Israel and others in
Europe, have followed the example of Australia and New Zealand by adopting restorative
conferencing with minor changes in style accordingly to their own social and legal contexts.162
Kathleen Daly asserts that Australia and New Zealand are the leading
159
See
Mark
Umbreit
&
Howard
Zehr,
Restorative
Family
Group
Conferences:
Differing
Models
and
Guidelines
for
Practice
in
Eugene
McLaughlin
et
al.,
eds.,
RJ:
Critical
Issues
(Thousand
Oaks,
CA:
Sage
Publications,
2003)
at
69-
70
160
See
Cameron,
note
2
at
15.
See
also
Children,
Young
Persons,
and
Their
Families
Act
1989
(N.Z),
1989/24,
2009
RS.
See
generally
F.W.M.
McElrea,
Restorative
Justice
-
A
New
Zealand
Perspective
in
David
J.
Cornwell,
ed.,
Criminal
punishment
and
Restorative
Justice:
Past,
present,
and
future
perspectives
(Winchester,
UK:
Waterside
Press,
2006)
at
119.
(Discussing
the
restorative
justice
principles
applied
in
the
2002
Sentencing
Act
at
New
Zealand).
See
also
Sentencing
Act
2002
(N.Z).,
2002/9,
2009
RS.
161
See
Mark
Umbreit,
Family
Group
Conferencing:
Implications
for
Crime
Victims
(2000)
U.S.
Department
of
Justice
-
Office
of
Justice
Programs.
See
also
note
122
at
12
(For
a
detailed
account
of
FGC
outside
New
Zealand,
specially
the
Wagga
Wagga
model
in
New
South
Wales,
Australia,
and
the
Thames
Valley
model
in
UK.
These
models
differ
from
the
New
Zealand
model
because
they
use
police
officers,
usually
in
uniform,
or
school
officials
to
set
up
and
facilitate
meetings.
No
other
agencies
are
involved
in
their
functioning.
They
are
clearly
based
on
reintegrative
shaming
theories
by
John
Braithwaite).
162
See
note
53,
Johnstorne
&
Van
Ness,
Handbook
of
RJ,
at
446-557.
(For
a
recent
account
of
RJ
experiences
around
the
globe).
See
also
Esther
Shachaf-Friedman
&
Uri
Timor,
Family-Group
Conferencing
in
Israel:
The
Voices
of
Victims
Following
Restorative
Justice
Proceedings
in
Natti
Rone
et
al.,
eds,
Trends
and
issues
in
Victimology
(Newcastle,
UK:
Cambridge
Scholars
Publishing,
2008)
at
58.
(Describing
the
Kedem
family
conferencing
model
in
Israel).
163
See
Kathleen
Daly,
Conferencing
in
Australia
and
New
Zealand:
Variation,
Research
Findings,
and
Prospects
in
Allison
Morris
&
Gabrielle
Maxwell,
eds.,
Restorative
Justice
for
Juveniles:
Conferencing,
mediation
and
circles
(Oxford,
UK:
Hart
Publishing,
2001)
at
59-61.
(Discussing
FGC
evolution
in
New
Zealand
and
Australia
while
pointing
out
misconception
about
the
use
of
restorative
conferencing
in
those
countries).
81
and Australia have been spearheading a campaign to use restorative conferencing for addressing
social problems, endemic racism in the justice system and to redress inequalities. As she
observes:
With the exception of two jurisdiction in Australia, all jurisdictions have statutory-
based schemes, with conferences typically used as on component in a hierarchy of
responses to youth crime.
The overarching goal in legislative frameworks is to keep juveniles out of the formal
system as much as possible.
The impetus for those policies, she argues, is a commitment to an ideology that
emphasizes social welfare and crime prevention. Moreover, their common law tradition allows a
greater degree of experimentation with new justice forms which is not possible in civil law
jurisdictions.
offender with the victim to discuss the causes and consequences of the crime and ways of
preventing its repetition; but in this specific model, offender and victim are also supported by
their families (in the case of young offenders usually their parents), friends or neighbours and the
responsibility is shared among all the participants who must work together to stop the offending
the offender and their family are usually supported by local social workers not employed by the
lawyer/advocate for the offender is invited, and a representative of the police department, who
164
Ibid.
at
59-60.
165
However,
Cameron
notes
that
unlike
sentencing
circles
FGC
participants
are
usually
limited
to
immediate
family
members,
as
opposed
to
the
larger
community
of
supporters.
See
note
2
at
15.
82
serves as the prosecutor, is present.166 After all participants views have been presented, the
entire group, which includes the extended community of care of offenders and victims, is
expected to come to a consensus on the outcome for the case, not just on a restitution agreement.
Goals of the conference would normally include accountability, prevention of future misconduct,
and victim empowerment.167 In some FGC configurations the offenders family is invited to
meet in private and draw up a plan which is submitted to the whole conference for acceptance.
FGC encounters are based upon the assumption that people are more likely to honour plans to
As one can infer, the same principles of empathetic dialogue and claims of
substantive benefits to victims and offenders applies to FGCs as to VOMs and VORPs.
However, Mark Umbreit points out the differences between VOMs and FGC, as follows:
Unlike VOM, FGC uses public officials (police officers, probation officers, school officials)
rather than trained volunteers as facilitators. Although their roles include mediation, they are
more broadly defined, combining mediation with other methods of interaction and allowing for
more directed facilitation. The FGC process also casts a much wider circle of participants than
VOM.168 In sum, FGC programmes provide the victim, the offender and all those who are
regarding sanctions and making amends. Finally, FGC may occur at any stage of a criminal legal
proceeding. However, most of the times they are used by police as an alternative to arrest and as
166
Supra
note
161.
167
Ibid.
168
Supra
note
161.
169
See
note
54
at
34.
83
iii. Restorative
and
sentencing
circles
This section is designed merely to give the reader a general comprehension of the purpose and
from different Aboriginal traditions, are closely related and share common emphasis.170 As
Frederick and Lizdas note, restorative circles practices place: a strong emphasis upon local
community member participation, making the circle community based; bringing victim and
victim and offender family members and friends, such as in family group conferencing.171
However, a clear distinction can be drawn between restorative circles and other restorative
conferencing models. The former places aboriginal understandings of justice based in mediation
encounters.172 This allows Frederick and Lizdas to point out that, These practices explicitly
empower each individual in the circle as an equal and lift up the relationship between justice and
the physical, emotional and spiritual dimensions of the individual in the context of community
and culture.173 In other words, those practices mean to Indigenous people at the same time the
experimentation of a more humane and meaningful form of justice, and a politically stronger and
170
There
is
a
general
consensus
in
the
literature
that
family
group
conferences
were
adapted
from
the
justice
traditions
of
the
Maori
People
in
New
Zealand,
while
restorative
circles
are
usually
associated
with
the
justice
traditions
of
Indigenous
people
in
Canada
and
United
States.
For
example,
the
Navajo
peacemaking
in
the
United
States.
See
note
138
at
48-49.
But
see
note
6.
(Arguing
that
sentencing
circlers
are
not
a
form
of
RJ,
but
a
manifestation
of
Aboriginal
Justice).
171
See
note
142
at
10.
172
The
Indigenous
practice
of
peacemaking
circles
as
a
form
of
conflict-resolution
is
the
basis
of
this
approach.
173
Ibid.
84
more empowering way of conceiving criminal justice in their own terms.174 In this sense,
restorative circles are perhaps the most culturally sensitive of RJ practices largely incorporating
concepts emanating from Aboriginal perceptions of justice.175 While in other RJ models which
restorative circles they are the essence of the experience. Certainly, this has contributed to the
vigour with which restorative circles were embraced by Indigenous communities in North
In fact, as we saw in a previous section of this chapter, there is even some doubt
about whether the distinction between restorative justice circles and Aboriginal justice still exists
in in practice.177 Just to illustrate this claim, it is generally accepted that for Indigenous people in
relationship between the offender and the victim as well as the offender and the community.178
Moreover, it is also thought that the stability of the community is dependent on healing those
174
But
see
the
following
footnote
commentary
by
Angela
Cameron:
Others
suggest
that
by
having
the
sentencing
judge
retain
control
of
the
ultimate
sentencing
decision,
circles
may
be
culturally
inappropriate,
as
they
are
being
used
by
the
conventional
justice
system
to
improve
mainstream
programs
rather
than
as
an
authentic
aspect
of
self-determination
for
Aboriginal
peoples
(Ryan
and
Calliou,
2002;
Linden
and
Clairmont,
1998;
in
the
Australian
context
see:
Behrendt,
2002).
See
note
2
at
36.
(Camerons
commentary
is
applicable
only
to
sentencing
circles
though).
175
This
claim
is
supported
by
Paul
McCold
who
argues,
in
his
words,
The
circle
is
central
to
traditional
aboriginal
cultures
and
social
processes.
As
Yazzie
(1998:129)
notes,
indigenous
cultures
around
the
world
have
developed
a
variety
of
similar
process
for
responding
to
wrongdoing.
See
note
138
at
48.
See
also
Robert
Yazzie
&
James
Zion,
Navajo
Restorative
Justice:
The
Law
of
Equality
and
Justice
in
B.
Galaway
&
J.
Hudson,
eds.,
Restorative
Justice:
International
Perspectives
(Mossey:Criminal
Justice
Press,
1996).
Contra
note
114
at
346
.
(Cunneen
argues
that
such
gross
generalizations
about
justice
practices
of
Indigenous
societies
trivialize
the
diversity
and
complexity
of
Indigenous
groups
around
the
world.
According
to
him,
we
cannot
assume
that
the
vision
of
justice
is
the
same
for
RJ
advocates
and
all
Indigenous
people).
176
Restorative
circles
operate
exclusively
or
primarily
with
Indigenous
persons
or
within
Indigenous
communities.
Although
there
are
references
in
the
literature
to
the
use
of
restorative
circles
in
non-indigenous
settings
they
are
not
numerically
relevant.
For
the
expository
purposes
of
this
segment,
I
will
ignore
these
experiences
that,
however,
will
be
mentioned
in
passing
in
a
following
chapter.
See,
e.g.
,note
2
at
13.
177
See
text
accompanying
note
111.
178
See
Heino
Lilles,
Circle
Sentencing:
Part
of
the
Restorative
Justice
Continuum
(Paper
presented
to
the
Third
International
Conference
on
Conferencing,
Circles
and
other
Restorative
Practices,
Minneapolis,
Minnesota,
8-10
August,
2002
[unpublished]
on
line:
http://www.iirp.org/article_detail.php?article_id=NDQ3
(Retrieved
on
25
March
2008).
85
strained relationships. Finally, according to a general Indigenous perception of justice the
community is better positioned to address the causes of crime, because they are often rooted in
the economic or social fabric of the community. All these standpoints are also echoed in the RJ
process that especially includes the assimilation and repackaging of the traditional imagery of
Indigenous justice practices like, e.g., peacemaking circles through the use of language and
restorative circles are not traditional practices of aboriginal peoples now being resuscitated.
Actually, they are a much more a palatable way of doing justice growing out the existing
conventional system introduced within aboriginal communities, for the most part fostered by the
Although the sentencing circle is drawn from Aboriginal customs, it is not a complete
return to traditional Aboriginal dispute-resolution techniques (Lowe and Davidson 2004).
Several authors have opined that sentencing circles are an example of inventing tradition,
not returning to tradition (Cameron 2006a, 2006b; Dickson-Glmore 1992; Green 1998;
McIvor 1996, Orchard 1998; Spiteri 2002).181
Soon, it also becomes evident that the adoption of restorative circles represent an
attempt of the status quo powers to redress the errors of the colonial past and the endemic
injustices found in the conventional criminal justice system towards Aboriginal people,
179
Paul
McCold
observes
that
Navajo
peacemaking
experiences
in
the
desert
Southwest
of
the
United
States
are
perhaps
the
first
restorative
circles
experiences
in
the
contemporary
world.
They
have
been
in
use
for
criminal
and
civil
cases
since
1982.
See
note
140
at
28.
See
also
Robert
Yazzie,
Navajo
Peacemaking:
Implications
for
Adjudication-based
Systems
of
Justice
(1998)
1
Contemporary
Justice
Review
123-131.
But
see
note
34,
Coker,
Navajo
Peacemaking.
(Noting
the
differences
between
Navajo
peacemaking
and
restorative
justice
models
like
sentencing
circles.
According
to
her,
while
the
peacemaking
process
is
completely
controlled
by
the
sovereign
Navajo
Nation,
in
sentencing
circles
the
processes
is
are
often
controlled
by
non-Indigenous
authorities
although
sometimes
in
consultation
with
Indigenous
leaders).
violence
180
See
Mary
Crnkovich,
Report
on
the
Circle
Sentencing
in
Kangiqsujuaq
(Paper
presented
to
for
Pauktuutit
and
Department
of
Justice,
Canada,
1993)
Inuit
Women
and
Justice:
Progress
Report
Number
one
[unpublished]
at
23.
181
See
note
13
at
969-978
in
a
kindle
e-book
version.
86
particularly, the over-incarceration of Aboriginal offenders in Canada and Australia.182 The
historic and systemic failures of these countries to ameliorate the impact of the criminal justice
system on Indigenous people puts them in the difficult situation of having both to renew and
reinvent their discourse and practice on justice processes just enough to make Indigenous people
believe that a change had, in fact, taken place and that adjustments were made, while actually
maintaining the basic structure of power on which their conventional criminal justice systems
depend. Notably, this has been achieved by mainly putting into practice top-down governance
strategies through which certain justice functions like sentencing powers are partially transferred
or shared with traditional institutions, e.g., Indigenous circles. As Julia Emberley suggests, this is
exactly the case in Canada where, ... the concept of legal pluralism (the multiple, and
sometimes combined, use of Aboriginal customary law and Canadian state law) is gaining
ground in the judicial system...183 Goel Rashmi echoes this perception arguing that sentencing
strategies, as Blagg prefers to name legal pluralist initiatives. In theory, the approach is intended
to empower aboriginal customary law and communitarian governance, but in practice, it keeps
the existing professionalized justice institutions from delineating how the experience works and
what outcomes can be achieved. In addition, there is the danger of overlooking the complex
power dynamics among victimized Aboriginal women, their offenders and the community,
especially within the context of domestic violence. Crnkovich, for example, argues that
182
See,
e.g.,
note
106.
183
See
Julia
Emberley,
Defamiliarizing
the
aboriginal:
cultural
practices
and
decolonization
in
Canada
(Toronto:
University
of
Toronto
Press,
2007)
at
68.
(Similar
policies
are
also
seen
within
the
context
of
Australia).
184
See
note
13
at
971-975
in
a
kindle
e-book
version.
87
sentencing circles can introduce new and perverse forms of silencing Aboriginal women. As she
The circle was the first of its kind, being supported by the judge and Inuit leaders. If she
[the victim] spoke out about further abuses or her dislike of this sentence, what would she
be saying about this process everyone supported? Now, in addition to fearing her
husband's retribution, she may fear that by speaking out she would be speaking out
against the community. The sentence created in this circle is one endorsed not only by the
Mayor and other participants, but also by the Judge and a highly respected Inuit
politician. The pressure to not speak out against a sentencing alternative supported by so
many is great. The victim may be afraid to admit she is being beaten because such an
admission, she may fear, may be interpreted as failure of this process. She may hold
herself to blame and once again continue to suffer the silence.185 Brackets added
In conclusion, the nature of the confluence between RJ and the Aboriginal justice
political project lies in the fact that both not only require a great involvement of the community,
but also share several core notions, such as healing; victim/offender personal transformation;
terms. However, the common language and shared institutional mechanisms have the potential to
obscure fundamental distinctions and divergent objectives between RJ and Aboriginal justice.
The apparent commonality of interests conceals competing political objectives and substantive
gaps between RJ theory and practice that can impact directly Aboriginal women within the
context of domestic violence. Actually, there are several other focuses of criticism or opposition
over the use of RJ language to articulate Aboriginal justice claims for recognition of customary
law and self-determination, especially in cases of domestic violence.186 However, they will be
185
See
note
180
at
24.
186
See,
e.g.,
David
Milward,
Making
the
Circle
Stronger:
an
effort
to
buttress
Aboriginal
use
of
Restorative
Justice
in
Canada
against
recent
criticisms
(2008)
4:3
IJPS
(For
a
discussion
over
the
use
of
restorative
justice
in
Aboriginal
settings.
The
author
includes
the
most
common
criticisms
over
the
idea,
but
contends
that
there
are
still
good
reasons
to
maintain
the
use
of
restorative
justice
in
Indigenous
criminal
justice)
88
The goals in that hybrid justice model are easily noticeable. Firstly, the aim is to
to allow Indigenous people to have a greater degree of input into and control over their own
justice processes that would become more aligned with self-determination political claims and
Aboriginal customary law. For example, according to traditional concepts of Aboriginal freedom
and individuality one person cannot impose a decision upon another as usually occurs in formal
courts.188 Therefore, court judgments might be seen as a form of imposing formal justice on the
Indigenous people who had been subjugated. Thirdly, to accommodate the particular needs of
Aboriginal people in conflict with the law providing a more familiar atmosphere in order to
reduce the lack of cultural sensitivity in the adjudication mechanism. Zernova, for example,
points out that measures like sentencing circles help to prevent the culture shock, which First
Nation people may experience when they have to appear in court.189 Finally, to involve the
community in creating and sharing knowledge, experiences, and solutions in order to pursue
restorative circles also imply that victims and offenders are not solely responsible for the
resolution of criminal justice-based disputes. Community members, victims and offenders are
supposed to participate in creating and expressing their own justice approach and, in so doing,
187
As
Cameron
has
observed,
Frustrated
with
the
over-incarceration
of
Aboriginal
offenders
in
remote
communities,
non-Aboriginal,
activist
judiciary
looked
to
community-based
alternatives
to
avoid
sending
recidivist
offenders
to
prison
in
the
South
(Hamilton,
2001;
Eber,
1997;
Stuart,
1996
a)
and
b);
Barnett,
1995;
Fafard,
1994).
Se
note
2
at
11.
(The
focus
is
on
reconciliation
and
rehabilitations
as
goals
for
sentencing.
By
broadening
sentence
alternatives
incarceration
is
seen
as
a
last
option).
188
See
note
140
at
28.
189
She
points
out
that
when
first
nation
people
follow
their
traditional
ethic
during
court
appearances
(such
as
avoiding
making
eye
contact,
showing
anger
and
confronting
or
criticizing
others),
their
behaviour
may
be
interpreted
as
contemptuous
acts
to
embarrass
or
engender
disrespect
for
the
court.
See
note
122
at
17.
89
themselves. Finally, restorative circles --- as in other models of RJ --- also require the usual
protagonists of the criminal justice system, i.e., judges, prosecutors, lawyers and law
enforcement agents, to act more as listeners and co-creators of solutions which result in a healthy
arguments for the merits of restorative circles. According to Zernova --- drawing from
commentaries originally developed by Barry Stuart --- a genuine and sincere participation in a
restorative circle has the potential to reconnect offenders to their communities, rebuild broken
relationships and address victims needs.190 In addition, it has the ability to educate the
community about its problems, fostering a sense of belonging to it. Moreover, it also helps to
reveal underlying causes of crime, which in other conditions may be overlooked. Finally,
restorative circles also generate community initiatives aimed at redressing the needs of victims
perception of them, e.g., traditional Indigenous talking circles or healing circles that are
primarily used to cope with substance abuse and other social conflicts outside the criminal
justice field, while others like sentencing circles incorporate more recent influences from the RJ
discourse and are chiefly designed to address serious criminal offences in conjunction with
formal judicial institutions. For this reason, the collective meaning given by Indigenous people
to circles is not reduced to a strictly criminal justice understanding. There is a spiritual and
curative facet that cannot be ignored. Both kinds of circle models follow similar basic principles
190
Supra
note.
(Former
Chief
Judge
of
the
Territorial
Court
of
Yukon
Barry
Stuart
pioneered
sentencing
circle
experiences
in
Canada.
More
detailed
examination
of
his
decisions
will
be
addressed
in
another
chapter)
90
of operation that I will describe in the next paragraphs. Nevertheless, emphasis will be given to
sentencing circles.
followed; it starts with applications from offenders who wish to participate in the process.191 The
prerequisites are full acceptance of the responsibility for the wrongdoing or at least a plea of
guilt. In addition, a strong connection between the offender and the community must exist.
McCold, acceptance into the circle is decided by a community justice committee or circle
support group.192
who demonstrate high levels of motivation and commitment to the process.193 In addition,
because the procedures are very time-consuming for everyone involved and also very costly,
only serious cases are referred to sentencing circles.194 Other considerations of public character
may be present since it is the Judge who refers the offender to the sentencing circle and only
after all the fact-finding issues have been already determined. Nevertheless, the general
assumption is that the community is the one best equipped to identify who must enter the circle.
So the final decision remains with the committee. As we can notice, therefore, sentencing circles
are restorative interventions that occur in a post-conviction stage of a regular legal proceeding
unlike other RJ models that usually occur apart from any formal proceeding.
191
The
procedures
and
guidelines,
however,
may
vary
considerable
from
one
community
to
the
other.
Cameron
points
out
that
in
Canada
this
lack
of
consistency
has
been
a
source
of
criticism
and
concern
both
in
the
literature
and
in
case
law.
See
note
2
at
15.
192
See
note
138
at
51.
193
See
note
178.
194
Ibid.
91
When a case is referred to the community committee and no concerns are
presented regarding the offenders acceptance or his commitment to the circles rules, the pre-
hearing arrangements can begin. The circle support group provides an initial contact with all
parties and their supporters as a way to promote their future link and commitment with the circle
plans and preparing all parties to participate.195 Victims voluntary participation in the circle is
encouraged, however, a family member or friend can also represent them and put forward their
interests. Moreover, there is one authoritative figure in the circle that deserves some attention:
the circle keeper. The keepers of the circle are respected community members, usually Elders
who lend their prestige and moral authority to the circle. According to Zernova, their function is
to act as facilitators of the process. The keeper, as she puts it, ensures respect for the teaching of
the circle, mediates differences and guides the circle toward a consensus.196
All participants are encouraged to get closer to others and sit in a circle at the
same level. All parties and the community are invited. Criminal justice professionals like the
offenders lawyer; the prosecutor and the judge will be equally present in the proceedings. Most
of the sentencing circles are held in courtrooms specially arranged to accommodate the circle.
McCold describes the way in which the circle Keeper conducts the opening procedures. He
writes: Opening the circle with a prayer, the keepers of the circle welcome everyone to the
circle and then introduce themselves by explaining who they are, what they do, where they are
from and why they are in the circle today. The Keeper then asks others to similarly introduce
195
See
note
138
at
51.
196
See
Zernova,
note
122
at
16-17.
See
also
McCold,
note
138.
(According
to
McCold,
the
function
of
the
Keeper
of
the
circle
in
the
first
experiences
with
sentencing
circles
was
played
by
the
Judge).
92
themselves, as an eagle feather or other sacred object used as a talking token is passed around
the circle.197
customary physical, emotional, spiritual and intellectual connections of the participants with
their own community, and provide an opportunity for reintegration, empathy and catharsis.198
Zernova also observes that most prayers stress the interconnectedness of all things and all people
and induce in the participants a feeling of being part of community. By doing so, the participants
amplify progressively a feeling that the suffering of one is the suffering of all, and that the
disharmony caused by the offence affects the entire community. As a consequence, everybody in
The Keeper then stresses the moral and non-moral purposes to be achieved by the
circle, and explains some guidelines. For example, to speak from the heart; to remain in the
circle until it finishes; to allow others to speak by speaking briefly; to respect others by not
interrupting, and, finally, to recognize the value of others contribution.199 At this point, the
charges are read and the prosecutor and defense lawyers make brief remarks about the offenders
conduct. Finally, every participant is invited to express his or her own opinion about the offence
and propose constructive solutions. As Lilles observes, those who participate in the circle speak
one at a time and may discuss issues not necessarily related to the criminal event.200 The issues
discussed may help to understand why the offence occurred and what needs to be done to meet
the needs of the victim, hold the offender accountable and prevent recidivism. Then the judge,
who is present during the whole process, passes a sentence and makes recommendations on the
197
Ibid.
198
Ibid.
199
See
note
138
at
51.
200
See
note
178.
93
basis of what has been said in the circle. McCold points out that the closing procedures normally
include summarizing what has or has not been agreed, outlining the next steps, thanking
everyone for their participation, passing the feather for closing comments by all participants, and
Now the basic question to be asked in this scenario is what happens after the
circle is closed, what follows the sentence plan? As Lilles explains, after being sentenced in a
circle, the offenders progress in following the sentencing plan is carefully monitored by his
support group, the community Justice committee and a probation officer.201 Actually, it is
expected that the preliminary screening of the circle candidates ensures that the offenders will
comply with the sentence plan without further problems. In addition, the sentence plan is not a
responsibility passed down by the formal justice system, but by his own community that vouches
for his credibility. Hence, the offenders commitment to the successful completion of the plan is
frameworks and builds a general critique around them. There are more substantial criticisms to
be made from a feminist perspective. However, this exploration will be developed in the next
chapter, which will focus on the feminist engagement with RJ within the context of domestic
violence and intersectionality theory. This section, therefore, provides only an overview of
specific points of criticism on RJ, how they are interconnected, and a sample of its complexity.
restorative justice. There is empirical research that can confirm or question specific points in this
201
Ibid.
94
critique of RJ.202 In this section, I extensively draw on the writings of Theo Gavrielides, R.D.
conspicuous dearth of critique.203 In fact, he contends that despite the near surfeit of literature
whatsoever. According to him, even among the critics there is a tendency to expose RJ
shortcomings and excesses with the sole purpose of avoiding any negative impact on the much
larger restorativist advocacy project. Indeed, for Koen most of the critics are themselves
committed to the success of the RJ project rather than truly critical of it.
authors like Milward.204 In his words: There has been a certain academic vogue since at least
the 1990s in extolling the virtues of restorative justice as an alternative approach. Efforts to
criticize restorative approaches have begun more recently by comparison, and are therefore less
in quantity.205 Wheeldon is of the same opinion, as he puts it: Numerous new publications in
the fields of criminology and criminal justice address restorative justice, yet few are critical of
the restorative justice paradigm.206 Gerry Johnstone, a renowned RJ scholar, seems to agree
202
For
a
review
on
empirical
studies
on
RJ
see
note
54.
203
See
Raymond
Koen,
The
Antinomies
of
Restorative
Justice
in
Elrena
Van
der
Spuy
et
al.,
eds.,
Restorative
Justice:
politics
,
policies
and
prospects
(Cape
Town:
Juta
&
Co
Ltd.,2007)
247.
(Critiquing
RJ
from
a
Marxist
point
of
view).
204
See
note
186
at
139.
205
Ibid.
206
See
Johannes
Wheeldon,
Finding
common
ground:
restorative
justice
and
its
theoretical
construction(s)
(2009)
12:1
Contemporary
Justice
Review
91-100
at
92.
95
with those points.207 He observes that the bulk of literature on RJ is written either by passionate
proponents or more cautious sympathizers. As a result, there are not many pieces of scholarly
However, this does not mean that RJ is immune from criticism. As a matter of
fact, there is a growing volume of critical analysis on RJ emerging from fields of study as
diverse as philosophy, law, psychology, and feminist socio-legal studies. Chris Cunneen points
postcolonial and liberal.209 According to him, these critiques cover various points of tension in
the RJ movement like the role of the state within RJ practice; RJ promises to stakeholders
(victims, offenders and community); the role of retribution and punishment in RJ theory;
concepts of globalization and community; relations of power, ethnicity and gender; and, finally,
questions about the rule of law, legal principles and due process of law.210 However, for the
purposes of this thesis, those lines of critical thought can be simplified and grouped into two
large categories according to the relationship of RJ with the conventional justice system.
207
See
Gerry
Johnstone,
Critical
perspectives
on
Restorative
Justice
in
Gerry
Johnstone
&
Daniel
W.
Van
Ness,
eds.,
Handbook
of
Restorative
Justice
(Portland,
Oregon:
Willan
Publishing,
2007)
598.
208
An
welcomed
exception
to
this
lack
of
critical
approach
on
RJ
is
Annalise
Acorns
work.
Her
book
Compulsory
Compassion:
A
Critique
of
Restorative
Justice
contains
a
full
psychoanalytic,
philosophical
and
social-legal
critique
upon
the
RJ
movement.
See
Acorn,
Compulsory
Compassion,
note
47.
209
See
Chris
Cunneen,
Thinking
Critically
about
Restorative
Justice
in
Eugene
McLaughlin
et
al.,
eds.,
Restorative
Justice:
Critical
Issues
(Thousand
Oaks,
CA:
Sage
Publications,
2003)
at
182.
See
Koen,
Antinomies
note
203.
(For
a
neo-marxist
critique
of
RJ).
See
Bruce
A.
Arrigo
&
Robert
C.
Schehrb,
Restoring
justice
for
juveniles:
A
critical
analysis
of
victim
offender
mediation
(1998)
15:4
Justice
Quarterly
629-666
(For
a
critique
of
RJ
from
a
psychoanalytic
semiotics
and
postmodern
perspectives).
See,
e.g.,
Chris
Cunneen,
Restorative
Justice
and
the
Politics
of
Decolonization
in
Elmar
G.M.
Weitekamp
&
Han-Jurgen
Kerner,
eds.,
Restorative
Justice:
Theoretical
Foundations
(Deon,
UK:
Willan
Publishing,
2002)
32-49
(For
a
postcolonial
critique
of
RJ).
Naturally,
this
paper
invites
criticism
and
discussion
on
RJ
based
on
a
feminist
perspective
within
the
context
of
critical
race
politics
and
domestic
violence.
The
feminist
critique
on
RJ
will
be
deeper
explored
in
the
next
chapter.
210
See
Mary
Ellen
Reimund,
"The
Law
and
Restorative
Justice:
Friend
or
Foe?
A
Systemic
look
at
the
legal
issues
in
Restorative
Justice"
(2004)
53
Drake
Law
Review
667.
See
also
Mary
Ellen
Reimund,
"Is
Restorative
Justice
in
collision
course
of
Constitution"
(2004)
3
Appalachian
Journal
of
Law
3.
Tina
S.
Ikpa,
Balancing
Restorative
Justice
Principles
and
Due
Process
Rights
in
Order
to
Reform
the
Criminal
Justice
System
(2007)
24
Journal
of
Law
&
Policy
301.
See
generally
Lode
Walgrave,
ed.,
Restorative
Justice
and
the
Law
(Cullompton,
UK:
Willan
Publishing,
2002).
(For
an
exploration
of
the
critical
liberal
arguments
on
restorative
justice).
96
The first category involves criticism that centers on advocates claims that RJ is
an authentic paradigmatic shift, i.e., a radical departure from the conventional justice system and
its traditional, adversarial, and punitive/retributive characteristics. This claim emerged from the
revolutionary discourse heralding the radical replacement of the existing criminal justice system
by an allegedly more humane, informal and inclusive justice system that could equally address
victims, offenders and community needs and interests. In addition, several argued that RJ could
provide not only a better way of doing justice, but a better way of living as well.211 That kind of
visionary and grandiose project for RJ was the focus of criticism by more cautious scholars and
practitioners who raised doubts about its ability to deliver such promised benefits. Some of them,
as we shall see, even expressed concerns about whether any are realizable at all.
The second category of criticism is focused on a more recent and practical facet of
restorative justice. By assimilating the just criticism of their first wave of writings, many RJ
proponents have retreated from allegations of life-changing virtues and adopted a more
pragmatic posture where RJ functions more as an adjunct of the conventional criminal justice
system rather than a replacement for it. This left the RJ movement less vulnerable to disapproval
from skeptical legal scholars and at the same time left it more palatable to more conservative
211
See
especially
John
Braithwaite,
Restorative
Justice:
Assessing
Optimistic
and
Pessimistic
Accounts
(1999)
25
Crime
and
Justice
1-127;
John
Braithwaite,
A
future
where
punishment
is
marginalized:
Realistic
or
Utopian?
(1999)
46
UCLA
Law
Review
17271746;
Gordon
Bazemore
&
Lode
Walgrave,
Restorative
juvenile
justice:
In
search
of
fundamentals
and
an
outline
for
systemic
reform
in
G.
Bazemore
&
L.
Walgrave
,eds.,
Restorative
juvenile
justice:
Repairing
the
harm
of
Youth
Crime
(Monsey,
NY:
Criminal
Justice
Press,
1999);
Lode
Walgrave,
Restorative
justice
for
juveniles:
Just
a
technique
or
a
fully-fledged
alternative?
(1995)
34:3
Howard
Journal
of
Criminal
Justice
228249;
Paul
McCold,
Restorative
justice
and
the
role
of
the
community
in
B.
Galaway
&
J.
Hudson,
eds.,
Restorative
Justice:
International
Perspectives
(Mossey:
Criminal
Justice
Press,
1996)
at
86,
and
Martin
Wright,
Justice
for
victims
and
offenders
(Philadelphia:
Open
University
Press,
1991).
See
also
Howard
Zher
note
47.
(That
was
the
first
generation
of
writers
on
RJ
who
emphasized
its
radical
virtues
in
order
to
canvass
support
among
those
discontent
with
rising
case
loads,
growing
prison
populations,
high
recidivism
and
lack
of
regard
to
victims
of
crime
and
to
the
community
generally.
The
strategy
of
a
radical
replacement
of
the
conventional
justice
system
proved
to
be
successful.
In
less
than
forty
years
the
RJ
movement
achieved
international
projection
with
hundreds
of
experiences
all
over
the
world
claiming
to
be
restorativists
in
body
and
soul).
97
audiences that found positive aspects in it like cost reductions, decrease of case loads, and victim
gathered momentum in the first decade of the 2000s when programs popped up in several
jurisdictions around the globe under the auspices of the very criminal justice system that it once
intended to replace. In this period of quick expansion even the United Nations was captured by
the intense interest in RJ and ended up buying the idea by adopting the Basic principles on the
use of Restorative Justice and sponsoring publications targeted to establish best practices in the
Here, proponents propose that restorative justice be seen as working within, and as a
basic complement to the demands, of state criminal justice. Bazemore and McLeod
(2002), Cooley (1999), and even Zher (2002) dilute the concept of 'alternative' by giving
it much more of a local, parochial meaning where restorative justice is seen as providing
limited alternatives to aspects of the existing criminal justice system. So, restorative
justice may be seen as offering an alternative to 'courtroom procedures' or 'penalty
regimes' within the criminal justice system, but not to the criminal justice itself. 213
conventional justice system became more a matter of how to incorporate it into the mainstream
and not whether it should be incorporated. In sum, hopes of a potentially independent justice
paradigm that could stand either in parallel or instead of the current retributive paradigm were
criminal justice systems provides the empirical context for this study --- that is based on feminist
critical perspectives --- but also for other avenues of criticism like the liberal one. Indeed, many
212
See
Yvon
Dandurand
&
Curt
T.
Griffiths,
Handbook
on
restorative
justice
programmes
Prepared
for
The
United
Nations
Office
on
Drugs
and
Crime
(Vienna:
United
Nations
Publications,
2006).
See
also
note
23.
(UN
Basic
Principles
on
RJ)
213
See
George
Clifford
Pavlich,
Governing
paradoxes
of
Restorative
Justice
(London,
UK:
Glasshouse
Press,
2005)
at
18.
(Arguing
that
RJ
works
as
a
imitor
paradox,
i.e,
it
is
supposedly
independent
from
conventional
justice,
but
ensnares
itself
within
criminal
justice
language,
logic
and
agencies).
98
of the questions about the relationship with RJ and the rule of law, legal principles and due
process of law have emerged from this merely complementary version of restorative justice.
This segment identifies the main criticisms of RJ within the context of its
consistent and independent criminal justice paradigm that has the potential to stand alone, and
which should replace the current one.214 The explanation Gravielides offers for this kind of
claim is consistent with the advocacy motives that seemed to guide the early years of restorative
justice. According to him, by introducing RJ as a paradigmatic shift, using liberal platitudes and
overstatements, its advocates were hoping to make the then new and untested concept of RJ
more appealing and interesting for theorists, practitioners and the general public.
sufficient maturity to leave the phase of innovative impact to enter in the phase of practical
implementation. At that point, those proponents seeking more unrealistic means of advancing RJ
were confronted with the harsh reality that their celebrated proposition of a paradigm shift ---
214
See
note
54
at
38.
See
also
James
Dignan,
Restorative
Justice
and
the
Law:
The
Case
for
an
Integrated,
Systemic
Approach
in
Lode
Walgrave,
ed.,
Restorative
Justice
and
the
Law
(Cullompton,
UK:
Willan
Publishing,
2002)
16890.
James
Dignan,
Towards
a
Systemic
Model
of
Restorative
Justice
in
A.
Von
Hirsch
et
al.,
eds.,
Restorative
Justice:
Competing
or
Reconcilable
Paradigms?
(Portland,
OR:
Hart
Publishing,
2003)
135-156.
99
that is still in circulation in some RJ circles --- was ill-conceived and vulnerable to criticisms.
Ross London, for example, contends that the characterization of restorative justice as a new
paradigm, as in the case of many other academic disciplines, is better regarded as rhetorical
It created ideological divisions that demanded dogmatic conformity from its adherents.
It rejected attempts to integrate the best features of the old and the new approaches
as threats to the purity of the new paradigm. 216
regarding its conceptualization as a different paradigm of justice and eventual replacement for
the existing criminal justice system. In the following subsections some of those criticisms are
215
See
Ross
D.
London,
Paradigms
Lost:
Repairing
the
Harm
of
Paradigm
Discourse
in
Restorative
Justice
(2006)
19:4
Criminal
Justice
Studies
397-422
at
400.
(Noting
systematic
weaknesses
in
the
RJ
claim
that
it
is
a
new
and
independent
paradigm
of
justice).
216
Supra
note
at
398.
See
generally
Thomas
S.
Kuhn,
The
Structure
of
Scientific
Revolutions,
3rd
ed.
(Chicago:
University
of
Chicago
Press,
1996).
100
ii. Restorative
Justice
versus
Retributive
Justice:
The
role
of
punishment
to the RJ movement emerges from advocates claims that it is the opposite of retributive
justice.217 Gavrielides points out that the views are divided into two groups.218 The first group
holds a purist version of RJ. They deny that RJ interventions can, in any way, be
retributive/punitive. In contrast, the second group holds a maximalist version of RJ that argues
that it cannot be prescinded from retributive justice elements like public censure and coercion.
According to Gavrielides, RJ scholars like Paul McCold, Wright, and Sullivan/Tifft reject
completely the idea of including any coercive judicial sanctions in the restorative process, as it
might shift RJ back to being punitive.219 However, other scholars such as Braithwaite, Walgrave
and Bazemore, while arguing that the RJ response should be primarily non-punitive recognize
that there is a role for limited punishment dispensed in a respectful way on public safety
grounds.220
justice. According to her, there is an artificial and almost Manicheist opposition between
restorative justice (depicted as good and virtuous), and retributive justice (depicted as inherently
bad) in the RJ rhetoric.221 Moreover, she observes that some RJ proponents also include
rehabilitative justice as detrimental to a holistic view of justice because it focuses only on the
offender and ignores the victim. Her insights suggest that the opposition between RJ and
217
See
Michael
T.
Cahill,
Retributive
Justice
in
the
Real
World
(2007)
85
Washington
University
Law
Review
815.
(For
an
overview
of
retributive
Justice
theory).
218
See
note
54
at
41.
219
Ibid.
220
Ibid.
221
See
Kathleen
Daly,
Restorative
justice:
The
Real
Story
(2002)
4
Punishment
&
Society
55-79
at
59.
See
especially
Kathleen
Daly,
Revisiting
the
relationship
between
retributive
and
restorative
justice
in
Heather
Strang
&
John
Braithwaite
,eds.,
Restorative
justice,
from
philosophy
to
practice
(Aldershot:
Dartmouth,
2000)
33
.
101
retributive justice is artificial, simplistic and inadequate. As she puts it, Advocates seem to
assume that an ideal justice system should be of one type only, that it should be pure and not
contaminated by or mixed with others.222 Rather, Daly suggests that RJ processes are not pure.
As a matter of fact, she observes retributive elements (censure for past conduct) and
of RJ salutary properties (the offender making amends to the victim) in restorative encounters.
For Daly, therefore, specific components of retributive justice, albeit with some modifications
place understandings about what to do in response to crime, including the need to incapacitate
dangerous offenders; prevent them from being recidivist; separate them from the community;
teach them a lesson; and aid them to help themselves.223 In the same line of reasoning, London
notes that strategies utilized to avoid the contradictions that arise from asserting a anti-retributive
alternative to controlling crime like limiting the scope of RJ programmes only to cooperative
offenders and to non-serious cases are destined to fail.224 According to him, although retaining
the purity of the non-punitive approach, they are still dependent on the conventional model
that refers the cases to it. In addition, in his words It strikes at the heart of the claim of
restorative justice as a new paradigm because it provides no alternate solutions to the very
problems that necessitate the creation of criminal law in the first place: serious offenses and
uncooperative offenders.225
222
Supra
note
Daly,
The
real
story,
at
59.
223
See
note
221,
Daly,
Revisiting
the
relationship,
at
45.
See
also
Antony
R.
Duff,
Alternatives
to
punishment
or
alternative
punishments?
in
W.
Cragg
,
ed.,
Retributivism
and
its
critics
(Stuttgart:
Franz
Steiner,1992)
48-62.
224
See
note
215.
225
Ibid.
at
412.
102
In fact, more recently the debate over the role of punishment within RJ
interventions, as London points out, became not so much a question of whether punishment
ought to be superseded by the new RJ paradigm, but rather, a question as to the nature and extent
of the punishment required in RJ interventions.226 In reality, even Howard Zehr, who initially
endorsed a purist view on RJ, in his subsequent writings, abandoned the view of restorative
justice as the opposite of retributive justice. As Zehr has noted, Restorative justice advocates
adversaries. As a restorative justice advocate who initially popularized this dichotomy, I have
Several of the issues concerning the restorative and retributive dichotomy overlap
various ways towards stakeholders. This kind of criticism is both unavoidable and indispensible
in a field like restorative justice, full of rhetoric excesses, and it has done much to clarify and
expose its vulnerabilities. In the following paragraphs, I briefly address some of them although I
do not claim allegiance to any other particular line of criticism besides of course the feminist
one. Having said that, I seek to give more emphasis to points on which feminists would also
express some concern. Moreover, I try to introduce issues regarding the Aboriginal use of RJ
practices.
226
Ibid.
227
See
Howard
Zehr,
Book
review
of
The
spiritual
Roots
of
Restorative
Justice
by
Michael
Hadley,
(2003)
43
British
Journal
of
Criminology
653654
at
654.
103
Privatizing
crime:
Lack
of
public
denunciation
Koen notes, RJ re-conceptualizes the criminal event as a private conflict between individuals that
has disturbed community relations.228 Accordingly crimes are re-conceptualized as harms and
victims and offenders rights re-conceptualized as needs. Thus, the primary goal of RJ is to
amend those relations without the intervention of professional actors of the formal justice system
(Lawyers, judges, prosecutors, etc.) and the punitive mechanisms of the state. This is, in Koens
view, the most radical tenet of RJ because it challenges the statist texture of criminal justice. In
his critical analysis of RJ as a new paradigm, London notes that the theoretical basis for
Conflicts as Property. As we have seen before, Christie argues that by replacing interpersonal
conflict resolution with a state-imposed solution, the state steals the conflict by re-framing the
problem as a crime against the state.229 By using the state as the offended party, it is claimed that
the needs of the actual victims are either neglected or addressed only incidentally, e.g., in victim
support services or compensation programs. As London points out, citing Kurki: The restorative
justice solution reverses this unhappy historical development by requiring the state to surrender
its monopoly over responses to crime to those who are directly affectedthe victim, the
Critics of RJ argue that those procedures make private what should be public, and
therefore fail to reinforce and extend both public norms of conduct and commitments to justice
embedded in formal judicial procedures. Feminist critics, for example, heavily criticize the
228
See
note
203
at
249.
229
See
note
84.
230
See
note
215
at
413.
104
privatization of crime in RJ theory, chiefly on the grounds that the RJ conceptualization of crime
as a private harm jeopardizes womens positions since it potentially denies public denunciation
of violence against women cases. Domestic violence cases, for instance, can be seen again as
private affairs and may be channeled into more informal processing which precludes public
awareness, discussion, and potential change. Thus, some feminist critiques would see RJ as a
retrograde step in their historical struggle for raising public awareness of violence against
women. Indeed, some feminists believe that RJ maintains the continuing repression of women in
guise of an alternative to the formal criminal justice system. This theme will be further explored
relations in RJ encounters. RJs proponents often claim that in restorative encounters everybody
can speak on the same terms, and theoretically have his or her concerns addressed equally.231
However, critics suggest that such claims are merely rhetorical and restorative conferences leave
power differentials and social, racial and gender inequalities unexamined, unattended, and
unchallenged.232 .233 The concerns are threefold. Firstly, from a victims perspective, there is the
fear that they can be physically our psychologically harmed by RJ dialogue-based processes due
to power imbalances between victims and offenders, especially in certain crimes marked by
231
See,
e.g.,
Mara
Schiff,
Satisfying
the
needs
and
interests
of
stakeholders
in
Gerry
Johnstone
&
Daniel
W.
Van
Ness,
eds.,
Handbook
of
Restorative
Justice
(Portland,
Oregon:
Willan
Publishing,
2007)
228.
(Discussing
the
needs,
interests
and
responsibilities
of
various
stakeholders
in
restorative
processes).
232
See,
e.g.,
Loretta
Capeheart
&
Dragan
Milovanovic,
Social
justice:
theories,
issues,
and
movements
(Piscataway,
NJ:
Rutgers
University
Press,
2007)
at
63.
233
See,
e.g.,
Loretta
Capeheart
&
Dragan
Milovanovic,
Social
justice:
theories,
issues,
and
movements
(Piscataway,
NJ:
Rutgers
University
Press,
2007)
at
63.
105
processes of control and power like domestic violence.234 Here the main related concern is the
danger to the victims security and empowerment due to the perils of revictimization.235
Secondly, in contrast, there is the fear that offenders can be left powerless by the
centered on the neutrality of the mediator/facilitator like in others alternative dispute resolution
schemes. In fact, the ideology behind RJ is allegedly supportive of the victim.237 For this reason,
critics have also raised concerns about the imbalance between supposedly powerless offenders
and supposedly powerful victims. Finally, critics of RJ often complain that both victims and
Accusations
of
manipulation
For victims --- our main focus of attention --- the worry is that RJ programmes
may treat them as no more than props for efforts to rehabilitate offenders, as Braithwaite has
put it.238 According to Delgado, RJ may be manipulating victims by pressuring them to forgive
offenders before they are psychologically mature enough to do so.239 In addition, he argues that
facilitators/mediators, who typically want both parties to put aside their negative emotions such
as anger, distrust, and desire for punishment, may suggest that victims are being obstructionist or
emotionally immature if they refuse to do so. In other words, victims are not free to be
234
See,
e.g.,
Goel,
note
13.
235
See
Cameron,
note
11
at
176.
236
See,
e.g.,
Richard
Delgado,
Goodbye
to
Hammurabi:
Analyzing
the
Atavistic
Appeal
of
Restorative
Justice
(2000)
52:
4
Stanford
Law
Review
751-775.
(Delgado
critiques
the
informal
setting
of
restorative
justice
processes
and
highlights
issues
of
unequal
treatment
regarding
victims
and
offenders).
237
Supra
note
at
760.
But
see,
e.g.,
Kelly
Richards,
Taking
Victims
Seriously?
The
Role
of
Victims'
Rights
Movements
in
the
Emergence
of
Restorative
Justice
(2009)
21
Current
Issues
Criminal
Justice
302.
(Arguing
that
RJ
is
not
as
intimately
tied
to
the
victims'
rights
movement
as
some
proponents
suggest).
238
See
John
Braithwaite,
Restorative
Justice
and
Responsive
Regulation
(New
York:
Oxford
University
Press,
2002)
at
139.
239
See
note
235
at
763.
106
themselves in restorative encounters, and facilitators/mediators or even the community would
have the capacity to induce an attitude in the victim in which he or she would feel inhibited to
express perfectly understandable feelings of anger and resentment over the crime or the outcome
of the RJ encounter.
Notably, Delgado observes that this problem is especially worrisome for victims
of domestic violence. According to him, such victims who already blame themselves may
magnify that self-blame. Delgado also explains that RJ casts the victim in the role of sentencer,
holding the power of judgment over the offender. As he writes, It may also place an unwelcome
burden on the victim who will end up determining the fate of the offender. Not every victim will
welcome this responsibility. In pressuring the victim to forgive and move on and handing him
the power of sentencer, VOM may end up compounding the injury received from the crime
itself.240
Postmodern
critique
of
RJ
mechanisms whereby subjects are pacified, normalized and, finally, silenced (e.g., trained to
accept system directives, rules, and roles).241 According to them, some critics borrow
schemes, i.e., mediators or community members help encourage agreements that are consistent
with status quo ante interests, values, norms, and other ideologies. As they put it:
240
Supra.
241
See
note
232
at
63.
See
also
Michel
Foucault,
Discipline
and
Punish:
the
Birth
of
the
Prison,
(New
York:
Random
House,
1975).
107
Arrigo and Schehr (1998) have argued that victim offender mediations programs rely
extensively on a master discourse within which system-sustaining frames of reference are
rehearsed, thus assuring predictability and stability in the programs. In other words,
victims are encouraged to verbalize their hurts in the language of mediation
(reconciliation, healing, restitution, responsibility, etc.) This language is already
ideological and points to certain outlooks (see also Acorn 2004; Pavlich 2005) 242
In short, this postmodern perspective would assert that there is not much
recognition on restorative processes of pre-existing power and status differentials regarding, for
interventions may reproduce and perpetuate the wider power imbalances embedded in the status
quo ante or even function as a discipline of silence. For example, female victims of domestic
violence may have little verbalization and influence in RJ encounters as Cameron and Cunnliffe
have noted.243
imbalances rooted in Aboriginal communities can reverberate in the restorative process itself. He
points out, citing a previous study by Sherene Razack, that the use of community-based
he puts it, Aboriginal communities are suffused with patriarchal power structures that replicate
sentencing initiatives, to the benefit of male Aboriginal offenders who commit crimes against
be tightly linked to the perpetuation of previous gender inequalities by the agency of disciplinary
242
Supra
note.
243
See
note
8,
Cameron
&
Cunliffe,
Writing
the
Circle
at
26-27.
244
See
note
186
at
144.
See
also
Sherene
Razack,
Looking
White
People
in
the
Eye:
Gender,
Race
and
Culture
in
Courtrooms
and
Classrooms
(Toronot:
University
of
Toronto
Press,
2001)
108
General
criticisms
here, but an exhaustive critique of the RJ movement is not the purpose of this segment. Thus, I
shall limit myself from now on to just listing those critiques that some canonical authors
consider worthy of further attention. Towards this end, I will make use of lists originally devised
by Johnstone, Morris and Delgado. Some of the criticisms listed by them overlap at various
points. In addition, some of them are interrelated with previous and upcoming notes.
critique. The first two scholars are RJ proponents, but they clearly distanced themselves from
partisan attitudes. As Morris asserts, I acknowledge that the restorative justice literature is
plagued with imprecision and confusion and I do not seek to defend all practices that claim to be
restorative justice.245
about what RJ can achieve and have multiple and unclear goals; 3) A significant move away
from punishment towards RJ would undermine the policy of deterrence; 4) A significant move
away from punishment towards RJ would result in a failure to do justice; 5) A significant move
away from punishment towards RJ would result in systematic departures from axiomatic
245
See
Morris,
Critiquing
the
Critics,
note
47
at
597.
See
also
Andrew
Ashworth,
Some
doubts
about
Restorative
Justice
(1993)
4:2
Criminal
Law
Forum
277-299.
(Raising
the
first
concerns
about
the
RJ
theoretical
framework).
But
see
Daniel
W.
Van
Ness,
A
Reply
to
Andrew
Ashworth
4:2
Criminal
Law
Forum
301-306
(Responding
to
the
criticisms
made
by
Ashworth).
109
wrongdoing, RJ actually is predicated on the existing criminal justice system and its use will
simply extend the reach of conventional systems of penal control (Net widening).246
crime (particularly mens violence against women); 4) RJ fails to restore victims and offenders;
outcomes; 7) RJ extends police powers (in specific programmes); 8) RJ leaves power imbalances
untouched; 9) RJ leads to vigilantism; 10) RJ lacks legitimacy and RJ fails to provide justice; 11)
RJ is too lenient an option to deal with crime, and RJ cannot deal with persistent offenders and
serious crimes. Furthermore, Delgado identifies other criticisms on RJ such as its lack of
safety and retribution); lack of state control; poor evaluation criteria based on users satisfaction;
sparking personal moral transformation and development, and treating conflict as a pathology.248
Other critics, such as Blagg and Adam Crawford, also make comments that the RJ association
with Indigenous forms of justice can be considered a form of orientalism and that the concept of
246
See
note
207.
247
Supra
note
244
at
600.
248
See
note
235.
249
See
Harry
Blagg,
A
Just
Measure
of
Shame?
Aboriginal
Youth
and
Conferencing
(1997)
37:4
Australia
British
Journal
of
Criminology
481-501.
See
also
Adam
Crawford
&
Todd
Clear,
Community
justice:
Transforming
communities
through
restorative
justice?
in
Gordon
Bazemore
&
Mara
Schiff,
eds.,
in
Restorative
Community
Justice:
Repairing
Harm
and
Transforming
Communities
(Otawa:
Anderson
Publishing,
2001)
127-149.
110
c) The
critique
revolving
around
RJ
as
an
appendage
of
the
justice
system
(compared to the volume of scholarly attention in the other category). It includes critiques of
relatively narrow scope and ambition, focused mainly on liberal concerns about RJ and the due
process of law (mainly due process protections and procedural safeguards for offenders). As I
did in the previous subsection, I will succinctly cover salient examples by means of listing them.
Cunneen, for example, lists those concerns related to the relationship between RJ and the
investigatory stage of criminal prosecution. According to him, they proceed as follows: 1) the
lack of independent legal advice; 2) pressures to admit an offence to obtain the benefit of a
diversionary alternative to court and the avoidance of a criminal record; 4) the lack of testing of
the legality of police searches, questioning and evidence-gathering and, finally, fears that the
pressure to admit an offence means that issues relating to the criminal intent in committing the
act (mens rea) and legal defenses are not considered by the court.250 In the same line of
reasoning, Reimund put forward concerns regarding, e.g., rights against self-incrimination and
conferences; and privation of the offenders liberty in the case of him failing with sentencing
circles adjudication and probation conditions.251 Tina Ikpa would include in the previous lists
concerns about the offenders right to trial and concerns with double jeopardy (when there is a
chance that the RJ interventions are not successful, and therefore the case proceeds to trial).252
250
See
Cunneen,
Thinking
Critically,
note
209
at
189.
251
See
Reimund,
Friend
or
Foe,
note
210.
252
See
Ikpa,
Balancing
Restorative
Justice,
note
210.
111
d) Feminist
critique
of
RJ:
Deferring
the
discussion
In recent years feminists have turned increasing attention to RJ, bringing new
issues and fresh critical perspectives to the field. Some are only concerned with traditionally
related fields such as domestic violence and the usability of RJ within that context. Other
feminists expand the breadth of the discussion to incorporate in their research questions about
the politics of race and gender in making justice claims, i.e., whether indigenous interests in
criminal justice system are compatible with RJ aims.253 However, these issues will not be
addressed here. They will be developed in the following chapters, where I will address how
feminist theorizing has been influencing and being influenced by RJ and I will engage my thesis
main arguments.
frameworks. The promises and shortcomings in some of the ideas put forward by the RJ
movement have been addressed. Particularly, I have noticed that the RJ movement has shown a
welcome aptitude to take account of criticisms and alter its position accordingly. Much of this is
due to its conceptual flexibility. However, RJ does not seem to be any nearer to a flawless theory
and practice. As we shall see, the feminist approach to RJ is strong evidence of this.
253
See
Cunneen,
Thinking
Critically,
note
209
at
192.
112
Chapter
II
Feminism,
restorative
justice
and
domestic
violence
Chapter outline
This chapter examines the feminist scholarship on RJ, briefly exploring its
ongoing critique and contributions for the conceptualization and practice of RJ particularly
within the context of violence against women. As mainstream feminist scholars and anti-
violence activists turned their attention to the new phenomenon of the RJ movement, a growing
distrust about its discourse and practice began to emerge. Utilizing insights from several varieties
of feminist thinking; from the battered womens anti-violence movement and other sources,
feminist scholars and activists presented their critique of the methods and practices used by
restorativists and sought to elevated a more gender sensitive approach in the RJ theoretical and
practical framework.
on restorative justice. Some emphasize the centrality of conventional gender issues while others
emphasize the increasingly relevant role of non-gender-specific issues like race and post-colonial
claims for remedial justice practices. As a result, that initial wariness based solely on gender
concerns cannot be attributed to the whole feminist theoretical spectrum. The feminist analysis
of RJ evolved to encompass distinct structural elements besides gender. In other words, the
feminist critical articulation of the dialectic between RJ and gender violence has developed
within the context of diverse theoretical feminist perspectives with focus on multiple loci within
inequality or analytical categories. For this reason, the feminist distrust of RJ is not as prevalent
as may be implied by a superficial survey of the feminist thinking on that subject matter. In this
chapter, I will draw up an overview of the complex relationship between feminist scholarship
113
and RJ with special attention to the role of feminist intersectionality theory in the broader
The aim here is to introduce the reader to the ways in which gender; culture; race;
self-determination politics; and other sites of inequality emerge and are used or misused in
sequence --- an outline of the feminist engagement with RJ considering the several strands of
feminist scholarship that have addressed it. Notably, this serves to introduce my perception of
intersectionality theory and its prevailing epistemic stance, i.e., anti-essentialism. Secondly, I
elaborate on how intersectionality theory has expanded the mainstream feminist critical analysis
of RJ to include criticisms and contributions concerning the intersections between sexism and
other forms of oppression and subordination such as racism, cultural domination and, above all,
post-colonial claims for social justice. Following that, I indentify potential vulnerabilities
practices analogous to Indigenous justice. The main reason for this is the severe underestimation
addressed with unintended consequences concerning their appraisals of RJs ability to promote
safety, empowerment and justice. The issue of how to assess intersectional perspectives for
reliability is critical, especially when unexpected detrimental effects to women may arise like
silencing and exclusion. I also introduce my insights about how other forces like the self-
114
advocacy discourse of RJ and political claims for social justice/self-governance can complicate
the process of a balanced interplay of loci of inequality used in intersectional analysis. Following
this, I turn back again to mainstream feminism. I address the concerns regarding the suitability of
RJ to deal with domestic violence cases regardless of race or culture. This provides a contrasting
point between how anti-violence feminism interprets the relationship between RJ and domestic
violence and how some intersectional feminists may view it from disparate positions.
arguments as ultimately reinforcing the marginal status of Indigenous women especially when
interacting with particular RJ practices. In sum, I contend that the critical examination of RJ
experiences by feminists using intersectionality analysis may be prone to distortions and co-
optation by other interests with detrimental consequences to victimized women and the
a) General
Issues
perspectives to RJ practices and it has been accompanied by efforts to ensure a safe, meaningful
gender-specific issues with which male victims (or offenders) interacting with RJ are not usually
confronted.254 In this process, feminists have identified RJ practices as a potential site of gender
254
In
general,
the
scholarly
attention
given
to
women
interacting
with
RJ
ascribes
to
them
the
role
of
victims.
Curiously,
however,
in
R
v.
Gladue
which
is
the
leading
case
on
the
application
of
restorative
justice
principles
for
Aboriginal
offenders
in
Canada
the
offender
is
a
woman.
Ms.
Gladue,
an
Aboriginal
woman,
stabbed
to
death
her
abusive
common
law
partner
and
was
sentenced
to
a
term
of
imprisonment.
The
Supreme
Court
of
Canada
interpreting
the
Section
718.2
of
the
Criminal
Code
of
Canada
attenuated
the
sentence
and
endorsed
the
notion
of
115
inequality and womens oppression.255 Their critiques essentially revolve around a common
theme, regardless of race or culture: the harmful effects of lack of security and empowerment to
processes have the potential to exclude and silence women. Others assert that they are not
designed to protect victims of gender violence from further victimization and they are not
effective solutions to domestic violence and its peculiarities.256 In essence, this means recurring
claims that gender issues have been largely absent from forums that settle the planning and
functioning of RJ models, which feminists deem to be skewed towards male offenders needs and
interests. In other words, feminist critics of RJ (to whom I will refer generically as mainstream
feminists) find that women and gender (or, more accurately, issues of concern to women
that may reproduce or perpetuate victimization and gender normative stereotypes as seems to be
Despite this generally negative view, however, this thesis identifies at least one
specific strand of feminist thinking that displays ambivalent positions that range from profound
distrust to open enthusiasm for the RJ project. I am referring --- of course --- to the feminist
relevant for understanding the empirical focus in this work, which are restorative models used as
restorative
justice
and
a
sentencing
regime
which
is
to
pay
fidelity
to
"healing"
as
a
normative
value
for
Aboriginal
offenders
even
if
the
offender
lives
outside
a
reserve.
See
R
v.
Gladue
[1999]
S.C.J.
No.
19,
online:
QL
(SCJ).
See
also
Mary
Ellen
Turpel-Lafond,
Sentencing
within
a
Restorative
Justice
Paradigm:
Procedural
Implications
of
R.v.
Gladue
(1999)
43
Crim.
L.
Q.
34.
In
addition,
there
is
a
growing
literature
on
youth
restorative
justice
and
girls
associated
to
gangs.
This
discussion,
however,
goes
beyond
the
scope
of
our
thesis
and
will
not
be
addressed.
255
See,
e.g.,
Julie
Stubbs,
Domestic
Violence
and
Womens
Safety:
Feminist
Challenges
to
Restorative
Justice,
in
John
Braithwaite
&
Heather
Strang,
eds.,
Restorative
Justice
and
Family
Violence
(Cambridge,
UK:
Cambridge
University
Press,
2002)
at
42.
256
See,
e.g.,
C.
Quince
Hopkins
&
Mary
P.
Koss,
Incorporating
Feminist
Theory
and
Insights
Into
a
Restorative
Justice
Response
to
Sex
Offenses
(2005)
11
Violence
Against
Women
693.
(Addressing
concerns
raised
by
feminists
about
the
use
of
restorative
justice
for
gendered
violence,
albeit
giving
nuances
in
its
use
for
cases
of
non-penetration
sex
violence).
116
hybrid justice constructs in postcolonial settings. To be more precise, RJ programmes and
practices --- mainly sentencing circles --- that are used ostensibly as state-sanctioned alternative
criminal justice responses designed to ameliorate the systemic racism and over-incarceration
rates that Aboriginal peoples experience in postcolonial jurisdictions such as Canada and
Australia. Intersectional perspectives on those experiences may vary substantially in content and
in critical tone depending on the emphasis given to gender among other categories (or sites) of
inequality; for example, ethnicity, race, culture and --- occurring in parallel --- postcolonial self-
determination political claims as they relate to culturally sensitive criminal justice experiences of
governance. As a consequence, some intersectional feminists have found themselves in the odd
position of feeling compelled to endorse RJ practices, against critical views from other feminists
(co-optation). This occurs mainly because some RJ models, such as sentencing circles, are
framed and presented to conform to intersectional images of what a successful and culturally
sensitive holistic criminal justice system ought to look like, despite serious objections to the lack
of standards and safeguards that can make restorative interventions unsatisfactory for victims of
gendered-violence. But before discussing such issues and their repercussions in this thesis --- the
theme of the next chapter --- an overview of the feminist engagement with RJ is warranted.
At first, it should be noted that the feminist movement is as diverse and complex
as the RJ movement and perhaps even more plurivocal. Nevertheless, it is possible to define a
distinct body of scholarship on RJ clearly marked by feminist concerns and insights. For
example, in the article The Feminist Engagement with Restorative Justice, Daly and Stubbs
117
chronicled how feminist scholarship has critically engaged restorative justice.257 According to
them, through the years the feminist engagement with RJ has taken a number of forms. More
specifically, there are five areas in which feminists have made direct contact with it, at times
showing overlapping interests and common philosophical stances. Those areas are mapped as
follows: 1) theories of justice; 2) the role of retribution in criminal justice; 3) studies of gender
(and other social relations) in RJ processes; 4) the appropriateness of RJ for partner, sexual or
family violence; and 5) the politics of race and gender in making justice claims.
covered to a considerable extent the first three thematic areas of feminist engagement. Thus, in
this chapter, only the last two areas of feminist involvement with RJ will be the focus of more
detailed examination, i.e., the suitability of RJ to cope with domestic violence; and the politics of
necessary to give a general outline of feminist theorizing in criminology and its implications for
the study of restorative justice. Daly, citing Gelsthorpe, traces out the central features of
recognition that social reality is a process and that research methods need to
reflect this;
257
See
Daly
&
Stubbs,
Feminist
Engagement,
note
5.
(This
article
was
later
expanded
and
reviewed
as
a
chapter
of
the
book
Handbook
of
Restorative
Justice
under
the
title
Feminist
Theory,
Feminist
and
anti-racist
politics
and
Restorative
Justice
).
See
note
9.
258
The
remainder
areas
of
feminist
engagement
with
RJ
were
examined
in
the
first
chapter
under
similar
headings.
See
pages
54
and
104.
118
a political commitment to social change;
Daly also observes that there are undeniable similarities between feminist
criminology and critical criminological avenues of research. She writes, There is a good deal of
affinity and crossover between feminist perspectives in criminology and those termed critical,
theories used, and preferred epistemologies and methodologies.260 Indeed, by comparing the
characteristics attributed to critical criminology with feminist criminology, the close proximity
between each other is readily noticeable. Below, for contrast, is the list compiled by Julie Stubbs
rejection of correctionalism;
political engagement, allegiances with social movements and turning cases into
issues;
As one can easily notice by going through the features listed above by Daly and
Stubbs, respectively; feminist criminology and critical criminological research have several
points of overlap. In fact, it is fair to recognize that they are coalesced into a single body of
scholarship in which critical criminological research can be described as the genus and feminist
criminology as the species. However, feminist criminology represents much more than just a
small subcategory of the critical criminology taxonomy. The significant body of work of
feminist criminology has provided key theoretical resources for understanding how gender plays
a role in RJ practices and how power relations among all the RJs stakeholders are significant
within the context of domestic violence. In other terms, feminist criminologists focusing on
gender and power relations have led to significant contributions in the developing of normative,
empirical and epistemological accounts of restorative justice. These contributions will become
gradually more intelligible to the reader when interpreted in the light of feminist theories, which
will be addressed in the following subsections. At the moment, suffice to say that without the
fore structure of feminist criminology, it would be very difficult to disentangle the complexities
of the relationship between restorative justice and gender violence. But the close proximity
between feminist criminology and critical criminology also raises some questions. Are there any
261
See
Julie
Stubbs,
Critical
Criminological
Research
(2008)
8:19
Legal
Studies
Research
Paper
University
of
Sidney
at
3.
120
differences between critical criminology and feminist criminology? What are the implications of
reflected its various critical and political characteristics sketched above. As Daly notes, both
approaches have the shared enterprise of transgressing and transforming the field of crime
and justice by promoting social justice and human rights.262 Notwithstanding this transformative
common nature and shared goals, there has been some reflection of differences between critical
criminology and feminist criminology. Stubbs, for example, points out that the presence of
general veins of critical criminology research. She notes: Early critical criminology showed
little interest in feminist concerns (Carrington 2002: 123, Naffine 1997).263 Feminist
criminology, therefore, distinguishes itself from general critical criminology research in its goal
of providing a normative analysis of gender and power in several areas of criminal justice.
towards the status quo and keep giving attention to power inequalities and its consequences to
offending, victimization and criminalization, feminist criminology has its own agenda and
peculiarities. Motivated by the historic feminist emancipatory political project of eliminating the
criminologists are also concerned with how criminal justice institutions and practices affect the
lives of women and how they are implicated in those systems. It is, therefore, a discipline that
conveys a distinctive epistemological and methodological critical attitude toward issues of crime
and justice and their interactions with women. It urges the reform of gender inequities in
262
See
note
257
at
9.
263
See
note
260
at
7.
121
criminal justice institutions and calls attention to neglected questions with the aim of improving
womens conditions in all areas of their exposure to the criminal justice system, whether in
critical and purposeful theory --- critical either of the criminal justice system itself or of the
structures of power embedded in it --- and purposeful for calling for change and womens
emancipation on the basis of those criticisms. There are, however, various established and
sometimes conflicting theoretical feminist discourses that differ in significant ways, regarding
thinking.264 This means that feminist criminology theories evolved directly from related strands
of feminist thinking, i.e., behind a particular feminist criminological perspective there is always
a larger feminist theoretical framework that has been its formative principle and is closely
associated with it. Roughly put, any feminist criminological perspective should somehow match
a school of feminist critical analysis, which is not necessarily concerned with crime issues.
Accordingly, the feminist scholarly treatment of RJ does not differ significantly from generic
feminist approaches (not necessarily concerned with crime) and criminological feminist theories
(concerned with crime). In fact, feminist scholars usually merge both lines of thought to form a
single line of argumentation that can be used to analyze the pros and cons of restorative justice.
As a consequence, the theoretical context that provides the impetus for each type
of feminist inquiry is crucial for the understanding of feminist appraisals on restorative justice. It
is not by chance that most of the scholars addressing feminist criminology and RJ before
advancing to specific issues about crime, spend some time and space in their works to
264
See,
e.g.,
Burgess-Proctor,
Intersections
of
Race,
Class,
Gender,
note
27
at
29.
122
contextualize their arguments within one or more of the varieties of feminist thinking. In the next
subsection, I will do the same by sketching out the most relevant feminist schools of thought,
specifically, intersectionality theory and its significance to restorative justice. The primary aim is
to provide a general context of feminist theoretical perspectives on law, gender and alternative
justice practices. To this end, I will use previous schematizations originally devised by feminist
There are several angles of feminist theorizing that paved the way for future
discussions within the context of restorative justice. This segment briefly lays out the various
schools of thought and areas of concern and interest that have occupied feminist thinking for the
past forty years. As Daly points out, they can provide a story of the emergence and
the wider field of feminist and other social theories.265 But the usual caveat applies; the
categories set below will be greatly simplified for the sake of brevity and important theoretical
differences among and within each strand may well be downplayed, although the gist of each
schools intellectual contribution to feminist legal thinking will be preserved. Besides that, some
schools are more or less relevant to the study of RJ depending on the emphasis given to crime
and justice matters in the form of alternative forms of adjudication. Anyway, wherever possible,
I seek to establish connections between each school of feminist thinking and restorative justice
It should also be noted that the following categorical feminist approaches are non-
exclusive and inevitably overlap. This means that they can and do coexist in close proximity
265
See
Daly,
Gen
Y
in
Mind,
note
258
at
10.
123
with one another. However, there are times when the theoretical differences between feminist
approaches may rise above common ground and shared interests to lead to diametrically opposite
outcomes. As we shall see, this is especially salient when a specific feminist theory is the
corollary of internal critiques of a preceding school of thought like, e.g., intersectionality theory
and previous strands of feminist theorizing. Finally, I will conclude this subsection by
identifying in more detail the practical applications of feminist intersectionality analysis in the
critical examination of the RJ movement. This will serve as a brief introduction to the next
chapter, where I provide a deeper and more satisfying account of the usefulness of that line of
The various feminist schools of thought traditionally arise from a more or less
approaches with minor variations concerning taxonomy and terminology. To categorize the
and predictability into a field that is well known for its diversity and at times overlapping
stances. In addition, each feminist research tradition may have different implications for
gender/power inequities and womens interaction with crime and justice. I will follow and adopt
the categorizations laid down by the feminist scholars cited earlier and frequently quoted within
the RJ field. Nevertheless, I will conflate their findings into a single catalogue of feminist
five major perspectives: liberal feminism; radical feminism; Marxist feminism; socialist
feminism, and postmodern feminist. In addition, these perspectives are supplemented by other
more recent trends in the feminist thinking such as Black feminism; critical race feminism;
124
lesbian feminism and multicultural feminism.266 Hopkins and Koss employ a slightly different
classification that is comprised of liberal, cultural, radical, Marxist and/or socialist, postmodern
(or poststructuralist), and multiracial feminism.267 Daly and Stubbs do not differentiate
themselves from others in their classification of the feminist schools of thought.268 According to
them, feminist perspectives on law and justice are usually divided into categories such as liberal
feminism, cultural feminism, radical feminism, critical race feminism, and postmodern or
feminist perspectives about how gender and power shapes crime and justice, we can eventually
generate our own selection of ways in which RJ can be influenced by feminist perspectives or, in
contrast, can influence them. Finally, I will consider only the classifications that are relevant to
I begin by describing the schools that have been labeled essentialist in order to
later introduce the concept of anti-essentialist schools of feminism. The relevance of this
some way to explain restorative dynamics. However, one important limitation on this
categorization of essentialist schools should be noted. There is a pejorative sense to the term
essentialist, so some of the feminist thinkers listed here would probably reject this label.
Anyway, the influences of essentialist stances on their feminist theoretical framework should not
The first category of feminist inquiry is concerned with equality, autonomy and
agency of women. As Dally and Stubbs observe, liberal feminism has been in place for over
three centuries as women have sought to secure equality of legal and citizenship rights with
men.269 Proponents of liberal feminism claim that womens lack of autonomy and self-
determination is due to the patriarchal nature of inherited traditions and institutions, and that the
women's movement should work to identify and remedy them.270 Classical liberal feminists are
at odds with legal frameworks that explicitly treat women differently than men, but still rely on
the state as the main agent of gender and social justice. In this sense, they recommend laws that
seek to change social policies or practices that put women in positions of lesser or secondary
importance. According to Hopkins et al., liberal feminists are also referred to as "sameness" or
"rule equality" feminists.271 They hold that "Sameness feminists" focus on the similarities
between individual men and individual women leads them to advocate "gender-neutral
categories that do not rely on gender stereotypes to differentiate between men and women."272
social, legal, moral) equality between women and men. Liberal feminists hold, therefore, that
women are essentially similar to men and for this reason the sexes should be treated equally (i.e.,
Within the crime and justice field, liberal feminists pursue law reforms and
practices that treat domestic violence cases in the same way that laws and practices treat stranger
269
Ibid.
270
See,
e.g,
Susan
Moller
Okin,
Women
in
Western
Political
Thought
(Princeton,
N.J.:
Princeton
University
Press,
1979).
271
See
C.
Quince
Hopkins,
Mary
P.
Koss
and
Karen
J.
Bachar,
"Applying
Restorative
Justice
to
Ongoing
Intimate
Violence:
Problems
and
Possibilities"
(2004)
23
St.
Louis
University
Public
Law
Review
289-312
at
297.
272
Ibid.
126
violence against men. Historically, for instance, liberal feminists were responsible for
deconceptualizing domestic violence and sexual assault cases as private or family matters
through their relentless worldwide political campaigns to criminalize and publically condemn
such practices as human rights violations. In addition, they developed actions at the theoretical
and empirical levels to protect the autonomy and agency of victimized women.273 As a
consequence, liberal feminists usually object to mandatory arrest and prosecution policies that
justice experiences due to their preconceived notions about autonomy and equality between
women and men. As asserted earlier, the feminist liberal theoretical discourse seeks to advance
the idea of equality between the genders and autonomy of women. In that sense, an issue that
proponents may raise is whether advocating hybrid justice constructs like RJ experiences in
Indigenous settings (sentencing circles) could also mean supporting the patriarchal schemes of
traditional societies that give women subservient status in contrast to that of men. As Susan
Moller Okin --- a leading exponent of the liberal feminism --- contends, feminists must object to
multicultural experiences like that since they bestow legitimacy upon patriarchal and traditional
cultures which results in womens repression, exploitation and discrimination.275 She suggests
273
Sometimes
this
stance
results
in
controversial
propositions
like,
for
example,
the
defence
of
using
firearms
for
protection
against
rape
or
domestic
violence.
See
infra
note.
See
especially
Richard
W.
Stevens,
Hugo
Teufel
III,
&
Matthew
Y.
Biscan,
Disarming
Women:
Comparing
Gun
Control
to
Self-Defense.
in
Wendy
McElroy,
ed.,
Liberty
for
Women:
Freedom
and
Feminism
in
the
Twenty-First
Century
(Chicago:
Ivan
R.
D.,2002)
238-263.
274
See,
e.g.,
Amy
R.
Baehr,
"Liberal
Feminism"
The
Stanford
Encyclopedia
of
Philosophy
(Fall
2008
Edition),
Edward
N.
Zalta
(ed).,
online:
(2010)
<http://plato.stanford.edu/archives/fall2008/entries/feminism-liberal/>
retrieved
on
April
2010.
(For
a
comprehensive
examination
of
the
liberal
feminism
theoretical
discourse
including
its
several
varieties:
a)
Classical
Liberal
feminism;
b)
Equity
feminists;
c)
Cultural
libertarian
feminists,
and
d)
Egalitarian
liberal
feminists).
275
See
Susan
Moller
Okin,
Is
Multiculturalism
Bad
for
Women?
(Princeton:
Princeton
University
Press,
1999).
See
generally
Monique
Deveaux,
Gender
and
Justice
in
Multicultural
Liberal
States
(Oxford:
Oxford
University
Press,
2006).
See
also
Roni
Reingold
&
Lea
Baratz,
Feminism
and
Multiculturalism:
Two
Common
Foundations
for
a
Vision
and
a
Practice
of
Transformative
Social
Activities
and
Education
in
Israel
(2009)
10:4
Journal
of
International
Womens
Studies
53.
127
that in multicultural experiences with alternative justice practices the proponents and traditional
leadership may exaggerate the level of communal consensus and the level of acceptance and
knowledge among participants, in order to present a united front to larger society. As a result,
multicultural polices such as sentencing circles could end up favoring some members of minority
groups over others; and more specifically putting aside the rights of women. In sum, liberal
feminists claim that there is the danger that women's autonomy or equality with men could be
Indeed, in several areas liberal feminists represent the instances or issues that
most intensely challenge RJ experiences in the context of domestic violence regardless of race or
culture. Their general presuppositions and principles about autonomy and equality go against RJ
in the sense that there is a fear --- in some cases justifiable --- that those offenders who inflict
gendered harms would not receive sanctions from such alternative justice schemes, just as those
who engage in gendered violent crime are sanctioned by the conventional justice system. In
addition, they claim that the power asymmetries in dialogue-based processes like RJ experiences
may result in detrimental consequences for women. These claims require more analysis, which
will be provided in the subsection of this chapter devoted to domestic violence and restorative
justice.
Hopkins and Koss, cultural feminists are also referred to as substantive equality or difference
128
feminists.276 As Burgess-Proctor explains, cultural feminists believe that women have
distinctive characteristics (both biological and socially conceived) that require difference or
theory that addresses the ways in which the legal system deals with differences between women
and men. Just recognizing those differences it would be possible to overcome gender-based
Hopkins and Koss observe --- disagree that alteration of formal rules will result in actual
equality for women; equal treatment, they argue, disadvantages women because the baselines
favor men.278 In fact, they do not believe in neutral-gender utterances of law and justice that
affect women and men, indifferently. Following this line of reasoning, they also do not believe
that the state is capable of advancing womens interests since it is already contaminated by
masculine and patriarchal traits like, for example, hierarchical structures and impersonal
institutions.
constructed as a distinct feminine moral development in the criminal justice field. According to
Daly, for example, the main contribution of cultural feminists to RJ is related to its foundational
theoretical framework. As she has points out, Carol Gilligans concept of the different voice of
women was influential in the articulation of a theory of justice guided by a feminine ethic of
care (i.e., relational; intimate; narrative; and collaborative) where gender differences upon
276
See
note
255
at
699.
(The
term
substantive
equality
has
other
meanings
in
Canadian
constitutional
equality
law.
However,
the
term
as
applied
by
Hopkins
and
Koss,
has
virtually
nothing
to
do
with
it).
277
Supra
note
265.
278
Supra
note
275.
129
moral thinking resulted in direct links between RJ and feminine justice.279 As Hopkins and Koss
explain:
For cultural feminists informed and persuaded by Carol Gilligans work on womens
ethic of care, collaboration and interpersonal relationships are particularly valued by
women, whereas hierarchy is particularly embraced by men (Gilligan,1982; West, 1988).
Many (but not all) cultural feminists today, however, claim not that women are, in fact,
inherently different from men but that certain traits and values are perceived as feminine
or female or as masculine or male. These masculine or male traits, the argument
continues, are embraced by legal and other institutions, while feminine or female traits
are devalued, marginalized, or even excluded by those institutions (West, 1988). In this
sense, for cultural feminists these institutions are masculinist in practice to the extent that
the rules under which they function exclude womens unique voices and lived
experiences. 280
masculine justice. In contrast to the traditional justice system, restorative justice experiences --
- much more personal, vocal and collaborative than conventional justice schemes --- are
generally well received by cultural feminists for being considered more feminine in
incorporating to a greater extent all the shades of meaning of a survivors full experience. For all
these reasons, cultural feminists, by and large, see relational and dialogue-driven alternative
dominance feminism. Roughly speaking, radical feminism implies that the entire legal system
dominant and women as naturally passive). As Hopkins and Koss explain, Traditional radical
feminists argue that religious, economic, political, and judicial institutions undergird as well as
create mens dominance over women, emphasizing the centrality of patriarchy and masculine
control of womens labor and sexuality (Curran & Renzetti, 2001; Flavin, 2004; MacKinnon,
For this reason, gender difference is itself a characteristic of male domination and
the natural implication is that masculinity is constructed to support the exertion of power and
control over women. Accordingly, radical feminism rejects cultural feminism claims of a
different female voice, emphasizing instead that a womans specificity is nothing more than a
function of male domination. Unlike liberal feminists, who view the state as a reliable tool of
social justice that only needs some formal adjustments to be adequate, radical feminists tend to
understand the state and its justice institutions as mirroring societal inequalities and power
asymmetries which also results in gender difference. As a result, dominance feminists usually
view the state with distrust and consider it compromised by pernicious gender relations of
dominance/subordination.
MacKinnon for whom female power is nothing more than a contradiction in terms, socially
speaking282. As Daly and Stubbs explain, In MacKinnons view, we cannot know what
womens values or voice are until there is a transformation of gender power relations.283
MacKinnon vehemently asserts, Take your foot off our necks, then you will hear in what
281
Supra
note
270
at
700.
282
See
Catharine
A.
MacKinnon,
Feminism
Unmodified:
Discourses
on
Life
and
Law
(Cambridge,
MA:
Harvard
University
Press,
1987)
at
53.
See
also
Catharine
A.
MacKinnon,
Difference
and
dominance:
On
sex
discrimination
in
K.
T.
Bartlett
&
R.Kennedy,
eds.,
Feminist
legal
theory
(Boulder,
CO:
Westview,
1991)
81-94.
283
See
note
9
at
150.
131
tongue women speak284 According to Burgess-Proctor: within criminology, radical feminists
often focus on manifestations of patriarchy in crimes against women, such as domestic violence,
rape, sexual harassment, and pornography, and recognize that womens offending often is
feminists are predisposed to believe that it provides a less structurally hierarchical framework
for resolution of gendered harms than traditional criminal justice, thus mapping onto the central
that the centrality of issues relating to power asymmetries in radical feminist models of inquiry
and the reality of power differentials and control schemes in domestic violence cases can expose
how dominance feminists may be suspicious of alternative justice schemes like restorative
justice. Indeed, stances based on radical feminism make their proponents essentially inclined to
be distrustful about RJs promises of equality, visibility and vociferousness to victims simply
because these promises usually ignore previous patterns of male power and privilege what is per
violence victims. In other terms, because social relations, especially in some traditional
communities, are shaped by male power and privilege, radical feminists can inscribe RJ as one
more example of gender-neutral justice models that mean negative consequences for women
because of their potential to neglect issues of power and privilege between the genders.
284
Supra
note
280
at
45.
285
Supra
note
265
at
31-34.
286
Supra
note
255
at
716.
132
iii. Anti-essentialist
schools
of
feminism
The feminist theoretical approaches that were featured in the established feminist
modes of inquiry of the 1960s and 1970s (i.e, sameness, difference and dominance feminist
theories) were seriously challenged from the mid-1970s onwards by critiques informed by new
streams of feminist thinking drawing from a variety of Marxist, anti-racist, postmodern and post-
structural social theories. In this period, changing political and ideological climates and internal
from one axis of inequality and power287 based uniquely in sex and gender differences --- as
Daly and Stubbs have put it --- to a more nuanced analysis. Consequently, others categories (or
sites) of inequality such as race, ethnicity, religion and class coul play a more important role in
social conditions.
In that context, a new tension has emerged across the epistemological and
ideological perspectives guiding the feminist movement as a whole. On one side we see
domination, inequality and subordination, i.e., based mainly in sex/gender related issues; while
on the other side we see an increasingly influent anti-essentialist feminist movement, determined
to reject the notion that gender/sex issues in feminist scholarship can or should be considered in
isolation from other topics important to women such as race, culture or socioeconomic class.288
287
See
note
9
at
150.
288
In
feminist
theory,
anti-essentialism
is
the
view
that
there
is
no
immanent
and
universal
essence
or
identity
of
woman
and,
even
if
so,
the
category
of
woman
could
not
be
used
to
represent
all
women.
Therefore
universal
claims
about
the
category
of
woman
are
questionable
by
nature
and
effectively
normalise
and
privilege
specific
forms
of
femininity,
e.g.,
white-heterosexual-middle-class
women.
See
Alison
Stone,
Essentialism
and
Anti-
Essentialism
in
Feminist
Philosophy
(2004)
1
Journal
of
Moral
Philosophy
135153.
(For
a
definition
of
133
The latter perspective spawned a bewildering array of complementary, but not entirely
equivalent feminist theories such as Marxist and Socialist feminism; critical race feminism;
addressed in this paper only in passing), etc. These anti-essentialist perspectives are instrumental
in developing the concept upon which the analytic model of intersectionality theory is built and
counterparts --- have understood womens marginal social condition as a result of economic
disparities and class struggle. According to Burgess-Proctor, Marxist feminism holds that the
capitalist mode of production shapes class and gender relations that ultimately disadvantage
women because women occupy the working class instead of the ruling class.289 This feminist
mode of inquiry also contends that revolutionary actions need to be established in order to
overcome womens oppression, namely, the overthrow of the existing economic order and class
structure, as Hopkins and Koss have noted.290 In sum, Marxist feminism is committed to the idea
that the root of womens oppression is their secondary class status within capitalist societies and
It should be noted that the centrality of the relationship between sex/gender and
important to Marxist feminists. As they believe that womens oppression only exists because
essentialism
and
anti-essentialism
in
feminist
theory).
See
also
note
52
(For
a
brief
definition
of
essentialism
in
feminist
theory).
289
See
note
27
at
29.
290
Supra
note
255
at
701.
134
economic and class oppression also exist, sex/gender and other attributes of mainstream feminist
critical analysis are demoted as merely ancillary categories of inequality. In this sense, Marxist
feminism, during the 1970s and early 1980s, inaugurated a whole new anti-essentialist tendency
in feminist modes of inquiry where sex/gender and within power relations are not seen as the
Unlike the revolutionary stances of Marxist feminism that seek to reject the
prevailing order altogether, --- and in the process reduce the importance of sex/gender in power
relations --- socialist feminists advocate a more nuanced understanding that encompasses a wider
range of inequality categories in which both class and sex/gender relations can co-exist as two
sides of the same coin. According to Burgess-Proctor, socialist feminism combines radical
and Marxist perspectives to conclude that womens oppression results from concomitant sex-
and class-based inequalities.291 While class struggle and economic disparity are the soul of
Marxist feminism, socialist feminists are not tied only to such inequality markers, given as they
are to placing some importance on the harm that may occur to women at the hands of sexism and
patriarchy alongside theories of class. As Burgess-Proctor puts it, In other words, class and
gender work in tandem to structure society, and socialist feminists call for an examination of the
ways in which gender relations are shaped by class and vice versa.292
Drawing from the epistemic stances and style analysis of dialectic materialism,
Marxist feminism and socialist feminism offer a view that violence against women is mainly the
result of unequal capitalist societies. Therefore, domestic violence is a product of the exploitative
class relations inherent in capitalism alongside power imbalances caused by male domination (as
291
See
note
27
at
29.
292
Ibid.
See,
e.g.,
Batya
Weinbaum,
The
Curious
Courtship
of
Women's
liberations
and
Socialism
(Boston:
South
End
Press,
1978)
(For
a
more
detailed
account
of
Socialism
Feminism).
135
argued specifically by Socialist-feminists).293 Furthermore, political identification with RJs
communitarianism, informality and claims of social change seems to indicate that Marxist-
materialism is a matter yet to be clarified, since, more recently neo-Marxist theorists have argued
that RJ, peace-making criminology and other alternative justice forms do not represent
observes, Neo-marxists contend that informalism enabled the state to extend and intensify its
control over individual lives. The welfare state could thereby deal with protracted legitimacy and
fiscal crises of the 19070s by turning over 'minor' cases to volunteers in the community;
however, in practice, it remained firmly in control of the finances, authorisation and even case
loads for given programs.295 In the words of Cunneen: What the Neo-marxist critique demands
is that restorative justice respond seriously to these broader social and economic issues and that
it be able to deal constructively with the various 'hidden injuries' of class, including alienation
293
See
Daniel
J.
Curran
&
Claire
M.
Renzetti,
Theories
of
crime
(Needham
Heights,
MA:
Allyn
&
Bacon,
2001)
at
223.
Jane
C.
Ollenburger
&
Helen
A.
Moore,
A
sociology
of
women:
The
intersection
of
patriarchy
capitalism,
and
colonization
(Upper
Saddle
River,
NJ:
Prentice
Hall,
1998).
(Arguing
that
feminist
theory
incorporates
three
separate
systems
of
opression:
patriarchy,
capitalism
and
colonization
and
that
mainstream
feminism
failed
to
address
the
diversity
of
the
womans
condition).
See
especially
Heidi
Hartmann,
"The
Unhappy
Marriage
of
Marxism
and
Feminism"
in
Lydia
Sargent,
ed.,
Women
and
Revolution
(Boston:
South
End
Press,
1981).
294
But
see
note
203.
295
See
note
213
at
7-8.
296
See
note
209
at
183.
136
Postmodern
and
poststructuralist
feminism
structural social theories.297 According to Hopkins and Koss, postmodern and poststructuralist
feminists draw on the notion of social constructionism and argue that legal discourse itself
creates the categories of women that law then proceeds to regulate.298 Daly and Stubbs
relations shifted from conceptualizing the dominance of one group (such men) over another
(such women) to analyzing the legal and social discourses which construct sex/gender
relations.299 In turn, Amanda Burgess-Proctor notes that postmodern feminism departs from
research is to challenge fixed inequality categories and identities in favor of the existence of
deconstructionism and insights derived from studies of systems of thought. Postmodern feminists
297
See
Ewa
P.
Ziarek,
An
ethics
of
dissensus:
postmodernity,
feminism,
and
the
politics
of
radical
democracy
(Stanford,
CA:
Stanford
University
Press,
2001).
See
also
Seyla
Benhabib,
Situating
the
self
:
gender,
community,
and
postmodernism
in
contemporary
ethics
(New
York:
Routledge,
1992).
(For
a
general
perspective
on
postmodern
feminism).
298
See
note
255
at
702.
299
See
note
9
at
151.
300
See
note
27
at
29.
301
See
Judith
Butler,
Gender
Trouble
(New
York:
Routledge,
1991).
(In
Gender
Trouble,
Butler
pioneered
the
concept
of
feminist
anti-essentialism
drawing
on
social
constructionism).
See
also
Nancy
Elizabeth
Dowd
&
Michelle
S.
Jacobs,
eds.,
Feminist
Legal
Theory:
An
Anti-Essentialist
Reader
(NY:New
York
University
Press,
2003).
(Collection
of
articles
addressing
anti-essentialist
feminist
perspectives).
137
constantly stress the need for social action to rectify the injustice and inequality in womens
lives, but shift the emphasis of analysis from binary constructs like gender and power (i.e., anti-
essentialism) to social discourses (i.e., the linguistic approach) in which they are devised and
employed. As Hopkins and Koss explain, In part, postmodern feminists seek to eradicate
inequality by undermining the existing binary construct of male and female that has the effect of
what society understands as available gender roles.302 Consequently, there is a strong emphasis
on critical insights and in exposing monolithically constructed systems of thought (as applied,
e.g., by Michel Foucault in his account of disciplinary mechanisms in prisons)303. In the next
paragraph, I briefly demonstrate how postmodern feminism can be used to address RJ and
Foucauldian disciplinary mechanisms and has concluded that some restorative interventions have
the potential to function as a new discipline of silence, as she calls it. According to her, RJ
interventions may function as disciplinary mechanisms that induce self-effacing sacrifice and
nutshell, she contends that the incorporation of collectivist rhetoric into the RJ movement means
that victimized women ought to act as if conceding their individual needs for safety, vocalization
and autonomy and yield to the most pressing political demands of the community. As a result,
302
Supra
note
296.
303
See
note
240.
(Giving
a
brief
account
of
the
postmodern
critique
of
RJ)
304
See
especially
Angela
Cameron,
"Sentencing
circles
in
cases
of
intimate
violence:
discipline,
space
and
law"
(Paper
presented
to
the
International
Round
Table
for
the
Semiotics
of
Law,
16
April
2005)
[Unpublished].
(Arguing
that
women
victims
of
violence
in
judicially
convened
sentencing
circles
are
being
subjected
to
a
type
of
infra-law
or
disciplinary
mechanism
while
offenders
themselves
are
subjected
to
a
lenient
form
of
juridical
discipline).
See
also
Angela
Cameron
&
Emma
Cunliffe,
Writing
the
circle,
note
8.
138
experiences mistakenly believing that they are serving the best interests of their communities
while in truth they are making concessions to remedial, non-punitive justice actions that often
benefit only offenders. In other words, some models of RJ can represent a new accomodationist
strategy of women when dealing with patriarchal domination. Cameron illustrates this point, by
using the example of Indigenous communities that adopted justice experiences analogous to RJ
like sentencing circles. The rationale is simple. Since in such practices women are assigned the
task of restoring the offender (and the whole community) and are also responsible for the
prevention of further harm to themselves, they end up contributing to their own oppression by
reproducing and perpetuating deeply enrooted gender hierarchies that keep them in an
obsequious silence.305
for a critique of RJ, Hopkins and Koss argue that feminist postmodernism provides a
survivors and responsible parties should be viewed as something different from predetermined
caricatures of victim and offender.306 This means to begin to break down the idea of a fixed,
single role attributed to victims and offenders, which often polarizes both into an adversarial
position. So, the idea behind a postmodern approach is to deconstruct such formal categories,
which is exactly what RJ has done with its stances on new identities of healing and
transformation for victims and offenders. After all, RJ in theory and practice demands
cooperation and empathetic dialogue between all the stakeholders in order to achieve its
305
Supra.
306
Supra
note
297.
139
iv. Incorporating
intersectionality
theory
and epistemic positions found in intersectionality theory are invaluable as a tool for interpreting
theoretical propositions and practical angles found in RJ rhetoric and practice.307 Intersectional
feminism uses aspects of different feminist theories to reflect many interactions among diverse
analytical categories such as gender, race, class, and sexual orientation. However, no single
oppression such as male violence against women. By revealing multiple, intersecting inequalities
exclusionary tendencies within the feminist movement itself. Notably, those tendencies that do
not take into account the heterogeneous experiences of women of color or lesbian women. In the
can see the ways in which restorative and Indigenous justice improve upon established criminal
justice, and where further improvements can be made308. Notwithstanding, I contend that some
intersectional approaches on the interplay between claims of gender and other loci of inequality
such as race and post-colonial justice in RJ practices are beginning to take potentially harmful
offenders behavior and disregarding victims interests for security, empowerment and
expression, whilst not giving privileges to women-centered perspectives and concerns. As Daly
has noted:
On the one hand, Indigenous women may, more than non-Indigenous women, see the
value of alternative justice practices, especially when these can translate into more
307
See
subsections
five
and
six
in
the
introduction
for
a
recapitulation
of
the
main
points
including
definition
and
standards
of
operation
of
intersectionality
analysis.
308
See
note
16,
Daly,
Seeking
Justice,
at
27.
140
meaningful ways of addressing crime and community disorder. At the same time, these
alternatives may appear to protect their men from deserved penalties or from removal
from the community. Their men (especially the more powerful leaders), in turn, may form
alliances with non-Indigenous judicial officers and lawyers, who align themselves with
the positional interests of offenders, although this is couched in terms of community
309
interests and culture
practices. Initially, I put forward the opinion that the anti-essentialist epistemic nature of
intersectional analysis of restorative justice. This means an epistemic attitude that makes
intersectionality analysis almost unable to critically address political conflicts and competing
pressures that emerge in sites of inequality found in some RJ models. In other words, I identify a
weakened version of intersectionality theory that lacks critical assessment of RJs standpoint on
gendered-violence. I then sketch a complementary line of reasoning that relates the existence of
other political forces operating in some RJ experiences that ultimately lead to shape the contours
of intersectional procedural values to fit their own needs, not womens emancipatory aims. In
basic terms these forces include: a) RJs self-advocacy stances and b) the rise of political
introduce the feminist schools of thinking that are pertinent to intersectionality theory. Indeed,
there are several clear and explicit applications of feminist theory in the context of
feminist theoretical disciplines such as critical race feminism, women of color feminism, post-
colonial feminism and Lesbian feminism.310 In fact, the identification of intersectionality theory
with such feminist modes of inquiry has gone so far that these schools of thought and their
perspectives on issues of power and dominance have become irremediably conflated with
intersectionality analysis methodology and epistemology. As a matter of fact, some scholars use
those disciplines almost as synonyms of intersectionality theory, which causes some confusion in
less attentive readers. But the relevant fact is that all those feminist venues of research basically
share the same epistemic position of intersectional analysis, i.e., they have abandoned the
primacy of sex/gender as an analytical standard that can claim overarching epistemic superiority
over others loci of inequality like race, ethnicity, sexual orientation and social class. Such
feminist models of investigation claim that there are important lessons to be learned from taking
into consideration the experiences of marginalized groups, i.e., not only a cohort of white,
middle class, English-speaking women, but also men and women in postcolonial societies,
All those feminist schools, therefore, cluster around more or less similar
intersectional sentiments that provided the impetus for feminist scholars and activists in
questioning the very essence of the category woman in several areas of feminist exploration. As
310
Actually,
each
one
of
these
strands
of
feminism
can
be
connected
to
marginalized
women's
standpoints
like,
e.g.,
black,
Latina,
lesbian,
postcolonial,
etc.
See
generally
Sandra
G.
Harding,
Is
Science
Multicultural?:
Postcolonialisms,
Feminisms,
and
Epistemologies
(Bloomington:
Indiana
University,
1998).
See
also
Richard
Delgado
&
Jean
Stefancic,
Critical
Race
Theory:
An
Introduction
(New
York:
New
York
University
Press,
2001)
(For
a
comprehensive
account
of
critical
race
theory.
The
author
also
describes
in
two
chapters
of
this
volume
the
significance
of
intersectionality
and
anti-essentialism
for
the
conceptualization
of
critical
race
theory).
See
especially
Maxine
Baca
Zinn
&
Bonnie
Thorton
Dill,
Theorizing
difference
from
multiracial
feminism
Feminist
Studies
22:2
321-331
(Describing
the
concept
of
multiracial
feminism.
(The
authors
argue
that
the
term
multicultural
feminism,
also
used
to
describe
multiracial
feminism,
does
not
place
sufficient
emphasis
on
race
as
a
power
system
that
interact
and
shape
gender).
142
Alcoff and Potter have asserted, feminist epistemic positions should no longer be taken as
involving a commitment to gender as the primary axis of oppression, in any sense of primary
or positing that gender is a theoretical variable separable from other axes of oppression and
susceptible to a unique analysis.311 Thus, those perspectives reflect a growing awareness of the
impact of culture and race inequalities within the larger sociocultural context. For reasons of
simplicity, however, I will condense all those feminist schools aforementioned into just one
is not arbitrary. It is used to describe in one single phrase several lines of feminist research that
have informed intersectionality theory. I have chosen the term multiracial feminism because it
best represents all other venues of feminist research without excluding any type of particular
racial, cultural or sexual orientation perspective. As Hopkins and Koss note, multiracial
feminism is an overarching concept first described by Zinn and Dill (1996) as embracing
several strands of feminist theory: womanism, women of color feminism, critical race feminism,
and multicultural feminism (cf. Sokoloff et al., 2004, referring to this group of scholars as third-
wave feminists).312 Also citing Baca Zinn and Thornton, Burgess-Proctor observed that,
multicultural feminism, the term multiracial feminism is preferred because it emphasizes race
as a power system that interacts with other structured inequalities to shape genders (Baca
Zinn&Thornton Dill, 1996, p. 324).313 In sum, the feminist mode of inquiry termed multiracial
feminism (or multicultural feminism) refers to all the forms of oppression being selectively
engaged (and, thus, prioritized) by several marginaled groups through intersectionality analysis.
311
See
Linda
Alcoff
&
Elizabeth
Potter,
Feminist
Epistemologies
(New
York:
Routledge,
1993)
at
3-4.
312
Supra
note
255
at
702-703.
See
especially
note
308,
Zinn
&
Dill,
Theorizing
difference,
321-331.
313
See
note
27
at
35.
Brackets
included.
143
As Burgess-Proctor points out, In many ways, the development of this intersectional approach
Indeed, since multiracial feminism was originally described there have been a
couple of developments in the same context. Perhaps the most significant is the integration of
Lesbian feminism and Queer theory into intersectional feminist investigation. Such groups, like
several other marginal groups in the past, sought both acknowledgement of their respective
unique identity and visibility in feminist analysis to present their own claims of social justice. In
criminology, for example, same-sex domestic violence was finally recognised as a relevant
The Queer movement has important theoretical implications because it puts into
and Dupont, the fact that both abuser and victim are women calls into question the primacy of
indicated above, Queer theorists and Lesbian feminists rely on anti-essentialist stances in order
to articulate their worldview and convey the message that the category woman is a fiction
and that feminist efforts must be directed toward dismantling this fiction317, as Alcoff has noted.
Nonetheless, for the purposes of this work the perspectives of Lesbian feminists and Queer
theorists to the understanding of RJ and domestic violence will not be addressed because there is
a lack of scholarly treatment to the theme that prevent discuss of it at length here.
314
Supra
note
27
at
37.
315
See
e.g.,
C.
M.
Renzetti,
Violence
in
lesbian
relationships:
A
preliminary
analysis
of
causal
factors.
Journal
of
Interpersonal
Violence
3
381-399.
316
See
Natalie
J.
Sokoloff
&
Ida
Dupont,Domestic
Violence
at
the
Intersections
of
Race,
Class,
and
Gender:
hallenges
and
Contributions
to
Understanding
Violence
Against
Marginalized
Women
in
Diverse
Communities
(2005)
Violence
Against
Women
11:1
38-64
at
43.
317
Linda
Alcoff,
Cultural
Feminism
versus
Post-Structuralism:
The
Identity
Crisis
in
Feminist
Theory
(1988) Signs
13:3
at
416
144
v. Connecting
multiracial
feminism,
restorative
justice
and
indigenous
justice
claims
This subsection seeks to address the connections that exist between multiracial
feminism (i.e., intersectionality analysis), Indigenous studies, and restorative justice. According
to Hopkins and Koss, along with reinterpreting the role of gender and race in feminist analysis,
studies to RJ experiences and in the process offering new ways to approach violence against
As we can see from the passage above, the multiracial (i.e., intersectional)
analysis of women in RJ settings is often conflated with coexistent political and theoretical
trends such as post-colonialism; Indigenous justice; human rights and anti-racist struggles. As
Daly puts it, There is growing interest in what is called intersectional race and gender politics,
which aim to negotiate differing Indigenous and feminist interests in seeking justice. () I use
the term in the latter sense to address the conflicting interests of victims and offenders, social
318
See
note
255
at
703.
See
also
note
291,
Ollenburger
&
Moore,
A
Sociology
of
Women.
See,
Razack,
note
322,
infra.
See
note
25,
Coker,
Transformative
Justice.
145
movement groups, and individuals and collectivities in responding to crime.319 Intersectionality
theory hence offered a new way to organize feminist theorizing on RJ, i.e., by integrating post-
colonial and Indigenous justice political issues into the debate about alternative justice remedial
practices developed to cope with violence against women. In so doing, intersectionality theory
provides a tool for understanding how new inequality categories emerge and are applied to
feminist theories were first and foremost about gender; and anti-racist theories were about
that took cultural and ethnic imperatives into account, intersectionality theory also transformed
the intellectual landscape by politicizing the discussions about the adherence of Indigenous
feminist thinking contributed to misidentify that alternative justice model, in the minds of many,
postcolonial processes of contestation, assertion and self-determination and also convey political
struggles that seek to redefine criminal justice relations with vulnerable groups, soon
intersectional feminists merged the two movements into the same struggle. However, some
versions of intersectional approaches are unable to recognize the dangers of such association
since pockets of patriarchy in Indigenous settings have been giving collective power
319
Kathleen
Daly
makes
use
of
the
phrase
Race
and
Gender
Politics
of
Justice
to
convey
her
own
view
on
multiracial
feminism
dealing
with
RJ
and
post-colonial
Indigenous
issues.
According
to
her,
with
the
emergence
of
intersectionality
theory
issues
like
colonialism,
culture,
and
race-ethnicity
entered
in
the
feminist
agenda,
however,
they
remained
at
odds
with
one
another
in
practice.
For
example,
within
the
context
of
RJ,
Indigenous
(or
racialiased
groups)
emphasise
offenders
interests
while
feminist
groups,
victims
interests.
See
note
16,
Kathleen
Daly,
Seeking
Justice,
at
8.
320
Ibid.
146
considerations precedence over objectives of individual gender development. In the following
paragraphs, I look more closely at the politicization of the use of RJ within Indigenous contexts.
In accordance with feminist intersectional views that coalesced RJ and gender and
race politics into the same theoretical framework, Indigenous leaders and RJ proponents
successfully aligned their political struggles and self-interest strategies. For example, RJ
proponents --- as already seen in chapter one --- adopted the language, processes and appearance
Indigenous people and state actors interested in promoting customary law practices, RJ
advocates structured restorative interventions so that they look like a version of Indigenous
justice practices. In turn, Indigenous leaders gave support to this RJ self-advocacy tactic and
corroborated the expectations or intuitions that many Indigenous people have had about RJ being
a manifestation of traditional Indigenous justice. The rationale for that was quite simple. They
used the RJ movement as a political platform to attempt to transform its emancipatory and
abolitionist stances into political rights for self-determination and social justice. As Cunneen has
pointed out, Indigenous demands for recognition of customary law and rights brought attention
to indigenous modes of social control, and indigenous leaders themselves would often articulate
their claims for indigenous law within the language of restorative justice.321 Nonetheless, there
are complicating factors in applying such alliances and connections that are being overlooked by
The first factor is that patriarchal relations can be embedded in many (perhaps all)
Indigenous settings and an awareness of this is a key to better understanding the limitations of
the intersectional approach. Just to illustrate, patriarchal relations of power and subordination
321
See
Chris
Cunneen,
Reviving
Restorative
Justice
traditions?
in
Gerry
Johnstone
and
Daniel
W.
Van
Ness,
eds.
Handbook
of
Restorative
Justice
(Mill
Street,
Uffculme:
Willan
Publishing,
2007)
113-131
at
115.
147
can be disguised as cultural discourses about gender disciplinary roles that can leave many
alternative but to accept their self-effacing role in RJ experiences.322 For example, most of the
leadership positions (e.g., Elders and circle keepers) may be held by a male elite and the
effective control of the whole restorative processes may be exercised exclusively by them, while
women exercise only secondary roles. Unfortunately, intersectionality theory does not warn us
against such Foulcadian disciplinary mechanisms of subordination and is prone, due to its anti-
cultural and political discourses for self-determination that are not always coincident with the
promotion of womens interests. For this reason, intersectionality analysis must also comprehend
and make some space for gender equality discussions although such an inequality category is not
There are other noticeable problems with the intersectional integration of non-
gender-specific issues into the discussion of RJ and domestic violence in Indigenous settings.
For example, by suggesting that the individual concerns of racialised women cannot be met
without first satisfying to some degree the collective concerns of postcolonial communities for
Indigenous women who are victims of intimate and sexual violence are not anymore at the center
of the worries and concerns of intersectional analysis. Such shift in focus results in the creation
of conflicting stances between analytical categories (e.g., culture and post-colonial political
322
See
note
303,
Cameron,
Discipline.
323
Especially,
because
claims
for
self-determination
and
self-government
convey
ideas
of
social
justice
like
the
desincarceration
of
Aboriginal
male
offenders.
See
Loretta
Kelly,
Using
Restorative
Justice
in
Aboriginal
Communities,
in
John
Braithwaite
&
Heather
Strang,
eds.,
Restorative
Justice
and
Family
Violence
(Cambridge,
UK
:Cambridge
University
Press,
2002)
at
219.
(Arguing
that
RJ
in
order
to
be
truly
culturally
appropriate
must
invoke
Indigenous
self-determination).
But
see
notes
39
and
43
and
accompanying
texts
for
a
critique
of
this
stance.
148
claims versus individual gender issues), and when an imbalance between them exists, the most
this means womens interests being put behind collective interests just because the latter are seen
category over the others, and in this process can end up provoking an undesirable
underestimation of gender equality as a strategic analytical category. Since we know that gender
relevance to the analysis of RJ within that context. After all, intersectionality theory never
established that gender equality concerns are unimportant or could be set aside in the discussion
of domestic violence, only that they were as important as other sites of inequality present in the
larger social context. Furthermore, as we shall see, a significant portion of mainstream feminist
literature on the ability of RJ to cope with violence against women also advances concerns for
redressing power asymmetries between victims and offenders. Those concerns are grounded
mainly in gender inequality concerns. Thus, there is no reason for gender --- as an analytical
Ultimately, the realities of gender equality rights in Indigenous settings are also readily
feminism gender equality concerns at some stage of the analytical process in order to be
balanced.
324
See
note
38
and
accompanying
text.
149
In reality, wariness of the internal conflicting forces present in intersectional
approaches to RJ in Indigenous communities has led some feminist scholars --- even those
sympathetic to intersectionality theory --- to put forward some criticisms.325 For example, Mary
Crnkovich asserted that although restorative conferences have the potential to resonate with
traditional Inuit justice values of harmony and social peace without making use of incarceration
measures, there is the danger of lack of uniformity and the possibility for victims to be
silenced.326 Sherene Razack, another multiracial feminist, warns that culture, community and
colonization can be used to compete with one another de-emphasizing gender-based harm
completely.327 Likewise, Rashmi Goel went on to conclude that RJ experiences --- especially
sentencing circles --- may overlook the internal and external conflicting interests existent in
Indigenous communities which can damage the reputation of the idea itself. As she writes:
There are competing interests, and political agendas, in addition to the stated goals of
resolving the dispute and stopping the behavior. There is tremendous diversity within the
community, which may render cultural values antagonistic to the needs and desires of
some community members. In such cases, it may be impossible to accurately represent
the needs of community members in a culturally specific process. Therefore, culturally
specific adjudication based solely on the cultural identity of the offender and victim,
without considering underlying interests, is unwise.328
Finally, as Daly and Stubbs observe, collective political aspirations in the form of
claims for self-determination and social justice, are not often acknowledged in alternative
modes of justice, nor are Indigenous womens perspectives typically addressed.329 In sum, an
depends on a complex interplay of her community political claims, her own various interests and
a number of offenders specific interests, and it stands to reason that there might be many places
325
Markedly,
in
the
Canadian
context.
326
See
note
180.
327
See
note
44,
Razack,
What
Is
to
be
Gained.
328
See
note
8,
Goel,
No
women
at
the
center,
at
333.
329
See
note
5
at
162
and
accompanying
text.
150
where the process can go awry. In other words, this means that the interaction between
intersectionality analysis, gender/race politics and the suitability of RJ to deal with violence
against women has great significance in understanding how RJ operates and is likely to be
perceived by Indigenous groups in post-colonial settings. This is especially true in the Canadian
context where Indigenous women hold mixed views toward RJ and domestic violence. However,
that Indigenous political demands of self-determination may cause in conjunction with other
existing co-optive forces in the context of RJ responses to domestic violence. In order to do that,
imbalanced intersectional approaches, i.e., those that put gender at the end of the list of
perspectives are important to intersectionality analysis within the context of RJ and domestic
Firstly, domestic violence affects women and their communities differently, and
that difference is seldom taken into account in the design and implementation of RJ programs
that usually view group interests and the individual needs of victimized women in a single
project. Secondly, under some existing RJ programs, women and men have unequal access to
voice their concerns and needs following wrongdoing. Particularly in light of the past social
injustices and patriarchal inequalities that underpin several traditional and Indigenous societies,
RJ may focus only on the interests of male offenders. Thirdly, in order to achieve optimum
restorative effects, as mentioned in the first chapter, the inclusion and effective participation of
151
all stakeholders in the restorative process is necessary. Though RJ may be conceived as the
means by which to deliver justice and voice to all, there are concerns that poorly managed RJ
processes.
feminist criminology --- could play a really constructive critical role by serving as an analytical
could help rectify power imbalances between stakeholders and to resolve conflicts between the
various categories of inequality present in such alternative justice systems. In practice, however,
seen, I state again, in the uncritical appreciation of the political demands for self-determination
theory. On the one hand, this means an emphasis on the idea of a critical posture towards agents,
systems and institutions of social control (e.g., conventional criminal justice system and
alternative formats like RJ).330 On the other, it means acceptance of the notion of political
engagement and allegiances with social movements in order to make the interests of the
330
Julie
Stubbs
notes
on
the
features
of
Critical
feminist
criminology.
Supra
note
260.
152
oppressed and marginal visible.331 However, there are potentially conflicting interests between
those two positions that can mean failure to recognize the problematic nature of womens
individual interests within cultural contexts, i.e., positions where collective political claims do
not necessarily match womens individual interests and needs. The oversight of the existence of
conflicting inequality categories and other forces that deemphasize individual claims for gender-
Notably, this happens because such intersectional approaches make concessions to analytical
categories other than gender equality and selectively engage them as more relevant in the
analysis. As a result, collectivists political demands are put ahead of womens individual
interests and needs, which are relegated to positions of subordination, passivity and silence. In
sum, there is an intersectional failure to recognize that the perspective of gender equality
Having said that, I move ahead with a brief critical exposition of the anti-
essentialist epistemic position of the intersectional approach, which I believe is one of the
reasons for that imbalance of intersectional approaches when dealing with the conflicting
analytical categories of restorative justice. I argue that anti-essentialist stances can contribute to
hinder our understanding of the increasingly self-effacing positions in which women are being
political underpinnings of RJ under the guise of Indigenous justice. But intersectional feminists,
because of existing epistemic problems, must be careful not to simply perpetuate patriarchal and
oppressive views of reality rather than advance womens emancipatory goals. Both key features
of feminist intersectionality theory, i.e., the rejection of gender as the standard category of
analysis, and the importance given to heterogeneous and multiple perspectives are direct
fragmented and multiple perspectives of womens conditions do not allow the recognition of
shared characteristics universal to all women, which in theory could have potential to unify them
undermine or overthrow it left feminist scholars and activists with a twofold problem. Firstly,
they lacked a common political identity and discourse on which to base their policy
questioned since gender underestimation led to a crisis of identity in the feminist movement.333
This famous quote from Teresa de Lauretis summarizes well the feminist unrest with anti-
Its absolute rejection of gender and its negation of biological determinism in favor of
cultural-discursive determinism results, as concerns women, in a form of nominalism. If
'woman' is a fiction, a locus of pure difference and resistance to logocentric power, and if
there is no woman as such, them the very issue of women's oppression would appear to
be obsolete and feminism would have no reason to exist. 334
332
See
note
287
for
a
definition
of
anti-essentialism
in
feminist
theory.
333
Ibid.
334
See
Teresa
de
Lauretis,
Upping
the
Anti
(sic)
in
Feminist
Theory
in
Simon
During,
ed.,
The
Cultural
Studies
Reader
(London:
Routledge,
1993)
307
at
314.
154
Other important feminist scholars like Naomi Schor, Gayatri C. Spivak and Diana
view, however, the main consequence of adopting a feminist analysis devoid of elements of
intersectionality theory) that may undermine individualist positions and womens subjectivities
regarding equality concerns even though the ultimate goal of intersectionality, as a feminist
critical theory, is exactly to promote them. The goal then is to improve the intersectionality
theory by highlighting certain anti-essentialist weaknesses while retaining its critical identity as a
specific way for understanding and describing gendered-violence in heterogeneous settings. The
bottom line is not to promote empty criticism, but rendering intersectionality theory into a better
approach to address RJ practices in Indigenous settings would first consider the socio-political
imperatives that would accommodate collectivist interests, e.g., privileging culture and ethnicity
political claims over gender individual concerns. Therefore, the impetus for an intersectional
approach may stem from the principle of legitimacy (mainly collectivist), i.e., from a desire to
maintain credibility and prestige in an overtly political environment like Indigenous justice. At
the same time, the motivation could stem from a sense of public responsibility, particularly for
335
See,
e.g.,
Naomi
Schor
&
Elizabeth
Weed,
eds.,
The
Essential
difference
(Bloomington:
Indiana
University
Press,
1994)
(In
this
collections
of
essays,
Lauretis;
Schor;
Sipvak;
Fuss
and
others
discuss
the
demonization
of
essentialism
within
the
feminist
movement
and
address
the
relationship
between
essentialism
and
post-colonial
studies.
They
also
speculate
about
whether
there
can
be
a
real
anti-essentialist
feminism,
and
whether
or
not
the
womans
question
can
be
so
easily
discarded
by
feminist
scholarship).
155
justice systems.
Efforts to stem the legitimacy and political development of Indigenous justice
(travestied as RJ) in ethnic communities, which often have taken the form of state-sponsored
efforts to promote experiences like sentencing circles, may make gender-based inequality even
worse for Indigenous women. In sum, anti-essentialist positions would eventually erase gender
equality concerns more focused on the choices of individual stakeholders and their personal
Strategic
essentialism
of RJ and Indigenous settings is that the tensions between the various analytical categories and
political stances present in that remedial alternative justice may remain overlooked. In so doing,
the fact that RJ disguised as Indigenous justice --- together with the related concepts of social
justice and self-governance --- may paradoxically accord with patriarchal and post-colonial
dominance.336 As a result collectivist interests may gain precedence over individual gender
issues. But there is room for retaining gender as a crucial analytical category in an intersectional
gender/sex position in order to achieve a particular political end. Such practice has been used
336
Since
alternative
justice
experiences
like
sentencing
circles
never
concede
actual
powers
to
Indigenous
people,
as
we
shall
see.
337
See
Gayatrcy
C.
Spivak,
Subaltern
Studies:
Deconstructing
Historiograph
in
Donna
Landry
&
Gerald
M.
MacLean,
eds.,
The
Spivak
reader:
selected
works
of
Gayatri
Chakravorty
Spivak
(New
York:
Routledge,
1996)
at
204.
156
asymmetrical power relationships. This is exactly the case of women in situations facing with RJ
and domestic violence in Indigenous settings. Strategic essentialism can reemphasize the focus
on gender issues in order to allow women to reclaim their autonomy and self-empowerment even
when power asymmetric conditions are present and women live in heterogeneous conditions.
Some intersectional feminists intuitively adopted such emphasis and avoided the pitfalls of anti-
capacity of informal adjudicatory practices like RJ largely depends on whether its audiences
activists and postcolonial scholars often voice concerns about whether such arrangements have
moral authority, and whether such informal practices are also culturally resonant in relation to
customary justice practices.339 Such perceived legitimacy is also important to sustain RJs
expectations for funding, political support and resources. RJ cannot survive --- being a
participatory democracy experiment --- without political support of the target audience. In
parallel, RJ language is adopted because it also offers novel political possibilities to Indigenous
activists. They transform RJs collective justice claims into new spaces of struggle for self-
338
See,
e.g.,
note
81,
Abel,
The
Politics
at
5.
339
See,
e.g.,
Harry
Blagg,
Crime,
Aboriginality
and
the
Decolonization
of
Justice
(Sidney:
Hawkins
press,
2008).
157
RJs advocacy discourse lies at the meeting of those Indigenous grievances and
several other interest groups claims and depends on their support to gain political legitimacy and,
therefore, progressive outcomes in restorative process. As Stubbs puts it, It has been suggested
that pro-feminist and anti-racist groups should be participants in restorative process in order to
bolster victim narratives and to challenge those who do not take responsibility for their
offending.340 For this reason, the RJ movement usually conveys ideas of social justice that are
less individualistic and more focused on communities and collectivist responsibilities and rights,
aligning them to particular cultural narratives and contexts.341 Sociologists and politic scientists
studying social movements theory describe that process as frame alignment.342 According to
Snow et al., frames or schemata of interpretation are not by themselves coherent ideas, but
ways of packaging and conveying ideas that generate prompt understanding by the target
audience, motivate collective action and create strategies of self-advocacy for supporters.343 As
340
See
note
254
at
59.
341
As
a
principle
RJ
practices
seek
to
involve
those
with
a
legitimate
stake
in
the
situation,
including
victims,
offenders,
community
members
and
society.
See,
e.g.,
Kay
Pranis,
Barry
Stuart
&
Mark
Wedge,
Peacemaking
Circles:
From
Crime
to
Community
(St.
Paul,
MN:
Living
Justice
Press,
2003).
342
See
David
E.
Snow,
et
al.,
Frame
Alignment
Processes,
Micromobilization,
and
Movement
Participation
(1986)
American
Sociological
Review
51:4
464-481.
See
also
Sidney
Tarrow,
Power
in
Movements:
Social
Movements
and
Contentious
Politics
(Cambridge:
Cambridge
University
Press,
1998).
343
Ibid.
344
See
Anders
Walker,
Shotguns,
Weddings,
and
Lunch
Counters:
Why
Cultural
Frames
Matter
to
Constitutional
Law
online:
(19
August,
2010)
Florida
State
University
Law
Review,
Forthcoming.
Available
at
SSRN:
<http://ssrn.com/abstract=1661981>.
158
In other words, the RJ social movement frames itself to make culturally
resonant connections with collective Aboriginal values and belief systems in order to consolidate
its position as a viable alternative justice practice.345 RJs proponents seek to relate their
legitimacy goals to the political goals or cultural assumptions of the targeted group. In so doing,
the restorative frame alignment strategy also takes a particular story of wrongdoing (victims vis-
-vis offenders) and makes it a collective political concern (shared responsibilities between
victims, offenders and communities). That particular story suddenly becomes politically relevant
in the recognition of customary group political rights and is attached to a larger political context
of collective empowerment. However, there is the chance those womens subjectivities and
individual perceptions are silenced or alienated in the process. As Ferree warns, choosing
cultural resonance as a frame alignment strategy requires the possibility of sacrificing ideals,
limiting demands on authorities, and possibly excluding vulnerable groups as their demands
The self-advocacy strategy of the RJ movement linking its credibility and moral
authority with the targeted audience in cultural terms becomes complicated when making
political alliances and building community self-empowerment turns out to be more important
than womens personal experiences when dealing with restorative justice. This is precisely the
problem RJ proponents confront when they develop advocacy strategies based on cultural frame
they may also be reinforcing pre-existing patriarchal notions about gender disciplinary roles.
While an Indigenous womans community struggles to reassert its self-determination, she may
345
See
note
61,
Daly
&
Immarigeon,
Origins,
at
10.
(Arguing
that
RJ
proponents
adopted
varied
organizational
and
advocacy
strategies.
According
to
them,
it
is
not
at
all
clear
whether
it
is
best
integrating
restorative
justice
practices
with
Indigenous
justice
customary
law
or,
alternatively,
replacing
traditional
practices
with
restorative
ones.
Anyway,
intersectional
feminists
coalesced
both
into
the
same
analytical
context).
346
See
Myra
Marx
Feree,
Resonance
and
Radicalism:
Feminist
Framing
in
the
Abortion
Debates
of
the
United
States
and
German
(2003)
109:2
American
Journal
of
Sociology
304-44
at
340.
159
find her new subject position within RJ awkward and relatively helpless due to power
asymmetries and gender devaluation. As we shall see in the next and final chapter, the literature
indicates that Indigenous women are basically being led to accept the existing patriarchal
institutions of their communities in face the of multicultural collectivists demands for political
self-determination. In addition, some RJ advocacy discourses --- reinforcing those demands ---
make them prone to a delegation of trust to those who advocate such alternative justice
interventions because these are allegedly culturally competent and, therefore, bear legitimacy for
coping with collective concerns for social justice. Indigenous women who fail or are resistant to
culturally framing their particular narratives of RJ experiences can be alienated and silenced. In
sum, Intersectional/multiracial feminists that are not aware of social movements theory,
particularly cultural frame alignment, may be compelled to endorse such self-advocacy practices
because they are structurally similar to their own conceptions about culture preeminence in RJ
justice. First and foremost, they brought women and gender issues to the fore and provided a
diversified critical framework with which to scrutinize it. Those critical theoretical perspectives
range from classic, but disparate lines of feminist thinking like liberal feminism or dominance
feminism, to postmodern feminism and Marxist-socialist feminism that require borrowing anti-
evolution of those feminist disciplines allowed the integration of Indigenous political claims for
self-determination and social justice into the discussion about RJ and domestic violence; notably,
through the work of multiracial feminists (i.e., intersectional feminists) that coalesced RJ and
Indigenous customary justice into a single analytical mass. Such positioning amplifies the
160
importance that some intersectional feminists attribute to Aboriginal collectivities, and shifts the
focus from victims subjectivities, such as womens needs and interests, to the formulation of a
political agenda, with reverence to non-emancipatory aims, in order to accomplish, manage, and
the intersectional research on RJ may be framed as devaluing sexuality and gender as primary
inequality categories (i.e., anti-essentialism), but also as placing strong emphasis on Indigenous
domestic violence seeking to investigate its suitability to contend with the complexities of
gendered-violence regardless of race or ethnicity. Typically, the focus of those studies has been
on worries about womens security, autonomy (or agency) and offenders accountability.347 All
these particular concerns primarily reflect mainstream feminists and battered womens
advocates gender equality concerns vis--vis power imbalances between victims and offenders.
scholarship - mainstream feminists and battered womens advocates draw from an essentially
gender/sex positional perspective; a pragmatic standpoint that recognizes the inherent power
differentials betweens female victims and male offenders.348 In addition, the pragmatic approach
is also in concert with fears of survivors revictimization and allegations of re-privatization and
common concerns would include, for example, RJ programs giving more emphasis to offenders
347
See
note
2,
Cameron,
RJ:
Literature
Review,
at
21-26.
(Angela
Cameron
developed
a
comprehensive
literature
review
on
the
topic
and
highlighted
these
specific
worries).
See
also
note
10
and
accompanying
text.
348
See
especially
Loretta
Frederick
&
Kristine
C.
Lizdas,
The
Role
of
Restorative
Justice
in
the
Battered
Women's
Movement
in
James
Ptacek,
ed.,
Restorative
Justice
and
Violence
Against
Women
(New
York,
NY:
Oxford
University
Press,
2009)
612-919
in
a
kindle
e-book
version.
161
rehabilitation rather than womens actual needs; the lack of consultation with battered womens
advocate; concerns that women victims should be given a better informed choice regarding
whether or not to participate in RJ experiences; and, finally, the lack of resources and proper
training.349
In fact, Cook et al. observed that by far the most prolific and significant niche of
feminist scholarly work about RJ hinges exactly on the investigation of the potential benefits and
a great deal of sound research on the subject matter recommending the summary of results from
existing commentaries by use of earlier reviewers' efforts. For reasons of space and simplicity, I
draw from Kathleen Daly and Julie Stubbs work that categorized that research to explain
contexts.
Daly and Stubbs have produced arguably the most extensive compilation of
scholarly discussion on the appropriateness of the use of RJ within the domestic violence
context. The practical approach described in their compilation represents a synthesis of some of
the best and most pragmatic commentaries and evaluations of domestic violence in the RJ
literature. It should be noted that their work is often cited or reproduced at length in other
scholarly works on the theme.351 For this reason, I take the liberty of reproducing their
349
See
Stephanie
Coward,
Restorative
Justice
in
Domestic
and
Sexual
Violence:
Healing
Justice?
(December
2000)
Directed
Interdisciplinary
Studies,
Carleton
University.
See
especially
note
54,
Stubbs,
Domestic
Violence.
See
also
note
25,
Coker,
Transformative
Justice.
See
note
49,
Cheon
&
Regehr,
RJ
Models.
See
generally
Lawrence
W.
Sherman,
Domestic
Violence
and
Restorative
Justice:
Answering
Key
questions
(2000-2001)
8:1
Virginia
Journal
of
Social
Policy
&
Law
263.
350
This
area
attracted
such
attention
of
feminist
scholars
that
Cook,
Daly
and
Stubbs
pointed
out
that,
Virtually
all
feminist
analyses
of
restorative
justice
have
centred
on
its
appropriateness
for
partner,
family
or
sexual
violence.
See,
e.g..,
Kimberly
J.
Cook,
Kathleen
Daly
&
Julie
Stubbs,
Introduction
Special
Issue
(2006)
10:1
Theoretical
Criminology
5-7
at
5.
351
See,
e.g.,
Gitana
Proietti-Scifoni,
Restorative
Justice
in
Cases
of
Gendered
Violence:
Views
from
Aotearoa
Opinion
Leaders
(B.Crim.
Thesis,
Griffith
University,
2008)
[unpublished]
at
11-12.
162
compilation of feminist insights on the suitability of using RJ in domestic violence cases. Their
work summarizes the existing stances about the use of RJ to cope with gendered-violence by
hinge on the impossibility to reconcile its ideology and practices with the harsh realities of
domestic violence. Daly and Stubbs pointed out several ways that negative concerns about using
RJ for domestic violence cases could be addressed. The following bullet points summarize and
Victim safety. As an informal process, RJ may put victims at risk of continued violence;
it may permit power imbalances to go unchecked and reinforce abusive behaviour.
Pressure on victims. Some victims may not be able to effectively advocate on their own
behalf. A process based on building group consensus may minimize or overshadow a
victim's interests. Victims may be pressured to accept certain outcomes, such as an
apology, even if they feel it is inappropriate or insincere. Some victims may want the
state to intervene on their behalf and do not want the burdens of RJ.
Role of the 'community'. Community norms may reinforce, not undermine male
dominance and victim blaming. Communities may not be sufficiently resourced to take
on these cases.
Mixed loyalties. Friends and family may support victims, but may also have divided
loyalties and collude with the violence, especially in intra-familial cases.
Symbolic implications. Offenders (or potential offenders) may view RJ processes as too
easy, reinforcing their belief that their behaviour is not wrong or can be justified.
Penalties may be too lenient to respond to serious crimes like sexual assault.352
352
See
note
9,
Daly
&
Stubbs,
Feminist
theory,
at
159.
According
to
Daly
and
Stubbs,
these
potential
problems
have
been
identified
by
Stubbs
(1997,
2002,
2004),
Coker
(1999,
2002),
Goel
(2000),
Presser
and
Gaarder
(2000),
Shapland
(2000),
Lewis
et
al.
(2001),
Busch
(2002),
Acorn
(2004),
and
Hopkins
et
al.
(2004).
For
more
details:
See
Julie
Stubbs,
Shame,
Defiance,
and
Violence
against
Women:
A
Critical
Analysis
of
"Communitarian"
163
As we can see, mainstream feminists prioritize the goals of individual women and
battered womens advocates --- safety and offender accountability --- over the goals of ethnic
collectivities looking for ways to redress endemic social injustice in their relationships with the
conventional criminal justice system and seeking to assert their political power in terms of self-
governance and self-determination. I share the same concerns and, therefore, I take a position
contrary to the use of RJ in domestic violence cases although I also incorporate procedural issues
Victim voice and participation. Victims have the opportunity to voice their story and to
be heard. They can be empowered by confronting the offender, and by participating in
decision-making on the appropriate penalty.
Communicative and flexible environment. The process can be tailored to child and
adolescent victims' needs and capacities. Because it is flexible and less formal, it may
be less threatening and more responsive to the individual needs of victims.
Conferencing,
in
Sandy
Cook
&
Judith
Bessant,
eds.,
Women's
Encounters
with
Violence:
Australian
Experiences
(London:
Sage,
1997)
109-26.
See
note
5,
Stubbs,
Domestic
Violence.
See
Julie
Stubbs,
Restorative
Justice,
Domestic
Violence
and
Family
Violence
Issues
Paper
9
(Sydney:
Australian
Domestic
and
Family
Violence
Clearinghouse,
2004).
See
Donna
Coker,
Enhancing
Autonomy
for
Battered
Women:
Lessons
from
Navajo
Peacemaking
(1999)
47:
1
UCLA
Law
Review
111.
See
note
25,
Coker,
Transformative
Justice.
See
note
34,
Coker,
Navajo
Peacemaking.
See
note
8,
Goel,
No
Women
at
the
Center.
See
note
81,
Presser
&
Gaarder,
Can
RJ
reduce
Battering?.
See
Joanna
Shapland,
Victims
and
Criminal
Justice:
Creating
Responsible
Criminal
Justice
Agencies
in
Adam
Crawford
&
Jo
Goodey,
eds.,
Integrating
a
Victim
Perspective
within
Criminal
Justice:
International
Debates,
(Aldershot:
Ashgate,
2000)
147-64.
See
Ruth
Lewis,
Rebecca
Dobash,
Russell
Dobash
and
Kate
Cavanagh,
'Law's
Progressive
Potential:
The
Value
of
Engagement
for
the
Law
for
Domestic
Violence'
(2001)
10
Social
and
Legal
Studies
105-30.
See
Ruth
Busch,
Domestic
Violence
and
Restorative
Justice
Initiatives:
Who
Pays
if
we
Get
it
Wrong?
in
Heather
Strang
&
John
Braithwaite,
eds.,
Restorative
Justice
and
Family
Violence,
(Cambridge:
Cambridge
University
Press,
2002)
223-48.
See
note
47,
Acorn,
Compulsory
Compassion.
See
note
270,
Hopkins
et.
al,
Applying
Restorative
Justice
to
Ongoing
Intimate
Violence.
164
Relationship repair (if this is a goal). The process can address violence between those
who want to continue the relationship. It can create opportunities for relationships to be
repaired, if that is what is desired.353
highly dependent on which RJ model is being analyzed (e.g., Family Group conference,
sentencing circles, etc.) and on which type of crime is committed by the offender (e.g., sexual
violence or just battering).354 A RJ model may look more favorable in comparison to one
perceptions of the idea. For example, Indigenous women are inclined to be more receptive to RJ
contrast, white women and battered womens advocates are more distrustful of it due to the
association of RJ with family mediation schemes and alternative dispute resolution. As Angela
Furthermore, Angela Cameron, Kathleen Daly and Julie Stubbs; feminist legal
scholars who performed systematic literature reviews on RJ, assert that there are few hard or
agreed empirical data sets to back up any of the positions outlined above. As Daly and Stubbs
point out, Although there is considerable debate on the appropriateness of RJ for partner, sexual
or family violence, empirical evidence is sparse.356 Cameron goes in the same direction. As she
notes: Arguments on either side are presented with emotion and a genuine desire for positive
social change. However, the fact remains that there is little empirical evidence to support either
position (R. Morris, 2000; Presser and Gaarder, 2000; Sherman, 2000; A. Morris, 2002)357 The
current impasse between feminists portrayed above and the lack of empirical evidence
practically ensures that no RJ model is a panacea to violence against women cases regardless of
race or ethnicity. In fact, any RJ program should be taken with care and must be studied with
developed planning that takes into consideration the potential problems and benefits described
above.
As we can see from the arguments above for and against the use of RJ in cases of
intimate violence, the negative or positive influence of existing feminist theories are not being
taking into consideration in the scholarly contribution within the theme. Any potential problems,
where they exist, usually stem from substantive issues not from procedural values or
355
See
note
15,
Cameron,
Stopping
the
Violence,
at
50.
356
See
note
5
at
160.
357
Supra
note
356
at
59.
166
practices in Canada and Australaia are increasingly dominated by intersectionality theory
insights and contributions. In fact, RJ interventions --- especially in ethnic and racial settings ---
collectivism; heterogeneity and ethnocultural political concerns) and have been shown to create
significant implications for RJ and its adoption and evaluation. For instance, as stressed in the
last chapter, Indigenous advocates and activists claim that RJ is a culturally appropriate response
to the harm done to Aboriginal people by colonialism. This is a sign that intersectional thinking
is pervasive in the RJ strategy of cultural frame alignment because it takes into consideration the
interaction of ethnicity and gender politics at the forefront of debates. A good example of that
are restorative-like experiments like sentencing circles. They are experiments clearly inspired by
multiculturalism and devised as intersectional remedial justice practices in Canada, which were
multiculturalism into RJ and Aboriginal Justice bring new benefits and potential risks to bear on
Aboriginal communities and greatly impact racialized women and their priorities.
The next and concluding chapter explores how intersectionality theory and
epistemic and political problems in intersectionality theory, as developed in this chapter, to apply
them to the use of sentencing circles within the specific geographical contexts of Canada and
Australia. A conflict between ethnocultural collective politics and individual gender equality
concerns in sentencing circles is articulated and developed. The prospects and perils of co-
167
Chapter
III
Further
developments,
implications
and
conclusions
Chapter
outline
After having presented in chapters one and two an overview of the theoretical
framework of the RJ movement and an outline of the feminist scholarship about it, plus some
instrumental and not substantive issues, i.e., seeks to identify and problematize an imbalanced
version of intersectionality theory --- especially concerning its interaction with RJ models
applied in Aboriginal settings --- all substantive (or empirical) considerations are relevant only to
the extent that they corroborate or refute that goal. Thus, I will not focus in this concluding
chapter on a specific RJ program, but only delineate and discuss the intersectional nature,
direction, and meaning of practical restorative experiences that may confirm that such a feminist
approach, paradoxically, can end up being harmful to Aboriginal women if managed without
In order to do that, this chapter builds on earlier studies and commentaries that
have addressed the interplay between collective ethnocultural political claims and issues of
form of sentencing circles. Furthermore, I move to end this paper by drawing implications and
168
conclusions from potential vulnerabilities of intersectional approaches within the study of RJ
coping with domestic violence in Indigenous settings. The overall conclusion is that certain
Before turning to the issues above, however, I pause to consider some of the
section of this chapter, therefore, I seek to develop connections between intersectionality theory,
multiculturalism and sentencing circles. In other words, I contend that the interplay between
consequence, I argue that sentencing circles experiences in those countries are a direct result of a
blend of multicultural rhetoric and intersectional feminists concerns. In reality, there is a similar
arrangement of values and goals associated with those two ideologies. For example, the two
approaches deal with similar subject matters (i.e., respect for ethnocultural diversity and
empowerment of minority groups) and they have other similarities like the accommodation of
Indigenous self-determination political claims in the form of culturally sensitive remedial justice
practices (e.g., sentencing circles). For these reasons, remedial justice practices like sentencing
and intersectional feminists; a relationship that also runs in parallel with the rise of the RJ
system. However, as we shall see, that relationship is fraught with potential dangers to
169
Notably, I stress the problems that multiculturalism may present to vulnerable
groups within ethnic minorities according to a feminist critique of the multicultural political
approaches to sentencing circles, i.e., intersectional feminist stances that prioritize the political
words, the ethnocultural focus of some intersectional feminists analyzing sentencing circles in
Aboriginal communities resonates with the multicultural political project of countries like
Canada and Australia. However, this brings possible problems to vulnerable subjects within
ethnic minorities like battered women in Indigenous groups whose interests do not necessarily
coincide with the collective political aims of ethnic communities dominant groups. The
significant conclusions we can make on the basis of RJ experiences like sentencing circles.
Notably, I illustrate and discuss how intersectional approaches on sentencing circles can be
distorted into a divisive and uncritical feminist analytical tool. In fact, the signs are that
intersectionality theory to leverage their own political platforms with unintended detrimental
170
consequences to racialized women like exclusion and effacement. This claim of co-optation and
violence in Indigenous settings since individual gender equality concerns might not be properly
considered in such a scale of values. In order to illustrate this contention, I make use of selected
literature on sentencing circles in Canada and Australia. The sample of literature moves from
general perspectives about RJ and its relationship with imbalanced versions of intersectional
thinking to more specific empirical problems within sentencing circles. Finally, I make some
justice.
The third section serves to wrap up key findings and to establish conclusions and
RJ and domestic violence in Aboriginal communities since it may be so conflated with non-
women-centered interests that it can mean the total abandonment of its critical and emancipatory
feminist interests this thesis also recommends developing essentialist strategic visions about the
importance of gender equality issues in sentencing circles and other RJ experiments. I conclude
by suggesting that intersectional feminists must be conscious of how their own political positions
regarding RJ experiments may affect their critical and emancipatory objectives. When
intersectional feminists place an excessive focus on ethnocultural political demands, they are
likely to ignore victims individual gender equality needs and concerns. In fact, I call for
scholarship by non-feminist interests. Only this way, victims of gendered-violence can fully
171
1. Further
developments:
Intersectional
feminism,
multiculturalism
and
sentencing
circles
that runs in close proximity with the nature, objectives and dynamics of feminist intersectional
intersectionality are distinct concepts, there are shared interests, objectives and concerns that can
intersectional approaches to sentencing circles. In fact, one key objective of this segment is to
link intersectional feminism and its approaches to sentencing circles with the broader political
better understanding of the vulnerabilities of this feminist analytical framework within the
context of restorative justice. Another goal in this section is to establish that the lessons drawn
from the critique of multiculturalism can also be applied to the study of the relationship between
358
See,
e.g.,
Anne
Philips,
Multiculturalism
without
Culture
(Princeton:
Princeton
Unversity
Press,
2007)
at
3.
See
also:
Canadian
Charter
of
Rights
and
Freedoms,
Part
I
of
the
Constitution
Act,
1982,
being
Schedule
B
to
the
Canada
Act
1982
(U.K).,
1982,
c.
11
[Charter].
Canadian
Multiculturalism
Act,
R.S.C.
1985,
c.
24
(4th
Supp).
Statement,
Multicultural
Australia:
United
in
Diversity:
Updating
the
1999
New
Agenda
for
Multicultural
Australia:
Strategic
directions
for
2003-2006,
Commonwealth
of
Australia
2003.
(Both
Canada
and
Australia
have
long
declared
themselves
officially
multicultural
countries.
In
Canada,
for
example,
since
1971,
when
prime-minister
Pierre
Elliot
Trudeau
has
delivered
his
famous
address
to
the
House
of
Commons
outlining
the
tenets
of
liberal
multiculturalism
in
Canada.
Multiculturalism,
since
them,
has
been
reflected
in
the
Canadian
legal
framework.
For
example,
through
the
Canadian
Multiculturalism
Act
and
section
27
of
the
Canadian
Charter
of
Rights
and
Freedoms.
In
Australia
as
far
back
as
1982
and,
more
recently,
with
the
statement
Multicultural
Australia:
United
in
Diversity
in
2003).
172
a) Multiculturalism
and
restorative
justice:
establishing
connections
philosophy about the proper way to respond to cultural and religious diversity.359 Song points
out that multiculturalism seeks to supersede the mere toleration of group differences by treating
members of minority groups, substantively and positively, as equal citizens.360 This includes
differentiated rights without, of course, promoting the centrality of any culture or ethnic group.
Song notes that group-differentiated rights can be operated individually or by a group. She
provides the example of individuals who are granted exemptions from generally applicable laws
in virtue of their religious beliefs or individuals who seek language accommodations in schools
or in voting. Moreover, she observes that group-differentiated rights can be held by the group
rather than its members individually; such rights are properly called group rights, as in the case
of Indigenous groups and other ethnic minorities, who claim the right of self-determination.361
She gives as examples of these policies the limited recognition of tribal sovereignty and the state
acknowledgement of customary justice practices by the dominant legal system in countries like
Canada and New Zealand.362 Hence, we can argue without great concerns, that the reception and
multiculturalism besides classical liberal values of equality and autonomy is exactly the critique
of colonialism and the advance of Indigenous rights for self-determination and self-governance
in formerly colonized states. Accordingly, multiculturalists look to the world from a postcolonial
perspective, focusing on colonial oppression and persistent denials of basic human rights to
cultural minority groups, as a point of critique. Multicultural theorists call this particular line of
Lastly, some philosophers have looked beyond liberalism in arguing for multiculturalism.
This is especially true of theorists writing from a postcolonial perspective. The case for
tribal sovereignty rests not simply on premises about the value of tribal culture and
membership, but also on what is owed to Native peoples for the historical injustices
perpetrated against them. Reckoning with history is crucial. Proponents of indigenous
sovereignty emphasize the importance of understanding indigenous claims against the
historical background of the denial of equal sovereign status of indigenous groups, the
dispossession of their lands, and the destruction of their cultural practices (Ivison 2006,
Ivison et al. 2000, Moore 2005, Simpson 2000). This background calls into question the
legitimacy of the state's authority over aboriginal peoples and provides a prima facie case
for special rights and protections for indigenous groups, including the right of self-
government.363
creates numerous opportunities for the adoption of culturally sensitive justice experiments such
justifications for the massive growth of RJ experiments in the last two decades in countries like
Canada and Australia, far beyond the broad limits envisioned by its proponents concerning a
paradigmatic shift from punishment and retribution, can be attributed to the political agency of
those liberal multicultural states in promoting what multicultural theorists define as the politics
363
Ibid.
364
The
right
of
self-government
involves
jurisdictional
authority
over
a
delimited
territory
and
institutional
mechanisms
to
enforce
it,
e.g.,
tribal
police
or
some
sort
of
Indigenous
Justice.
See
Margaret
Moore,
Internal
Minorities
and
Indigenous
Self-Determination,
in
Avigail
I.
Eisenberg
and
Jeff
Spinner-Halev,
eds.,
Minorities
within
Minorities:
Equality,
Rights
and
Diversity
(Cambridge:
Cambridge
University
Press,
2005)
at
271-293.
174
of recognition.365 As Song explains, a politics of recognition challenges status inequality and
the remedy it proposes is cultural and symbolic change. With respect to criminal justice and its
formal institutions, this symbolic change means, for instance, the introduction of alternative
justice practices like RJ that presupposes non-incarceration measures for Aboriginal offenders;
dialogue-driven adjudication; diversion from formal courts and, finally, a more holistic and
justice schemes like sentencing circles developed first through Indigenous groups in Canada and
Australia. Multicultural policies of recognition fueled the RJ boom in liberal democracies like
Canada and Australia in conjunction with the influence of several other social movements and
differentiated rights, i.e., the emphasis on certain rights for self-determination for Indigenous
approach that organized feminist theorizing on RJ practice around the integration of issues like
post-colonialism, anti-racism and, especially, political claims for self-governance and self-
365
See
Charles
Taylor,
The
Politics
of
Recognition
in
A.
Gutmann,
ed.,
Multiculturalism:
Examining
the
Politics
of
Recognition
(New
Jersey:
Princeton
University
Press,
1994).
(Explaining
the
concept
of
recognition
from
several
perspectives).
366
See
note
319,
Cunneen,
Reviving
RJ
traditions.
(Describing
the
emergence
of
RJ
practices
within
the
context
of
Indigenous
groups
through
multicultural
policies).
175
determination by Indigenous groups.367 This means that intersectionality analysis also focuses
attention on responses to inequality that have long been the subject of debate and examination
intersectionality analysis and sentencing circles, i.e., concerns about self-government rights by
Indigenous people and decolonization mechanisms comes to look similar in direction and nature
to multiculturalists concerns and; thus, the turn to the critiques made against multiculturalism
becomes a valuable resource for understanding the vulnerabilities of the intersectional approach
systems of action and meaning that share, in some aspects, common ideological and political
According to Reingod and Baratz, there is a very strong bond between feminist
theories in general and multiculturalist theories since both share a general concern for promoting
social justice and ethnic equality and there are transformational and emancipatory goals
motivating both intellectual enterprises.368 However, they also acknowledge that this connection
between the feminist paradigm and multiculturalism is not free from dissension. They have
identified three distinct stances among academic commentators. In the first stance, feminism is at
odds with multiculturalism. As they have noted, Advocated mainly by liberal feminist thinkers,
the first approach claims that feminism and multiculturalism are contradictory, and there is a
367
See
note
316
and
accompanying
text.
(Actually,
Chris
Cunneen
have
established
this
connection
between
feminism
and
RJ,
but
in
general
terms).
See
note
209.
368
See
note
273,
Reingod
&
Baratz,
Feminism
and
Multiculturalism.
(The
vision
is
emancipatory
in
a
broader
political
sense,
whereby
intersectionality
and
multiculturalism
rhetoric
can
serve
as
tools
for
decolonization
and
anti-racist
policies).
176
strained relationship between them.369 This position is, especially, defended by feminists
inspired by liberal thinking like Susan Moller-Okin and Ayelet Shachar.370 In the second
position, feminism and multiculturalism are both contradictory and complementary at the same
time. Notably, scholars within the context of education defend such positions.371 Finally, there
are scholars that consider multiculturalism and feminism as essentially compatible with each
other like Shohat and Volpp.372 These scholars advocate what some feminists call multicultural
feminism, i.e., a strand of feminist theorizing also known by the term multiracial feminism or in
some academic circles as intersectional feminism.373 Nonetheless, the important point of this
claim is not the terminological similarity between multiculturalism and multicultural feminism as
seems to be the case at first sight. More importantly, it is the coincidence of objectives and
The proponents of the third approach in the polemic assert that multiculturalism and
feminism offer similar arguments to explain why women suffer from discrimination and
injustice, presenting similar solutions for creating equality between the genders ( ) and
374
is essentially the thesis of the feminist school known as "Afro-American feminism.
369
Supra
note
at
54.
370
See
note
274
and
accompanying
text.
(The
concept
of
multiculturalism
has
been
critiqued
by
Susan
Moller-
OKin.
According
to
her
claims
of
minority
cultures
contradict
norms
of
gender
equality
pursued
by
women
in
liberal
states).
See
also
Ayelet
Shachar,
Multicultural
Jurisdictions:
Cultural
Differences
and
Women's
Rights
(Cambridge:
Cambridge
University
Press,
2001).
(Addressing
the
relationship
between
multiculturalism
and
feminism
as
oppositional
due
to
conflicts
between
aiming
to
support
and
protect
many
cultures
and
aiming
to
promote
the
equality
and
dignity
for
women).
371
See
note
273
at
54.
(For
an
account
of
scholars
that
share
this
position).
372
See,
e.g.,
Ella
Shohat,
ed.,
Talking
Visions:
Multicultural
Feminism
in
a
Transnational
Age
(Cambridge:
MIT
Press,
1998).
See
also
Leti
Volpp,
Multiculturalism
versus
Feminism
in
Natalie
J.
Sokoloff
&
Christina
Pratt,
eds.,
Domestic
violence
at
the
margins:
readings
on
race,
class,
gender,
and
culture
(Piscataway,
NJ:
Rutgers
University
Press,
2006)
39.
(Arguing
that
positing
feminism
and
multiculturalism
as
oppositional
is
flawed
and
illogical
under
the
perspective
of
immigrant
minorities.
She
contends
that
there
is
a
common
ground
for
a
constructive
dialogue
between
the
two
ideological
stances.)
373
See
infra
note
372.
374
Ibid.
177
In reality, the terms Afro-American feminism (or Black feminism), critical race
feminism and multicultural feminism come to identify several feminist perceptions that are
aligned at the same time with certain features of multiculturalism and multicultural feminism.
For example, as we have seen in chapter two, multicultural (or multiracial) feminism is greatly
influenced by intersectionality theory in the sense of the attention given to the interplay of
and insights.375 Thus, we can identify in multicultural (or intersectional) feminism one strand of
multiculturalism, in particular, the respect for diversity and empowering culturally diverse
groups (e.g., Indigenous people). In short, the postcolonial multicultural rhetoric in its
proposition of rights to self-determination for cultural minority groups like Indigenous people
posits several interrelated and reinforcing proximal political and philosophical drivers that
multiculturalism and intersectionality as applied to RJ does not mean that the two ideologies are
totally equivalent. What may approximate multiculturalism to intersectional feminism may also
confound scholars trying to make sense of their dissimilarities concerning epistemic approaches.
It is precisely because their goals and subject matters look so close to one another in some
aspects that it becomes necessary to establish clear distinctions between the two ideological
375
See
notes
310
and
311
and
accompanying
texts.
(Explaining
the
use
of
other
terminologies
to
convey
the
idea
of
intersectionality
theory
like,
for
example,
multiracial
feminism).
178
positions. Actually, intersectionality theory is not equivalent to multiculturalism.376 Although
there are highly significant similarities between postcolonial multiculturalism and intersectional
feminism, particularly, as applied to RJ, the two concepts cannot be confounded with each other.
There are clearly disparate epistemic stances between the two theories. Multicultural theories are
arguably defined mainly by essentialist positions; i.e. multicultural rhetoric treats individuals as
if their particular ethnocultural group essentially defines them. For this reason, in multicultural
theory culture plays the role of homogenization that sex/gender can play in women's studies. In
contrast, intersectionality theory, in ideal terms, operates through well balanced anti-essentialist
positions and explores the tension that arises along multiple inequality categories and axes of
Both concepts have evolved from similar articulations within the RJ realm, but they have
sentencing circles --- that work to deemphasize gender/sex equality concerns about individual
victims (concerning, e.g., security, autonomy and offender accountability) almost to the point of
ethnocultural political themes, they leave underestimated other inequality markers like gender
power differentials. This suggests a close proximity with postcolonial multiculturalism, which
376
See
Rita
Dahamoon,
Cultural
versus
Culture:
Locating
Intersectional
Identities
and
Power
(Paper
presented
at
the
Annual
Meeting
of
the
Canadian
Political
Science
Association,
June,
2004)
[unpublished].
377
Ibid.
179
also accords a strong emphasis on culture and collective identities, but without great concerns
they prevent intersectional practices from considering other loci of inequality. Unfortunately,
claims over survivors individual needs sabotages the very conception of intersectional feminism
as an emancipatory and critical feminist analytical tool. This is especially worrisome because
Sarah Song states that one of the most common criticisms of multicultural policies
are the objections raised against protections to minority groups that may come at the price of
reinforcing internal oppression of vulnerable members of those groups.378 Indeed, this critique
produced in what has been called by academic commentators the problem of minorities within
minorities or collective rights versus individual rights in multicultural theory. In her summary
of some of this criticism, Song notes that multicultural theorists have focused on inequalities
between minority groups and the wider society, particularly, arguing for special protections for
cultural minority groups, but such group-based special protections can, paradoxically, end up
exacerbating inequalities within minority groups.379 According to Margaret Moore, the drive for
this concern is the fear that ethnic minority elites will use group-differentiated cultural rights to
oppress or discriminate against their own vulnerable members such as religious dissenters,
378
See
note
362.
379
Ibid.
180
nonconformists, homosexuals, women, and children --- hence formulating policies that will work
to unfairly marginalize or discriminate against people who occupy positions that are at odds
with dominant or accepted cultural understanding.380 Ayelet Shachar calls this fear the paradox
of multicultural vulnerability, which draws attention to the less recognized costs of multicultural
Under such conditions, well-meaning accommodation by the state may leave members of
minority groups vulnerable to severe injustice within the group, and may in effect, work
to reinforce some of the most hierarchical elements of a culture. I call this phenomenon
the paradox of multicultural vulnerability. By this term I mean to call attention to the
ironic fact that individuals inside the group can be injured by the very reforms that are
designed to promote their status as group members in the accommodating, multicultural
state.382
protecting minority groups from oppression by the majority may make them more likely to
undermine the basic liberties and opportunities of internal vulnerable members. First, Moore
highlights what she calls positional or status diversity contexts.383 According to her, vulnerable
members of minority cultures, as in any cultural context, will occupy different positions within
that culture and the reality of the culture may mean discrimination against some people within
that culture. This concern has been primarily raised by feminist writers who point to the
patriarchal nature of many traditional cultures and the perils of cultural arrangements that can be
Second, Moore argues for philosophical or ideological diversity that is a source of concerns
related to the external conduct or self-advocacy stances of minority groups. As Moore explains,
this stance is concerned about questions of the dynamics of majority-minority relations within
380
See
note
367
at
273.
381
See
note
372,
Shachar,
Multicultural
Jurisdictions,
at
57.
382
Supra
note
at
3.
383
See
note
367
at
273.
384
See
note
372.
181
the state, and the tendency for the minority group to seek to appear unified, especial vis--vis the
Citing a previous work by Leslie Green, Moore remarks that there is a tendency
to minority groups in the state to exaggerate the extent of solidarity behind their particular
political program, because any dissent from it is likely to be interpreted by the majority group as
a sign of weakness, as a sign that compromise is unnecessary, that the elites are not
with certain cultural accommodations may find difficulties in conveying their own needs and
would also include in the typology womens self-imposition of conformist roles due to
lists, among others, the following examples of problems with minorities within minorities in
customary law within the dominant legal system, and self-government rights for Indigenous
feminism frequently arises in liberal postcolonial settings where dominant legal systems
informed by multicultural theories are prepared to adopt new alternative justice remedies and
customary Indigenous justice practices. With regard to self-government rights for Indigenous
communities, we can assume not only a commonality of themes and interests, but also of
385
See
note
367
at
273.
386
Ibid.
See
also
Leslie
Green,
The
Rights
of
Minority
Cultures
(New
York,
NY:
Oxford
University
Press,
1995).
387
See
note
302
and
accompanying
text.
388
See
note
362.
182
potential problems between the two approaches. If we can identify potential problems with
vulnerable groups within minorities in multicultural policies, we can also speculate about similar
strand of feminist thinking brings into discussion within the RJ field exactly the same questions
risen by multicultural theorists, i.e., issues related to Indigenous rights for self-determination and
problems derived from extreme anti-essentialist positions and cultural frame alignment strategies
of the RJ movement itself that also resonate with multiculturalism. For example, imbalanced
versions of intersectional feminism assign great worth to collective ethnocultural claims while
paradox of vulnerability occurs. This highlights how crucial multiculturalism is for the correct
concerning the perils around issues of diversity and internal minorities. Intersectional feminists
should be aware of these functional similarities concerning potential problems in order to be able
to avoid them within RJ settings, if necessary. In short, there is a coincidence of subject matters
and epistemic drives that suggest similar negative outcomes when multicultural policies and
imbalanced intersectional feminist approaches are present within RJ contexts. Indeed, this nexus
between intersectionality and multiculturalism should spawn further investigatory efforts and
questions in both research and practice. For the moment, it is sufficient to say that unbalanced
intersectional approaches on RJ programs are tied to multicultural initiatives and that the critique
183
of these policies may actually serve to shed some light on what can go wrong with intersectional
within the same analytical frame, particularly bringing into discussion themes of great
within Aboriginal settings feminist scholars have made laudatory references to intersectionality
analysis, while also emphasizing the need to incorporate this kind of feminist approach into their
scholarship. Restorative justice scholar Ruth Busch, for instance, argues that if restorative
experiences are to be used with domestic violence cases, it is imperative to have understanding
of intersectionalities of race and gender in the lived realities of battered victims lives.389 In the
same vein, Donna Coker argues for incorporating insights from critical race theory (i.e.,
intersectionality theory) in order to understand the intersecting oppressive systems that operate in
the lives of men and women in Indigenous communities.390 Moreover, Julie Stubbs points out
that an intersectional framework which acknowledges the multiple and indivisible operations of
race, class and gender may assist to examine how cultural practices work to sustain the power
differences between politics and practices which represent Aboriginal people but ignore their
gender or the reverse.391 Finally, Angela Cameron clearly states her commitment to
389
See
note
350,
Busch,
Who
pays
if,
at
224.
See,
e.g.,
note
314,
Sokoloff
and
Dupont,
Domestic
Violence
at
Intersections.
(Noting
that
the
incorporation
of
intersectional
approaches
to
domestic
violence
studies
is
a
classic
line
of
feminist
research.)
390
See
note
25,
Cocker,
Transformative
Justice,
at
129.
391
See
note
254
at
49.
184
intersectional thinking when she notes that either a cultural or sexist focus on judicially
Beyond this limited list there are, of course, other feminists and RJ scholars willing to give
implicit or explicit support to intersectionality analysis in RJ studies --- but none of them, I
would suggest, are prepared to push forward the epistemological and political challenges of the
This segment critically reflects on the above feminist stances bringing into
discussion not only positive, but also negative implications of intersectional thinking within the
theory has no negative implications clearly recognized by scholarly work, leading many
if they did not exist at all.393 To the best of my best knowledge, for example, this paper is the
first to problematize intersectionality theory within the context of RJ, domestic violence and
postcolonial Aboriginal justice. Because little or no research has been conducted directly
problematizing the concept of intersectionality within RJ and domestic violence settings, there is
a paucity of information to allow intersectional feminists to question their own political and
ideological commitments and how this affects their subjective perceptions of RJ initiatives. For
addition, intersectional feminism operates on the assumption that all interests, including
individuals membership within a particular group, can be adequately protected through the
392
See
note
2,
Cameron,
RJ:
Literature
Review,
at
29.
393
But
see
Rita
Dahamoon,
Considerations
in
Mainstreaming
Intersectionality
as
an
Analytic
Approach
(Paper
presented
at
the
Annual
Meeting
of
the
Western
Political
Science
Association,
20-22
March,
San
Diego.)
[unpublished].
(Expressing
fears
that
mainstream
intersectionality
may
end
up
reducing
an
understanding
of
difference
and
power
because
of
the
wrongly
perceived
but
widespread
idea
that
categories
can
be
fractured
into
never-ending
sub-categories.
Dahamoon
also
argues
that
the
prevalence
of
racism,
sexism,
homophobia,
disableism,
and
class
privilege
within
intersectionality-type
methods
will
mean
that
theoretical,
conceptual,
and
normative
linkages
that
challenge
the
status
quo
may
be
diluted
or
rejected
entirely.)
185
recognition of their needs as members of the collectivity. However, as we have seen, imbalanced
intersectional approaches can favor communal political interests of the majority, tainting the
women.
regarding the emptying out of the concept of intersectionality analysis due to its ubiquitous
witnessing a period of flattening the intersections and decoupling lives from political conditions;
and that intersectional analyses are being used to splinter social movements rather than create the
ground for varied groups to come together. 395 This position is also shared by Rachel Luft who
warning of the presence of multiple intersecting oppressions in such alternative justice projects.
However, there are also potential problems in some intersectional approaches that, ironically,
can serve to reinforce the very identity roles and patriarchal structures that intersectionality
394
See
especially
note
29,
Davis,
Intersectionality
as
Buzzword.
See
also
Leslie
McCall,
The
Complexity
of
Intersectionality
(2005)
30:3
Signs:
Journal
of
Women
in
Culture
and
Society.
(These
authors
provide
an
excellent
account
of
the
ubiquitous
influence
of
intersectionality
analysis
in
feminist
studies).
395
See
Kathleen
Guidroz
&
Michele
Tracy
Berger,
A
Conversation
with
the
Founding
Scholars
of
Intersectionality
in
Kathleen
Guidroz
&
Michelle
T.
Berger,
eds.,
The
intersectional
approach:
transforming
the
academy
through
race,
class
and
gender
(The
Univ.
of
North
Carolina
Press,
2009)
61.
(The
authors
in
this
chapter
organized
a
conference
call
between
the
founding
scholars
of
intersectional
theory
such
as
Kimberl
Crenshaw,
Nira
Yuval-
Davis
and
Michele
Fine
to
discuss
the
challenges
that
intersectionality
has
been
facing
in
the
academia
and
activist
circles).
396
See
also
Rachel
E.
Luft,
Intersectionality
and
the
Risk
of
Flattening
Difference
in
Kathleen
Guidroz
&
Michelle
T.
Berger,
eds.,
The
intersectional
approach:
transforming
the
academy
through
race,
class
and
gender
(The
Univ.
of
North
Carolina
Press,
2009)
100.
186
recognition of those roles and structures, since both of them can be obscured by the supposedly
and negative aspects of intersectionality as applied to RJ, an important omission since this same
feminist approach plays an important role in RJ models with a specific ethnocultural component.
In fact, as indicated earlier, there is a scarcity of related research that has examined
intersectionality as an analytical tool that pits gender inequality against culture as a worrisome
trade-off, e.g., with non-Indigenous feminists pushing for more equality and offender
Kathleen Daly who seems to be concerned with that delicate balance when she notes that
Indigenous groups (or the collectivity) emphasize offenders interests; while feminist groups
proposes what she calls an intersectional politics of justice that can be equally critical of the
conflicts and competing interests that emerge in the different sites of contestation between
As noted previously, Daly claims that the sites of contestation are the inequality
caused by crime (between victims and offenders), social divisions (race and gender politics), and
individuals and collectivities (rights of offenders and victims).399 She believes that it is possible
to respond to these inequalities in a way that is not necessarily a matter of a zero sum game, i.e.,
397
See
note
16,
Daly,
Seeking
Justice,
at
1.
398
See
note
16,
Daly,
Seeking
Justice,
at
8.
399
Ibid.
187
an intersectional analysis is capable of avoiding leveraging one site of inequality over the other.
While I would agree with Dallys contention that intersectionality analysis has the capacity to
address all the intersecting sites of inequality equally, I also believe that there are overlooked
imbalanced versions of intersectional thinking that can reinforce zero sum expectations or even
positions. Unlike Cameron, Daly and other intersectional feminists, I believe that intersectional
thinking within the RJ field can be misrepresented and appropriated to serve political
commitments not fully aligned with womens interests. More recently, even Kimberl Crenshaw
--- a seminal thinker in intersectionality theory --- recognized that, There's an imbalance in how
intersectionality gets used, mostly as a point of entry for gender but not as a point of entry for
race.400 She also observes that the differences between postmodernism, anti-essentialism, and
intersectional critiques are at the core of this imbalance generating, paradoxically, gender
underestimation.
in some intersectional approaches to RJ and domestic violence that slides towards gender
jeopardizes racialized womens positions by downplaying their need for security, offender
violence. In fact, I have noted in other parts of this paper that imbalanced versions of
interests not centered in the subjectivities and needs of racialized female victims of violence.
Such claims, needless to say, are the direct result of my previous articulation of the ubiquitous
400
See
note
392
at
76.
188
presence of intersectional analysis within RJ and postcolonial Indigenous justice and have great
significance on how racialized women are perceived and treated in RJ settings, including
sentencing circles.
advocacy (i.e., cultural frame alignment) and multiculturalism theory vulnerabilities (i.e., the
paradox of vulnerability). All these practical forces plus political issues mean that what is
women affected by multiple systems of oppression and privilege, simply does not play out in the
real world. Internalized ethnocultural political ideologies and distorted intersectional approaches
can then lead to collective unjust decisions and underestimated perceptions of battered women in
RJ settings, especially, when these women express some discomfort with ethnocultural
restorative practices. In fact, the pervasive influence of intersectionality analysis makes it even
more susceptible to distortions because its good reputation among feminists can hide or skew
Until this point all these claims were developed in this work in a merely
speculative and correlational way. But, it is also important to contextualize the reality of those
real restorative experiences that have the potential to jeopardize the lived experiences of women
intersectional approaches are capable of the emptying out of the concept itself. I start with some
clarifications on sentencing circles in Canada and Australia, just to address some issues left open
in the previous chapters. Having made such clarifications, I move on to identify in a synthesized
189
selected literature on sentencing circles in Canada and Australia some indications that
interests.
Three basic restorative models were initially described in chapter one: victim-
However, I will give attention only to the last-mentioned restorative model. Sentencing circles
are employed as a sentencing method that incorporates culturally sensitive guidelines with the
offenders. To be more precise, I am referring to what Cameron and Cunliffe call judicially
convened sentencing circles judgments, i.e., a form of sentencing practice that takes into
consideration insights from respected members of an Indigenous community (e.g., Elders) and
other stakeholders (e.g., victims, offenders and their families and supporters) that are literally
somehow connected to that community.401 The general functioning of a sentencing circle has
It is largely accepted that the first sentencing circle was held in the Canadian
justice system. According to several sources, in 1992, the then Yukon territorial judge Barry
401
See
note
8,
Cameron
&
Cunliffe,
Writing
the
circle,
at
12.
(Hereafter,
I
will
refer
to
judicially
convened
sentencing
circles
judgments
simply
as
sentencing
circles.
Although
sentencing
circles
has
been
used
either
principally
or
exclusively
to
Aboriginal
offenders,
there
are
accounts
of
non-aboriginal
people
with
a
connection
to
Aboriginal
communities
being
judged
in
sentencing
circles
schemes).
For
example,
in
R.
v.
Sellon,
172
Newfoundland
Supreme
Court
Trial
Division
(unreported)
(April
4,
1996).
See
note
13,
Goel,
Canadian
Sentencing
circles,
at
934-943
in
a
kindle
e-book
version.
See
also
note
176.
190
measures were fully justified and community participation incorporated into the sentencing
process, on policy grounds compatible with customary Indigenous traditions and RJ practices.402
Stuart articulated the principles of sentencing circles in the following passage of his decision:
Currently the search for improving sentencing champions a greater role for victims of
crime, reconciliation, restraint in the use of incarceration, and a broadening of sentencing
alternatives that calls upon less government expenditure and more community
participation. As many studies expose the imprudence of excessive reliance upon
punishment as the central objective in sentencing, rehabilitation and reconciliation are
properly accorded greater emphasis. All these changes call upon communities to become
more actively involved and to assume more responsibility for resolving conflict. To
engage meaningful community participation, the sentence decision-making process must
be altered to share power with the community, and where appropriate, communities must
be empowered to resolve many conflicts now processed through criminal courts.403
are seen in Indigenous and academic circles as legitimate attempts of redressing the colonial
exclusion of Indigenous people from legal and judicial decision-making.404 However, it should
be noted that the whole sentencing process occurs under the supervision and direction of an
official Judge, usually non-indigenous, who retains de facto power over the ultimate sentencing
outcome. This characteristic of sentencing circles has been a source of criticism from the
Indigenous community and some RJ academics. Dickson-Gilmore and Laprairie, for example,
argue that while the sentencing circle may contribute to an appearance of power-sharing, this
contribution is more illusory than real since the court retains both authority and jurisdiction to
impose whatever sentences the judge rather than the circle, decides or recommends for a
405
particular offender. Actually, sentencing circle experiences are entirely handled under the
auspices of the conventional legal system that also set clear limits on the sentencing outcomes. In
402
See,
e.g.,
note
13.
403
See
R.
v.
Moses,
[1992]
3
C.N.L.R.
at
118.
404
See
note
319,
Cunneen,
Reviving
RJ
traditions,
at
121.
405
See,
e.g.,
note
8,
Dickson-Gilmore
&
Laprairie,
Will
the
Circle
be
unbroken,
at
142.
(Anyway,
the
collective
adjudication
is
largely
respected
by
trial
judges.
191
Canada, for example, this type of restorative circle follows the provisions of the Criminal Code,
section 718.2(e), which calls on courts to consider all available alternatives to incarceration for
The exact numbers of sentencing circles held in Canada are sketchy due to the
lack of formal written records in some cases, but anecdotal evidence suggests hundreds in
several Canadian provinces.407 Cameron remarks that there are a considerable number of
ongoing sentencing circle programs in several Canadian jurisdictions.408 The numbers may well
be dozens, perhaps almost a hundred sentencing circles and this suggests large acceptance of this
specific RJ model in Canada. Within the Australian context sentencing circles are also largely
accepted. The version of sentencing circles practiced there is a blend of indigenous and imported
elements that consolidated itself in the period following the international expansion of RJ
practices in the early 1990s. To be more accurate, Kathleen Daly observes that sentencing circle
schemes were adapted from the Canadian experience and then imported into Australia in
1992.409 Marchetti provides more details on the implementation and operation of sentencing
circles in Australia. She notes that there are over 50 Indigenous sentencing courts operating
in all Australian states and territories, except Tasmania. These courts were first established in
urban centres in South Australia (the first was opened in Port Adelaide, a suburb of Adelaide,
406
Ibid.
(According
to
Cameron
and
Cunliffe,
before
the
provisions
of
the
Criminal
Code
the
judge
made
use
of
common
law
sentencing
powers
to
justify
sentencing
circle
schemes).
See
also
Criminal
Code,
R.S.C.
1985,
c.
C-46,
s.
718.2(e).
407
See,
e.g.,
note
8,
Dickson-Gilmore
&
Laprairie,
Will
the
Circle
be
unbroken.
408
See
note
2,
Cameron,
Literature
Review.
409
See
note
16,
Daly,
Seeking
Justice,
at
10.
(Unlike
Canadian
sentencing
circles,
Daly
observes
that
Australian
sentencing
circles
are
organized
as
a
regular
part
of
the
courts
sentencing
schedule.
Nevertheless,
Australian
sentencing
circles
like
they
Canadian
counterpart
do
not
enforce
customary
law,
but
ordinary
criminal
law.)
192
Australia on June 1, 1999) and today they operate under varied legislative frameworks and with
There are objective criteria recognized by case law in Canada to hold sentencing
circles. In R. v. Joseyounen Judge Fafard of Saskatchean Provincial Court established seven clear
criteria that are often quoted by subsequent case law and scholarly commentary:
(1) The accused must agree to be referred to the sentencing circle; (2) The accused must
have deep roots in the community in which the sentencing is held and from which the
participants are drawn; (3) There are Elders or respected non-political community leaders
willing to participate; (4) The victim is willing to participate and has been subjected to no
coercion or pressure in so agreeing; (5) The court should try to determine beforehand, as
best it can, if the victim is subject to battered women's syndrome. If she is, then she
should have counseling and be accompanied by a support team in the circle; (6) Disputed
facts have been resolved in advance; (7) The case is one which a court would be willing
to take a calculated risk and depart from the usual range of sentencing.411
In Australia, Potas et al. note that sentencing circles seek to incorporate the
following objectives:
(a) include members of Aboriginal communities in the sentencing process; (b) increase the
confidence of Aboriginal communities in the sentencing process; (c) reduce barriers
between Aboriginal communities and the courts ;(d) provide more appropriate sentencing
options for Aboriginal offenders;(e) provide effective support to victims of offences by
Aboriginal offenders; (f) provide for the greater participation of Aboriginal offenders and
their victims in the sentencing process; (g) increase the awareness of Aboriginal offenders
of the consequences of their offences on their victims and the Aboriginal communities to
which they belong; (h) reduce recidivism in Aboriginal communities.412
410
See
Elena
Marchetti,
Indigenous
Sentencing
Courts
and
Partner
Violence:
Perspectives
of
Court
Practitioners
and
Elders
on
Gender
Power
Imbalances
During
the
Sentencing
Hearing
(2010)
43:
2
The
Australian
and
New
Zealand
journal
of
Criminology
263281.
See
also
Elena
Marchetti
&
Kathleen
Daly,
Indigenous
Sentencing
Courts:
Towards
a
Theoretical
and
Jurisprudential
Model
(2007)
29
Sydney
Law
Review
415-443.
(Identifying
differences
between
Indigenous
sentencing
circles
and
RJ
experiences
while
recognizing
that
there
are
elements
in
common.
The
authors
also
provide
an
informative
table
describing
all
Indigenous
sentencing
courts
established
in
Australia
from
June
20006
to
January
2007.
In
addition,
this
table
includes
legislation
and
other
directives
that
governs
establishment
and
procedures
of
those
courts
in
all
local
contexts
where
such
experiences
are
applied).
411
See
R.
v.
Joseyounen,
[1996]
1
C.N.L.R.
182.
See
also
note
13.
412
See
Ivan
Potas;
Jane
Smart;
Georgia
Brignell;
Brendan
Thomas;
Rowena
Lawrie;
Rhonda
Clarke,
"Circle
Sentencing
in
New
South
Wales:
A
Review
and
Evaluation"
(2004)
8:4
Australian
Indigenous
Law
Reporter
73.
193
Judicially convened sentencing circles judgments provide the best empirical
framework for the identification of epistemic and political problems with intersectionality
analysis that may indicate possible damaging consequences to Indigenous women:413 This is
most notably because such models have been largely used to engage cases of intimate violence
in Indigenous settings.414 In fact, Goel notes that Canadian sentencing circles have been used in
domestic violence cases with Indigenous defendants for almost 15 years.415 In addition, they
have produced substantial analyses of feminist scholars committed to the two lines of
intersectional thinking: one more centered in collective ethnocultural political interests and the
other concerned with individual interests of battered women. The geographical context to be
considered is again mainly Canada and Australia.416 The rationale for this choice was already
clarified in previous chapters. But it is sufficient to say here that those countries are liberal
democratic systems that apply extensively hybrid justice constructs like sentencing circles, at the
same time seeking to assert Aboriginal rights for social justice and self-determination while
victim healing (i.e., through safety and empowerment) they also bring new preoccupations to the
413
As
earlier
noted,
the
harmful
consequences
flowing
from
imbalanced
intersectional
approaches
include
a
number
of
negative
positional
outcomes
to
victimized
women,
such
as
physical
and
psychological
re-victimization,
feelings
of
exclusion
and
alienation,
and
silencing
before
the
primacy
of
communal
interests.
414
Evidence
in
the
case
law
supports
this
claim.
In
Canada,
for
example,
Cameron
and
Cunliffe
compiled
the
following
cases:
R.
v.
Morris
(2004),
B.C.C.A
305,
186
C.C.C
(3d)
549
[Morris,
cited
to
C.C.C.];
R.
v.
Naappaluk,
[1994]
2
C.N.L.R
143
(Q.C.
(Crim.
Div).)
[Naappaluk];
R.
v.
Bennett,
[1992]
Y.J.
No.
192
(y.
terr.
Ct).
(QL)
[Bennett];
R.
v.
Charleyboy,
[1993]
B.C.J.
No
2854
(B.C.
Prov.
Ct.
(Crim.
Div).)
(QL)
[Charleyboy];
R.
v.
Green,
[1992]
Y.J.
No.
217
(Y.
Terr.
Ct).
(QL)
[Green];
R.
v.
H.K.C.
[1997]
S.J.
No.
577
(Sask.
C.A).
(QL)
[H.K.C.];
R.
v.
J.J.
(2004)
N.L.C.A
81,
192
C.C.C
(3D)
30
[J.J.,
cited
to
C.C.C.]
and
R.
v.
W.B.T.,
[1995]
132
Sask.
R.
221
(sub
nom.
R.
v.
Taylor),
3
C.N.L.R.
No.
167
(Sask.
Q.B.
)
(QL).
See
note
8,
Cameron
&
Cunliffe,
Writing
the
circle.
415
See
note
13.
416
In
fact,
Australasia
since
New
Zealand
will
be
addressed
as
well,
however,
in
a
lesser
degree
of
attention.
The
reason
for
that
is
simple.
Sentencing
circles
are
more
common
in
the
Canadian
and
Australian
contexts
while
in
New
Zealand
family
group
conferences
plays
a
more
dominant
role.
194
field of restorative justice. According to Goel, for example, there are unstated political goals and
implications in those particular RJ models.417 She argues that sentencing circles are backed
dispute resolution.418 Thus, sentencing circles adopt an ethnocultural approach in searching for
appropriate sentences for Indigenous offenders. The underlying premise when using sentencing
circles as part of such Aboriginal political projects is that they capture unique minority features
that can considerably affect sentencing outcomes. To fully understand these inherently political
variables and their effects on racialized women, we need to study them in a way that takes into
consideration such postcolonial discourses and the positioning of intersectionality theory within
identified in the literature as an important problematic topic in the field of applied restorative
imperialism and fracturing and destabilizing hegemonic epistemology, colonial structures, and
domination.419 She also argues that sentencing circles are consistent with postcolonial remedial
justice approaches. Such restorative experiences --- as multicultural policies --- call for
recognition and respect for diverse ways of life, institutions, values and cultures, while also
aiming to remedy the consequences of colonial marginalization like overincarceration and over-
emerging threat in those postcolonial additional goals of Indigenous people when using
sentencing circles. She questions whether or not communal ethnocultural political ambitions in
417
See
note
13,
Goel,
Canadian
Sentencing
Circles,
at
931-938
in
a
kindle
e-book
version.
418
Ibid.
419
See
note
8,
Adjin-Tettey,
Sentencing
Aboriginal
offender,
at
187.
195
sentencing circles have the potential to undermine individual victims' rights and safety. As she
puts it:
The process and outcome [of sentencing circles] can be influenced by community politics
in ways that undermine their transformative potential. Concerns that womens interests
and their need for protection might be compromised in some restorative justice initiatives
threaten to undermine their alleged goals since womens interests may be subordinated to
the interests of offenders and perceived community harmony.420 Brackets added
I shall return to this issue later, but it is pertinent to acknowledge since now that
the presence of intersectional approaches have an important role in the answers given to such
postcolonial feminists and Indigenous women to believe that sentencing circles and other RJ
experiences are always congruent with womens emancipatory values and needs, but the
interventions within Indigenous settings it might seem that this analytical frame would lead to a
unified perspective of the value and efficacy of such experiences.421 However, conflicting
and subjective evaluation of sentencing circles and other RJ models. Notably, it fostered
divisiveness among intersectional feminists and between non-indigenous and indigenous women.
Intersectional feminists, program participants and RJ activists with a variety of interests and
420
Supra
note
at
193.
421
See
note
30,
Hancock,
Intersectionality
as
a
Research
paradigm.
(Describing
the
notion
of
intersectionality
as
a
widespread
feminist
method
of
research.)
See
also
subsection
V
in
the
previous
chapter.
196
focuses produced different and sometimes clashing visions of restorative justice.422 In Canada,
for example, intersectional feminists and grassroots activists assessing sentencing circles were
polarized into two roughly contrasting groups. On the one hand, we can find a group comprised
of feminist legal scholars, indigenous and non-indigenous women and anti-violence activists
who place strong emphasis on the roles that gendered inequalities and power differentials play in
the implementation and operation of sentencing circles in domestic violence cases and that,
usually, project distrust and criticism on such experiences.423 On the other, a distinct group
comprised of feminists and mainly Indigenous women who tend to suggest favorable outcomes
of restorative sentencing circles due to their potential benefits for anti-colonial and antiracist
observed, these feminists and Indigenous women view race and culture, and the effects of
422
But
see
note
349.
(There
is
space
for
intermediary
positions
as
Proietti-Scifoni,
for
example,
has
suggested.
She
identified
a
three-way
typology
that
challenges
the
dichotomous
for
and
against
debate
in
the
literature.
According
to
her,
at
least
among
Aboriginal
opinion
leaders
in
New
Zealand,
there
are
supporters,
sceptics,
and
contingent
thinkers
regarding
the
appropriateness
of
using
RJ
in
cases
of
intimate
violence.)
I
concede
that
reducing
the
complexity
of
the
feminist
debate
over
RJ
in
only
two
diametrically
opposing
sides
is,
admittedly,
somewhat
of
an
oversimplification.
There
are,
of
course,
many
areas
of
both
actual
and
potential
agreement
between
the
sides,
and
it
is
possible
to
identify
more
nuanced
approaches
that
blend
aspects
of
each
position
among
feminist
scholars
and
participants.
However,
the
initial
claims
validity
remains.
Research
is
replete
with
studies
demonstrating
the
segregation
of
Aboriginal
and
non-Aboriginal
woman
in
two
conflicting
sides
concerning
RJ
experiences.
Likewise,
feminists
share
different
opinions
according
to
their
ideological
views
on
the
issue.
See
note
349
at
14.
(Listing
examples
of
empirical
literature
where.)
See
also
infra
note.
423
For
a
detailed
list
of
these
authors:
See
note
15,
Cameron,
Stopping
the
Violence,
at
53.
(Cameron
cites
several
authors
and
groups
that
explicitly
assume
such
position,
e.g.,
Mary
Crnkovich;
Carol
LaPrairie;
Emma
LaRoque,
Aboriginal
Womens
Action
Network
and
Kelly
MacDonald.
I
would
include
Cameron
herself.
[citations
omitted].
As
Angela
Cameron
explains,
This
group
of
writers
and
activists
employ
feminist
theory
and
methodology
alongside
various
Aboriginal
worldviews
on
gender
roles
and
equality.
Their
work
centres
on
the
particular
oppressions
faced
by
Aboriginal
women,
and
their
analysis
of
western
RJ
and
Aboriginal
justice
is
informed
by
feminist
and
anti-racist
perspectives.
They
speak
both
to
colonial
and
patriarchal
oppression
of
the
Canadian
state
and
the
oppression
of
a
powerful
male
elite
within
their
own
communities).
424
Ibid
at
55.
(Cameron
lists
several
Aboriginal
authors
and
non-indigenous
scholars
and
groups
as
well,
e.g.,
Patricia
Monture-Okanee;
Therese
Lajeunesse;
Ross
Gordon
Green;
Sharon
Perrault
and
Jocelyn
Proulx
and
the
Provincial
Association
of
Transition
Houses.
[citations
omitted].
She
points
out
that,
For
these
women,
Aboriginal
culture
(and
sovereignty)
is
the
primary
tool
to
be
used
against
colonialism.)
See
also
Sara
Mills,
Post-colonial
Feminist
Theory
in
Jackie
Jones,
ed.,
Contemporary
feminist
theories
(Edinburgh:
Edinburgh
University
Press,
1998)
98.
(Their
stances
are
directly
connected
with
postcolonial
feminism,
i.e.,
a
strand
of
feminist
theorizing
derived
from
mainstream
postcolonial
theory
which
centers
around
the
conception
that
racism,
colonialism,
and
the
long
lasting
effects
detrimental
(economic,
political,
and
cultural)
of
colonialism
in
the
postcolonial
setting,
are
inextricably
bound
up
with
the
unique
gendered
realities
of
non-white,
non-Western
women.)
197
colonialism and oppression on racialized groups as the primary lens though which to evaluate RJ
Although such literature pays attention to gender and gendered violence, race and culture
is prioritized, leading these commentators to conclude that restorative justice should be
used in cases of intimate violence in racialised communities. In their view, restorative
justice not only protects survivors from violence, it plays the very important role of
426
protecting racialised offenders from the state.
In other words, some feminists and indigenous and non-indigenous women may
attempt to employ intersecting inequality categories (i.e., gender, ethnicity, race, culture) as a
signal that intersectional thinking embraces, above all, individual gender inequality concerns in
RJ experiments; a signal most often relevant to victims of domestic violence who are prioritized
in order to stress their needs for security, empowerment and offenders accountability (e.g.,
through public denunciation). In contrast, other feminist scholars and mainly Indigenous women
--- who give primacy to political in nature ethnocultural claims --- may also attempt to employ
those same intersectionalities as a signal that they have prioritized collectivist interests (e.g.,
most often relevant to the political agenda of dominant groups within Indigenous communities
that seek to demonstrate their own fitness for culturally competent self-governance, particularly,
Similarly, within Australia, some feminist scholars and Aboriginal women seem
to give more attention to collectivist ethnocultural considerations rather than individual gender
inequality imperatives within RJ initiatives. Australian RJ scholar Henry Blagg, albeit not
writing from an intersectional feminist perspective, argues that the principle of self-
425
See
note
2,
Cameron,
Literature
Review,
at
30.
426
Ibid.
198
determination needs to be placed at the centre of restorative initiatives since it is a sine qua non
for the cultural and physical survival of Aboriginal people.427 His claim is echoed in the writings
intersectional explanation of the difficulties of Aboriginal men and women in RJ settings. For
example, Larissa Behrendet, Loretta Kelly (Aboriginal), Rowena Lawrie (Aboriginal) and
although recognizing the plight of Aboriginal victims of violence in the colonization process,
they identify their own core commitments to political autonomy and self-governance of
Aboriginal people, and then select from the existing intersectionalities those which are best
suited to give those commitments more expression.428 Just to illustrate, Behrendet contends that
the legacy of colonization will end only when Indigenous sovereignty is fully recognized by
former colonized states allowing, e.g., Indigenous people jurisdiction and decision-making
powers through the inherent right of self-government.429 She concludes pointing out that, ()
the principles of self-determination and empowerment need to guide any restorative justice
strategy that seeks to navigate and negate the dynamics and forces that encourage family
violence to flourish.430
427
See
Henry
Blagg,
Restorative
Justice
and
Aboriginal
Family
Violence:
Opening
a
Space
for
Healing
in
John
Braithwaite
&
Heather
Strang,
eds.,
Restorative
Justice
and
Family
Violence
(Cambridge,
UK:
Cambridge
University
Press,
2002)
at
199.
428
See
note
321,
Kelly,
Using
Restorative
Justice.
See
Larissa
Behrendet,
Lessons
from
the
Mediation
Obsession
Ensuring
that
Sentencig
Alternatives
Focus
on
Indigenous
Self-Determination
in
John
Braithwaite
&
Heather
Strang,
eds.,
Restorative
Justice
and
Family
Violence
(Cambridge,
UK:
Cambridge
University
Press,
2002)
178-190.
See
Rowena
Lawrie
&
Winsome
Matthews
Holistic
Community
Justice:
A
Proposed
Response
to
Family
Violence
in
Aboriginal
Communities
(2002)
25
The
University
of
New
South
Wales
Law
Journal
228-232.
But
see
Pam
Greer,
Aboriginal
Women
and
Domestic
Violence
in
New
South
Wales
in
Julie
Stubbs,
ed.,
Women,
Male
Violence
and
the
Law
(Sidney,
Sydney:
Institute
of
Criminology,
1994)
at
65.
(Arguing
the
safety
and
offender
accountability
should
be
the
primary
objectives
in
alternative
justice
experiences
developed
in
Australia
to
cope
with
domestic
violence.
She
has
noted
that,
While
too
many
Aboriginal
men
have
died
in
custody,
too
many
Aboriginal
women
have
died
in
their
communities.
In
two
States
more
Aboriginal
women
have
died
in
their
communities
than
all
of
the
total
national
Aboriginal
deaths
in
custody.)
429
Supra
note,
Behrendet,
Lessons,
at
190.
430
Ibid.
199
Even in empirical research on sentencing circles this commitment to the
than the immediate needs of women victims of violence. In fact, how intersectionalities (e.g.,
race, culture, gender) are addressed in empirical research can communicate powerful messages
about what is valued and devalued in certain intersectional approaches. For example, recently RJ
scholar Elena Marchetti conducted an empirical study in the Australian states of Queensland and
New South Wales, exploring the extent to which gendered power imbalances are present in
Indigenous sentencing court hearings concerning intimate partner violence offending.431 She has
noted that, A decolonising and critical race approach was adopted when conducting the
In practical terms, this meant that she shifted the focus from a mainstream
feminist binary-based explanatory model of domestic violence (i.e., female victim/ male
offender) to one in which intersecting systems of oppression and privileges were considered with
more emphasis. And inevitably, this also meant ethnocultural preoccupations with issues like
racism and colonialism and its past and present effects on the program participants surveyed.
Hence, Marchetti strategically focused her research process on analyzing how ethnocultural
insights from Elders and court practitioners could address power imbalances that can be present
during a sentence hearing for an intimate partner violence offence. Marchettis intersectional
approach, therefore, distanced her critical perspective from conventional issues of mainstream
431
The
study
was
conducted
in
2010.
Supra
note
408.
432
Supra
note
408.
433
Ibid.
(Marchetti
points
out
that
Aboriginal
sentencing
experiences
cannot
be
considered
restorative
justice.
However,
she
also
remarks
in
her
research
that
they
are
comparable
in
several
aspects
like
functioning
and
values.)
200
feminist exploration in domestic violence (e.g., gender inequality between victim and offender),
albeit these were not totally absent. Accordingly, she restricted the scope of her research by
interviewing only Elders and court practitioners instead of victimized women and offenders.434
the Elders and court practitioners the only representative cross-section of the Aboriginal
led to a biased representation of gender disciplinary norms, not only failing to capture the
existing heterogeneous perspectives, but worse failing to understand the versions that could
jeopardize marginalized community members like battered women. Consequently, the RJ and
intersectionality theory crucial task of giving voice to marginalized and oppressed women who
are battered was obscured by other collective intersectionalities like race, class, and colonialism.
Marchettis study overlooked the singular narrative accounts of victimized women to privilege
perspective of dominant elites in Aboriginal groups that naturally tended to favor collectivist
interests. Just to illustrate this point, in her research findings all Elders and court practitioners
434
Ibid.
(It
should
be
noted
that
Marchetti
recognized
the
need
to
interview
offenders
and
victims
in
future
research.)
435
Ibid
at
271.
201
interviewed were clearly favorable to the use of the Indigenous courts in sentencing offenders of
intimate partner violence. Although Elders and Indigenous and non-Indigenous court
practitioners recognized the existence of power asymmetries, they poorly addressed mechanisms
of power imbalance between victims and offenders and, therefore, potential detrimental effects
to victimized women in the circles were overlooked.436 The omission of victims perspectives in
feminists to political and ideological influences that result from ethnocultural collectivist views.
can efface womens positions in sentencing circles. Potas et al., analyzed 13 sentencing circles
cases in New South Wales Aboriginal communities. Similarly to Marchettis findings their
preliminary report suggested that Elders, offenders and Aboriginal communities see sentencing
circles as an unqualified success. As they have noted, In reviewing the effectiveness of circle
sentencing it has been difficult to find any real deficits.437 In addition, they observed that
436
Ibid
at
278.
437
See
note
410,
Potas
et
al,
Circle
Sentencing
in
NSW,
at
part
4.
438
Ibid.
202
Commenting on the above research, Julie Stubbs has observed that, although two
sentencing circles analyzed by Potas et al. were related to domestic violence cases, no mention
of any safety planning or follow-up with victims was suggested in the sentencing outcome.439
Actually, Stubbs noted that victims expectations were superficially addressed in the program
design. As she has noted, Most victims reported that they had been unclear about what to expect
and were unprepared for the emotional intensity of the process.440 In addition, she has observed
that the report gave strong emphasis to the role played by Elders in legitimizing the sentencing
process. As she put it, The Aboriginal Elders were seen as the greatest strength of the program,
instilling moral and values and lending authority and legitimacy to the process441 However, to
acknowledge the influence of Elders in the functioning of sentencing circles does not necessarily
mean that such participation is always positive to victimized women, especially because they are
the most important articulators of ethnocultural political claims within Indigenous settings. That
said, while Elders accord with the collective importance of sentencing circles in reaffirming self-
governance and autonomy in Justice matters they may not give adequate importance to the need
to protect victimized women from further harm. Womens voices remain silenced in the circles
due to communal tolerance to domestic violence, for instance. Actually, the accommodation of
ethnocultural political goals conveyed by Elders and respected persons, historically seen as
community mediators in Indigenous settings, may end up threatening even more the positions of
racialized women. In reality, within Canada, where sentencing circles have been studied for
twenty years, some feminist scholars like Goel; Adjin-Tettey; Cunnliffe and Cameron have
identified several negative effects of the political influence of collective ethnocultural claims in
439
See
note
6,
Stubbs,
RJ
and
Gendered
Violence,
at
1696-1703
in
a
Kindle
e-book
version.
440
Ibid.
441
Ibid.
203
Returning to insights devised by feminist scholars Rashmi Goel and Adjin-Tettey,
for instance, it is possible to develop a number of compelling arguments about the narrow-
minded biases and blind spots that an intersectional approach may have due to its interactions
with collectivists ethnocultural political commitments to Indigenous groups.442 Moving from the
functioning of RJ experiences within the Canadian context. As noted in the previous subsection,
Goel has argued that Aboriginal people in Canada through a history of colonial subjugation and
oppression come to apply restorative-like experiences with three specific political goals: 1)
to convey their philosophical and spiritual ideas and insights to internal and external audiences.
This means that historically constructed causes of societal problems in Aboriginal communities
can be denounced in sentencing circles by addressing issues like colonialism, alcohol/drug abuse
and endemic racism --- within and outside of the justice system. As she puts it, In other words,
the circle serves as an opportunity to highlight the victimization of Aboriginal people at the
443
hands of the majority community. Therefore, intersectionality theory depicts Aboriginal
people within RJ settings through a rhetorical mode of victimization, bringing into discussion the
colonial historic context, victim story-telling, and the semantics of oppression to challenge
442
See
note
13,
Goel,
Canadian
Sentencing
Circles,
at
1010-1016
in
a
kindle
e-book
version.
443
Ibid.
204
Another political goal is autonomy and self-governance. According to Goel, the
circle can also represent an opportunity to involve Aboriginal people with the control of their
own destiny. This means greater cultural and judicial autonomy for Aboriginal people. In
addition, the circle can also mean political integration, i.e., it may help to establish healthy
interactions between Aboriginal perspectives and Western justice. As Adjin-Tettey points out,
sentencing circles, () are seen to have better chances of rehabilitation, the reduction of
recidivism, and the promotion of a just, peaceful, and safe society.444 But circles political and
legal benefits have to be balanced against the risk of undermining womens positions. In the next
Rashmi Goel has observed that collective political goals can undermine the
effective function of circles in some sentencing goals. With respect to rehabilitation, for
example, she has observed that some circles spend considerable time discounting offenders
behavior by recounting their personal histories as victims of social injustice and acknowledging
colonial factors that contributed to it.445 As noted in a previous chapter, Goel points out that
sentencing circles can easily leave the impression that Elders --- who probably once experienced
racism and colonial injustice in their own lives --- can treat eligible offenders as less culpable for
their acts than non-Aboriginal offenders.446 Moreover, they can convey the notion that
conventional punishment is always inappropriate even when the offender can be considered a
repetitive or violent aggressor. In other words, the ethnocultural political approach of unbalanced
sentencing circles can compromise victims safety by having an excessive focus on offenders
444
See
note
8,
Adjin-Tettey,
Sentencing
Aboriginal
offender,
at
180-181.
445
Supra
note
440.
446
Ibid.
205
vindication and rehabilitation. Adjin-Tettey points out that a failure to account for and be
significant effect of further alienating women in particular and, more generally, hindering the
With respect to self-governance, Goes argues that the desire for autonomy and
empowerment can make Indigenous communities overestimate their ability to control offenders
and underestimate the resources required to operationalize RJ stated goals in relation to them. As
a result, offenders can see sentencing circles as an easy way out of harsher penalties --- and make
them more likely to enter in the circles with mental reservations. As she notes, This brings into
question not only the ability of the community to provide the necessary rehabilitative support
(Green 1998; Orchard 1998), but also the offenders genuine desire to change.448 Furthermore,
in line with the political ethnocultural narrative style of restorative circles, Indigenous
communities can see sentencing circles as a culmination of their anti-racist and anti-colonial
struggles. Here, however, sentencing circles function not as a symbol of an alternative justice
practice aiming to promote victims interests (i.e., security, empowerment and offenders
the overcoming of colonial hegemonic forces. As Goel puts it, Community input may however
447
Ibid
at
1043-1050.
448
Ibid.
206
be compromised by political goals. In particular the desire for self-government may force a
unified front, especially vis--vis the state. Some participants may concede with the positions
enunciated by Elders, even when at heart they disagree, so that the views expressed in the
sentencing circles may not always be the real view of community members.449
Finally, Goel argues that the communitys political goals can play a part in the
silencing of the womens individual histories, reinforcing the fact that the representation of
domestic violence survivors within sentencing circles has not been adequately resolved and
remains deeply problematic.450 She observes, for example, that women may be reluctant to
charge abusers because of the treatment Indigenous men receive within the conventional justice
system. In addition, self-government impairs a victims ability to advocate for herself. According
to Goel, in the Aboriginal way, women have a tendency to put the community before themselves.
This means that they go along with the community view of the correct sentence, even at the cost
of their own disparate opinions. As Goes has noted, Finally, the importance of supporting a
uniquely Aboriginal response to the problem is also voiced by community leaders, only
increasing the pressure on victims to toe the line.451 In other words, Indigenous women who are
victims of domestic violence can find themselves between two appealing choices: They are
wedged between a perceived need to advance their communal ethnocultural political claims in
the face of the state and the desire to express an individual identity and their perception of
449
Ibid.
(As
we
have
seen,
this
is
very
similar
to
articulation
of
the
paradox
of
multicultural
vulnerability)
450
Ibid.
See
also
note
8,
Cameron
&
Cunliffe,
Writing
the
Circle
at
18-20.
(Cameron
and
Cunliffe
have
observed
that
institutional
accounts
produced
by
trial
judges
in
sentencing
circles
decisions
also
attempt
to
rationalize
offenders
behaviour
and,
usually,
assume
an
apologetic
tone.
In
addition,
they
have
identified
through
a
review
of
case
law
that
issues,
aspects,
and
concerns
related
to
survivors
of
domestic
violence
within
sentencing
circles
were
disregarded,
poorly
addressed,
or
avoided
in
trial
records.
They
observed
that
survivors
can
be
absent
in
trial
judgements
records
in
three
ways.
As
they
put
it,
First
and
most
simply,
in
two
of
the
trial
decisions,
the
judge
makes
no
reference
whatsoever
to
the
presence
of
the
survivor
in
the
sentencing
circles.
Second,
in
several
decisions,
the
trial
judge
records
that
the
survivor
was
present
when
the
sentencing
circle
occurred
but
fails
to
describe
the
nature
and
extent
of
the
participation
or
to
record
her
words.
Finally,
the
trial
decisions
overwhelmingly
disregard
the
need
to
ensure
that
the
sentencing
circles
is
conducted
in
a
way
that
reassures
the
survivor
of
the
community's
concern
for
her
safety
and
emotional
well-being.)
451
Ibid
at
1084-1092.
207
themselves as a vulnerable group within a minority with which they share a history of
oppression. In short, Indigenous women are caught between a proverbial rock and a hard place.
through which feminist researchers have examined RJ initiatives. However, its importance
became more pronounced within Indigenous settings because of its resonance with postcolonial
and anti-racist claims embedded in RJs ethnocultural political discourses for self-governance
and autonomy. As also noted in previous subsections, some intersectional feminists interpreting
RJ experiences within Indigenous settings tend to be, above all, in the service of their own anti-
racist and anti-colonial critical views of the conventional criminal justice system and this can
take the form of uncritical validation of alternative RJ practices seen as more legitimate and
culturally competent. Although racialized womens positions are not fully secure against further
empowerment of the community and anti-colonial benefits are often present in such
in such cases proves to be much more essentialist than anti-essentialist in nature and direction.
culture without any qualification or interrogation of its usage and without reference to
overlapping and multiple aspects of cultural identity. As a matter of fact, intersectional feminists
with strong anti-colonial inclinations insist on treating culture as if it were synonymous with
political claims for self-determination and self-governance: In pursuing one the other is also
achieved, they seem to believe. In this simplistic view, the community life and collective
208
ethnocultural politics gain more space than the needs of survivors of domestic violence. Culture
gains primacy over individual rights and liberties. Hence, some intersectional feminists tend to
exalt culture and collective political gains in detriment of victims interests and needs that should
have been limited by a myopic reading of sentencing circle experiences. Although professing to
serve or represent a feminist cause or professing to be critical or transformative, they are actually
incapable of detecting and denouncing the preexisting patriarchal structures and power
asymmetries between offenders and victims that effectively silence and further alienate battered
women. The reason for that is rather simple. The political commitments that drive unbalanced
intersectional approaches shift from individual issues or grievances from victimized women to
collectivist political interests. This indicates that intersectional efforts may be channeled into a
feminist analytical tool with the paradoxical effect of making womens interests recede in
priority. Even if those collectivist ethnocultural interests can be considered legitimate --- and
essentially they are --- there is also a need to understand that battered womens individual needs
may remain unaccounted for, as we have seen above. This means that they remain subordinated
by gender disciplinary identity roles and patriarchal discourses that minimize or ignore the value
of placing the needs and views of battered women at the center of the RJ encounter, even though
such placement is an absolutely critical factor for ending domestic violence. In fact, there
interests not fully coincident with womens emancipatory aims. Below, I will further discuss
of intersectionality, with the caveat that this assertion is valid only where intersectional
disempowerment occurs.
209
e) Tendencies
to
co-optation
with a value base aimed at social justice outcomes. As a consequence, intersectional approaches
are inherently political in implication and emancipatory in purpose. This means that
scholarly methodologies to achieve sustainable pragmatic outcomes for the benefit of oppressed
women. Besides that, much of intersectionality theory potential for social justice stems from its
i.e., the uniqueness of a specific individual or group claim, even while this individual or group
may share inequality markers with other individuals or groups (e.g., domestic violence affects
differently middle-class white women, and poor, marginalized women of color). However, as
noted earlier, in some imbalanced intersectional approaches, the promotion of gender equality as
a form of intersectional justice has been sacrificed to a simplistic --- albeit rather pragmatic ---
approaches is a clear sign that co-optation and misrepresentation are increasingly --- and
insidiously --- emptying out the transformative and critical attributes of intersectional thinking.
politics is evidenced through a shift in declared goals. The original intersectional goals of
revealing socially and culturally constructed gendered categories of discrimination and privilege
appear to have been set aside in the name of postcolonial theory platforms and values. In this
context, as noted in the previous chapter, a new tension has emerged across intersectional
perspectives guiding RJ experiences. On one side we see feminists, often focused on the resolute
defense of womens individual concerns; on the other side feminists focused on ethnocultural
210
political agendas. By ethnocultural political agendas, I mean collectivist political interests (e.g.,
self-government and autonomy) that can potentially downplay antisexist priorities normally set
conventional feminist critical concerns for security, agency and offender accountability are
appeased through the appearance that such issues are being adequately addressed and, as a result,
pseudo-feminist stance. Such rhetoric suggests --- galvanizing political support from some
feminist perspectives --- that domestic violence is above all a sub-product of colonization
from the broader cultural and political history of which they are a part, domestic violence is also
a complex phenomenon involving much more than a colonial hangover. The above mentioned
intentioned one, may contribute even more to womens effacement within RJ settings through
the false perception that ethnocultural claims can ensure a meaningful place to women in RJ
panacea for domestic violence in Indigenous communities. Through silence and alienation, as we
have seen earlier, the intersectional feminist promise of political and personal transformation
proves to be an unfulfilled ambition since individual experiences of gender inequality and power
452
See
note
8,
Goel,
No
women
at
the
center,
at
299-312.
(According
to
Goel,
for
example,
colonialism
fostered
violence
against
women
in
Indigenous
communities
in
three
ways:
By
reducing
the
power
and
status
of
Aboriginal
women
by
stifling
the
values
and
traditions
which
protected
and
honoured
them;
stripping
Aboriginal
people
of
their
culture
and
proffering
European
values
in
return;
decimating
any
opportunities
women
had
to
hold
power
and
by
validating
violence
against
women
as
a
way
to
resolve
domestic
disputes.)
211
differentials within RJ settings are rendered invisible as they are folded into and subsumed under
intersectional insights being used to validate RJ experiences without careful consideration of the
implications of bringing into discussion such issues. As Luft and Ward have warned, The fact
that intersectionality has developed intellectual, political, and moral capital, however, has
created unintended consequences. The extent to which it has become a trend with leverage
means it is also being appropriated to less than intersectional ends.453 They also have observed
that, When not joined to intersectional practice, intersectional intonations function as a kind of
same mind with regard to the RJ social movement and ethnocultural cooptive processes, i.e., the
language of intersectionality can serve to convey political claims that are divorced from the lived
reality of battered women and, ironically, can be appropriated to veil hierarchical power relations
of domination and subordination, inclusion and exclusion. Such a trend does a disservice to the
transformative and social justice aims of intersectionality theory as applied to restorative justice.
Rachel Luft, who understood both the irony and the paradox of intersectional co-optation long
before other intersectional theorists, wrote, As more movement actors adopt intersectional
frameworks without substantive pursuit of intersectional aims --- whether out of naivet or a
453
See
Rachel
E.
Luft
and
Jane
Ward,
"Toward
an
Intersectionality
just
out
of
reach:
Confronting
challenges
to
intersectional
practice"
in
Vasilikie
P.
Demos
&
Marcia
Texler
Segal,
eds.,
Perceiving
gender
locally,
globally,
and
intersectionally
(Howard
House,
Emerald
Publishing
ltda.,
2009)
at
16.
454
Ibid
at
17.
455
See
note
394
at
103.
212
and practitioners are conscious of the cultural, social, political and other forces that contribute to
such tendencies of co-optation. Only this way can they also reveal key intersections between RJ
initiatives and the influence of other contextual factors like RJ cultural frame alignment, the
intersectional thinking that, as we have seen, predominantly situate Aboriginal women in the
awkward position of perpetuating their own oppression and subordination through the
In this subsection, I point out potential research implications drawn from the
subsection briefly examines the ways that RJ programs like sentencing circles are transplanted
from one geographical context to another. I highlight the example of sentencing circles in
Canada and Australia. In addition, I establish that intersectional disempowerment may also be a
potential problem when other countries marked by processes of conquest and colonization seek
to embrace the idea of RJs cultural competence without caution. I conclude arguing that
domestic violence and, therefore, about the risks of co-optation of intersectional approaches by
While RJ practitioners and activists have been active in Canada and the United
States since the 1970s, RJ scholars and advocates began to adopt transnational networking as an
advocacy strategy only in the early 1990s. Moving into the 1990s there was a rapid progress and
213
spread of RJ initiatives at an international level, especially with the promotion of restorative
models as less retributive, individualistic and more focused on collective responsibility. It was
estimated, for example, that by mid-2000s well over 100 countries used some form of restorative
practice in addressing criminal justice cases.456 However, as we have seen previously, the rapid
international growth of RJ initiatives resulted much more from advocacy strategies and grass-
roots efforts than strong empirical evidence supporting restorative promises. Actually, RJ
advocates lobbying efforts in the eighth (1990), ninth (1995) and tenth (2000) United Nations
congresses for the Prevention of Crime and Treatment of Offenders were those responsible for
the incorporation of the RJ social movement into the international arena with such visibility and
prevalence. In these congresses much of their work focused on educating international criminal
justice policymakers about RJ while lobbying UN members into lending their support to the idea
document that gathered in one place all basic policies for the use of RJ, i.e., the UN Declaration
of Basic Principles on the use of Restorative Justice Programmes in Criminal Matters.457 And
most importantly, the declaration also called for countries to specifically create laws and
programs to begin dealing with restorative justice. In short, that document allowed RJ advocates
to put their message on the agendas of several international policymakers and lawmakers. In
addition, RJ advocates formed transnational networks that multiplied their lobbying power
throughout the world. Nowadays, there are a number of associations of RJs practitioners and
NGOs like the Centre for Justice and Reconciliation at Prison Fellowship
456 Th
See
Daniel
Van
Ness,
An
Overview
of
Restorative
Justice
Around
the
World
(Paper
presented
to
the
11
United
Nation
Congress
on
Crime
Prevention
and
Criminal
Justice,
22
April
2005)
[unpublished]
457
See
David
J.
Cornwell,
ed.,
Criminal
punishment
and
Restorative
Justice:
Past,
present,
and
future
perspectives
(Winchester,
UK:
Waterside
Press,
2006)
at
114.
See
also
note
23.
(The
UN
Declaration
of
Basic
Principles
on
the
use
of
RJ
programmes,
also
calls
for
countries
to
specifically
create
laws
and
programs
to
begin
dealing
with
restorative
justice).
214
(www.restorativejustice.org) entirely dedicated to expanding RJ methodologies to every corner
of the world.
For this reason, RJ experiments have over the last two decades or more become an
increasing trend for international organizations and activists working on legal development
realities.458 Other professionals rushed to lead these workshops, given the growing demand for
specialists. Just to illustrate this trend, in Europe six international conferences on restorative
justice have been held since 1999. As Van Ness noted, In only twenty-five years, restorative
justice has become a worldwide criminal justice reform dynamic.459 There is no doubt RJ is a
developed by proponents and state partners in one setting and replicating them in another setting
with minor adaptations. As Cornwell has observed, citing insights from Robert Cormier, one of
different cultures while still adhering to its own specific principles and vision.460 In fact, RJ
processes are relatively easy to transport and apply in different settings precisely because the
458
In
fact,
my
first
personal
contact
with
restorative
justice
was
in
a
workshop
organized
in
Brazil,
my
home
country,
in
2004
by
a
visiting
mission
from
New
Zealand
composed
of
scholars
and
legal
professionals
involved
with
restorative
experiments
in
juvenile
justice.
On
that
occasion,
I
was
attracted
to
the
Indigenous
roots
of
restorative
practices
in
New
Zealand
and
the
culturally
competent
features
of
restorative
justice.
Being
myself
of
Indigenous
descent
and
with
an
interest
in
informal
justice
only
made
the
RJ
concept
more
attractive,
at
least,
as
a
first
impression.
459
See
note
451.
460
Supra
note
454.
215
processes of colonization, and its effects, are pretty homeogenous allowing similar
practice are sentencing circles, which were imported from Canada to Australia by RJ activists
and advocates and ultimately accommodated by the Australian state in its legal system with
minor changes. In particular, RJ experiences like sentencing circles have been heralded as
something that has successfully addressed the needs and interests of Indigenous communities
in Canada and Australia. As Cornwell has observed, the Canadian perspective bears remarkable
similarities to that from Australia and New Zealand in relation to the extent to which particular
ambitions and culture of Indigenous peoples have been afforded recognition within
considerations of criminal justice.461 As he puts it, This has, to some extent, opened the door to
wider application of restorative principles within the mainstream debate and the determination of
criminal justice policies and legislation.462 However, as we have seen, this process of
transplanting culturally competent RJ programs from one country to another makes it necessary
at times to align the feminist intersectional approach with the ethnocultural political rhetoric of
Indigenous dominant elites in order to attract support and gain legitimacy before the group, the
majority and the state. As a result, there is a blend of ethnocultural rhetoric and intersectional
feminists concerns within RJ experiences. But they can be blended so fully, that they also merge
into preexisting patriarchal and sexist relationships, where intersectional approaches may
colonization and with large populations of marginalized Indigenous people may be attracted to
461
Ibid
at
xvii.
462
Ibid.
216
embrace the idea of restorative culturally competent initiatives to deal with domestic violence.
As noted earlier, RJ activists and advocates have developed an efficient transnational network
preoccupied with the international promotion of RJ models. Indeed, RJ has over the last two
required. South America, my native region, is a prime example of a prospective market for RJ
experiences. In particular, because RJ methodologies are not yet fully incorporated or developed
into the legal frameworks of most of the countries of the region due to a variety of reasons such
as the historic reliance on retribution and punishment lately exacerbated by penal populism; lack
of social capital to organize communities around informal justice initiatives; resistance of legal
lack of funding and a Romano-Germanic legal tradition that does not allow the exercise of great
As a consequence, in the region there are only pilot projects mainly designed to
of RJ programs. Now RJ pilot projects are underway in Argentina, Colombia, Brazil and Peru,
where the idea is not employed for cases of domestic violence, despite some exceptions, and not
demand from Indigenous groups in countries like Bolivia, Brazil, Paraguay, Ecuador, Colombia
and Venezuela for informal and culturally competent adjudication methodologies in expectation
463
See
Pedro
Scuro,
Regional
Review
Latin
America
in
Gerry
Johnstone
&
Daniel
W.
Van
Ness,
eds.,
Handbook
of
Restorative
Justice
(Portland,
Oregon:
Willan
Publishing,
2007)
500-510
(This
Brazilian
author
provides
an
account
of
the
development
of
RJ
initiatives
in
Latin
America
under
a
sociological
perspective).
464
See
Willem
Assies,
Gema
Van
der
Haar,
&
A.
Hoekema,
eds.
The
Challenge
of
Diversity,
Indigenous
Peoples
and
Reform
of
the
State
in
Latin
America
(Amsterdam:
Thela
Thesis,
2000).(
More
recently,
Article
5
of
the
United
Nations
Declaration
on
the
Rights
of
Indigenous
Peoples
provides
for
the
right
of
indigenous
peoples
()
to
maintain
and
strengthen
their
distinct
political,
legal,
economic,
social
and
cultural
institutions
()
which
includes
217
experiences based directly in RJ methodologies currently functioning in the region, it is only a
matter of time until one of the countries of the region imports an RJ-like model to deal with the
specific needs of that ethnic group. However, as noted above, the formulaic incorporation and
political claims are present, may hide risks for victimized women within Indigenous settings. For
example, by perpetuating harmful and oppressive sexist practices within their own cultural
groups like communal tolerance to battering. For this reason, the notions of intersectional
political ethnocultural discourses within RJ settings are problems that policymakers and law-
makers in prospective RJ markets may want to address since the assessment of restorative
outcomes may vary according to the persuasion of those ethnocultural political claims.
The central thesis of this paper focused primarily on the problem of conventional
views of the use of intersectionality theory within the context of the RJ movement. The
introductory claim was that some intersectional stances could fail to address gender inequality ---
mainly within Indigenous settings --- and this resulted in misleading assessments of RJ
experiences as applied in cases of violence against women. In particular, the underlying question
was whether or not feminist intersectional critical analysis could be neutralized either by its own
present in the RJ field (e.g., RJ cultural frame alignment and ethnocultural political demands).
My research findings suggest that it can in both cases. The following paragraphs summarize key
justice
systems
compatible
to
Indigenous
perception
of
justice).
See
UN
General
Assembly,
Declaration
on
the
Rights
of
Indigenous
Peoples,
General
Assembly,
Res.
61/295,
UN
Doc
A/RES/61/295
(2007).
218
findings, at the same time suggesting some conclusions drawn from the study. I conclude making
some recommendations to prevent the problem of the neutralization of the critical attributes of
Initially, this study established that the RJ movement evolved from a complex
scholarship and political claims such as the social movements of the 1960s and1970s; the
victims advocates movement; penal abolitionism; the feminist movement and insights from
Indigenous and spiritual conceptualizations of justice. The result was a fragmented theoretical
and empirical movement with no general agreement concerning a unifying conceptual structure.
Indeed, as noted earlier, whether a process, outcome, or model is deemed RJ will likely vary
according to the ideological affiliations; theoretical background; ethnic identity, and even the
spiritual beliefs of the evaluator. In this sense, different RJ theorists and practitioners have
different conceptions of restorative justice. Thus, I have reached the conclusion that the RJ
definition is what William Gallie in 1956 called an essentially contested concept, i.e., we cannot
reach agreement about the criteria for its application because they combine a general agreement
on the abstract notion that the idea represent with continual disagreements about what they might
mean in practice.465 I have also argued that this lack of definitional clarity is not an impediment
various types of processes and outcomes, held together only by the following descriptive
elements --- though not necessarily present in all RJ models: 1) Crime is considered a harm
against individual and communal relationships; 2) no fact-finding judicial adjudication, i.e., the
465
See
note
53.
219
wrongdoer has admitted partial or total responsibility for offending; 3) problem-solving
conferences making room for the personal involvement of those mainly concerned with the
wrongdoing, i.e., the offender and the victim (or a surrogate), but also their families and
communities; 5) requires follow-up and accountability mechanisms for offenders and victims; 6)
the need for an holistic approach and; 7) It is hoped that the processes and/or outcomes will deter
offenders from further lawbreaking and provide some form of reintegration into the community,
although neither may really be achieved. In addition, a great diversity of models exists among RJ
initiatives, but in general they are summarized in the following: 1) faith-based victim-offender
(VOMs) programs; 2) family group conferences (FGCs) and restorative circles. Although there
are several eloquent accounts and anecdotal assessments of the positive impact of RJ models in
terms of victims satisfaction and offender reintegration into the community, little reliable
research has been done to assess the real impact of restorative practices on recidivism, criminal
justice, or offenders accountability. In fact, it is still unclear whether or not RJ practices are able
was originally conceived as part of a paradigmatic shift and, as such, represented a challenge to
the hegemonic discourse of the conventional criminal justice system in which was based on
retributive justice theories. Therefore, RJ --- at least in its early years --- could be described as a
radical social movement. This contention that RJ was a radical social movement is justified by
its initial orientation towards a fundamental change in the criminal justice system that
emphasized new protagonists in the criminal justice systems (victims, offenders and community
220
rather than a formal adversarial due process of law); and new principles and values (repairing the
harm rather than punishment); all of which were outside those already in existence in the
However, I also established that this claim was indeed a rhetorical device that
and the conventional criminal justice system, and specific components of retributive justice that
with some modifications could also be important elements of restorative justice. In reality, the
rupture with the conventional justice system and retributive (and deterrence) theory never come
to reality. As a matter of fact, contrary to what some RJ proponents prescribe, the most striking
feature of the contemporary RJ scenario is the intensification of its ancillary relationship with the
conventional criminal justice system, especially, through the use of restorative experiences as
advocacy strategy required to convert RJ proposals into something that could be more promptly
accepted by legal actors, scholars and the public who in general were disenchanted with the
conventional justice system. Most importantly, this stance of the RJ social movement led to a
people because of the idea that it contested the status quo --- the status quo represented by the
oppressing colonial criminal justice system --- increasing the willingness of individuals and
participants sensed a resonance in the making and understood RJ experiences fitting alongside
their own customary justice practices, albeit in essence this perception was only the result of the
cultural frame alignment of RJ as a social movement seeking space as a new alternative justice
221
system. Increasingly --- though scholars have differentiated between western RJ and those
justice experiences driven by Indigenous customary practices --- the so-called Indigenous Justice
and certain models of white-based restorative justice (mainly conference-based) have been more
difficult to distinguish from one another. In this context, the idea of RJ as a close relative to
presented Indigenous people at the heart of decision-making in justice initiatives. However, this
history of Aboriginal people in Canada and Australasia, but de-emphasized the role of the
summary of RJ critique, I have developed the notion of two great lines of reasoning that
challenged the RJ movement. The first category grouped criticisms around themes related to the
notion of RJ as a paradigmatic shift. They are directly tied to a set of arguments challenging the
questionable and manicheist opposition between restorative justice (depicted as good and
virtuous), and retributive justice (depicted as inherently bad) in the RJ proactive advocacy
manipulative in various ways towards stakeholders and especially victims. Notably, through the
and victims and, as critics have pointed out, by leaving power differentials and social, racial and
In this sense the R. v. Naappaluk case provides a clear example of how ethno-
cultural political references can shape a restorative encounter in detrimental ways to victimized
222
women.466 This RJ encounter was the first judicially convened sentencing circle held in an Inuit
community in 1994 and was witnessed at first hand by feminist researcher Mary Crnkovich. She
had no doubt that she had witnessed a political contrived acting that was essentially negative to
women. According to her, there was no concrete connection to the victim 's life since all the
discussion was conveyed by the personal narrative strands of the Elders, the Judge and the
offender and its supporters, who seemed to be more interested in the advantages of Indigenous
justice than real life consequences to the female victim. Indeed, she observed that the female
victim felt isolated by an intimidating focus on the offender and community political interests.
She noted, for example, that the victim had had very few supporters and spoke only three times -
--when requested by the judge and Elders to do so--- during the entire restorative encounter.
Moreover, all the moral support lent by the circle was channeled to the offender benefit rather
than the victim empowerment. At least one political leader present in the circle expressed only
the concerns and wishes of the community. For these reasons, she concluded that the circle
outcomes were too pat and the focus highly suspect and those who cared for the victim had been
The Sentencing Circle may have imposed an even greater silence. The circle was the first
of its kind, being supported by the Judge and Inuit leaders. If she spoke out about further
abuses or her dislike of this sentence, what would she be saying about this process every
one supported? Now, in addition to fearing her husband's retribution, she may fear by
speaking out against the community. The sentence created in this circle is one endorsed
not only by the mayor and other participants but by the judge and a highly respected Inuit
politician. The pressure to not speak out against a sentencing alternative supported by so
many is great. The victim may be afraid to admit she is being beaten [in later counselling
sessions] because such an admission, she may fear, may be interpreted as a failure of this
process. She may hold herself to blame and once again continue to suffer in silence.467
466
See
R.
v.
Naappaluk
note
414.
(Jusip
Naappaluk
had
plead
guilty
of
assaulting
his
wife
Kullutu
Naappaluk.
It
was
Mr.
Naappalucks
fourth
formal
charge,
but
he
admitted
informally
to
the
circle
several
other
assaults
to
his
wife.
No
imprisonment
was
suggested
and
Mr.
Naappaluk
was
put
on
probation
under
the
supervision
of
the
community).
See
also
note
13,
Goel,
Canadian
Sentencing
circles,
at
72-74.
467
See
Mary
Crnkovich,
A
Sentencing
Circle
(1996)
Journal
of
Legal
Pluralism
36
159-181
at
172-173.
223
The second category of criticisms was concerned with RJ as an appendage of the
contradiction at the core of the RJ movement, i.e., its practical functioning as an adjunct of the
conventional criminal justice system rather than a replacement for it. Many critics, for example,
raised objections related to the rule of law, legal principles and due process of law such as lack
of punishment in general terms (deterrence, rehabilitation, public safety and retribution); the lack
of independent legal advice; pressures to admit an offence to obtain the benefit of a diversionary
alternative to court and the avoidance of a criminal record; the lack of testing of the legality of
police procedures, questioning and evidence-gathering and, finally, the privation of the
offenders liberty in the case of him failing with sentencing circles adjudication and probation
conditions (double jeopardy claims). Finally, I have identified an important body of literature
concerned with a postmodern and feminist critique of restorative justice. In particular, the
postmodern critique advanced many negative impacts of current experiences with restorative
justice like battered womens effacement and the danger of overlooking preexisting power and
status differentials in cases of domestic violence. These critical stances have drawn from the
Foucauldian notion of disciplinary mechanisms to argue that restorative programs are ultimately
system-supporting schemes, i.e., mediators or community members facilitate agreements that are
consistent with status quo ante interests, values, norms, and other ideological and political
interests.
Furthermore, given that the RJ movement since its inception is deeply rooted in
feminist thought and activism --- with a particular focus on violence against women ---, the
feminist critique is a sine qua non part of any account of debates on restorative justice. As a
consequence, this paper also considered the role of feminist theory and criminology and their
connections with the RJ movement, arguing that the feminist critical analysis on RJ sought to
224
add women and gender perspectives to RJ practices and was marked by efforts to ensure a safe,
feminist commentators and researchers have advanced concerns related to the harmful effects of
ineffective security and empowerment to women in restorative encounters and conferences that
lead to revictimization issues. Most notably, the mainstream feminist critique established that
restorative dialogue-driven processes and outcomes have the potential to disregard and silence
women by keeping them absent from forums that settle the planning and functioning of RJ
models, which feminists deem to be excessively skewed towards male offenders needs and
interests. Indeed, it is generally agreed that RJ programs on intimate violence should only be
undertaken with certain conditions present, such as strong offender accountability mechanisms;
and basic guarantees of free communication and transparency. However, given the informal and
fragmented nature, form, and implementation of RJ experiences this rarely occurs. For this
reason, mainstream feminists claimed that the informal arrangements of RJ practices and strong
collectivist views of what constitutes a restorative encounter or conference could mean that
women are treated in ways that may reproduce or perpetuate victimization and collective gender
normative stereotypes as seems to be the particular case of some RJ practices used in Aboriginal
settings.
thinking with respect to RJ and emphasized the importance of examining the various schools of
feminist thought from essentialist to anti-essentialist feminist schools. After describing the most
salient examples of essentialist and anti-essentialist feminist schools, I have reached the
225
Indigenous settings. First of all, I have identified intersectionality theory as a new way to
political issues into the debate about alternative justice remedial practices developed to cope
with violence against women. In addition, I have argued that intersectional approaches also
transformed the intellectual landscape by generating polarized and politicized views of the
have argued that the politicized rhetoric was not prevalent among intersectional feminists and
several intersectional feminists remained skeptical about the efficacy of RJ to cope with
intersectionality theory tended, as described in this chapter, to generate a sympathetic rather than
structurally critical response to gender inequality issues of restorative justice. That sympathetic
nature towards RJ overlooked womens alienation and exclusion within RJ experiences, which is
to follow collective directives favorable to RJ interventions even at the cost of their expression
and security. This raised a dilemma for battered women in Indigenous communities since they
were cornered into taking stances that would either make them betray their own community ---
eager to assert self-determination in justice matters through RJ interventions --- or betray their
own interests and needs for security, offender accountability and empowerment.
theory --- among other characteristics --- is built on the interplay among diverse and sometimes
competing inequality markers such as gender; race; class; culture; and ethnicity. For this reason a
equal basis without giving primacy to a specific inequality marker in explaining systems of
oppression like male violence against women. However, I also concluded that an imbalance in
226
anti-essentialist positions in some intersectional approaches tended to take insufficient account
settings. In this sense, I have identified an epistemological vulnerability caused by radical anti-
essentialist stances that can render some intersectional approaches to RJ virtually incapable of
addressing gender inequality properly. This vulnerability --- that consists of an under-
appreciation of gender inequality issues ---- and, consequently, the difficulties that confront
form of intersectional disempowerment where womens concerns are put aside in order to
cooptative forces --- namely, a) RJ cultural frame alignment; b) the rise of ethnocultural political
Canada and Australasia --- that helps to explain why some intersectional approaches are unlikely
tackle the epistemic problem at its source, i.e., by adopting strategically essentialist positions that
ethnocultural and sexist settings. As I hope I have shown, some intersectional approaches to RJ
have developed epistemic problems and an ethnocultural political inflection that downplays
gender issues. This is weakening an analytical structure that is already under attack from other
Indigenous settings is too linked to postcolonial discourses, contingent multicultural rhetoric and
227
short-term anti-racist objectives that shifted the focus from womens issues. Thus, the sensible
intersectionality theory is to forge ahead in providing a safe and meaningful space to Indigenous
battered women within the RJ movement, it is essential that researchers work closely with RJ
practitioners to develop, implement, and analyze methods and programs that can be shown to
benefit, above all, victimized women not other political interests. In the next paragraph I advance
some recommendations for improving the use of intersectionality theory within RJ contexts.
analytical intersectional standard in RJ interventions.468 She identified --- like in this study ---
that there has been little consultation between victimized women and antiviolence groups, which
are not sufficiently heard or taken into consideration. For this reason she recommended
comprehensive consultations with those actors before, during and after RJ encounters and
encourage a sense of control, and foster an equal exchange of information among all the
RJ initiatives which accept cases of domestic violence must be evaluated as soon as possible
the same opinion, especially to avoid inadequate outcome measures (e.g., to measure
468
See
note
11
at
199.
469
Ibid
at
200.
228
stakeholders satisfaction) and short follow-up periods, which limit the value of empirical
evidence collected in such investigations. I would also include putting women in leadership
order to avoid offender-centered stances and the unwillingness to value the needs and visions of
battered women.
simply to convert the sympathy for the RJ movement that multiculturalism and ethnocultural
political claims elicit from the intersectional evaluator into a critical orientation towards specific
inequality issues like gender injustice since those concerns are embedded in the intersectional
thought on restorative justice. Notably, because they stem from legitimate concerns over
decision-making policies, or from the unfair treatment of Indigenous people. But it is perfectly
possible to steer the debate to more women-centered positions by reintroducing the social fact
that gender inequality matters most in domestic violence cases. Although intersectionality at its
believe we cannot rescind from the strategic use of gender-issues, politically and pragmatically,
within RJ experiences. As Rachel E. Luft wrote: Movement actors with intersectional analysis
and commitments have to manage the effects of their own dominant and subordinate identities,
and the competing directives that a solidarity politics bases on each suggests, as the navigate a
field of shifting allies, opponents, and power dynamics in a context of a larger, macro structural
within Indigenous settings are vulnerable to at least two objections: First, epistemological issues
470
See
note
451
at
32.
229
that deemphasize gender inequality. Second, cooptive mechanisms that also tend to shift the
focus away from womens issues, most notably, when intersectional feminists contend with
domestic violence in RJ contexts. However, intersectional frames are supposed to come with
strong critical and social change goals. At its essence intersectionality may function as the most
critical step in ending or limiting domestic violence by revealing systems of oppression and
privilege in heterogeneous settings. It can act instrumentally and substantially to reveal sexist
culturally heterogeneous communities that can perpetuate or reproduce sexist gender roles.
Responding to this dilemma, this study sought to serve as a cautionary note. By this I mean that
close attention must be paid to the intersectional thinking that emerges in RJ settings since it can
backfire on the very individuals and groups it was designed to protect and emancipate.
230
Bibliography
Abel, Richard L., ed., The Politics of Informal Justice (New York: Academic Press, 1982) Vol. I
& II.
Alcoff, Linda. Cultural Feminism versus Post-Structuralism: The Identity Crisis in Feminist
Theory (1988) Signs 13:3
Alcoff , Linda & Elizabeth Potter. Feminist Epistemologies (New York: Routledge, 1993)
Austl., W.A., Law Reform Commission of Western Australia, Aboriginal Customary Laws: The
interaction of Western Australian law with Aboriginal law and culture (Final Report No.94) by
Commissioner AG Braddock (Perth: Quality Press, 2006)
Arrigo, Bruce A. & Robert C. Schehrb. Restoring justice for juveniles: A critical analysis of
victim offender mediation (1998) 15:4 Justice Quarterly 629-666
Ashworth, Andrew. Some doubts about Restorative Justice (1993) 4:2 Criminal Law Forum
277-299.
Baehr, Amy R. Liberal Feminism The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy (Fall 2008
Edition), Edward N. Zalta (ed)., online: (2010)
<http://plato.stanford.edu/archives/fall2008/entries/feminism-liberal/> retrieved on April 2010.
Bailey, Alison. On Intersectionality and White Feminist Philosophy SSRN (29 September
2008), online: Available at SSRN: http://ssrn.com/abstract=1334786
Bazemore, Gordon & Lode Walgrave. Restorative juvenile justice: In search of fundamentals
and an outline for systemic reform in G. Bazemore & L. Walgrave , eds., Restorative juvenile
justice: Repairing the harm of Youth Crime (Monsey, NY: Criminal Justice Press, 1999)
Behrendet, Larissa. Lessons from the Mediation Obsession Ensuring that Sentencig
Alternatives Focus on Indigenous Self-Determination in John Braithwaite & Heather Strang,
eds., Restorative Justice and Family Violence (Cambridge, UK: Cambridge University Press,
2002)
231
Benhabib, Seyla. Situating the self : gender, community, and postmodernism in contemporary
ethics (New York: Routledge, 1992).
Bianchi, Herman. Tsedeka Justice (1973), Review for Philosophy and Theology 306-317.
Bianchi, Herman. Justice as Sanctuary: Toward a New System of Crime Control (Bloomington:
Indiana University Press, 1994
Blagg, Harry. A Just Measure of Shame? Aboriginal Youth and Conferencing (1997) 37:4
Australia British Journal of Criminology 481-501
Blagg, Henry. Restorative Justice and Aboriginal Family Violence: Opening a Space for
Healing in John Braithwaite & Heather Strang, eds., Restorative Justice and Family Violence
(Cambridge, UK: Cambridge University Press, 2002)
Blagg, Harry. A new way of doing justice business? Community justice mechanisms and
sustainable governance in Western Australia (2005) State Solicitors Office, Background Paper
No. 8. Perth: Law Reform Commission of Western Australia
Blagg, Harry. Crime, Aboriginality and the Decolonization of Justice (Sidney: Hawkins press,
2008)
Burgess-Proctor, Amanda. Intersections of Race, Class, Gender, and Crime: Future Directions
for Feminist Criminology (2006) 1 Feminist Criminology 7
Braithwaite, John. Crime, Shame and Reintegration (New York, NY: Cambridge University
Press, 1989)
Braithwaite, John & Philip Petit. Not Just Deserts: a Republican Theory of Criminal Justice
(Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1990)
Braithwaite, John & Kathleen Daly. Masculinities, Violence and Communitarian Control in
Tim Newburn and Elisabeth A. Stanko, eds., Just Boys Doing Business? Men, Masculinities, and
Crime (London: Routledge, 1994) 189-213
Braithwaite, John. Restorative Justice: Assessing Optimistic and Pessimistic Accounts (1999)
25 Crime and Justice 1-127
Braithwaite, John. Restorative Justice and Responsive Regulation (New York: Oxford University
Press, 2002)
Braithwaite, John. Principles of Restorative Justice, in A. Von Hirsch, et al. ,eds, Restorative
Justice: Competing or Reconcilable Paradigms?, (Portland, OR: Hart Publishing, 2003)
232
Brzozowski, Jodi-Anne et al. Victimization and offending among the Aboriginal population in
Canada. (2006) 26:3 Juristat. Statistics Canada Catalogue no. 85-002-XIE
Busch, Ruth & Stephen Hooper. Domestic Violence and Restorative Justice Initiatives: The
Risks of a New Panacea. Waikato Law Review (1996) 4:188
Busch, Ruth. Domestic Violence and Restorative Justice Initiatives: Who Pays if we Get it
Wrong? in Heather Strang & John Braithwaite, eds., Restorative Justice and Family Violence
(Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2002) 223-48
Cameron, Angela. Gender, Power and Justice: A Feminist Perspective on Restorative Justice
and Intimate Violence (LL.M. Thesis, University of British Columbia, 2003) [unpublished]
Cameron, Angela. Sentencing circles in cases of intimate violence: discipline, space and law
(Paper presented to the International Round Table for the Semiotics of Law, 16 April 2005)
[Unpublished].
Cameron, Angela. Restorative Justice: A Literature Review (Paper presented to the British
Columbia Institute Against Family Violence, 2005) [unpublished]
Cameron, Angela & Emma Cunliffe. Writing the Circle: Judicially Convened Sentencing
circles and the Textual Organization of Criminal Justice (2007) 19:1 Canadian Journal of
Women and the Law 1-35
Cameron, Angela. Stopping the Violence: Canadian Feminist Debates on Restorative Justice
and Intimate Violence (2006) 10 Theoretical Criminology
Cahill, Michael T. Retributive Justice in the Real World (2007) 85 Washington University
Law Review 815
Capeheart, Loretta & Dragan Milovanovic. Social justice: theories, issues, and movements
(Piscataway, NJ: Rutgers University Press, 2007)
Cheon, Aileen & Cheryl Regehr. RJ Models in Cases of Intimate Partner Violence: Reviewing
the Evidence (2006) 1:4 Victims & Offenders 369-394
Christie, Nils. Conflicts as Property (1977) 17:1 British Journal of Criminology 1-15
Cook, Kim. A Restorative Justice Critique of Shelters for Battered Women in the American
Deep South Center Prison Fellowship International Centre for Justice and Reconciliation, on
line (26 August 2006): Restorative Justice On line:
<http://www.restorativejustice.org/10fulltext/cook/view/> Retrieved on March 2010.
233
Cook, Kimberly J. et al., Introduction Special Issue (2006) 10:1 Theoretical Criminology 5-
7
Coker, Donna. Enhancing Autonomy for Battered Women: Lessons from Navajo Peacemaking
(1999) 47: 1 UCLA Law Review 111
Coker, Donna. Crime Control and Feminist Law Reform in Domestic Violence Law: A Critical
Review (2001) 4 Buffalo Criminal Law Review 801-860
Coker, Donna. Restorative justice, Navajo Peacemaking and domestic violence (2006) 10:1
Theoretical Criminology 67-85
Cornwell, David J., ed., Criminal punishment and Restorative Justice: Past, present, and future
perspectives (Winchester, UK: Waterside Press, 2006)
Cornwell, David J. & Heather Strang. The Penal Crisis and the Clapham Omnibus: Questions
and Answers in Restorative Justice (Hampshire, UK: Waterside Press, 2009)
Coward, Stephanie. Restorative Justice in Domestic and Sexual Violence: Healing Justice?
(December 2000) Directed Interdisciplinary Studies, Carleton University
Crawford, Adam & Todd Clear. Community justice: Transforming communities through
restorative justice? in Gordon Bazemore & Mara Schiff, eds., in Restorative Community
Justice: Repairing Harm and Transforming Communities (Otawa: Anderson Publishing, 2001)
Crenshaw, Kimberl. Demarginalizing the Intersection of Race and Sex: A Black Feminist
Critique of Antidiscrimination Doctrine, Feminist Theory, and Antiracist Politics (1989) 14
University of Chicago Legal Forum, 538-54
Crenshaw, Kimberl. Mapping the Margins: Intersectionality, Identity Politics, and Violence
against Women of Color (1991) 43:6 Stanford Law Review 1241-1299
Crnkovich, Mary. Report on the Circle Sentencing in Kangiqsujuaq (Paper presented to for
Pauktuutit and Department of Justice, Canada, 1993) Inuit Women and Justice: Progress Report
Number one [unpublished]
Cunneen, Chris. Thinking Critically about Restorative Justice in Eugene McLaughlin et al.,
eds., Restorative Justice: Critical Issues (Thousand Oaks, CA: Sage Publications, 2003)
234
Cunneen, Chris. Restorative Justice and the Politics of Decolonization in Elmar G.M.
Weitekamp & Han-Jurgen Kerner, eds., Restorative Justice: Theoretical Foundations (Deon,
UK: Willan Publishing, 2002) 32-49
Cunneen, Chris. What are the Implications of RJs Use of Indigenous Traditions? in Howard
Zehr & Barb Toews, eds., Criticial Issues in Restorative Justice (Monsey, New York: Criminal
Justice Press, 2004) 345-353
Cunneen, Chris. Reviving Restorative Justice Traditions? in Gerry Johnstone and Daniel W.
Van Ness, eds. Handbook of Restorative Justice (Mill Street, Uffculme: Willan Publishing,
2007)
Curran, Daniel J. & Claire M. Renzetti. Theories of crime (Needham Heights, MA: Allyn &
Bacon, 2001)
Dahamoon, Rita. Cultural versus Culture: Locating Intersectional Identities and Power
(Paper presented at the Annual Meeting of the Canadian Political Science Association, June,
2004 Vancouver) [unpublished].
Daly, Kathleen & Russ Immarigeon. Restorative Justice: Origins, Practices, Contexts, and
Challenges" (1997) August ICCA Journal on Community Corrections 1-17
Daly, Kathleen & Russ Immarigeon. The Past, Present, and Future of Restorative Justice: Some
Critical Reflections (1998) 1:1 The Contemporary Justice Review 21-45
Daly, Kathleen. Restorative Justice in Diverse and Unequal Societies (2000) 17:1 Law in
Context
Daly, Kathleen. Revisiting the relationship between retributive and restorative justice in
Heather Strang & John Braithwaite ,eds., Restorative justice, from philosophy to practice
(Aldershot: Dartmouth, 2000)
Daly, Kathleen. Conferencing in Australia and New Zealand: Variation, Research Findings, and
Prospects in Allison Morris & Gabrielle Maxwell, eds., Restorative Justice for Juveniles:
Conferencing, mediation and circles (Oxford, UK: Hart Publishing, 2001)
Daly, Kathleen. Restorative justice: The Real Story (2002) 4 Punishment & Society 55-79
Daly, Kathleen. Mind the Gap: Restorative Justice in Theory and Practice in A. Von Hirsh et.
al, eds., Restorative Justice and Criminal Justice (Oxford: Hart Publishing, 2004)
235
Daly, Kathleen & Sarah Curtis-Fawley. Gendered Violence and Restorative Justice: The Views
of Victim Advocates" (2005) 11 Violence Against Women 603
Daly, Kathleen & Sarah Curtis-Fawley. Justice for Victims of Sexual Assault in Karen Heimer
& Candace Kruttschnitt, eds., Gender and Crime: Patterns of Victimization (New York: New
York University Press, 2005).
Daly, Kathleen. The Limits of Restorative Justice in Dennis Sullivan & Larry Tifft ,eds., The
Handbook of Restorative Justice: A Global Perspective (New York, NY: Routledge, 2006)
Daly, Kathleen & Julie Stubbs. Feminist Engagement with RJ (2006) 10:1 Theoretical
Criminology 9-28
Daly, Kathleen. Restorative Justice and Sexual Assault: An Archival Study of Court and
Conference Cases (2006) 46:2 The British Journal of Criminology
Daly, Kathleen & Julie Stubbs. Feminist Theory, Feminist and anti-racist politics and
Restorative Justice in Gerry Johnstone & Daniel W. Van Ness, eds., Handbook of Restorative
Justice (Portland, Oregon: Willan Publishing, 2007)
Daly, Kathleen. Seeking Justice in the 21st Century: Towards an Intersectional Politics of
Justice in H. E. Ventura Miller, ed., RJ: From Theory to Practice. Sociology of Crime, Law,
and Deviance Series, Vol. 11 (Amsterdam: Emerald Group Publishing Ltd., 2008)
Dandurand, Yvon & Curt T. Griffiths. Handbook on restorative justice programmes Prepared
for The United Nations Office on Drugs and Crime (Vienna: United Nations Publications, 2006)
Daly, Kathleen. Feminist Perspectives in Criminology: A Review with Gen Y in Mind in Tim
Newburn & Eugene McLaughlin, eds., The SAGE handbook of Criminological Theory (London:
Sage Publications Ltd., 2010).
Delgado, Richard & Jean Stefancic. Critical Race Theory: An Introduction (New York: New
York University Press, 2001)
Dignan, James. Restorative Justice and the Law: The Case for an Integrated, Systemic
Approach in Lode Walgrave, ed., Restorative Justice and the Law (Cullompton, UK: Willan
Publishing, 2002)
Dignan, James. Towards a Systemic Model of Restorative Justice in A. Von Hirsch et al.,
eds., Restorative Justice: Competing or Reconcilable Paradigms? (Portland, OR: Hart
Publishing, 2003)
236
Doolin, Katherine. But what does it mean? Seeking Definitional Clarity in Restorative Justice
(2007) 71 J. Crim. L. 427-440
Dowd, Nancy Elizabeth & Michelle S. Jacobs, eds., Feminist Legal Theory: An Anti-Essentialist
Reader (NY:New York University Press, 2003).
Deveaux, Monique. Gender and Justice in Multicultural Liberal States (Oxford: Oxford
University Press, 2006)
Environics Institute, The Urban Aboriginal Peoples Study (2010) online: Urban Aboriginal
People Study < http://uaps.ca/> retrieved on 11 April 2010.
Feree, Myra Marx. Resonance and Radicalism: Feminist Framing in the Abortion Debates of
the United States and German (2003) 109:2 American Journal of Sociology 304-44
Foucault, Michel. Discipline and Punish: the Birth of the Prison, (New York: Random House,
1975)
Frederick, Loretta & Kristine C. Lizdas. The Role of Restorative Justice in the Battered
Women's Movement in James Ptacek, ed., Restorative Justice and Violence Against Women
(New York, NY: Oxford University Press, 2009)
Gavrielides, Theo. RJ Theory and Practice: Addressing the Discrepancy (Monsey, New York:
Criminal Justice Press, 2007)
Gavrielides, Theo. "Restorative Justice: The Perplexing Concept: Conceptual Fault-Lines and
Power Battles within the Restorative Justice Movement"(2008) 8 Criminology and Criminal
Justice 165-183
237
Gelsthorpe, Loraine. Feminism and Criminology in Mike Maguire et al., eds., The Oxford
handbook of criminology, 3rd ed., (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2002)
Goel, Rashmi. No Women at the Center: The use of the Canadian Sentencing Circles in
Domestic Violence Cases(2000) 15 Wisconsin Womens Law Journal 293-3334
Goel, Rashmi. Aboriginal Women and Political Pursuit in Canadian Sentencing Circles: At the
Cross Roads or Cross Purposes? in James Ptacek, ed., Restorative Jutice and Violence Against
Women (New York, NY: Oxford University Press, 2009) at 1048-1051 in a kindle e-book
version.
Guidroz, Kathleen & Michele Tracy Berger. A Conversation with the Founding Scholars of
Intersectionality in Kathleen Guidroz & Michelle T. Berger, eds., The intersectional approach:
transforming the academy through race, class and gender (The Univ. of North Carolina Press,
2009)
Green, Leslie. The Rights of Minority Cultures (New York, NY: Oxford University Press, 1995).
Greene, Dana. Repeat Performances: Why Good Reforms Go Bad & Testing the Next Wave, RJ
(Ph.D. Thesis, The city University of New York, 2005) [unpublished]
Greer, Pam. Aboriginal Women and Domestic Violence in New South Wales in Julie Stubbs,
ed., Women, Male Violence and the Law (Sidney, Sydney: Institute of Criminology, 1994)
Harris, Angela P. Race and Essentialism in Feminist Legal Theory (1990) 42 Stanford Law
Review
Harris, Nathan et al., Emotional Dynamics in Restorative Conferences (2004) 8:2 Theoretical
Criminology 191-210
Hart, Barbara J. Arrest, Whats the Big Deal (1997) 3 Wm. & Mary J. Women & L. 207-209
Hartmann, Heidi. The Unhappy Marriage of Marxism and Feminism in Lydia Sargent, ed.,
Women and Revolution (Boston: South End Press, 1981).
Hopkins, C. Quince, Mary P. Koss and Karen J. Bachar. Applying Restorative Justice to
Ongoing Intimate Violence: Problems and Possibilities (2004) 23 St. Louis University Public
Law Review 289-312 at 297.
Hopkins, C. Quince & Mary P. Koss. Incorporating Feminist Theory and Insights Into a
Restorative Justice Response to Sex Offenses (2005) 11 Violence Against Women 693
Hudson, Barbara. Restorative Justice: The Challenge of Sexual and Racial Violence (1998)
25:2 Journal of Law and Society 237-56
Hudson, Barbara. Restorative Justice and Gendered Violence: Diversion or Effective Justice?
(2002) 42 British Journal of Criminology 616-34.
Hulsman, L. The Abolitionist Case: Alternative Crime Policies (1991) 25 Israel Law Review
681-709
Ikpa, Tina S. Balancing Restorative Justice Principles and Due Process Rights in Order to
Reform the Criminal Justice System (2007) 24 Journal of Law & Policy 301
Johnstone, Gerry, ed., A Restorative Justice Reader: Texts. Sources, Context (Mill Street,
Uffculme: Willan Publishing, 2003)
Johnstone, Gerry & Daniel W. Van Ness, eds., Handbook of Restorative Justice Handbook of
Restorative Justice (Mill Street, Uffculme: Willan Publishing, 2007)
239
Johnstone, Gerry. Critical perspectives on Restorative Justice in Gerry Johnstone & Daniel W.
Van Ness, eds., Handbook of Restorative Justice (Portland, Oregon: Willan Publishing, 2007)
Kelly, Loretta. Using Restorative Justice in Aboriginal Communities, in John Braithwaite &
Heather Strang, eds., Restorative Justice and Family Violence (Cambridge, UK: Cambridge
University Press, 2002)
Koen, Raymond. The Antinomies of Restorative Justice in Elrena Van der Spuy et al., eds.,
Restorative Justice: politics, policies and prospects (Cape Town: Juta & Co Ltd.,2007)
Koss, Mary et al., Restorative Justice for Sexual Violence: Repairing Victims, Building
Community and Holding Offenders Accountable (2003) 989 Annals of the New York Academy
of Science 384-96
Kuhn, Thomas S. The Structure of Scientific Revolutions, 3rd ed. (Chicago: University of
Chicago Press, 1996).
Kymlicka, Will. Multicultural Citizenship: A Liberal Theory of Minority Rights (Oxford: Oxford
University Press, 1995)
Lauretis, Teresa de. Upping the Anti (sic) in Feminist Theory in Simon During, ed., The
Cultural Studies Reader (London: Routledge, 1993)
Lawrie, Rowena & Winsome Matthews. Holistic Community Justice: A Proposed Response to
Family Violence in Aboriginal Communities (2002) 25 The University of New South Wales
Law Journal 228-232
LaPrairie, Carol & Jane Dickson-Gilmore, Will the Circle be Unbroken? Aboriginal
Communities, Restorative Justice and the Challenges of Conflict and Change (Cullompton, UK:
Willan Publishing 2005)
Lerman, Lisa G. Mediation of Wife Abuse Cases: The Adverse Impact of Informal Dispute
Resolution on Women (1984) 7 Harvard Womens Law Journal 57
Levy, J. T. Classifying Cultural Rights, in W. Kymlicka and I. Shapiro, eds., Nomos XXXIX:
Ethnicity and Group Rights (New York: New York University Press, 1997)
240
Lewis, Ruth et al. 'Law's Progressive Potential: The Value of Engagement for the Law for
Domestic Violence' (2001) 10 Social and Legal Studies 105-30
Lilles, Heino. Circle Sentencing: Part of the Restorative Justice Continuum (Paper presented to
the Third International Conference on Conferencing, Circles and other Restorative Practices,
Minneapolis, Minnesota, 8-10 August, 2002 [unpublished] on line:
http://www.iirp.org/article_detail.php?article_id=NDQ3 (Retrieved on 25 March 2008)
London, Ross D. Paradigms Lost: Repairing the Harm of Paradigm Discourse in Restorative
Justice (2006) 19:4 Criminal Justice Studies 397-422
Luft, Rachel E. Intersectionality and the Risk of Flattening Difference in Kathleen Guidroz &
Michelle T. Berger, eds., The intersectional approach: transforming the academy through race,
class and gender (The Univ. of North Carolina Press, 2009)
Luft, Rachel E. & Jane Ward. "Toward an Intersectionality just out of reach: Confronting
challenges to intersectional practice" in Vasilikie P. Demos & Marcia Texler Segal, eds.,
Perceiving gender locally, globally, and intersectionally (Howard House, Emerald Publishing
ltda., 2009)
MacKinnon, Catharine A. Feminism Unmodified: Discourses on Life and Law (Cambridge, MA:
Harvard University Press, 1987)
Marshall, Tony F. The Evolution of Restorative Justice in Britain (1996) 4 European Journal
on Criminal Justice and Research 21-43
Martin, Brian. Justice Ignited: The Dynamics of Backfire (Lanhan, Maryland: Rowman &
Littlefield Publishers, 2007)
McCall, Leslie. The Complexity of Intersectionality (2005) 30:3 Signs: Journal of Women in
Culture and Society
McCold, Paul. Restorative justice and the role of the community in B. Galaway & J. Hudson,
eds., Restorative Justice: International Perspectives (Mossey: Criminal Justice Press, 1996)
241
MacCold, Paul. Primary Restorative Justice Practices in Allison Morris & Gabrielle Maxwell,
eds., Restorative Justice for Juveniles: Conferencing, mediation and circles (Oxford, UK:Hart
Publishing, 2001)
MacCold, Paul. The Recent History of Restorative Justice Mediation, Circles and
Conferencing in Dennis Sullivan & Larry Tifft , eds., The Handbook of Restorative Justice: A
Global Perspective (New York, NY: Routledge, 2006)
MacCold, Paul interview by Abbey J. Porter, Restorative Conferences reduce Trauma from
Crime, Study shows from the International Institute of Restorative Practices (15 August 2006)
on Restorative Practices EForum online:www.iirp.org retrieved on January 10, 2009
Mackay, Robert. Reparation and the Debate about Justice (Edinburgh: University of Edinburgh,
1992)
Marchetti, Elena & Kathleen Daly, Indigenous Sentencing Courts: Towards a Theoretical and
Jurisprudential Model (2007) 29 Sydney Law Review 415-443
Marchetti, Elena. Indigenous Sentencing Courts and Partner Violence: Perspectives of Court
Practitioners and Elders on Gender Power Imbalances During the Sentencing Hearing (2010)
43: 2 The Australian and New Zealand journal of Criminology 263281
Milward, David. Making the Circle Stronger: an effort to buttress Aboriginal use of Restorative
Justice in Canada against recent criticisms (2008) 4:3 IJPS
Mills, Sara. Post-colonial Feminist Theory in Jackie Jones, ed., Contemporary feminist
theories (Edinburgh: Edinburgh University Press, 1998)
McElrea, F.W.M. Restorative Justice - A New Zealand Perspective in David J. Cornwell, ed.,
Criminal punishment and Restorative Justice: Past, present, and future perspectives (Winchester,
UK: Waterside Press, 2006)
McLaughlin, Eugene et al., eds., Restorative Justice: Critical Issues (Thousand Oaks, CA: Sage
Publications, 2003)
Morris, Allison & Loraine Gelsthorpe. Re-Visioning Men's Violence Against Female Partners
(2000) 39 Howard Journal of Criminal Justice 412-28.
242
O
Okin, Susan Moller. Women in Western Political Thought (Princeton, N.J.: Princeton University
Press, 1979)
Okin, Susan Moller. Is Multiculturalism Bad for Women? (Princeton: Princeton University Press,
1999)
Ollenburger, Jane C. & Helen A. Moore. A sociology of women: The intersection of patriarchy
capitalism, and colonization (Upper Saddle River, NJ: Prentice Hall, 1998).
Pavlich, George Clifford. Governing paradoxes of Restorative Justice (London, UK: Glasshouse
Press, 2005
Peachey, Dean E. The Kitchener Experiment in Gerry Johnstone, ed., A Restorative Justice
Reader: Texts, Sources, Contexts (Devon, UK: Willan Publishing, 2003)
Pennell, Joan & Gale Burford. Widening the Circle: The Family Group Decision Making
Project (1994) 9 Journal of Child & Youth Care 1-12
Pennell, Joan & Gale Burford. Feminist Praxis: Making Family Group Conferencing Work in
Heather Strang & John Braithwaite, eds., Restorative Justice and Family Violence (Cambridge,
UK: Cambridge University Press, 2002) 108-127
Philips, Anne. Multiculturalism without Culture (Princeton: Princeton Unversity Press, 2007)
Potas, Ivan; Jane Smart; Georgia Brignell; Brendan Thomas; Rowena Lawrie; Rhonda Clarke.
"Circle Sentencing in New South Wales: A Review and Evaluation" (2004) 8:4 Australian
Indigenous Law Reporter 73
Pranis, Kay et al., Peacemaking Circles: From Crime to Community (St. Paul, MN: Living
Justice Press, 2003)
Presser, Lois & Emily Gaarder. Can Restorative Justice Reduce Battering? Some Preliminary
Considerations (2000) 27 Social Justice 175
Ptacek, James, ed., Restorative Justice and Violence Against Women (New York, NY: Oxford
University Press, 2009)
243
R
Razack, Sherene. What is to be Gained by Looking White People in the Eye? Culture, Race,
and Gender in Cases of Sexual Violence (1994) 19 Signs 894-923
Razack, Sherene. Looking White People in the Eye: Gender, Race and Culture in Courtrooms
and Classrooms (Toronto: University of Toronto Press, 2001)
Reimund, Mary Ellen. The Law and Restorative Justice: Friend or Foe? A Systemic look at the
legal issues in Restorative Justice (2004) 53 Drake Law Review 667
Reingold, Roni & Lea Baratz. Feminism and Multiculturalism: Two Common Foundations for
a Vision and a Practice of Transformative Social Activities and Education in Israel (2009) 10:4
Journal of International Womens Studies 53
Richards, Kelly Taking Victims Seriously? The Role of Victims Rights Movements in the
Emergence of Restorative Justice (2009) 21 Current Issues Criminal Justice 302
Roberts, Ann Wamer. Is Restorative Justice Tied to Specific Models of Practice?, in Howard
Zehr & Barb Toews eds., Critical Issues in Restorative Justice (Monsey, New York: Criminal
Justice Press, 2004)
Roche, Declan. Dimensions of Restorative Justice (2006) 62:2 Journal of Social Issues 217-
238
Schiff, Mara. Satisfying the needs and interests of stakeholders in Gerry Johnstone & Daniel
W. Van Ness, eds., Handbook of Restorative Justice (Portland, Oregon: Willan Publishing,
2007)
Schor, Naomi & Elizabeth Weed, eds., The Essential difference (Bloomington: Indiana
University Press, 1994)
Scuro, Pedro. Regional Review Latin America in Gerry Johnstone & Daniel W. Van Ness,
eds., Handbook of Restorative Justice (Portland, Oregon: Willan Publishing, 2007)
Shachaf-Friedman, Esther & Uri Timor. Family-Group Conferencing in Israel: The Voices of
Victims Following Restorative Justice Proceedings in Natti Rone et al., eds, Trends and issues
in Victimology (Newcastle, UK: Cambridge Scholars Publishing, 2008)
244
Shachar, Ayelet. Multicultural Jurisdictions: Cultural Differences and Women's Rights
(Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2001).
Shapland, Joanna. Victims and Criminal Justice: Creating Responsible Criminal Justice
Agencies in Adam Crawford & Jo Goodey, eds., Integrating a Victim Perspective within
Criminal Justice: International Debates, (Aldershot: Ashgate, 2000)
Shapland, Joanna & et al., Situating Restorative Justice Within Criminal Justice (2006) 10:4
Theoretical Criminology 505-532
Sharpe, Susan. How Large Should The Restorative Justice Tent" be? in Howard Zehr & Barb
Toews eds., Critical Issues in Restorative Justice (Monsey, New York: Criminal Justice Press,
2004)
Sherman, Lawrence W. Domestic Violence and Restorative Justice: Answering Key questions
(2000-2001) 8:1 Virginia Journal of Social Policy & Law 263
Shohat, Ella, ed., Talking Visions: Multicultural Feminism in a Transnational Age (Cambridge:
MIT Press, 1998)
Skelton, Ann. Tapping indigenous knowledge: traditional conflict resolution, restorative justice
and the denunciation of crime in South Africa (2007) Acta Juridica 228-246
Sokoloff, Natalie J. & Ida Dupont. Domestic Violence at the Intersections of Race, Class, and
Gender: Challenges and Contributions to Understanding Violence Against Marginalized Women
in Diverse Communities (2005) Violence Against Women 11:1 38-64
Statement, Multicultural Australia: United in Diversity: Updating the 1999 New Agenda for
Multicultural Australia: Strategic directions for 2003-2006, Commonwealth of Australia 2003
Strang, Heather. Repair or Revenge: Victims and RJ (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2002)
245
Strang, Heather. & John Braithwaite, eds., Restorative Justice and Family Violence (Cambridge,
UK: Cambridge University Press, 2002)
Strang, Heather. Is Restorative Justice Imposing its Agenda on Victims? in Howard Zehr &
Barb Toews eds., Critical Issues in Restorative Justice (Monsey, New York: Criminal Justice
Press, 2004)
Stevens, Richard W., Hugo Teufel III & Matthew Y. Biscan, Disarming Women: Comparing
Gun Control to Self-Defense. in Wendy McElroy, ed., Liberty for Women: Freedom and
Feminism in the Twenty-First Century (Chicago: Ivan R. D., 2002)
Stubbs, Julie. Shame, Defiance, and Violence against Women: A Critical Analysis of
"Communitarian" Conferencing, in Sandy Cook & Judith Bessant, eds., Women's Encounters
with Violence: Australian Experiences (London: Sage, 1997) 109-26
Stubbs, Julie. Domestic Violence and Womens Safety: Feminist Challenges to Restorative
Justice, in John Braithwaite & Heather Strang, eds., Restorative Justice and Family Violence
(Cambridge, UK: Cambridge University Press, 2002)
Stubbs, Julie. Restorative Justice, Domestic Violence and Family Violence Issues Paper 9
(Sydney: Australian Domestic and Family Violence Clearinghouse, 2004).
Stubbs, Julie. Critical Criminological Research (2008) 8:19 Legal Studies Research Paper
University of Sidney
Stubbs, Julie. Restorative Justice, Gendered Violence, and Indigenous Justice in James Ptacek,
ed., Restorative Justice and Violence Against Women (New York, NY: Oxford University Press,
2009) at 1656-1659 in a kindle e-book version.
Tarrow, Sidney. Power in Movements: Social Movements and Contentious Politics (Cambridge:
Cambridge University Press, 1998)
Umbreit, Mark. Family Group Conferencing: Implications for Crime Victims (2000) U.S.
Department of Justice - Office of Justice Programs.
246
Umbreit, Mark & Howard Zehr. Restorative Family Group Conferences: Differing Models and
Guidelines for Practice in Eugene McLaughlin et al., eds., RJ: Critical Issues (Thousand Oaks,
CA: Sage Publications, 2003)
U.S. Department of Health and Human Services, The Role of Restorative Justice in the Battered
Womens Movement, by Loretta Frederick & Kristine C. Lizdas, (Washington: Battered
Women's Justice Project, 2003).
Van Ness, Daniel W. A Reply to Andrew Ashworth 4:2 Criminal Law Forum 301-306
Van Ness, Daniel W. An Overview of Restorative Justice Around the World (Paper presented
to the 11Th United Nation Congress on Crime Prevention and Criminal Justice, 22 April 2005)
[unpublished]
Volpp, Leti. Multiculturalism versus Feminism in Natalie J. Sokoloff & Christina Pratt, eds.,
Domestic violence at the margins: readings on race, class, gender, and culture (Piscataway, NJ:
Rutgers University Press, 2006)
Walgrave, Lode, ed., Restorative Justice and the Law (Cullompton, UK: Willan Publishing,
2002)
Walker, Anders. Shotguns, Weddings, and Lunch Counters: Why Cultural Frames Matter to
Constitutional Law online: (19 August, 2010) Florida State University Law Review,
Forthcoming. Available at SSRN: <http://ssrn.com/abstract=1661981>.
Walmsley, Roy. World Prison Population List, 8th ed. (London: International Centre for Prison
Studies, 2009)
Wang, Ping et al., Regional Review Asia in Gerry Johnstone & Daniel W. Van Ness, eds.,
Handbook of Restorative Justice (Portland, Oregon: Willan Publishing, 2007) 477-487
Weinbaum, Batya. The Curious Courtship of Women's liberations and Socialism (Boston: South
End Press, 1978)
Weitekamp, Elmar G. M. & Hans-Jrgen Kerner, eds., RJ: Theoretical Foundation (Mill Street,
Uffculme: Willan Publishing 2002)
Wright, Martin. Nobody Came: Criminal Justice and the Needs of Victims (1977) Howard
Journal 16:1 22
Wright, Martin. Justice for victims and offenders (Philadelphia: Open University Press, 1991)
247
Wheeldon, Johannes. Finding common ground: restorative justice and its theoretical
construction(s) (2009) 12:1 Contemporary Justice Review 91-100
Yazzie, Robert & James Zion. Navajo Restorative Justice: The Law of Equality and Justice in
B. Galaway & J. Hudson, eds., Restorative Justice: International Perspectives (Mossey:Criminal
Justice Press, 1996)
Yuval-Davis, Nira. Intersectionality and Feminist Politics (2006) 13:3 European Journal of
Womens Studies
Zehr, Howard. Changing Lenses: A New Focus for Crime and Justice (Scottsdale, Pennsylvania:
Herald Press, 1990)
Zehr, Howard & Harry Mika. Fundamental Concepts of Restorative Justice (1998) 1
Contemporary Justice Review at 47-55.
Zehr, Howard. The Little Book of Restorative Justice (Intercourse, PA: Good Books, 2002)
Zehr, Howard & Barb Toews, eds., Critical Issues in Restorative Justice (Monsey, New York:
Criminal Justice Press, 2004)
Zehr, Howard. Book review of The spiritual Roots of Restorative Justice by Michael Hadley,
(2003) 43 British Journal of Criminology 653654
Zernova, Margarita and Martin Wright. Alternative Visions of Restorative Justice in Gerry
Johnstone and Daniel W. Van Ness, eds. Handbook of Restorative Justice (Mill Street,
Uffculme: Willan Publishing, 2007) 91
Zernova, Margarita. Restorative justice: Ideals and Realities (Hampshire, UK: Ashgate
Publishing Ltd., 2007) at 2-3.
Ziarek, Ewa P. An ethics of dissensus: postmodernity, feminism, and the politics of radical
democracy (Stanford, CA: Stanford University Press, 2001).
Zinn, Maxine Baca & Bonnie Thorton Dill. Theorizing difference from multiracial feminism
Feminist Studies 22:2 321-331
248
Legislation and Statues
UN Economic and Social Council, Declaration of Basic Principles on the use of Restorative
Justice Programmes in Criminal Matters, ECOSOC Res. 2002/12, UN Doc A/40/881 (1999).
Children, Young Persons, and Their Families Act 1989 (N.Z), 1989/24, 2009 RS.
Canadian Charter of Rights and Freedoms, Part I of the Constitution Act, 1982, being Schedule
B to the Canada Act 1982 (U.K)., 1982, c. 11 [Charter].
Case Law
R. v. Morris (2004), B.C.C.A 305, 186 C.C.C (3d) 549 [Morris, cited to C.C.C.]
R. v. Bennett, [1992] Y.J. No. 192 (y. terr. Ct). (QL) [Bennett]
R. v. Charleyboy, [1993] B.C.J. No 2854 (B.C. Prov. Ct. (Crim. Div).) (QL) [Charleyboy]
R. v. Green, [1992] Y.J. No. 217 (Y. Terr. Ct). (QL) [Green]
R. v. J.J. (2004) N.L.C.A 81, 192 C.C.C (3D) 30 [J.J., cited to C.C.C.]
R. v. W.B.T., [1995] 132 Sask. R. 221 (sub nom. R. v. Taylor), 3 C.N.L.R. No. 167 (Sask. Q.B. )
(QL).
249