Three Centuries of Discussion
Three Centuries of Discussion
147
MARJOLEIN DEGENAAR
MOLYNEUX'S PROBLEM
THREECENTURIESOF DISCUSSION
ON THE PERCEPTIONOF FORMS
Founding Directors:
P. Dibont (Pads) and R.H. Popkin (Washington University, St. Louis & UCLA)
Directors: Brian Copenhaver (University of California, Los Angeles, USA), Sarah Hutton
(The University of Hertfordshire, United Kingdom), Richard Popkin (Washington Univer-
sity, St Louis & University of California, Los Angeles, USA)
Editorial Board: J.F. Battail (Pads); F. Duchesneau (Montreal); A. Gabbey (New York); T.
Gregory (Rome); J.D. North (Groningen); M.J. Petry (Rotterdam); J. Popkin (Lexington);
Th. Verbeek (Utrecht)
Advisory Editorial Board: J. Aubin (Pads); A. Crombie (Oxford); H. Gadamer (Heidelberg);
H. Gouhier (Pads); K. Hanada (Hokkaido University); W. Kirsop (Melbourne); P.O.
Kristeller (Columbia University); E. Labrousse (Paris); A. Lossky (Los Angeles); J.
Malarczyk (Lublin); E. de Olaso (C.I.F. Buenos Aires); J. Orcibal (Pads); W. R6d
(Miinchen); G. Rousseau (Los Angeles); H. Rowen (Rutgers University, N.J.); J.P.
Schobinger (Z0rich); J. Tans (Groningen)
MOLYNEUX'S PROBLEM
Three Centuries of Discussion
on the Perception of Forms
MARJOLEIN DEGENAAR
Erasmus University Rotterdam
L~
KLUWER A C A D E M I C PUBLISHERS
DORDRECHT / BOSTON / LONDON
A C.I.P. Catalogue record for this book is available from the Library of Congress
ISBN 0-7923-3934-7
Preface . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 1
1 Introduction . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 13
2 Molyneux's P r o b l e m . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 17
1 The First Formulation of M o l y n e u x ' s P r o b l e m . . . . . . . 17
2 Background to Molyneux's Problem . . . . . . . . . . . 18
3 The Publication of Molyneux's Problem . . . . . . . . . 21
4 Conclusions . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 23
6 M o d e r n Approaches . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 113
1 Historical Analyses . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 113
2 Surgically Treated Cataract Patients . . . . . . . . . . 114
3 Visual Deprivation in Animals . . . . . . . . . . . . . 118
4 Sensory Substitution Systems . . . . . . . . . . . . . 12o
5 Electrical Stimulation of the Visual Cortex . . . . . . . . 124
6 Conclusions . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 124
Bibliography . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 135
11
CHAPTER ONE
INTRODUCTION
13
14 Chapter One
because it was thought that they could serve to demonstrate what types of
knowledge we possess thanks to the various distinct senses. From other angles,
the blind, the deaf and the lame were also seen as curious creatures since--
according to some--they were thought to possess not only another capacity
for acquiring knowledge but also different beliefs, morals and msthetics. In
the mid-eighteenth century theoretical interest in the deaf and the blind was
combined with a humanitarian interest which led to philanthropists such as
l'abb@ de L'l~p@e and Valentin Hafiy being able to put through social reforms,
including provision of care and education for deaf mutes and the blind.
Finally, the history of Molyneux's problem illustrates elegantly how an area
of research traditionally included under philosophy was affected by numerous
factors (including the use of new methods and techniques and the information
they provided) and has become part of other disciplines such as psychology
and neurophysiology.
The aim of this study is to investigate how Molyneux arrived at his problem,
how the problem has been interpreted in the course of history, in what types
of context it has been discussed and what sort of arguments have been evinced
to justify the various solutions. At the same time an attempt will be made
to isolate factors that have played a rSle in the changes in interpretation and
argumentation.
The idea of sketching a history of the development of Molyneux's problem is
not entirely new. Between 1772 and 1782 the Swiss philosopher Jean-Bernard
M@rian published a number of articles in which he attempted to present a
histoire raisonnde of Molyneux's problem. Of more recent date are the article
by John Davis (196o), the book by Michael Morgan (1977) and Appendix A
of John Gerald Simms's biography of Molyneux (1982). Obviously M~rian's
writings are limited to the eighteenth century. Davis and Simms gave only a
brief historical survey of the discussion about the problem. Morgan's some-
what disorganised book contains many digressions on matters which only
indirectly relate to Molyneux's problem. It would thus seem desirable and
justified to write a more adequate and more extensive history which would
also cover the nineteenth and twentieth centuries.
This book is organized as follows. The second chapter gives a description
of Molyneux's problem with a sketch of the background. The third chapter
concentrates on the arguments originally used in the attempts to solve the
problem. As will be seen, it was at first regarded as a purely hypothetical
problem amenable to solution by philosophical analyses regarding the identity
(or otherwise) of visual and tactile sensations (or concepts) of forms. The
solutions proposed were usually closely connected with the positions taken up
by their proponents in the empiricism-rationalism debate.
The discussion took a new turn in 1728 when the English surgeon William
Cheselden published a report of the observations made by a patient, blind
Introduction 15
MOLYNEUX'S P R O B L E M
Dublin July. 7. 88
A Man, being born blind, and having a Globe and a Cube, nigh of
the same bignes, Committed into his Hands, and being taught or
Told, which is Called the Globe, and which the Cube, so as easily
to distinguish them by his Touch or Feeling; Then both being taken
from Him, and Laid on a Table, Let us suppose his Sight Restored
to Him; Whether he Could, by his Sight, and before he touch them,
know which is the Globe and which the Cube? Or Whether he Could
know by his Sight, before he stretchd out his Hand, whether he Could
not Reach them, tho they were Removed 2o or lOOO feet from him?
If the Learned and Ingenious Author of the Forementiond Treatise
think this problem Worth his Consideration and Answer, He may at
any time Direct it to One That Much Esteems him, and is
1According to the Julian calendar, which remained in use in England until 1752.
~Molyneux writing to the authors of the Biblioth~que universelle et historique, 7 July
1688 (original spelling). Oxford, Bodleian Library, ms. Locke c. 16, fol. 92 recto; reprinted
(with slight changes) in Locke 1976-199o, vol. 3 (1978), no. lO64. In 1688 Molyneux was
not a personal friend of Locke and thus he addressed his letter to "Les Auteurs de la
Biblioth~que," c/o Mr. Waesberg, bookseller in Amsterdam, who had published Locke's
work in 1688.
17
18 Chapter Two
What was it that had caused Molyneux to formulate this problem and why
did he submit it for Locke's consideration?
1See W. Molyneux 18o3, C. Molyneux 182o, Chillingworth 1946 , Hoppen 1963, Dahl
1968, Hoppen 197o, Kelly 1979, Simms 1982, and Breathnach 1984. The Case o/Ire-
land's Being Bound by Acts o/ Parliament in England, Stated (1698) is Molyneux's most
important political publication.
2Molyneux to Flamsteed, 11 April 1682, quoted in Simms 1982, p. 61.
3See Kepler 16o4. It had long been a well known fact that a person with two eyes
can perceive depth, but after Kepler's discovery of the two-dimensional retinal image this
fact became an object of disbelief because no-one could explain the phenomenon. In 1838
Charles Wheatstone demonstrated that it is possible to perceive depth when presented with
two fiat images.
4See Sabra 1967 for more information on these developments.
Molyneux's Problem 19
1William Molyneux and Lucy Domville married on 19 September 1678; a little over two
months later--on 24 November--Lucy had a stroke which rapidly made her blind. See
Simms 1982, pp. 2o-22.
~See, for example, Aristotle's De anima, bk. II, ch. 6. See also Mackie 1976, pp. 28-32.
3The term "idea" was used by Locke and his contemporaries with different meanings.
This sometimes leads to problems in the interpretation of fragments of text. It is not,
for instance, always clear whether they are concerned with sensations or with concepts.
Whenever I give expression to the opinions of Locke and other philosophers I do that in
their own terms. See Chappell 1994 for a more elaborate discussion of Locke's usage of the
term "idea."
4Locke 1688, p. 51.
5Locke 1688, p. 52.
20 Chapter Two
what he was now seeing was red or blue unless someone had told him. But
while blind he would certainly have learnt (by touch) the difference between
a sphere and a cube. He would have a concept of shapes; he would know
the characteristics of a spherical object and of a cube-shaped object. Quite
possibly Molyneux thus regarded it as worthwhile to try to find out whether
a person cured of congenital blindness would be capable of distinguishing and
naming by sight two objects that he had previously learnt to distinguish and
name by touch alone. It is probable that Molyneux presented his problem to
Locke because the latter had expressed certain opinions concerning the ideas
of the congenitally blind and the ideas of shapes that can be obtained both
through touch and through sight. An additional factor was that Molyneux
greatly admired Locke's work.
In the Dioptrica Nova (which was published in 1692 , a couple of years
after Molyneux's letter to Locke) there is a passage where Molyneux explicitly
indicates the function he accorded to a person cured of congenital blindness.
In his discussion of the question why we see objects the right way up while
the retinal image is reversed, Molyneux wrote that the terms "right way up"
and "inversed" are relative to "up" and "down" or to "farther" and "nigher"
to the centre-point of the Earth. 1 Molyneux stated that we see things in their
natural position because "the Mind takes no notice of what happens to the
Rays in the Eye by Refraction or Decussation, but [...] the Mind does hunt
back by means of each Pencil of Rays [...] to the Point from whence it comes,
and is thereby directed strait thereto. ''~ The fact that this natural power
ensures that we see trees and suchlike the right way up can be confirmed by
the presumed reaction of someone standing on his head: he would regard the
trees that he sees as being the right way up and himself as being upside-
down. 3 And this would be even more apparent in the reaction shown by a
person blind from birth who suddenly recovers the faculty of sight:
~Molyneux 1692 , p. 1o 5.
2 M o l y n e u x 1692 , pp. 2 8 9 - 2 9 0 .
3 M o l y n e u x 1692 , p. 212.
4 M o l y n e u x 1692 ~ p. 212.
Molyneux's Problem 21
Suppose a Man born blind, and now adult, and taught by his touch
to distinguish between a Cube, and a Sphere of the same metal, and
highly of the same bigness, so as to tell, when he felt one and t'other,
which is the Cube, which the Sphere. Suppose then the Cube and
Sphere placed on a Table, and the Blind Man to be made to see.
Qua~re, Whether by his sight, before he touch'd them, he could now
distinguish, and tell, which is the Globe, which the Cube. 1
In P l a i n Vision t h e E s t i m a t e we m a k e of t h e Distance of O b j e c t s
(especially when so far removed, t h a t t h e I n t e r v a l between our two
Eyes, b e a r s no sensible P r o p o r t i o n thereto; or when l o o k ' d u p o n w i t h
one E y e only) is r a t h e r t h e A c t of our Judgment, t h a n of Sense;
a n d a c q u i r e d by Exercise a n d a F a c u l t y of comparing, r a t h e r t h a n
Natural. 3
on the fourth edition of 17oo; for reasons of chronology quotations are given as "Locke
[1694] 1975."
1Locke [1694] 1975, bk. II, ch. ix, §8. Instead of "of the same metal" Molyneux had
written "(Suppose) of Ivory." See Molyneux to Locke, 2 March 1692/3, in Locke 1976-
199o , vol. 4 (1979), no. 16o9.
Lievers has written that "the Molyneux problem is not primarily concerned with the
application of concepts nor with the correlation between sight and touch, but must be
placed within the context of a solution to the problem of depth perception" (Lievers 1992 ,
p. 415). This may be true of the first formulation but hardly seems to apply to the second.
3Molyneux 1692, p. 113.
4Molyneux 1692, p. 113.
Molyneux's Problem 23
4 CONCLUSIONS
P H I L O S O P H I C A L DISCUSSIONS IN
THE EIGHTEENTH CENTURY
1Similar thought experiments are still being proposed today. Think, for example, of
Frank Jackson's imaginary scientist Mary, who knows all about the neurophysiology of
colour vision but has spent her life in a black-and-white environment. Would she learn
anything she did not know before if she left her rooms? (Jackson 1982. ) The analogy
between Jackson's experiment and Molyneux's problem is noted in Levin 1986.
25
26 Chapter Three
Molyneux assumed that the person born blind had learnt both to distinguish
a sphere from a cube by touch and to give them their correct names. The
question he put to Locke was actually a double question: if the man were
to recover his power of sight would he be able to distinguish them by sight,
without the help of the sense of touch, and would he be able to name them?
Molyneux himself did not give separate answers to these two questions, for
his answer was as follows:
Not. For though he has obtain'd the experience 0/, how a Globe, how
a Cube affects his touch; yet he has not yet attained the Experience,
that what affects his touch so or so, must affect his sight so or so; Or
that a protuberant angle in the Cube, that pressed his hand unequally,
shall appear to his eye as it does in the Cube. 1
Experience will have taught the man that a cube has projecting angles which
exert uneven pressure on the hand, while a sphere feels the same over its entire
surface. But he will as yet not have had the experience of the impressions
made by these angles and by this regular object on the eye. The man would
not know that what he was seeing were a sphere and a cube because he would
not have had the experience that what he was seeing had anything to do with
what he had previously felt. In brief, Molyneux believed that the relationship
between tactile and visual sensations of the shape of objects would not be
immediately apparent but would have to be learnt. And it is possible that he
regarded such a relationship as necessary.
In his Essay Locke expressed agreement with Molyneux's statement, but he
did not seem particularly interested in the link between the sense of touch and
the faculty of sight: in the chapter dealing with perception he used Molyneux's
problem to illustrate the thesis that we often have false beliefs about the way
in which we perceive--without our taking notice of it. Locke stated that
when, for instance, we look at a uniformly coloured sphere, the idea we get
of it is that of a (flat) circle with a variety of shades and colours. But from
experience we have learnt that this sort of idea is caused by a sphere and thus
we interpret the idea of the unevenly coloured circle as the idea of a uniformly
coloured sphere. This happens so quickly that we hardly notice it.
In order to make this process clearer, Locke used a language metaphor
which was to take on a persistent life of its own in discussions on Molyneux's
problem. Whenever a person reads or listens to something with attention
~Locke [1694] 1975, bk. II, ch. ix, §8. See also Molyneux to Locke, 2 March 1692/3 , in
Locke 1976-199o, vol. 4 (1979), no. 16o9.
Philosophical Discussions in the Eighteenth Century 27
and understanding, stated Locke, he does not take note of the letters or the
sounds but of the concepts that they call forth. 1 Just as sounds are signs of
concepts, so also is a circle a sign for a sphere. The passage in which Locke
put his opinion regarding unconscious judgments reads as follows:
m a y be b e h o l d i n g to experience, i m p r o v e m e n t , a n d a c q u i r e d notions,
w h e r e he thinks, he has not t h e least use of, or help from t h e m : A n d
t h e r a t h e r , b e c a u s e this o b s e r v i n g Gent. f a r t h e r a d d s , t h a t having
upon the occasion of my Book, proposed this to divers very ingenious
Men, he hardly ever met with one, that at first gave the answer to it,
which he thinks true, till by hearing his reasons they were convinced. 1
W h a t is n o t i c e a b l e here is t h a t Locke did not deal with M o l y n e u x ' s q u e s t i o n
r e g a r d i n g t h e a b i l i t y of t h e n e w l y - s i g h t e d i n d i v i d u a l to d i s t i n g u i s h b e t w e e n
t h e s p h e r e a n d t h e cube b u t only t r e a t e d t h e question of naming t h e o b j e c t s .
A f u r t h e r p o i n t w o r t h n o t i n g is t h a t Locke believed t h a t t h e m a n would be
unable to say with certainty which was the sphere a n d which t h e cube. W e
know t h a t Locke a s s u m e d t h a t we a r e able n a t u r a l l y only to see s h a p e s in
two d i m e n s i o n s 2 A m a n b o r n b l i n d who gains his sight a n d who is n o t yet
affected by h a b i t would, in Locke's view, o b t a i n from a s p h e r e t h e i d e a of a
circle a n d from a cube t h a t of a s q u a r e or some sort of h e x a g o n , d e p e n d i n g on
his angle of vision. 3 If we a s s u m e t h a t t h e m a n b o r n blind were to be given
t h e two o b j e c t s to view s e p a r a t e l y , a c c o r d i n g to Locke's opinion he should
a t least b e a b l e to perceive a difference between t h e two o b j e c t s , t h a t is he
s h o u l d be able to d i s t i n g u i s h t h e m one from t h e other. 4 If he were to b e
p r e s e n t e d w i t h t h e two o b j e c t s s i m u l t a n e o u s l y ( a n d in all likelihood t h a t was
M o l y n e u x ' s idea), it would be s o m e w h a t m o r e difficult. P e r h a p s he m i g h t
s u s p e c t t h a t t h e s q u a r e or t h e h e x a g o n h a d s o m e t h i n g to do w i t h a c u b e a n d
t h e circle w i t h a sphere, b u t he would not know it for sure. In o r d e r to be
a b l e to n a m e t h e cube a n d t h e s p h e r e c o r r e c t l y he would first have to l e a r n
t h a t c e r t a i n t w o - d i m e n s i o n a l p r o j e c t i o n s of the o b j e c t s t h a t he is o b s e r v i n g
c o r r e s p o n d in s o m e w a y to t a n g i b l e t h r e e - d i m e n s i o n a l objects. 5 T h i s could
e x p l a i n w h y Locke w r o t e t h a t t h e m a n would not be able to say with certainty
which was t h e s p h e r e a n d which t h e cube.
1Locke [1694] 1975, bk. II, ch. ix, §8. Molyneux responded to Locke's writing with
the following words: "My most Honour'd Friend, For so you have publickly allowd me to
call you; and tis a Title wherein I boast more than in Maces or Parliament-Robes. [...] I
can only Pour out my thanks to you for the Favourable Character under which you have
transmitted me to posterity." Molyneux to Locke, 28 July 1694, in Locke 1976-199o, vol. 5
(1979) ' no. 1763 .
2This conflicts with Locke's statement that we can gain a notion of space through the
sense of sight. See Locke [1694] 1975, bk. II, ch. v, and bk. II, ch. ix, §8. See also Berman
1974b.
3See Park 1969 about "real" and "apparent" dimensions of objects. According to Bolton
Brandt 1994, the man cured of blindness would not at first receive visual ideas of the bodies
he looks at, but would only be aware of light and colour. See also Vienne 1992.
4According to Mackie 1976 , p. 32, "Locke could [...] hold that we get the same idea of
shape from both sight and touch, provided that this is confined to two-dimensional shape."
5See Brandt 1975.
Philosophical Discussions in the Eighteenth Century 29
Like Molyneux, Locke probably assumed that visual and tactile ideas of
shape have an essential relationship to one another which can be learnt by
experience; nowhere did Locke defend the idea of the complete heterogeneity
of sight and touch, an idea which the Irish philosopher George Berkeley was
most certainly to support, and his notions on this point are crystal clear.
While Locke used Molyneux's problem merely as an illustration of his thesis
that we owe more to experience than we tend to admit and that unconscious
judgments can play a part in perception, George Berkeley (1685-1753) gave
it a central rSle in his philosophy. Ernst Cassirer even stated that "die Neue
Theorie des Sehens, die den Auftakt zu Berkeleys Philosophie bildet und die
alle ihre Ergebnisse implizite enth£1t, [...] nichts als der Versuch einer voll-
st£ndigen systematischen Entwicklung und Aufhellung des Molyneuxschen
Problems list]." 1 Because of the importance of Molyneux's problem for Berke-
ley's philosophy on the one hand and, on the other, the influence of Berkeley's
theory of sight on the discussion surrounding Molyneux's problem, we need
here to make a detailed examination of Berkeley's ideas.
One of his most important motivations was the fight against scepticism,
the principal cause of which Berkeley believed to be the general belief in the
existence of material entities or external objects. He made it his business,
therefore, to overthrow this belief. Berkeley was interested in theories of
vision because the existence of the visible world is usually--and, according
to him, unjustifiably--used as an argument for the existence of a material
world. He studied the works on optics written by Descartes, Barrow and
Molyneux as well as Newton's Opticks which had just been published2 These
thinkers studied mainly geometrical optics, whereas Berkeley was interested
in the psychology of seeing, as witness his An Essay towards a New Theory
of Vision (17o9).
The aim of the Essay was "to shew the manner wherein we perceive by
sight the distance, magnitude, and situation of objects. Also to consider the
difference there is betwixt the ideas of sight and touch, and whether there be
any idea common to both senses. ''3 As Berkeley remarked in the Appendix
to the second edition of his Essay in 171o , his whole theory rested on the
theory that we perceive distance neither directly nor by means of anything
else that has an essential link with it, such as lines and angles. Following in
Molyneux's footsteps Berkeley stated:
1Cassirer 1932, p. 145. See also Teape 187o, p. 3: "[Berkeley's] philosophy can alone
be truly known, when seen germinating from the question of Molyneux." Quoted by Luce
[1934] 1967, P. 34, note 1.
~Descartes 1637, Barrow 1674, Molyneux 1692 , Newton 17o4.
3Berkeley [17o9] 1975, §1.
3o Chapter Three
Any idea not directly perceived, said Berkeley, must be perceived by means
of another ideaP Ideas which, according to Berkeley, suggest distance include
the sensation produced by the turn of the eyes (convergence), the unclarity
of the appearance and the tension of the eye (accommodation). Among other
factors contributing to the creation of the idea of distance he mentioned the
quantity, the size and the nature of the objects we perceive. He believed that
experience links such factors to the notion of distance. 3
A person born blind gaining the power of sight would in the beginning, said
Berkeley, obtain no idea of distance through the faculty of sight; the sun and
the stars, nearby and distant objects would all appear to be in his eye--or,
rather, in his mind.
The objects intromitted by his sight would seem to him (as in truth
they are) no other than a new set of thoughts or sensations, each
whereof is as near to him as the perceptions of pain or pleasure, or the
most inward passions of his soul. For our judging objects perceived
by sight to be at any distance, or without the mind, is [...] entirely
the effect of experience, which one in those circumstances could not
yet have attained to. 4
Berkeley stated that it is only after we have had long experience of certain
ideas derived from the sense of touch being linked to certain ideas derived
from sight that we can immediately conclude which tactile ideas will follow
certain visual ideas in a natural way. Visual ideas suggest tactile ideas, just
as a flushed face suggests embarrassment and a pale face suggests fear. 5
In order to prevent confusion Berkeley distinguished two kinds of objects
of sight: primary and secondary. By means of primary, direct objects of sight
(viz. light and colours) we are, he said, able to perceive secondary, indirect
1Berkeley [17o9] 1975, §2. The remark "It is [...] agreed by all" should probably be
regarded as rhetorical. In fact Berkeley believed that it was the general opinion that we
see things at a distance outside ourselves.
2Berkeley [17o9] 1975, §9: "It is evident that when the mind perceives any idea, not
immediately and of itself, it must be by means of some other idea."
3Berkeley [17o9] 1975, §§16-28.
4Berkeley [17o9] 1975, §41.
5Berkeley [17o9] 1975, §45 and §65. In the Philosophical Commentaries Berkeley speaks
of "the constant & long association of ideas." Berkeley [17o7-17o8] 1975, no. 225.
Philosophical Discussions in the Eighteenth Century 31
and improper objects of sight. Berkeley believed these latter properly to be-
long to the sense of touch. 1 Just as Locke had understood flat surfaces as
signs of three-dimensional shapes and had compared the visual perception
of three-dimensional shapes with the understanding of linguistic tokens, so
Berkeley compared the perception of secondary objects of sight with the un-
derstanding of the meaning of words. Whenever we hear a familiar language
we receive simultaneously the sounds and the corresponding meaning of the
words. These two are, through experience, so tightly bound together that it
seems as if we are hearing not sounds but meanings.: Where Locke made
no more than a passing reference to the analogy between visual perception
and the understanding of language, this analogy plays an important part in
Berkeley's writings.
Berkeley believed that size as well as distance was perceived indirectly.
Consequently he regarded visual size not as a primary but as a secondary or
improper object of sight. The visual size of an object can change, whereas
the tactile size is always the same. The estimates we make of visual size, said
Berkeley, depend entirely on experience. An assessment of size made by a
person born blind opening his eyes for the first time would be totally different
from the assessment we would make. 3
Berkeley introduced a third variant of Molyneux's problem relative to the
perception of the position of objects. He thereby made clear the function he
accorded to such a thought experiment. Berkeley believed that it is useful to
place ourselves in the blind man's shoes in order to rid ourselves of our visual
experience and its accompanying prejudices regarding visual perception. He
was convinced that this would, to a certain extent, be possible:
The person born blind, said Berkeley, would not at first think that what he
was seeing was high or low or the right way up or upside-down. It would only
be after some experience had been gained that he would learn that objects
pictured on the lower part of his eye are above, since he would see them clearly
by aiming his gaze upwards. Without this eye movement, terms related to the
position of tangible objects, such as "right way up" and "upside-down," would
never have been transferred to the ideas which belong to sight. 1 Berkeley
believed that what had largely contributed to writers on optics being misled
in this m a t t e r was that they had placed too much emphasis on retinal images.
Whenever they thought of these tiny images they imagined that they were
looking at the b o t t o m of the eye of another person and that they saw the
images which were pictured there2 In addition, Berkeley was of the opinion
t h a t it was erroneous to imagine that retinal images were representations of
external objects, for in fact there would be nothing in common between ideas
of sight and those of touch; moreover the direct objects of sight do not, he
stated, exist without the mind.
This brings us to the second aim of the Essay regarding the heterogeneity
of sight and touch. Berkeley ventured to make the following statement:
mind by a new inlet an idea he has been already well acquainted with. ''1 We
should therefore either assume t h a t visual forms differ from tactile forms or
t h a t the solution proposed by Molyneux and Locke ("those two thoughtful and
ingenious men") is incorrect. Berkeley pointed to his earlier statement t h a t a
person born blind gaining his sight would have names for objects previously
perceived by touch, but would be unable to give these same names to objects
perceived for the first time by sight:
Cube, sphere, table are words he has known applied to things perceiv-
able by touch, but to things perfectly intangible he never knew t h e m
applied. [...] the ideas of sight are all new perceptions, to which there
be no names annexed in his mind: he cannot therefore u n d e r s t a n d
what is said to him concerning them: and to ask of the two bodies he
saw placed on the table, which was the sphere, which the cube? were
to him a question downright bantering and unintelligible. ~
Berkeley emphasised t h a t it was erroneous to think t h a t one and the same
thing affected b o t h the sense of touch and the sense of sight. If the same
angle or shape which was the object of touch was also the object of sight,
w h a t would prevent the m a n from knowing it at first sight? 3
In order to provide an answer to the question of why visual and tactile
shapes are given the same name while not being of the same kind, Berkeley
once again m a d e a comparison with language. Words are not considered as
entities in themselves, he said, but as signs of things. Since it would be
superfluous to have a name for a thing and for a sign of t h a t thing, it is
c u s t o m a r y to indicate b o t h by the same name. T h e same would apply to
forms: visual forms are signs of tactile forms and are hardly regarded as
entities in themselves. It would be superfluous to have different names for
the tactile form and the visual form which indicates it. This does not imply
t h a t tactile and visual shapes are of the same sort. A tangible square and a
visible square are just as different as a tangible square and the six-letter word
"square" which indicates it. 4
R e s p o n d i n g to the objection t h a t a tactile square is more like a visual
square t h a n a visual circle, Berkeley stated t h a t while this is true,
it is not because it is liker, or more of a species with it, but because
the visible square contains in it several distinct parts, whereby to
Just as certain visual forms are more appropriate to represent certain tac-
tile forms, Berkeley stated, so also do certain written words better describe
sounds. The fact that letters represent sounds is in itself arbitrary. But
once it has become the object of common consent, the combination of letters
representing a certain sound is no longer arbitrary.
The question could be put as to why visual and tactile ideas can be so
easily confused, which is not the case with other symbols. Berkeley believed
that this was so because visual signs are constant and universal and because
their relationship to tactile ideas is learnt immediately after birth. ~ The signs
are not determined by man but the objects of sight constitute "the universal
language of Nature. ''3 It is a universal language which instructs us in how to
behave in order to acquire those things which are necessary for our existence
and welfare, and in order to avoid that which can cause us harm. However,
there is no necessary connection between visual and tactile figures and, said
Berkeley, this becomes evident if we consider that what seems round and
smooth to the touch may, when viewed under the microscope, appear quite
different .4
Berkeley closed his Essay with a few remarks on geometry. On the basis
of what we have already seen, he determined that the object of geometry is
constituted not by visual but by tactile extension and/orm. An intelligent
being having the sense of sight but lacking that of touch (an unbodied spirit,
a kind of inverse of Molyneux's person born blind) would, he thought, be
incapable of perceiving solid bodies or flat shapes. 5
To round off this section we are going to look at a philosopher influenced by
Berkeley (among others) but whose ideas regarding the relationship between
touch and sight were somewhat more subtle: Thomas Reid (171o 1796), the
founder of the Scottish school of common sense philosophy and later known
for his faculty psychology. In his An Inquiry into the Human Mind (1764)
Reid proposed two solutions to Molyneux's problem, one for when the man
was using only his sight and one for when he was also capable of mathematical
reasoning.
Reid had originally espoused the doctrine which stated that ideas are the
only immediate objects of awareness but, like Kant at a later date, he was
awakened from his slumbers by Hume's Enquiry concerning Human Under-
standing (1748). Reid considered Hume's philosophy to be a reductio ad
absurdum of scepticism; it was a system that pulled the carpet from under
our feet because it made it impossible to justify any of our beliefs. Reid came
to the conclusion that the origin of scepticism was to be found in the doc-
trine of ideas, this latter being based on prejudice and confusion. Reid was
thus of the opinion that the notion that the immediate data of perception are
ideas was nothing more than a hypothesis which could nowhere find support.
Moreover, the notion failed to fulfil the r51e for which it was created, since it
left unanswered all questions regarding the reliability of each perception.
Reid attacked the doctrine of ideas by appealing to common sense: the man
in the street is convinced that what he perceives is the thing itself and not
an idea nor an impression. Reid also believed that ideas in the philosophical
sense do not exist but are fictitious creations that simply do not need to be
postulated. Locke and Hume had based their notions on certain assumptions
regarding elements of knowledge (for Locke, simple ideas and for Hume, im-
pressions) and they had then gone on to regard knowledge as the result of
combining these elementary data with the perception of their similarities and
differences. However, Reid believed that the so-called elementary data were
nothing more than the result of analysis.
To bring some clarity into the discussion, Reid made a distinction between
sensation and perception. A sensation is, according to Reid, a feeling that
exists exclusively in the mind of the perceiver. 1 Sensations have nothing in
common with external objects, of which they are merely signs. By way of
example of a sentence indicating a sensation Reid gave "I feel a pain"; the
sentence "I see a tree" would, on the contrary, indicate a perception. ~ Reid
held that a perception always involves an object distinct from the action by
which it is perceived. 3 The perception of an object implies a concept of its
form and a belief in its current existence. This belief is a consequence of our
constitution and not of argumentation: "There is no reasoning in perception
1Reid [1764] 197o, ch. VI, §xx: "[a sensation] appears to be something which can have
no existence but in a sentient mind, no distinction from the act of the mind by which it is
felt."
2Reid [1764] 197o, ch. VI, §xx.
3Reid [1764] 197o, ch. VI, §xx: "Perception [...] hath always an object distinct from the
act by which it is perceived."
36 Chapter Three
[...] The belief which is implied in it, is the effect of instinct. ''1 In contrast to
Berkeley, Reid believed that an object can exist whether or not it be perceived.
Reid drew a distinction between two types of perception: some are natural
and original, others are acquired through experience. 2 It is true of all senses
to say that we have far more acquired than original perceptions, and it is
especially true of sight:
Like Locke and Berkeley, Reid drew a comparison between perception and lan-
guage. Our original perceptions are, he said, analogous to natural languages,
whereas acquired perceptions could be compared to artificial languages. The
signs employed in original perceptions are observations; the signs used in
natural languages are facial expressions, physical gestures and vocal modu-
lations. These signs are universal and the capacity to interpret them is not
acquired but inborn. In acquired perceptions the signs are either sensations
or things that we perceive through means of sensations. In artificial languages
the signs are articulated sounds. In both cases we discover the relationship
through experience. 4
Reid believed that perception must not only be distinguished from sen-
sation but also from the knowledge of the objects of sense which we have
acquired by reasoning. "When I look at the moon, I perceive her to be some-
times circular, sometimes horned, and sometimes gibbous. [...] from these
various appearances of her enlightened part, I infer that she is really of a
spherical figure. This conclusion is not obtained by simple perception, but by
reasoning." 5
Reid regarded sight as the noblest of our senses, but despite this he be-
lieved that only a fraction of the knowledge acquired by sight could not be
communicated to a person blind from birth. To clarify this notion he drew a
distinction between the visual appearance of things and the things which are
suggested by that appearance:
A book has various appearances, depending on the distance and the position
from which it is observed. But habit has taught us that we should regard
it as one and the same book: "overlooking the appearance, we immediately
conceive the real figure, distance, and position of the body, of which its visible
or perspective appearance is a sign and indication. ''~ Reid thus agreed with
Berkeley's "just and important observation" that the visual appearances of
objects constitute a kind of language used by nature to inform us of distance,
size and shape. Whenever we hear a familiar language we do not, after all,
take notice of the sounds but of the meaning of the words, of the things
indicated.
Reid believed that the visual form of an object is used only as a sign of
the real figure. He put it this way: When I use my original powers of sight
to look at a globe standing before me, I perceive only something of a circular
form, variously coloured. The visible figure has no distance from the eye, no
convexity, nor is it three-dimensional. But once I have learnt to perceive the
distance of every part of this object from the eye, this perception gives it
convexity and adds a third dimension. 3
Reid attempted to reveal the characteristics of visual forms by introducing
the Idomenians, creatures who (like Berkeley's unbodied spirit) would possess
only the faculty of sight. 4
1Reid [1764] 197o, ch. VI, §ii. The only profession for which it would be required to draw
the distinction alluded to is, said Reid, that of a painter. See Reid [1764] 197o, ch. VI, §iii.
~Reid [1764] 197o, ch. VI, §ii.
3Reid [1764] 197o, ch. VI, §xxiii.
4The Idomenians can be regarded as the predecessors of the nineteenth-century Flat-
landers invented by Edwin A. Abbott (Abbott 1884).
5Reid [1764] 197o, ch. VI, §ix.
6See also Daniels 197o.
38 Chapter Three
Reid believed that while a blind person gaining his sight would perceive
the same visible appearances of objects as we do, he would not understand
their language; he would only take note of the signs without realising their
significance. The blind man in Molyneux's question would therefore not know
which of the two objects was the sphere and which the cube if he only used
his ]aculty o/ sight:
As we will see in the next section, Reid believed that the result would be
different if the man was capable of mathematical reasoning.
Although there are other philosophers who gave a negative answer to Moly-
neux's question, the four already dealt with above will suffice here, since the
philosophical analyses proposed by the rest do not differ essentially from those
proposed by Molyneux, Locke, Berkeley and Reid. To the extent that these
other philosophers based their conclusion (partly) on empirical data, they will
be dealt with at a later stage.
Molyneux wrote to Locke that "upon Discourse with several concerning
your Book and Notions, I have proposed [my Problem] to Diverse very In-
genious Men, and could hardly ever Meet with One that at first dash would
give me the Answer to it, which I think true; till by hearing My Reasons they
were Convinced. ''~ W h a t were the grounds advanced by these learned men
for stating that a person blind from birth cured of blindness would be able to
use no more than his faculty of sight to state which was the sphere and which
the cube?
1Edward Synge, bishop of Raphoe (x714) and archbishop of Tuam (1716), was particu-
larly well known for his Gentleman's Religion (Synge 1693).
2Synge to Quayle, 6 September 1695, in Locke 1976-199o, vol. 5 (1979), no. 1984.
Molyneux enclosed a copy of Synge's letter with the letter he wrote to Locke on Tuesday
24 December 1695. Synge's letter was published in Locke 17o8.
3Synge to Quayle, 6 September 1695, in Locke 1976-199o, vol. 5 (1979), no. 1984.
4In fact this is what Synge wrote: "if immediately upon the sight of the globe and the
cube there be ground enough for such a person Clearly to perceive the Agreement and the
difference between his preconceived ideas and the newly conceived images of those figures
then he may be able to know which is the globe and which is the Cube." [My italics if and
then.]
40 Chapter Three
In his letter, Molyneux said that Locke would very easily be able to uncover
"by what false steps this Gentleman is lead into his Error. "1 Locke replied:
I see by Mr. S's answer to that which was originally your question,
how hard it is, even for ingenious men to free themselves from the
anticipations of sense. The first step towards knowledge is to have
clear and distinct ideas; which I have just reason every day more
and more, to think few men ever have, or think themselves to want;
which is one great cause of that infinite jargon and nonsense which
so pesters the world2
1Molyneux to Locke, 24 December 1695, in Locke 1976-199o, vol. 5 (1979), no. 1984.
2Locke to Molyneux, 5 April 1695, in Locke 1976-199o, vol. 5 (1979), no. 2%9.
3 L e e 1 7 o 2 , Preface.
4This only applies to front lighting.
Philosophical Discussions in the Eighteenth Century 41
ural Structure of the Eye appear farther off than otherwise they would, and
so the whole Superficies of the Globe appear protuberant, as it really is. "1
Regarding Molyneux's problem Lee wondered "whether there be not con-
stituted in Nature a necessary Connexion between a certain Motion upon the
organs of Touch, and a certain Perception, and a certain Figure at the bottom
of the Eye, and that same Perception. ''~ Lee thought that there must be a
relationship of this nature, otherwise we would never be able to perceive one
and the same object by both touch and sight. If the relationship did not exist,
this would mean that nature had interposed a separation between the various
senses, and Lee could not believe that this was the case. As we have seen,
Berkeley proposed such a separation. He believed that there was no question
of one single object being capable of being perceived by both touch and sight,
but rather was it a question of two different objects. But even if there was a
necessary relationship as proposed by Lee, the question would still remain as
to whether a person born blind gaining his sight would immediately perceive
the relationship.
Using a variant on Molyneux's problem Lee attempted to suggest that this
was the case and that experience had no part to play. A person born blind
who had learnt to distinguish between a saucer and a plate, which vary only
in size, would--believed L e e - - b e able to see which was the larger and which
the smaller without recourse to experience. 3 In the same way, the man would
be able to see that in the case of a cube the distance from the centre point to
points on the edge shows variations, whereas the radius of the sphere remains
constant. Lee therefore believed that "the Author of Nature has annex'd the
same Mode of Perception to a certain Motion upon the Organs of Touch as
there is a certain Figure in the Eye. TM The person born blind would only
have to learn the name of the mode. In view of the fact that he had done
that using the sense of touch, as Molyneux had assumed, Lee believed that
he would be able to identify the sphere and the cube.
Locke's Essay met with resistance not only in England but also on the Con-
tinent. It persuaded the versatile scholar Gottfried Wilhelm Leibniz (1646
1716 ) to write a critical commentary, a document on the basis of which Leib-
niz attempted some time around 1695 to arrange discussions with Locke, but
Locke did not react. In 17oo the French translation of Locke's Essay was
published, 5 which persuaded Leibniz that he should lay out his criticism for a
wider audience in an attractive literary f o r m - - a s a dialogue. The result, the
je crois que, suppos@ que l'aveugle sache que ces d e u x figures qu'il
voit sont celles du cube et du globe, il p o u r r a les discerner, et dire
sans toucher. Ceci est le globe, ceci le cube. 4
1In 17o6 Leibniz wrote to Thomas Burnet: "La mort de M. Locke m'a 5t~ l'envie de
publier mes remarques sur ces ouvrages; j'aime mieux publier maintenant mes pens@es ind~-
pendamment de celles d'un autre." Quoted by J. Brunschwig in his introduction to Leibniz
[1765] 1966, p. 15.
2Leibniz [1765] 1966 , bk. II, ch. i, §2.
3Leibniz accused Locke of failing to adhere to his own programme: "I1 semble que notre
habile auteur pr@tend qu'il n'y a rien de virtuel en nous et m@me rien dont nous ne nous
apercevions toujours actuellement; mais il ne peut pas le prendre ~ la rigueur, autrement
son sentiment serait trop paradoxe, puisque encore les habitudes acquises et les provisions
de notre m@moire ne sont pas toujours aper§ues [...] I1 limite aussi sa th~se en d'autres
endroits, en disant qu'il n'y a rien en nous dont nous ne nous soyons au moins aper~us
autrefois." Leibniz [1765] 1966, Prdface.
4Leibniz [1765] 1966 , bk. II, ch. ix, §8.
Philosophical Discussions in the Eighteenth Century 43
a distinction between the two objects. For the man would know beforehand
that he was to be shown a sphere and a cube. According to Th@ophile it was
therefore without question that he would be able to distinguish them "[par]
les principes de la raison, joints £ ce que l'attouchement lui a fourni aupar-
avant de connaissance sensuelle. ''1 The reason for this conviction was that a
sphere has no points which are distinct from other points because its surface
is flat and without angles, while a cube has eight points which are distinct
from each other.
Leibniz thus placed arguments in Th~ophile's mouth similar to those ad-
vanced by Synge. He subsequently had Th@ophile state that if this means of
distinguishing forms were not to exist, a blind person would not be capable
of understanding the basics of geometry by means of touch, whereas we know
that persons blind from birth can certainly do this. In contrast to Berkeley
Leibniz believed that a paralytic could, indeed, do geometry. He even stated
that geometry is mostly learnt by sight alone. And if the geometry of a blind
person were to be compared with that of a paralytic, we would see that both
have arrived at the same ideas, though they would not have any common
images:
Et il faut que ces deux g@om~tries, celle de l'aveugle et celle du para-
lytique, se rencontrent et s'accordent et m@me reviennent aux m@mes
id@es, quoiqu'il n'y ait point d'images communes2
Les idles qn'on dit venir de plus d'un sens, comme celle de l'espace,
figure, mouvement, repos, sont plutSt du sens commun, c'est-£-dire
de l'esprit-m@me, car ce sont des idles de l'entendement pur, mais
qui ont du rapport £ l'ext@rieur, et que les sens font apercevoir; aussi
sont-elles capables de d~finitions et de d~monstrations. 4
This opinion is, indeed, very close to what Locke had stated.
Leibniz emphatically added, through the mouth of Th~ophile, that he was
not speaking of what the man would immediately do when amazed and con-
fused by the novelty, or when he was scarcely used to drawing consequences:
"je ne parle pas de ce qu'il fera peut-~tre en effet et sur-le-champ, ~tant 6bloui
et confondu par la nouveaut~ ou d'ailleurs peu accoutum~ £ tirer des consS-
quences." 3 In this, Leibniz was of the same opinion as Berkeley.
Francis Hutcheson (1694-1747) , an Irish philosopher known particularly for
his theory of moral sense in ethics, gave an answer to Molyneux's question
which is remarkably similar to that given by Leibniz. On 6 September 172 7
Hutcheson wrote a letter to William Mace of Gresham College in which he
dealt with Berkeley's immaterialism and, partly in response to his point of
view, gave a positive answer to Molyneux's question. The letter was first
published in 1788. 4
As already mentioned, Berkeley had stated in his Essay that either visual
extension and forms differ from tactile extension and forms or that the solution
proposed by Molyneux and Locke was incorrect. 5 Berkeley was of the opinion
that the former was the case; Hutcheson held to the latter: "Messrs. Locke
and Molyneux are both wrong about the cube and sphere proposed to a blind
man restored to sight. He would not at first know the sphere from a shaded
plain surface by a view from above; but a side view would discover the equal
uniform relievo in one, and the cubic one in the other. ''1
According to Hutcheson we can judge by touch, with eyes closed, what the
visual extension of a touched object will be when we open our eyes, but we
cannot determine by touch which colour we will see:
which shews visible and tangible extension to be really the same idea,
or to have one idea common, viz. the extension; though the purely
tangible and visible perceptions are quite disparate. 2
This statement clearly recalls the statement made by Leibniz that visual and
tactile images of forms differ from one another, although their exact ideas
are the same. Both philosophers meant that while visual and tactile sensa-
tions of forms are different, the accompanying concepts are the same or have
something in common. 3
Like Leibniz, Hutcheson believed that a blind person would understand
nothing of geometry if visual and tactile ideas of extension were totally differ-
ent, as Berkeley had suggested. However, blind people do in fact understand
geometry--using, for example, wooden s h a p e s - - a n d thus visual and tactile
ideas must, he believed, be the same.
Hutcheson wanted to illustrate the erroneous nature of Berkeley's thesis
using a thought experiment inspired by Molyneux's problem. Imagine a per-
son, proposed Hutcheson, both paralytic and blind, with no notion of either
type of extension, yet having a keen sense of smell. Imagine further that an
object exists which changes its smell with every change of its shape. The
blind paralytic will give the various smells various names. Another person,
this one sighted, will use the same names for the various shapes. This latter
person will reason concerning the shapes or will formulate one of Euclid's
theorems concerning the relationship between the sides. Would it be possi-
ble, asked Hutcheson, for the blind paralytic to agree with this? Would he
recognise the meaning by means of the smells? Hutcheson did not answer
this rhetorical question. Possibly he was hoping that all right-thinking people
would answer "no," since smells and visual forms and extension have noth-
ing in common. But a blind person would certainly be able to speak about
geometry with someone possessing only the sense of sight. This, stated Hutch-
eson, demonstrates that visual and tactile extension (and forms) possess an
idea in common. And apparently he believed that a person born blind would
immediately notice this idea when he first saw a sphere and a cube.
In the second edition of his Essai philosophique sur l'dme des b~tes, pub-
lished in 1737, the Dutch preacher and philosopher David Renaud Boullier
(1694-1759) proposed a solution to Molyneux's problem which was in line
with those put forward by Leibniz and Hutcheson. 1 The aim of his Essai was
to prove that animals possess a soul and to investigate the nature of this soul.
Boullier's discussion of the perception of animals tempted him into enlarging
on the nature of our sensations, which brought him to Molyneux's problem,
which he called "Paradoxe de mr. Locke."
The answer given by Locke was, said Boullier, incorrect and "peu digne
d'un Esprit aussi solide que le sien. ''~ The reason why Locke's reasoning did
not add up was, according to Boullier, as follows:
Boullier therefore concluded that a person born blind gaining his sense of
sight would discover the same difference between the sphere and the cube as
he had already learnt through his sense of touch:
1The first edition of this work appeared in 1728. I have not seen this edition.
2Boullier [1728] 1737, part II, ch. vi, §18.
3Boullier [1728] 1737, part II, ch. vi, §18.
4Boullier [1728] 1737, part II, ch. vi, §18. Here Boullier added that "la vue de ces deux
Solides perfectionnera, rendra plus nette et plus vive l'id@equ'il en avoit d~ja reque par un
autre sens, et lui fera faire par cons@quent un discernement plus exact et plus juste entre
Fun et l'autre."
Philosophical Discussions in the Eighteenth Century 47
and t h a t it has, like other senses, its illusions which other senses, experience
and understanding have to correct. Sight, for example, would show us solid
objects as flat and deformed:
Selon la distance et l'aspect, les Corps sont vus sous une figure diffS-
rente de la v6ritable. Les angles d'un Cube sont 6moussez, certains
c6tez retr6cis, un Globe nous paroit une surface platte et circulaire
etc. 1
However, Boullier believed that this does not prevent our sight from providing
knowledge of the same properties as does our sense of touch and that it assures
us of the identity of the object that we have perceived through these two
senses.
Boullier was of the opinion that the example of the sphere and the cube
was deceptive because sight does not give us immediately an idea of solidity,
nor of the hardness or resistance of a body. He was the first to suggest taking
a square and a circle. The blind person in question will acquire the idea of
these two shapes and their properties vi£ the sense of touch, said Boullier,
and since the faculty of sight will reveal the same properties the man will be
able to say which is the square and which the circle:
La vue lui offre les m~mes rapports d'6galit6 entre les rayons du Cer-
cle, la m~me uniformit6 de Courbure, les m~mes differences entre le
Cercle et le Quarry, que le tact lui avoit d~ja fait apercevoir. L£-des-
sus il dira sans hSziter, c'est un Cercle; et de l'autre figure, c'est un
Quarr6.2
Is it not asking too much to ascribe this type of reasoning to a blind person?
Would we not be raising him to the level of a deep-thinking philosopher? No,
affirmed Boullier, for I am merely proposing that he is capable of thinking,
which in no way deviates from the terms in which the problem is laid out;
moreover it is well known that blind people are good practitioners of geometry.
W h a t we should really be asking, according to Boullier, is whether the man
would be capable of distinguishing the two objects from each other without
first thinking deeply about it:
1Joseph Priestley (1733-18o4) , the discoverer of oxygen, agreed with Jurin's answer to
Molyneux's question: see Priestley 1772 , pp. 72o-725 .
~Jurin 1738 , p. 29, §17o. Nicholas Saunderson (1682-1739) was one year old when he
lost his sight as result of smallpox. He was Lucasian professor of mathematics and the
subjects he taught included Newtonian philosophy, hydrostatics, astronomy, acoustics and
optics. He practised palpable arithmetic using a calculating table which he had himself
invented. Saunderson detailed his arithmetic in Saunderson 174o.
3Reid [1764] 197o , ch. VI, §vii.
4Reid [1764] 197o , ch. VI, §xi.
50 Chapter Three
the first surprise caused by new objects has subsided, the man should be
given time to study them in his mind and to compare them with the ideas
obtained by touch; and especially to compare in his mind the visual form
and extension with the form and extension in length and breadth with which
he is already familiar thanks to the sense of touch. Reid believed that the
man would be capable of perceiving that both have length and breadth: "he
will perceive, that there may be visible as well as tangible circles, triangles,
quadrilateral and multilateral figures. ''1 This would be particularly true of
small objects which can be perceived at a glance. In the case of larger objects,
Reid believed, the properties of visual forms would differ from those of the
flat surfaces they represent. Reid concluded that
if Dr. Saunderson had been made to see, and attentively had viewed
the figures of the first book of Euclid, he might, by thought and
consideration, without touching them, have found out that they were
the very figures he was before so well acquainted with by touch. 2
If flat surfaces were to be looked at from an angle, this would be more diffi-
cult since the visual form then differs more from the tactile form. And, said
Reid, the visual representation of three-dimensional forms would be less per-
fect because visual extension does not have three but only two dimensions.
Nonetheless, we can say that there is some similarity, so Reid believed. And
therefore Berkeley had committed a major error by assuming that there is
absolutely no agreement between the extension, form and position which we
see and which we perceive by touch. 3
As far as the positive replies to Molyneux's question are concerned, we will
limit our investigations to the above philosophers. Here too the same applies:
others thinkers replied in similar ways. Those who supported their point of
view with empirical data will be dealt with in a subsequent chapter.
4 CONCLUSIONS
All the philosophers we have so far examined made the basic assumption that
tactile and visual sensations differ from one another, and that is an acceptable
point of view. A number of them based their solution to Molyneux's problem
on this point. Some philosophers were of the opinion that there is a necessary
relationship between visual and tactile sensations of the form of objects. Those
who, like Molyneux, believed that this relationship can only be found out
through experience expected that the person born blind would be incapable
of distinguishing a sphere from a cube by sight. However, those who, like Lee,
were convinced that this relationship could be perceived immediately, gave
positive answers to Molyneux's question. Those who adopted a third position,
including Jurin and Reid, were of the opinion that the relationship could
be deduced by (mathematical) reasoning; they too gave a positive answer.
Berkeley and his disciples, however, believed that experience merely created
an arbitrary relationship between visual and tactile perceptions. A person
born blind would, they said, be unable to identify the sphere and the cube by
sight.
Molyneux's problem was also solved on the basis of other considerations,
related to the relationship between visual and ~actile concepts of the form
of objects. Some philosophers assumed that these concepts differ from one
another and can be made to relate to one another either by experience or by
understanding. Reasoning of this kind produced a negative and a positive
response respectively.
Other scholars, however, believed that visual and tactile concepts of form
are essentially identical or, at any rate, possess a common concept. Some of
these people, including Boullier and Hutcheson, believed that this could be
immediately perceived. Others, such as Leibniz, were of the opinion that this
identity would only be brought to light by understanding. These philosophers
were of the opinion that the person born blind restored to sight would be able
to state (immediately or not) which of the objects was the sphere and which
the cube.
In brief, there was a range of opinions which served as arguments in the
solutions proposed to Molyneux's question. There was no unanimity as to
what the correct solution could be. The most that can be said is that thinkers
who were inclined towards rationalism tended to give a positive answer while
the empiricists usually answered Molyneux's question in the negative.
The varying interpretations given to Molyneux's question hampered any
attempts to reach a unanimous answer. Some philosophers assumed that the
person born blind had to answer immediately while others thought it normal
that he be allowed to use his understanding and to move around the objects.
Some thought it would even make a difference if the man were to know that
he was to be presented with a sphere and a cube. And, of course, the various
options led to different answers.
Molyneux's problem inspired philosophers to invent further thought exper-
iments designed to provide us with information about our perception. Berke-
ley, for example, introduced the notion of an unbodied spirit, while Hutcheson
imagined a world in which the re-shaping of objects would be accompanied
by different smells. Leibniz, moreover, pointed to the importance of studying
52 Chapter Three
the ideas of people lacking one or other of the senses, a theme which we will
encounter again.
Up till this stage no-one had posed the question as to whether a person born
blind could really be given the power of sight. Everyone regarded Molyneux's
problem as a hypothetical question amenable to a solution by reasoning. It
was not until it became known that certain people born blind could be given
their sight by a cataract operation that the question arose as to whether the
eyes could provide useful information immediately following the operation.
From that moment attempts were made to test the solutions grounded in
theory against experimental data.
In fact Berkeley was the first to perceive the importance of experience as
the touchstone for his solution to Molyneux's problem. In the Appendix to
the second edition of his Essay of 171o he announced that shortly after the
publication of the first edition of the Essay he had learnt that a man born
blind in the vicinity of London had recovered his sight at the age of twenty:
Such a one may be supposed a proper judge to decide how far some
tenets laid down in several places of the foregoing essay are agreeable
to truth, and if any curious person hath the opportunity of making
proper interrogatories to him thereon, I should gladly see my notions
either amended or confirmed by experience.1
T H E F I R S T E X P E R I M E N T A L DATA
1 CHESELDEN'S OPERATION
1William Cheselden (1688-1752) was famous not only for the cataract operation alluded
to here but also for his "lateral operation for the stone" (an operation to remove kidney
stone) (1727) which was attended by surgeons from the whole of Europe. Cheselden was
the discoverer of the artificial pupil. He wrote two seminal works: The Anatomy of the
Human Body (1713) and Osteographia, or Anatomy of the Bones (1733). The Anatomy is
full of magnificent copperplate engravings produced using the camera obscura. See Cope
1953 and Hausmann 1989.
2The following section explains what a cataract operation is.
53
54 Chapter Four
Cheselden did not write his report until after the second operation, prob-
ably basing his writing on what he could remember and not on notes made
at the time. In general he set down the observations made by his patient
without further comment. Only a few times did he report verbatim what the
boy had said. One of these passages caused great confusion for decades and
was the occasion of a great deal of criticism.
Because Cheselden's report is of major significance, I quote it in full. Then
I take the opportunity to describe cataract as it actually is and the sorts of
cataract operation usual in the eighteenth century. Following that I shall seek
out the information contained in Cheselden's report that can be related to
Molyneux's problem. But first let us hear the voice of William Cheselden,
"F. R. S. Surgeon to her Majesty, and to St. Thomas's Hospital":
Thing, nor any one Thing from another, however different in Shape,
or Magnitude; but upon being told what Things were, whose Form he
before knew from feeling, he would carefully observe, that he might
know them again; but having too many Objects to learn at once, he
forgot many of them; and (as he said) at first he learn'd to know, and
again forgot a thousand Things in a Day. One Particular only (tho'
it may appear trifling) I will relate; Having often forgot which was
the Cat, and which the Dog, he was asham'd to ask; but catching
the Cat (which he knew by feeling) he was observ'd to look at her
stedfastly, and then setting her down, said, So Puss! I shall know you
another Time. He was very much surpriz'd, that those Things which
he had lik'd best, did not appear most agreeable to his Eyes, expecting
those Persons would appear most beautiful that he lov'd most, and
such Things to be most agreeable to his Sight that were so to his
Taste. We thought he soon knew what Pictures represented, which
were shew'd to him, but we found afterwards we were mistaken; for
about two Months after he was couch'd, he discovered at once, they
represented solid Bodies; when to that Time he consider'd them only
as Party-colour'd Planes, or Surfaces diversified with a Variety of
Paint; but even then he was no less surpriz'd, expecting the Pictures
would feel like the Things they represented, and was amaz'd when he
found those Parts, which by their Light and Shadow appear'd now
round and uneven, felt only flat like the rest; and ask'd which was
the lying Sense, Feeling or Seeing?
Being shewn his Father's Picture in a Locket at his Mother's watch,
and told what it was, he acknowledged a Likeness, but was vastly
surpriz'd; asking, how it could be, that a large Face could be express'd
in so little Room, saying, It should have seem'd as impossible to him,
as to put a Bushel of any thing into a Pint.
At first, he could bear but very little Sight, and the Things he saw,
he thought extreamly large; but upon seeing Things larger, those first
seen he conceiv'd less, never being able to imagine any Lines beyond
the Bounds he saw; the Room he was in he said, he knew to be but
Part of the House, yet he could not conceive that the whole House
could look bigger. Before he was couch'd, he expected little Advan-
tage from Seeing, worth undergoing an Operation for, except reading
and writing; for he said, He thought he could have no more Pleasure
in walking abroad than he had in the Garden, which he could do
safely and readily. And even Blindness he observ'd, had this Advan-
tage, that he could go any where in the Dark much better than those
who can see; and after he had seen, he did not soon lose this Quality,
nor desire a Light to go about the House in the Night. He said, every
56 Chapter Four
new Object was a new Delight, and the Pleasure was so great, t h a t he
wanted Ways to express it; but his Gratitude to his O p e r a t o r he could
not conceal, never seeing him for some Time without Tears of Joy in
his Eyes, and other Marks of Affection: And if he did not h a p p e n
to come at any Time when he was expected, he would be so griev'd,
t h a t he could not forbear crying at his Disappointment. A Year after
first Seeing, being carried u p o n Epsom Downs, and observing a large
Prospect, he was exceedingly delighted with it, and call'd it a new
Kind of Seeing. And now being lately couch'd of his other Eye, he
says, t h a t Objects at first a p p e a r ' d large to this Eye, but not so large
as t h e y did at first to the other, and looking upon the same Object
with b o t h Eyes, he t h o u g h t it look'd a b o u t twice as large as with
the first couch'd Eye only, but not Double, t h a t we can any Ways
discover. 1
1Cheselden 1728, PP. 447-450. Cheselden included his report in later editions of The
Anatomy and added the following sentence: "I have couched several others who were born
blind, whose observations were of the same kind; but they being younger, none of them
gave so full an account as this gentleman." Quoted by Morgan 1977, p. 21.
2Von Senden [1932] 196o, pp. 326-335, supplies an extensive list of reported cataract
operations, beginning with that carried out by Ammar (c. looo, Egypt) up to this century.
3Pastore 1971, p. 99.
The First Experimental Data 57
2 CATARACT
3 CATARACT OPERATIONS
1A healthy lens is transparent thanks to the regular placing of the lens tissue fibres. The
formation of deviant fibres results in a more or less opaque lens.
2Susruta (looo s.c.?) may have been the first surgeon who performed the couching
operation (see Bidyadhar 1939, 194o , 1941, and Dutt 1938). The first description of a
cataract operation in European literature can be found in Celsus's De re medicina (first
half of the first century) (Celsus 1935-1938, vol. 3, PP. 349 353). It has been suggested
that Jesus effected his miraculous cures of blind people (see, for instance, Mark 8:22 26)
by pushing aside the opaque lenses of cataract patients (see Forrest 1965 and Forrest 1974).
(Cheselden and the Biblical miracles were already mentioned in one breath in Charles Bew
18oo, p. 58.)
3Ammar extracted opaque lenses with hollow needles as early as looo A.D., but this had
been forgotten. See Hirschberg 19o5, pp. 1128-1129.
The First Experimental Data 59
M. M~ry croit qu'on pourroit tirer les Cataractes hors de l'oeil par
une incision faite k la Corn~e, &: que cette maniere dont il ne paro~t
pas qu'il y ait rien k apprehender, pr~viendroit tousles p~rils ou les
inconveniences de l'operation ordinaire. II est bien stir que la Cata-
racte ne remonteroit point, ~: ne causeroit point les inflammations
qu'elle peut causer, lorsqu'on la loge par force dans le bas de l'oeil.~
A third advantage of the new method was that it was no longer necessary to
postpone the operation until the cataract was mature or hard. 3
The first successful cataract extraction was performed by the Parisian doc-
tor Petit on 17 April 17o8. 4 Despite the advantages of the new method,
doctors continued to use the old one until Jacques Daviel, "oculiste ordinaire
de Louis XV," improved Petit's method and instruments in 1753 .5 This was
the reason why Daviel is usually said to be the discoverer of the cataract
extraction technique. In the second half of the eighteenth century the ad-
vantages and disadvantages of reclination and extraction were the subject of
heated debate. 6
It is important to note here that eyesight can never be perfect after these
two types of operation since the lens has disappeared and, with it, part of the
eye's refractive capacity. A ~ataract operation makes the patient far-sighted
and if good eyesight is to be restored there is need of optical correction, in
1M~ry was present at the eye operation carried out by Charles de Saint-Yves on Sunday
2o February 17o7 on a patient whose lens was pressing against the iris. Saint-Yves removed
the lens from the eye, thus performing the first recorded lens extraction in modern times.
See Mfinchow 1984, p. 264.
~[Fontenelle] 17o7, p. 24. I do not know whether Mfinchow's (1984, p. 280) ascription
of this anonymous article to Fontenelle is correct.
3It has been discovered that it is important that babies suffering from double cataract
should be operated on as soon as possible (preferably before they are two months old) since
otherwise they will develop amblyopia as a result of visual deprivation.
4petit performed the operation after consultation with and in the presence of M~ry
and Saint-Yves, who had previously carried out a lens extraction. See Mfinchow 1984,
pp. 264-265.
5In 1747 Daviel (1693-1762) performed his first cataract extraction after an attempt at
couching had failed. From 175o onwards he decided to use the new method exclusively. He
published his findings in Daviel 1748 and Daviel 1753.
6Daviel's method was fiercely supported by, for example, the elder Baron Wenzel--who
did, however, admit to having destroyed "a hatful of eyes" before mastering the technique
(Lebensohn 1969, p. 176 ). Gerard ten Haaff (172o-1791), lector at the Illustere School
of Rotterdam, was the first surgeon in the United Republic of the Netherlands to apply
Daviel's method. See Ten Haaff 1761 and Henkes 1982 , p. 11.
6o Chapter Four
the form of a lens or glasses. 1 The need for optical correction was already
perceived by Benito Daza de Valdes in 1623. In his Uso de los antojos, one
of the first books about spectacles, he recommended the wearing of glasses
for patients who had had a cataract operation. Similarly, Jacques Rohault
wrote in his Trait~ de physique (1672): "ceux £ qui l'on a ost~ des Cataractes
ne s~auroient voir que confus~ment; [...] ils ont besoin de lunettes fort pour
voir distinctement. ''~ And Louis wrote in the Encyclopddie: "apr~s qu'on
a abaiss6 la cataracte, la personne ne peut plus voir qu'£ l'aide d'une verre
lenticulaire. ''3 As will be seen in the next few sections, this fact was missed
by all the eighteenth-century commentators on Cheselden's report.
4 CHESELDEN'S OBSERVATIONS
1After a cataract operation the patient will normally need glasses of approximately +1o
dioptres with a 2-dioptre cylinder at 18o degrees (to compensate for the vertical flattening
of the cornea caused by the incision). These days it is also possible to fit a contact lens or
an intra-ocular lens. See Trevor-Roper & Curran [1974] 1984, p. 452.
2Rohault 1672, p. 488.
3Louis 1752, p. 77o,
The First Experimental Data 61
little confirmed, many years after I had been led into the discovery of them
by reasoning." •
Robert Smith (1689-1768), mathematician and professor of astronomy and
experimental philosophy at Cambridge's Trinity College, quoted Cheselden's
report in its entirety in his influential book A Compleat System o/Opticks
(1738)P This work, which deals with popular, mathematical, mechanical and
philosophical aspects of optics, contains a chapter on the ideas that we obtain
from our sense of sight and it was here that Smith described Molyneux's
problem. As far as Smith was concerned, the answer given by Molyneux and
Locke had turned out to be correct: "this opinion has since been confirmed by
the experience of several persons, who receiving their sight from the operation
of Couching, could not know any one thing from another, however different
in shape and magnitude."3 Smith referred to The Tatler 4 and to Cheselden's
report. Smith suspected that the patient had learnt to recognise the position,
size, shape and distance of objects by sight by following the movements of his
hand with his eyes. The ideas acquired by sight would then, he believed, be
associated with those gained through touch by means of habituation.
Berkeley's theory of vision gained a great deal of support especially in Great
Britain, but there were also some followers to be found on the Continent.
Voltaire (1694-1778), for instance, who visited England in the years 1726-
1728, was impressed not only by the liberal political and cultural climate he
found there but also by the experimental science of Newton, the empiricist
philosophy of Locke and the ideas advanced by Berkeley regarding the sense
of sight. The works he wrote after returning home included the Eldmens de la
philosophie de Neuron (1738), a popularisation of Newton's philosophy. The
book contained not only an explanation of the way in which we learn to see
such things as distance but also a summary of Cheselden's report, thereby
making it accessible to the French-speaking world. ~
Voltaire believed that distance, position, size and shape are not directly
seen with the aid of optical lines and angles. Like Berkeley he considered that
this had been proved by the reactions of people born blind who had undergone
surgery:
des distances, des grandeurs et des situations, il efit ~t~ vrai que les
angles optiques, form,s tout d'un coup dans sa r~tine, eussent ~t~ les
causes imm~diates de ses sentimens. [...] Mais off trouver l'aveugle
dont d~pendait la d~cision indubitable de cette question? 1
As could have been anticipated, Voltaire found this blind person in Ches-
elden's patient. Voltaire provided a s u m m a r y of the report written by this
"clever and skilful" surgeon and invented a few details himself. He wrote, for
example, that at the beginning the young man could not distinguish between
objects that he had assessed, using his hands, as rounded or angled. 2 Voltaire
was convinced that the experiences of the young man confirmed everything
that Locke and Berkeley had so accurately predicted: "I1 ne distingua de
long-temps ni grandeurs, ni situations, ni figures mSme. ''3
Voltaire considered his opinion regarding how we do not see things to have
been justified. The question now was how we do imagine shapes and suchlike.
His answer, which betrays Berkeley's influence, was as follows: in the same
way as we imagine people's passions, namely by reading their facial expres-
sions and the colour of their faces. It is a language spoken by nature to all
eyes; but we need experience to learn to understand it. Voltaire compared
the way in which we learn to see with the way in which we learn to speak or
read, with the difference that seeing is easier.
Strictly speaking, said Voltaire, distance, size and position are not visible
things; the real and direct object of seeing is nothing more than coloured light.
All the rest we observe only after a time and through experience. And since
as far as the representation is concerned all mankind has the same language
which apparently links colour to objects, we could be tempted to believe that
we see extension. We could also tend to think that there is a necessary link
between words and meanings if everyone spoke the same language, but we
know that such is not the case.
Voltaire believed that in addition to experience we need the help of other
senses in order to assess a (sudden and arbitrary) judgment about distance
and suchlike. But he tempered this opinion by stating that a being that
possessed no more than the sense of sight would still be able to form ideas of
distance and such through experience:
Sans doute ses idles d'~tendue, de distance, ne seraient pas rigoureu-
sement les m~mes que les n5tres, puisque le sens du toucher n'aurait
pas contribu@ k les former: sans doute ses jugemens sur le lieu, la
forme, la distance, seraient plus souvent erron@s que les n6tres, parce
qu'il n'aurait pu les rectifier par le toucher. Mais il est tr~s probable
que c'est k quoi se bornerait toute la diff@rence entre lui et nous. 1
How this creature would form these ideas according to Voltaire is not clear.
But the strong suspicion expressed by Voltaire in this passage would certainly
not have been confirmed by Berkeley who, in fact, believed that an unbodied
spirit would be unable to perceive extension or shapes.
Whereas Voltaire introduced Cheselden's report into the French-speaking
world, it was Willem J a c o b ' s Gravesande who was the first Dutchman to
allude to it, in his Introductio ad philosophiam, metaphysicam et logicam con-
tinens (1736). ~ The relevant passage reads as follows (in the second edition
of 1737):
Facultatem hanc de objectis visis judicandi, Usui & Experientim tan-
turn deberi, ex natura rei deducitur. Sed omnis scrupulus removetur,
si perpendatur historia Juvenis cceci nati, & qui, inter annum mtatis
decimum tertium & decimum quartum, visum recuperavit; qum inve-
nitur in Actis Philosophicis Societatis Regime Anglicanm. Num. 4o2.
Art. 7 .3
Like his colleague Petrus van Musschenbroek, 's Gravesande had been influ-
enced by the new experimental philosophy during a visit to England. 4 Both
imitated Locke in fiercely opposing the notion that we have inborn ideas of
external objects. They were convinced that people lacking one of the senses
would not be capable of forming ideas of the related characteristics of objects.
Both philosophers referred to cured cataract patients in order to support their
belief that we learn to see. 5
The methods employed in and the results obtained from Cheselden's studies
were challenged mainly in France, where Berkeley's teachings on the faculty
of sight turned out to be less sacrosanct than in Great Britain. 1 A number of
philosophes wondered, for instance, if the patient's eyes immediately follow-
ing the operation had been in good condition and whether the patient had
been questioned in an appropriate, non-suggestive manner. Julien Offray de
La Mettrie (17o 9 1751 ) was the first to a t t e m p t to deal with these matters.
La Mettrie, whose reputation was largely due to his L'homme machine
(1747) , had previously proclaimed his materialistic doctrine anonymously in
the Histoire naturelle de l'dme (1745).: As is well known, La Mettrie opposed
the dualism of body and soul as proclaimed by Descartes. La Mettrie assumed
t h a t the activities of the soul are dependent on the structure and functions of
the nervous system. Like the body, therefore, the soul would be amenable to
experimental research. The "natural history of the soul" should therefore not
be the territory of the theologian or metaphysician but of the natural scientist.
La Mettrie deprived mankind of the status that Descartes still accorded the
species. Where Descartes excluded mankind from his notion of all living
creatures as a u t o m a t a , La Mettrie regarded man too as a machine or self-
regulating system. Since in La Mettrie's view nature was self-explanatory,
he did not require a hypothesis of a creator God. As could be expected,
La Mettrie's materialistic-atheist philosophy met with fierce resistance, but it
also had considerable influence.
In the Histoire naturelle de l'dme La Mettrie revealed himself a defender
of the notion that all our ideas come from our senses. At the end of the book
he set out a number of true accounts designed to support this statement. 3
T h e y are stories of individuals whose fate differed from that of "normal"
people. The first concerned a deaf-and-dumb boy from Chartres who suddenly
1In Great Britain criticism of Berkeley's theory of vision and his solution to Molyneux's
problem came from such quarters as Anti-Berkeley 1752 and Porterfield 1759.
2The title page was designed to give the impression that the book had been translated
from English. The work was reprinted (with modifications) as Traitd de l'~me in La Met-
trie's (Euvres philosophiques (La Mettrie 1751).
3La Mettrie 1745, ch. XVII; this is chapter XV in La Mettrie 1751.
66 Chapter F o u r
1The original text dealing with the deaf boy of Chartres can be found in the Histoire de
l'Acaddmie des Sciences pour l'annde 17o3, second edition (Paris 172o), pp. 18-19.
2According to Verbeek 1988, vol. 1, p. 117, La Mettrie took this story from Bernard
Connor 1697.
3Arnobius, Adversus gentes (c. 3oo A.D,), bk. II. See Arnobius 1949 for a modern
translation.
4The physician J. C. Amman (1669-1724) occupied himself with the education of deaf-
and-dumb people. See Amman 1692.
5La Mettrie 1745, "Conclusion de l'ouvrage."
6La Mettrie was the first to point out that Cheselden's account was inconsistent: the
boy was said not to perceive any size, and yet he said that his thumb was as big as a house.
La Mettrie 1745, ch. XVII, Histoire iii.
The First Experimental Data 67
opened up new paths by his observation and analysis of the human mind. But
Condillac accused Locke of not having succeeded in setting out a consistent
form of empiricism since he had introduced reflection as an inborn capacity.
Condillac's Essai was intended to correct Locke's failures and it also contained
the first criticism of Berkeley's theory of vision.
Condillac's entire philosophy was based on the statement that we may not
ascribe any capacities to the mind of which we are not aware or of which we
cannot make ourselves aware. He thus criticised both Locke and Berkeley who
had assumed unconscious judgments as an explanation of certain phenomena
of perception. Judgments of this type, said Condillac, would be in conflict
with our experience. Molyneux's problem, which Locke had introduced in
order to illustrate his thesis, would in no way refute this. 1
Condillac agreed with Locke that the retinal image of a sphere was an
unevenly coloured circle. But he did not accept that the sensation we have
by means of the retinal image is the sensation of a circle:
P a r m i ces suppositions, Locke avance, sans preuve, que la sensation
de l'£me ne repr~sente rien de plus que l'image que nous savons se
tracer dans l'oeil. Pour moi, quand je regarde un globe, je vois autre
chose qu'un cercle plat: experience £ laquelle il me paro~t tout naturel
de m ' e n r a p p o r t e r 2
In Condillac's opinion Locke should have been consistent and should have
argued about distance, position, size and extension in the same way that he
had concerning shape. But Locke had not done so: in Molyneux's problem
he required the globe and the cube to be of approximately the same size,
thereby implying that sight can give us various notions of size without the
help of any other judgment whatsoever. Locke thus contradicted himself,
believed Condillac, since it is impossible to understand how one can have
ideas of size without having ideas of shape.
In contrast to Locke, Berkeley had drawn the conclusion that a blind person
suddenly being given the faculty of sight would be unable to determine not
only shape, but also position, distance and size. Berkeley had invented a
thought experiment regarding an unbodied spirit in order to demonstrate that
the pure objects of sight cannot be considered geometrical forms. This kind
of ~eil animd, as Condillac called it, would in Berkeley's view be able to see
only coloured light, but no extension etc. It would become accustomed, stated
Condillac, to judging the whole of nature as a mathematical point. But what
we in fact see, according to Condillac, is light and colours which of necessity
delineate different distances, different sizes and different positions.
il ne faut pas croire qu'au moment qu'il ouvre les yeux, il jouisse
d~j£ du spectacle que produit dans toute la nature ce mSlange admi-
rable de lumi~re et de couleur. C'est un tr~sor qui est renferm~ dans
les nouvelles sensations qu'il ~prouve; la r~flexion peut seule le lui
d~couvrir et lui en donner la vraie jouissance. 1
When we ourselves turn our eyes to a richly decorated painting and see it in
its entirety we do not as yet form any particular idea of it. We must first,
said Condillac, consider all its parts separately.
Once the person born blind is capable of reflecting on what he sees, Condil-
lac believed that he would no longer see a point but extension with a certain
length, breadth and depth. When he comes to analyzing this extension, he
will form ideas for himself of surface, line, point and all kinds of shapes, and
those ideas will be identical to those which he has acquired through touch:
The person born blind would thus be able to distinguish the sphere from the
cube by sight, because he would recognise in them the same ideas he had
formed through the sense of touch. 3
It would be possible, said Condillac, to have the man defer his judgment
by asking him what made him so sure that bodies must have the same shape
when perceived by sight as when perceived by touch. Indeed, it could well
be that an object that looks like a sphere may appear on touching it to be a
cube. Condillac was of the opinion that it was awkward to find a convincing
proof of this; only experience would provide a solution. 4
Condillac admitted that Cheselden's report seemed to create difficulties
for him: "c'est une experience qui paro~t, en tous points, contraire au senti-
ment que je viens d'Stablir. ''5 He explained the apparent contradictions, as
La Mettrie had done, by pointing out that the young man's eyes did not func-
tion well immediately after the operation because they had not been used for
years. He would require many days of exercise before being able to persuade
the different parts of the eye to work together in a coordinated fashion after
having become stiffened in the course of time. And, said Condillac, that was
the reason why Cheselden's patient had subsequently gone round feeling his
way in the dark for another two months. In contrast to Berkeley, Condillac
believed that if the young man had not used his hands he would have obtained
by the power of sight the same ideas as those which he had earlier obtained
through touch. The only difference would be that it would have taken longer.
Condillac accused of bias those who could think of no other explanation
for the young man's weak powers of sight than those advanced by Locke and
Berkeley. And, he added, they were the wrong reasons since they were not
in agreement with the principle that only that may be proposed which is
indisputable and which everyone with the least powers of reflection can note
in themselves.
Where Condillac defended in his Essai the thesis that from birth we can
perceive size, shape, distance and position immediately outside ourselves, M lie
Elisabeth Ferrand (17oo-1752), "the Egeria of the Enlightenment," was able
to convince Condillac of the incorrectness of his thesis. 1 This caused him
to change his view radically: in his later work, the Traitd des sensations
(1754) , he praised Berkeley's insights and qualified his own earlier opinions
as prejudice.
The main cause of the widespread belief in this prejudice was, believed
Condillac, that we have formed such a deeply rooted habit of judging from
sight the things with which we are surrounded that we can no longer remem-
ber what we saw when we first opened our eyes. Molyneux had proposed his
problem of the man born blind for various reasons, including a desire to inves-
tigate what we see by nature, without being prejudiced by habit. Condillac
wanted to do something similar, but for all the senses. He wanted a tool with
which we could more easily imagine what we owe to each sense. The tool was
handed to him by M ne Ferrand. She suggested that Condillac should imagine
a statue whose various senses should be opened up. In fact it was more a
question of a series of statues: a statue that was open exclusively to the sense
of smell (or taste or sight, etc.); a statue that disposed of the sense of smell
plus taste (or smell plus sight, etc.), etc.
In fact Condillac was not the only one to set up a thought experiment of
this type. Denis Diderot had already suggested, in his Lettre sur les aveu-
gles (1749), that it should be possible to imagine a block of marble able to
think and feel. 1 In his Lettre sur les sourds et muets (1751) he had written
that he wanted to conduct a sort of metaphysical anatomy by dividing up
an individual, as it were, into five persons, each of which would have only
one sense2 And Buffon had wondered what the perceptions and judgments
would be of the first man at the instant of creation. 3 On these grounds
Condillac was accused of plagiarism. 4 The force of his thought experiment
was also the subject of discussion. Grimm, for instance, was of the opinion
that Condillac's assumptions were arbitrary and impossible and that it would
be better to "faire la vdritable histoire m~taphysique de l'homme."5
Condillac believed that a statue that was endowed exclusively with the
sense of sight would only have sensations of light and colour and would not
realise that such sensations were in fact caused by external objects. If the
statue were given the additional sense of touch, it would also be able to
perceive size, shape, distance and position. If it were to see only those objects
which it touched and touch only those objects which it saw, it would be unable
to distinguish the sensations of sight from those of touch. Since our power
of sight always works jointly with the sense of touch, the sensations of sight
would mingle with those of touch. 6
Condillac emphasised that there is a difference between seeing (volt) and
looking (regarder); certainly the statue would see immediately, but it would
have to learn to look and to know what it saw. In contrast to Locke, Condillac
denied the existence of unconscious judgments. We do not see objects first
as flat bodies and then as solid, stated Condillac, but it is more a case of
the experience of touch being necessary for us to realise that we are seeing
objects.
According to Condillac, Berkeley was the first to note that the eye cannot
of itself judge distance, position, shape and size. The man born blind in Moly-
1Diderot [1749] 1961 , p. 144: "Madame, combien nos sens nous sugg~rent de choses; et
que nous aurions de peine, sans nos yeux, k supposer q u ' u n bloc de m a r b r e ne pense n i n e
sent!"
2Diderot believed that these five persons would be able to communicate with one another
using geometry: "par la facult~ qu'elles auroient d'abstraire, elles pourroient toutes 8tre
g~om~tres, s ' e n t e n d r e / ~ merveille, & ne s ' e n t e n d r e qu'en g~om~trie." Diderot [1751 ] 1965,
P. 45.
3Buffon 1749 1789, vol. 3 (1749), Histoire naturelle de l'homme, chapter "Des sens en
g~n~ral."
4See, for instance, F. M. G r i m m , "Lettre i er novembre 1755," in G r i m m & Diderot
1813, vol. 1, p. 445: "M. l'abb~ Condillac avoit noy~ la statue de M. de Buffon dans un
t o n n e a u d'eau froide." Condillac defended himself against the accusations in his "R~ponse
un reproche," which was a p p e n d e d to his Traitd des sensations.
5 G r i m m , "Lettre 1er d~cembre 1754," in G r i m m & Diderot 1813, vol. 1, p. 263.
6Condillac [1754] 1947, part III, ch. iv, §2: "ses sensations se mSlent avec les idles qu'elle
lui doit."
72 Chapter Four
1Condillac [1754] 1947, part HI, ch. iv, §3. Bonnet 176o also uses the notion of a statue.
Bonnet was of the opinion that a blind person who had been operated on would not be
able to recognise a round object by sight since there would be absolutely no link between
tactile and visual ideas.
2Condillac [1754] 1947, part III, ch. iv, §3.
3Condillac [1754] 1947, part III, ch. v. In 1754 Condillac discussed Cheselden's report
in far greater detail than he had done in 1746. It is likely that he was taking his data no
longer exclusively from Voltaire's Elemens (1738) but also from Buffon 1749-1789, vol. 3
(1749), Histoire naturelle de l'homme, chapter "Du sens de la vue." See Pastore 1973.
4Condillac [1754] 1947, part III, ch. vi.
The First Experimental Data 73
je n'ai jamais dout~ que l'Stat de nos organes et de nos sens n'ait pas
beaucoup d'influence sur notre m6taphysique et sur notre morale, et
que nos idSes les plus purement intellectuelles, si je puis parler ainsi,
ne tiennent de fort pros ~ la conformation de notre corps. 3
One could also state that the religious opinions and attitudes of blind people
are vastly different from those entertained by the sighted. After all, the blind
are not capable of witnessing the wonders of nature with their own eyes; and
ce beau spectacle qui n ' a jamais ~t~ fait pour moi! J'ai ~t~ c o n d a m n ~
/~ passer m a vie dans les t~n~bres; et vous me citez des prodiges que
je n'entends point, et qui ne prouvent que pour vous et pour ceux qui
voient c o m m e vous. Si vous voulez que je croie en Dieu, il faut que
vous me le fassiez toucher. ~
Diderot then allowed Saunderson to speculate on the origin of time and ob-
jects. Originally there would have been overall chaos, but this would have
slowly resolved itself and a large n u m b e r of misformed and a few well-formed
beings would have come into existence. By natural selection the monsters
would be destroyed in the course of time, thus producing the wondrous order
so highly appreciated by Newton, Leibniz and Clarke. But the order in the
world is not perfect, remarked Saunderson, pointing to himself: ' T o r d r e n'est
pas si parfait [...] qu'il ne paraisse encore de temps en temps des productions
monstrueuses." 3
T h e discussion with the Reverend Holmes made such a deep impression on
Saunderson t h a t he fell into a delirium, uttered the i m m o r t a l line " 0 Dieu
de Clarke et de Newton, prends pitid de moi/" and gave up the spirit. 4 T h e
atheist a t t i t u d e expressed by Diderot in the Lettre sur les aveugles was not
appreciated: the French government locked him up in the prison of Vincennes.
A large part of the Lettre sur les aveugles deals with Molyneux's problem.
Locke, Berkeley and m a n y others had used Molyneux's t h o u g h t experiment as
a means of better reflecting on our original perceptions. By p u t t i n g ourselves
in the shoes of someone born blind it should be easier for us to imagine what
we saw before we had formed j u d g m e n t s and habits. Diderot, however, did
not see the sense in such an enterprise:
1Holmes does indeed appear to have been a witness of Saunderson's death: "The rev-
erend Gervas Holmes informed him [i.e., Saunderson] that the mortification gained so much
ground that his best friends could entertain no hope of his recovery. He received this notice
of his approaching death with great calmness and serenity and after a short silence, resumed
life and spirits." Quoted by Verni~re in Diderot [1749] 1961, p. 118, note 2. What Diderot
wrote was, of course, apocryphal.
~Diderot [1749] 1961, pp. 118-119.
3Diderot [1749] 1961' p. 122.
4Diderot [1749] 1961, p. 124.
The First Experimental Data 75
If, despite these difficulties, the decision is taken to operate on one born
blind, said Diderot, a n u m b e r of conditions need to be fulfilled in order to
obtain reliable information. ~ First of all a blind person with a g o o d dose of
c o m m o n sense is required, preferably a philosopher since such a person can
think clearly. He would need to be t h o r o u g h l y prepared and the observations
should only begin some considerable time after the operation has been per-
formed, when the eyes are completely healed. Meanwhile the patient should
be kept in darkness, where he should be given the o p p o r t u n i t y to exercise
his eyes. M o r e o v e r - - a n d this was a s o m e w h a t sticky p r o b l e m - - h e should be
questioned in a skilful m a n n e r so t h a t he tells no more t h a n t h a t which is hap-
pening within him. Finally the questioning should take place before a forum
of learned men. 3 In brief, "Preparer et interroger un aveugle-n5 n'efit point
St@ une occupation indigne des talents r~unis de Newton, Descartes, Locke et
Leibniz." 4
Like Boullier, Diderot replaced the sphere and the cube in M o l y n e u x ' s
problem with a circle and a square, since he believed t h a t we can only judge
distance from experience and t h a t someone opening his eyes for the first time
sees only (flat) surfaces and does not know t h a t objects project forwards. A n d
even if a person born blind perceived projections and solidity from the first
instant of restored sight, and even if he could distinguish not only a circle
from a square but also a sphere from a cube, he would not, asserted Diderot,
be able to do this with more complex objects (such as a glove, a housecoat or
a d o c t o r ' s headgear). 5
Diderot was of the opinion that Molyneux's question, when seen in a some-
what more general sense than Molyneux had done, actually contained two
questions: (1) will the blind person be able to see immediately after the
cataract operation? and (2) if so, will he see sufficiently well to be able to
distinguish shapes; will he be capable, without hesitation, of giving the same
names to objects by sight as he did by those of touch; and will he have a proof
of the fact that he is using the correct names?
With regard to the first question, Diderot had no hesitation in saying that
a blind person cured of cataract would, like a baby when it first opens its eyes,
be incapable of seeing anything: "on n'est affectS, dans les premiers instants
de la vision, que d'une multitude de sensations confuses. ''1 Diderot believed
that touch could help the eye to distinguish shapes one from the other. But
he was also convinced that the eye would be capable of doing this without
the aid of touch: "je pense nullement que l'ceil ne puisse s'instruire, ou, s'il
est permis de parler ainsi, s'exp@rimenter de lui-mSme. ''2 A living eye (un
oeil vivant et animd) would, said Diderot, be able to distinguish the size and
s h a p e - - o r at least the rough outlines--of objects.
It in no way surprised Diderot that Cheselden's famous discoveries had
concluded that his patient could distinguish nothing in the beginning. He
concluded that the eye needed time to exercise and gain experience, and not
that touch would be required to distinguish shapes. Moreover, added Diderot,
what can we really expect of someone who was unaccustomed to reflect on
himself and who was unaware of the advantages of sight, who was insensitive
to his own unhappiness and was totally incapable of imagining the extent of
the damage done to his own satisfaction by the loss of this sense? Saunderson
would certainly not have been as indifferent as Cheselden's patient and he
would most certainly have reacted differently.
If the person born blind is given the time, said Diderot, at some point he
will succeed not only in distinguishing colours but also the overall outline of
an object. Suppose that he masters this skill in a short time or that he should
obtain it by moving his eyes in the dark: would he then be able to recognise
and name objects by sight that he had previously touched? Diderot gave
various answers to this question, depending on the intelligence of the blind
person. 3
blind should receive his sight and a black cube and a red sphere be placed against a white
background, he would immediately distinguish the limits of these shapes. Diderot [1749]
1961, p. 137.
1Diderot [1749] 1961, p. 135.
2Diderot [1749] 1961, pp. 135-136.
3Diderot [1749] 1961, pp. 141-143.
The First Experimental Data 77
1In order to gain an impression of how Saunderson worked with his computing board,
see Saunderson 174o or Diderot [1749] 1961.
78 Chapter Four
able to see and what he would see with the aid of visual experience (though
not aided by touch). Then he laid down, stage by stage, how a patient should
be prepared for a cataract operation and what kind of observations should be
carried out if the experiment was to have any explanatory force. What, in
fact, Diderot did was to formulate a number of methodological criteria which
a psychological experiment had to meet. Finally he pointed out that patients
from different backgrounds would not all react in the same manner and that
perception was perhaps not as universal as Berkeley had suggested.
Like his French colleagues La Mettrie, Condillac and Diderot, the Swiss
philosopher Jean-Bernard M@rian (1723-18o7) wrote about Molyneux's prob-
lem, criticised Cheselden's report and suggested alternatives. All of this was
contained in a series of eight Mdmoires published between 1772 and 1782 in
the Nouveaux mdmoires de l'Acaddmie Royale des Sciences et Belles-Lettres
of Berlin. 1 In his first Mdmoire MSrian underlined the importance of Moly-
neux's problem:
1In x748 M@rian went to Berlin at Maupertuis's invitation to take a seat in the Acaddmie
de Berlin. In 1797 he succeeded Formey as secrdtaire perpdtuel of the Aeaddmie.
2Merian [1772] 1984, P. 5.
3M~rian [1772] 1984, §2, pp. 5-8.
The First Experimental Data 79
answer. Or perhaps they will take no sides if neither the pros nor cons seem
to be decisive. 1
We will not go into M~rian's historical review here but simply record his
preference for Berkeley's solution. M~rian defended Berkeley's position that
the objects of sight and those of touch are different and can only be related by
experience. The fact that the words "extension" and "shape" can be applied
to both visual and tactile qualities says nothing about their real identity:
"nous concevrons que leur identit~ nominale ne prouve point leur identit~
r~elle. ''2 Like Berkeley, M~rian illustrated the nature of the link between
visual and tactile objects using a language metaphor:
M~rian was of the opinion that the objects of sight and those of touch could
fulfil the function both of sign and of the thing referred to: "De sorte que de
leur nature, ils sont ~galement propres £ ~tre, les uns £ l'~gard des autres, ou
le signe, ou la chose signifi~e. ''4 This relationship is therefore mutual, said
M~rian, and what first touches us always seems to summon up the idea of
the other. And yet the visual object is usually given the function of sign, in
view of the fact that our sense of touch is more important for our survival:
"I1 nous importe donc bien davantage d'etre avertis par la Vue de l'effet que
feront sur nous les objets tangibles, que de l'Stre par le Tact de l'effet que
feront sur nous les objets visibles. ''5 Like Locke and Berkeley, M~rian thus
made the objects of sight subordinate to the objects of touch.
In order to clarify Molyneux's problem M~rian invented a new thought
experiment with some resemblance to that proposed by Hutcheson. Imagine
a world, said M~rian, inhabited exclusively by people born blind and in which
objects give off odours more or less complex according to the complexity of
their form. Would someone born without the sense of smell who suddenly has
this sense restored then be able to distinguish a sphere from a cube without
touching the objects? M~rian believed n o t ?
According to M~rian, Berkeley's theory had benefitted from a rare ad-
vantage that few philosophical writings can boast of, namely that of being
confirmed by experience, that is by the observations of Cheselden's patient?
Although the young man appeared to find no similarity between visual and
tactile extension and shape, M~rian wanted to cover himself against hasty
conclusions: "je me garderai bien de prononcer p~remptoirement d'apr~s une
experience aussi d~licate, et dont nous ne connaissons pas m~me les d~tails
autant qu'il serait £ souhaiter.'3
It would be desirable, stated M6rian, if philosophers were able to perform
many more authentic observations on people born blind after being operated
upon, using measures laid down prior to the observations. This would enable
them to compare experiences and find out from the one what the other had
missed. The problem was, however, according to M~rian, that such opportu-
nities are rare; you have to wait for a stroke of luck to come along. And not
all patients are equMly suitable; there is often a lack of time to prepare them
and circumstances sometimes prove adverse. In addition, true researchers are
no less unusual: "Les philosophes sont trop indolents, trop peu curieux pour
rechercher les moyens de s'instruire; ils aiment mieux argumenter que voir.
Pour le grand nombre la philosophie est un m~tier plut6t qu'une science. "4 In
view of this state of affairs it is thus no wonder, proposed M6rian, that since
Cheselden's time--forty years previous--there had been no new experiences
of such an important matter.
M~rian believed that there was one major objection in the case of Ches-
elden's patient, as there is in that of all those born blind who undergo a
cataract operation: cataract does not cause general blindness. And in this he
was right, for even those with a mature cataract have their projection of light
intact. Those blinded by cataract combine the weak light that they perceive
with tactile extension, said M6rian, and thus they can have no purely visual
perceptions once they have undergone the operation. 5
M~rian suggested a bizarre plan to counteract these objections. Instead
of waiting until there was a suitable case of cataract, he suggested that a
1Merian [1777] 1984, §5, PP. 119-121, and M~rian [1779] 1984, §2, p. 131.
2M~rian [1774] 1984, §1, p. 6o, and M~rian [1776] 1984, §4, P. 89. M~rian referred to
Condillac's versions of Cheselden's report; he also mentioned The Tatler ([Steele] [17o9]
1898), and contradictory observations of a person born blind operated on by Marchan. See
M~rian [1782] 1984, pp. 175-177. I have only been able to check on Marchan 1768, but he
says nothing about an experiment with a sphere and a cube, as stated by M~rian.
3M6rian [1773] 1984, part II, §7, P. 54.
4M~rian [1782] 1984, p. 178.
5M~rian [1782] 1984, p. 179.
The First Experimental Data 81
En un mot, comme leur esprit serait, pour ainsi dire, entre nos mains,
que nous pourrions le p6trir comme une cire molle, et y d~velopper
les connaissances dans telle succession qu'il nous plairait, on serait 5~
port6e de prendre toutes les Pr@cautions , et de varier les experiences
de toutes les fa§ons imaginables. 3
Once they have obtained various ideas in this manner it will be easier to
interrogate them one by one once the veil is lifted from their eyes, wrote
M6rian.
M@rian foresaw two kinds of problem, the one physical and the other moral.
In the first place one could fear that these children could lose their powers
of sight completely and would really become blind. If this should turn out
to be the case, the whole enterprise would, stated M@rian, be useless and
would even be improper. But he could think of no fact that would confirm
this possibility and he left it up to those whose task it is to study the human
body. 4 Another objection could be that light is present everywhere and that
no darkness is so intense that it cannot illuminate the eye when the eye has
grown accustomed. M~rian brushed this problem aside by pointing out that
experts would doubtless be able to invent a suitable blindfold.
The gravest objection would be that nobody wishes to sacrifice their chil-
dren for metaphysical experiments, that it is unjust to require this of anyone
and that it witnesses to cruelty towards those children. M~rian replied: "Je
r@ponds que mon projet s'adresse aux philosophes embras~s de l'amour de la
1One could state with some measure of irony that in this M~rian was anticipating the
Institution Nationale des Jeunes Aveugles established in 1784 by Valentin Haiiy.
2M~rian [a782] 1984, p. 18o.
aM@rian [1782] 1984, pp. 18o-181.
4At present we know that visual stimulation is of essential importance in the first months
following birth. Neonates brought up in darkness show serious visual defects.
82 Chapter Four
Science, qui savent qu'on ne va au grand qu'en foulant aux pieds les pr6jug6s
populaires." 1
Moreover the implementation of his plan would not be M~rian's own affair
nor that of any private individual, but that of a sovereign or of a magistrate
endowed with public authority. Without even speaking of the source offered
by orphanages for subjects, we should allow our gaze to wander through the
streets of a large town, said M~rian. Observe all those objects of our disgust
and pity, these half naked children, scarcely clothed in miserable rags, the prey
of vermin, brought up in laziness and debauchery, these accursed children,
crippled, often even made incurably blind by monsters with pretensions to
being their parents. Where is the evil in tearing these tender victims from
their persecutors so that they may serve in our experiments and may be turned
into useful or even famous citizens one day?
M6rian assumed that if our senses could have been developed one by one we
would have derived a great deal more benefit from them. They damage each
other by their simultaneous activity, since the one perfects itself at the expense
of the other. M6rian would like to have control over the first impressions, since
these are the most important for the general development of the individual:
In addition to all of this, science too would gain. W h a t new discoveries could
be made when children started to use their eyes, what discoveries through
the association with the other senses and especially that of touch! W h a t
progress could be made in geometry, optics, natural history and philosophy!
It would become possible to have them clarify the most complex questions
and unravel the most aggravating problems. They would make discoveries
for us by discovering themselves and it would be seen that in these places of
darkness an excellent philosophical academy had been createdP
Would they blame you for having deprived them of their sight, M@rian
asked rhetorically. Of course not: "ils vous en remercieront avec des larmes
de joie, [...] ils se f@liciteront, toute leur vie, de l'@ducation que vous leur avez
donn@e."3 And that was precisely the reaction shown by the young man who
was restored to sight by Cheselden: he too greeted his benefactor with tears
of joy.
MSrian's enlightened notions of the possibility of creating good, educated
people seem not to have found much echo, no matter how interesting they
may have been from a variety of angles. 4
6 CONCLUSIONS
Anyone who studied the problem proposed by Molyneux was, of course, cu-
rious to know what a person born blind really would see when restored to
sight. It is no surprise, therefore, that many threw themselves into discus-
sion of Cheselden's report with great enthusiasm. Some philosophers judged
that the report left nothing to be desired as far as clarity was concerned. It
confirmed their suspicions that someone cured of congenital blindness would
at first be unable to distinguish objects one from the other, would be unable
to determine shape, size or distance, and would have to learn to see. The
report proved, they believed, without a shadow of doubt that the man born
1In all congenital cataract patients (whether operated on one eye or both) there is a lack
of stereoscopic vision.
The First Experimental Data 85
that these would provide us with insight into the working of our senses. They
expected that we would be able to shrug off our prejudices and habits if we
could place ourselves in the shoes of a person born blind (or of a living eye, of
a statue or some such). We would then be more easily able to imagine what
we would perceive before having formed our prejudices and habits. Diderot
believed, however, that this was an illusory quest. He had no confidence in
the reactions of someone who opened his eyes for the first time. He would
have preferred to have the problems facing the theory of vision solved by a
philosopher endowed with common sense.
M~rian too doubted whether cataract patients could be useful in the search
for a description of pure visual perceptions. Cataract patients are, after all,
not completely blind; they always retain some projection of light. However,
this was not necessarily a problem within the context of Molyneux's question
since this concerned only perception of shapes. Since cataract patients are
not capable of perceiving shapes, they would in principle be of use in finding
out whether, immediately following the operation to remove the cataracts,
they could distinguish different shapes.
M~rian developed an interesting plan which would enable the (visual) de-
velopment of people to be guided along pre-determined lines. He suggested
having newly-born children grow up under a variety of conditions in total
darkness. Once they had reached the age of reason they would be exposed
to various series of visual impressions. They would then be able to provide
an answer to the urgent questions regarding our powers of sight. It would,
moreover, be possible to provide them with that visual information most ap-
propriate to the end to which they were being educated. M~rian's plan for a
Sdminaire des Aveugles Artificiels was, in fact, a precursor of the deprivation
experiments performed on chimpanzees after the Second World War. As will
be shown in the sixth chapter, the results of the experiments were less rosy
than M~rian had prophesied.
Although Cheselden's report was often referred to again in the nineteenth-
century discussions of Molyneux's problem, its influence had been on the wane
since the end of the eighteenth century. Admirers of the report had meanwhile
been able to single out the remarkable results, while its critics had indicated
the weak points.
Without there really being any question of a cmsura, around 18oo a number
of developments took place which justify the suggestion that a new period
was dawning in the history of Molyneux's problem. First of all there were
new reports of cataract operations which were associated with the problem.
Some of these provided results that agreed with Cheselden's observations while
others appeared to be in conflict with them. In addition data on the visual
powers of newly-born animals and babies began to be applied in discussions on
Molyneux's question. Furthermore Wheatstone's clarification of stereoscopic
86 ChapterFour
vision came to play its part in the matter. As will be shown in the next
chapter, the data mentioned above acted as arguments in the nineteenth-
century empiricism-nativism debate in which Molyneux's problem frequently
figured.
CHAPTER FIVE
E M P I R I C A L A P P R O A C H E S IN
THE NINETEENTH CENTURY
1See Bourdon 19o2 , pp. 362-391 , and Von Senden [1932 ] 196o.
~Hamilton in Reid [1837] 1863, vol. 1, p. 136 , note.
3Bailey a842, pp. 169-17o.
4Bailey 1842, pp. 179-18o.
5Cheselden 1728, p. 448.
87
88 Chapter Five
From the numerous reports that have come down to us I will select a few
points which can be regarded as important in solving Molynenx's problem. I
will deal with only one case extensively, that of the Leipzig doctor J. C. Au-
gust Franz, dated 1841. This is the most interesting and most accurately
documented and, moreover, involved the first experiment carried out with a
sphere and cube.
When we examine the various cases we note that they differ in a number of
ways. First of all, the patients were not all equally blind before the operation.
Some could merely distinguish between light and dark, a number were also
capable of distinguishing between various colours and one or two could also
perceive size, distance and motion. In a few cases there was some doubt as
to whether the patient really had been born blind, or had perhaps lost the
power of sight after a year or two. And some doctors even failed to report on
the pre-operative state of their patients.
There was also wide divergence in the patients' age and intelligence and
their emotional response varied greatly. A twenty-two-year-old female patient
treated by the French doctor Jean Janin (1731-1799) , for instance, gazed
around her with an expression of surprise and satisfaction while saying re-
peatedly: "Ha, mon Dieu, que cela est beau! ''1 The forty-six-year-old female
patient of the London eye doctor James Wardrop (1782-1869) was in stark
contrast, appearing "bewildered from not being able to combine the knowl-
edge acquired by the senses of touch and sight, and felt disappointed in not
having the power of distinguishing at once by her eye, objects which she could
so readily distinguish from one another by feeling them. ''2
Another difference was that the various doctors failed to perform their
experiments at the same time subsequent to the operation and that the ex-
periments were of different types. Jacques David, whom we have already
encountered as the inventor of cataract extraction, was one of the first doc-
tors to perform experiments with his cataract patients. None of them turned
out to be able to distinguish by sight the round and triangular objects which
D a v i d showed them. 3 Nor was Janin's patient able to distinguish objects
shown to her one from the other, which Janin took to be a proof of the hy-
pothesis advanced by Molyneux, Locke and Berkeley. 4
Some remarkable results were obtained in tests performed by the surgeon
Everard Home (1756 1832), which he described in "An Account of two Chil-
dren born with Cataracts in their Eyes" (1807). Ten minutes after Home had
removed the cataract from the left eye of his seven-year-old patient he showed
him a number of cards an inch in diameter and having various shapes and
colours. The boy was able to name the colours correctly but he described as
round not only the round cards but also the square and triangular ones. He
gave a negative answer to the question of whether the cards were touching
his eye but he was unable to say how far away they were. Two hours after
the operation he was again shown a square and was asked if he could find
corners. He had some trouble discovering a corner and then he counted the
four corners of the square. In the same way he counted the triangle's corners:
"in doing so his eye went along the edge from corner to corner, naming them
as he went along. ''1 A fortnight later the boy was still unable to distinguish
shape without counting the corners one by one, "running his eye quickly along
the outline, so that it was evident he was still learning, just as a child learns
to read.": A week later the boy was able to determine the shape of the cards
almost as quickly as their colours.
The experiences of Home's patient were generally regarded as a proof of
intuitive seeing of distance and angles and thus as unfavourable to Berkeley's
theory of vision. Bailey was of the opinion that Home's experiment had finally
solved Molyneux's problem:
By far the most interesting case is that of Franz. This doctor was acquainted
with Molyneux's problem and he was also familiar with a number of earlier
reports of cataract operations. He was the first (no less than a century and
a half after Molyneux had laid his problem before Locke!) actually to carry
out experiments with a sphere and a cube. Franz described the results of
his experiments in his "Memoir of the Case of a Gentleman Born Blind, and
Successfully Operated Upon in the 18th Year of his Age, with Physiological
Observations and Experiments" (1841).
Franz's patient was born squinting and with double cataracts. At the
end of his second year his right eye was operated on, leaving him with an
atrophied eyeball. In subsequent years his left eye was operated on twice,
both times without success. At the age of seventeen, when he met Franz, he
was unable to perceive any light with his right eye. He was able to see light
and colours with his left eye but not objects. The boy himself thought that
he could partially see brightly lit objects but Franz was convinced that this
was completely imaginary. He believed that the young m a n ' s behaviour was
in complete accord with that of other educated blind people not completely
amaurotic: they try to convince others that they see more than they really
can in order to cover up their handicap and to avoid being treated with pity.
Franz removed the cataract from the left eye. Following the operation
it became apparent that light caused too much pain for experiments to be
performed and therefore the eye was bandaged. The bandages were taken
off for the first time three days after the operation. In answer to Franz's
question as to what he could see the boy said he saw "an extensive field of
light, in which everything appeared dull, confused and in motion. ''1 He could
not distinguish objects. The pain caused by the light obliged the young man
to close his eye again. When he opened it again two days later he described
what he saw as % number of opake watery spheres, which moved with the
movements of the eye, but, when the eye was at rest, remained stationary, and
then partially covered each other. ''2 Again after an interval of two days the
same phenomena were perceived, but now the spheres were less transparent
and the movements steadier. The boy stated that he was able for the first
time "to look through the spheres, and to perceive a difference, but merely a
difference, in the surrounding objects." 3
As soon as the young man could stand the light, Franz conducted a number
of experiments. In the first series he tested whether the young man could
recognise coloured ribands fixed to a black background. This proved to be
the case. In the second series Franz showed the boy a piece of paper on which
two strong black lines had been drawn, the one horizontal and the other
vertical. After looking closely the young man was able to name the lines
correctly. When he was asked to point with his finger to the horizontal line
"he moved his hand slowly, as if feeling, and pointed to the vertical, but after
a short time, observing his error, he corrected himself. ''4 The contours of a
square, in which a circle containing a triangle was drawn, was also recognised
and accurately described by the boy. However, he had no notion at all of
wavy or zig-zag lines.
This was exactly what Franz had noted in his patient. He underlined the
importance of his study: "This is the only case on record within my knowledge
wherein, with a person born blind and afterwards successfully operated upon
at a period of life as far advanced as in this instance, such experiments have
ever been made." ~
Most of the reactions to Franz's report were simply congratulatory. A. W.
Volkmann, for instance, wrote: "Den interessantesten Fall der Art hat Dr.
Franz beschrieben [...] Diese Thatsachen sind ~ufierst wichtig und diirften
manche Streitfragen entscheiden, fiber welche sich die Physiologen bis auf die
letzten Zeiten nicht vereinigen konnten, i'3 Abbott too praised Franz's re-
search: "It is remarkable as the case in which the previous blindness was the
most perfect, the patient the best instructed, and the observations the most
accurate. ''4 He added sarcastically: "yet as far as British metaphysicians are
concerned it might as well have been buried in the pages of the Illuminated
Doctor. It is ignored by one and all of them, and is only noticed (and that very
imperfectly) by German philosophers; while Cheselden's inconclusive case has
been sedulously copied by one fi'om the other for more than a hundred years." 5
But Abbott voiced criticism too. He was of the opinion that the fact that the
patient could not perceive a sphere and a cube as such was the fault of the
experimental set-up: "Even if the young man's eye had been perfect, then, the
bodies were too small and too distant for a fair experiment on the perception
of solidity." 1 Other criticisms related to his use of language. W. H. S. Monck
blamed Franz for not having tried to investigate what his patient had meant
by extraordinary expressions such as "watery spheres": "Dr. Franz's obser-
vations, though usually regarded as among the best which we possess on the
subject, present features which are to me utterly inexplicable. "~
After Franz's experiments, other doctors in their turn performed tests with
a sphere and a cube. In his book entitled On the Organs of Vision (1858) the
London eye doctor Thomas Nunneley (18o9-187o) described the reaction of
a nine-year-old patient. The boy was able to distinguish a difference in shape
immediately, but he could in no way say which was which:
it was only after several days that he could or would tell by the eyes
alone, which was the sphere and which the cube; when asked, he
always, before answering, wished to take both into his hands; even
when this was allowed, when immediately afterwards the objects were
placed before the eyes, he was not certain of the figure. 3
The fact that Franz's patient had been able to name the perspective projec-
tions of the sphere and cube and Nunneley's patient had not was, according
to some, because Nunneley's patient was less developed than Franz's. 4
In 1875 the eye surgeon Arthur von Hippel (1841 1916) published an article
in which he described how his patient, a four-year-old girl, reacted to a sphere
and a cube:
Von Hippel stated that this confirmed the correctness of the hypothesis ad-
vanced by Molyneux and Locke. 6
Finally we should mention R a m s a y ' s "Case of a Man Blind from Congenital
Cataract who Acquired Sight after an Operation when he was 3o Years of Age"
which appeared in The Lancet in 19o 3 . On the second day after the operation
R a m s a y showed his patient a ball and a toy brick. He told him that he was
showing him these objects and asked him whether he could distinguish them
one from the other:
When asked how he had been able to distinguish the ball from the block the
patient answered that "he was so much in the habit of handling objects that
he had come to have a 'notion in his mind' regarding the form of things. ''2
Although R a m s a y did not exclude the possibility of the man having learnt on
the first day after his operation what an angle was as a result of having seen
a table or a chair, he suspected that the man had given the correct answer
because he was capable of comparing that which he saw to that which he had
felt.
Abbott regarded R a m s a y ' s case as "the first instance in which Molyneux's
question was put exactly as he suggested. ''3 Indeed, Franz had not told his
patient that he was showing him a sphere and a cube, whereas R a m s a y did.
And that (at least for Abbott) closed the case.
When we compare the various cases we see that we can find the entire range
of possible solutions to Molyneux's problem. In a number of cases the cataract
patients operated upon were incapable of seeing even the slightest difference
between a sphere and a cube (or between two other objects). However, fol-
lowing the operation most of the people born blind were able to distinguish
the objects from each other though they did not recognise them nor could
they name them. One patient took the sphere for a circle and the cube for a
square. Another was able to distinguish the objects one from the other and
could name them once the doctor had expressly told him what he was being
shown. Finally, a couple of patients were able to identify the objects correctly
without further help.
It is no surprise that the reactions shown by the various cataract patients
should show such a variety. The cases were, after all, very different in nature.
Those wishing to make use of the experiences of the patients in order to
solve Molyneux's problem therefore had at their disposal a number of cases
which were contradictory and difficult to compare. The cases they used often
depended on the point of view they were defending. Information agreeing
with the theoretical standpoint was preferred to d a t a that failed to fit the
bill. And whenever the language used by doctor or patient was ambiguous
the option was usually taken for the interpretation that fitted the point of
view being defended.
for perception which an eye with its lens just extirpated affords. ''1 He drew
the same conclusion as Bailey and Abbott: "Obviously, positive cases are of
more importance than negative. ''=
Another possibility which had to be taken into account in cases of persons
born blind being operated on was pointed out in the Essays on Philosophi-
cal Subjects (1795) by the philosopher and political economist Adam Smith
(1723-1790), published after his death. Smith supported Berkeley's theory
of vision and thus started from the assumption that there is no agreement
between visual and tactile objects. However, he did believe that visual ob-
jects show in some way a certain affinity with tactile objects, an affinity that
we notice naturally. In this context Smith spoke of "instinctive perception."
Animals, said Smith, possess a similar instinctive perception and possibly
children too. But blind people operated upon would have lost this faculty:
Around the year 18oo information regarding the powers of sight of newborn
animals and babies was introduced into the discussion of Molyneux's problem.
This information took its place next to the wide variety of data concerning
the visual perception of persons born blind whose sight had been restored
by surgical operation. The importance attached to the visual behaviour of
the three groups differed from philosopher to philosopher. For instance Ab-
bott regarded the case histories of people undergoing a cataract operation
as unsatisfactory and ascribed more value to the powers of sight of babies:
"[infants have] the advantage over the blind, since an instinct or faculty un-
employed may tend to decay, but in the infant all the natural powers are
fresh. ''1 John Stuart Mill (18o6-1873), on the contrary, characterised the in-
formation regarding children as "singularly inconclusive" and that on blind
people operated on for cataract as "the most valuable facts of all. ''2 Bailey,
finally, called blind people cured of cataract "perhaps the most interesting
source" and regarded certain forms of behaviour exhibited by young animals
as a decisive proof against Berkeley's doctrine of sight and thus as a denial of
his answer to Molyneux's question. 3
As will be seen, there was also a difference of opinion as to whether the
power of sight possessed by the cured blind, young animals and babies was
similar or not. Some believed that information relative to the one group could
be extrapolated to the other, while others pointed to fundamental differences
between the three groups.
Researchers generally agreed that certain animals can perceive objects at
various distances immediately after birth. Adam Smith illustrated this using
the behaviour of chickens, partridges, grouse and suchlike which, as soon as
they emerge from the egg, walk around the field calmly and pick up the seeds
indicated by their mothers: "they no sooner come into the light than they seem
to understand this language of Vision as well as they ever do afterwards. ''4
This also applied, said Smith, to animals which open their eyes only a few
days after birth and for certain beasts, such as calves and foals. Thomas
Brown held a similar opinion: "The calf, and the lamb, newly dropt into the
world, seem to measure forms and distances with their eyes, as distinctly, or
at least almost as distinctly, as the human reasoner measures them, after all
the acquisitions of his long and helpless infancy. ''5
According to the German physiologist and comparative anatomist Johan-
nes Miiller (18o1-1858), the fact that some newborn animals immediately see
their mother's nipples proves that the power of seeing simple shapes is not
acquired. And thus he failed to understand why Molyneux and Locke had
1 A b b o t t 1864, p. 163.
~Mill [1842 ] 1859 , p. lO6 a n d p. 11o, respectively.
3See Bailey 1842, p. 149 a n d p. 166.
4 S m i t h 1795, p. 319 •
5 B r o w n [182o] 186o, Lecture 28, p. 181.
Empirical Approaches in the Nineteenth Century 99
Bailey too was of the opinion that the proof obtained from animal behaviour
was "complete and conclusive.": Abbott was of a similar opinion.3
Despite all this criticism, one or two individuals took great pains to hold
up Berkeley's theory. John Stuart Mill, for example, agreed that it was true
that the data derived from young animals "have long been felt to be a real
stumbling-block in the way of the theory. ''4 But he regarded them as little
more than a difficulty rather than a complete denial of Berkeley's doctrine.5
Moreover Mill found fault with the conclusion based on some types of be-
haviour on the part of young animals that they can perceive distance imme-
diately after birth. Kittens and puppies, stated Mill, are born blind and yet
they find their mother's teats before their eyes open. 6
Though there may have been agreement regarding the nature of the faculty
of sight in newborn animals, researchers seemed to have problems agreeing
what newborn babies can see. It was not without reason that Abbott wrote
that "nothing [...] is more difficult than tracing the earliest development of
ideas in the mind of an infant. ''7 Experimental developmental psychology
had not yet got off the ground; there were scarcely any effective research
methods and too little had at the time been published on babies' powers of
sight. The few publications which did exist coupled with observations made
by the researchers themselves did persuade some to conclude that neonates
are not capable of seeing objects at various distances immediately after birth.
But others believed that, like newborn animals, they were capable of such
activity.
Thomas Brown (1778-182o) was one of those who assumed that man's
powers of sight were substantially different from those possessed by animals.
Brown believed that the fact that some animals can instinctively perceive
distance proves that there is no physical impossibility involved in supposing
that a similar "original suggestion" may take place in man. But he believed
that experience teaches us that a great deal of time is required before infants
are capable of distinguishing different objects by sight and to fix their gaze
on things. Hence his conclusion that "in man, there is not that necessity for
the instinct, which exists in the peculiar situation of the other animals; and
we find, accordingly, that there is no trace of the instinct in him. ''1 Brown
believed that the situation of babies could be compared to that of people born
blind whose sight is restored at a later age and cannot distinguish a sphere
from a cube: in both cases the actual size, shape and position of objects has to
be learnt in the manner of a new language. This showed, according to Brown,
"that we learn to see,--and that vision is truly, what Swift has paradoxically
defined it to be, the art o/ seeing things that are invisible.":
Other philosophers, however, believed that the human faculty of sight was
indeed similar to that of animals. Thus Adam Smith found it difficult to
imagine that man would be the only animal whose young would have no
instinctive perception. The young of humans are, however, dependent on
others for such a long period, they have to be carried in the arms of their
mothers or nurses so long, said Smith, that instinctive perception of this
kind would seem to be less necessary for them than for other species. Before
it came to have any useful purpose, observation and experience would have
sufficiently forged the connections between visual and tactile objects. But
because children appear to see the distance, shape and size of objects at a
very early stage, Smith tended to believe that even they enjoyed some kind
of instinctive perception, "though possibly in a much weaker degree than the
greater part of other animals."3 As already mentioned, Smith attributed to
decay of the powers of sight the failure of blind people operated on for cataract
to immediately see objects at a distance.
Bailey too believed that babies' powers of vision were similar to those
enjoyed by young animals. And while Bailey was convinced that babies did
not possess full perception of distance immediately after birth, he still thought
that this did not prove that of its nature the eye was unable to perceive
distance, as Berkeley had stated. Failure to perceive in a complete manner
would, he believed, be attributable to the immaturity of the organ. 4 And
even with regard to his other senses and limbs, thought Bailey, man was at
a disadvantage: it takes time for all human organs to mature. But as soon
as this is achieved, the organs can perform all the functions for which they
were created. Thus Bailey was quite sure that "the power of performing all
the functions of sight is in the eye as soon as it has come to maturity." •
Physiologists and mothers, stated Bailey, had noticed that babies open
their eyes immediately following birth and that they quickly start directing
their gaze towards sources of light, at first by turning their heads and later
also their eyes towards these sources. They had then noted that babies very
quickly demonstrate interest in faces and see relative sizes and distances. The
studies performed had also shown, said Bailey, that touch remains inert for a
long time and develops later than sight: babies do not start using their hands
until they are a few months old and it takes a long time for them to point in
the right direction or to estimate distance.:
When babies use their hands for the first time, said Bailey, they a t t e m p t
instinctively to touch what they see. In the beginning they fail, for they need
to learn how to adapt their muscle power to visual distances:
A person born blind and cured surgically is required to learn to connect his
new visual sensations and his old tactile sensations, while babies need to
do the reverse: to connect their new tactile sensations and their old visual
sensations. According to Bailey the a t t e m p t made to grasp an object implies
that the object is seen at a certain distance. On the basis of the above, Bailey
drew the following conclusion:
In the progress of the human infant, then, it is clear that the priority
of definite perceptions of extension is with the sight, and that in the
connection which is soon established between his visual and tactual
sensations, the process is so far the reverse of what Berkeley's theory
requires it to be. 4
The greater the resemblance between the organs of sight and the
general phenomena of the nervous system in men and beasts, the
greater this improbability. As every advance in physiology tends to
develop this resemblance and to strengthen the conception of the
unity of system in the animal kingdom, this argument has also become
strongerP
1Abbott 1864, p. 167. Cf. Hamilton [1858-186o ] 1861 1866, vol. 2, Lecture 28, pp. 181-
182.
2Abbott 1864, p. 168. Abbott left open the possibility that human beings have to learn
from experience what animals perceive directly, but he did not believe that anyone had
demonstrated that this was the case.
3/Abbott 1864, p. 166.
lo4 Chapter Five
In t h e a n c i e n t world t h e p e r c e p t i o n of d e p t h was r e g a r d e d as s e l f - e x p l a n a t o r y . :
A t t h e b e g i n n i n g of t h e s e v e n t e e n t h c e n t u r y a change o c c u r r e d when K e p l e r
d i s c o v e r e d t h a t t h e o u t s i d e world was p r o j e c t e d onto the r e t i n a in reverse a n d
fiat. F r o m t h a t t i m e t h e question b e g a n to be p o s e d as to how it was p o s s i b l e
to o b t a i n depth from a fiat r e t i n a l i m a g e ? M o r e t h a n two centuries l a t e r t h e
a l l - r o u n d i n v e n t o r a n d physicist Charles W h e a t s t o n e (18o2-1875) succeeded
in p r o v i d i n g an answer.
W h e a t s t o n e d e s c r i b e d his discoveries in an a r t i c l e in t h e Philosophical
Transactions which b e c a m e v e r y famous. 3 Here he showed with t h e aid of
t h e s t e r e o s c o p e , which he h a d himself invented, t h a t p e r c e p t i o n of d e p t h is
achieved by j o i n t a c t i o n of n o n - c o r r e s p o n d i n g r e t i n a l points. 4 To d e m o n s t r a t e
this, W h e a t s t o n e h a d m a d e two line d r a w i n g s of the s a m e object: one from
t h e angle of vision of t h e left eye a n d t h e o t h e r from t h e angle of vision of t h e
right eye. W h e n these two d r a w i n g s were looked at t h r o u g h a stereoscope,
t h e r e was an u n m i s t a k e a b l e i m p r e s s i o n of a solid t h r e e - d i m e n s i o n a l o b j e c t .
( W h e a t s t o n e r e m a r k e d t h a t different r e t i n a l i m a g e s can be c r e a t e d only when
t h e o b j e c t looked at is close to t h e eyes. W h e n an o b j e c t is looked a t from
s o m e c o n s i d e r a b l e d i s t a n c e t h e o p t i c a l axes of b o t h eyes are p a r a l l e l a n d t h e
p e r s p e c t i v e p r o j e c t i o n s a r e t h e s a m e on b o t h retinas. 5)
1Abbott 1864, p. 14o , for instance, spoke of "cases in which the phenomena of sight are
given most pure and independent--viz., those of infants, of persons born blind, who have
been enabled to see, and of the lower animals." Cf. Bailey 1842, p. 148.
2See Crone 1989.
3Wheatstone 1838.
4In order to explain why an object looked at with both eyes is seen as single, Christiaan
Huygens had defined the so-called corresponding points: "chaque point du fond de l'ceil a
son point correspondant dans le fond de l'autre en sorte que lors qu'un point de l'object est
peint dans quelques deux de ces points correspondants, alors il ne parait que simple comme
il est" (Huygens [1667] 1916). Wheatstone rejected the suggestion that seeing a single image
was possible only with corresponding points, since objects depicted on non-corresponding
points of the retina do not have to be seen as double. If they are seen as single, they create
a sensation of depth.
5Wheatstone stated that this explained why an artist can never make a true-to-life
image of a nearby object. In the case of a painting, two identical images are projected onto
Empirical Approaches in the Nineteenth Century lo5
the retina. Leonardo da Vinci had earlier discovered that a painter will never succeed in
perfectly reproducing the sensation of depth. In order to provide the best illusion of depth
he advised looking at a picture from some distance with one eye.
1Bailey 1842, pp. lOO-lOl.
~Bailey 1842, p. lol. This is a false assumption in view of the fact that binocular vision
suffers more greatly and in a more definitive fashion as a result of visual deprivation than
does monocular acuity.
3Mill [1843] 1859, p. 117: "Mr. Bailey, in his reply, insists very much on [...] the confir-
mation which he imagines his theory to derive from Mr. Wheatstone's discoveries respecting
binocular vision, exhibited in the phenomena of the stereoscope." Bailey's pamphlet was
published as Bailey 1843.
4Mill [1843] 1859, p. 118.
5Mill [1843] 1859, p. 116.
lo6 Chapter Five
1He quoted Cheselden's patient in a discussion of this point: "nun mut~ man, wie der
Blinde des Cheselden fragen: was betriigt mich, das Gesicht oder Geffihl?" Kant 1788,
"Vorrede," p. 2 7.
2See Kant [1781] 1787, bk. I, part 1, §i.
Empirical Approaches in the Nineteenth Century lo7
T h i n k e r s inclined to t h e n a t i v i s t v i e w p o i n t c a m e to a v a r i e t y of conclusions.
S o m e of t h e m believed t h a t t h e p e r s o n b o r n blind would be able to do no
m o r e t h a n d i s t i n g u i s h t h e o b j e c t s from one a n o t h e r , while o t h e r s a s s u m e d
t h a t he would also be able to n a m e them. 1 A few n a t i v i s t s believed t h a t
t h e s o l u t i o n to M o l y n e u x ' s p r o b l e m h a d indeed been e x p e r i m e n t a l l y p r o v e d
b u t t h e y a s c r i b e d the i n c a p a c i t y shown by the p a t i e n t s involved to m e n t a l
confusion a n d u n f a v o u r a b l e c i r c u m s t a n c e s , r a t h e r t h a n to t h e lack of an i n b o r n
r e p r e s e n t a t i o n of space. 2
T h e difference b e t w e e n empiricists a n d n a t i v i s t s was, in fact, not as g r e a t
as it was m a d e to seem. A. W . V o l k m a n n n o t e d this at an e a r l y s t a g e when
he w r o t e t h e following:
that such a person would be able to distinguish these two objects one from the other but
would be unable to name them. See Raehlmann 1891 , p. 94.
1See, for example, Janet 1879 , p. 7, respectively Tourtual 1827, Mfiller 1837-184o, vol. 2,
p. 362, and Stumpf 1873, p. 291. Stumpf was of the opinion that the man would be able
to name the objects provided that he was educated.
~James 189o , vol. 2, p. 21o, Mach 1886, p. 62, and Schlodtmann 19o2 , p. 260, note.
3Volkmann 1863, pp. 139-14o. Hering had a similar opinion: "Zwischen 'Nativismus'
und 'Empirismus' besteht kein grunds£tzlicher, sondern nur ein gradweiser Unterschied.
Wenn uns, um dies hier abermals abzusprechen, die Organe angeboren sind, so sind es bis
zu einem gewissen Grade auch ihre Functionen, das mfissen selbst die strengsten 'Empiris-
ten' zugeben; und andererseits hat es nie einen 'Nativisten' gegeben, der den gewaltigen
Einflu6 geleugnet h~tte, welchen Gebrauch und Ubung auf die Functionen unserer Organe
und besonders der Sinnesorgane hat." Hering [1874] 1878, as quoted in Schlodtmann 19o2 ,
p. 257.
Empirical Approaches in the Nineteenth Century lo9
1Born 1791, pp. 11o-111: "Man darf daher nicht, mit Molyneux, die Frage aufwerfen:
ob ein Blinder, der Kugel und Wfirfel durchs Gef/ihl gekannt hatte, sie auch durchs An-
sehen kennen wiirde, wenn er pl5fllich das Gesicht bek/~me? [...] Denn da das Gesicht und
das Geffihl von denselbigen Gegenst/~nden nicht auf einerley Art afficirt werden; so muB
daher die empirische Raumvorstellung von k6rperlichen R/iumen in Personen, bey welchen
sie durch das einseitige Gefiihl bestimmt wird, ganz anders ausfallen, als bey Leuten, die
Gesicht und Geffihl verbinden."
2Platner [1776] 1793, §765, p. 44o.
3platner [1776] 1793, §765, p. 441.
4James 1887, p. 211.
5Hagen 1844, p. 718: "Was uns Raum ist, ist bei [Blindgeborenen] blo• Zeit." See also
Lotze [1881] 1882.
6Hamilton [1858-186o] 1861-1866, vol. 2, Lecture 28, pp. 176 177.
11o Chapter Five
had come to a similar conclusion. 1 John Stuart Mill also subscribed to Plat-
net's suggestion that the idea of space could eventually be reduced to that of
time and, furthermore, he believed that Platner's observations had demon-
strated that the concept of extension or distance is generated by the series
of sensations of muscle movements, as Bain had proposed. ~ Platner found a
fierce defender even halfway through the twentieth century; the German psy-
chologist Max yon Senden thought Platner to be "the first to conclude that
we merely allow ourselves to be deceived by the verbal habits of the blind and
that in reality they have no awareness of space. ''3
As could be expected, there was also criticism of Platner. 4 The French
philosopher Charles Dunan (1849-1931), while regarding Platner's observa-
tions as confirmation of the thesis that the blind would lack the notion of
space possessed by the sighted, said that this did not mean that they would
have no notion of space at all, as Platner had stated. Through discussions
that he himself had had with blind people Dunan was convinced that the
blind certainly do have a good notion of space; it is simply different from
that of the sighted. On these grounds Dunan responded in the negative to
Molyneux's question. 5
James thought that Dunan, in his turn, had only been partially right. He
believed that the notion the blind have of space may well differ from that of
the sighted, but that at the same time there is a deep analogy between the
two:
"Big" and "little," "far" and "near," are similar contents of conscious-
ness in both of us. But the measure of the bigness and the farness is
very different in [the blind man] and in ourselves. He, for example,
can have no notion of what we mean by objects appearing smaller
as they move away, because he must always conceive of them as of
their constant tactile size. Nor, whatever analogy the two extensions
involve, should we expect that a blind man receiving sight for the first
time should recognise his new-given optical objects by their familiar
tactile names. 6
James was therefore not surprised that the answer given by Molyneux and
Locke to Molyneux's question had been experimentally confirmed. 1
W h a t James was trying to make clear was that there are different concepts
of space. One of the major differences between visual and tactile space is
that visual space is projective and non-Euclidean whereas tactile space is
Euclidean. In the case of sight it can be said, for instance, that an object
reduces in size in proportion to its distance from the observer, that angles
change according to the point of view and that circles can pass vi£ ellipses
into straight lines. This does not apply to the sense of touch: angles, lines
and surfaces are unchangeable, no matter how an object is rotated.
James was convinced that the concepts of space originally different from
each other and even incoherent are eventually through experience reduced to
a common measure, namely that of the real world. 2 At the end of the nine-
teenth century Stratton demonstrated experimentally that tactile localization,
as regards both direction and distance, can be influenced by a disturbance of
normal visual localization. This caused him to conclude that through asso-
ciation a correspondence between touch and sight is formed point-by-point
and that we learn only through experience which visual position corresponds
to which tactile position. Stratton saw confirmation of his opinion in the
reactions shown by blind people after an operation. 3
5 CONCLUSIONS
:James 189o , vol. 2, p. 21o. As already stated, James partially ascribed the incapacity
of the patients in question to unfavourable circumstances and attached more importance
to positive than to negative cases. See also Villey 1914, pp. 168-184.
2 "The various space-senses are, in the first instance, incoherent with each other; [...] The
education of our space-perception consists largely of two processes--reducing the various
sense-feelings to a common measure, and adding them together into the single all-including
space of the real world." James 1887, pp. 536-537; also in James 189o, vol. 2, pp. 268-269.
3Stratton 1899. Stratton conducted an experiment in which mirrors were used to project
the image of the test subject diagonally before him.
112 Chapter Five
between visual and tactile sensations or between visual and tactile concepts,
as had previously been the case, but were more involved with empirical d a t a
concerning the perception of blind people restored to sight, newborn animals
and babies.
It is remarkable that there was still no agreement as to what was the most
plausible answer to Molyneux's question. New cataract operations performed
on people born blind provided results that were contradictory and difficult
to assess. If we have to indicate a general tendency, we could say that most
researchers believed that a person born blind receiving his sight would be able
to distinguish a sphere from a cube but would not be able to name the objects
correctly.
One of the principal shifts in the nineteenth century was that Berkeley's
theory of vision (and therefore his solution to Molyneux's problem) lost its
ability to convince. Information on the powers of sight of newborn animals
(and to a lesser extent that of human infants) and Wheatstone's explanation
of stereoscopic vision contributed to this. Animals were seen to be capable
of perceiving objects at different distances immediately after birth, infants
showed evidence of spatial vision before any tactile experience worthy of men-
tion and Wheatstone demonstrated that stereoscopic perception of depth was
caused by retinal disparity. In short, it became clear that spatial vision was
not derived from touch, as Berkeley had stated.
There was disagreement surrounding the question of the extent to which
spatial vision was more acquired than inborn. As we shall see in the next
chapter, discoveries were about to be made in the field of neurophysiology
which would provide more clarity in the matter, just as research into visual
deprivation was to provide greater insight into the way to assess d a t a derived
from blind persons treated surgically.
CHAPTER SIX
MODERN APPROACHES
1 HISTORICAL ANALYSES
1See, for example, Bourdon 19o2, Schlodtmann 19o2, Villey 1914, Dennis 1934, and
Murray 1944.
2See, for example, Klein 197o, Pastore 1971, Murray 1983, Dember & Bagwell 1985,
Van Hof & Walter [1978] 1984, Crone 1992, and Zeki 1993.
113
114 Chapter Six
Over the centuries cataract has been diagnosed and treated at increasingly
earlier stages, leading to a decrease in the number of reports of (older) patients
operated on. The reports which are published hardly differ from the cases we
have already examined. The fact that a couple of them are discussed here is
merely for the sake of completeness.
By far the most influential was Von Senden's Raum- und Gestaltauffassung
bei operierten Blindgeborenen (1932) which contains reports on sixty cataract
operations. Von Senden stated that Molyneux was the first to draw attention
to the importance of such patients for theories regarding our conceptions of
space. Using various cases Von Senden attempted to investigate whether the
tactile impressions of blind people provide them with any spatial awareness
and he also wished to discover how spatial awareness develops in blind people
who have been surgically treated.
Like Platner, as already stated, Von Senden believed that spatial awareness
can only be obtained through sight. He came to this conclusion "because it
repeatedly emerged throughout virtually all the cases, that everything spatial
presented to the patient after the operation is entirely new to him, and that
no bridge, however narrow, can be opened up to it from his tactual mode of
1In a later article Gregory stated that he had shown a sphere and a cube to the patient
immediately after the operation and that the man had named them correctly as round
and square. However, the original report does not mention this experiment. Gregory also
suggested that Molyneux's question had distracted research from what he considered to
be fruitful territory, namely the study of the "innate" knowledge of babies. See Gregory
1974b, p. 429. See also Mackie 1974 and Berman 1974b.
2Gregory & Wallace 1963, p. 39: "It would seem that the difficulty is not so much in
learning per se as in changing perceptual habits and strategies from touching to seeing."
3Sacks 1993 describes a patient who "had at first been unable to recognize any shapes
visually [... ]. To him, a touch square in no sense corresponded to a sight square. This was
his answer to the Molyneux question."
Modern Approaches 117
The same applies to the interpretation of the case studies. The various cases
are difficult to compare because of the differences in pre-operative and post-
operative situations. In addition it is often unclear from what age and to
what extent the person in question was blind. The only progress made is
that greater insight has been obtained into the effects of long-lasting (total or
partial) light deprivation on the development of the visual system.
Despite the difficulties, the various reports are used as evidence for so-
lutions to Molyneux's problem. A few people have regarded the results as
confirmation of Locke's position? But most researchers have concluded that
a congenitally blind person undergoing a successful operation can indeed dis-
tinguish a sphere from a cube but cannot name the objects correctly? Gregory
and Wallace were the only ones to show conviction that the patient in question
was also able to name the objects correctly.
A number of authors have expressed criticism. They regarded the contra-
dictory results unsuitable for providing an answer to Molyneux's question.
Morgan, for instance, wrote the following: "We cannot answer confidently be-
cause the evidence is contradictory." 3 John Heil expressed himself in similar
terms: "evidence bearing on Molyneux's question remains inconclusive and
unsatisfactory. ''4 Crone too believed that cataract patients can provide no
conclusive evidence because they have forgotten the skill of seeing thanks to
their long-term blindness, s
To avoid the problems surrounding the clinical cases, alternatives with
greater experimental control were sought. These included animal experiments
involving deprivation. In 197o the historian Klein thus wrote: "In recent
decades the [Molyneux] problem has been tackled by animal physiologists by
methods more amenable to experimental control than is possible in clinical
studies." 6
1See, for example, Klein 197o, p. 391, and Dember & Bagwell 1985, pp. 279-280.
2See, for example, Von Senden [1932] 196o, p. 169, Zuckerman & Rock 1957, pp. 286-
287, Mackie 1976, p. 31, Van Hof-Van Duin 1981, p. 1655, and Van Hof & Walter [1978]
1984, PP. 524-525•
3Morgan 1977, p. 18o.
4Hell 1987, p. 233.
5Crone 1992. See also Murray 1944, p. 607, Mackie 1976, p. 31, and Evans 1985, pp. 38o-
382.
6Klein 197o, p. 391.
118 Chapter Six
Since Spalding's experiments with newborn chicks deprived of light for a few
days by means of a small cap, various species of animals have been the subject
of studies into the effects of visual deprivation on the development of the
visual system. 1 These animals have included fish, rats, rabbits, cats and
chimpanzees, allowed to mature in variable periods of total darkness from
birth. Once the period of darkness had passed, the eyes of the animals were
exposed to a quantity of light, limited or not as the case may be, and the
results of the deprivation were studied systematically. The results showed
that the effects of light deprivation vary from species to species.:
Various researchers have used the results of deprivation experiments to
solve Molyneux's problem. In view of the fact that such experiments per-
formed on human beings are generally unacceptable from a moral viewpoint
(despite the plea made by the eighteenth-century philosopher M~rian) and
animal experiments seem to meet with less resistance, researchers have based
their conclusions mainly on the experiments performed on chimpanzees, Man's
close relative. 3
In the forties the psychologist Austin Riesen allowed two chimpanzees to
spend the first sixteen months of their life in darkness. After the period had
passed they exhibited reflexes which showed that their eyes were sensitive to
light. However, they were incapable of recognising by sight objects--such
as a feeding b o t t l e - - t h a t they had learnt to recognise by touch. After the
sixteen months of darkness Riesen exposed one of the chimpanzees to a limited
amount of light for five months and the other for seventeen months. Then
the animals were placed in an environment with normal daylight. After a
number of months the first chimpanzee managed to recognise objects, but the
behaviour of the second appeared to be greatly retarded. At first its faculty
of sight improved briefly but then relapsed rapidly. 4
In another experiment a chimpanzee that had spent the first seven months
of its life in a normal environment and had good eyesight was closed up in
darkness until the age of twenty-four months. Subsequently it was unable to
recognise its feeding bottle and other objects and was even unable to look at
people or objects. Its recovery was slow and partial. 5
In a third experiment Riesen had a chimpanzee spend the first three months
of its life in darkness. This animal took longer to react adequately to visual
stimuli than did chimpanzees that had spent the first seven months in dark-
ness. Riesen believed that this indicated that visual discrimination is a matter
of both maturity and learning. 1
Later research showed that long-term stimulus deprivation had led to de-
generation of some of the retinal ganglion cellsP During the development
of the visual system there seems to be a particular period of sensitivity to
deprivation of light. Within this sensitive or critical period changes brought
on by deprivation can be undone. But when exposure to light is postponed
for too long the development of normal visual mechanisms becomes extremely
difficult if not impossible.
On the basis of other experiments Riesen came to the conclusion that it is
not only light itself that is essential for normal visual development: stimulus
through visual patterns is also an essential requirement. 3 Other researchers
confirmed this. The famous studies carried out on cats by Hubel and Wiesel
showed that individual neurons react to simple visual forms, such as a thin
moving rod in a particular orientation against a constant background surface. 4
Neuronal detectors of this type are present at birth and their behaviour can be
modified by experience. Blakemore and Cooper, for instance, demonstrated
that cats raised in an environment lacking vertically oriented stimuli have a
reduced number of neurons that react to vertical stimuli. The animals showed
perceptual deviations: they collided with such objects as the legs of tables and
chairs.5
As already said, the results of visual deprivation experiments were again
referred to in the context of Molyneux's problem. Riesen regarded his exper-
imental results as complementary to the clinical data assembled by Von Sen-
den. a The neurophysiologist Van Hof-Van Duin described Molyneux's prob-
lem as a deprivation experiment raised in order to establish a point of view
in the empiricism-nativism debate. She was of the opinion that although
it was impossible to take up an unambiguous position, modern deprivation
experiments had clearly shown that the visual system can be permanently af-
fected under the influence of abnormal conditions during development/ The
When, after three hundred years of discussion, no definitive solution has been
found for a particular problem, said Morgan, the problem is either useless or it
has been subjected to the wrong approach. 5 The discovery of a new technique
or the invention of a new piece of equipment can sometimes breathe life into an
exhausted problem. "It promises to be thus with Molyneux's question, which,
after long and inconclusive debates about recovery from blindness, has been
recently tackled by a totally new approach," was the way Morgan expressed
his opinion. 1 The approach he was referring to was the use of what was called
the Tactile Visual Substitution System (TVSS) developed at the end of the
sixties by the Smith-Kettlewell Institute of Visual Sciences. 2
A TVSS is a device which can be used to project images of objects onto the
skin of a person, blind or not. Its major components are a television camera
and a matrix of twenty by twenty electrically powered vibrotactors which are
fixed to the back or stomach of the observer. The television camera transmits
signals vi£ an electronic circuit to the vibrotactors, causing some of them to
vibrate, depending on the pattern registered by the camera. Each vibrotactor
covers a small area of the image captured by the camera, just as a newspaper
photograph reproduces a situation as a series of tiny dots. The pattern of
tactile stimulation corresponds roughly to an enlarged visual image.
It turned out that provided that participants in the experiment were able to
move the camera actively themselves, after practising for some time they were
able to learn to distinguish and identify objects with the aid of the TVSS. 3
Bach-y-Rita conducted experiments involving blind people, who first were
given an explanation of how the equipment worked and were then trained to
distinguish between horizontal, vertical, diagonal and curved lines. Then they
learnt to recognise combinations of lines (such as circles, squares and triangles)
and solid objects. After an hour's practice the leader of the experiment showed
the subjects a series of day-to-day objects and drew their attention to the
various components of an object, to the relationships between the components
and to the object as a whole. Once each object had been analyzed the leader
of the experiment presented the subjects with a particular object and asked
them to identify it. At first it took five to eight minutes before an object was
recognised; after ten hours' practice the reaction time was no more than a few
seconds. 4
It became clear that test subjects can learn to determine not only the
shape of objects but also their position, relative size, number, orientation
and direction, as also the speed of movement of the camera. They form
visual concepts such as perspective, shadows, shape distortion as a function of
viewpoint and apparent change in size as a function of distance. 5 Test subjects
react with a shock when an object suddenly looms up. A remarkable thing
is that sensations of stimuli to the skin disappear in the course of time and
give way to the perception of external objects: "[the] subjects spontaneously
1Warren & Strelow 1984, pp. 331-332. Warren and Strelow were aware that a "sensory
aid is not, strictly speaking, a new modality."
2The BSA was designed by L. Kay. See Kay 1974.
3Warren & Strelow 1984, p. 348. Heil regarded information on the use of sensory sub-
stitution systems as disproving Locke's assoeiationist position. See Heil 1987, p. 239.
4Warren and Strelow also pointed out that certain results would perhaps not be obtained
if blind rather than blindfolded people were used as test subjects. Research carried out by
Aitken and Bower (1982) also showed that blind babies quickly observe objects rather than
echoes.
12 4 Chapter Six
6 CONCLUSIONS
As was the case in the nineteenth century, Molyneux's problem played not
such a prominent r61e in the twentieth century as it did in the eighteenth
century. And yet it would appear that it still keeps minds occupied. Many
modern publications on the subject are of an historical nature, usually inter-
pretations of the positions taken up by famous philosophers in earlier times.
A couple of authors have written s u m m a r y histories of the problem. In ad-
dition philosophers, psychologists and other scientists have themselves made
a t t e m p t s to solve the problem, using tools both old and new. The old meth-
ods included appeals to results obtained in tests carried out on congenitally
blind people whose sight has been restored surgically. The approach provided
no new insights, particularly because of the problems of interpretation, which
refuse to become less with the passage of time.
More interesting are the results of experiments in which animals were de-
prived of visual stimuli. Among the data such experiments have provided is
the knowledge that the nature of the stimulus during what has come to be
called the critical period is of importance in the development of the visual
1In this interesting article, Evans aimed to show "how Molyneux's Question is linked to
fundamental issues in the philosophy of mind and perception" (p. 399). See also Campbell
1989.
2Evans 1985, pp. 392 ft. See also Brindley & Lewin 1968 and Dobelle 1977.
Modern Approaches 12 5
M O L Y N E U X ' S P R O B L E M IN R E T R O S P E C T
1As we have seen, Berkeley disagreed with this; the early Condillac suggested that it
was possible that an object resembling a sphere when seen could turn out to be a cube
when felt.
127
128 Chapter Seven
and philosophers agreed with this suggestion. Diderot further remarked that
the solutions proposed for Molyneux's problem could not simply be regarded
as universally valid. For if a person cured of blindness were to be shown com-
plex objects, such as a glove or a bathrobe, he would have greater difficulty
identifying them. This is an acceptable assumption.
One of the conditions set by Molyneux was that the sphere and the cube
offered to the blind person first to be touched and then, later, to be viewed
should be made of the same material and should be of the same size. Clearly
Molyneux wished to avoid the objects being recognised on the basis of their
structure and size rather than their shape. Condillac and Diderot regarded
such conditions as superfluous.
A further requirement was that both objects should be placed on a table.
Although nobody suggested as much, it is not difficult to imagine this condi-
tion rendering recognition of the objects more difficult: the blind person now
sighted would have to distinguish not only the cube from the sphere but also
the objects themselves from the table and the table from the background. If
the cube and sphere were to be placed against a plain background this prob-
lem would be obviated. 1 Most researchers assumed implicitly that the person
in question would see the cube and sphere as separate objects.
One of the major assumptions made by Molyneux was that the blind per-
son in question would have his sight restored. When the question was first
formulated participants accepted this hypothesis for the sake of the discus-
sion without really believing that restoration of sight was possible. All this
was changed when Cheselden restored the faculty of sight to a patient with
congenital cataract. From then on, many philosophers believed that the expe-
riences of surgically treated patients with congenital cataracts were, at least in
principle, suitable for solving Molyneux's problem. Only M~rian made an ob-
jection to using cataract patients for this purpose: they are never completely
blind. He also pointed out that people coming into the world completely blind
can never acquire the faculty of sight.
There was some lack of clarity regarding the question of whether Molyneux
would tell the blind person that he was to be shown a sphere and a cube or not.
Leibniz and Jurin, for example, assumed that the blind man would be given
this information and that he would thus only be called on to make the required
distinction. They believed that if this information was not imparted, the
subject would be incapable of distinguishing the sphere from the cube. Others,
including Condillac, thought it desirable not to ask any leading questions and
therefore not to tell the man what objects he was to be shown. And indeed
1Diderot proposed a variant on Molyneux's problem in which a black cube and a red
sphere would be placed against a white background. See Diderot [1749] 1961, p. 137.
Molyneux's Problem in Retrospect 129
3 CONCLUSIONS
to the original problem, have gone on to lead a life of their own. Some of
these are philosophical in nature, such as problems relating to the conceptual
clarification of perceptual terms, to the justification of claims to knowledge, to
the status of philosophical thought experiments, 1 and so on. Others are in the
field of psychology; for example, psychological questions concerning pattern
recognition, learning processes, formation of concepts, methodological issues,
and so on. Still other questions, such as those concerned with the study of
the development of the visual system, critical periods for development, and
the nature and function of the association cortex belong to the domain of
neurophysiology.
And thus the discussions surrounding Molyneux's problem provide us with
the same image as we get from a river. The problem had its source in 1688
in Molyneux's mind. It bubbled along a little until Cheselden performed his
cataract operation in 1728 and initiated a flood. The question then quit the
high country of philosophy and flowed into the wide plains of experimental
psychology and neurophysiology. The mighty stream into which it then flowed
has since spread out to form such a wide delta that it is no longer possible to
measure its extent.
1Wilkes 1988 devotes some attention to the often problematical status of philosophical
thought experiments.
BIBLIOGRAPHY
135
136 Bibliography
BEW, C. 18oo. "Observations sur la c~cit~ et sur l'usage des autres sens pour sup-
plder £ la perte de la vue. T~aduites de l'anglais." In: A. G. Schwenger (ed.),
Mdmoires sur les aveugles, sur la rue et la vision, suivis de la description d'un
tdldgraphe tr~s simple. Paris: Chez l'auteur, A m a n d Koenig, F. Didot, J. J.
Fuchs; Amsterdam: Chez le successeur de C. N. Gu~rin; pp. 23-58.
BIDYADHAR, N. K. 1939. "Susruta and his Ophthalmic Operations." Archives of
Ophthalmology 22, 550-574.
BIDYADHAR, N. K. 194o. "Evolution of Cataract Surgery from the Pre-Historic
Age up to the Present Time." Antiseptic 37, 339-346.
BIDYADHAR, N. K. 1941. "Principles of Susrutian Ocular Therapy Interpreted
in the Light of Modern Ophthalmic Science." Archives of Ophthalmology 25,
582-628.
BLAKEMORE, C. ~ COOPER, G. F. 197o. "Development of the Brain depends on
the Visual Environment." Nature 228, 477-478.
BOLTON BRAND% M. 1994. "The Real Molyneux Question and the Basis of Locke's
Answer." In: G. A. J. Rogers (ed.), Locke's Philosophy. New York: Oxford
University Press.
BONCIE, L. L. 1977. Diderot's Femme savante. Oxford: The Voltaire Foundation
at the Taylor Institution. (Studies on Voltaire and the Eighteenth Century 166.)
BONGIE, L. L. 1978. "A New Condillac Letter and the Genesis of the Traitd des
sensations." Journal of the History of Philosophy 16, 83-94.
BONNET, C. 176o. Essai analytique sur les facultds de l'dme. Copenhague: Chez
les fr~res C1. et Ant. Philibert.
BORN, F. G. 1791. Versuch iiber die urspriinglichen Grundlagen des menschlichen
Denkens und die davon abhiingigen Sehranken unserer Erkenntniss. Leipzig:
Johann Ambrosius Barth.
BOULLIER, D. R. [1728 ] 1737. Essai philosophique sur l'dme des bgtes: o~ l'on
trouve diverses rd]~exions sur la nature de la libertd, sur eelle de nos sensa-
tions, sur l'union de l'dme et du corps, sur l'immortalit~ de l'dme. Amsterdam:
Francois Changuion, 1728. Seconde ~dition revue et augment~e, ~ la quelle on
a joint un trait~ des vrais principes qui servent de fondement £ la certitude
morale. Amsterdam: Fran§ois Changuion, 1737.
BOURDON, B. 19o2. La perception visuelle de l'espace. Paris: Schleicher Fr~res.
BRANDT, R. 1975. "Historical Observations on the Genesis of the Three-
Dimensional Optical Picture (Gassendi, Locke, Berkeley)." Ratio 17, 176-19o.
BREATHNACH, C. S. 1984. "Biographical Sketches, No. 39: Molyneux." Irish
Medical Journal 77, 118.
BREIDERT, W . 1989. George Berkeley: 1685-1753. Basel: Birkh~user.
BRINDLEY, G. S. ~: LEWlN, W. S. 1968. "The Sensations Produced by Electrical
Stimulation of the Visual Cortex." Journal of Physiology 196 , 479 493.
BRISSEAU, M. 17o 9. Traitd de la cataracte et du glaucoma. Paris: D'Houry.
BROWN, T. [182o] 186o. Lectures on the Philosophy of the Human Mind. Twentieth
Edition. London: William Tegg, 186o.
138 Bibliography
DIDEROT, D. [1749] 1961. Lettre sur les aveugles, d l'usage de ceux qua voient.
Londres 1749. Reprinted in: Diderot, (Euvres philosophiques. Textes dtablis,
avec introductions, bibliographies et notes par P. Verni~re. Paris: Garnier
Fr~res, 1961.
DIDEROT, D. [1751] 1965. Lettre sur les sourds et muets, ~ l'usage de ceux quA
entendent et qua parlent. Edition commentde et presentde par P. H. Meyer.
Gen~ve: Librairie E. Droz, 1965.
DIDEROT, D. ~ ALEMBERT, J. LE ROND D' (EDS.) 1751-1780. Encyclopddie, ou
dictionnaire raisonnd des sciences, des arts et des mdtiers, par une socidtd de
gens de lettres, mis en ordre par Diderot et D'Alembert. Paris: Briasson.
DILTHEV, W. [19Ol] 1927. "Friedrich der Grosse und die Deutsche Aufkliirung."
Reprinted in: Wilhelm Dilthey's Gesammelte Schriften. Vol. 3. Leipzig und
Berlin: B. G. Teubner, 1927; pp. 83-209.
DOBELLE, W. H. 1977. "Current State of Research on Providing Sight to the Blind
by Electrical Stimulation of the Brain." Journal of Impairment and Blindness
71, 29o-297.
DUFAU, P. i . 1837. Essai sur l'dtat physique, moral et intellectuel des aveugles-
nds: avec un nouveau plan pour l'amdlioration de leur condition sociale. Paris:
Imprimerie Royale.
DUNAN, C. 1888. "L'espace visuel et l'espace tactile." Revue philosophique 25,
134-169, 354-386, 591-619 •
DUTT, K. C. 1938. "Cataract Operations in the Prehistoric Age." Archives of
Ophthalmology 2o, 1-15.
EBBINGHAUS, H. 19o8. Abrijff der Psychologie. Leipzig: Veit und Co.
ERHARDT-SIEBOLD,E. VON. 1932. "Harmony of the Senses in English, German,
and French Romanticism." Publications of the Modern Language Association
of America 47, 577-592.
EVANS, G. 1985. "Molyneux's Question." In: Evans, Collected Papers. Edited by
A. Phillips. Oxford: Clarendon Press; pp. 364 399.
[FONTENELLE, B. LE BOVIER DE]. 17o7. "Sur les cataractes des yeux." Histoire
de l'Acaddmie Royale des Sciences pour l'annde 17o7, 22-25. Paris: Chez la
Veuve de Jean Boudot.
FORREST, D. W. 1965. "Recovery of Sight in the Blind." American Journal of
Psychology 78, 147-148.
FORREST, D. W. 1974. "Von Senden, Mesmer, and the Recovery of Sight in the
Blind." American Journal of Psychology 87, 719-722.
FRANZ, J. C. A. 1839. The Eye: A Treatise on the Art of Preserving this Organ in
a Healthy Condition, and of Improving the Sight; to which is Prefixed, a View
of the Anatomy, and Physiology o/ the Eye; with Observations on its Expression
as Indicative of the Character and Emotions of the Mind. London: J. Churchill.
FRANZ, J. C. A. 1841. "Memoir of the Case of a Gentleman Born Blind, and
Successfully Operated Upon in the 18th Year of his Age, with Physiological
Observations and Experiments." Philosophical Transactions of the Royal Soci-
ety of London 131 , 59-68.
Bibliography 141
MACH, E. 19oo. Die Analyse der Emp]~ndungen und das Verhiiltniss des Physi-
schen zum Psychischen. Zweite vermehrte Auflage der Beitriige zur Analyse
der Empfindungen. Jena: Gustav Fischer.
MACKIE, J. L. 1974. "Philosophical Prediction." Times Literary Supplement,
3 May, 477.
MACKIE, J. L. 1976. Problems from Locke. Oxford: Oxford University Press.
MACLEAN, K. 1936. John Locke and English Literature of the Eighteenth Century.
New Haven: Yale University Press.
MAITRE-JAN, A. 17o7. Traitd des maladies de l'oeil et des rem~des propres pour
leur gudrison. Troyes: Le Febvre.
MARCHAN, L. 1768. Observatien over de quaalen der oogen, en 't gebruik van
een ophtalmickswaater, om die te geneezen. Uit het Fransch. 's-Gravenhage:
D. Monnier.
M~aIAN, J. B. [1772/73/74/76/77/79/81/82 ] 1984. "Sur le probl~me de Molyneux:
premier-huiti~me mdmoire." Nouveaux mdmoires de l'Acaddmie Royale des
Sciences et Belles-Lettres pour l'ann~e 177o/71/72/74/75/77/79/8o. Berlin:
Voss, 1772/73/74/76/77; Berlin: Decker, 1779/81/82. Reprinted in: M~rian,
Sur le probl~me de Molyneux. Suivi de "M~rian, Diderot et l'Aveugle" par
Francine Markovits. Paris: Flammarion.
MILL, J. S. [1842] 1859. "Bailey on Berkeley's Theory of Vision." Westminster
Review, October 1842. Reprinted in: Mill 1859, pp. 84-114.
MILL, J. S. [1843] 1859. "Rejoinder to Mr. Bailey's Reply." Westminster Review,
May 1843. Reprinted in: Mill 1859, pp. 114-119 .
MILL, J. S. 1859. Dissertations and Discussions: Political, Philosophical, and
Historical. Vol. 2. London: Longmans, Green, Reader and Dyer.
MILL, J. S. 1865. An Examination of Sir William Hamilton's Philosophy and
of the Principal Philosophical Questions Discussed in his Writings. London:
Longman, Green, Longman, Roberts and Green.
MOLYNEUX, C. 182o. An Account of the Family and Descendants of Sir Thomas
Molyneux, Kt., Chancellor of the Exchequer in Ireland to Queen Elizabeth. Eve-
sham: J. Agg.
MOLYNEUX, W. 1692. Dioptrica Nova: A Treatise of Dioptricks, in Two Parts,
Wherein the Various Effects and Appearances of Spherick Glasses, Both Con-
vex and Concave, Single and Combined, in Telescopes and Microscopes, To-
gether with their Usefulness in many Concerns of Humane Life, are Explained.
London: Printed for Benj. Tooke.
MOLYNEUX, W. 1698. The Case of Ireland's Being Bound by Acts of Parliament
in England, Stated. Dublin: Joseph Ray.
MOLYNEUX, W. 1803. Anecdotes of the Life of the Celebrated Patriot and Philoso-
pher Win. Molyneux, Author of The Case of Ireland. Published from a Manu-
script Written by Himself, in Possession of Sir Capel Molyneux, to Which are
Annexed Explanatory Notes by the Editor. Dublin: Privately printed.
MONCK, W. H. S. 1882. "Observations in Cases of Couching for Cataract." Mind
7, 107-110.
146 Bibliography
15i
152 Index of Names
Daviel, J., 59, 64, 89, 93 n, 139 Hamilton, W., 87, 96n, 99, l o o n , l o 3 n ,
Davis, J. W., 14, lo7 n, 113, 114n , 139 lo7n, lO9, 141, 145, 147, 148
Davy, H., 99 Hamlyn, D. W., 135
Daza de Valdes, B., 6o, 139 Hausmann, H., 53 n, 141
De Beer, E. S., 144 Hafiy, V., 14, 81 n, 141
Delacampagne, C., 75 n, 139 Heath, P., 147
Dember, W. N., 113n , 117n , 119n , 139 Hebb, D. O., 115, 116, 119n , 141
Dennis, W., 113n , 139 Heil, J., 117, 123n , 141
Descartes, R., 18, 29, 65, 75, 139 Helmholtz, H. L. F. yon, 13, lO6, lO7 n,
Dewey, J., lo7, 139 141
Diderot, D., 13, 7o, 71 n, 72-78, 84, 85, Henkes, H. E., 59 n, 141
89 n, 111, 113, l 1 5 n , 127, 128, 131 , Hering, E., lO6, lo8n, 141
132, 135, 137, 139--141, 144--146 Hippel, A. von, 94, lo7n, 141
Dilthey, W., 83n , 14o Hirsch, H. V. B., 119n , 141
Dobelle, W. H., 124n, 14o Hirschberg, J., 58 n, 94 n, lOO n, 1o 7 n,
Doesschate, G. ten, 64 n, 138 142
Domville, L., 19 Hof, M. W. van, l13n , 117n , 12o, 142
Dufau, P. A., 13n , 14o Hof-Van Duin, J. van, 117n , 119, 142
Duggan, T., 147 Holmes, G., 74
Duin, J. van. See Hof-Van Duin, J. van Home, E., 89, 9o, 142
Dunan, C., lOTn, 110, 140 Hoppen, K. T., 18 n, 142
Dutt, K. C., 58n, 14o Hubel, D. H., 119, 142
Hume, D., 35, 142
Ebbinghaus, H., l o 7 n , 14o Humphrey, N. K., 99, 116, 135
Egeria, 7° Hutcheson, F., 44-46, 51, 79, 13o, 136,
Erhardt-Siebold, E. von, 13 n, 14o 142
Euclid, 37, 45, 50, 111, 139 Huygens, Chr., 18, 23, lO4 n, 142
Evans, G., l l O n , l 1 5 n , l 1 7 n , 124, 129,
138, 14o Jackson, F., 25 n, 142
James, W., 13, 88n, 96 , 97 n, 1o8n,
Ferrand, E., 70 109--111 ~ 14~
Flamsteed, J., 18 Janet, P., 88 n, lO8 n, 142
Flourens, M. J. P., 99 n Janin, J., 89, 93 n, 143
Fontenelle, B. Le Bovier de, 59n, 14o Jaynes, J., 118n, 136
Formey, J. H. S., 78 n Jesus, 58 n
Forrest, D. W., 58n, 14o Jones, B., 115 n, 143
Franz, J. C. A., 89-95 , 14o Joyeuse, 139
Fraser, A. C., 94n, 136 Jurin, J., 48, 49, 51, 128, 129, 143
Freud, S., 56
Kant, I., 35, lO6-1o8, 143
Gassendi, P., 137 Kay, L., 123n, 143
God, 65-67, 74, 89 Kelly, P. H., 18n, 143, 148
Goethe, J. W. von, 64 n Kepler, J., 18, 23, lO4, 143
Grant, R., 52, 6o, 87, 141, 148 Kimble, G. A., 139
's Gravesande, W. J., 63-64, 141, 146 Klein, D. B., 113n , 117, 12o, 143
Gregory, R. L., 115-117, 122 n, 141 KShler, W., 115 n, 143
Grimm, F. M., 71, 141 Kolk, J. L. C. Schroeder van der, lO3
Guarniero, G., 121n, 122, 141 Kr/iger, J. G., 62 n, 143
accommodation, 3 ° , 58 eye
amaurotism, 91, 92 anatomy of, 57
amblyopia, 59 n movement, 23, 32 , 61, 76 , 91
apperception, 42
association cortex, 133 faculty psychology, 34
association of ideas, 3o n, 49, 61
associationism, 123 n
atheism, 65, 74 Gestalt psychology, 115 n
"idea", 19 n
cataract, 57-58
idea vs. image, 39, 43, 46
surgical treatment of, 58-59
immaterialism, 44
Cheselden's report, 53-56
criticism of, 6o, 65-83, 87-88
regarded as supportive of Berkeley's judgment, unconscious, 27, 29, 40, 42, 68,
theory of vision, 6o-64, 84 71
common sense, 35, 43, 75
common sense philosophy, 34 language metaphor. See visual
convergence, 3 ° perception, analogy with the
couching (cataract operation), 58 understanding of language
critical period, 97 n, 116, 119, 124, 132 looking vs. seeing, 71
cross-modal transfer, 116
materialism, 42 , 65
deprivation, visual microscope, 18, 34, 63 n
animal studies, 118--120, 124-125, 132 Molyneux's problem
in humans, 59 n, 80-83, l o 5 n , Xl 7 as empirically solvable problem,
depth, perception of. See distance, 52-125, 13o-132
perception of; space, perception of as thought experiment, 25-52 , 13o
development (visual system). See background, 18-2o
deprivation, visual first formulation, 17-18
Ding-an-sich, lO6, lO 7 first publication, 21-23
distance, perception of. See also space, history of, 14, 113-114
perception of interpretations of, 127-129
Berkeley on, 29-32 , 131 Molyneux's question
in newborn animals and babies, negative answers to, 26-38. See also
98-1o4, 131 Cheselden's report: regarded as
Molyneux on, 22 23 supportive of Berkeley's theory of
Wheatstone on, lO4-1o6, 131 vision
dualism, 65 positive answers to, 39-50. See also
Cheselden's report: criticism of
empiricism, 42, 51, 66 68, lO6-111, 113
extraction (cataract operation), 58-59 nativism, lO6-111, 113
155
156 Index of Subjects
85. B6rault Stuart, Seigneur d'Aubigny: Traitd sur l'art de la guerre. Introduction et
6dition par t~lie de Comminges. 1976 ISBN 90-247-1871-6
86. S.L. Kaplan: Bread, Politics and Political Economy in the Reign of Louis XV. 2 vols.,
1976 Set ISBN 90-247-1873-2
87. M. Lienhard (ed.): The Origins and Characteristics of Anabaptism / Les ddbuts et les
caractdristiques de l'Anabaptisme. With an Extensive Bibliography / Avec une
bibliographie d6taill6e. 1977 ISBN 90-247-1896-1
88. R. Descartes: R~gles utiles et claires pour la direction de l' esprit en la recherche de la
v~ritd. Traduction selon le lexique cart6sien, et annotation conceptuelle par J.-L.
Marion. Avec des notes math6matiques de P. Costabel. 1977 ISBN 90-247-1907-0
89. K. Hardesty: The 'SupplEment' to the 'Encyclopddie'. [Diderot et d'Alembert]. 1977
ISBN 90-247-1965-8
90. H.B. White: Antiquity Forgot. Essays on Shakespeare, [Francis] Bacon, and Rem-
bran&. 1978 ISBN 90-247-1971-2
91. P.B.M. Blaas: Continuity and Anachronism. Parliamentary and Constitutional
Development in Whig Historiography and in the Anti-Whig Reaction between 1890
and 1930. 1978 ISBN 90-247-2063-X
92. S.L. Kaplan (ed.): La Bagarre. Ferdinando Galiani's (1728-1787) 'Lost' Parody. With
an Introduction by the Editor. 1979 ISBN 90-247-2125-3
93. E. McNiven Hine: A Critical Study of [l~tienne Bonnot de] Condillac' s [1714-1780]
'TraitFdes Syst~mes'. 1979 ISBN 90-247-2120-2
94. M.R.G. Spiller: Concerning Natural Experimental Philosphy. Merle Casaubon [1599-
1671] and the Royal Society. 1980 ISBN 90-247-2414-7
95. F. Duchesneau: La physiologie des Lumi~res. Empirisme, modules et thC,ofies. 1982
ISBN 90-247-2500-3
96. M. Heyd: Between Orthodoxy and the Enlightenment. Jean-Robert Chouet [1642-
1731] and the Introduction of Cartesian Science in the Academy of Geneva. 1982
ISBN 90-247-2508-9
97. James O'Higgins: Yves de Vallone [1666/7-1705]: The Making of an Esprit Fort.
1982 ISBN 90-247-2520-8
98. M.L. Kuntz: Guillaume Postel [1510-1581]. Prophet of the Restitution of All Things.
His Life and Thought. 1981 ISBN 90-247-2523-2
99. A. Rosenberg: Nicolas Gueudeville and His Work (1652-172?). 1982
ISBN 90-247-2533-X
100. S.L. Jaki: Uneasy Genius: The Life and Work of Pierre Duhem [1861-1916]. 1984
ISBN 90-247-2897-5; Pb (1987) 90-247-3532-7
101. Anne Conway [1631-1679]: The Principles of the Most Ancient Modern Philosophy.
Edited and with an Introduction by P. Loptson. 1982 ISBN 90-247-2671-9
102. E.C. Patterson: [Mrs.] Mary [Fairfax Greig] Sommerville [1780-1872] and the
Cultivation of Science (1815-1840). 1983 ISBN 90-247-2823 - 1
103. C.J. Berry: Hume, Hegel and Human Nature. 1982 ISBN 90-247-2682-4
104. C.J. Betts: Early Deism in France. From the so-called 'd6istes' of Lyon (1564) to
Voltaire's 'Lettres philosophiques' (1734). 1984 ISBN 90-247-2923-8
ARCHIVES INTERNATIONALES D'HISTOIRE DES IDt~ES
105. R. Gascoigne: Religion, Rationality and Community. Sacred and Secular in the
Thought of Hegel and His Critics. 1985 ISBN 90-247-2992-0
106. S. Tweyman: Scepticism and Belief in Hume's 'Dialogues Concerning Natural
Religion'. 1986 ISBN 90-247-3090-2
107. G. Cemy: Theology, Politics and Letters at the Crossroads of European Civilization.
Jacques Basnage [1653-1723] and the Baylean Huguenot Refugees in the Dutch
Republic. 1987 ISBN 90-247-3150-X
108. Spinoza's Algebraic Calculation of the Rainbow & Calculation of Changes. Edited
and Translated from Dutch, with an Introduction, Explanatory Notes and an Appendix
by M.J. Petry. 1985 ISBN 90-247-3149-6
109. R.G. McRae: Philosophy and the Absolute. The Modes of Hegel's Speculation. 1985
ISBN 90-247-3151-8
110. J.D. North and J.J. Roche (eds.): The Light of Nature. Essays in the History and
Philosophy of Science presented to A.C. Crombie. 1985 ISBN 90-247-3165-8
111. C. Walton and P.J. Johnson (eds.): [Thomas] Hobbes's 'Science of Natural Justice'.
1987 ISBN 90-247-3226-3
112. B.W. Head: Ideology and Social Science. Destutt de Tracy and French Liberalism.
1985 ISBN 90-247-3228-X
113. A.Th. Peperzak: Philosophy and Politics. A Commentary on the Preface to Hegel's
Philosophy of Right. 1987 ISBN Hb 90-247-3337-5; Pb ISBN 90-247-3338-3
114. S. Pines and Y. Yovel (eds.): Maimonides [1135-1204] and Philosophy. Papers
Presented at the 6th Jerusalem Philosophical Encounter (May 1985). 1986
ISBN 90-247-3439-8
115. T.J. Saxby: The Quest for the New Jerusalem, Jean de Labadie [1610-1674] and the
Labadists (1610-1744). 1987 ISBN 90-247-3485-1
116. C.E. Harline: Pamphlets, Printing, and Political Culture in the Early Dutch Republic.
1987 ISBN 90-247-3511-4
117. R.A. Watson and J.E. Force (eds.): The Sceptical Mode in Modern Philosophy. Essays
in Honor of Richard H. Popkin. 1988 ISBN 90-247-3584-X
118. R.T. Bienvenu and M. Feingold (eds.): In the Presence of the Past. Essays in Honor of
Frank Manuel. 1991 ISBN 0-7923-1008-X
119. J. van den Berg and E.G.E. van der Wall (eds.): Jewish-Christian Relations in the
17th Century. Studies and Documents. 1988 ISBN 90-247-3617-X
120. N. Waszek: The Scottish Enlightenment and Hegel's Account of 'Civil Society'. 1988
ISBN 90-247-3596-3
121. J. Walker (ed.): Thought and Faith in the Philosophy of Hegel. 1991
ISBN 0-7923-1234-1
122. Henry More [1614-1687]: The Immortality of the Soul. Edited with Introduction and
Notes by A. Jacob. 1987 ISBN 90-247-3512-2
123. P.B. Scheurer and G. Debrock (eds.): Newton's Scientific and Philosophical Legacy.
1988 ISBN 90-247-3723-0
124. D.R. Kelley and R.H. Popkin (eds.): The Shapes of Knowledge from the Renaissance
to the Enlightenment. 1991 ISBN 0-7923-1259-7
ARCHIVES INTERNATIONALES D'HISTOIRE DES IDt~ES
INTERNATIONAL ARCHIVES OF THE HISTORY OF IDEAS
125. R.M. Golden (ed.): The Huguenot Connection. The Edict of Nantes, Its Revocation,
and Early French Migration to South Carolina. 1988 ISBN 90-247-3645-5
126. S. Lindroth: Les chemins du savoir en Suede. De la fondation de l'Universit6 d'Upsal
Jacob Berzelius. l~tudes et Portraits. Traduit du su6dois, pr6sent~ et annot6 par J.-F.
Battail. Avec une introduction sur Sten Lindroth par G. Eriksson. 1988
ISBN 90-247-3579-3
127. S. Hutton (ed.): Henry More (1614-1687). Tercentenary Studies. With a Biography
and Bibliography by R. Crocker. 1989 ISBN 0-7923-0095-5
128. Y. Yovel (ed.): Kant's Practical Philosophy Reconsidered. Papers Presented at the 7th
Jerusalem Philosophical Encounter (December 1986). 1989 ISBN 0-7923-0405-5
129. J.E. Force and R.H. Popkin: Essays on the Context, Nature, and Influence of Isaac
Newton's Theology. 1990 ISBN 0-7923-0583-3
130. N. Capaidi and D.W. Livingston (eds.): Liberty in Hume's 'History of England'. 1990
ISBN 0-7923-0650-3
131. W. Brand: Hume's Theory of Moral Judgment. A Study in the Unity of A Treatise of
Human Nature. 1992 ISBN 0-7923-1415-8
132. C.E. Harline (ed.): The Rhyme and Reason of Politics in Early Modern Europe.
Collected Essays of Herbert H. Rowen. 1992 ISBN 0-7923-1527-8
133. N. Malebranche: Treatise on Ethics (1684). Translated and edited by C. Walton. 1993
ISBN 0-7923-1763-7
134. B.C. Southgate: 'Covetous of Truth'. The Life and Work of Thomas White
(1593-1676). 1993 ISBN 0-7923 - 1926-5
135. G. Santinello, C.W.T. Blackwell and Ph. Weller (eds.): Models of the History of
Philosophy. Vol. 1: From its Origins in the Renaissance to the 'Historia Philosphica'.
1993 ISBN 0-7923-2200-2
136. M.J. Petry (ed.): Hegel and Newtonianism. 1993 ISBN 0-7923-2202-9
137. OttovonGuericke: The New (so-called Magdeburg) Experiments [Experimenta Nova,
Amsterdam 1672]. Translated and edited by M.G.Foley Ames. 1994
ISBN 0-7923-2399-8
138. R.H. Popkin and G.M. Weiner (eds.): Jewish Christians and Cristian Jews. From the
Renaissance to the Enlightenment. 1994 ISBN 0-7923-2452-8
139. J.E. Force and R.H. Popkin (eds.): The Books of Nature and Scripture. Recent Essays
on Natural Philosophy, Theology, and Biblical Criticism in the Netherlands of
Spinoza's Time and the British Isles of Newton's Time. 1994 ISBN 0-7923-2467-6
140. P. Rattansi and A. Clericuzio (eds.): Alchemy and Chemistry in the 16th and 17th
Centuries. 1994 ISBN 0-7923-2573-7
141. S. Jayne: Plato in Renaissance England. 1995 ISBN 0-7923-3060-9
142. A.P. Coudert: Leibniz and the Kabbalah. 1995 ISBN 0-7923-3114-1
143. M.H. Hoffheimer: Eduard Gans and the Hegelian Philosophy of Law. 1995
ISBN 0-7923-3114-1
144. J.R.M. Neto: The Christianization of Pyrrhonism. Scepticism and Faith in Pascal,
Kierkegaard, and Shestov. 1995 ISBN 0-7923-3381-0
145. R.H. Popkin (ed.): Scepticism in the History of Philosophy. A Pan-American
Dialogue. 1996 ISBN 0-7923-3769-7
ARCHIVES INTERNATIONALES D'HISTOIRE DES IDt~ES
146. M. de Baar, M. L6wensteyn, M. Monteiro and A.A. Sneller (eds.): Choosing the
Better Part. Anna Maria van Schurman (1607-1678). 1996 ISBN 0-7923-3799-9
147. M. Degenaar: Molyneux's Problem. Three Centuries of Discussion on the Perception
of Forms. 1996 ISBN 0-7923-3934-7