Thomas Aquinas On Essence, Form, Matter, and Individuation
Thomas Aquinas On Essence, Form, Matter, and Individuation
Individuation
14. In composed substances there are form and matter, for example, in man
soul and body.
15. But we cannot say that either one of them alone may be said to be the
essence. That matter alone is not the essence of a real thing is clear, since
through its essence a real thing is knowable and assigned to a species or to
a genus. But matter alone is neither a principle of knowledge, nor is it that
by which something is assigned to a genus or to a species; rather a thing is
so assigned by reason of its being something actual.
16. Neither can the form alone of a composed substance be said to be its
essence, although some try to assert this. For it is evident from what has
been said that essence is what is signified by the definition of a real thing.
And the definition of natural substances contains not only form, but matter
as well; otherwise natural definitions and mathematical ones would not
differ.
17. Neither can it be said that matter is placed in the definition of a natural
substance as something added to its essence or as something outside its
essence, because this mode of definition is proper to accidents, which do
not have a perfect essence. This is why accidents must include in their
definition a subject which is outside their genus. It is clear therefore that
essence includes matter and form.
18. Further, neither can it be said that essence signifies some relation
between matter and form or something added to them, because this would
of necessity be an accident or something extraneous to the real thing, and
the real thing would not be known through it. And these are traits of
essence. For through the form, which is the actuality of matter, matter
becomes something actual and something individual. Whence what
supervenes does not confer on matter actual existence simply, but such an
actual existence; as accidents in fact do. Whiteness, for example, makes
something actually white. Whence the acquisition of such a form is not
1
called generation simply, but generation in a certain respect. It remains,
therefore, that the word “essence” in composed substances signifies that
which is composed of matter and form.
20. Reason, too, is in accord with this, because the existence of a composed
substance is not the existence of the form alone nor of the matter alone,
but of the composite itself; and essence is that according to which a real
thing is said to be. Whence it is necessary that the essence, whereby a real
thing is denominated a being, be neither the form alone nor the matter
alone, but both, although the form alone in its own way is the cause of such
existence. …
22. But matter is the principle of individuation. From this it might perhaps
appear to follow that an essence which includes in itself matter along with
form is only particular and not universal. And from this it would follow that
universals would not have a definition, if essence is that which is signified
by a definition.
24. It is clear, therefore, that the essence of man and the essence of Socrates
do not differ, except as the non-designated from the designated. …
2
from Summa Theologiae I.3.3, Reply (~1274 AD)
translated by Brian J. Shanley (2006)
God is identical with his essence or nature. In order to grasp this, we must
understand that, among things composed of matter and form, the nature
or essence must be different from the individual subject. This is because the
essence or nature comprises only those things that are included in the
definition of the species. For example, humanity encompasses everything
that belongs to the definition of human being; for through these a human
being is a human being, and that is what ‘humanity’ signifies—that, namely,
by which a human being is a human being. But individuated matter, along
with all the accidents individuating it, is not included in the definition of the
species, since the definition of humanity does not encompass this particular
flesh, these particular bones, white, black, or anything like this. Hence this
flesh and these bones, along with the accidental features that demarcate
this matter, are not included in humanity. Yet they are included in any
individual human. Thus an individual human contains something that
humanity does not contain. And for this reason a human being is not entirely
identical with humanity, but rather humanity is signified as the formal part
of the human being, since the defining principle functions as the form with
respect to the individuating matter. Accordingly, in the case of those things
not composed of matter and form, whose individuation is not through
individual matter (that is, through this matter), but rather the very forms are
individuated through themselves, the forms themselves must be subsisting
subjects. Hence there is no difference in them between subsisting subject
and nature. And thus, since God is not composed of matter and form, as
shown above, it is necessary that God be his divinity, his life, and whatever
else is predicated of God in this way.
3
Duns Scotus on Universals
This question can be treated first by arguing against the position of Plato,
who, according to Aristotle, posited Ideas on account of the formal entity of
things..., and on account of scientific knowledge, since it is only about
necessary items while singulars are corruptible …
If this view proposes that an idea is some substance apart from motion and
from accidental accidents, which has nothing in itself except the separated
specific nature complete to the extent that it can be complete, and which
perhaps has in itself attributes of the species (otherwise nothing would be
known about it), this view cannot be validly disproved …
And neither does Aristotle unqualifiedly disprove it. Rather … in book VII he
argues not its impossibility but its lack of necessity. For here he argues
against Ideas as follows: Nothing which is not obvious is to be posited by
philosophers without necessity. There is no necessity in the reasons for
positing Ideas; therefore, they should simply not be posited. …
But if someone further proposes that this idea is formally universal in such
a way that it is predicated as identical with this corruptible item by a
predication which says ‘this is this’, immediately a contradiction arises,
because numerically the same item is the quiddity [i.e., essence, or nature]
of many different items and yet is outside them (for otherwise it would not
be incorruptible). …1
1
Scotus is notoriously painful to read. So, I’ll interpret for you. All he’s said so far is this: Plato
believed that things like ‘humanity’, ‘horseness’, ‘circularity’, and ‘redness’ were REAL things,
existing on their own in the realm of Ideal Forms. Aristotle didn’t agree. But, he wasn’t really able
to disprove it. He just said that we don’t NEED to posit the existence of such weird entities in order
to explain reality. Still, maybe there’s KIND OF a proof: For instance, we say that Socrates IS
human. It seems like we’re saying that ‘Socrates = human’. Yet, Socrates is ‘corruptible’ (he can
die), while ‘human’ (or human-ness) is not. It always exists. But, ‘Socrates = human’ and ‘human
= incorruptible universal’ yields the conclusion that ‘Socrates = incorruptible universal’, which is
absurd. So, maybe ‘humanity’ isn’t really some weird incorruptible universal thing after all.
4
We find here two opposed opinions:
The first is that the universal is in things. There are three arguments for this:
The first of these is that the universal is that which is naturally suited to be
said of many. But a thing naturally suited to be said of many is so of itself. …
Against this view there are three ways of arguing [the third is omitted here].
2
There are two main views about universals. View #1 (Realism): There really DO exist things like
‘human-ness’, ‘horseness’, and so on—i.e., single things that are somehow in many things (if
humanity is a thing, it is a thing that is in you AND in me). Philosophers call these things
‘universals’. In favor of their existence: You can’t say that someone has some attribute (e.g., human-
ness) if that attribute doesn’t exist. Furthermore, we clearly understand universals independently
of individuals. For instance, ‘human’ is intelligible without reference to any specific human. So, it
seems to exist independently, or prior to, any individual humans.
(His comment about “natures” being “limited” by a “grade” is referring to something he argues for
elsewhere. Namely: In each individual person, your common nature (i.e., ‘humanness’)—which is
a nature that many different people have—is constricted into being the humanness of THIS
particular individual (i.e., YOU, and no one else). More on that later.)
5
This reasoning is bolstered because even this nature as prior to its limiting
grade, if it were understood, would be correctly attributed to only one item.
For this concept is not correctly attributed to another singular, but rather
there is another concept of another nature which is in the other [singular].
The other opinion is that the universal is only in the intellect. In support of
this: the authority of the Commentator [Averroës] in De Anima I: The
intellect makes the universality in things, otherwise the agent intellect would
not seem to be necessary. … Also Boethius, speaking about unity and ‘one’:
“Everything which is is one in number.” …
Against this opinion: The object naturally precedes the act. Therefore, the
universal naturally precedes the ideation when it is ideated. But it is actually
in the intellect only by an ideation. This is bolstered by the fact that if the
object, as object and as prior to the ideation, were not universal, it could not
be related by the intellect to the many items outside the mind.
To these points it can be said that although the object is prior by nature to
the act, still this need not be in the object necessarily, especially when it is a
matter not of the mode of the known but of a mode under which it is known,
and especially if the object exists only at the same time as the act, as
Avicenna claims of the universal.
But, contrary to this, it would follow that if no one were thinking there would
not be an actual universal, and thus scientific knowledge as a competence
would not be of an actually universal object. …4
3
Against realism: (1) How in the heck can a single thing be in many places at once? (2) The
realist seems to be saying that every human being shares one and the same nature. But surely
each individual has a nature, or essence, that is distinct from everyone else’s. For, how in the
heck could it be the case that MY nature also YOUR nature? (3) Also, if Socrates=man, and
man=universal, then Socrates=universal, which is false (see note 1, above).
4
View #2 (Nominalism): Universals don’t really exist “out there” in the world. Rather, they’re just
in the mind. Against nominalism: It seems like things are human, or red, or round, etc., BEFORE
any mental act of thinking about them as such. Nominalism seems to entail that, if no one had
ever thought about, e.g., roundness, then nothing in the world would be round (which is absurd).
6
from Ordinatio, Book 2, Distinction 3, Question 6 (~1304 AD)
translated by Martin M. Tweedale (2006)
The reality of the individual is similar to the specific reality in this respect: it
is a sort of act that determines the reality of the species, which is a sort of
possible and potential item. …
This is shown by the fact that when we apprehend any quidditative entity
(speaking now of limited quidditative entity), we find it is common to many
and it does not reject being said of many items each of which is it. …
Thirdly, when we relate the specific difference to what is on the same level
as it, i.e. to another specific difference, we find that … the ultimate specific
difference is primarily diverse from another … In this regard I say that the
individual difference resembles the specific difference of the ultimate sort,
because every individual entity is primarily diverse from any other. …5
5
You and I are different individuals. But, how? It’s not our NATURES that differ, for I have a
human nature and so do you. There must exist some THING that I have, which you do not have,
and vice versa. Whatever it is, it must be sort of LIKE a species (e.g., humanity). For, having
7
And if you ask me what is this individual entity from which we get the
individual—is it matter or form or a composite?
‘humanity’ makes you be a KIND of thing distinct from any other (e.g., it excludes the possibility
of your being a horse). Similarly, having the individuating thing in question (he hasn’t said what
it is yet) is just whatever it is that makes you be YOU and not any other individual. Somehow, it
constricts your human-ness (an attribute that many can have) into THIS PARTICULAR HUMAN
(an attribute which no one but you can have).
6
Objection: Scotus, what in the heck are you talking about? What is this “thing” that makes me
be ME, and not someone else? Answer: Well, it can’t be form, or matter, or a composite of the
two. (Aquinas thought it was matter. He said, I have THIS matter, and you have THAT matter, so
that’s how we’re different. But, that can’t be right, for the same question still remains—it’s just
that now it’s about matter instead of humans—namely: What makes this matter be THIS matter,
and what makes that matter be THAT matter?) So, it must be the case that, just as I have the
species-nature, humanity, which makes me be this KIND of thing, I must also have an
individual-nature (e.g., ‘John Scotus-ness’), which makes be this PARTICULAR thing.
A further complication: There are not really TWO entities here, however (humanity and Scotus-
ness). Scotus says they are only “formally distinct” and not REALLY distinct. Long story short,
Scotus-ness JUST IS humanity, “restricted” or contracted into Scotus’s individual humanity.
(Note: The individuating entity Scotus is arguing for the existence of has come to be known as a
‘haecceity’, which translates as ‘this-ness’. So, for example, my nature or ‘quiddity’—which
translates as your ‘what-ness’—is ‘human-ness’. A human being is WHAT I am. My haecceity is
‘Chad-ness’. I am THIS particular human: Chad).
8
William of Ockham on Universals
As for the identity and distinction of God from creature, it must be asked
whether there is something univocal common to God and creature and
essentially predicable of both. But because this question, along with much
of what has already been said and is about to be said in the following
questions, depends on a knowledge of univocal and universal nature,
therefore in order to clarify what has been and will be said I will first ask
some questions about universal and univocal nature.
Scotus’s Theory7
On this question there is one theory that says every univocal universal is a
certain thing existing outside the soul, really in each singular and belonging
to the essence of each singular, really distinct from each singular and from
any other universal, in such a way that the universal ‘man’ is truly one thing
outside the soul, existing really in each man, and is really distinguished from
each man and from the universal animal and from the universal substance.
So too for all genera and species …
7 Ockham says some people attributed this theory to Scotus. But in fact the view described here is
not Scotus’s, but rather Walter Burley’s.
9
So according to this theory, however many universals are predicable … there
are that many really distinct things in that singular, each of which is really
distinguished from the other and from the singular. All those things—not
multiplied in themselves in any way, no matter how much their singulars are
multiplied—are in each individual of the same species. …
10
from Summa Logicae, Part I, translated by Michael Loux (1974)
First, it should be noted that the term “particular” has two senses. In the first
sense a particular is that which is one and not many. Those who hold that a
universal is a certain quality residing in the mind which is predicable of many
… must grant that, in this sense of the word, every universal is a particular.
Just as a word, even if convention makes it common, is a particular, the
intention of the soul signifying many is numerically one thing a particular;
for although it signifies many things it is nonetheless one thing and not
many.
In another sense of the word we use “particular” to mean that which is one
and not many and which cannot function as a sign of many. Taking
“particular” in this sense no universal is a particular, since every universal is
capable of signifying many and of being predicated of many. Thus, if we
take the term “universal” to mean that which is not one in number, as many
do, then, I want to say that nothing is a universal. One could, of course,
abuse the expression and say that a population constitutes a single universal
because it is not one but many. But that would be puerile.
Therefore, it ought to be said that every universal is one particular thing and
that it is not a universal except in its signification, in its signifying many
things. This is what Avicenna means to say in his commentary on the fifth
book of the Metaphysics. He says, “One form in the intellect is related to
many things, and in this respect it is a universal; for it is an intention of the
intellect which has an invariant relationship to anything you choose.” He
then continues, “Although this form is a universal in its relationship to
individuals, it is a particular in its relationship to the particular soul in which
it resides; for it is just one form among many in the intellect.” He means to
say that a universal is an intention of a particular soul. Insofar as it can be
predicated of many things not for itself but for these many, it is said to be a
universal; but insofar as it is a particular form actually existing in the intellect,
it is said to be a particular. Thus “particular” is predicated of a universal in
the first sense but not in the second. … [T]he intention of the soul is said to
be a universal because it is a sign predicable of many things, but it is said to
be a particular because it is one thing and not many. …
11
Chapter 15: That the universal is not a thing outside the mind
But it is not enough just to state one’s position; one must defend it by
philosophical arguments. …
12
and, consequently, He would destroy the universal which is in that thing and
in others of the same essence. Consequently, other things of the same
essence would not remain, for they could not continue to exist without the
universal which constitutes a part of them.
13
From these remarks it is clear that the universal is an intention of the soul
capable of being predicated of many. The claim can be corroborated by
argument. For every one agrees that a universal is something predicable of
many, but only an intention of the soul or a conventional sign is predicated.
No substance is ever predicated of anything. Therefore, only an intention of
the soul or a conventional sign is a universal …That substance is not capable
of functioning as predicate is clear; for if it were, it would follow that a
proposition would be composed of particular substances; and,
consequently, the subject would be in Rome and the predicate in England
which is absurd.
It may be clear to many that a universal is not a substance outside the mind
which exists in, but is distinct from, particulars. Nevertheless, some want to
claim that the universal is, in some way, outside the soul and in particulars;
and while they do not want to say that a universal is really distinct from
particulars, they say that it is formally distinct from particulars. Thus, they
say that in Socrates there is human nature which is contracted to Socrates
by an individual difference which is not really, but only formally, distinct
from that nature. Thus, while there are not two things, one is not formally
the other.
First, in creatures there can never be any distinction outside the mind unless
there are distinct things; if, therefore, there is any distinction between the
nature and the difference, it is necessary that they really be distinct things. I
prove my premise by the following syllogism: the nature is not formally
distinct from itself; this individual difference [i.e., haecceity] is formally
distinct from this nature; therefore, this individual difference is not this
nature. …
14
Again, if a common nature were the same thing as an individual difference,
there would be as many common natures as there are individual differences;
and, consequently, none of those natures would be common, but each
would be peculiar to the difference with which it is identical.
Therefore, one should grant that in created things there is no such thing as
a formal distinction. All things which are distinct in creatures are really
distinct and, therefore, different things. In regard to creatures modes of
argument like the following ought never be denied: this is A; this is B;
therefore, B is A; and this is not A; this is B; therefore, B is not A. Likewise,
one ought never deny that, as regards creatures, there are distinct things
where contradictory notions hold. …
15
from Ordinatio, Distinction 2, Question 8
translated by Philotheus Boehner (1955)
… I maintain that a universal is not something real that exists in a subject [of
inherence], either inside or outside the mind, but that it has being only as a
thought-object in the mind. It is a kind of mental picture which as a thought-
object has a being similar to that which the thing outside the mind has in
its real existence. What I mean is this: The intellect, seeing a thing outside
the mind, forms in the mind a picture resembling it, in such a way that if the
mind had the power to produce as it has the power to picture, it would
produce by this act a real outside thing which would be only numerically
distinct from the former real thing. The case would be similar, analogously
speaking, to the activity of an artist. For just as the artist who sees a house
or building outside the mind first pictures in the mind a similar house and
later produces a similar house in reality which is only numerically distinct
from the first, so in our case the picture in the mind that we get from seeing
something outside would act as a pattern. For just as the imagined house
would be a pattern for the architect, if he who imagines it had the power to
produce it in reality, so likewise the other picture would be a pattern for him
who forms it. And this can be called a universal, because it is a pattern and
relates indifferently to all the singular things outside the mind. Because of
the similarity between its being as a thought-object and the being of like
things outside the mind, it can stand for such things. And in this way a
universal is not the result of generation, but of abstraction, which is only a
kind of mental picturing. …
[F]ictions have being in the mind, but they do not exist independently,
because in that case they would be real things and so a chimera and a goat-
stag and so on would be real things. So some things exist only as thought-
objects.
16
Again, works of art do not seem to inhere in the mind of the craftsman as
independent subjects any more than the creatures did in the divine mind
before creation. …
I maintain, then, that somebody wishing to hold this opinion may assume
that the intellect apprehending a singular thing performs within itself a
cognition of this singular only. This cognition is called a state of mind, and
it is capable of standing for this singular thing by its very nature. Hence, just
as the spoken word ‘Socrates’ stands by convention for the thing it signifies,
so that one who hears this utterance, ‘Socrates is running’, does not
conceive that this word, ‘Socrates’, which he hears, is running, but rather
that the thing signified by this word is running; so likewise one who knew
or understood that something was affirmatively predicated of this cognition
of a singular thing would not think that the cognition was such and such,
but would conceive that the thing to which the cognition refers is such and
such. Hence, just as the spoken word stands by convention for a thing, so
the act of intellect, by its very nature, and without any convention, stands
for the thing to which it refers.
Beside this intellectual grasp of a singular thing the intellect also forms other
acts which do not refer more to one thing than to another. For instance, just
17
as the spoken word ‘man’ does not signify Socrates more than Plato, and
hence does not stand more for Socrates than Plato, so it would be with an
act of intellect which does not relate to Socrates any more than to Plato or
any other man …; and so with other notions.
To sum up: The mind’s own intellectual acts are called states of mind. By
their nature they stand for the actual things outside the mind or for other
things in the mind, just as the spoken words stand for them by convention.
…
18