Introductory Geometry and Arithmetic
Introductory Geometry and Arithmetic
– Aristotle
i
C
B
And a slightly more advanced example. If you
X take any triangle ABC and drop perpendiculars
C from each vertex to its opposite side, these three
A perpendiculars all meet at one point, X ...
C
the midpoint of the opposite side, these three
lines all meet at one point, Y ...
A
ii
There are many more surprises than these in geometry, but to get into
them would take us out of this introduction, and into the science itself.
iii
(3) GEOMETRY IS FULL OF FUNDAMENTALS. Over the en-
trance to Plato’s Academy there hung a sign which read Let no one igno-
rant of mathematics enter here. Why did a school of philosophy desig-
nate mathematics as a prerequisite for admission? Plato saw that many
universal principles are most readily accessible to us through mathematics.
The geometrical science of proportion, for example, shows in a con-
crete way how some things can be known by proportions or analogies.
We can come to know an unknown quantity x if we see it in proportion
to other terms already known to us, say if x has to 4 the same ratio that
3 has to 2. Knowing 4, 3, and 2, and knowing the relationship between
3 and 2, we can come to know the mysterious x. This is a useful way
of getting at something to which we have no direct access, say if x were
a length we could not measure directly, like the height of an Egyptian
pyramid. There is no way to drop a plumb line from the peak of a pyr-
amid straight down to its base, but three other lengths that we can meas-
ure might form a proportion with the inaccessible height. Philosophers
and scientists, too, must sometimes find ways to investigate things not di-
rectly observable or imaginable, and one tool for this purpose is propor-
tion or analogy, the most fundamental use of which we find in geometry.
Geometry is also fundamental in another way. It is the science
most easily acquired by the human mind with rigor and exactness. In
geometry, one can settle disagreements. One can draw inescapable con-
clusions. This makes geometry an ideal entryway into the whole life of
the mind.
iv
good. There is such a thing as mental exercise, too, which both strength-
ens and exhilarates the mind. Studying geometry is among the best of
mental workouts, simultaneously exercising one’s imagination, memory, and
reason. In the course of a proof, the imagination must follow a line of
reasoning from one part of a diagram to another; it must flip, rotate, and
otherwise manipulate geometrical objects; it must interpret two-dimensional
diagrams of three-dimensional things; it must picture how the other parts
of a diagram are affected if one part is moved or changed. Memory also
gets a workout, since geometry is cumulative. Each conclusion must be
understood, and then used to establish later results, which in turn help to
establish still more advanced results. And geometry obviously exercises
reason. There is no reasoning more exact than a mathematical argument.
Geometrical objects are perfect subject matter for forming definitions and
proofs, proposing difficulties and finding resolutions, drawing distinctions,
finding examples … in short, for doing all the best things that human
reason can do. Thus geometry builds people’s confidence that reason can
find satisfying answers to serious questions.
v
ly), emphasizing instead various formulas, exercises, and problem-solving
techniques.
This course is written for anyone motivated to study geometry for
the wonder and beauty of it, for readers disposed to contemplate theorems
as if they were works of art. And yet it begins at the very beginning.
To master it, you need no prior training in mathematics. In consequence,
this course represents a unique introduction to geometry. Readers interest-
ed in learning mathematics will find it better suited to their needs than
study manuals or high school geometry books because of its scope, its pu-
rity, and its rigor.
THE SCOPE OF THIS COURSE by far surpasses that of the typi-
cal introduction. This course covers most of the content of the thirteen
books of Euclid’s Elements, whereas typical introductions do not cover
material much beyond the first three or four books of Euclid. Written
most often for the high school level, they do not go deep enough into ge-
ometry to reach the most beautiful and exciting material accessible to rec-
reational mathematicians. Yet this course is not longer than the average
high school textbook, but actually shorter, since it does not multiply exer-
cises.
THE PURITY OF THIS COURSE should be refreshing to anyone
who loves geometry. Other introductions to the science, written so read-
ers can “get the right answer,” employ algebra, trigonometry, number
lines, a system of coordinate axes, and a host of other devices. Such de-
vices and techniques, though useful (elsewhere) and important to study
(elsewhere), have no place in a formal introduction to geometry intended
for those who wish to begin at the beginning and understand the reasons
for things. The impression is given that there is no geometry without
vi
these extras. The truth is that geometrical things can be known geometri-
cally, without recourse to algebra or trigonometry.
The proof of the Pythagorean Theorem given in this book, for ex-
ample, makes no use of algebraic operations. The theorem is demonstra-
ble on purely geometrical grounds. The proof given for this theorem in
many introductory books is an algebraic one that quickly leaves behind
the diagram altogether. The result is a very abstract and unmemorable
proof, the steps of which are not explicitly correlated with the right trian-
gle and the squares that the geometrical theorem is about. The purpose
of teaching the Pythagorean Theorem algebraically is to encourage profi-
ciency in applying it to problems. This denies students any real under-
standing of the theorem, however, and reinforces the idea that geometry
has no intrinsic worth or beauty.
RIGOR. Many introductory books use theorems they do not prove,
such as the theorem that if a cone and a cylinder stand on the same cir-
cle and have the same height, the volume of the cone is one third that of
the cylinder. Current high school textbooks including this theorem or a
formula based on it do not attempt even a sketchy proof for it. In this
course a complete proof is given for this theorem and for every other the-
orem covered. Once again, the implicit message of the textbook is that
understanding the theorem is not important, but only the use of a formula
which one should be willing to take on faith. This presumes an audience
uninterested in the reasons for things, or incapable of understanding them.
Like a novel, it is essential to read this book in the order in which
it is written, but unlike a novel, you can stop after any chapter or theo-
rem and come away with something completely understood. But enough
of introductions. On to the adventure of geometry.
vii
SYMBOLS
A = B A is equal to B
A > B A is greater than B
A < B A is less than B
AB ⊥ CD AB is perpendicular to CD
AB ║ CD AB is parallel to CD
60° sixty degrees
∠ABC angle ABC
rABC triangle ABC
rABC ≅ rDEF triangle ABC is congruent to triangle DEF
£AB the square on line AB
£ABCD the square with corners A, B, C, D
AB · CD the rectangle with sides of length AB and length CD
3A three times A
A : B = C : D A has to B the same ratio that C has to D
A : B > C : D A has to B a greater ratio than C has to D
viii
Q.E.F. Short for Quod Erat Faciendum, a Latin expression
meaning “that which was to be done,” and a customary
way of marking the end of a construction or “how to”
theorem.
ix
Chapter One
Triangles
and
Parallelograms
DEFINITIONS
2. A solid stops at its SURFACE (or surfaces); so a surface has length and width, but no
depth.
The top face of a gold brick is a surface, having a length HL, and a width HW.
But it has no depth, since it is only the
W face of the brick; if it had any depth, it
L
would not be the top face of a brick, but
H it would be a brick itself, even if a very
slim one.
3. When a surface comes to an end, it stops at a LINE (or lines); so a line has length, but
no width or depth.
One edge of the brick's top surface, such as HL, is a line, having a certain length.
But it has no width or depth. It has no depth, since it is an edge of a surface, which has
no depth. It has no width, since it is only the edge of the surface; if it had any width, it
would not be only the edge of a surface, but it would be a surface itself, even if a very
narrow one.
Today a finite line is often called a “line segment.” But since infinite lines don’t
come up too frequently, and it is tedious to say “line segment” every time a finite line is
meant, I will call a finite line simply a “line.”
4. When a line comes to an end, it stops at a POINT; so a point has no length, no width,
no depth.
One end of the edge of the brick's top surface, such as H, is a point, having no
length, width, or depth. It has no width or depth, since it is the end of a line, which itself
has no width or depth. It has no length, since it is only the end of a line; if it had any
length, it would not be only the end of the line, but it would itself be a line, even if a very
short one. Although it has no shape or size, a point does have one positive feature: its
location.
2
5. A STRAIGHT LINE is a perfectly uniform line. Every part of it is the same “shape”
as every other part, regardless of length, and different straight lines differ only in length,
location, and orientation. Every other kind of line is called a CURVED LINE.
One imaginative way to express the uniformity of a straight line is with the
following “thought experiment.” If you look at a straight line on end, it will look like a
point; that is, none of the line’s length will be visible. Another way to express the
uniformity of straight lines is like this: it is impossible for both endpoints of one straight
line to coincide with those of another, without the straight lines themselves completely
coinciding.
A straight line is sometimes defined as the shortest distance between two points.
We will see more about the “shortness” of straight lines in Theorem 17. In the
meantime, it is enough to note that the reason a straight line is so short and direct
compared to other lines is because of its uniformity.
NOTE: Since this book is only about straight lines and circles, and no other kinds
of lines, when I say “line” I will mean one of these, and which one I mean will be clear
by context.
D
8. A RECTILINEAL ANGLE is an angle formed by two
different straight lines.
Angle DEF is an example.
E F
3
A
9. When one straight line stands on another in such a way that
the two adjacent angles formed are equal to each other, each
angle is called a RIGHT ANGLE.
1 2 Thus if AB stands on CD making angle 1 equal to angle
C B D 2, then each of these angles is a “right” angle.
A
12. An obtuse angle and an acute angle are called SUPPLEMENTARY when they add
up to two right angles. Two acute angles are called COMPLEMENTARY when they add
up to one right angle.
Angles CBE and EBD are supplementary; angles CBE and EBA are
complementary.
4
D 15. A CIRCLE is a plane figure contained by one curved
E
line whose every point is the same distance from a single
point inside it.
C
Figure ADEBFA is a circle, since it is bounded by
A
B
the one line ADEBFA, and all the points on that line, such
as A,D,E,B,F, are the same distance from C; that is, CA =
F CD = CE = CB = CF.
16. The single point inside a circle which is the same distance from every point along the
curved line bounding the circle is called the circle's CENTER. And the curved line
bounding the circle is called the circle's CIRCUMFERENCE.
C is the center of the circle ADEBF, and ADEBFA is its circumference.
D E 17. Any straight line drawn from the center of a circle and
stopping at the circumference is called a RADIUS of the
A
C
B circle. Thus, by definitions 15 & 16, it is evident that all the
radii of a circle are equal.
The plural of “radius” is “radii.”
F
Any straight line drawn through the center of a circle
and terminated at each end by the circumference is called a DIAMETER of the circle. It
is evident that any diameter of a circle bisects the circle, that is, cuts the circle into two
equal parts.
CD is an example of a radius of circle C, and ACB is an example of a diameter of
circle C.
18. A SEMICIRCLE is the figure contained by a circle’s diameter and the circumference
cut off by it.
The figure contained by ADEB and the straight line AB is an example of a
semicircle.
5
20. Among triangles, an EQUILATERAL TRIANGLE is one with all three sides equal.
An ISOSCELES TRIANGLE is one with only two sides equal. A SCALENE
D F TRIANGLE is one without any equal sides.
B H
ABC is an equilateral triangle, DEF
is an isosceles triangle, GHK is a scalene
A C
triangle.
G K
N Q
R S
21. Among triangles, a RIGHT
TRIANGLE is one containing
a right angle. An OBTUSE
TRIANGLE is one containing M L P
O
T
an obtuse angle. An ACUTE
TRIANGLE is one with all three of its angles acute.
LMN is a right triangle, OPQ is an obtuse triangle, RST is an acute triangle.
In a right triangle, the side opposite the right angle is called the HYPOTENUSE, and the
two sides containing the right angle are called LEGS.
NL is the hypotenuse of triangle LMN; MN and ML are its legs.
22. If two straight lines lie in one plane together, but never meet each other in either
direction however far they are extended, they are
A B
said to be PARALLEL to each other.
C D AB and CD are parallels.
E F
23. Among quadrilaterals, a SQUARE is a quadrilateral
with all four sides equal and all four angles right; a
H G RECTANGLE is a quadrilateral with all four angles right
K L but not all four sides equal; a RHOMBUS is a
N M
quadrilateral with all four sides equal but no right angles.
O P
EFGH is a square, KLMN is a rectangle, OPQR
is a rhombus.
R Q A PARALLELOGRAM is any quadrilateral
S T contained by two pairs of parallel straight lines.
Quadrilaterals that are none of the above will be called
V U TRAPEZIA.
X
Y STUV is a parallelogram, even though it has no
right angles and not all of its sides are equal. WXYZ is a
W Z trapezium.
6
24. Two straight lines are INCLINED TOWARD EACH OTHER if, when cut by a third
straight line, the sum of the two interior angles on one side is less than the sum of the two
exterior angles on that same side.
For example, if 1 + 2 is less than 3 + 4, then AB and
3
A
CD are inclined to each other toward the right.
1
B
2 D
C 4
7
GEOMETRICAL POSTULATES
2. Any straight line can be extended continuously in a straight line in either direction
and as far as you please.
3. A circle can be drawn around any point as its center and with a radius of any
given length.
L
For example, around point P we may draw a circle whose radius
shall be any given length, such as PL.
P
Not only are adjacent right angles equal to each other, such as 1
4 and 2, but even those that are not adjacent, such as 1 and 3.
3
1 2
5. Straight lines inclined towards each other eventually meet, when extended far
enough.
A 3
For example, let A and B be two straight lines that cut
1 across another straight line C, making angles 1 & 2
C
to the right of C. If 1 + 2 is less than 3 + 4, then A
and B must eventually meet on the right side of C at
2
B
4
some point.
8
GENERAL PRINCIPLES
1. Things equal to the same thing are also equal to each other.
For example, 36 inches is equal to a yard, but 3 feet is also equal to a yard, so 36 inches
has to be equal to 3 feet.
For example, if Fred and Jack are both exactly five feet tall, and this summer each will
grow the exact same amount, then their heights will still be equal.
3. When equals are subtracted from equals, the remainders are equal.
For example, if two brand new pencils have exactly the same length, and then you
sharpen them down by exactly the same amount, they will still have equal lengths.
4. Things that can be made to coincide with each other are equal.
That is, if two things are such that neither one goes outside of the other even a little bit,
then neither is greater than the other, and so they must be equal. For example, if the
bottom surface of a box fits exactly on the surface of a table, nowhere hanging over the
edge or letting any part of the table's surface show, then the bottom of the box and the
surface of the table have equal areas.
The surface area of a whole lake is greater than the surface area of any part of it; fifty
dollars is greater than any part of fifty dollars, etc.
9
THEOREMS
If someone gives us a straight line AB, how can we make an equilateral triangle on top of
it so that AB is the base of the triangle?
As follows.
Q.E.F.
10
THEOREM 1 Remarks
1. Notice what we have done in this first theorem: we have made a perfectly
equilateral triangle without measuring anything. There is something surprising about
that. And who would have thought that circles are helpful for making triangles?
2. The equilateral triangle is the simplest rectilineal figure, and so it makes sense
that we should begin geometry by making it. It has the fewest number of sides, and they
are all the same.
3. Despite the simplicity of the equilateral triangle, it is a figure rich with surprising
properties, some of which we will discover in this book. Also, it is very useful for other
constructions, as we will see once we get to Theorem 7. We have already accomplished
something significant in making the equilateral triangle, right here in the very first
theorem!
THEOREM 1 Questions
2. Looking at the diagram, find a way to make a rhombus. Prove all four of its sides
are equal. (We have not yet done enough geometry to prove that its angles are not right
angles.)
3. Imagine that your compass became so rusty you can no longer adjust it, so that
you can make circles only of one size. If the unadjustable radius of your compass is not
equal to AB in the diagram, but was something less than AB, can you still use it to make
an equilateral triangle on AB? (Remember that you still have a straight-edge which lets
you extend straight lines as far as you like.)
4. Using a method of construction similar to that for the equilateral triangle, can you
find a way to make an isosceles triangle? What about a scalene triangle?
5. What happens if you make 3 more equilateral triangles, one on each side of
ΔABC ?
11
THE SIDE-ANGLE-SIDE THEOREM
THEOREM 2: If in one triangle a side, the next angle, and the next side, are
respectively equal to a side, the next angle, and the next side in another triangle, then all
the corresponding sides and angles of the two triangles are equal, and they have equal
areas.
[1] Imagine moving rABC so that AB lies on DE; since they are equal, they will
coincide, so that A is on D and B is on E.
B E
[4] So AB, BC, AC coincide with DE, EF, DF. Thus the two triangles have been made
to coincide exactly, and so they are completely identical (Common Notion 4).
Q.E.D.
THEOREM 2 Remarks
1. This theorem is often called the “Side-Angle-Side” Theorem. If a side, the next
angle, and the next side in one triangle are equal to a side, the next angle, and the next
side in another triangle, then the two triangles are identical to each other.
12
B E 2. This “Side-Angle-Side” Theorem is used
throughout geometry, and throughout this book. Since
the areas of the two triangles are equal, and also the
corresponding sides and angles, this theorem is useful
C F
for proving the equality of (1) lines, (2) angles, and
A D
(3) areas.
4. The two triangles in this theorem are not only equal in area, but all their
corresponding sides and angles are equal. Such triangles are said to be congruent to each
other; in fact, any pair of figures which are both the same shape and the same size are
called “congruent”. The symbol for congruency is ≅. The squiggly line over the equal
sign means “similar”, so that the two symbols together mean “equal and similar to”, or
“the same size and the same shape”. So when you read “ΔABC ≅ ΔDEF”, this means
that all the corresponding sides and angles of triangle ABC and triangle DEF are equal,
and the two triangles have the same area.
THEOREM 2 Questions
1. When we are told which initial sides and angles are equal, exactly how do we
decide which of the remaining angles and sides in the two triangles are “corresponding”
sides and angles?
2. What if the two triangles in question are mirror images of each other? Then it is
not possible to slide one over on top of the other. So how would we prove the theorem?
3. What if ∠ABC = ∠DEF, AB = DE, but BC is greater than EF? What can we say
about the two triangles then?
13
THEOREM 3: In an isosceles triangle, the base angles are equal to each other,
and the angles under the base are equal to each other.
[8] ∠EBA = ∠DCA (being corresponding angles in ΔADC & ΔAEB; Step 6)
but ∠EBC = ∠DCB (being corresponding angles in ΔCEB & ΔBDC; Step 7)
so ∠CBA = ∠BCA (the remainders of equals are equal; C.N. 3)
i.e. the angles at the base of ΔABC are equal to each other.
[9] And the angles under the base of ΔABC are also equal, namely ∠DBC & ∠ECB,
being corresponding angles of ΔBDC & Δ CEB (Step 7).
Q.E.D.
14
THEOREM 3 Remarks
1. Notice the plan of attack, or strategy of this theorem. It is to establish first that
the larger overlapping triangles (ADC and AEB) are identical or congruent, and then to
use information gained from that to prove the small overlapping triangles under the base
are identical or congruent (BDC and CEB). Once that is accomplished, we can derive
that the base angles are equal as well as those under the base by using corresponding
angles and by subtracting equals from equals. To understand more elaborate proofs it is
always helpful to figure out the overall strategy used.
THEOREM 3 Questions
A
1. You can prove this theorem in another way by flipping the
triangle ABC over onto itself: since AB = AC, each will fit on top of
the other when we flip the triangle over, and so ∠ACB will coincide
exactly with the place where ∠ABC was. Therefore these two angles
are equal.
B C
A
2. In Theorem 7 we will learn how to bisect any angle. Imagine
that ∠BAC was already bisected for us by the straight line AM. Given
that AB = AC, can you see how to prove once more that ∠ABC =
∠ACB?
B M C
15
THEOREM 4: If two angles in a triangle are equal to each other, then the sides
opposite them are also equal to each other, i.e., the triangle is isosceles.
[1] From AB, the supposedly greater of the two sides, cut off BD
= AC and join CD.
B C
[3] But that is ridiculous, since ΔDBC is a part of ΔACB, and the part is always less than
the whole (Common Notion 5).
[4] Since something impossible follows from the assumption that AB > AC, therefore
the assumption that AB > AC is itself impossible. So AB is not greater than AC.
[5] By the same reasoning we can show that AC is not greater than AB.
[6] Since AB and AC are such that neither is greater than the other, therefore AB = AC
after all.
Q.E.D.
THEOREM 4 Remarks
1. By Theorem 3, an equilateral triangle has all three of its angles equal. Does it
follow from Theorem 4 that, since an equilateral triangle has any two of its angles equal
to each other, it must therefore be an isosceles triangle? An equilateral triangle is
“isosceles” in the sense that it has at least two of its sides equal, but not in the more
restrictive sense that it has only two of its sides equal. We might restate Theorem 4 by
saying “If a triangle has two angles equal, then it has at least two sides equal, namely
those opposite the equal angles.”
16
2. Theorem 4 is the “converse” of Theorem 3. The “converse” of any statement is
the statement formed by switching its subject and predicate; for example the converse of
the statement
Every bachelor is a man who never married
is the statement that
Every man who never married is a bachelor.
Not all converses of true statements are themselves true. For example,
Every triangle is a figure = TRUE
Every figure is a triangle = FALSE.
That is why we must often prove the converse of a true statement. Still, sometimes this is
unnecessary. Looking back at Theorem 2, we learned that triangles having certain
corresponding parts equal will have all corresponding parts equal. The converse is also
true, but needs no proof, namely that if two triangles have all corresponding parts equal,
then they will also have some of their parts equal.
So Theorem 4 proves the converse of Theorem 3, since this is what each proves:
Theorem 3: An isosceles triangle is a triangle with two equal base angles.
Theorem 4: A triangle with two equal base angles is an isosceles triangle.
3. The point of proving the converse of a theorem (whenever its converse is true) is
to show that the property we showed belongs to some figure belongs only to that kind of
figure. In Theorem 3 we learned that ALL isosceles triangles have equal base angles –
but is having equal base angles unique to isosceles triangles (namely those with at least
two equal sides), or can scalene triangles have that property too? Well, in Theorem 4 we
learn that ONLY isosceles triangles have equal base angles. As soon as the base angles
are equal, the sides opposite them must also be equal.
THEOREM 4 Question
Use Theorem 4 to prove that any triangle with 3 equal angles is an equilateral triangle.
17
THEOREM 5: Triangles are rigid.
Is that possible? No! To see the impossibility, try to suppose it is possible ...
[4] Now, by Step 3 we can substitute (∠3 + ∠4) in place of ∠2 anywhere we please,
since they are equal. So in Step 2 let's replace ∠2 with (∠3 + ∠4), which gives us
∠1 + (∠3 + ∠4) = ∠3
[6] Therefore the original supposition from which this absurdity follows is also
impossible, namely that the triangle ABM might be flexible, and we could keep all its
sides the same length but change its angles. So triangles are rigid.
Q.E.D.
18
THEOREM 5 Remarks
1. The kind of proof we just used for Theorem 5, like the proof for Theorem 4
before it, is called a “reduction to the absurd” (reductio ad absurdum or reductio ad
impossibile in Latin). It is also called “indirect proof.”
The strategy of such a proof is to assume the opposite of what we wish to prove,
show that something impossible would necessarily follow from such an assumption, and
conclude that therefore the original assumption which gave rise to the impossibility is
itself impossible. And so the thing we wish to prove is necessarily true – since its
opposite turned out impossible.
Theorem 4 was a perfect example of such a line of reasoning. We wanted to
show that any triangle with two equal angles is isosceles. Assuming the opposite, namely
that we could have a triangle with equal angles whose opposite sides were not equal, it
would follow that we could cut out a part of that triangle which is equal to the whole
triangle. But that’s impossible. So we also had to condemn the initial assumption. That
is, the sides opposite equal angles in a triangle must be equal, lest an absurdity follow.
2. Another way to state Theorem 5 is this: given three straight lines making up a
triangle, it is impossible to take them apart and put them together again and get a different
triangle. Try it.
C D
3. It is possible to make two triangles on top of
AB which have identical sides but do not coincide,
such as rABC and rABD. Yet they remain
congruent, having identical sides and angles, and it is
not AD that AC is equal to, but BD. The triangles are
mirror images of each other. Therefore we do not get
A B rADB by “tilting” rACB, but by flipping it over.
4. Theorem 5 has some applications in building things. If you look at most bridges
and frames for roofs, you find triangular braces everywhere – that's because triangles add
rigidity. If we use only rectangles, things can fold over, tilt, collapse!
19
THEOREM 5 Questions
P
1. What if we supposed triangle ANB fell
inside the original triangle AMB? Could we still
M prove the theorem then? Draw yourself a diagram:
1
join MN as before, extend AM to any point P and
2
extend AN until it meets MB at a point R. You will
want to use the part of Theorem 3 about angles
R
3 under the base of an isosceles triangle, since you are
N
4 given that AM = AN (making AMN isosceles) and
that BN = BM (making BMN isosceles, too). Begin
A B by writing out the angles which must therefore be
equal, and see if you can find something impossible.
If so, you will have proved that neither is it possible to squish triangle AMB down to a
smaller triangle ANB while keeping all the sides the same length.
M
2. How would the proof go if we assume N fell on MA or on
N MB?
A B
3. Five sticks are nailed together to make a pentagon, with only one nail at each
corner. How many cross braces are needed to make the figure rigid? In how many
different ways can this be done?
20
THE SIDE-SIDE-SIDE THEOREM
[2] Since triangles are rigid (Thm. 5), A and B must coincide.
[3] Since points A & B must coincide, therefore CA coincides with CB, and DA
coincides with DB.
[5] Since things which coincide are equal, therefore these two triangles have all their
corresponding angles equal, and are also equal in area.
Q.E.D.
THEOREM 6 Remarks
2. As with Theorem 2, it does not matter if the two triangles are mirror images of
each other – we have only to flip one of them over, and then the proof can proceed as it
does.
21
THEOREM 6 Question
Using this Theorem, prove that the two equilateral triangles made on the same straight
line (one above it and the other below it) are equal to each other.
A F C
[8] So the 3 sides of ΔFBD are equal to the 3 sides of ΔFBE, and so their corresponding
angles are equal (Side-Side-Side, Thm. 6).
Q.E.F.
22
THEOREM 7 Remarks
1. It follows from this Theorem that there is no smallest rectilineal angle, since no
matter how small it is, we can always use this theorem to bisect it and get two smaller
angles.
2. The way to trisect any random angle, that is, cut it into 3 equal angles, is not so
easy; in fact it is impossible if we limit ourselves to using circles and straight lines in a
plane. Some angles can be trisected without difficulty, but others, such as the angle of an
equilateral triangle, require more sophisticated tools than circles and straight lines.
3. Since we are cutting angles in half, we might as well mention here the mechanical
tool for doing this, the protractor, and the unit it uses, the degree.
Suppose you have a circle whose circumference has been divided into 360 equal
parts for you. Each part is one 360th of the way around a circle, and it is called a degree.
Degrees, accordingly, can be used to measure either the length of an arc around the circle,
or the angle drawn from the center standing on that arc.
A
If we go along the circumference of a circle from A
R
through R to B, and we have gone one quarter of the way around,
then we have gone through 90 of the 360 equal parts of the
D
C
B circumference, or 90°. We can say that the arc ARB is an arc of
90°, or we can say that the angle ACB is an angle of 90°.
To go halfway around the circle from B to D is to go 180°
(since that is half of 360°), and that is to open up an angle into a
straight line DCB. Since ∠ACB is 90°, ∠ACD must also be 90° (since together they
make 180°). Since they are adjacent equal angles and DCB is a straight line, each of
them is right. So a right angle is 90 degrees. Any angle more than that is obtuse, and
any angle less than that is acute.
A protractor is a simple hand tool used for measuring angles – it is basically a
circle (or semicircle) with degrees marked off along its circumference and numbered. In
geometry, a protractor can be handy for making accurate diagrams, even though we don't
need it to prove anything.
THEOREM 7 Questions
1. Will the construction and proof for Theorem 7 still work if we put the equilateral
triangle on top of DE?
2. Draw any triangle and, using the method in Theorem 7, bisect its three angles as
carefully as you can. What do you notice about the three bisectors?
23
3. Do you need to draw the sides of the equilateral triangle in order to draw the
bisector in Theorem 7? No. That is only for the sake of the proof. Then what is the
fewest number of steps needed in order to bisect an angle?
4. If 90° is a right angle, and 180° is two right angles, then give the complementary
and supplementary angle for each of the following angles: 30°, 45°, 37.5°, 27.368°.
[6] So by the Side-Angle-Side Theorem (Thm 2), the other corresponding sides and
angles of ΔACD and ΔBCD are also equal.
Q.E.F.
24
THEOREM 8 Remarks
1. From Theorem 8 it follows that there is no smallest straight line, since no matter
how small it is we can use this Theorem to bisect it and get two smaller lines.
3. Unlike the problem of cutting an angle into 3 equal parts, the problem of cutting a
straight line into 3 equal parts is not very difficult. In fact, later in this book, we will find
a way to cut any straight line into any number of equal parts. Before we get there, see
whether you can come up with a way to do it yourself.
THEOREM 8 Questions
1. Looking back to the diagram for Theorem 1, can you see the fewest steps needed
in order to bisect a straight line?
2. Draw any triangle you like and bisect the three sides of it. Join each vertex of the
triangle to the midpoint of the opposite side. What do you notice about the three straight
lines you have drawn?
THEOREM 9: How to draw a line at right angles to any straight line from any
point on it.
25
[3] Join PR.
[4] PD = PC (Step 1)
[7] So, by the Side-Side-Side Theorem (Thm. 6), all of the corresponding angles of
ΔRPC and ΔRPD must be equal.
[9] So ∠RPC and ∠RPD are adjacent angles, formed by one line RP standing on
another, AB, and they are equal to each other. Therefore they are right angles (Def. 9).
[10] Thus a straight line, PR, has been set up at right angles to the given line AB and
from the point P on it.
Q.E.F.
THEOREM 9 Remarks
1. Since we can now draw right angles, we can also draw right triangles. In fact, we
have drawn two right triangles in the construction for this Theorem, namely ΔRPC and
ΔRPD.
2. In order to avoid having to go through all the steps in this construction every time
a right angle is needed, carpenters and engineers use a tool called a carpenter's "square",
which is a tool shaped like a big right angle or letter "L". You can also use a protractor to
mark off angles of 90°. Of course, all such tools have to be constructed by employing
geometrical constructions such as the one we have given here.
26
THEOREM 9 Questions
2. What is the fewest number of steps needed to draw a line from a point P at right
angles to a line through P?
C D
B
THEOREM 10: How to drop a perpendicular line to any straight line from any
point above it.
Now suppose you have a straight line AB, and I pick a random point P above it. How
can you drop a line from P which is perpendicular to AB? Easy.
27
[6] PG = PE (being radii of circle P)
[7] HG = HE (since we bisected GE at H)
[8] PH is common to ΔPHG and ΔPHE.
[9] So, by the Side-Side-Side Theorem (Thm. 6), all the corresponding angles of ΔPHG
and ΔPHE are equal.
[10] ∠PHG = ∠PHE (being corresponding angles of ΔPHG and ΔPHE)
[11] But these two equal angles, ∠PHG and ∠PHE, are adjacent angles formed by one
line, PH, standing on another, AB, and so they are right angles (Def. 9).
[12] Hence PH has been drawn perpendicular to AB (Def. 10).
Q.E.F.
THEOREM 10 Remarks
THEOREM 10 Question
Do we need to draw PG and PE in order to draw PH? No; they were drawn for the sake
of the proof that PH is perpendicular. So what is the fewest number of steps actually
needed to draw a perpendicular from a point to a straight line?
28
THEOREM 11: When one straight line stands on another one, the adjacent
angles add up to two right angles.
P
Obviously if PB stands upon CD at right angles, then
∠PBC + ∠PBD equals two right angles. Now what if
A
AB stands upon CD, but not at right angles to it? Will it
still be true that ∠ABC + ∠ABD = 2 rights? Yes.
2
To see it,
1 3
C D
B [1] Draw BP at right angles to CD (Thm. 9).
Q.E.D.
THEOREM 11 Remarks
1. Theorems 9 & 10 began the study of right angles; now we are investigating “two
right angles.”
2. This Theorem 11 is rather obvious even without a proof. If CBD is a straight line,
then BD must go through half of one full rotation to get to BC, which is 180°. It does not
make any difference how we divide up that 180° with another line such as AB; the two
angles into which the 180° has been divided must still add up to 180°.
3. We should note in connection with this Theorem that angles supplementary to the
same angle are equal to each other. For example,
if ∠X + ∠Y = two rights,
and ∠X + ∠Z = two rights,
then ∠Y = ∠Z,
29
being both supplementary to ∠X. This is obvious, since each is equal to two right angles
minus ∠X (recall that all right angles are equal, and that equals with equals subtracted
from them leave equal remainders).
4. Recall Postulate 5, which says that inclined straight lines eventually meet. By
definition, lines such as A and B are “inclined to each other” if 1 + 2 < 3 + 4. With the
help of Thm. 11, we can now define “inclined straight lines” another way.
We know that 1 + 3 = two rights
and that 2 + 4 = two rights
thus 1 + 2 + 3 + 4 = four rights
so if 1 + 2 is less than two rights,
it follows that 3 + 4 is more than two rights.
A 3 In other words, if 1 + 2 is less than two
1 rights, then these two inside angles are less
C than the outside angles 3 + 4, and therefore
B
2 the two lines A and B will incline to each
4 other toward the right, and eventually meet
there. So we can now restate our fifth
postulate like this: if two straight lines make less than two right angles on one side of a
third straight line, then they will eventually meet on that side.
THEOREM 11 Questions
30
THEOREM 12: If two adjacent angles add up to two right angles, then the two
lines other than the line common to both angles are in a straight line with each other.
[4] So ∠1 + ∠2 = ∠1 + ∠2 + ∠3,
putting together Steps 2 & 3, since each side is supposedly equal to two right
angles.
[5] But that is crazy. For ∠1 + ∠2 is only a part of ∠1 + ∠2 + ∠3, and the whole
never equals a part of itself (Common Notion 5).
And since this impossibility follows from our initial supposition that PC is not the
extension of AP in a straight line, therefore that initial supposition is also
impossible.
Q.E.D.
THEOREM 12 Remarks
31
2. Notice that we use Postulate 4 for the first time in this theorem. In Step 4 we say
that
∠1 + ∠2 = ∠1 + ∠2 + ∠3
on the grounds that each side is equal to two right angles. We are presuming that “two
right angles” is always the same amount, i.e. that all right angles are equal.
3. Notice that if from the equation in Step 4 we subtract ∠1 + ∠2 from both sides,
we get ∠3 = nothing! If that were true, then PX would coincide with PC, and AP would
be in a straight line with PC, which is what we set out to prove.
THEOREM 12 Question
Does it make any difference to the proof if someone says that PX actually falls below
PC?
THEOREM 13: When two straight lines cut each other, they make the vertical
angles equal to each other.
Q.E.D.
32
THEOREM 13 Remarks
To be more concrete, look at the adjoining figure: If 1 = 2, and line A is in line with line
C, then line B must also be in line with line D.
On the other hand, if A is in line with line D, the adjacent leg in the other angle, it is not
true that B has to be in line with line C.
THEOREM 13 Questions
2. Looking back at the diagram for Theorem 13, how many degrees does ∠1 + ∠2 +
∠3 + ∠4 equal?
33
THEOREM 14: If any side of a triangle is extended, the exterior angle is greater
than either of the interior and opposite angles.
G
[1] Bisect AC at E. (Thm. 8)
[2] Join BE and produce it far enough to cut off EF = BE.
[3] Join CF. Now,
Q.E.D.
34
THEOREM 14 Remarks
THEOREM 14 Questions
1. In Step 12 of Thm. 14, I said “by the same argument as before, ∠BCG > ∠ABC.”
Go through the actual steps. Make a diagram for yourself, bisecting BC this time.
2. Join AF in the original diagram or in your copy of it. What shape does AFCB
appear to be?
THEOREM 15: In any triangle, a greater side will have opposite to it a greater
angle.
[1] Since AC > AB, we can cut off AD = AB. Join BD.
35
[3] ∠2 > ∠3 (Thm. 14; since ∠2 is exterior to ΔBDC)
[5] ∠ABC > ∠1 (Since the whole is greater than the part)
[7] That is, ∠ABC > ∠BCA (∠BCA is the same as ∠3)
Q.E.D.
THEOREM 15 Remarks
2. These facts might lead us to think that angles in a triangle are somehow
proportional to their opposite sides, for example that if one side is double another side,
then the opposite angle is double the opposite angle. Unfortunately, that is completely
FALSE! To see this better, take a look at Question 2 below.
THEOREM 15 Questions
If A=C
and B=D
but E<F
Show that 1<2
36
H
2. Draw an equilateral triangle GHK. Bisect GK at M and
join HM. Now just focus on ΔHMK. Clearly HK is double MK,
1
but are their opposite angles respectively double? That is, is ∠2
double ∠1? Prove it is not so.
2
G M K
THEOREM 16: In any triangle, a greater angle will have opposite to it a greater
side.
[10] Since AC is neither equal to AB (Step 5), nor less than AB (step 9), therefore AC is
greater than AB.
Q.E.D.
37
THEOREM 16 Remarks
2. Theorem 16 is the converse of Theorem 15. The strategy here is the process of
elimination. If there are only three possibilities, and we eliminate two of them, then the
third one must be true.
4. Even though angles are not exactly proportional to sides in a triangle, we now
know that the order of inequality among angles corresponds to the order of inequality
among their opposite sides.
If you have a protractor, but not a ruler, you can still tell which is the greatest side
in the triangle just by measuring the angles.
If you have a ruler, but not a protractor, you can still tell which is the greatest
angle in the triangle just by measuring the sides.
THEOREM 16 Questions
38
b 40 e
35 36 36
38
2. Given the lengths of some of the sides in each of these a c d f g
triangles, say what we know about the labeled angles. 37 22
k
51 51 120
35
3. Given the number of degrees in some of the angles of n r s
t h
25
these triangles, say what we know about the labeled sides. 100 35
m
THEOREM 17: In any triangle, any side is less than the sum of the other two
sides, but greater than their difference.
2 Proof:
C
[1] Extend BA to D so that AD = AC.
[2] Join CD.
B
Q.E.D.
39
THEOREM 17 Remarks
1. We could also look at the theorem this way: if you had to race someone from A
to B, would you run first from A to C, then from C to B? No way. AB is the shortest
distance from A to B.
2. A more general version of this theorem is this: A straight line is the shortest
distance between two points. Every jointed or curved path is longer.
Obviously, that does not mean that the straight path is always the easiest to travel.
The shortest distance between two points on either side of a forest is a straight line, but
the quickest way through might be a curved path that takes us around the trees! Hence
the expression “as the crow flies”, which means I am telling you the straight line
distance, although the path you actually take to walk the distance might be curved and
therefore much longer. Crows don’t have to move around obstacles.
3. Although the straight line is the shortest distance between two points, there is
obviously no longest distance between two points. You can take as convoluted a path
from point A to point B as you like, and there will always be one even more convoluted
and longer.
This often happens in mathematics, that there is one kind of limit, e.g. a shortest
or smallest, but there is no limit in the opposite direction, e.g. a longest or greatest.
4. This theorem shows that there is a condition that must be fulfilled before any 3
straight lines will be able to make a triangle. Any two of those lines added together has to
be greater than the third. Otherwise, you can't make a triangle with those 3 straight lines.
For example, try to make a triangle whose sides are equal to 1, 2, and 3 unit lengths (say
1 inch, 2 inches, and 3 inches). Good luck!
This means that as soon as I give you two sides to make a triangle with, I have
placed a restraint on what you can use for the third side: whatever you use has to be less
than the sum of the two sides I already gave you, but greater than their difference. For
example, if I give you a side of 4 feet and a side of 7 feet, you cannot use 24 feet for the
other side, since that is bigger than 11 feet (the sum of the two sides I gave you). On the
other hand, you cannot use 2 feet, since that is smaller than 3 feet (the difference between
the sides I gave you). Any side you choose must therefore be greater than 3 feet and yet
less than 11 feet.
5. This condition is not true with regard to the angles of a triangle, i.e. it is not true
that any 2 angles in a triangle, taken together, have to add up to more than the remaining
angle. It is possible, for example, to have a triangle whose angles are 1°, 1°, and 178°.
40
THEOREM 17 Questions
1. Say which of the following triads of straight lines can be used to form a triangle,
and which cannot (say the lengths are all in inches):
(a) 3 4 5
(b) 1 2 3
(c) 1 2 1
(d) 4 5 6
(e) 1 10 11
(f) 1 1 1
(g) 3 2 3
(h) 7 9 8
2. If I give you a line 5” long, and another that is 6” long, the Theorem states that
any third line able to form a triangle with them must be between 1” and 11”; it must be
more than 1” long, and less than 11” long. What is the range of possible lengths for the
third side of a triangle with one side of 8 miles and another side of 11 miles?
3. Cut out six thin strips of paper with the following lengths in inches: ½, 1, 2, 6, 8,
10, 19. Measure exactly. Color the 10-inch strip red. Next make any triangle you like
using any three of these strips as sides.
I will now make a prediction: the triangle you made uses the red strip, and the
angle opposite to it is a right angle.
Why was I able to predict that you used the red strip? (The reason I know the
angle opposite it is a right angle you will learn in Theorem 37.)
41
THEOREM 18: The shortest distance from a point to a straight line is the
perpendicular from the point to the line.
Q.E.D.
THEOREM 19: How to make a triangle out of any three straight lines (provided
any two of them together are greater than the third).
42
[5] Since AD and BF add up to more than AB (given), the circles with radii AD and BF
will overreach each other along AB. So at least a part of AB is inside both circles at
once. Thus the circles around A and B overlap.
[6] Since BA and AD add up to more than BF (given), thus BD is greater than the radius
of circle B, and so point D lies outside circle B.
[7] Since AB and BF add up to more than AD (given), thus AF is greater than the radius
of circle A, and so point F lies outside circle A.
[8] Thus circle A and circle B must cut each other. For they overlap each other (by Step
5), and each passes outside of the other, since D on circle A lies outside circle B (Step 6),
and F on circle B lies outside circle A (Step 7).
[9] Call the point where circles A and B cut each other point C.
[11] AC = AD = X
AB = Y
BC = BF = Z
[12] So triangle ABC has been made, with its sides equal to X, Y, and Z.
Q.E.F.
THEOREM 19 Remarks
Thm. 17 says: If 3 lines can form a triangle, then any 2 of them is greater than the
remaining one,
Thm. 19 says: If 3 lines are such that any 2 of them is greater than the remaining
one, then they can form a triangle.
THEOREM 19 Question
Make a triangle with sides equal to 3”, 4”, and 5”. What do you notice about it?
43
THEOREM 20: How to make an angle equal to any angle.
R
S P T V
[1] Pick points A & B at random on each of the
legs of ∠X, and join them.
[5] But ∠ZPT begins at P, and PT lies along PR, and ∠AXB is the given angle X.
Q.E.F.
THEOREM 20 Remark
44
THE ANGLE-SIDE-ANGLE THEOREM
THEOREM 21: If in a triangle two angles and the side joining them are
respectively equal to two angles and the side joining them in another triangle, then all the
corresponding sides and angles of the two triangles are equal, and the triangles have the
same area.
∠BAC = ∠EDF
AB = DE
∠ABC = ∠DEF
A D
[2] Since ∠BAC = ∠EDF, therefore AC and DF will lie in line together.
[3] Since ∠ABC = ∠DEF, therefore BC and EF will lie in line together.
[7] So the 3 sides of ΔABC coincide with the 3 sides of ΔDEF, and so all of their
corresponding sides and angles are equal and they also have equal areas (Side-Side-Side
Theorem).
Q.E.D.
45
THEOREM 21 Remarks
C F
1. This is our third triangle-congruence theorem. We now
have:
SAS (Side-Angle-Side)
A D SSS (Side-Side-Side)
ASA (Angle-Side-Angle)
B E
2. As with the other congruence theorems, it is possible for the given triangles to be
mirror images of each other. In that case, we must flip over one of the triangles to show
that they can coincide.
THEOREM 21 Questions
2. Some Boy Scouts stood at the edge of a canyon at point E, across from a tree on
the other side of the canyon standing at T. They needed to measure the distance across
the canyon, namely the distance ET. But how could they
T
measure a distance across a canyon? Here is what they did.
They marked E with a stake, and from it sighted along a
straight stick, pointing it at T, putting the stick in line with ET.
Next, they walked out to some point P further along the edge
E
30 P S of the canyon, so that ∠TEP was a right angle, and then they
marked P with a tall pole. Then they continued in a straight
40 line to S until PS was the same distance as EP, and then
50
marked S with another stake. Then they walked away from the
K
D canyon along the line SD so that SD was at right angles to PS.
They stopped at the point D where the pole at P was in the
same line of sight with the tree at T across the canyon. Then they just measured SD, and
said that was the same length as the distance ET across the canyon. Prove they were
right.
Incidentally, how could they ensure EP is at right angles to ET? They could
stretch a string E in the same line of sight with T, say 40 feet long, then form a triangle
with EP being 30 feet long, and KP 50 feet long. Why angle KEP would be 90° we shall
see later.
46
ANGLE-ANGLE-SIDE THEOREM
THEOREM 22: If two triangles have two angles equal to two angles, and a side
equal to a side (namely a side opposite an equal angle), then they will have all their
corresponding sides and angles equal, and they will also have equal areas.
[C] Suppose you have two triangles ABC and DEF such
that
4
C F ∠BCA = ∠EFD
∠BAC = ∠EDF
2 3 AB = DE
{C}
Then the remaining sides and angles of the two
1
triangles must be equal, too. To prove it:
A B D E
Q.E.D.
47
THEOREM 22 Remarks
THEOREM 22 Question
48
THEOREM 23: If two straight lines are cut by a third making the alternate
angles equal, then the two straight lines are parallel.
[1] Suppose, if possible, that AB and CD are not parallel, but rather EB and FD meet
toward the right (when extended far enough) at some point X.
[5] And so the exterior angle of triangle EFX is equal to one of its interior and
opposite angles, which is absurd, since by Theorem 14 the exterior angle is
always greater.
[6] Since the absurdity in Step 5 follows from our initial assumption that AB and CD
are not parallel, but meet and form a triangle, therefore that assumption is absurd,
and we must say instead that AB and CD are parallel, and never meet so as to
form a triangle with EF.
Q.E.D.
THEOREM 23 Remarks
2. It is amazing that we can prove that two straight lines never meet, even though we
can't actually extend them forever and check. We have managed a way around that!
3. The straight line EF is called a transversal in relation to the straight lines AB and
CD, since it cuts across them both.
49
THEOREM 23 Question
Prove Theorem 23 in another way by the symmetry of the diagram; is there reason to
think that what happens on one side of EF must also happen on the other side? And if so,
can you see how that will help prove the theorem? Recall that two straight lines cannot
enclose a space.
THEOREM 24: If two straight lines are cut by a third making interior angles on
one side add up to two rights, then the two lines are parallel.
E
Suppose AB & CD are cut by EF so that
∠2 + ∠3 = two right angles.
A
1 2
B Then AB is parallel to CD.
Why?
3
C D
Q.E.D.
THEOREM 24 Remarks
50
2. Notice that the postulate is about lines that do meet, and this theorem is about
lines that do not meet.
P
3. It follows from this theorem that there cannot be two
perpendiculars from one point to one straight line, but only one.
Assume that you could have two perpendiculars, PR & PL, from
the same point P to the straight line AB. Then we have formed a
triangle PRL having two right angles in it, namely ∠PRL &
∠PLR. By Theorem 24, RP and LP have to be parallel! And so
either RP and LP do not meet (and therefore there is no point P
A R L B common to them), or one of those two angles is less than a right
angle.
THEOREM 24 Questions
THEOREM 25: If a straight line cuts two parallels, it makes interior angles on
one side add up to two rights, and it makes equal alternate angles.
51
[1] Suppose, if possible, that 1 > 3.
[5] So AB and CD eventually meet on the side of angles 3 & 2, if AB and CD are
extended far enough. (Postulate 5, as restated in Thm.11, Remark 4)
[6] But that is absurd, since AB and CD are given to us as parallel straight lines, i.e. lines
that never meet no matter how far they are extended.
[7] Therefore our initial supposition, namely that 1 > 3, is also absurd.
[8] By the same kind of argument, we can show that 1 < 3 is also absurd.
[9] Since 1 is neither greater than 3 (Step 7) nor less than 3 (Step 8), therefore 1 = 3.
Q.E.D.
THEOREM 25 Remarks
2. In this theorem, we make the first use of our 5th Postulate, namely in Step 5.
3. Notice the order of Theorems 23 & 24 & 25. In Theorems 23 & 24, we are given
lines that are disposed to a transversal at certain angles, and then we prove that they must
be parallel. In Theorem 25 we are given lines that are parallel, and then we prove that
they are disposed to a transversal at certain angles. We begin by giving ourselves what
we know we can have, namely two lines disposed at certain angles to a transversal; we
can construct that. But we do not know how to construct parallel straight lines (or even
that they exist) until after Theorems 23 & 24. That is why we wait until Theorem 25 to
give ourselves a pair of parallels, and ask what has to be true about them.
52
4. We have just proved that if AB & CD are parallel, then ∠2 + ∠3 must add up to
180°. That means that if ∠2 + ∠3 do not add up to 180° (but add up to something more
or less than that), then AB & CD are not parallel.
If they add up to less than 180°, then they meet out toward the right side, which is
what the fifth postulate says. If they add up to more than 180°, then they will meet on the
other side of GH, toward the left, since the angles on that side will then add up to less
than 180°.
THEOREM 25 Questions
X
1. Using Theorem 25, prove that only one line through a
P L point P can be parallel to any given line AB. Start by assuming
the possibility of having two parallels to AB drawn through the
A B same point P (call the other one PX), and join P to any random
R
point R along AB, making PR a transversal.
A
1
THEOREM 26: Straight lines parallel to the same straight line are parallel to
each other.
4
C
53
To prove it:
[1] Cut all three straight lines with another straight line D; in doing so you form
angles 1, 2, 3, 4.
Q.E.D.
THEOREM 26 Remarks
B
1
C
3. Another theorem similar to Theorem 26 is this: If the sides of
4
3 one angle are parallel to the sides of another angle, then the two
D
2
E angles are either equal or supplementary. Consider the case of
∠ABC and ∠DEF, where AB║EF and BC║DE. Join BE, and
F
54
suppose that each angle lies on opposite sides of BE. It is easy to see that ∠1 = ∠2, i.e.
that ∠ABC = ∠DEF. For:
1 + 3 = 4 + 2 (since AB║EF; Theorem 25)
and 3=4 (since BC║DE; Theorem 25)
thus 1 = 2 (subtracting the equal angles 3 & 4 from each side).
Obviously the converse of this theorem is not true, namely “If two angles are
equal, then the sides of one are parallel to the sides of the other”.
THEOREM 26 Questions
1. What true statement can we make about two straight lines that are perpendicular
to the same straight line?
A
K D 3. Show that if two straight lines cut, then so do their
4 X
parallels. Suppose AB ‖EF, and CD ‖GH, and suppose
2 that AB cuts CD at a point X. Prove that GH must also cut
C
L
B
EF.
E Start by joining GE and extending it. Since GE
3 passes through E, but EF is the only parallel to AB through
F E, BE must cut AB at some point, say K. Likewise GE
H must cut CD at some point, say L. You have now formed a
1
triangle KXL. Can you see how to proceed from there?
G
R
U 4. In Remark 3 above, we chose
G O one particular case of two angles
13
S
11
V W whose corresponding sides are parallel,
5 9
H
6
K
P 10
12 14
Z namely the case where each angle falls
L
7
T
15
on an opposite side of the line joining
Q
M
8
N X
16
their vertices. See if you can prove the
Y
theorem in some of the remaining
cases, and state when the angles are equal, and when they are supplementary to each
55
other. Consider, for example, what happens when (1) Each angle falls on the same side
of the line joining their vertices, as ∠GHK and ∠LMN, (2) Each angle straddles the line
joining their vertices, but in such a way that parallel lines are on the same side of it, as
∠OPQ and ∠RST, or (3) Two of the parallel lines lie on the same side of the line joining
the vertices, but the other two parallel lines lie on opposite sides of it, as in ∠UVW and
∠XYZ.
THEOREM 27: How to draw a line parallel to any straight line, and passing
through any point.
Q.E.F.
THEOREM 27 Remarks
THEOREM 27 Questions
A B
1. A more practical way to draw a line
X
parallel to another line AB through a point P is
to draw PA perpendicular to AB using a
P R carpenter's square, go out to the other end of
AB and draw BR also perpendicular to AB (and make it equal to AP in length), and then
join PR.
56
Prove that PR is parallel to AB by first assuming the opposite, namely that AB and PR do
meet, say out to the right at some point X. Use Angle-Angle-Side to show that the two
resulting triangles AXP and BXR must be equal – and say why that is impossible.
THEOREM 28: In any triangle the three angles added together equal two right
angles, and the exterior angle equals the two interior and opposite angles added
together.
[1] Draw CP parallel to BA (Thm. 27), thus dividing exterior angle ACX into the two
angles 4 and 5.
Q.E.D.
57
THEOREM 28 Remarks
1. This theorem is actually quite surprising, if you think about it. Triangles can be
wildly different shapes from each other, and yet the three angles in any of them will
always add up to the same sum!
2. Recall Theorem 14, which says that ∠ACX has to be greater than ∠2 and also
greater than ∠3. Now we see, more precisely, that it is greater than either because it is
equal to the sum of both of them.
3. A corollary of this theorem, meaning “a side-result we get for free” is that Any
two angles of a triangle add up to LESS than 180°, because only all three together add up
to 180°. This corollary is the exact converse of the 5th Postulate.
Corollary: In a triangle, 2 angles add up to less than 180°
5th Postulate: 2 angles (on one side of a transversal) that add up to less than 180°
are angles in a triangle, i.e. the two outside lines forming the angles must eventually meet
and form a triangle.
4. Another corollary to the theorem is this: In any right triangle, the right angle is
the greatest angle. That has to be, since if there were another angle equal to or greater
than the right angle, the sum of the three angles in the triangle would be greater than
180°. Also, since the side opposite the greatest angle is the greatest, it follows that in any
right triangle the hypotenuse is the greatest side.
Yet another corollary is this: In any obtuse triangle, the obtuse angle is the
greatest. The same reason applies, and obviously the side opposite the obtuse angle must
be the greatest.
5. It also follows from this theorem that In any right triangle, the angles other than
the right angle are complementary to one another. Since the right angle plus the other
two equals two right angles, therefore the other two together equal one right angle, i.e.
they are complements of each other.
THEOREM 28 Questions
1. Draw any triangle on a piece of paper and label its angles 1, 2, 3. Next cut out the
triangle with a pair of scissors. Now tear off each angle of the triangle and line up the
three angles so that they all come to a single point. Do the three of them add up to a
58
straight line? See if you can come up with two reasons why this procedure does not
constitute a proof that the angles in every triangle add up to exactly to two right angles.
2. Using Theorem 28, you should be able to find the angle-sum of any rectilineal
figure, by cutting it into triangles and adding up the angles. Start with a quadrilateral:
what is the angle-sum of any quadrilateral? What is the angle-sum of any pentagon? Of
any hexagon? Can you find a general rule, so that given the number of sides in a convex
polygon, you can state the sum of its angles?
D
A
R L 4. Prove Theorem 28 by drawing a straight line RAL through
2 point A parallel to the base BC.
3 1
B C
A A A
5. A
Place any straight edge (such as a
pencil) along BC, then rotate it through
∠BCA; from CA, next rotate the straight
B C B C B
B C C
edge through ∠CAB; from AB, finally
rotate the straight edge through ∠ABC. You have rotated the straight edge through the 3
angles of the triangle. Can you see that the straight edge has turned through exactly one
half a full rotation, namely 180°?
6. Using Theorem 17, prove that every angle in an equilateral triangle is acute.
Prove, further, that every angle in an equilateral triangle is 60°.
Can a scalene triangle be right? Acute? Obtuse?
Can an isosceles triangle be right? Acute? Obtuse?
7. Armed with Theorem 28, go back to Theorem 1 Question 2 and prove that the
figure is a rhombus.
8. In Theorem 19, we showed how to make a triangle given any three straight lines
(as long as any two of them summed up to more than the third line). Can we make a
triangle with any three angles? Yes, as long as the three of them add up to two right
angles.
Suppose ∠1, ∠2, ∠3 add up to 180°. Given a
straight line AB, can you make a triangle, using AB
1 2
as one of the sides, whose three angles are ∠1, ∠2,
3
and ∠3?
59
9. Since we now know that the angles of a triangle add up to two right angles, or
180°, it is possible to make a triangle whose angles are 30°, 60°,
B
and 90°, since these add up to 180°. Suppose triangle ABC is
just such a triangle. Prove that in such a triangle, AB is double
30
the length of AC, and furthermore that this triangle is actually the
E left half of an equilateral triangle. Start by making an equilateral
triangle on AC; since the angles of an equilateral triangle each
equal 60°, therefore ΔAEC will sit right inside angle BAC. And
A
60
C
since AE = AC, and AC < AB (since AB is the hypotenuse and
thus the longest side of triangle ABC), AE < AB, too, and thus E
will land somewhere between A and B. See if you can prove that it lands exactly in the
middle of AB, and you will be nearly done. (Hint: prove EC = EB first, using Thm.3.)
THEOREM 29: If two triangles have two angles equal to two angles, then the
remaining angle is equal to the remaining angle.
[2] 1=4
2=5 (the angles are given that way)
Q.E.D.
60
THEOREM 29 Remarks
1. Just by applying Thm. 28, we see that given any two angles of a triangle, the third
can be determined. In fact, even if we do not know the two angles of a triangle
separately, but we know their sum, then we also know what the remaining angle must be.
For example, if ∠1 = 30°, and ∠2 = 50°, then since they add up to 80°, the
remaining angle, ∠3, must be 100° in order for all three of the angles to add up to 180°
(as Thm. 28 says they must).
And if ∠1 + ∠2 = 121°, then even if we don't know their values separately, we
still know that ∠3 must be 59°, in order for all the angles to add up to 180°.
2. Notice that we cannot say the same thing about the sides of a triangle, namely that
given any 2 of them, we can figure out the length of the third side. Suppose, for example,
that Side One = 5”, and Side Two = 6”. What is the third side? There's no telling. Could
it be 8”? Yes, since 5, 6, 8 are such that any two are greater than the third. Could it be
10”? Yes, since 5, 6, 10, are also such that any two are greater than the third. Could it be
3”? Yes, since 5, 6, 3 are also such that any two of them are greater than the third.
THEOREM 29 Questions
1. Are triangles ABC and DEF the same size? Are they the same shape?
2. If ΔABC has an angle of 35°, and another angle of 42°, then what is the value of
the remaining angle?
THEOREM 30: If one pair of opposite sides in a quadrilateral are both parallel
and equal, then the quadrilateral is a parallelogram.
61
[1] Join AD, forming ΔACD and ΔABD.
[5] So, by the Side-Angle-Side Theorem, all the corresponding sides and angles of
ΔACD & ΔABD are equal.
Q.E.D.
THEOREM 30 Remark
We could also state Theorem 30 in another way: If two straight lines are parallel and
equal, then the straight lines joining their corresponding endpoints are also parallel and
equal.
THEOREM 30 Questions
1. Construct a parallelogram on a given straight line CD, and having a given point A
above CD as one of its corners.
62
THEOREM 31: In any parallelogram, the opposite sides and angles are equal,
and the diagonal bisects the parallelogram.
[4] So, by the Angle-Side-Angle Theorem, all the corresponding sides and angles of
ΔABC & ΔADC will be equal, and the triangles themselves are equal in area.
[5] So the diagonal AC cuts the parallelogram ABCD into two triangles of equal area,
i.e. AC bisects the area of the parallelogram, and
Q.E.D.
THEOREM 31 Remark
Theorem 31 is the partial converse of Thm. 30, which says that in a quadrilateral, if one
pair of sides is both parallel and equal, then the other pair is parallel and equal. 31 says
that in a quadrilateral, if both pairs of sides are parallel, then both pairs of sides are equal.
63
THEOREM 31 Questions
2. Prove that if ABCD is a quadrilateral, and ∠ABC = ∠ADC and ∠BAD = ∠BCD,
then also AB║DC and AD║BC.
This, together with the solution to Q.1 above, proves the full converse of Thm. 31.
4. Prove the converse: that if the diagonals of a quadrilateral bisect each other, then
the quadrilateral is a parallelogram.
6. Prove the converse, that if the diagonals of a quadrilateral are equal, then the
quadrilateral is a rectangle.
7. Prove that the diagonals of any equilateral quadrilateral are perpendicular to each
other; then prove the converse, that if the diagonals of a quadrilateral are perpendicular to
each other, the quadrilateral is equilateral (i.e. has all its sides equal to each other, and so
is either a square or a rhombus).
THEOREM 32: Parallelograms on the same base and in the same parallels have
equal areas.
A D C F
4
Imagine two parallels AF and BE that
1 3
contain two parallelograms ABED and
CBEF which stand on base BE. Then
2 ABED and CBEF have equal areas.
Surprised? Well, here's proof:
B E
64
[4] AC = DF (Step 3)
AB = DE (being opposite sides of a parallelogram)
BC = EF (being opposite sides of a parallelogram)
so by the Side-Side-Side Theorem, ΔABC & ΔDEF are congruent triangles and so have
the same area.
Q.E.D.
THEOREM 32 Remarks
1. Notice how parallelograms ABED & CBEF have the same area, but do not have
the same shape. One cannot simply be placed right on top of the other one so as to
coincide with it. This shows that things can be equal, or have the same quantity, without
being exactly identical in every way, e.g. without having the same shape.
The word congruent is commonly used to name the relationship between figures
that have not only the same size, but also the same shape, as we remarked after Theorem
2 (Remark 4). Congruent triangles, for example, would be those which are entirely
identical, according to the theorems of Side-Angle-Side or Side-Side-Side or Angle-Side-
Angle. You might say that “congruence” is a particular kind of equality, the most perfect
kind of equality.
65
THEOREM 32 Questions
A C D F
A C/D F
2. Prove Thm. 32 in the case where point C lands
right on point D.
B E
3. Prove the converse, namely that if parallelograms ABCD & EFGH have the same
area and their equal bases AB & EF are in a straight line, then their tops DC & HG must
D C L K
also be in a straight line. Start by assuming DC &
H
V
HG are not in a straight line, but, say, DC is higher
G
up, and extend DC to V, and EH & FG to L & K
forming a new parallelogram ELKF.
A B E F
THEOREM 33: Triangles on the same base and in the same parallels have equal
areas; and a triangle on the same base and in the same parallels as a parallelogram has
half the area of the parallelogram.
66
[4] ΔABG = ½ABGK (Thm. 31)
ΔABC = ½ABLC (Thm. 31)
[6] Also, it is evident that ΔABC is equal to half of parallelogram ABGK, since it is
half its equal, namely parallelogram ABLC.
Q.E.D.
THEOREM 33 Remarks
1. Obviously, it follows that a triangle is half of any rectangle that stands in the same
parallels and has an equal base.
2. Notice that in Step 5 we use the principle that the halves of equal things are equal.
3. The converse for this Theorem can be proved in the same way that the converse
for Theorem 32 is proved (see Q.3 after Thm. 32). And, just like with Thm. 32, the two
triangles need not have the same base, but equal bases is enough.
4. What we call the “base” of a triangle is not any special side of it – any of the three
sides can be called its “base”. In this case we call the “base” the side which lies along
one of the parallels.
67
THEOREM 33 Questions
1. If a rectangle has Side One = 3”, and Side Two = 4”, then what is the total area of
the rectangle in square inches? What operation does one perform on 3 & 4 to get the
right answer? Why is that the operation performed? Draw a diagram that shows your
procedure was right.
2. What if one side of a rectangle is 2 and the other is 2½? Will that change the
procedure? Draw a diagram of the rectangle, and divide it into squares showing that the
answer is still correct using the same procedure.
Accordingly, the formula for calculating the area of a rectangle is
A = bh
Where A means the area of the rectangle, and b means the length of its base, and h means
the height of the rectangle, and putting b and h right next to each other means to multiply
them. The result is the number of unit square areas in the rectangle.
68
THEOREM 34: In any parallelogram, the “complements” of any two
parallelograms about the diagonal are equal.
[4] 5 + 3 + 1 = 6 + 4 + 2,
since diagonal AC bisects the area of parallelogram ABCD.
[5] 1 = 2,
subtracting the equal areas 5 + 3 and 6 + 4 from each side of the equal areas in
Step 4.
Q.E.D.
THEOREM 34 Remarks
1. It is also true that if we join and extend GE, and then join and extend FH, and then
extend CA, these three straight lines will all meet each other in the same point! In fact,
that will still be true even if EF and HG do not pass through the same point along the
diagonal AC (just as long as they are each parallel to one of the sides of the original
parallelogram). We don’t have the tools to prove it, yet, though.
2. Notice that the little parallelograms EH and GF seem to be the same shape as the
original parallelogram BD.
69
THEOREM 34 Question
A G Y
Now prove the converse of Thm. 34. Let 1 & 2
E
X
2 (DVCH and GVFE) be parallelograms of equal
D F
V area drawn inside the opposite angles of the larger
1
parallelogram ACBE by drawing DVF║CB, and
C H Z B GVH║AC. Join AB. You should be able to show
that V lies on AB.
Start by assuming that V does not lie on diagonal AB, but instead DVF passes
through AB at another point X. Then draw YXZ║AC and see what happens when you
apply Thm. 34.
[6] But the angles opposite 1 & 2 are equal to them, since ABCD is a parallelogram
(Thm. 31),
so 3 = one right (being opposite ∠1)
and 4 = one right (being opposite ∠2)
[7] And the sides opposite AB & AD are equal to them, since ABCD is a
parallelogram (Thm. 31),
so DC = AB
and CB = AD
70
[8] But AB = AD (we made them so)
[10] So ABCD is equilateral (Step 9), and has all right angles (Steps 5 & 6), and so it
is a square (Def. 23)
Q.E.F.
THEOREM 35 Remarks
1. We have now made two regular rectilineal figures, the equilateral triangle and the
square. A regular rectilineal figure is one all of whose sides are equal and all of whose
angles are equal. We have made the 3-sided regular figure, and the 4-sided; we will learn
how to do the 5-sided, 6-sided, 8-sided, 10-sided, 12-sided, and 15-sided later.
Parallelogram
Rhombus 2. As you know, rectangles, rhombuses, and
squares are special kinds of parallelograms.
Moreover, a square can be considered as a special
kind of rectangle, namely one whose sides are all
Rectangle
Square equal. A square can also be considered as a special
kind of rhombus, namely one which has been
“squared up”.
Because a square is a parallelogram, its
diagonals bisect each other; because a square is a
rectangle, its diagonals are equal to each other; and because a square is equilateral (like a
rhombus), its diagonals are perpendicular to each other.
3. Make a square on two consecutive sides of your original square, and then add a
fourth square in between the two added squares. You now have one big square made out
of the four little squares.
Look at one of the little squares and compare it to the big square.
How do the lengths of their sides compare? How do their areas compare? Does
the area of a square increase in the same proportion as the length of its side increases?
THEOREM 35 Questions
1. Using a compass and a straight edge, what is the fewest number of steps in which
you can make a square on a given straight line as one of its sides? Count each circle or
straight line you make as one step. See if you can find the top two corners of the square in
5 steps.
71
2. As we will see later, among all quadrilaterals, the square has the greatest area for
a given perimeter, and conversely the least perimeter for a given area. We can say the
same thing about the equilateral triangle among all triangles. Proof will come later.
THEOREM 36: In any right triangle, the square on the hypotenuse is equal to
the sum of the two squares on the remaining sides.
B C
[1] Drop AL perpendicular to DE, thus
forming rectangles BL & LC.
Join AD, join CF.
Q.E.D.
72
THEOREM 36 Remarks
1. This is the most famous theorem in all of geometry. The first general proof of it
is attributed to Pythagoras, a Greek philosopher who lived five centuries before Christ.
Legend has it he was so delighted by the Theorem that he went out and sacrificed an ox
in thanksgiving to the gods for so beautiful a truth.
2. In the diagram for this theorem, FC, AL, and BK all pass through one point! If
you draw a careful diagram, you can verify this for yourself – but we won’t burden
ourselves with a proof for it right now.
3. Numerically, the way to calculate the area of a square, as with any rectangle, is to
multiply the number of unit lengths in one side by the number of those same unit lengths
in an adjacent side. But since any two adjacent sides of a square are equal, it follows that
we need only multiply the numerical length of one side times itself to obtain the number
of unit squares in the whole square. The algebraic symbol for the product of any number
n times itself is n2. So if a is the hypotenuse of a right triangle, and b and c are its other
two sides, we can express the Pythagorean Theorem this way:
a2 = b2 + c2
THEOREM 36 Questions
E
3
4 1. Illustrate the Pythagorean Theorem by making a
5 2 1
G puzzle. If DEF is a right triangle, and DF the hypotenuse,
and FDKL the square on it, then extend KD to H on the
F D larger of the two other squares, and draw EG parallel to
DF. If you draw this carefully, and then cut out areas 1, 2,
3, 4, 5, you will see that they can be placed together to
make a square identical to DFLK.
L K
C F
2. We can now prove another “Triangle Congruence
Theorem”, although it is limited to right triangles. If we
have two right triangles ABC and DEF, and two sides of
one of them equal two corresponding sides in the other,
A B then the triangles are identical. This is true even if the
D E
73
b 3. See the two figures at left? Each is made by
a
c a
taking four identical right triangles with sides a,
b, c (c being the hypotenuse). Can you verify
=
b the Pythagorean Theorem by looking at these
c
two figures? In the left figure, we see that the
square on c is equal to the big square minus
four triangles. In the right figure, we see that the squares on a and b together are equal
to the big square minus four triangles.
5. Given the triangle at left, with one leg of 12 and the hypotenuse of
15
15, how long is the other leg?
12
13
6. Given that the hypotenuse of a right triangle is 13 units long,
and one leg is 12, how long is the other leg?
12
D C
7. ARB is a right triangle, AB its hypotenuse. AR = 4, RB =
3, and ABCD is a square. What is the area of the figure
R ARBCD?
4 3
A B
G H
E 8. EFG is a right triangle, EF its
T
hypotenuse. EF = 25, EG = 24, and
GFKH is a square. What is the area of
F K
triangle GTF?
X
25
9. XY = 15, XZ = 25. What is the area of triangle XYZ?
15
Z Y
74
THEOREM 37: If the square on one side of a triangle equals the sum of the
squares on the remaining sides, then the triangle is a right triangle.
A
Suppose you have a triangle ABC in which
£AB = £AC + £BC. Then the angle opposite
AB is a right angle, i.e. ∠ACB is a right angle.
Here's proof:
Q.E.D.
THEOREM 37 Remarks
2. It follows that the square on the side of an acute or obtuse triangle does not equal
the sum of the squares on the remaining two sides.
3. A triangle whose sides are 3 units long, 4 units long, and 5 units long is a right
triangle, and the longest side, 5, is its hypotenuse. This fact is often used in carpentry. If
you need to make a very large right angle, say at the corner of a house's foundation, then
a little carpenter's square won't do. You might be off (or the carpenter's square might be
off) of 90° by only a miniscule amount near the square, but by the time you extend
straight lines far from the square, you might have an appreciable difference between
where you end up and where a precise 90° angle would end up. You can get around this
by marking lengths along a string (with knots) that are 3, 4, and 5 units long; if you
75
stretch them tight and form a triangle with them (there is only 1 triangle you can form
with them!), then the angle between the sides of lengths 3 & 4 (feet or yards or whatever)
will be a right angle.
THEOREM 37 Questions
1. Using Theorem 37, prove that a triangle having one side 3 feet long, another side
4 feet long, and the remaining side 5 feet long is a right triangle, and that the 5-foot long
side is the hypotenuse.
since 52 = 32 + 42
i.e. 25 = 9 + 16.
3, 4, and 5 are not the only whole numbers that do that. Any three whole numbers which
do that are called “Pythagorean Triples”. Here are all the Pythagorean Triples in which
no member is greater than 50:
3 4 5 14 48 50
5 12 13 15 20 25
6 8 10 15 36 39
7 24 25 16 30 34
8 15 17 18 24 30
9 12 15 20 21 29
9 40 41 21 28 35
10 24 26 24 32 40
12 16 20 27 36 45
12 35 37 30 40 50
In each case, the squares of the first two numbers, when added together, equals the square
of the third number. Obviously, some of these triples are based on others, e.g. 30, 40, 50,
is based on 3, 4, 5. Can you see any others that are based on 3, 4, 5?
76
HOOK THEOREMS
Here is another “hook theorem.” Take an equilateral triangle ABC, and pick any point P
inside it. Now draw the perpendiculars from P to the three sides: PQ, PR, PS. If you add
up those three lengths, their sum is equal to AT, the altitude of the triangle (the
perpendicular drawn from A to BC).
A
R
Q
P
C B
S T
77
(3) PAPPUS’ THEOREM.
Here is a third hook. If DF, KG be any two straight lines in a plane, and E, H be any
points on them, and we form three “X” figures by joining DH & EK (intersecting at L),
EG & FH (intersecting at N), DG & FK (intersecting at M), then L, M, N will lie in a
straight line.
F
E
N
M
L
K H G
78
Chapter Two
Squares
and
Rectangles
DEFINITIONS
D C
1. A rectangle is said to be CONTAINED BY any two of
R its adjacent sides, and any two straight lines are said TO
CONTAIN a rectangle made with adjacent sides equal to
E F
them.
For example, rectangle R is contained by DE and EF.
And if A and B are two straight lines equal to DE and EF respectively, then R is
the rectangle which A and B contain.
79
THEOREMS
THEOREM 1: The rectangle contained by any line L and the sum of two other
lines (A + B) is equal to the sum of the rectangles contained by L and A and by L and B.
A B
That is to say L (A + B) = L ⋅A + L ⋅B
Q.E.D.
THEOREM 1 Remarks
1. This simple theorem is not limited to just two lines. If we had a third line C, then
it is likewise true that the rectangle contained by L and (A + B + C) is equal to the sum of
the rectangles L ⋅A + L ⋅ B + L ⋅ C.
Y (X - Y)
2. This theorem is obviously true for subtraction as well,
i.e. L (X – Y) = L ⋅X – L ⋅Y
L
3. This theorem is a cousin to a very similar theorem about numbers, since the
number of square units of area in a rectangle is found by multiplying the numerical
measure of the sides. The theorem about numbers says Any number n multiplied by the
sum of any two numbers (m + p) is equal to the sum of the products n × m and n × p. As
with the rectangles, there can be more than two numbers in the sum. Thus if we add a
third number, r, it will be true that n (m + p + r) = n × m + n × p + n × r.
80
THEOREM 2: If through any point on the diagonal of a square two lines are
drawn parallel to each side of the square, then the four resulting figures inside are two
squares along the original diagonal and two identical complementary rectangles.
A B G
Take any square AGFD, and choose any random
point R along its diagonal DG. Now draw BRE
C H
R parallel to AD, and CRH parallel to DEF. I say that
CRED and BGHR are squares, and that ABRC and
RHFE are identical rectangles.
[2] Now CAB is a right angle, and AB║CR and AC║BR, so it is clear that ABRC is a
rectangle. Likewise RHFE is a rectangle. Moreover, since CR = RE (being sides of
square CRED) and BR = RH (being sides of square BGHR), therefore ABRC and RHFE
are identical rectangles.
Q.E.D.
THEOREM 2 Questions
2. What figures do we get if BE and CH are drawn parallel to the sides of the square,
but they do not intersect along either diagonal of the square?
3. What if AGFD were a rectangle? What four figures would we get? By drawing
two lines parallel to its sides, could we ever get a square? Could we ever get two
squares? Four squares?
5. Prove the converse, i.e. prove that if two little squares situated in opposite corners
of a big square touch at their corners, their common corner lies on the diagonal of the
original square (and the other two figures are identical rectangles).
6. Prove another form of the converse, i.e. prove that if two identical rectangles in
opposite corners of a square touch at their corners, that common corner lies on the
diagonal of the original square (and the other two figures are squares).
81
THEOREM 3: Given any two lines, the square on their sum is equal to the sum of
the squares on each plus twice the rectangle they contain.
[3] Which is to say that given any two lines DE and EF, the square on their sum
(£DF) is equal to the sum of the squares on them (£DE + £EF) plus twice the rectangle
they contain (2 DE · EF).
Q.E.D.
THEOREM 3 Remarks
1. This theorem has a cousin theorem about numbers, namely that The square of the
sum of two numbers is equal to the sum of the squares of each number plus twice their
product. That is, if n and m are our numbers, then (n + m)2 = n2 + m2 + 2nm.
82
THEOREM 4: The difference between any two squares equals the rectangle
contained by the sum and the difference of their sides.
D E F N
[2] Since LR = DE
and DN = (DF + DE)
while NT = FM = EF = (DF – DE)
we can substitute these lengths in the equality of Step 1, and say that
£DF – £DE = (DF + DE)(DF – DE)
[3] In other words, the difference between any two squares (£DF – £DE) equals the
rectangle contained by the sum of their sides (DF + DE) and the difference between their
sides (DF – DE).
Q.E.D.
THEOREM 4 Remarks
1. The corresponding truth about numbers is that The difference between the squares
of two numbers is equal to the product of the sum of those numbers and the difference
between those numbers. That is, supposing the numbers are n and m, and n is the greater
of the two, then n2 – m2 = (n + m)(n – m)
For example 72 – 42 = (7 + 4)(7 – 4).
83
THEOREM 5: How to make a single rectangle equal to any two given rectangles.
B A M T
P Suppose you have two rectangles
with no length of any side common
to both, and yet you would like to
make one big rectangle equal to the
two of them. Easy. Put their corners
together as ABCD and DEFG in
such a way that CD and DG are in a
G L straight line. Extend BA out to P,
R
C D and CDG out to R, as far as needed.
E F K
Next,
[6] Therefore MGLT is equal to DEFG in area, but has one side equal to a side of
rectangle ABCD. So if we slide MGLT over until it is right up against ABCD, the two of
them will form one rectangle together. And the area of that rectangle will be equal to
ABCD + DEFG.
Q.E.F.
THEOREM 5 Remarks
1. Notice that we can use this construction to add together as many rectangles as we
please into one big rectangle. Suppose, instead of just two rectangles, you had three,
namely 1, 2, and 3, and you wanted to make a big rectangle equal to the three of them.
Using the theorem, make a rectangle R which is equal to 1 + 2. Using the theorem again,
make a rectangle T which is equal to R + 3. Since R = 1 + 2, thus T = 1 + 2 + 3.
2. Notice that rectangles DEFG and MGLT have the same area but they do not have
the same shape. That leads us to expect a difference in their perimeters, or the total
length around their sides. In fact, it is quite possible for two different rectangles to
contain the same area, but with unequal perimeters.
84
For example, consider two rectangles, one of which is 2” × 6”, the other of which
is 3” × 4”. Each has an area of 12 square inches, but the 2” × 6” rectangle has a perimeter
of 16 inches, whereas the 3” × 4” rectangle has a perimeter of only 14 inches.
6 A 2” × 5” rectangle also has a perimeter of
Area = 12
2
Perimeter = 16
14 inches, but it has less area than the 3” × 4”
rectangle, i.e. only 10 square inches of area.
Stranger still, a 1” × 7” rectangle has a bigger
4
perimeter than the 3” × 4” rectangle, namely 16
Area = 12 inches, and yet it has less area (namely 7 square
3
Perimeter = 14
inches). So if your yard is 30 yards by 40 yards,
and mine is 10 yards by 70 yards, then the fence
5 around your yard is shorter than the fence around
2
Area = 10 my yard, and yet your yard is bigger than mine.
Perimeter = 14
7
Area = 7
1
Perimeter = 16
P
In any circle with center M and any diameter
AMB, choose any point along the circumference
and drop PR perpendicular to AB. I say that
£PR = AR ⋅ RB.
A M R B
The proof:
[3] Thus £PR = £MB – £MR (MP = MB, being radii of the circle)
85
[6] i.e. £PR = (AM + MR)(MB – MR),
since AM = MB, both being radii of the circle.
Q.E.D.
THEOREM 7: How to make a square that has the same area as any given
rectilineal figure.
B
Suppose you have a rectilineal figure ABCDE
with as many sides as you want (in this case,
1 five). How can you make a square that is equal
A C to it in area? The general procedure is to cut it
2 3 up into triangles, turn each triangle into a
E
D
rectangle, turn all the rectangles into one big
rectangle, and turn that big rectangle into a
J
F H B G P square.
1
[1] You can always divide a rectilineal
figure into triangles by joining its vertices
A M C
together, say into Δ1 and Δ2 and Δ3.
Q
[2] Now make a rectangle equal to each
triangle.
To do this, just take each triangle, such
K
O
R
as Δ1, and draw a line JP through its vertex
L parallel to its base AC. Next, draw AF and CG
P N
perpendicular to base AC, forming rectangle
ACGF. Since Δ1 and ACGF are on the same
base and in the same parallels, therefore Δ1 is half of rectangle ACGF (Ch.1, Thm. 33).
Bisect AC at M, and draw MH perpendicular to base AC, dividing ACGF into
two rectangles AFHM and HMCG. These rectangles are identical, since AM = MC and
since HM is a side common to both. Since they have equal areas, and since the two
together make up rectangle ACGF, either one of these rectangles is half of rectangle
ACGF.
86
But that means each of these rectangles is equal to Δ1, which is also half of
rectangle ACGF. That is how to make a rectangle equal to a triangle. And so, equal to
Δ1, Δ2, Δ3 etc., we will have rectangle 1, rectangle 2, rectangle 3 etc.
[3] Now make a rectangle equal to rectangle 1 + rectangle 2, using Theorem 5 above.
Next, make a rectangle equal to that rectangle plus rectangle 3, again using
Theorem 5. The result is a rectangle equal to Δ1 + Δ2 + Δ3. Continuing this process as
often as needed, we can make a rectangle equal to any number of triangles added
together.
[4] Let KLNP be the finished product, namely a rectangle whose area is equal to
Δ1 + Δ2 + Δ3.
Q.E.F.
THEOREM 7 Remarks
1. This theorem obviously does not enable us to make a square equal to any plane
figure, but only to a rectilineal figure. The construction requires us to resolve the given
figure into triangles, which we can’t do if we are given, for example, a circle.
2. To make a square equal to a given rectangle, we can skip right down to Step 5 in
the construction and start making our semi-circle. There is no need to divide the
rectangle into triangles.
87
THEOREM 7 Question
THEOREM 8: An isosceles triangle has less perimeter than any other triangle
under the same height and on an equal base.
This theorem, along with Theorems 9 and 10, is interesting in its own right, but I include
all of them here for the sake of the upcoming Theorem 11 ...
Suppose ABC is an isosceles
A
P triangle. Draw AP║BC. Let ARK be any
other triangle in the same parallels (slid
over, if necessary, until its vertex
coincides with vertex A of rABC), and
B K let its base RK be equal to BC – thus the
G R C
two triangles have equal areas.
Nonetheless, I say that the perimeter of
ΔABC is less than the perimeter of ΔARK.
[1] Cut off BG = RC. Join AG. Thus it is evident that rARG is also isosceles.
88
[3] Thus if we extend AC to E so that AC = CE as well, it is obvious that AKEG is a
parallelogram, since AC = CE and GC = CK.
[5] If we now add the lines RK and BC, given as equal, to either side of this
inequality, we get
RA + AK + RK > BA + AC + BC
which is to say that the perimeter of rARK is greater than that of rABC.
Q.E.D.
Suppose ABCD is a quadrilateral, but it is not equilateral. The following steps will make
an equilateral quadrilateral equal to it, but having less perimeter.
X
89
[5] Putting together Steps 3 & 4, it is clear that quadrilateral KLMN equals
quadrilateral ABCD, but has less perimeter. And KLMN is equilateral.
Q.E.F.
THEOREM 9 Remark
It is of course possible that ABC should be isosceles, and thus AKC would have the same
perimeter as ABC, coinciding with it, and not less perimeter. But that does not affect the
proof, since ABCD has to have some unequal adjacent sides, being given as not
equilateral.
THEOREM 10: Any square of the same area as a rhombus has less perimeter
than the rhombus.
[2] DEKA is a square with the same perimeter as rhombus ABCD, because they both
have four sides equal to AD.
But DEKA = ALMD (parallelograms on same base, under same height)
and ALMD > ABCD (whole is greater than part)
so DEKA > ABCD
[3] Now any square of less area than DEKA has less perimeter than it.
But the square equal to ABCD has to be of less area than DEKA (by Step 2).
Therefore the square equal to ABCD has less perimeter than DEKA,
i.e. less perimeter than ABCD.
Q.E.D.
90
THEOREM 11: A square has the least perimeter of all quadrilaterals with the
same area, and the greatest area of all quadrilaterals with the same perimeter.
[2] If A is not a rhombus, and thus is not equilateral, then make an equilateral
quadrilateral R with the same area as A but less perimeter (Thm.9). If R happens to be a
square, then since it has the same area as square S, it will be identical to it, and thus again
it is clear that S, just like its twin R, must have less perimeter than A.
[3] If R is a mere rhombus, then it is clear that square S has less perimeter than it,
since they have equal areas (Thm.10). But R was made with less perimeter than A.
Therefore S has still less perimeter than A. Q.E.D.
Q.E.D.
91
THEOREM 11 Remarks
G D K
C 2. But what about comparing the
Q U
equilateral triangle and the square? Which
one of them makes “better” use of a given
perimeter? Which one holds more area for a
given perimeter? Let’s see. Say equilateral
A E B S R
triangle ABC and square SQUR each have a
perimeter of 12 inches.
Then SR = 3
and AB = 4.
92
3. If among rectilineal figures those which are more uniform and have a greater
number of sides can hold more area within a given perimeter, what plane figure would
hold the most area within a given perimeter?
THEOREM 12: How to extend a straight line so that the square on the original
line is equal to the rectangle contained by the whole new line and the extension.
[7] But £SK = £AS (SK = AS, being two sides of square ASKG)
So £AS = DS⋅BS
Q.E.F.
Line ASB is cut at S in a famous ratio called “The Golden Section,” which we will learn
more about in Chapter 6. In the next chapter, we will need this construction to make a
regular pentagon.
93
“HOOK”: MARION’S THEOREM.
In 1993 Mathematics Teacher published this interesting theorem: Take any triangle
ABC, and cut each side into three equal segments. Then join each vertex to the two
section-points on the opposite side. This will form a hexagonal figure in the middle.
This hexagonal figure has an area exactly one tenth that of the whole triangle. Similar
theorems result from cutting the opposite sides into other odd-numbered portions.
A
D G
Y
M E
N Q
J S
T
V Z
O
P
R W
B C
K F
94
Chapter Three
Circles
DEFINITIONS
A C
4. The side of a circular arc on which lies the straight line joining its endpoints is its
CONCAVE side. The other side is its CONVEX side.
For example if FH, the straight line joining the G
endpoints of arc FGH, lies below FGH, then the underside
of arc FGH is concave, and its top side is convex. F H
95
6. Two CIRCLES EXTERNALLY TANGENT TO EACH
OTHER are those which touch each other at some point on
their convex sides, but do not cut into each other there. A
CIRCLE INTERNALLY TANGENT TO ANOTHER N X
CIRCLE is one whose convex side touches the concave side
of another circle at some point without cutting out of it there.
For example, the two circles outside each other are
externally tangent at X, and the circle inside the other circle
is internally tangent to it at N.
D
8. An ANGLE IN A SEGMENTis the angle joining the
endpoints of a segment's base to any point on its
circumference.
For example, CDE is an angle in a segment.
C E
N
9. A rectilineal angle drawn inside a circle
is said to STAND ON the arc that it cuts off,
K and to be AT THE CENTER if its vertex
H
lies on the center of the circle, but AT THE
O
CIRCUMFERENCE if its vertex lies on the
L M circumference of the circle.
For example, angle HKL stands on
arc HL, and it is at the center of the circle. Angle MNO stands on arc MO, and it is at
the circumference.
when the vertex of every one of its angles lies on the circle's B
circumference. When this happens, the circle is said to be
CIRCUMSCRIBED AROUND A RECTILINEAL FIGURE. A D
For example, ABCDE is inscribed in a circle, and the
circle is circumscribed around it. E
96
11. A rectilineal figure is said to be CIRCUMSCRIBED H
12. A REGULAR POLYGON is one all of whose sides are equal and all of whose angles
are equal.
For example, a square, if we call it a polygon (often the name "polygon" is
reserved for rectilineal figures having more than four sides), is a regular polygon, since
all four of its sides are equal AND all four of its angles are equal. On the other hand, a
rhombus is not a regular figure, since not all of its angles are equal, although all its sides
are equal. Likewise a rectangle, although its four angles are all equal, is not regular,
since not all its sides are equal. A regular polygon must be both equilateral and
equiangular.
97
THEOREMS
Then M is the center of the circle. Why? First of all, the center has to lie somewhere
along DE, for if it did not, but was somewhere else like the point X, then
[7] Thus ∠ACX = ∠ACD (since both are right angles; we made ∠ACD right)
But that is impossible, since ∠ACD is only part of ∠ACX.
[8] Therefore our initial assumption, namely that the center of the circle does not lie
on the line DE, is itself impossible. So the center of the circle does lie on DE
somewhere.
[9] Since the center of the circle is equidistant from D and E, it must lie at the
midpoint of DE, that is, at M.
Q.E.F.
98
THEOREM 1 Remarks
1. From this Theorem it is plain that Whenever a line bisects any chord of a circle at
right angles, the center of the circle must lie on that line.
[3] So CA, the radius of the circle, is greater than CR. Therefore R lies inside the
circle. Thus every point along AB lies inside the circle.
Q.E.D.
THEOREM 2 Remarks
1. This Theorem is rather obvious for big chords drawn inside the circle, but what
about very small ones? The smaller the chord is, the closer it gets to the circumference of
the circle, and the less distinguishable from the circumference it becomes. Without this
Theorem, we might think that very small chords could actually coincide with a very small
part of the circumference, or that a very small portion of a circle is no different from a
straight line.
99
2. A corollary of this Theorem: no straight line can have more than two points in
common with the circumference of a circle. So a straight line cannot cut the
circumference of a circle more than twice.
THEOREM 3: If a straight line through the center of a circle bisects a chord not
drawn through the center, it cuts it at right angles.
[3] Thus ∠CMD = ∠CME, being corresponding angles of ΔCMD and ΔCME.
But these two angles are adjacent; therefore they are each right angles.
Thus AMB is at right angles to DME.
Q.E.D.
THEOREM 3 Question
Why must we stipulate that the bisected line is not through the center?
100
THEOREM 4: If a straight line through the center of a circle cuts a chord at
right angles, it bisects it.
D M E
Q.E.D.
THEOREM 5: If two straight lines in a circle cut each other, but their
intersection is not the center of the circle, then they do not bisect each other.
C
Imagine that AB and CD are drawn inside a circle, and
they cut each other at a point X, but X is not the center
of the circle. Then X cannot bisect both AB and CD.
Here's what happens if you suppose it does:
B
M
X [1] Assume CX = XD
and AX = XB
A D
[2] Find M, the center of the circle. (Thm. 1)
101
[3] Join MX.
[4] Now ∠CXM is a right angle, since M is the center and X is supposedly the
midpoint of CD (Thm. 3).
[5] But ∠BXM is a right angle, too, since M is the center and X is supposedly the
midpoint of AB (Thm. 3).
Q.E.D.
THEOREM 5 Questions
1. What if one of the lines is a diameter? Does that affect the proof?
2. Can one of the two lines (which cut each other not through the center) be bisected
by the other?
THEOREM 6: If two circles cut each other, they cannot have the same center.
C B
Conceive of two circles, circle A and circle B,
that cut each other at some point C. Then they
have different centers. Why?
M
A X
P
[2] Since circles A and B cut each other, each passes into and back out of the other, so
choose any point P on circle B that is outside circle A. Join MP.
102
[3] Since M is inside circle A (being its center), and P is outside circle A (that is how we
chose it), thus MP must pass out of circle A at some point, X. Thus MX is only part of
MP, and so
MX < MP
but MX = MC (these being radii of circle A)
so MC < MP
[4] Hence MC and MP, being unequal, are not radii of circle B. And thus M cannot be
the center of circle B. But M is the center of circle A. Therefore circles A and B have
different centers.
Q.E.D.
THEOREM 6 Remarks
The flip side of this Theorem is this: If two circles DO have the same center, then they
don't cut each other.
THEOREM 7: If two circles touch one another, then they cannot share the same
center.
[2] Since circle A touches circle B inside it, then at least some of circle B must be
outside of circle A. Choose any point P on circle B that is outside circle A. Join MP.
[3] Since M is inside circle A (being its center), and P is outside circle A (that is how we
chose it), thus MP must pass out of circle A at some point, X. Thus MX is only part of
MP, and so
MX < MP
but MX = MT (these being radii of circle A)
so MT < MP
103
[4] Hence MT and MP, being unequal, are not radii of circle B. And thus M cannot be
the center of circle B. But M is the center of circle A. Therefore circles A and B have
different centers.
Q.E.D.
THEOREM 7 Remarks
1. Notice that the proof of the Theorem is only about internally tangent circles.
What about externally tangent circles? Can they have the same center? Obviously not.
If they are outside each other, and touch each other at some point but don't cut into each
other there, then clearly they have different centers, because each circle's
center is inside it, and therefore outside the other one. Besides, nothing
prevents us from making an argument similar to that above for the case
of externally tangent circles.
2. Taking Theorems 6 and 7 together, we see now that If two distinct circles DO
have the same center, then their circumferences do not have any points in common at all.
Circles which have the same center are called "concentric" circles – like the circular
waves on the surface of a pond into which we have dropped a pebble.
THEOREM 8: If three lines drawn from one point inside a circle to three points
on its circumference are equal to each other, then that point is the center.
B
Imagine a circle with a point M inside it, and three
E
points along the circumference, A, B, C. If MA =
C MB = MC, then M has to be the center of the circle.
M Now the proof.
D
[1] Bisect BC at E; join ME.
A
[2] Bisect AC at D; join MD.
[3] Now AM = MC (we are given that the three original lines from M are equal)
and AD = DC (we bisected AC at D)
and MD is common to ΔAMD and ΔCMD
so the corresponding angles of ΔAMD and ΔCMD are equal (Side-Side-Side)
104
[4] Thus ∠ADM = ∠CDM, being corresponding sides of ΔAMD and ΔCMD. But
these two angles are also adjacent; therefore they are right angles.
[5] So MD is at right angles to AC (Step 4) and it also bisects AC (Step 2), and
therefore the center of the circle lies somewhere along MD, as we saw in the way to find
a center (Ch.3, Thm.1).
[6] But likewise we can prove that the center has to lie along ME somewhere, since
ME will also be at right angles to BC, and it bisects it.
[7] Therefore the center of the circle is a point common to both MD and ME. But M
is the only point common to ME and MD (since two different straight lines can never
have more than one point in common, because they cannot cut each other twice).
Therefore M is the center of the circle.
Q.E.D.
THEOREM 8 Remarks
1. Why 3 lines? If 2 lines drawn from one point to the circumference of a circle are
equal, isn't that enough to conclude that the point is the center? No. Just look back at the
diagram for this Theorem. AD = DC, and yet D is not the center of the circle. 3 is the
minimum number of equal lines required to conclude that we have found the center, and
4 is superfluous.
It often happens in mathematics (and elsewhere in life) that Three is enough. We
need at least 3 straight lines to make a rectilineal figure – two won't do. And things often
come in threes. For example, there are three basic relationships between two comparable
quantities: greater than, less than, equal to. And accordingly there are three main species
of triangle (equilateral, isosceles, and scalene), and three species of angle (right, obtuse,
and acute). If you are watchful for it, you will see, over and over again, that important
things often come in threes.
105
2. Can three equal lines be drawn to a circle from a point outside the circle? No. It
will be possible to draw two equal lines from it to the circle, but it will be impossible to
draw three equal lines to the circle. Assume for a moment
that a point P has been chosen outside a circle, and PE = PG
= PH. To see the impossibility of this, draw from center K K
the lines KE, KG, KH. Now, if PGK happens to be a single
straight line, then
E H
KG = HK (radii)
and GP = PH (they are assumed equal) G
so KG + GP = PH + HK
i.e. KP = PH + HK
which is impossible, since PHK is a triangle, and so side KP
has to be less than the sum of the remaining sides. P
THEOREM 9: The circumferences of two distinct circles cannot have more than
two points in common.
[3] Since circles 1 and 2 have common points at A and B, therefore they cannot have the
same center (Thms. 6 & 7). But M is the center of circle 1. Therefore M is not the center
of circle 2.
106
[4] Now if three equal straight lines from M fall upon the circumference of a circle, then
M will be its center (Thm.8). But M is not the center of circle 2 (Step 3), and hence three
equal straight lines cannot be drawn from M to the circumference of circle 2.
[5] Since MA, MB, MP are three equal straight lines from M (being radii of circle 1),
hence they do not all fall on the circumference of circle 2 (Step 4). But MA and MB do
fall on the circumference of circle 2 (given). Therefore MP does not.
[6] Therefore any random point P on circle 1 other than A and B cannot lie on circle 2.
Therefore circles 1 and 2 cannot have more points in common than A and B.
Q.E.D.
THEOREM 9 Question
So the maximum number of times two circles can cut each other is twice. Is it possible
for two circles to cut each other only once?
A
Suppose the circumferences of circles 1 and 2 have two
points in common, namely T and P. I say the circles cut
C each other, rather than touch each other, at these two
points.
T P
M [1] Join TP and bisect it at M. Draw a perpendicular to
TP at M, cutting circle 1 at A and B, and circle 2 at C and
1 D.
B
2 [2] Since TP is a chord in both circles, therefore it lies
D inside both (Thm.2). Thus the circles overlap each other.
[3] Since TP is a chord in both circles, therefore its perpendicular bisector is a diameter
of both circles (Thm.1). Since TM is perpendicular to these diameters, therefore the
square on TM equals the rectangles contained by the segments into which M divides the
diameters (Ch.2, Thm.6), i.e.
£TM = AM · MB
and £TM = CM · MD
thus AM · MB = CM · MD.
107
[4] Now MB cannot equal MD, since then B and D would be the same point, and thus
circles 1 and 2 would have three points in common, which is not possible (Thm.9).
Therefore they are unequal. Suppose
MB < MD.
But then, since the rectangles are equal, it is necessary that
AM > CM.
[5] Since MA > MC (Step 4), thus point A on circle 1 lies outside circle 2.
Since MB < MD (Step 4), thus point D on circle 2 lies outside circle 1.
Thus each circle falls partly outside the other.
[6] Since circles 1 and 2 partly overlap (Step 2) and each falls partly outside the other
(Step 5), therefore each cuts into and out of the other. Since T and P are the only points
shared by their circumferences, therefore these are the points at which they cut one
another.
THEOREM 10 Remarks
A corollary to this Theorem, or another way of stating it, is that If two circles touch one
another, whether internally or externally, their circumferences have no point in common
other than the one point of contact.
THEOREM 11: If one circle is internally tangent to another, the straight line
joining their centers (when extended) passes through their point of contact.
E
Circle 1 is internally tangent to circle 2 at point C. Find A, the
D center of circle 2, and join AC. I say that the center of circle 1
1
P lies along AC.
C
A
[1] Inside circle 1, pick any random point P not on line AC.
Join AP and extend it until it cuts circle 1 at D and circle 2 at
E. Join PC.
108
[3] So PC > PE (subtracting AP from each side in Step 2)
but PE > PD (whole and part)
so PC > PD
[4] Thus PC and PD, being unequal, are not radii of circle 1, and therefore P is not
the center of circle 1. Thus no point which is not on AC can be the center of circle 1.
Therefore the center of circle 1 lies along AC.
[5] Hence the straight line joining center A and the point of contact, C, passes
through the center of circle 1. And therefore the straight line joining the centers of the
circles, when extended, passes through the point of contact.
Q.E.D.
THEOREM 12: If two circles are externally tangent, the straight line joining
their centers passes through their point of contact.
2
1
Circle 1 and circle 2 are externally tangent at
point C. Find A, the center of circle 1, and B,
C B
and join AC, extending it through circle 2
A
until it meets it again at point B. I say that the
D
E
center of circle 2 lies along CB.
P
[1] Inside circle 2, pick any random point P not on line CB. Join AP, which must pass
out of circle 1 at a point (D), and into circle 2 at another point (E).
[4] Thus the straight line joining center A and the point of contact, C, passes through
the center of circle 2 when extended. That is, the line joining the centers passes through
the point of contact.
Q.E.D.
109
THEOREM 13: In any circle, equal chords are equally distant from the center.
[2] So EB = ½AB
So too CG = ½CD
[4] Therefore £EB = £CG (squares built on equal sides are equal)
[10] So ME = MG,
since the sides of equal squares have to be equal.
So the perpendicular distances of equal chords from the center of the circle are equal.
Q.E.D.
110
THEOREM 13 Remarks
Why do we call the perpendicular distance between a point and a line the distance
between them? Because 1. there is only one perpendicular distance, and 2. it is the least
distance.
THEOREM 13 Questions
Prove the converse, using the same diagram. Given that ME = MG, i.e. that the
perpendicular distances of chords AB and CD from the center are equal, prove that the
chords themselves are equal.
THEOREM 14: The diameter is the longest chord inside a circle, and chords
closer to the center are greater than those further away from it.
[3] But CR = AC
and CN = CB (since all these are radii of the circle)
Q.E.D.
111
P E
D That's the first part of the Theorem. For the next part,
take any other chord DE, whose perpendicular distance
N
from the center (namely CP) is greater than RN's
C perpendicular distance from the center (namely CG). I
say that RN > DE. Why?
G
[3] Now whenever we subtract a lesser thing from something, it leaves a greater
remainder than if we subtract something greater from it. So if we subtract £CG from
£CD, it leaves a greater remainder than if we subtract £CP from £CD. That is,
£CD – £CG > £CD – £CP
[5] So £CR – £CG > £CD – £CP (putting together Steps 3 & 4)
[8] i.e. RG > DP, since the side of a greater square is greater.
Thus 2RG > 2DP, since double a greater line remains greater than double the
lesser line.
Q.E.D.
112
THEOREM 15: A straight line drawn at right angles to the end of a circle's
radius is tangent to the circle.
[1] Choose any random point P along TG other than T. Join CP.
[2] Looking at triangle CPT, since angle CTP is right, therefore ∠CPT is acute.
[4] But CT is a radius of the circle. Therefore, since CP is greater than a radius of the
circle, P must lie outside the circle.
[5] But P is just a random point on TG other than T. Hence every point on TG other than
T itself lies outside the circle. Therefore TG is tangent to the circle at T.
Q.E.D.
THEOREM 15 Remarks
1. Will TG cut into the circle on the other side, namely to the right of CT? No.
Because ∠CTG is a right angle, therefore when we extend GT to the right, the angle
adjacent to it will also be a right angle, and so the exact same proof will apply on the
right side as well.
2. We could state the Theorem another way: a straight line drawn at right angles to
a circle’s radius has one and only one point in common with the circumference of the
circle, namely the endpoint of the radius to which it is drawn at right angles.
3. Notice that this Theorem gives us an easy construction for a tangent to any point
on the circumference of a circle: if the point is T, merely find the center of the circle
(Thm.1), say C, and join CT, and then draw a straight line at right angles to CT through
point T.
113
THEOREM 16: Any straight line drawn at less than a right angle to the end of a
circle's radius cuts into the circle.
P
S
A
[3] But B lies along the line AS, and A is another point on AS on the circumference of
the circle. Therefore line AS (extended, if need be) joins two points on the circumference
of the circle, and therefore it is a chord (Thm.2).
Q.E.D.
THEOREM 16 Remarks
1. From this Theorem it follows that it is impossible to draw two tangents to a circle
touching it at the same point. For each and every point on the circumference of a circle,
there is one and only one tangent, namely the straight line drawn through it at right angles
to the radius drawn to it.
114
2. This Theorem is truly surprising. To see why, draw the tangent AT at right angles
to CA, and draw a line AS making CAS an acute angle as close to a right angle as you
like. By the Theorem, AS must cut into the circle at A
and out again at some other point (very close to A).
Now there is a space between the circumference of the
circle and the tangent AT all the way down to the point C
A. And a straight line has no thickness, and so in a way
it doesn't take up any space. And yet we still can't find S
THEOREM 17: How to draw a straight line tangent to any circle from any point
outside it.
If I give you a circle M, and a point P outside it, can you draw a line from P tangent to
circle M? Sure. All you have to do is …
B
D
[1] Find the center, C.
[5] Join DP. This line DP is in fact tangent to circle M. Here's why:
[9] But CD is a radius of circle M, and so DP, drawn at right angles to CD, is tangent
to circle M (Thm.15).
Q.E.F.
115
THEOREM 18: If a straight line is tangent to a circle, then the radius joined to
the point of tangency is perpendicular to the tangent.
[2] If ∠2 were less than a right angle, then TN would cut the circle at T, and so NTM
would not be tangent to the circle (Thm.16). But NTM is tangent to the circle, and
therefore ∠2 is not less than a right angle.
[3] If ∠2 were more than a right angle, then ∠1 would be less than a right angle
(since together they add up to two rights), and so TM would cut the circle at T, and so
NTM would not be tangent to the circle (Thm.16). But NTM is tangent to the circle, and
therefore ∠2 is not more than a right angle.
[4] Since ∠2 is neither less than a right angle (Step 2), nor more than a right angle
(Step 3), therefore it is a right angle. That is, ∠CTN is a right angle.
Q.E.D.
THEOREM 18 Remarks
116
2. We can see from Theorem 18 that If a straight line is drawn at right angles to a
circle's tangent at the point of tangency, the line will pass through the center of the circle.
Use the same diagram as in Theorem 18. We are given that MTN is tangent at T, and we
want to show that the perpendicular at T passes through the center. Find center C and
join TC. Then by Theorem 18 TC is perpendicular to MTN. Therefore the line
perpendicular to MTN at the point of tangency passes through the center of the circle.
3. Prove that there are only two tangents to a circle from a given point outside it.
Q.E.D.
117
THEOREM 19 Remarks
B
M
1. Does it make any difference if CM goes between
the legs of the angles?
A D
E
2. The angle at the center and the angle at the
circumference do not actually have to be on the same arc in K
order for the theorem to hold. They need only be on equal
arcs. In a circle with center K let arc EF = arc HG. F
Choose a random point R on the circumference and draw
RH and RG. Then it is still true that H G
∠EKF = 2∠HRG
Start by drawing KH and KG. Now, since the arcs EF and HG are equal, therefore if pie-
piece EKF is rotated clockwise so that E is on G, then also F will be on H. Therefore KE
and KG will coincide while KF and KH also coincide. In other words, ∠EKF will
coincide with ∠GKH. Therefore
∠EKF = ∠GKH
but 2∠HRG = ∠GKH (Thm.19)
so 2∠HRG = ∠EKF
A C
[1] ∠1 = ½∠AMC,
since ∠1 is at the circumference, ∠AMC is at the center,
R and they stand on the same arc (Thm.19).
118
[2] ∠2 = ½∠AMC,
since ∠2 is at the circumference, ∠AMC is at the center, and they stand on the
same arc (Thm.19).
Q.E.D.
THEOREM 20 Remarks
R
E
1. As with the last theorem, this Theorem does not depend
on the angles at the circumference being on the same arc; they
need only be on equal arcs. So if arc EF = arc HG, and P and R K
P
are points chosen on the circumference, then
F
∠EPF = ∠HRG H G
Take center K, and draw KH and KG.
Now ∠HRG = ½∠HKG (Thm.19)
But ∠EPF = ½∠HKG (since arc EF = arc GH; Thm.19, Remark 2)
So ∠EPF = ∠HRG
3. Theorem 20 is just as true if the two angles are not in the same circle, but instead
are in two different but equal circles 1 and 2. That is, if ∠X at the circumference of
circle 1 stands on arc A, and ∠Z at the circumference of circle 2 stands on arc B, and arc
A = arc B, then also ∠X = ∠Z.
119
THEOREM 21: The opposite angles of a quadrilateral inscribed in a circle add
up to two right angles.
A
Imagine a quadrilateral ABCD whose four corners lie B
2
on the circumference of a circle.
Then ∠ABC + ∠ADC = two right angles
and ∠DCB + ∠DAB = two right angles. 4
Join AC and join BD to begin the proof. 1 3
C
[1] First ∠1 = ∠4 D
(both stand on arc AB; Thm.20)
[7] But since the angles of any quadrilateral add up to four right angles (since it is
made up of two triangles, each of whose angles add up to two right angles), and since
∠DCB + ∠DAB equal two rights, therefore the remaining angles of quadrilateral ABCD
must add up to the remaining two right angles. That is, ∠ABC + ∠ADC = two rights.
Q.E.D.
THEOREM 21 Remarks
1. It follows from this that a quadrilateral whose opposite angles do not add up to
two right angles cannot be inscribed in a circle. Take two identical equilateral triangles
and put two of their sides together – you now have a rhombus one pair of whose opposite
angles are 60° and 60°. Such a quadrilateral cannot be inscribed in a circle – draw it for
yourself and confirm it with a diagram.
A quadrilateral that can be inscribed in a circle is sometimes called a "cyclic"
quadrilateral. "Cyclic" comes from the Greek word for "circle". Since a pair of angles
that add up to two right angles are called supplementary angles, we can restate Theorem
21 like this: In cyclic quadrilaterals, opposite angles are supplementary.
120
A
2. The converse of Theorem 21 is also true, and it goes E
B
like this: If the opposite angles in a quadrilateral are
supplementary, then we can circumscribe a circle around
G
it. M
Suppose quadrilateral ABCD is such that its
opposite angles are supplementary. Bisect AB at E and BC C
D
at G. Draw lines perpendicular to AB and BC at E and G,
and where these two perpendiculars meet call M. Join MA,
MB, MC. A
B
Now ΔAEM ≅ ΔBEM (Side-Angle-Side) 2
so MA = MB
and ΔCGM ≅ ΔBGM (Side-Angle-Side)
so MB = MC D
1
Thus MA = MB = MC, and so the circle with center M and 3 C
radius MA will pass through A, B, and C. X
But will it pass through D, the other corner of quadrilateral ABCD? Yes, it must.
For suppose it did not, but rather D fell inside the circle. Then extend AD until it
cuts the circle at X. Join CX.
Now ∠3 + ∠2 = two rights (quadrilateral ABCX is inscribed in a circle)
but ∠1 + ∠2 = two rights (quadrilateral ABCD is given that way)
so ∠1 = ∠3, that is, an angle exterior to triangle CDX is equal to one of its interior
and opposite angles, which is impossible (Ch.1, Thm.14). So it is impossible for D to fall
inside the circle. Likewise it is impossible for it to fall outside the circle. Therefore D
falls on the circumference of the circle.
B
3. Theorem 21 has a cousin theorem about
quadrilaterals that are circumscribed around circles.
F
Consider quadrilateral ABCD, circumscribed around a
E
circle and so having its four sides tangent to the circle at
C
E, F, G, H. Although its opposite angles do not have to
A add up to two right angles, its opposite sides must have
the same sum, that is AD + BC = AB + DC.
H G
D
The proof is easy. Since AH is tangent to the circle at H,
and AE is tangent to it at E, therefore AH and AE are two tangents to the same circle
from the same point, and thus
AH = AE (Thm.18, Remark 1)
and HD = DG (Same reason)
and BF = BE (Same reason)
and CF = CG (Same reason)
so AH + HD + BF + CF = AE + DG + BE + CG
or (AH + HD) + (BF + CF) = (AE + BE) + (DG + CG)
i.e. AD + BC = AB + DC.
121
THEOREM 22: In any circle, the arcs cut off by equal chords are equal.
A R
Imagine a circle with any
center M and having two B
equal chords AB and CD in it M
cutting off arcs ARB and M
CLD. Then these two arcs (B) C
must be equal. To see the C
(A)
proof, draw these lines: MA,
D
MB, MC, MD. D L
[2] Since ΔAMB and ΔCMD are congruent, therefore if we were to rotate the pie-
piece MARB clockwise so that A is on C, then also B would be on D, and so the arc ARB
would then coincide with the arc CLD (for if it fell outside as the dotted line, the radii
from M would not all be equal!).
[3] Since the arcs ARB and CLD can be made to coincide with each other, therefore
they are equal.
Q.E.D.
THEOREM 22 Remarks
122
Thus arc ECD = arc ARB (arcs of equal chords are equal; Thm.22)
but arc CLD = arc ARB (that is given)
so arc CLD = arc ECD,
which is to say that the part is equal to the whole, which is impossible. So AB is not
greater than CD. Likewise we can prove that neither is it less. Therefore
AB = CD.
2. Theorem 22 and its converse are also true about chords and arcs in equal circles:
* If arc A in one circle equals arc B in an equal circle, then their chords are equal.
* If chord A in one circle equals chord B in an equal circle, then their arcs are equal.
D
R Suppose you have any arc of a circle, ARB. How
do you cut it into two equal parts? Like this:
A B
C
[2] Bisect AB at C.
Q.E.F.
123
THEOREM 23 Remarks
Have we done enough geometry now to cut any circular arc into 3 equal parts? No – that
is a problem for more advanced geometry, and its simplest solution involves the use of
conic sections. It is impossible to cut an arc of 60° into three equal parts, for example,
using nothing but circles and straight lines, which are the only tools we are allowing
ourselves in this book.
How about 4 equal parts? Of course. We simply bisect the arc once, and then
bisect each of its halves.
How about 5 equal parts? No. That is even more difficult than 3.
Neither can we cut any given arc into 6 or 7 equal parts. But we can cut any
given arc into 8 equal parts simply by repeated bisection (likewise with 16, 32, etc.).
R
Take any circle with diameter AB cutting it into two
semicircles, pick any point R along the circumference,
and then join AR and RB. Angle ARB is a right angle.
A B
To see it for yourself, start by picking any point T
on the other semi-circumference, and then join AT and
TB.
T
Q.E.D.
124
THEOREM 24 Remarks
G
X X
1
2 G
The converse of this Theorem is also
3 true, namely The circle whose
E
diameter is the hypotenuse of a right
F E F
triangle must pass through the vertex
of the right angle. If EGF is a right
triangle, and ∠EGF is the right angle,
then the circle having EF as its
diameter passes through point G. If possible, assume it doesn't, but instead G winds up
inside the circle. Then FG and the circle will intersect at some other point, X; join XE.
THEOREM 24 Questions
P
125
W 3. Prove that the angle in a segment of a circle
that is greater than a semicircle is acute, and that the
S T
angle in a segment that is less than a semicircle is
obtuse. Let ST divide a circle into two unequal
Z segments, i.e. one greater than a semicircle, and one
less. Find the center Z. Pick W and X at random on
each of the two arcs. Draw SW, WT, SX, and XT.
Draw the diameter TZY, and join WY. Start the
Y
proof by showing that ∠SWT is obtuse; then show
X
that ∠SXT is acute by using Theorem 21.
THEOREM 25: The angles between a tangent to a circle and any straight line
drawn through the circle from the point of tangency are equal to the angles in the
alternate segments of the circle.
D
Conceive of a circle with a straight line TPN
S
X tangent to it at point P, and any straight line
PS drawn through the circle and cutting it into
R two segments. Choose any point X on the arc
C
of one segment, and any point R on the arc of
the other. Then
∠SPN = ∠SXP
and ∠SPT = ∠SRP.
T P N
[2] Thus PD is at right angles to TPN, since TPN is tangent at P and C is the center of
the circle (Thm.18).
126
[6] So ∠SDP = ∠SPN,
because according to Steps 4 and 5, these two angles are complementary to the same
angle, namely ∠DPS.
[10] But ∠SPN + ∠SPT = two rights (they are adjacent angles)
Q.E.D.
[1] Now, MB is at right angles to AS, since MB is drawn from the center and it
bisects AS (Thm.3). So MBS and MBP are right triangles.
127
[3] Now, £TP = £MP – £MT (ΔMTP; Pythagorean Theorem)
Q.E.D.
THEOREM 26 Remarks
128
and EP · PD = £PT (Thm.26)
so EP · PD = AP · PS
2. The converse of Theorem 26 is also true. That is, if PSA is drawn through a
circle, and PT is drawn to the circle such that £PT = AP · PS, then PT is tangent to
the circle at T.
Proof: Two tangents from P can be drawn to the circle. A
THEOREM 26 Question
M
What if PSA goes through the center M? How will that
change the proof?
S
P
T
129
“HOOK”: THE MIQUEL POINT.
If ABC is any triangle, and E, D are any two points along AC, AB, and we join BE, CD,
we get a “dented triangle,” or a “Menelaos Figure.” There are four triangles in this
figure—two small ones and two larger, overlapping ones. If we circumscribe a circle
around each of these four triangles, the four circles will all cut each other at one point, p.
E B
p
C
130
“HOOK”: CENTER OF WEIGHT OF A TRIANGLE.
If you take any triangle ABC, bisect its sides, and join each vertex to the midpoint of the
opposite side, these three lines intersect at one point inside the triangle, Y. This point is
the center of weight of the triangle. If you were to make such a triangle out of some
rather uniformly dense material, and drill a hole through Y, then hang it on a small nail
through Y, you could rotate the triangle into any orientation and it would always be
balanced.
B
Take any three circles in one plane, so long as no one of them is completely inside
another one. Then it will be possible to take them in three pairs, and for each pair there
will be a pair of straight lines tangent to both circles and which intersect—as DPG, DNK
are each tangent to the two circles PN, GK. The three resulting points of intersection,
namely D, E, F, all lie in a straight line.
H
G A F
K
L Q
W
R
M
C
B T V S
P
N
U E
O
131
Chapter Four
Polygons
THEOREM 1: How to inscribe in a circle a triangle that is equiangular with a
given triangle.
Take any triangle you like, and call its angles 1, 2, 3. Take any circle you like – call it K.
Can we put inside circle K a triangle whose angles are equal to 1, 2, and 3? Of course.
B
K
[1] Draw a tangent TPN through any
2 point P along circle K’s circumference.
N
Q.E.F.
131
THEOREM 1 Questions
1. We can now inscribe a triangle of any shape inside a given circle. Obviously we
cannot inscribe a triangle of any size inside a given circle – some triangles are too big or
too small to be inscribed in a given circle. In fact, once we are given the three angles
which the inscribed triangle is to have, and once we are given the circle to inscribe it in,
the size of the inscribed triangle is already determined.
2. Try to prove that If two triangles are inscribed in the same circle and they are
equiangular, then they will be congruent, i.e. all their corresponding sides will also be
equal and they will have the same area. Consider using the converses of Theorems 20
and 22 in Chapter 3.
[1] Extend any side of ΔABC both ways, say BC (to D and E), forming the exterior
angles 4 and 5.
132
[4] Since PFK is drawn at right angles to the end of radius MF, it is tangent to the
circle at F (Ch.3, Thm.15). Likewise KRL is tangent at R, and PGL is tangent at G.
Thus the triangle PKL is circumscribed about circle M (Ch.3, Def. 11).
[5] Now the angles of quadrilateral FMRK add up to a total of four right angles (since
it is composed of two triangles, each of whose angles add up to two right angles).
But ∠KFM + ∠KRM = two rights, since each of these is a right angle.
Thus the remaining two angles in quadrilateral FMRK must add up to two rights,
i.e. ∠4 + ∠FKR = two rights,
Likewise ∠RLG = ∠2
Q.E.F.
THEOREM 2 Questions
1. How do we know the lines drawn at right angles to MF, MR, and MG at F, R, and
G will meet, as is asserted in Step 3?
2. What about a quadrilateral? If I give you a random quadrilateral and a circle, will
you be able to circumscribe around the circle a quadrilateral whose angles are equal to
the given quadrilateral? What must be true about the quadrilateral for it to be possible?
133
THEOREM 3: How to inscribe a circle in any triangle.
A
Now suppose I give you a triangle. Can you draw
inside it a circle to which all three sides are tangent?
E You can, like this:
G
D
[1] Take your triangle ABC and bisect ∠ABC and
∠ACB (any two angles will do).
Let the bisectors meet at D.
B C
F
Q.E.F.
134
THEOREM 3 Remarks
There is another important theorem lurking within Theorem 3, namely that The bisectors
of the three angles of any triangle all meet at one point. BD and CD bisect angles ABC
and ACB, and they meet at D. Join DA; if we can prove that it bisects angle BAC, then
all three angle-bisectors meet at one point.
First, DE = DG (proved in Step 6 of Theorem 3)
so £DE = £DG
so £AD – £DE = £AD – £DG (subtracting equals from the same thing)
but £AD – £DE = £AE (ΔADE; Pythagorean Theorem)
and £AD – £DG = £AG (ΔAGD; Pythagorean Theorem)
so £AE = £AG
i.e. AE = AG A
thus ΔADE ≅ ΔAGD by the Side-Side-Side
Theorem, since AE = AG, DE = DG, and AD is
common to both triangles. Therefore their E
corresponding angles are equal, so G
∠EAD = ∠GAD, D
So the 3 angular bisectors of a triangle all meet in one point. You can illustrate
this fact by carefully cutting out any triangle from a piece of paper and folding each of its
angles in half. Do the three creases all pass through one point?
THEOREM 3 Question
Prove that the bisectors of angles ABC and ACB must in fact meet, as is asserted in Step
1, and that they must meet inside the triangle, not outside it. To prove these bisectors
must meet, use the fact that any two angles of a triangle (such as rABC) add up to less
than 180°. To prove they must meet inside the triangle, assume for a moment that they
meet outside, and see whether they can really bisect the angles of the original triangle
anymore.
135
THEOREM 4: How to circumscribe a circle about any triangle.
Q.E.F.
THEOREM 4 Remarks
1. Notice that, unlike quadrilaterals, all triangles are “cyclic”; all triangles can have
a circle drawn through their three points.
136
2. There is an important theorem A
lurking within Theorem 4, namely this:
The three perpendicular bisectors of the
sides of any triangle all meet at one point. E
DM and EM meet at M, and these are the D
perpendicular bisectors of AB and AC. M
Drop MX perpendicular to BC, and if we
can show that it bisects BC then we will C
have proved that the perpendicular X
B
bisectors of all three sides meet at M.
THEOREM 4 Questions
1. What happens if ∠BAC is a right angle? What does BC become in relation to the
circumscribed circle? Where will center M fall? What happens if ∠BAC is obtuse?
Where will M fall then?
2. Prove that the two lines drawn perpendicular to AB and AC at D and E must in
fact meet, as is asserted in Step 2. Start by joining DE, and you should see immediately
that the perpendiculars at D and E must make angles less than two right angles on one
side of DE.
137
THEOREM 5: How to inscribe a square in any circle.
[2] Draw AB, BC, CD, and DA, forming quadrilateral ABCD inscribed in circle M.
[7] Since BMD is a diameter, therefore ∠BAD is a right angle (Ch.3, Thm.24). For
the same reason every other angle of quadrilateral ABCD is a right angle.
[8] Since ABCD is both equilateral (Step 6), and also right angled (Step 7),
ABCD is a square.
Q.E.F.
138
THEOREM 5 Questions
THEOREM 6: How to make an isosceles triangle whose base angles are each
double its peak angle.
X Recall that in every isosceles triangle the base angles are equal to each
other. But, for the sake of the upcoming Theorem 7, we want to make a
particular kind of isosceles triangle in which each base angle is double the
2X 2X peak angle X. Here’s how:
N T P
[2] Circumscribe a circle about rAST. (Thm.4)
Since £AS = AP · PS (Step 1)
thus £PT = AP · PS (PT = AS; Step 1)
thus PT is tangent to the circumscribed circle (see Ch.3, Thm.26, Remark 2).
[4] Hence the supplements of these angles are also equal to each other,
i.e. ∠ATP = ∠TSP
[5] But ∠TPA = ∠TPS (they are actually the same angle)
thus rAPT is equiangular with rTSP (Ch.1, Thm.29)
139
[6] Hence rTSP is also isosceles, so
PT = ST
but PT = AS (Step 1)
so AS = ST
so rAST is also isosceles.
Q.E.F.
THEOREM 6 Remarks
1. The triangle we have constructed is called The Golden Triangle, for reasons we
will understand later. Can you find another golden triangle in the construction diagram
other than rATP? Prove it.
2. What are the angles of a golden triangle in degrees? How many degrees is the
peak angle? How many degrees is one of the base angles? If we call the peak angle X,
each base angle is 2X, thus the sum of the angles in the whole triangle is 5X. But this
must be 180°. Therefore X = 180° ÷ 5, which is 36°. So the peak angle is 36°, and
each base angle is 72°.
A
Imagine you have a circle A, and you want
to draw a regular pentagon inside it (that is, 1
a five-sided polygon that is equilateral and B E
140
[2] In the circle inscribe rACD whose angles equal those of triangle T (Thm.1).
Thus ½∠ADC = ∠1
and ½∠ACD = ∠1
[4] Now, ½∠ADC = ∠ADB (we bisected ∠ADC with DB; Step 3)
but ½∠ADC = ∠1 (Step 2)
so ∠ADB = ∠1
[6] And all these equal angles are at the circumference. Therefore the arcs on which
they stand are all equal to each other (Ch.3, Thm.20, Converse proved in Remarks),
[7] Since all these arcs are equal, the chords joining their endpoints are all equal, too
(Ch.3, Thm. 22, Converse proved in Remarks). That is
AB = BC = CD = DE = EA.
[8] Now ∠ABC stands on three of the five equal arcs, namely on
arc CD + arc DE + arc EA.
Likewise ∠BCD, ∠CDE, ∠DEA, ∠EAB each stand on three of the five equal arcs.
Therefore these five angles stand on equal arcs.
[9] And all five of these angles standing on equal arcs are at the circumference.
Therefore they are equal (Ch.3, Thm.20, proof in Remarks).
That is, ∠ABC = ∠BCD = ∠CDE = ∠DEA = ∠EAB.
[10] Thus the pentagon ABCDE, inscribed in the circle, is both equilateral (Step 7) and
equiangular (Step 9). Therefore it is a regular pentagon.
Q.E.F.
141
THEOREM 7 Remarks
THEOREM 7 Questions
G
1. How many degrees is each angle of the regular pentagon?
Start by recalling that ∠HGK is 72° in isosceles triangle HGK.
H K
142
E F
Take any circle; call its center M. We want to make
a regular hexagon inside it, that is, we want to
inscribe in it a six-sided polygon all of whose sides M
and angles are equal. D A
[2] Make an equilateral triangle on MA; thus its vertex F will lie on the
circumference of the circle (Ch.1, Thm.1).
[3] Extend AM to D.
Make an equilateral triangle on MD; thus its vertex E will also lie on the
circumference of the circle.
[5] Since all three angles of an equilateral triangle are equal, any one of its angles is
one third of two right angles.
so ∠FMA = one third of two rights
and ∠EMD = one third of two rights.
and ∠EMF must equal one third of two rights also, since these three angles
add up to a straight line or 180°.
[8] In the same way, we can prove that ΔCMB and ΔMBA are equilateral triangles,
too, whose side is the radius of the circle.
[9] Therefore the sides of hexagon ABCDEF are the sides of six identical equilateral
triangles, and so all of its sides are equal. And each of the angles of hexagon ABCDEF is
composed of two angles of an equilateral triangle, and so all of its angles are equal.
Therefore hexagon ABCDEF, inscribed in the circle, is a regular hexagon.
Q.E.F.
143
THEOREM 8 Remarks
It is amazing that the radius of a circle fits inside its circumference exactly six times.
THEOREM 8 Questions
1. How many degrees are in one angle of an equilateral triangle? How many
degrees are in one angle of a regular hexagon?
tiles, since we leave gaps. Incidentally, can you identify the shape of 4 6
144
THEOREM 9: How to inscribe a regular decagon in any circle.
K C
[1] Inscribe a regular pentagon inside the
circle, ACEGK (Thm.7). M
H D
[2] Bisect each of the five equal arcs cut off
by its sides, namely arc AC at B, arc CE at D, arc
G E
EG at F, arc GK at H, and arc KA at L.
F
[3] Draw AB, BC, CD, DE, EF, FG, GH, HK, KL, LA.
[4] Since the five arcs cut off by the sides of the pentagon are equal, their halves are
equal. And since those ten arcs are equal, the chords joining their endpoints are equal
(Ch.3, Thm.22 Converse), i.e.
AB = BC = CD = DE = EF = FG = GH = HK = KL = LA
Thus the decagon ABCDEFGHKL is equilateral.
[5] Draw MA, MB, MC, thus forming isosceles triangles AMB and BMC.
[7] Similarly we can prove that all ten of the isosceles triangles having a side of the
decagon as base and having center M as vertex are identical. And therefore they all have
the same base angle. But every angle of the decagon is equal to two of these identical
base angles (e.g. ∠ABC = ∠MBA + ∠MBC), and so all of the angles of the decagon are
equal.
[8] Since decagon ABCDEFGHKL, inscribed in the circle, is both equilateral (Step
4) and equiangular (Step 7), it is regular.
Q.E.F.
145
THEOREM 9 Remarks
Obviously, we can also do the 16-sided, by starting with the regular octagon (the
“stop sign”) and bisecting.
Now what about the regular 17-sided figure? (This figure is called a regular
“heptadecagon.”) Believe it or not, we actually can make it using nothing but circles and
straight lines! This was not known until the great German mathematician Carl Friedrich
Gauss (1777 – 1855) discovered it. He also found the general formula for determining
when it is possible to make a regular polygon of a given prime number of sides using
nothing but circles and straight lines, and when not.
146
A
B 2. Having mentioned the 12-sided regular polygon or
dodecagon, it is worth adding here an interesting little
D
C theorem about it: Its area is exactly 3 times that of the square
on the radius of the circle in which it is inscribed.
M
Given: Regular dodecagon ABC etc. in circle with center M.
Prove: The dodecagon’s area = 3 £BM.
Now by the regularity of the figure, AB = BC, and ∠ABD = ∠CBD, but BD is common
to triangles ABD and CBD. Hence they are congruent, and so the adjacent angles ADB
and CDB are right angles. Therefore AD is the height of rMAB, taking BM as base.
Since rMAB is half the rectangle of that height and on that base, i.e. it is half rectangle
MB · AD, therefore 12 triangles such as MAB equal 6 such rectangles. Therefore
Area Dodecagon = 6 MB · AD
Area Dodecagon = 3 MB · AC
And since AC cuts off one sixth of the circumference of the circle, it is the side of the
regular hexagon, which is equal to the radius of the circle. Therefore AC = MB, so that
the rectangle MB · AC is the same as the square on MB, or the square on the radius.
Hence
THEOREM 9 Questions
147
“HOOK”: THE 3-4-5 TRIANGLE AND THE CIRCLE.
B
If EP is 3 units of length, and PB is 4, and BE
is 5, then EPB is a “3-4-5 right triangle.” If we
inscribe the circle in it, center C, its radius will
have a length of 1 unit.
C
A
T
P
N
M
148
“HOOK”: BRIANCHON’S THEOREM.
Take any circle and draw a tangent to it, RS, of whatever length you please. From S,
draw another tangent, ST. Continue doing this so that you end up with a hexagonal
figure circumscribed about the circle, RSTVWZ. Join the “opposite” vertices of this
figure: RV, SW, TZ. These three straight lines will intersect in a single point.
Z
X
V
W
In a circle with center O and a unit-long radius OR, draw a regular polygon of any
number of sides you like, N, using R itself as the starting vertex. If we now join R to all
the other vertices, we
get chords (such as B
RA, RB, RC, etc.).
Since we are calling
the radius “1,” it is C A
decided for us what
we have to call each
of the other chords. If
we then multiply all
the lengths of these O
chords together, what D R
will the result be? It
will always be N. For
instance, if our
polygon is a hexagon,
the chord-product will
be 6. If an octagon, 8. E G
And so on.
F
149
Chapter Five
Proportion in General
DEFINITIONS
1. A lesser quantity is said TO MEASURE a greater one if it goes into it exactly a whole
number of times.
For example, a foot measures a yard, since it goes into it exactly three times; but
it does not measure a meter, since three feet is less than a meter, but four feet is more
than a meter.
2. When a lesser quantity measures a greater one, the lesser is called A MEASURE of
the greater, and the greater is called A MULTIPLE of the lesser.
For example, a foot is a measure of a yard, and a yard is a multiple of a foot. If
B is a multiple of A, say 3 times A, then the shorthand notation for this is B = 3A, which
reads " B is three A", or " B is three times A".
4. Whenever two quantities are capable of exceeding each other by being multiplied
enough times, the relative size of one to the other is called a RATIO.
For example, a foot, when multiplied four times, exceeds a yard, and a yard, when
multiplied two times, exceeds four feet. So the relation of a foot to a yard is a "ratio",
namely the ratio of 1 to 3, and the yard also has a ratio to the foot, namely that of 3 to
1.
But a line does NOT have a ratio to an area, such as a rectangle. Even though
each is a kind of quantity, the line has no area at all, and so no multiple of it can ever
exceed the area of the rectangle. There is, then, no comparison of these two quantities
with respect to size.
If a quantity A has a ratio to another quantity B, the shorthand notation for their
ratio is A : B, which reads "A to B". The order of the terms in a ratio makes a
difference. For example, if A has to B the ratio of 1 : 2 , then A is HALF of B. On the
other hand, if A has to B the ratio of 2 : 1 , then A is the DOUBLE of B.
5. The first term in a ratio is called its ANTECEDENT, and the second term in a ratio is
called its CONSEQUENT.
149
6. Given four quantities in two ratios, taking CORRESPONDING MULTIPLES of them
means taking equimultiples of the antecedents, and again taking equimultiples of the
consequents.
For example, given quantities A, B, C, D in the ratios A : B and C : D, if we
take multiples of A and B such as 3A and 5B, then the corresponding multiples of C
and D are 3C and 5D.
7. One pair of quantities in a ratio is said to COMPARE THE SAME WAY as another
pair when each pair is the ratio of a greater to a lesser, or when each is the ratio of a lesser
to a greater, or when both pairs are equalities.
For example, the numbers in the ratio 5 : 3 and those in the ratio 7 : 4 compare
the same way, since 5 > 3 and 7 > 4.
Again, the numbers in the ratio 5 : 5 and those in the ratio 7 : 7 compare the
same way, since 5 = 5 and 7 = 7.
But the numbers in the ratios 6 : 4 and 9 : 12 do not compare the same way,
since 6 > 4 but 9 < 12.
8. If the multiples of two quantities always compare the same way as the corresponding
multiples of two other quantities, then the first two quantities have the SAME RATIO as
the other two.
For example, suppose you have two ratios A : B and C : D. And suppose their
corresponding multiples compare the same way, e.g.
5A > 3B and 5C > 3D
2A < 4B and 2C < 4D
and so on. If this is true for all their corresponding multiples, then A has to B the
same ratio that C has to D.
9. If one quantity has to a second the same ratio that a third has to a fourth, then the four
quantities are said to be PROPORTIONAL.
If quantity A has to B the same ratio that C has to D, the shorthand notation for
that proportion is A : B = C : D , which reads "A is to B as C is to D", or, if you
prefer, "the ratio of A to B is the same as the ratio of C to D".
The four terms in a proportion need not all be different. For example, three terms
X, Y, Z can be in proportion like this: X : Y = Y : Z.
10. By contrast, when it is possible to find a multiple of a 1st quantity greater than some
multiple of a 2nd, but the corresponding multiple of a 3rd quantity is not greater than the
corresponding multiple of a 4th, then the 1st has to the 2nd a GREATER RATIO than the
3rd has to the 4th.
For example, take 3, 5, 6, and 17 in that order. Let's multiply 3 and 5 by 4 and 2
respectively, and likewise multiply 6 and 17 by 4 and 2 respectively.
150
Notice that 4(3) > 2(5), whereas 4(6) < 2(17). We took multiples of 3 and 5, and
then corresponding multiples of 6 and 17, but the two pairs of multiples do not compare
the same way. Since the multiple of 3 exceeded the multiple of 5, whereas the
corresponding multiple of 6 fell short of the corresponding multiple of 17, therefore 3 has
to 5 a greater ratio than 6 has to 17. The way to write this is 3 : 5 > 6 : 17.
Again, take 5, 2, 3 and 4 in that order. Multiply 5 and 2 by 8 and 6, and
also 3 and 4 by 8 and 6.
Now 8(5) > 6(2) but 8(3) = 6(4)
hence 5 : 2 > 3 : 4.
11. If one term in a ratio is not greater than the other, then it is either less than or equal to
it. The symbol for this is ≤. Again, if one term in a ratio is not less than the other, then it
is either greater than or equal to it. The symbol for this is ≥ .
Using these symbols, we can define “greater ratio” as follows.
If A : B > C : D,
then for some pair of numbers n and m it will happen that
nA > mB but nC ≤ mD.
151
THEOREMS
3A 3B
3A + 3B = 3(A + B)
5A + 5B + 5C = 5(A + B + C)
and so on.
Q.E.D.
152
THEOREM 1 Remarks
2. Another very basic truth about multiples is this: If we multiply a quantity by one
number, and then the result by another number, it makes no difference which multiplier is
used first. For example, if we double A and then triple its double, we get 6 times A, and
again if we triple A and then double its triple, we still get 6 times A. In other words,
3(2A) = 2(3A).
Here's why.
A B C D
[3] Restating the information in Step 2, but putting B & D first in each case, we have
if 3B < 5A, then 3D < 5C
but if 3B > 5A, then 3D > 5C,
and that will be true for any multiples of B and A, and the corresponding multiples of D
and C.
[4] So taking any multiples of B and A, the corresponding multiples of D and C must
compare the same way. Therefore
B:A = D:C (Def. 8).
Q.E.D.
153
THEOREM 2 Remarks
THEOREM 3: Two ratios that are the same with a third ratio are the same as
each other.
[5] So, taking any multiples of A and B, it turns out that they must compare the same
way as the corresponding multiples of C and D.
Therefore A : B = C : D. (Def. 8)
Q.E.D.
154
THEOREM 3 Remarks
1. That two quantities equal to the same thing are equal to each other is a self-
evident axiom. But the fact that two ratios the same as a third ratio are also the same as
each other needs to be proved, because “same ratio” has a rather involved definition.
2. Notice that it is not necessary for all 4 quantities to have a ratio in order for the
Theorem to be true. For example, two lines may have the same ratio as two numbers (for
example, the ratio of being double), and two areas may also have that same ratio. Then it
will follow that the two lines and the two areas have the same ratios, even though neither
line has any ratio to either area.
THEOREM 4: No ratio can be greater than another ratio, and at the same time
less than it.
A B C D
For some pair of numbers, say 7 and 3,
Now, multiply both sides of the top two inequalities by N, and multiply both sides of the
bottom two inequalities by 7, and we get four new inequalities:
Q.E.D.
155
THEOREM 4 Remarks
We can now see that just as any two comparable quantities must either be equal, or one
greater than the other, likewise any two ratios must either be the same or one must be
greater than the other. Consider any two ratios, A : B and C : D. Either all multiples of
C and D corresponding to multiples of A and B compare in the same way, or some
don’t. If all do, then the two ratios are the same (Def. 8). If some do not, then one ratio
will be greater, and by the present Theorem, the other must be less.
Given: Quantities A, B, C, D.
Numbers n and m such that
nA = mB and nC = mD
[1] Take any random multiples of A and B, say xA and yB, where x and y are any
numbers you please. Suppose first that xm > ny.
Q.E.D.
156
THEOREM 5 Remarks:
THEOREM 6: Equal quantities have the same ratio to any one quantity.
A 2A
Take any two equal quantities A and B, and
any third quantity C to which they have a B 2B
[4] Thus any multiples of A and C must compare the same way as the corresponding
multiples of B and C. Therefore
A:C = B:C (Def. 8).
Q.E.D.
THEOREM 6 Remarks
1. We used the numbers 2 and 3 in this Theorem, but there is nothing special about
them – if you look at the proof carefully, you will see that no Step depends on those
specific numbers. We could have used general symbols for any two numbers (such as n
and m) just as easily.
3. It should also be clear that the same quantity has the same ratio to equal
quantities: If A = B, then C : A = C : B. For, by the present Theorem, A : C = B : C,
but by Theorem 2, these are proportional inversely, i.e. C : A = C : B.
157
THEOREM 7: How to find equimultiples of two unequal quantities such that the
multiple of the greater will be greater than some multiple of a third quantity, while the
multiple of the lesser will be less.
Believe it or not, no matter how close A and B are to being equal, no matter how small
the difference between them is, we can always do it. Here's how:
[2] There must also be a first multiple of C that is greater than 9B.
Let it be 4C.
Since 4C is the first multiple of C that exceeds 9B,
hence 9B is greater than or equal to 3C
so C + 9B is greater than or equal to 4C (adding C to each)
We did it!
Q.E.F.
THEOREM 7 Remarks:
1. As with Theorem 6, there is nothing special about the numbers 9 and 4 occurring
in this Theorem. Use n and m, or some other pair of numbers, if you prefer.
158
2. Let's try a numerical example. Let
A = 20
B = 19
C = 23
We want to multiply 20 and also 19 by the same number, so that the multiple of 20 is
greater than some multiple of 23, while the multiple of 19 is less.
Following what we did in the Theorem, (A – B) = 1. And the first multiple of this
that is greater than 23 is 24. That is Step [1]. Following Step [2], we next find the first
multiple of 23 that is greater than 19 × 24. Well,
19 × 24 = 456
and 20 × 23 = 460, so that is the first multiple of 23 that is greater than 19 × 24.
According to the Theorem, the multiples satisfying the requirements are:
24 × A = 480
24 × B = 456
20 × C = 460
3. Find a way to multiply 36 and 35 by the same number so that the multiple of 36
exceeds some multiple of 57, but the multiple of 35 does not.
THEOREM 8: Of two unequal quantities, the greater one has a greater ratio to
any other quantity than the lesser one has to it.
A
Let A and B be unequal quantities, A the greater one,
B
and C any other quantity comparable with them. Then
A : C > B : C. C
[1] Since A > B, therefore we can find a multiple of A that is greater than some
multiple of C, while the same multiple of B is less (Thm.7). Suppose then that
5A > 3C
but 5B < 3C.
Q.E.D.
159
THEOREM 8 Remarks
1. Here is a numerical example. Since 7 > 3, then if we take any third number, such
as 5, it follows that 7 : 5 > 3 : 5.
2. Also, of two unequal quantities, any other quantity has to the lesser one a greater
ratio. Say A and B are unequal, A the greater, and C is any third quantity comparable to
them. Then C : B > C : A. Why?
Since A > B, we can find a multiple of A that is greater than some multiple of C,
while the same multiple of B is less (Thm.7). Say
3C > 5B
but 3C < 5A.
Therefore it is possible to take multiples of C and B (namely 3C and 5B), such that the
multiple of C is greater than that of B, while the same multiple of C is less than the
corresponding multiple of A. Therefore
C:B > C:A (Def. 10).
Here's why: A B C D
160
[3] So 5A > 2B (Step 1)
but 5C < 2D (Step 2)
And therefore it is possible to take a multiple of A that is greater than some multiple of B
whereas the corresponding multiple of C is less than the corresponding multiple of D.
Therefore A:B > C:D (Def.10)
Q.E.D.
THEOREM 9 Remarks
THEOREM 10: Quantities having the same ratio to the same quantity are equal.
161
[2] If A were less than B, then A:C < B:C (Thm.8)
But in fact A:C = B:C (given)
Therefore A is not less than B.
[3] Since A is not greater than B, nor is it less than B, therefore it is equal to B.
Q.E.D.
THEOREM 10 Remarks
2. This Theorem is an important tool for proving the equality of all kinds of
quantities. Whenever we can derive a proportion such as this: X : Z :: Q : Z, we can
conclude from this Theorem that X = Q.
THEOREM 11: Of two quantities, the one having a greater ratio to any third
quantity is greater.
A
Suppose you have three quantities A, B, C, and A : C > B : C.
B
Then A > B.
C
Proof:
[3] Since A is not equal to B, nor is it less than B, therefore it is greater than B.
Q.E.D.
162
THEOREM 11 Remarks
Also, of two quantities, the one to which any third quantity has a lesser ratio is greater.
Suppose that C : B > C : A. Then it has to be that A > B. Why?
(1) If A = B, then C : B = C : A (Thm.6, Remark 3)
but C:B > C:A (given)
Therefore A is not equal to B.
(2) If A < B, then C : A > C : B (Thm.8, Remark 2)
but C:B > C:A (given)
and two ratios cannot be greater than each other (Thm.4).
Therefore A is not less than B.
(3) Since A is not equal to B (Step 1), and A is not less than B (Step 2),
therefore A is greater than B.
THEOREM 12: If the first term in a proportion is greater than the third, then the
second will be greater than the fourth (but if less, less, and if equal, equal).
Proof:
A B C D
163
So B is not less than D.
Q.E.D.
THEOREM 13: Any two quantities have the same ratio as their equimultiples,
taken in corresponding order.
[4] So, taking any multiples of A and B, it turns out that the corresponding multiples
of 3A and 3B must compare the same way. Therefore A : B = 3A : 3B (Def. 8).
Q.E.D.
164
THEOREM 13 Remarks
1. It follows also that two quantities have the same ratio as their corresponding
measures. For example: A : B = ⅓A : ⅓B.
The reason is that A and B are equimultiples of ⅓A and ⅓B, and so, by the
present Theorem, the four of them are proportional.
165
THEOREM 14: Alternating the terms in a proportion makes a new proportion.
Suppose that A : B = C : D.
Then also A : C = B : D.
Here's why: A B C D
[4] So, taking any multiples of A and C, it turns out that the corresponding multiples
of B and D must compare in the same way. Therefore
A:C = B:D (Def. 8)
Q.E.D.
THEOREM 14 Remarks
1. Of course, the proportion will not alternate unless all four quantities are
comparable. For example, if two lines have the same ratio as two areas, we cannot
alternate the proportion, since then we would be saying that a line has to an area the same
ratio that another line has to another area, whereas, in fact, a line does not have any ratio
to an area at all.
2. The new ratios resulting from alternating the terms in the original proportion do
not have to be the same as the ratios in the original proportion. For example, given
2 : 4 = 3 : 6,
if we alternate that proportion, we get a new proportion:
2 : 3 = 4 : 6.
But these two new ratios are not the same as the two original ratios.
166
THEOREM 15: If any two ratios are the same as a third, then the sums of their
corresponding terms also have that same ratio.
A B C D E F
[4] Therefore, taking any multiples of A and B, we find that whenever they are
unequal, the corresponding multiples of (C + E) and (D + F) are also unequal and in the
same order. Therefore A : B = C + E : D + F.
Q.E.D.
THEOREM 15 Remarks
167
Take any multiples of A + B and B, e.g. 2(A + B) and 3B.
Take the corresponding multiples of C + D and D, i.e. 2(C + D) and 3D.
That is, taking any random multiples of (A + B) and B, they must compare the same way
as the corresponding multiples of (C + D) and D. Therefore A + B : B = C + D : D.
Q.E.D.
Notice that this Theorem does not depend on A, B, C, and D being all comparable
quantities. A and B must be comparable, and C and D also, but A and B might be
volumes, and C and D might be areas.
THEOREM 16: If any two ratios are the same as a third, then the differences of
their corresponding terms also have that same ratio.
Suppose that A : B = C : D
and also that A : B = E : F
then A : B = (C – E) : (D – F)
A B C D E F
We will start by proving that (C – E) and (D – F) have the same ratio as E and F, and
from there it will be easy to show they have the same ratio as A and B. Accordingly,
168
[2] Now, C : D = E : F,
as is clear from what is given. Therefore, alternately
C:E = D:F (Thm.14)
So if 3C > (5 + 3)E then 3D > (5 + 3)F (Def. 8)
i.e if 3C > 5E + 3E then 3D > 5F + 3F (Thm.1)
so if 3C – 3E > 5E then 3D – 3F > 5F (subtracting 3E and 3F)
so if 3(C – E) > 5E then 3(D – F) > 5F (Thm.1)
[4] So, taking random multiples of (C – E) and E, they must compare the same way
as the corresponding multiples of (D – F) and F. Therefore
(C – E) : E = (D – F) : F (Def. 8)
Q.E.D.
THEOREM 16 Remarks
169
then 2A – 2B > 3B (Thm.1)
so 2A > 5B (adding 2B to each side)
thus 2C > 5D (since A : B = C : D)
so 2C – 2D > 3D (subtracting 2D from each side)
i.e. 2(C – D) > 3D. (Thm.1)
That is, taking any random multiples of (A – B) and B, we find they must compare the
same way as the corresponding multiples of (C – D) and D.
Therefore A–B:B = C–D:D (Def. 8)
Q.E.D.
THEOREM 17: If the antecedents in one proportion are also the antecedents in
a second proportion, then a new proportion arises by taking the consequents of the first
proportion as antecedents, and the consequents of the second proportion as consequents.
B D
A E C F
170
[2] So C : 2D < A : 3E (Step 1)
but A : 3E = C : 3F (since A : E = C : F; & Thm.13 Remark 3)
thus C : 2D < C : 3F
therefore 2D > 3F (Thm.11 Remarks)
[4] That is, taking any random multiples of B and E, they must compare the same
way as the corresponding multiples of D and F.
Therefore B : E = D : F. (Def. 8)
Q.E.D.
THEOREM 17 Remarks
3. It is not necessary for the antecedents of the two proportions to be the same in
order for the Theorem to work; they need only be proportional. Thus
if A:B=C:D
and E:F=G:H
and A : E = C : G (i.e. the antecedents of the first two proportions are proportional)
then B : F = D : H (i.e. the consequents of the first two proportions are proportional).
If you don't believe it, here is the proof:
A : B = C : D (given)
A : E = C : G (given)
so B : E = D : G (Thm.17)
so E : B = G : D (Thm.2)
171
but E : F = G : H (given)
so B : F = D : H (Thm.17). Q.E.D.
THEOREM 18: If the extreme terms in one proportion are also the extreme
terms in a second proportion, a new proportion arises by taking the middle terms of the
first proportion as extremes, and the middle terms of the second proportion as middles.
Suppose that A : B = C : D
and also that A : E = F : D
then B:E = F:C
172
[2] So C : 3D < F : 5D (Step 1)
but F : 5D = 3F : 15D (Thm.13; multiplying by 3)
thus C : 3D < 3F : 15D
[5] That is, taking any random multiples of B and E, they must compare to each other
the same way as the corresponding multiples of F and C compare to each other.
Therefore B:E = F:C (Def. 8)
Q.E.D.
THEOREM 18 Remarks
2. As a mnemonic device for remembering the proportion that arises out of the
original two proportions, think of it as forming a “letter U”: if you look at B, E, F, and C,
in the original two given proportions, you are tracing out a letter “U”. And that is the
order in which they form a proportion: B : E = F : C. So we might call this “The U-
Theorem”, and we might call the procedure of forming a proportion in this way “Tracing
the U”. Ancient geometers called this a “perturbed proportion.”
3. For the Theorem to work, the extremes need not be the same, but only
proportional in the order of the letter U. Thus
if A:B = C:D
and E:F = G:H
and A:E = H:D (i.e. extremes of the 1st two proportions are proportional)
then B : F = G : C (i.e. the middles of the 1st two proportions are proportional)
173
First A:B = C:D (given)
and A:E = H:D (given)
so B:E = H:C (Thm.18)
so E:B = C:H (inverting)
but E:F = G:H (given)
so B:F = G:C (Thm.18)
Q.E.D.
There are many different kinds of “means” or “middles” between any two comparable
magnitudes, e.g. between two line-lengths. Three of the most interesting are the
arithmetic mean (or average), the geometric mean (or mean proportional), and the
harmonic mean:
ARITHMETIC MEAN
Definition: ma – a = b – ma
Formula: ma = (a + b)/2
GEOMETRIC MEAN
Definition: a : mg = mg : b
Formula: mg = √ab
HARMONIC MEAN
Formula: mh = (2ab)/(a+ b)
174
There are many interesting theorems relating these means. Here is one of them:
THEOREM: The product of two extremes is equal to the product of their arithmetic and
harmonic means.
Proof:
Multiply the two formulas as given, and the (a + b) terms cancel out, and so do the 2s,
leaving just (ab), the product of the extremes.
Q.E.D.
PORISM 1: The geometric mean mg is the geometric mean not only between the
original extremes a and b, but also between the arithmetic and harmonic means
between a and b.
so (√a·b)(√a·b) = mamh
so ma : mg = mg : mh
Q.E.D.
D
A C E B
a b
175
PORISM 2:
CD : DE = DE : DK
i.e. it is the 3rd proportional from the arithmetic and geometric means between a and b.
But only the harmonic mean between a and b can be that (according to Porism 1
above). Hence DK is the harmonic mean between a and b.
Q.E.D.
Again, it is plain that the following figure exhibits the three means between a and b:
a b
176
Chapter Six
Proportions
in Plane Geometry
DEFINITIONS
PQR”. N R
175
C
5. Two figures have RECIPROCALLY PROPORTIONAL
D
SIDES if a side in the first figure is to a side in the second figure as
another side in the second figure is to another side in the first figure.
For example, the sides of rectangles C · D and E · K are E
reciprocally proportional if C : E = K : D.
K
6. A straight line is CUT IN MEAN AND EXTREME RATIO if the whole of it has
to the greater part of it the same ratio that the greater part of it has to the remaining part
of it.
For example, AB is cut in mean and extreme ratio at G if BA : AG = AG : GB.
A G B
176
THEOREMS
THEOREM 1: Triangles having the same height are to each other as their bases.
Parallelograms having the same height are to each other as their bases.
[6] And so whatever multiples of rDHE and rEHG we take, however they
compare, the corresponding multiples of their bases must compare the same way.
Therefore rDHE : rEHG = DE : EG (Ch.5, Def. 8)
[7] And since these triangles have the same ratio as their doubles (Ch.5, Thm.13), it
follows that the parallelograms DMHE and EHNG, being the doubles of these triangles
(Ch.1, Thm.33), also have the same ratio as the bases DE and EG.
Q.E.D.
177
THEOREM 2: If a straight line is drawn inside a triangle parallel to one of the
sides, it will cut the remaining sides proportionally; and if a straight line cut two sides of
a triangle proportionally, it will be parallel to the remaining side.
[5] So AP : PB = AL : LC,
since each of these ratios is the same as rAPL : rLCP (by Steps 3 and 4), and since
two ratios the same with a third ratio are the same as each other (Ch.5, Thm.3).
And so the sides of the triangle have been cut proportionally. Q.E.D.
Again, suppose that in some triangle ABC the sides have been cut proportionally, such
that AP : PB = AL : LC. I say that PL is parallel to BC.
[1] AP : PB = AL : LC (given)
AP : PB = rAPL : rPBL (Thm.1)
so AL : LC = rAPL : rPBL (Ch.5, Thm.3)
but AL : LC = rAPL : rLCP (Thm.1)
so rAPL : rPBL = rAPL : rLCP
[2] Thus rPBL and rLCP have the same ratio to the same thing (namely to
rAPL).
Thus rPBL = rLCP (Ch.5, Thm.10)
[3] But rPBL and rLCP are on the same base LP. Since they are equal, therefore
they must also be under the same height (Ch.1, Thm.33 converse). Therefore P and L
must each be the same height above BC, i.e. PL is parallel to BC. Q.E.D.
178
THEOREM 2 Remarks
THEOREM 3: The line bisecting an angle of a triangle cuts the base into two
parts having the same ratio as the two sides.
Conversely, if the base of a triangle is cut into two parts having the same ratio as
the two sides, then the line joining the point of section to the opposite angle bisects the
angle.
Q.E.D.
179
Conversely, take any triangle ABC, and suppose that BK : KC = BA : AC.
I say that AK bisects ∠BAC, i.e. ∠1 = ∠2.
Draw CP‖AK, cutting BA extended at P.
Q.E.D.
X
Suppose ΔABC and ΔDCE are equiangular, i.e.
7
∠1 = ∠2
∠3 = ∠4 A
∠5 = ∠6 3
D
Then I say that the sides about their equal angles
are proportional when taken in corresponding 4
order, and thus rABC ~ rDCE. 1 5 2 6
B E
C
180
[5] So ACDX is a parallelogram.
[8] So AB : BC = CD : CE (Step 6)
and BC : AC = CE : DE (Step 7)
so AB : AC = CD : DE (Ch.5, Thm.17, ex aequali)
[9] So AB : BC = DC : CE (Step 6)
and BC : CA = CE : ED (Step 7)
and BA : AC = CD : DE (Step 8)
Therefore the sides about the equal angles in the two triangles are proportional.
Therefore rABC ~ rDCE.
Q.E.D.
THEOREM 4 Remarks
1. All we need is two angles, of course, because if two angles in a triangle are equal
to two angles in another triangle, they must be equiangular.
2. Can you prove the assumption in Step 2 that BA and ED must meet at some
point?
H
M
3. Notice that similar triangles need not be
oriented the same way; for example, one can be
“flipped” compared to the other, as rGHK and K N
L
rLMN. G
181
THEOREM 5: Triangles with proportional sides are similar.
AB : BC = DE : EG
BC : CA = EG : GD A
CA : AB = GD : DE 5 D
Q.E.D.
THEOREM 5 Remarks
There are 3 proportions given for this Theorem. Even if there were only two given, the
Theorem will still hold, because the third one would follow automatically from the other
two ex aequali, as illustrated in Theorem 4, Step 8.
182
THEOREM 6: Triangles with one angle of one equal to one angle of the other,
and with the sides about the equal angles proportional, are similar.
[1] Draw ∠7 = ∠1
Draw ∠8 = ∠3
Thus rKEG is equiangular with rABC.
Thus rKEG is similar to rABC (Thm.4), and so the sides about the equal
angles are proportional.
[2] So AB : BC = KE : EG
but AB : BC = DE : EG (given)
so KE : EG = DE : EG (these ratios are both the same as AB : BC)
so KE = DE (each has the same ratio to EG)
Q.E.D.
THEOREM 6 Remarks
183
2. Here is a related Theorem: If two triangles B
have one angle in one equal to one angle in the other, 1
and another pair of corresponding angles both acute,
and a pair of sides in one proportional to a A
corresponding pair in the other, then the triangles are 2
similar. C
BA : AC = BG : GH 3
H
Prove: rABC is similar to rGBH
THEOREM 7: The perpendicular dropped from the right angle to the hypotenuse
in a right triangle divides it into two right triangles similar to each other and to the
whole.
B
Let ABC be a right triangle, AC its hypotenuse,
and drop BP perpendicular to AC.
Then rAPB ~ rBPC ~ rABC.
Is that just my opinion? No, it's a fact. Here's 1 2
why: A
P
C
184
[2] Now ∠BPC = ∠ABC (they are both right angles)
and ∠2 is common to rBPC and rABC
so rBPC and rABC are equiangular (Thm.4)
so rBPC ~ rABC
Q.E.D.
THEOREM 7 Remarks
THEOREM 8: How to cut a given straight line similarly to a given cut straight
line; also, how to cut off any fraction of a straight line.
B
Suppose you have a straight line AB, and also another straight C
line DE cut at some point K. How can you cut AB at a point C
so that AC : CB = DK : KE ?
Like this:
A H
G
[1] Draw AH at any angle to AB, and make AH = DE.
Proof:
Q.E.F.
185
L M N P
X X X
Suppose now you want to cut off some particular
fraction of AB, say two thirds of AB. How do
you do it? Lay out any straight line X, and lay it out three times in a straight line. Thus
LN is two thirds of LP.
Using the construction above, cut AB at a point C so that
AC : AB = LN : LP.
Since 2 : 3 = LN : NP
thus AC : CB = 2 : 3
i.e. AC is two thirds of AB, and so we have cut AB in the required fraction.
Similarly we can cut off any other fraction of straight line AB.
Q.E.F.
Q.E.F.
186
THEOREM 9 Remarks
We can now also find a third proportional to two given straight lines. For example, if we
are given A and B, we can find a third line D such that A : B = B : D. All we have to
do is use the same construction we just used, letting C = B, or PK = EG. For by the
construction
A : B = C : D.
But since C = B, then we have
A : B = B : D.
THEOREM 10: How to find the mean proportional between two straight lines.
[5] But ∠DEP and ∠PEF are equal angles (both being right) in these two
triangles. Therefore the sides about them are proportional, i.e.
DE : EP = EP : EF.
Q.E.F.
187
THEOREM 10 Remarks
P
188
THEOREM 11: Equal and equiangular parallelograms have
reciprocally proportional sides; conversely, equiangular parallelograms with
reciprocally proportional sides are equal.
L C K
H A
[1] Place EB and BD in a straight line.
Thus ∠EBC + ∠CBD = two rights
But ∠EBA = ∠CBD (given)
so ∠EBC + ∠EBA = two rights
and thus AB and BC are also in a straight line.
[2] Extend HE and KC till they meet at L, completing parallelogram ELCB, having
the same angles as the two other parallelograms.
Q.E.D.
Q.E.D.
189
THEOREM 11 Remarks: L C K
Since AB : BC = DB : BE,
thus AB : BD = CB : BE (alternating the proportion)
so BA : AG = LE : EB (since BD = AG and CB = LE)
but ∠BAG = ∠LEB (by the parallels)
hence rBAG is similar to rLEB (Thm.6)
so ∠ABG = ∠ELB
and ∠EBA = ∠BEL (by the parallels)
so ∠ABG + ∠EBA = ∠ELB + ∠BEL (adding equals to equals)
Now if we add ∠EBL to both sides, we get
∠ABG + ∠EBA + ∠EBL = ∠ELB + ∠BEL + ∠EBL
But the right side of this equation is all the angles in rEBL, and so they add up to 180°.
So ∠ABG + ∠EBA + ∠EBL = 180°
from which it follows that LBG is a straight line.
You should be able to prove now that parallelograms EBAH and CBDK are
similar to each other and to HLKG.
C D
Or again, they can have equal areas without being equiangular,
as C and D.
190
3. It is also true, conversely, that if two
parallelograms are equal in area and have G D F
THEOREM 12: If four straight lines are proportional, then the rectangle
contained by the means is equal to the rectangle contained by the extremes.
Conversely, if two rectangles are equal, then their sides are reciprocally
proportional.
[3] And also their sides are reciprocally proportional, since we are
given that B
A : B = C : D.
C
191
Conversely, let A · D = B · C, i.e. suppose these are any two rectangles having equal
areas. Then I say that A : B = C : D.
Q.E.D.
THEOREM 12 Remarks
THEOREM 13: If two lines inside a circle cut each other, then their segments
contain equal rectangles.
A
D
L
X Let AB and CD cut each other inside a circle at X.
R I say that AX · XB = CX · XD, i.e. these
rectangles have the same area.
C
B
192
So the sides about their equal angles are proportional (when taken in
corresponding order).
[4] Since ∠XCB = ∠XAD, therefore the sides opposite these angles are
corresponding sides, i.e. XB and XD are corresponding sides.
Likewise ∠CBX = ∠ADX, therefore the sides opposite these angles are
corresponding sides, i.e. CX and AX are corresponding sides.
[5] Thus CX : XB = AX : XD, these being corresponding sides about the equal
angles CXB and AXD (Steps 3 and 4).
[6] So AX · XB = CX · XD (Thm.12).
Q.E.D.
THEOREM 13 Remarks
193
THEOREM 14: How to make, on a given straight line, a rectilineal figure
similar and similarly situated to a given rectilineal figure.
C
Take any rectilineal figure ABCD, and L
any straight line EH. How can we make D K
a figure on EH similar to ABCD, in
which EH is the side corresponding to E H
AB? As follows. A B
[1] Divide ABCD into triangles (in this case two) ABD and DBC.
[4] Thus figure EHLK is equiangular with figure ABCD, each being composed of an
equal number of correspondingly arranged equiangular triangles.
[5] In order for EHLK and ABCD to be similar, though, the sides about their equal
angles must be proportional. Is that the case?
Obviously DA : AB = KE : EH (rEHK ~ rABD; Step 2)
And BC : CD = HL : LK (rKHL ~ rDBC; Step 3)
Likewise CD : DA = LK : KE.
[7] Since EHLK and ABCD are equiangular (Step 4), and since the sides about their
equal angles are proportional (Steps 5 and 6), therefore they are similar to each other, and
AB corresponds to EH.
Q.E.F.
194
THEOREM 14 Remarks
Since we made a rectilineal figure similar to a given one by putting together triangles that
are similar to those into which the given figure was divided (and by arranging them
similarly), it is an obvious corollary to this Theorem that Any two similar rectilineal
figures can be divided into an equal number of similar triangles, similarly arranged.
THEOREM 15: If a third proportional is found to the sides of two squares, then
the first square is to the second square as the side of the first square is to the third
proportional.
[1] For, the square ABDE and the rectangle DBTF are parallelograms under the same
height, and so they are as their bases (Thm.1),
i.e. £AB : DB · BT = AB : BT
or £AB : AB · BT = AB : BT (AB = DB)
Q.E.D.
195
THEOREM 15 Remarks
3. Looking back to Definition 4, we can also now say that Squares are to each other
in the duplicate ratio of their sides.
THEOREM 16: Similar triangles have the same ratio as the squares on their
corresponding sides. G B L
N E Q
Take any two similar triangles, ABC and
DEF, and build squares ACKH and DFPO
on corresponding sides AC and DF. I say A
R
C D
T
F
O P
[1] Drop BR perpendicular to AC. Drop
ET perpendicular to DF. H K
Since ∠BAR = ∠EDT
(since rBAC is similar to rEDF)
thus rBAR is equiangular with rEDT,
so BR : RA = ET : ED
but BA : AC = ED : DF (since rBAC is similar to rEDF)
hence BR : AC = ET : DF (ex aequali, Ch.5, Thm.17)
196
[2] Complete the rectangle of height BR, base AC, namely ACLG.
Complete the rectangle of height ET, base DF, namely DFQN.
Now ACLG : £AG = LC : CK (Thm.1)
Q.E.D.
D
THEOREM 17: Similar rectilineal L
figures have the same ratio as the squares on their E R
M X
corresponding sides. S C Y K
G Z
A
Take any two similar rectilineal figures ABCDE T
H
and GHKLM.
B
I say that ABCDE : GHKLM = £AB : £GH.
[1] By the corollary to Theorem 14, we know we can divide ABCDE and GHKLM
into similarly arranged similar triangles, equal in number. For brevity, let the triangles in
ABCDE be called R, S, T, and let those in GHKLM be called X, Y, Z.
Q.E.D.
197
THEOREM 17 Remarks:
Looking back at Theorem 15, Remark 2, we can now see that similar rectilineal figures
are to each other in the duplicate ratio of their corresponding sides.
THEOREM 18: Figures similar to the same rectilineal figure are similar to each
other.
A
Suppose A is similar to X, and B is also similar to X.
X Then A is similar to B. Why? Because …
B
[2] The sides about the angles in A have the same ratios as the sides about the equal
angles in X.
The sides about the angles in B also have the same ratios as the sides about the
equal angles in X
So the sides about the angles in A have the same ratios as the sides about the
equal angles in B (since two ratios that are both the same with another ratio are the same
as each other).
[3] So A and B are equiangular and the sides about the equal angles are proportional.
Therefore A is similar to B (Def. 1).
Q.E.D.
198
THEOREM 19: If four straight lines are proportional, the similar figures
similarly situated on them will be proportional.
W
Y
A D
X
Z
B E
C F
[1] Find a third proportional line to the straight lines A and B, namely C, so that
A:B = B:C (Thm.9)
Find a third proportional line to the straight lines D and E, namely F, so that
D:E = E:F (Thm.9)
[3] But the similar figures are also in the ratios of these squares on their
corresponding sides (Thm.15),
so W:X = A:C
and Y:Z = D:F
[5] But each of the ratios in this last proportion is the same as one of the ratios of
similar figures (see Step 3).
So W:X = Y:Z
Q.E.D.
199
THEOREM 20: If two parallelograms share an angle and are about the same
diagonal, then they will be similar.
A K D
Take any parallelogram ABCD, and choose any
point P along its diagonal, completing
parallelogram AEPK. I say that AEPK is similar
E P to ABCD.
B C
[3] Since the opposite angles in any parallelogram are equal, it follows that the
remaining angles in AEPK and ABCD are correspondingly equal. So they are
equiangular.
[4] Now since ∠AEP = ∠ABC (Step 1), and ∠EAP is common to rEAP and
rBAC, hence these triangles are equiangular and therefore similar.
So AE : EP = AB : BC
[5] Since the opposite sides in any parallelogram are equal, it follows that the
remaining sides in AEPK and ABCD about their equal angles (and taken in
corresponding order) are proportional.
Thus AEPK is similar to ABCD. So all parallelograms about the diagonal and
sharing an angle with the whole parallelogram ABCD will be similar to the whole and
therefore to each other.
Q.E.D.
THEOREM 20 Remarks:
Conversely, if two similar parallelograms share an angle they will also share a diagonal.
Using the same diagram as in the Theorem, suppose that AEPK and ABCD are similar
parallelograms sharing the angle at A. I say that P lies on diagonal AC. From the
similarlity of the parallelograms, AE : EP = AB : BC. Since EP is parallel to BC, it
must cut AC at some point, say Q. And since EPQ is parallel to BC in triangle ABC,
therefore AE : EQ = AB : BC. From the two proportions, it is clear that EQ = EP, and
therefore Q and P are the same point. So P lies on AC.
200
THEOREM 21: How to cut a line in mean and extreme ratio.
G
Take any straight line AB. F
How can we cut it at a point K so that BA : AK = AK : KB ?
Thus: K B
A
Q.E.F.
THEOREM 21 Remarks:
201
A
2. We used Ch.2, Theorem 12 to make a “Golden Triangle” in
Ch.4, Theorem 6. This was the isosceles triangle TAP, whose base
angles were each double its peak angle. Recall that in the course
of making it, we made line ASP such that £AS = AP · PS ;
S
thus PA : AS = AS : SP, so that AP was divided at S in mean
and extreme ratio or the “Golden” ratio. But we had also made PT
= AS, so that AP : PT was also the Golden ratio. For this reason, T P
rTAP is called a “Golden Triangle.”
A P K B
5. It should be clear, too, that any two lines cut in mean and extreme ratio are cut in
the same ratio. To cut any other line besides AB in mean and extreme ratio, we would
use the same construction again, and the similarity of all the figures in both constructions
would make it obvious that the lines are cut similarly.
F G T
6. Looking back at the diagram for this Theorem, complete
the rectangle FDCT. Notice that square FK and rectangle KC are
equal (Step 6), and they are parallelograms drawn in opposite
K
A B corners of FDCT and they are both equiangular with rectangle
FDCT. They also have a common corner K. Therefore K lies on
the diagonal of rectangle FDCT (Ch.1, Thm.34 Questions).
Accordingly rectangles AKRD and GTBK are similar to the whole
D R C rectangle FDCT and to each other (Thm.20).
202
7. Since AK : KB is the golden ratio,
and GK : KB = AK : KB,
hence GK · KB is called a “Golden Rectangle.”
Since, by the preceding remark, GK · KB is similar to AD · DR and FD · DC, these
are also golden rectangles.
8. Note that if we draw a square inside a Golden Rectangle on its lesser side, the
remaining rectangle is another Golden Rectangle. e.g. FDCT is a Golden Rectangle, and
when we take away square ABCD, what remains is BA · AF.
But BA : AF = BA : AK (since AF = AK),
and BA : AK is the Golden ratio.
Hence BA : AF is also the Golden ratio, and thus BA · AF is a Golden Rectangle. And
when we subtract square FGKA from it, we are left with Golden Rectangle GK · KB.
[1] First, £AB : £AC = X : Y, since similar figures are as the squares on their
corresponding sides (Thm.17).
[3] Now £BC : £AC = Z : Y, since similar figures are as the squares on their
corresponding sides (Thm.17).
Thus £BC : Z = £AC : Y (alternating the proportion)
Q.E.D.
203
THEOREM 22 Remarks:
1. The diagram depicts rectangles, but they could just as well be irregular (but
similar) pentagons, or any other kind of rectilineal figure.
2. Do you think that the Theorem would hold for similar curvilineal figures, such as
semicircles?
If in any triangle XYZ lines drawn from the three vertices to the opposite sides (XR, YS,
ZQ) are concurrent at P, cutting the sides XY, YZ, ZX into a & b, c & d, e & f
(labeling all these clockwise from X),
then a c e
⋅ ⋅ = 1
b d f
and conversely.
c
b
R
Q
P
d
a
X Z
f S e
204
“HOOK”: THE EQUILATERAL TRIANGLE AND THE GOLDEN RATIO.
If the midpoints of two sides of an equilateral triangle inscribed in a circle be joined and
extended to meet the circle, this line is cut in mean and extreme ratio.
A B C
205
Chapter Seven
Numbers
DEFINITIONS
1. When the same kind of thing is taken repeatedly, the result is a MULTITUDE.
For example, if you take a chair, and another chair, you have a multitude of
chairs. Again, if you have a pear, a banana, and an orange, although you do not have a
multitude of pears, you do have a multitude of fruits.
206
Nothing prevents us from choosing something divisible or something having
position or orientation as a kind of conventional unit to measure other things of like kind,
such as a unit length or a unit weight or a unit time. For example, we might lay out
Y
straight lines X and Y at right angles to each other at point
O, to use as references for designating any point in the plane.
Choose any point on X to the right of O and label it 1. Thus
the line length between O and 1 (call it “U”) is our chosen
-1 O 1 unit length. To distinguish the same length in the opposite
X
direction, we call it – 1 (“negative one”). Notice that U is
U
something divisible, having position, and also direction (it is
to the right of O). All this proves to be very useful elsewhere
in mathematics, of course, but note that U is not a pure unit.
It is not “the unit,” the “one” by which we count all things,
but a unit length, having an arbitrary length and orientation (none of which belong to
“one” as such). It is no more identical with “one” than “two apples” is identical with
“two.”
207
4. An EVEN NUMBER is a number divisible into two equal numbers.
For example, 2, 4, 6 are even numbers.
6. A FACTOR of a number is any number that measures it, i.e. goes into it exactly some
number of times.
For example, the factors of 12 are 1, 2, 3, 4, 6, 12 (but not 5, 7, 8, 9, 10, 11). A
factor of a number is also called a “divisor” of it, since it divides it exactly, and it is also
called a “measure” of it since it fits into it exactly.
8. Two different numbers are PRIME TO EACH OTHER if they have no factor in
common except 1.
For example, 8 and 15 are prime to each other, having no factor in common other
than 1. But 12 and 15 are not prime to each other, since they share a factor besides 1
(namely 3).
10. TO MULTIPLY one number N by another number M means to find the sum of as
many N's as there are units in M. The resulting number is called the PRODUCT of M
times N.
For example, to multiply 3 by 5 means to add together as many threes as there
are units in 5, i.e. 3 + 3 + 3 + 3 + 3 = 15. So 15 is the product of 5 times 3.
The symbolic notation for multiplying 5 times 3 is this: 5 × 3 = 15. We can also
write it this way: 5 · 3 = 15.
208
11. TO DIVIDE one number N by another number M means to count the number of
times M can be subtracted from N. The resulting number is called the QUOTIENT of N
divided by M.
For example, to divide 12 by 4 means to count the number of times 4 can be
subtracted from 12:
(1) 12 – 4 = 8
(2) 8–4 = 4
(3) 4–4 = 0
It can be subtracted 3 times. So 3 is the quotient of 12 divided by 4.
The symbolic notation for dividing 12 by 4 is this: 12 ÷ 4 = 3.
Obviously a greater number is not always exactly divisible by a lesser one, for
example 16 ÷ 3. 3 can be subracted from 16 five times, but one unit of 16 is left over.
Note that multiplication and division are opposite operations, and they undo each
other. If
(a) M×N = P
then by definition N fits into P exactly M times. But that means we can subtract N
from P exactly M times, i.e.
(b) P÷N = M
Now by equation (a) we know that P = M × N, so let us substitute M × N for P in
equation (b):
( M×N )÷N = M
which is to say that any number M multiplied by any number N, and then again divided
by N, leaves us with M once more. Or, by equation (b), M = P ÷ N, so let us substitute
P ÷ N for M in equation (a):
( P÷N )×N = P
so any number P divided by a number N, and then again multiplied by that number N,
leaves us with P once more (at least, so long as we suppose N goes into P some exact
number of times; it is also true more generally, but that goes beyond the point made
here).
209
13. A SQUARE NUMBER is the product of two equal numbers. The number which,
thus multiplied by itself, yields a square number, is the SQUARE ROOT of the square
number.
For example, 4 is a square number, since 4 = 2 × 2, and 2 is the square root of 4. And 9
is the next square number, since 9 = 3 × 3, and 3 is the square root of 9. The symbolic
notation 52 = 25 reads “five squared equals twenty five”, and the notation 5 = 25
reads “five equals the square root of twenty five”. Square numbers are called “square”
because their units can be arranged in a square pattern. Accordingly, the square root is
also called the “side” of the square, as in “3 is the side of the square number 9”.
14. A CUBE NUMBER is the product of three equal numbers. The number which, thus
multiplied by itself, yields a cube number, is the CUBE ROOT of the cube number.
For example, 8 is the first cube number, since 8 = 2 × 2 × 2, and 2 is the cube root of 8.
The symbolic notation 23 = 8 reads “two cubed equals eight”, and the notation 2 = 3 8
reads “two equals the cube root of eight”.
15. A POWER of a number is the product of that number times itself any number of
times.
For example, the fourth power of 5 is 5 × 5 × 5 × 5, and the notation 54 = 625
reads “five to the fourth power equals six hundred and twenty five”.
17. A PERFECT NUMBER is a number equal to the sum of all its factors less than itself.
For example, 6 is the first perfect number, since, other than 6 itself, all its factors
are 1, 2, 3, and it also happens that 6 = 1 + 2 + 3. With most numbers the sum of all
their factors (other than themselves) falls short or exceeds the number itself. For
example, the factors of 8 less than itself are 1, 2, 4 which add up to 7. The factors of 12
less than itself are 1, 2, 3, 4, 6 which add up to 16.
210
PRINCIPLES OF NUMBER THEORY
4. Any two numbers can be added together, and the result is a number.
Any number can have numbers added to it without limit.
5. Any two numbers can be multiplied together, and the result is a number.
Any number can be multiplied without limit.
6. Any lesser number can be subtracted from a greater number, and the result is a
number.
7. Any number can be divided by any one of its factors, and the result is a number.
9. A number that measures two unequal numbers also measures their difference.
For example, if 3 goes evenly into 15, and also into 9, then 3 also goes evenly into 15 – 9.
10. A number that measures a number also measures any of its products.
For example, if 5 goes into 35, then 5 also goes into 26 × 35, and also into 327 × 35, and
in general 5 must go into N × 35, no matter what number N is.
211
THEOREMS
THEOREM 1: The unit has to any number the same ratio that any second
number has to the product of the two numbers.
Take any two numbers, say N and M. Then I say that the following proportion holds:
1:M = N: N × M
Start off with the ratio of 1 to M. Any equimultiples of these two have the same ratio that
they have to each other (Ch.5, Thm.13). So let's take each of them N times, giving us N
× 1 and N × M. Thus we have
1 : M = N × 1 : N × M.
But N × 1 is taking N once, which is just N. So we have, in fact,
1 : M = N : N × M.
Q.E.D.
THEOREM 1 Remarks
1. Let's just confirm this with a few concrete examples, for the sake of clarity.
2 × 3 = 6, and lo and behold, it is also true that 1 : 2 = 3 : 6.
Also, 4 × 5 = 20, but also it is true that 1 : 4 = 5 : 20.
2. Can you see how this Theorem is actually just a different way of stating
Definition 10?
3. We can formulate a similar Theorem for the division of numbers, namely that The
unit has to any number the same ratio which its quotient with a second number has to the
second number. That is, for any two numbes M and N, it will be true that
1 : M = N ÷ M : N.
Start by noting that M × ( N ÷ M ) = N (see Def.11). Thus, by Theorem 1, the above
proportion follows. Here is an example:
12 ÷ 4 = 3, and it is also true that 1 : 4 = 3 : 12.
212
THEOREM 2: The order of multiplication makes no difference.
This is no big surprise. But it is still worth noting that “three fives” equals “five threes”;
although the result is the same, the process of adding together three fives is not identical
to the process of adding together five threes. So why must the result be the same?
[2] Since B × A and A × B have the same ratio to A, therefore they must be equal.
Q.E.D.
THEOREM 2 Remarks:
3
3
3
1. The truth of this Theorem can be manifested visually: 5 rows of 3 is 3
necessarily at the same time 3 columns of 5, i.e. 5 threes must equal 3 3
3
fives, since they are just two different ways of looking at the same 3
3
number. 3
3
2. The Theorem proves the case for two numbers, but it is just as true for any number of
numbers we multiply together. The final product is the same regardless of the order in
which we multiply them. For example, 3 × 4 × 5 = 5 × 4 × 3. For, by the Theorem
4×5 = 5×4 (each is equal to 20)
but again, by the Theorem
3 × 20 = 20 × 3
and so
3 × 4 × 5 = 5 × 4 × 3.
213
THEOREM 3: For any three numbers A, B, C, as long as B is exactly divisible
by C, then (A × B) ÷ C = A × (B ÷ C).
Whether we multiply A × B first, and then divide the product by C, or instead divide B
by C first, and then multiply the result by A, we get the same number. For example,
(4 × 6) ÷ 3 = 4 × (6 ÷ 3).
or 24 ÷ 3 = 4 × 2
Must it always work out, regardless of the numbers we choose? Naturally. And here’s
proof:
[1] Let (A × B) ÷ C = K
thus A×B = K×C (multiplying both sides by C)
Q.E.D.
THEOREM 3 Remarks:
2. Here is another similar rule: suppose you have four numbers A, B, C, D and
A is exactly divisible by C and B is exactly divisible by D. Then I say that
(A × B) ÷ (C × D) = (A ÷ C) × (B ÷ D)
For example (6 × 4) ÷ (3 × 2) = (6 ÷ 3) × (4 ÷ 2).
Why must this always work out?
[2] Since multiplication is the reverse of division, hence it is also true that
M×C = A
and N×D = B
214
[4] But (A × B) = [M × C] × [N × D] (see Step 2)
Hence, dividing both sides by (C × D), we have
(A × B) ÷ (C × D) = ([M × C] × [N × D]) ÷ (C × D)
and since the order of multiplication makes no difference, we can write
(A × B) ÷ (C × D) = (M × N) × (C × D) ÷ (C × D)
But since on the right we first multiply and then divide by (C × D), this leaves us
with the number (M × N), and so
(A × B) ÷ (C × D) = M × N
THEOREM 4: If four numbers are proportional, the product of the means equals
the product of the extremes. Conversely, if among four numbers the product of the means
equals the product of the extremes, then they are proportional.
Given: A : B = C : D
Prove: A × D = B × C
Q.E.D.
Now, conversely,
Given: A × D = B × C
Prove: A : B = C : D
Q.E.D.
215
THEOREM 5: Beginning with any two unequal numbers, the last number
produced by reciprocal subtraction is a common factor of them both.
Of course you are wondering what “reciprocal subtraction” means. It’s not hard. Take
unequal numbers, say 9 and 7, and take the lesser from the greater:
9–7 = 2
Now compare the subrtracted number to the difference, and take the lesser from the
greater:
7–2 = 5
Now compare the subtracted number to the difference, and take the lesser from the
greater:
5–2 = 3
You get the idea. This process cannot go on forever, since numbers are finite and the
number from which we are subtracting is smaller every time. So we must eventually end
up with nothing. But the only subtraction that leaves us with nothing is when something
is subtracted from itself. Hence the last subtraction in such a process must be
[1] X–X=0
Now the Theorem states that X is a factor of both original numbers, whatever they may
be. Why? Note that after the first step, the two numbers in the subtraction for any step
are (a) the number that was subtracted in the previous step, and (b) the difference in the
previous step. So, given our last step, the second to last step must be
[2] Z–X = X
[3] Q–X = Z
Q.E.D.
216
THEOREM 5 Remarks:
27 – 12 = 15
15 – 12 = 3
12 – 3 = 9
9–3=6
6–3=3
3–3=0
So the last number produced was 3, and indeed it is a factor of both 27 and 12. Notice,
too, that the last step is of the form X – X = 0, and the second to last step is of the form
Z – X = X, as asserted in the proof.
2. What happens if we choose numbers that are prime to each other, which have no
common factor except the unit? Then the process must end by producing the unit, since
we proved that the process ends with a common factor of the two original numbers. Try
an example. Start with 9 and 4, which are prime to each other:
9–4=5
5–4=1
4–1=3
3–1=2
2–1=1
1–1=0
Notice that 1 showed up before the process finished – the Theorem does not forbid that,
but demands that if 1 is the only common factor of the two original numbers, the last
number in the process must be 1.
217
THEOREM 6: Given any pair of numbers that are prime to each other, to find
multiples of them that differ by a unit.
Suppose you have a pair of numbers A and B which are prime to each other. Can you
multiply each of them so that the multiples differ by 1? Consider 12 and 5, which are
prime to each other. By Theorem 5, we know that their reciprocal subtraction must
produce the number 1, at least at the end of the process if not sooner. Let’s go through
the steps, then:
[1] 12 – 5 = 7
[2] 7–5=2
[3] 5–2=3
[4] 3–2=1
Since we hit 1 (as we must), let’s stop on this last Step [4]:
3 – 2 = 1
(5 – 2) – 2 = 1
[5 – (7 – 5) ] – (7 – 5) = 1
And by Step [1] we see that 7 = 12 – 5. So replace:
[5 – { (12 – 5) – 5 } ] – [ (12 – 5) – 5 ] = 1
(5 + 5 + 5 + 5 + 5) – (12 + 12) = 1
That is, we have a multiple of 5 and a multiple of 12 which differ by 1. Since this
process does not depend on 5 and 12 in particular, but presumes only that the original
pair of numbers are prime to each other, we have found a way to multiply any pair of
numbers that are prime to each other so that their multiples differ by 1.
Q.E.F.
218
THEOREM 6 Remarks:
1. Using the process described in the Theorem, find a pair of multiples of 16 and 7 that
differ by 1.
2. Sometimes, of course, a pair of numbers that are prime to each other themselves differ
by 1. In fact, any two consecutive numbers are prime to each other, such as N and N +
1. Why? Because any number that measures them both must also measure their
difference, namely 1. But the only thing that measures 1 is 1. Therefore the only thing
that measures both is 1, i.e. N and N + 1 are prime to each other.
3. The Theorem stipulates that the original pair of numbers must be prime to each other.
Must we use numbers that are prime to each other, or can we use any pair of numbers?
We must use numbers that are prime to each other. If instead we start with a pair of
numers that have a common factor greater than 1, then it will be impossible to find
multiples of them that differ by 1. Proof:
Take any two numbers, A and B, and any unequal multiples of them, NA and
MB. Now any number that measures both A and B must also measure both their
multiples NA and MB. And whatever measures both NA and MB must also measure
their difference. Hence, if A and B have a common factor greater than 1, then since this
common factor must measure the difference between any unequal multiples of A and B,
it follows that such a difference must be greater than 1. In general all unequal multiples
of any two numbers must differ by at least the greatest common factor of those two
numbers. For example, since 4 and 6 have a greatest common factor of 2, all multiples of
4 and 6 that differ must differ by 2 or more.
THEOREM 7: Two numbers proportional to two numbers that are prime to each
other are equimultiples of them.
Given: A is prime to B
A:B = C:D
[1] Since A is prime to B, therefore find multiples of them that differ by 1 (Thm.6).
Say nA – mB = 1
219
[3] Hence mD = mB(nC – mD) (products of means and extremes)
thus D = B(nC – mD) (dividing both sides by m)
and so B measures D exactly (nC – mD) times.
[4] Now looking at the given proportion, and multiplying the means and extremes,
A · D = B · C
or A · B · (nC – mD) = B · C ( D = B · (nC – mD), by
Step 3)
and so A · (nC – mD) = C (dividing both sides by B)
and so A measures C exactly (nC – mD) times.
[5] Looking at Steps 3 and 4, we see that B measures D and A measures C, and the
same number of times in each case.
Q.E.D.
THEOREM 7 Remarks:
1. How do we know that we can subtract nC – mD? This will not be a number at all
unless nC is greater than mD. Look at Step 2: nA : mB = nC : mD. We know that nA
is greater than mB, since nA – mB = 1 (Step 1). Hence, by the proportion, it must also
be true that nC is greater than mD.
2. From this Theorem, it is evidence that numbers which are prime to each other are the
least numbers in their ratio, measuring all others that are in the same ratio with
themselves. For example, 5 and 6 are prime to each other, and all other numbers in their
ratio are equimultiples of them, such as 10 and 12.
For example, 3 is the greatest common factor of 6 and 15, i.e. of 2 × 3 and 5 × 3. And, as
the Theorem states, 2 and 5 have no common factor but 1. Now let’s prove it generally:
If possible, suppose A and B have a common factor other than 1. Then say it is M, and
A = R×M
and B = S × M.
220
Thus A × N = R × M × N (substituting R × M for A)
and B×N = S×M×N (substituting S × M for B)
So M × N is now a common factor of A × N and B × N. But since M is supposedly
greater than 1, it follows that M × N is greater than N. Therefore M × N is a common
factor of A × N and B × N and it is greater than N. Which is absurd, since it is given that
N is the greatest common factor of A × N and B × N. Therefore our original assumption,
namely that A and B have a common factor other than 1, is impossible. Therefore A and
B have no common factor other than 1, and so they are prime to each other.
Q.E.D.
Given: A × N : B × N = C × M : D × M,
N is the greatest common factor of A × N and B × N
M is the greatest common factor of C × M and D × M
Prove: A=C
B=D
[1] First of all, we know that A : B = C : D, just by removing the identical multipliers
in the given proportion (cf. Ch.5, Thm.13).
[2] We also know that A is prime to B, since N is the greatest common measure of A
× N and B × N (Given, and Thm.8).
[3] Therefore C and D are equimultiples of A and B (looking at Steps 1 and 2, and
applying Thm.7).
[5] Therefore A and B are equimultiples of C and D (applying Thm.7 to Steps 1 and
4).
[6] Thus A and B are equimultiples of C and D (Step 3), and yet C and D are also
equimultiples of A and B (Step 5). Which is impossible, except when A = C and B = D.
Therefore A = C and B = D.
Q.E.D.
221
THEOREM 9 Remarks:
Verify the Theorem in some numerical examples. Find any proportional numbers, and
divide out the greatest common factor of the first two numbers and again the greatest
common factor of the last two numbers, and see what you have left.
THEOREM 10: A prime number is prime to any number that is not its multiple.
Q.E.D.
THEOREM 10 Remarks:
What about 1? Is that a “prime number”? If so, it is an unusual one, since every other
number is a multiple of it. Shall we say, then, that 1 is not prime to any number, since it
measures them all? But then again, 1 and 3 are prime to each other in the sense that
nothing except 1 measures both of them. Still, 1 measures 3, and that kind of thing does
not happen with other numbers that are prime to each other. Take any other pair of
numbers that are prime to each other, such as 3 and 5, and we see that neither one can
measure the other; if 3 measured 5, then they would have another common factor besides
1, namely 3. Hence, in the case of numbers other than 1, if two numbers are prime to
each other, then neither one measures the other.
222
THEOREM 11: If a number is prime to two numbers, it is also prime to their
product.
For example, 3 is prime to 4 and also prime to 5. Hence 3 is also prime to 4 × 5. Now
let’s prove it generally:
[1] To see it, let F be any common factor of P and A × B. Suppose, then that
P = F×N
and A × B = F × M.
[3] According to Ch.5, Theorem 13, we can divide the first two by the same number,
and maintain the proportion. So divide the first two equal numbers by B:
A : (F × Μ) ÷ Β = P : F × N
Now let's alternate that proportion:
A : P = (F × M) ÷ B : F × N
Again, we can divide both numbers in the second ratio by F and maintain the proportion:
A : P = M÷B : N
[4] And since A and P are given as prime to each other, it follows that N is a
multiple of P (Thm.7).
But P=F×N (Step 1)
So P is also a multiple of N.
But the only way P and N can be multiples of each other is if P = N, and F = 1.
[5] Since F was a randomly taken common factor of P and A × B, and F must
equal 1, therefore 1 is the only factor common to P and A × B. Therefore P is prime to
A × B.
Q.E.D.
223
THEOREM 11 Remarks
2. It also follows that if P is prime to A and to B and to C, that P must also be prime to
the product of all three. For since P is prime to A and also to B, therefore, by the above
Theorem, it is also prime to A × B. Since P is prime to A × B and also to C, therefore, by
the above Theorem, it is also prime to A × B × C.
Obviously, this works for any number of numbers to which P is prime.
3. Does it follow from the Theorem that P does not measure A × B? Not necessarily.
Suppose P = 1. If P, A, B are 1, 3, 5, then 1 is prime to 3 × 5 because it has no
common factor with it but 1, which is itself. But it also measures 3 × 5. However, if P is
anything besides 1, then it will not measure A × B, since it would then have another
factor in common with A × B, namely P itself.
If P were not a factor of any of the numbers A, B, C, what would follow? Since none of
those numbers would be a multipl3 of P, then by Theorem 10 it would follow that P is
prime to each of them. Since P would be prime to each of the numbers A, B, C, then by
Theorem 11, it would follow that P is prime to their product A × B × C. But P is not
prime to that product (since it is given that it measures that product, and so P and A × B ×
C have at least P as a common factor). Therefore P cannot be prime to A and to B and to
C. Therefore P must measure at least one of them.
Q.E.D.
THEOREM 12 Remarks:
From this Theorem we can draw the following corollary: If a prime number measures a
square number, then it also measures its side. For suppose that the prime number P
measures the square number S × S. By the present Theorem, P must therefore measure
at least one of the factors of S × S, i.e. it must measure S, the side of the square number.
For example, if a prime number measures 6 × 6, it must also measure 6. 1, 2, and 3 are
the only prime numbers that measure 36, and all of them also measure 6.
224
THE UNIQUE PRIME FACTORIZATION THEOREM
Q.E.D.
225
THEOREM 13 Remarks:
THEOREM 14: All the factors of any number are: the primes in its prime
factorization, all their products, and 1.
Q.E.D.
THEOREM 14 Remarks:
If two or more of the prime factors are the same, then some of the factors of the number
N will simply be powers of those prime factors. For example, suppose we take the
number 56, whose prime factorization is 2 × 2 × 2 × 7. What are the factors of 56?
According to the present Theorem, they are 1, 2, 22, 23, 7, 2 × 7, 22 × 7, 23 × 7.
226
THEOREM 15: There is always a bigger prime number.
Suppose someone thought the prime number 5 was the biggest prime number of all, so
that no number after 5 was prime. Let's prove him wrong.
Form the number 5! + 1 (i.e. “five factorial plus one”), which is the number
(5 × 4 × 3 × 2 × 1) + 1
If this number is prime, then since it is obviously greater than 5, we are done. On the
other hand, if it is composite, since every composite number is expressible as the product
of primes (Thm.13), so this number will be also. But since 2 goes evenly into (5 × 4 × 3
× 2 × 1), then it will not go evenly into (5 × 4 × 3 × 2 × 1) plus one, because the unit is
not divisible. For the same reason, (5 × 4 × 3 × 2 × 1) + 1 is not evenly divisible by 3, or
by 4, or by 5. Therefore whatever prime number does measure (5 × 4 × 3 × 2 × 1) + 1 has
to be greater than 5. Therefore there is a prime number greater than 5.
By exactly the same argument, we can always prove that there is a prime number
greater than any given prime number P, just by forming the number P! + 1. This means
that there is an unlimited multitude of prime numbers.
Q.E.D.
THEOREM 15 Remarks:
Note that sometimes P! + 1 is itself a prime greater than P. In other cases it is not
prime, but is still measured by a prime greater than P.
For example, if someone says 3 is the greatest prime number, we can refute him
by proving that 3! + 1 is either a greater prime, or is measured by one. In this case, 3! +
1 = 7, which is a prime number greater than 3.
But if someone says 5 is the greatest prime number, we can refute him by
proving that 5! + 1 is either a greater prime, or is measured by one. In this case, 5! + 1
= 121, which is not prime, but it is measured by 11, which is a prime greater than 5.
Also, notice that 11 is not the next prime after 5.
Accordingly, the proof shows that there must always be a greater prime, but gives
us no sure way of producing it. To this day, there is no known formula which generates
all the prime numbers. The only way to find the primes is to list all the numbers as far as
you like and cross out all the ones that have factors other than 1; the remaining numbers
are the primes. This method is called the “Sieve of Eratosthenes.”
227
THEOREM 16: Give me any number: I can always find that many consecutive
numbers none of which is prime.
We might wonder how primes are “spaced” as we take the next biggest prime, the next
biggest, etc. Are they more or less evenly spaced, or do they become “rarer”? They
become much rarer. For example, is it possible to find 99 consecutive numbers none of
which is prime? Yes indeed.
Just form the factorial number (99 + 1)!, or 100!
Now 100! + 1 is, of course, divisible by 1, but it might be prime.
Still, 100! + 2 must be divisible by 2, since 100! is divisible by 2,
and so is 2. Thus 100! + 2 is not prime.
Again, 100! + 3 is divisible by 3, and thus not prime.
Again, 100! + 4 is divisible by 4, and thus not prime.
So there you have 99 consecutive numbers none of which is prime. Likewise, we can
construct a billion consecutive numbers none of which is prime! Just begin with the
number (1,000,000,000 + 1)! + 2.
Q.E.F.
THEOREM 16 Remarks:
Notice that even though the prime numbers “thin out” as we climb upward in the
numbers, that does not mean the distances between consecutive primes steadily increases
as we go. That is because strange clusters of prime numbers show up – something still
not well understood to this day. For example, prime numbers which have only one
number between them are called “Twin Primes”, such as 5 and 7, or 29 and 31, or 197
and 199, or 821 and 823. As I write these words, it is still not known to the mathematical
community whether or not the “Twin Primes” run out, i.e. whether there is a highest pair
of twin primes, or if there is always another pair.
There are only 26 prime numbers less than 100, which are:
1, 2, 3, 5, 7, 11, 13, 17, 19, 23, 29, 31, 37, 41, 43, 47, 53, 59, 61, 67, 71, 73, 79, 83, 89,
97. How many pairs of twin primes can you find in this list?
228
THEOREM 17: How to find the greatest common factor of any two numbers.
Repeatedly subtract the lesser from the greater till nothing remains (which must happen,
since numbers are finite):
A–B=C
C–B=D
B–D=E
etc. etc. ...
Z–X=X
X–X=0
Then X is the greatest common factor of A and B!
First of all, that X is a common factor of A and B is clear already from Theorem 6
(go back and look at it if you forget!). But how do we know that it is the greatest factor
common to A and B?
Take any number N which is a factor of both A and B. I will show you that it
cannot be greater than X.
Since N measures both A and B, therefore it measures their difference, which is A
– B, i.e. C. Since we now see that N measures both B and C, it must also measure their
difference, i.e. D. Since we now see that N measures both C and D, it must measure their
difference, E, etc. So N must measure every number in the whole process, including X.
Therefore any factor common to A and B must also measure X, and therefore must be
equal to or less than it. Therefore X is the greatest factor common to A and B.
Q.E.F.
THEOREM 17 Remarks:
1. If A and B are prime to each other, D will equal 1. If they are not prime to eacah
other, D will be some number greater than 1. So for any two numbers there is always a
G.C.F., even if it is only 1.
2. We can see from this that If a number measures two numbers, it will also measure
their greatest common factor.
229
3. Notice that in this Theorem we have found a way to discover the greatest common
factor of two numbers without factoring either number! Let’s try an example. What is
the greatest common factor of 36 and 81?
81 – 36 = 45
45 – 36 = 9
36 – 9 = 27
27 – 9 = 18
18 – 9 = 9
9–9=0
So 9 is their greatest common factor. Now try it with 176 and 132.
4. Obviously, we can also find the G.C.F. of three numbers A, B, C simply by finding
the G.C.F. of A and B (say it is N), and then the G.C.F. of B and C (say it is M), and then
finding the G.C.F. of N and M (say it is G). G then has to be the GCF of the 3 numbers
A, B, C. For since the G.C.F. of the 3 numbers measures both A and B, it must also
measure their G.C.F., namely N. And since it measures both B and C, it must also
measure their G.C.F., namely M. And since it measures both N and M, it must measure
their G.C.F., namely G. So the G.C.F. of A, B, C must measure G. And therefore G is
the greatest common factor of the 3 numbers. Q.E.F.
THEOREM 18: How to find the least common multiple of any two numbers.
[1] First, by Theorem 17, find the greatest factor common to both A and B. Say it is
N, and that
A=C×N
B=D×N
[2] Therefore
A : B = C×N : D×N (By the two equalities above)
thus A : B = C : D (Chapter 5, Thm.13)
Now since N is the greatest factor common to A and B, it follows that C and D
are prime to each other (Thm. 8).
230
[3] Now the product of the extremes is equal to the product of the means, so
A×D=B×C (Thm.4)
Notice that A × D is measured by A (namely D times), but it is also measured by B
(namely C times). Therefore A × D is a common multiple of A and B. I say that it is
also the least.
[4] For let A and B measure any other number, K, and say that
A×R=K
B×T=K
So that K is also a multiple of both A and B. I say that K is greater than A × D.
[5] Now since the factors of equal numbers are reciprocally proportional (Thm.7),
and A×R=B×T (Since they both equal K)
Thus A : B = T : R (Thm.7)
But A:B = C:D (Step 2)
so C:D = T:R
But C and D are prime to each other (Step 2)
Thus D measures R (Thm.7)
Thus D is less than or equal to R.
So A × D is less than or equal to A × R (multiplying both by A).
i.e. A × D is less than or equal to K.
And since, by supposition, K is a common multiple of A and B other than A × D,
therefore A × D is less than K.
Thus A × D is the least common multiple of A and B.
Q.E.F.
THEOREM 18 Remarks:
1. There is no greatest common multiple of two numbers, since all multiples of their
least common multiple will also be common multiples of them, and we can multiply their
least common multiple as many times as we like.
2. Let’s try a numerical example. Take 24 and 18. What is the least number that both
of them measure? Divide out their greatest common factor, namely 6, and we form the
proportion
24 : 18 = 4 : 3
Multiplying the extremes (or the means), we get 72, which is the least common multiply
of 24 and 18. Now try it with 36 and 15.
231
3. Notice that the product of two numbers is always a common multiple of them, but it is
not always their least common multiple. For example, 4 × 6 = 24, and 24 is indeed a
multiple of both 4 and 6, but it is not their least common multiple – rather, it is 12.
Other times, however, it is the least, e.g. 5 × 6 = 30, and 30 is the least multiple
common to 5 and 6. When does that happen? When the two original numbers are
prime to each other. Use the procedure for finding the L.C.M. of any pair of numbers
that are prime to each other (such as 5 and 6) and you will quickly see why this must be
so.
4. Can you see how to find the L.C.M. of any three numbers?
Q.E.D.
232
THEOREM 19 Remarks:
1. Carl Friedrich Gauss, the great German mathematician, discovered this formula for
triangular numbers all by himself at the tender age of 6. His teacher assigned his class
this problem: add all the numbers from 1 to 100. The teacher, expecting the students to
be busy for a solid hour, was surprised when little Gauss approached him with the correct
answer right away: 5050. Gauss saw that 1 + 2 + 3 + … + 98 + 99 + 100 is equal to 50
pairs each equal to 101. So he simply multiplied 50 times 101 and got his answer.
Prove: The sum of these two numbers is a square number whose side is N + 1.
Our two triangular numbers are half of N(N + 1) and (N + 1)[(N + 1) + 1] respectively.
So their sum is half the sum of these two numbers, or
N (N + 1) + (N + 1) [(N + 1) + 1] divided by two,
which is N (N + 1) + (N + 1) (N + 2) divided by two.
Now, using Theorem 1 of Chapter 5, we can “factor out” the (N + 1) common to both
parts of our sum, which is to say that our whole sum is the same as
(N + 1) [N + (N + 2)] divided by two
which is (N + 1) (2N + 2) divided by two
Again, using Theorem 1 of Chapter 5, we can “factor out” the 2 common to both parts of
(2N + 2), which is to say that our whole sum is the same as
233
(N + 1) (N + 1)2 divided by two
And since our whole sum is reached by multiplying by two but then dividing by two, we
can simply say that the sum of our two triangular numbers is
(N + 1) (N + 1)
which is, by definition, a square number whose side is N + 1.
Q.E.D.
THEOREM 20 Remarks:
1. As a kind of porism, we can say that any square number is equal to the sum of
consecutive numbers from 1 up to its square root and back down to 1. For example,
16 = 1 + 2 + 3 + 4 + 3 + 2 + 1
The reason is that 1 + 2 + 3 is a triangular number
and again 1 + 2 + 3 + 4 is the next triangular number,
and so, by the Theorem, their sum is equal to 42. But their sum is the same as the
numbers from 1 up to 4 and back down again to 1.
2. Can a number be both square and triangular? Yes. For example, 36 is both 62 and
also 1 + 2 + 3 + 4 + 5 + 6 + 7 + 8. How many numbers are both square and triangular?
An infinity of them, but we won't prove that here.
234
THEOREM 21: Every square number N2 is the sum of N consecutive odd
numbers beginning with 1; and the even number following the last odd number added is
double the side of the square.
Now add the numbers in pairs, each number in the top row to the one below it in the
bottom row, and we have
N2 = 1 + (2 + 1) + (3 + 2) + (4 + 3) + … + (N + N – 1)
Since in each case we are adding an even number and an odd one, the parentheses all
contain odd sums. And since, moreover, each member of each pair is always one more
than its corresponding member in the previous pair, the result is that each pair adds up to
two more than the previous pair. i.e. we are adding consecutive odd numbers. i.e.
N2 = 1 + 3 + 5 + 7 + … + 2N – 1
And the last number added is (2N – 1), and so the number after it is simply 2N, half of
which is N, the side of the square.
Q.E.D.
THEOREM 21 Remarks:
Since 2N is double the number of odd numbers from 1 to N, it follows that N is not only
the side of the square, but also the number of consecutive odds which add up to the
square. For example, 1 + 3 + 5 = 9, and the side of this square, namely 3, is also the
number of odds added.
235
THEOREM 22: The product of two square numbers is a square number (whose
side is the product of their sides).
Given: A × A and B × B
Prove: (A × A)(B × B) is a square
Q.E.D.
THEOREM 22 Remarks:
For example, 5 2 × 9 2 = (5 × 9) 2
or 25 × 81 = 45 2 = 2025.
It is also true that the product of two cubes is a cube whose side is the product of their
sides. That is, (A × A × A)(B × B × B) = (A × B)(A × B)(A × B)
For example 2 3 · 5 3 = (2 · 5) 3
or 8 · 125 = 10 3
THEOREM 23: If a square times some number makes a square, the number is
also a square.
Given: (A × A) × N = ( B × B)
Prove: N is a square number.
Now either A is prime, or else it is the product of primes (Thm.13). Either way, A can be
expressed in terms of nothing but primes, so say
A = P1 P2 P3
Since A measures B × B, therefore all these primes measure B × B. But any prime that
measures a square number must also measure the side of the square (Thm.12 Remarks).
Therefore all these primes measure B. Hence P1P2P3 must be found in the prime
factorization of B. But that means that each B in B × B is measured by P1P2P3, or
more simply, by A. Since each B is divisible by A, it follows that B ÷ A is a number.
Now A × A × N = B × B (given)
so N = ( B × B) ÷ (A × A) (dividing both sides by A × A)
so N = ( B ÷ A) × ( B ÷ A) (See Ch.6, Thm. 4)
and since ( B ÷ A) is a number, therefore N is a square number. Q.E.D.
236
THEOREM 23 Remarks:
2. It follows from this Theorem that No square number is double any other square
number. For if so, i.e. if Q × 2 = R where Q and R are both square numbers, it would
follow by the Theorem that 2 is a square number, which it certainly isn't.
Thus, in general, it follows that No square number is a non-square multiple of any
other square number. For example, no square number is 3 times another, or 5 times
another, or 6 times another, etc.
Take any two distinct prime numbers N and M. I say that N and M do not have the same
ratio as any two square numbers.
[2] Since N and M are distinct primes, they have no common factor but 1, and hence
are prime to each other. Therefore, according to the proportion above, N must measure
A2 (Thm.7). But since N is prime, it must also measure A, since any prime number that
measures a square number also measures its side (Thm.12, Remarks). Likewise M
measures B.
[4] Then A2 : B 2 = K2 · N 2 : L 2 · M 2
But N and M have the same ratio as A2 and B2 (Step 1), so
N : M = K2 · N 2 : L 2 · M 2
Now dividing both antecedents by N, and both consequents by M, we have
1 : 1 = K2 · N : L 2 · M
From which it obviously follows that
K2 · N = L 2 · M
Since the factors of equal numbers are reciprocally proportional (Thm.4), thus
N : M = L 2 : K 2
237
[5] By Step 3 it is plain that L2 and K2 are less than A2 and B2. But by Step 4, we
see that L2 and K2 have the same ratio as N and M, whereas A2 and B2 are
supposed to be the least squares in that ratio. Which is impossible. Therefore N and M
cannot have the same ratio as two square numbers.
Q.E.D.
THEOREM 24 Remarks:
Citing Step 3, Step 5 asserts that K2 < A2 and L2 < B2. How is this clear from Step 3?
Because A2 = K2 · N 2 and B2 = L2 · M 2.
But what if N = 1 ? 1 is a prime number, after all. And in such a case
A2 = K2 .
All right, but then since N and M are distinct primes, M is not 1, but some number
greater than 1. So since B2 = L2 · M 2 it will still be true that
B2 > L2.
So the Theorem will hold regardless.
From this Theorem, then, it follows that no two square numbers have the ratio of
1 to 2, or 1 to 3, or 2 to 3, or 3 to 5, etc.
THEOREM 25: Two numbers whose factors are proportional have a mean
proportional between them.
Consider A ⋅ B and C ⋅ D
where A : B = C : D.
I say that A ⋅ B and C ⋅ D have a mean proportional number between them.
Q.E.D.
238
THEOREM 25 Remarks:
2. Any two square numbers have one mean proportional between them. For N × N and
M × M obviously have proportional factors: N : N = M : M. Thus the mean
proportional between them is the product of their sides, N × M. Confirm this with some
examples.
3. Also, any two cube numbers have two mean proportionals between them. Consider
A⋅A⋅A and B⋅B⋅B. The 2 means between them are A⋅A⋅B and A⋅B⋅B. Why?
Because A⋅A : A⋅B = A⋅A : A⋅B obviously, since these ratios have identical
terms. Now we maintain the proportion if we multiply the first two terms by A and the
last two terms by B, giving us
(1) A⋅A⋅A : A⋅A⋅B = A⋅A⋅B : A⋅B⋅B
Again A⋅B : B⋅B = A⋅B : B⋅B obviously, since these ratios have identical
terms. Multiplying the first two terms by A and the last two terms by B, we have
(2) A⋅A⋅B : A⋅B⋅B = A⋅B⋅B : B⋅B⋅B
Putting together Proportion (1) with Proportion (2), we see that A⋅A⋅B and A⋅B⋅B are
mean proportionals between the two original cube numbers.
THEOREM 26: Two numbers with a mean proportional between them have
proportional factors.
[1] Find the G.C.F. of X and N, and call it G (Thm.17). Since G is a factor of both X
and N, therefore each is equal to some number times G, say
A ⋅ G = X
B ⋅ G = N
[2] And since G is the greatest factor common to X and N, it follows that A and B are
prime to each other (Thm.8). Now, from the two equalities in Step 1, it is clear that
A⋅G : B⋅G = X : N
thus A:B = X:N (dividing the first terms by G)
but X:N = N:Z (given)
thus A:B = N:Z (each is the same as the ratio X : N)
239
[3] But A and B are prime to each other, and therefore N and Z are equimultiples of
A and B (Thm.7). Say N and Z are each F times A and B, i.e.
A ⋅ F = N
B ⋅ F = Z
Q.E.D.
THEOREM 26 Remarks:
It follows from this Theorem that two numbers whose factors are not proportional have
no mean proportional between them. For if they did have a mean proportional between
them, their factors would be proportional (by this Theorem). Find some numerical
examples to confirm this and other numerical examples to confirm the Theorem.
THEOREM 27: The product of two numbers with proportional factors is square.
For example, consider 12 and 48, whose factors are proportional, since 3 × 4 = 12, and
6 × 8 = 48, and since 3 : 4 = 6 : 8. Hence the product of 12 and 48 is square, and
indeed 3 × 4 × 6 × 8 = 576 = 24 2. Now let’s prove it generally ...
Given: A × B and C × D
A:B = C:D
Q.E.D.
240
THEOREM 28: If one number measures the square of another, then there is a
third number proportional to the two numbers; if not, not.
Given: A measures B2
Since A measures B2 some definite number of times, let that number be N, so that
A ⋅ N = B ⋅ B
Thus A:B = B:N (Thm.4)
So N is a third proportional to A and B. Q.E.D.
Q.E.D.
THEOREM 28 Remarks:
2. If two numbers (neither of which is 1) are prime to each other, then there is no third
proportional to them. Say A and B are prime to each other. Therefore A is prime to B2,
since A is given as prime to B and therefore it must also be prime to the product of two
B's (Thm.11). Therefore A does not measure B2. So there is no third proportional
number to A and B (by the present Theorem). Therefore if two numbers are prime to
each other, they have no 3rd proportional.
Of course, 1 and 3 are prime to each other, and yet they have a third proportional,
namely 9. But that is because 1 is not only prime to every number, but measures every
number (see Thm.11, Remark 3). So 1 must measure the square of every number, and
therefore for 1 and any number X there will always be a third proportional.
241
THEOREM 29: If one number measures the product of two others, then there is
a fourth number proportional to them; if not, not.
Given: A measures B × C
Q.E.D.
Q.E.D.
Consider the numbers 1, 3, 9, 27, 81. They are in a continuous proportion beginning
from 1, since 1 : 3 = 3 : 9 = 9 : 27 = 27 : 81.
Also 9 = 32
and 27 = 33
and 81 = 34
That is, all the terms after 3 are consecutive powers of 3. Every continuous proportion
beginning from 1 must be this way. Here’s why:
242
Given: A, B, C, D, E etc. in continuous proportion beginning from 1,
i.e. 1 : A = A : B = B : C = C : D = D : E etc.
Prove: B = A2
C = A3
D = A4 etc.
and so on.
Q.E.D.
THEOREM 31: How to find the sum of N numbers that are in a continuous
proportion beginning from 1.
Recalling the last theorem, numbers in continuous proportion beginning from 1 look like
this: 1, A, A2, A3, A4 etc.
If we want the sum of these up to and including A4, just take the difference (A5 – 1) and
divide it by (A – 1). For example
1 + 3 + 32 + 33 + 34 = (35 – 1) ÷ (3 – 1)
so S (A – 1) = A + A2 + A3 + A4 + A5 – 1 – A – A2 – A3 – A4
or S (A – 1) = A5 – 1
hence S = (A5 – 1) ÷ (A – 1)
Q.E.F.
243
THEOREM 31 Remarks:
1. Although the proof sums terms only up to A4, you can see why 1 + A + A2 + A3 + A4
+ A5 = (A6 – 1) ÷ (A – 1). In general, the sum of continuously proportional numbers
from 1 to AM is (AM + 1 – 1) ÷ (A – 1).
[1] To see this, recall that a perfect number is a number equal to the sum of all its factors
other than itself. Now what are all the factors of the product T? Since (2N – 1) is prime
P, and since (2N – 1) is a power of 2 made of nothing but a bunch of twos multiplied
together (and 2 is prime), therefore all the factors of T = (2N – 1) (2N – 1) are:
{a} 1, plus all the powers of 2 up to 2N – 1,
and {b} the products of P with 1 and with all those different powers of 2.
This we know from Theorem 14.
[2] As for the sum of {a}, namely of 1 and all the powers of 2 up to 2N – 1, this is
equal to 2(N – 1) + 1 – 1 (Thm.31, Remark 2).
So the sum of {a} = (2N – 1).
[3] As for the sum of {b}, namely the products of P with 1 and with all the powers of
2, this is equal to the product of P with the sum of 1 plus all those powers of 2 (Ch.5,
Thm.1),
so the sum of {b} = P (1 + 2 + 22 + 23 + ... + 2N – 1)
i.e. the sum of {b} = P [ sum of {a} ]
that is, sum {b} = P (2N – 1)
[4] Since all the factors of T add up to sum {a} + sum {b}, hence all the factors of T
add up to (2N – 1) + P (2N – 1) (Steps 2 and 3)
or (2N – 1) (1 + P) (factoring out (2N – 1); Ch.5, Thm.1)
N N
or (2 – 1) (1 + 2 – 1) (writing out the expression for P)
so (2N – 1) (2N) is the sum total of all the factors of T.
244
[5] So what is the sum of T’s factors that are less than itself? Nothing but the sum of
all its factors minus itself, i.e.
(2N – 1) (2N) – T
Replacing T with its whole expression, this is
(2N – 1) (2N) – (2N – 1) (2N – 1)
But 2 is double 2N – 1, since every power of two is double the previous power of two.
N
Hence 2N = (2N – 1 + 2N – 1). Substituting this expression for 2N, all the factors of T
less than itself add up to
(2N – 1) (2N – 1 + 2N – 1) – (2N – 1) (2N – 1)
But the product on the left equals the sum of (2N – 1) times each term in the parentheses
(Ch.5, Thm.1). So we have
(2N – 1) (2N – 1) + (2N – 1) (2N – 1) – (2N – 1) (2N – 1)
But this simply leaves
(2N – 1) (2N – 1)
which is T !
[6] So the sum of all T’s factors less than itself is equal to T itself. Therefore T is a
perfect number.
Q.E.D.
THEOREM 32 Remarks:
245
3. There are some interesting facts about perfect numbers. First, it is unknown to this
day whether or not any odd perfect numbers exist. All the perfect numbers of the type
described in this Theorem are obviously even. It is known, however, that all perfect
numbers that are even are of the form described in this Theorem.
4. If you add the digits in a perfect number, and do the same with the resulting number,
and so on until you can go no further, the result is always 1. The only exception is with
the first perfect number, 6. But the next is 28, and its digits add up to 10, whose digits
add up to 1. The next perfect number is 496, whose digits add to 19, whose digits add to
10, whose digits add to 1. The next perfect number is 8128, whose digits add to 19,
whose digits add to 10, whose digits add to 1, etc.
5. It has been proved that there is an infinity of perfect numbers, but fewer than 50 are
known today.
6. Every number of the form (2N – 1)(2N – 1), including those that are perfect (namely
when 2N – 1 is prime), is a triangular number whose base is (2N – 1). So the prime
number which is distinctive of each even perfect number is also its triangular base.
7. No even perfect number is square. That is obvious, since its prime factorization is a
bunch of twos and one odd prime. There is no way to divide up those factors into two
equal factors.
8. No even perfect number measures any other. That is clear because if they are
different, their unique primes are different. But then if one measures the other, all its
factors will have to measure the other, also. And so its unique prime will measure the
other, and so the other will have that prime in its prime factorization, too, which is
impossible. For each even perfect number has only one odd prime in its factorization,
namely 2N – 1.
10. All even perfect numbers (except 6) have the same remainder when you divide them
by 6, namely a remainder of 4.
If you add consecutive numbers starting from 1, the sum is called a “triangular number.”
But if you add consecutive square numbers starting from 1, the sum is called a “square
pyramidal number,” because the units can be arranged in the form of a “square pyramid”.
Question: Is any square pyramidal number also a square number? Yes! The number
4900 = 702 = 12 + 22 + 32 + ... + 242 .
246
What is more amazing, 4900 is the only square pyramidal number which is also a square
number (other than the trivial example of 1).
1
55
91
208335
When G. H. Hardy pulled up in front of Ramanujan’s flat for the first time, in a cab
numbered 1729, Hardy remarked it was a singularly uninteresting number, to which
Ramanujan famously replied “Not at all, it is a very interesting number, since it is the
first to be expressible as the sum of two cubes in two ways,” meaning
Apparently, this identity was found in Ramanujan’s notebooks dated earlier than this
meeting, so he did not simply come up with it on the spot.
247
It is perhaps unsatisfying that 1 is involved, since 1 is in a way a “cube number” only in a
degraded sense. So here are a couple other examples which don’t involve 1:
Is it ever the case that the sum of two square numbers is itself a square number? Yes.
For example:
32 + 42 = 52
But what about cube numbers? Is it ever the case that the sum of two cube numbers is
itself a cube?
No! With the trivial exception of 0 (which, for the purposes of this book, is not
considered a “number” anyway), it is never the case that
a3 + b3 = c3
an + bn = cn
This more general statement is Fermat’s famous last theorem, proved only in the 20th
century.
248
Chapter Eight
Irrational Magnitudes
DEFINITIONS
3. Designating any straight line as our unit length, straight lines commensurable with it
are called RATIONAL LINES in reference to it; those incommensurable with it are
called IRRATIONAL LINES. And any areas commensurable with the square on the unit
line (i.e. the “unit square”) are called RATIONAL AREAS in reference to it; those
incommensurable with the unit square are called IRRATIONAL AREAS.
5
8
And “eight fifths” of a straight line is a fraction of it, since that means taking one fifth of
it eight times, and it is written
8
5
Though eight fifths is larger than the original line, it is still called a fraction (although
sometimes it is called an “improper” fraction).
248
PRINCIPLES
1. Any two commensurable magnitudes have to each other the same ratio as some pair of
numbers, and any two magnitudes having the same ratio as some pair of numbers are
commensurable with each other.
For example, if a straight line measures another straight line 5 times, and yet
another straight line 8 times, then the two measured lines have the ratio 5 : 8. And if two
straight lines have the ratio 5 : 8, then they are commensurable.
2. No two incommensurable magnitudes have to each other the same ratio that any two
numbers have, and magnitudes not having the same ratio that any two numbers have are
incommensurable with each other.
3. Any two multiples of the same magnitude are commensurable with each other, and
have the same ratio as the multiplying numbers.
For example, 5A and 3A are commensurable, having A as a common measure,
and they have the same ratio as 5 and 3.
249
THEOREMS
F M
Q.E.D.
THEOREM 1 Remarks:
1. It does not matter whether F is greater or smaller than M. The proof still works in
exactly the same way.
2. Any fraction of the unit length is rational. For a fraction of the unit length will have to
be commensurable with it (by this Theorem), and any length commensurable with the
unit length is rational (Def.3).
3. Any fraction of the unit square is rational. For a fraction of the unit square will have
to be commensurable with it (by this Theorem), and any area commensurable with the
unit square is rational (Def.3).
4. No irrational line length is expressible as a fraction of the unit line, for then it would
be rational (Remark 2 above). So if we call a certain line length “1,” then it is impossible
to designate an irrational line (i.e. one that is incommensurable with the line we have
chosen to call 1) as a fraction, e.g. as “two thirds” or as “one-hundred-and-twenty-three
thousandths.”
250
THEOREM 2: Squares with commensurable sides have the same ratio as two
square numbers.
A B
Given: Square A and square B, which have
commensurable sides.
mK
nK
Prove: Square A has to square B the same
ratio as a square number to a square number.
mK
nK
Since the side of A is commensurable with
the side of B, let K, their common
measure, go n times into the side of A, and m times into the side of B.
Now divide the sides of A into n equal parts, and divide the sides of B into m
equal parts, each part therefore being equal to K, and complete the “grid” in each square.
The area of square A is now divided into n rows each containing n of the
equal squares, each with a side of K. So the area of A equals n × n such squares.
Likewise, the area of B equals m × m of those same squares, each with a side of K.
And so squares A and B have the same ratio as a pair of square numbers.
Q.E.D.
THEOREM 2 Remarks:
1. The proof reveals that if the sides of two squares are as the numbers n and m, then
the squares themselves are as the numbers n2 and m2.
2. It follows that squares with areas that do not have the ratio of any two square numbers
have incommensurable sides. For if their sides were commensurable, then their areas
would have the same ratio as a pair of square numbers.
251
THEOREM 3: Any square whose area is a non-square number of times the unit
square has an irrational side.
Q.E.D.
THEOREM 3 Remarks:
1. Incidentally, how would you make a square with 2 times the area of the unit square?
How do you make a square that is double the area of a given square? How about triple?
How about 4 times? Can you see how to make a square that has any number of times the
area of a given square? Start by taking the given square the required number of times,
and putting them together into one rectangle. Now make a square equal to that rectangle.
2. Even if we do not use the unit square, but just any old square S, the proof works the
same way to show that the side of another square that is a non-square number of times the
area of S is incommensurable with the side of the first square.
252
THEOREM 4: The diagonal of a square is incommensurable with its side.
Q.E.D.
THEOREM 4 Remarks:
This Theorem, even more clearly than the last one, shows that some
magnitudes are incommensurable. We can easily make a square – now
just draw the diagonal, and it will be incommensurable with the side of
the square. In the absence of proof, it might seem impossible for two
comparable magnitudes to be incommensurable. Given any pair of
straight lines, A and B, can’t we find a tiny straight line that fits
exactly into each of them some number of times? After all, there is no A B
limit to how small straight lines can get – there must be one small
enough to measure both A and B exactly ... right?
Wrong! Some magnitudes are incommensurable. We have just shown that
nothing measures both the side of a square and its diagonal.
Before reading this Chapter, you might have thought that all ratios can be
expressed numerically, as a ratio between two numbers. After all, there is an infinity of
numbers, and an infinity of numerical ratios. So given any two straight lines, such as A
and B, musn’t their ratio be expressible as a ratio between two numbers? Not if A and B
are incommensurable, as the side of a square and its diagonal are. Not all ratios are
numerical ratios, and all the numerical ratios are not all the ratios.
253
THEOREM 5: The height of an equilateral triangle is incommensurable with its
side.
A
B H C
Proof: Since BH is half the length of the side of the triangle, thus AB = 2BH. Hence the
square on AB is four times the square on BH, i.e.
£AB : £BH = 4 : 1
so £AB : £AB – £BH = 4 : 4 – 1 (Ch.5, Thm.16, Remark 3)
i.e. £AB : £AH = 4 : 3 (£AB - £BH = £AH; Pythagorean)
Now 4 and 3 don't have the same ratio as any two square numbers. For if possible,
suppose that
4 : 3 = M2 : N2
thus 4N2 = 3M2 (Ch.7, Thm.4)
And since 4N2 is a square number (since a square number times square number yields a
square number), thus 3M2, its equal, is also a square number. But since only a square
number times a square number yields a square number (Ch.7, Thm.23), thus 3 must be a
square number. But that's impossible. Therefore, too, it is impossible that 4 and 3 should
have the same ratio as any two square numbers.
But since the ratio of 4 : 3 is not the ratio of any two square numbers, therefore
the ratio of £AB : £AH is likewise not the ratio of any two square numbers. Therefore
(by Thm.2 Remarks) it follows that their sides are incommensurable, i.e. AB is
incommensurable with AH.
Q.E.D.
254
THEOREM 6: The parts of a magnitude cut into mean and extreme ratio are
incommensurable.
[2] Since m and n are the least numbers in their ratio, hence they measure the
numbers in the same ratio with them (Ch.7, Thm.7). So the antecedent measures the
antecedent in the proportion above, i.e. m measures n. But since m and n are prime
to each other, they have no common measure but 1. So m = 1.
Q.E.D.
255
THEOREM 7: Two magnitudes each commensurable with the same magnitude
are also commensurable with each other.
Since A and C are commensurable, they have a common measure, say W, that goes into
each of them some number of times. Say
A = 5W
C = 7W
Since B and C are commensurable, they have a common measure, say Z, that goes into
each of them some number of times. Say
B = 3Z
C = 4Z
[2] thus 7 · 4 · A : 7 · 4 · 5W = 7 · 4 · B : 7 · 4 · 3Z
All we have done in this step is multiply every term in the proportion of Step 1 by 7 × 4,
i.e. by 28. Doing this does not destroy the proportion. A few inconsequential
rearrangements of the multipliers gives us
And since 7W = C (as we set out in the beginning), and 4Z = C, we can replace those two
terms in the proportion with C:
so 28A : 4 · 5 · C = 28B : 7 · 3 · C
or 28A : 20C = 28B : 21C
thus 28A : 28B = 20C : 21C (alternating the proportion)
i.e. A : B = 20 : 21
So A and B have to each other the ratio that a number has to a number, and so they are
commensurable.
Q.E.D.
256
THEOREM 7 Remarks:
2. We have seen many relationships which are transitive, i.e. which are such that if two
things have that relationship to a third thing, they also have it to each other. This is true
about the relationships of (a) equality, (b) congruence, (c) parallelism, (d) sameness of
ratio, (e) similarity, and now (f) commensurability.
Z
Given: A and B are incommensurable with each other
A
Z is commensurable with A
Q.E.D.
THEOREM 8 Remarks:
Now it is also clear that if a straight line is commensurable with an irrational line, it is
irrational too.
257
THEOREM 9: The sum of two incommensurable magnitudes is incommensurable
with each of them – and the difference of two incommensurable magnitudes is
incommensurable with each of them.
B
Prove: A + B is incommensurable with A
A + B is incommensurable with B
If A were commensurable with A + B, then they have some common measure M going
into each some number of times, say
A + B = 5M
and A = 3M
thus B = 2M (subtracting equals from equals)
And so M also measures B, not just A. Thus A will be commensurable with B. But it is
given that it is not. Therefore neither can A be commensurable with A + B.
Likewise B cannot be commensurable with A + B.
Q.E.D.
For suppose, if possible, that A and A – B were commensurable, and so each is measured
by a common measure, M, some definite number of times, say
A = 12M
A – B = 8M
thus B= 4M (subtracting equals from equals)
And so again A and B would have to have M as a common measure, which is contrary to
what is given about them. Therefore A must be incommensurable with A – B.
Likewise B is incommensurable with A – B.
Q.E.D.
258
THEOREM 10: Either of two commensurable magnitudes is commensurable
with their sum, and also with their difference.
Since A and B are commensurable, they have a common measure, M,which goes into
each some number of times, say
A = 7M
B = 5M
Thus A + B = 12M, and so their sum is also measured by M, the common measure of A
and B, and so A + B is commensurable with A and with B.
And A – B = 2M, and so their difference is also measured by M, and thus is
commensurable with A and also with B.
Q.E.D.
259
THEOREM 11: How to make an infinity of magnitudes, every one of which is
incommensurable with all the rest.
A
Given: Two incommensurable magnitudes to start with,
A and B, such as the side and diagonal of a square. B
Find: A way to generate from them an infinity of magnitudes every one of which is
incommensurable with every other.
A + 1B
A + 2B
A + 3B … etc.
I say that every one of these is incommensurable with all the rest. Consider, for example,
A + 5B and A + 12B. I say they are incommensurable.
Q.E.D.
260
THEOREM 11 Remarks:
1
1
Here is another way to set out an 2
1
infinity of lines all incommensurable 3
with each other. Set out the unit line
1, make another line equal to it at 4
1
right angles and join the endpoints.
Since this hypotenuse is in fact the 5
diagonal of the square on the unit
10 6 1
line, the square on that hypotenuse
9 7
equals two times the unit square. 8
Call this line side of square two. 1
1
Now draw another unit line at right
angles to the side of square two, and 1
1
join its endpoint to the other end of 1
the side of square two. By the
Pythagorean Theorem, the square on
this new hypotenuse equals the
square on 1 (i.e. 1 square unit) plus the square on the side of square two (i.e. 2 square
units), and so it is equal to 3 square units of area. Call this line side of square three.
Repeat the process and you will get the hypotenuses which are the sides of squares 4, 5, 6
etc., having 4 square units of area, 5 square units of area, and so on.
Looking at the hypotenuses, the squares on any two of them are as the numbers
under the radical signs, which are simply all the numbers (if the process is carried on
indefinitely). Now attend only to the hypotenuses with prime numbers. The squares on
any two of these will be as those prime numbers – but no two prime numbers have the
same ratio as two square numbers (Ch.7, Thm.24). So the squares on any two prime-
numbered hypotenuses will not be as a square number to a square number, and so those
hypotenuses themselves will be incommensurable (Thm.2, Remark 2). But we can make
as many such hypotenuses as there are prime numbers, and there is an infinity of those
(Ch.7, Thm.15). Therefore we can make an infinity of straight lines, each one of which is
incommensurable with all the others.
261
THEOREM 12: How to make an infinity of straight lines commensurable with a
given line, but falling between two given lengths.
R V P
A
I N
Suppose I give you a straight line G, and also two other lengths AR and AP differing
by however much or little you please. Can you find a way to make an infinite series of
different lengths falling between AR and AP, which are all commensurable with G?
Absolutely.
[1] First notice that however small RP may be, some multiple of it will exceed G.
Suppose 57 RP > G
Now divide G into more than 57 equal parts, say 5700 equal parts (Ch.6, Thm.8), and
call each one F. So G = 5700 F.
So now 57 RP > 5700 F
hence RP > 100 F
So if we now multiply F until it first exceeds AR, we will have to add almost another
100 F’s before we reach P. In other words, there are plenty of multiples of F between
AR and AP.
[3] Since AI and AN are both commensurable with G (all three are multiples of F),
hence AI is sommensurable with AN (Thm.7)
so AI is commensurable with IN (their difference; Thm.10)
but IV is commensurable with IN (IV is half IN)
so AI is commensurable with IV (Thm.7)
thus AI is commensurable with AV (their sum; Thm.10)
but AI is commensurable with G (both are multiples of F)
so AV is commensurable with G
[4] So AV lies between AR and AP in length, and it is commensurable with G, the given
line. If we now bisect IV at Q, AQ will likewise lie between AR and AP and be
commensurable with G by similar reasoning, and their is no limit to how many lines we
can make like this.
Q.E.F.
262
THEOREM 13: Between any two irrational lengths there is an infinity of
rational lengths; and between any two rational lengths there is an infinity of irrational
lengths, each incommensurable with all the others.
Q RT
L P
[1] Set out the unit length U, and any two irrational lengths LQ and LP, with as small
a difference between them as you like. By Thm.12, we can construct an infinity of
straight lines falling between LQ and LP in length, but all commensurable with U, and
hence rational. So the first part of the Theorem is proved.
[2] Take any two rational lengths LR and LT (falling between LQ and LP if you
wish), with as small a difference between them as you like. Set out any irrational line D
(such as the diagonal of the square on U).
Consider the length D + U. Since D is incommensurable with U, hence their
sum is also incommensurable with U and hence irrational (Thm.9). But by Thm.12, we
can make an infinity of lines between LR and LT in length, all commensurable with D
+ U, and thus all irrational. Choose any one of these and call it X1.
[3] Now consider the length D + 2U. It must likewise be irrational, since D is
incommensurable with U and hence with all its multiples such as 2U, and so 2U is
incommensurable with their sum D + 2U (Thm.9). Therefore U, being commensurable
with 2U, is also incommensurable with D + 2U (Thm.8). Therefore D + 2U is
irrational.
Also, D + 2U is incommensurable with D + U (Thm.11). But again, using
Thm.12, we can make an infinity of lines between LR and LT in length, all
commensurable with D + 2U, all of them therefore irrational and incommensurable with
D + U. Choose any of these, and call it X2.
Because X1 is commensurable with D + U, but X2 is commensurable with D
+ 2U, it follows that X1 and X2 are incommensurable with each other.
[4] We can continue with D + 3U, and make X3 between LR and LT, another irrational
length, again incommensurable with both X1 and X2. And so on forever.
Q.E.D.
263
THEOREM 14: If a straight line is divided into two parts incommensurable with
each other, it is impossible to divide it into two other parts commensurable with the
original two parts.
B
A C
X
and so the difference between them, XB, must be commensurable with each of them,
Now since AB and BC are incommensurable (given), and XB is commensurable with one
of them, namely AB, it follows that
and so the sum of these two must be incommensurable with each of them (Thm.9),
And so it is impossible to divide the line AC at any point other than B so as to get two
parts that are each commensurable with AB and BC respectively.
Q.E.D.
THEOREM 14 Remarks:
Obviously we could make X the same distance from A that point B is from C, and thus
AX would be commensurable with BC (being equal to it), and XC with AB (being equal
to it). But then we would not have really divided the line into two new kinds of parts.
264
THEOREM 15: It is possible to contain a rational area with irrational lines, and
also to contain an irrational area with rational lines.
Begin with the square on the unit line, the unit square. Form the
square on its diagonal. Since this diagonal is incommensurable
with the unit side (Thm.4), it is irrational. So the square on the
diagonal of the unit square is contained by four irrational lines.
And yet its area is rational, being double (and so commensurable
with) the area of the unit square. So it is possible to contain a
1 rational area with irrational lines.
H R
Begin again with the square on the unit line, and extend one
of its sides, AB, to D, so that DA = AB (and so DB is
called 2 in reference to the unit length). Now make
equilateral triangle DHB on DB. Thus AH is both the
height of rDHB, and the extension of one side of the unit
square (namely EA). Complete the rectangle AHRB. D B
A
But AH is the height of the equilateral triangle, and so it is incommensurable with its
side, DB (Thm.5). Thus height AH is also incommensurable with AB, half the side.
Thus AH is also incommensurable with EA, which is equal to AB. So EA is
incommensurable with AH, and thus EA : AH is not a numerical ratio.
which is to say that these two areas are incommensurable with each other. But since
square EABC is the unit square, hence rDHB is an irrational area. And yet it is
contained by rational sides, each of its sides being double (and thus commensurable with)
the unit length. So it is possible to contain an irrational area with rational lines.
Q.E.D.
265
Chapter Nine
P
2. You have a STRAIGHT LINE PERPENDICULAR TO A
PLANE if it is perpendicular to all the straight lines it stands
on in that plane. B
For example, PR stands on AB, and is perpendicular
R
to it. And if PR is perpendicular to all such lines in the plane A
passing through R, then PR is perpendicular to the plane.
B
4. Consider a straight line AB that passes through some plane
at point A, and is not perpendicular to the plane, but leans over
somewhat. How much does it lean? If we choose any point B
along it, and BP falls perpendicular to the plane, then the
A P
INCLINATION OF THE STRAIGHT LINE TO THE PLANE
is angle BAP.
267
6. PARALLEL PLANES are those which never meet, no matter how far they are
extended.
B D
A 7. A PLANAR SOLID ANGLE is formed by three or more
planes meeting at a point.
For example, in a cube, one angle of it is formed by three
right-angled faces, namely BAC, BAD, CAD.
268
12. SIMILAR CONES or SIMILAR CYLINDERS are those in which the axes and the
diameters of the bases are proportional.
14. SIMILAR POLYHEDRONS are those whose faces are similar, each to each, and
similarly arranged.
By “similarly arranged” I mean that if any two faces in one solid meet each
other, then the two correspondingly similar faces in the other solid also meet each other,
forming an edge; also, if a solid angle in one solid is convex, then the corresponding
solid angle in the other solid is also convex, but if concave, then concave.
SIMILAR AND EQUAL POLYHEDRONS are similar polyhedrons whose
corresponding faces are equal in size. These can also be called congruent polyhedrons.
269
BASIC PRINCIPLES OF SOLID GEOMETRY
1. If any two points of a straight line lie in a plane, the whole straight
line lies in that plane.
4. Any plane can be rotated about any straight line that lies within it.
270
THEOREMS
THEOREM 1: Any three points not lying in a straight line lie only in one plane,
and every triangle lies only in one plane.
B
Now, since A and B both lie in plane Q, therefore straight line AB lies in plane Q (Princ.
1). And since A and B both lie in plane Z, therefore straight line AB lies in plane Z
(Princ. 1). Therefore plane Q and plane Z have line AB in common, i.e. they intersect
along that straight line. But then they have no other points in common, beyond those
lying in a straight line with AB (Princ. 2). Therefore point C, not lying in line with AB
(given), is not common to planes Q and Z. And thus it is not possible for A, B, C to lie
all in plane Q, and also all in plane Z.
Again, the whole triangle ABC lies only in one plane. For any plane containing
all of triangle ABC must also contain its three vertices A, B, and C. But we have just
showed that there is only one such plane. Therefore the whole of any triangle lies only in
one plane.
Q.E.D.
THEOREM 1 Remarks:
1. One point can have many straight lines passing through it, but any two points lie only
in one straight line. Similarly, two points can have many planes passing through them,
but any three points (if they are not in a straight line) lie only in one plane.
It is obvious that any two points can in fact have a straight line passing through
them. Is it also obvious that any three points can have a plane passing through them?
Yes. Say the points are A, B, C. Join AB, and pass any plane through AB. Now rotate
the plane around AB like a hinge until it hits C, and the result is a plane containing points
A, B, and C.
271
So any three points do lie in one plane. But a fourth point might not lie in the
same plane.
2. Obviously, if you have 3 points in a straight line, there is an infinity of planes that
contain those 3 points. Pass any plane through the straight line containing the 3 points,
and this plane will contain all 3 points.
3. If it were not obvious enough by itself, it is now obvious that One and only one plane
can be drawn through a given straight line and a given point not on that straight line.
For example, only one plane goes through straight line AB and point C – otherwise, more
than one plane would contain the three points A, B, C.
4. If it were not obvious enough by itself, it is now obvious that One and only one plane
can be drawn through a given pair of intersecting straight lines. For example, only one
plane goes through the straight lines AB and BC – otherwise, more than one plane would
contain the three points A, B, C.
THEOREM 2: One and only one plane passes through any pair of parallel
straight lines, and any straight line joining any two points on the parallels also lies in
that plane.
B
P
Given: AB and CD, a pair of parallel straight lines, A
with P and R being random points on each of them.
D
Prove: One and only one plane passes through both
R
AB and CD, and PR lies in that plane. C
Put a pencil down on the table, and imagine it indicating a straight line going on forever
in both directions, say North and South. Now hold a pen over the pencil, but pointing
East and West. These two straight lines will never intersect each other, and yet we do not
call them “parallel.” Why? Because they are not in the same plane. It is especially
interesting that even in the same plane two straight lines can be so oriented that they will
never meet – there is in fact only one orientation you can give a straight line to make it
parallel to another. And thus “parallel” means not only “never meeting,” but also “in one
plane.” Therefore the first part of the theorem, namely that any two straight lines that are
parallel must lie in the same plane, is really self-evident. It is part of what “parallel”
means.
It is also clear that the parallels AB and CD lie only in one plane – it is not
possible for more than one plane to contain them both. For supposing it were so, then
two distinct planes would contain points A, B, C, even though these do not lie in a
straight line with each other, which is impossible (Thm.1). Thus it is impossible for more
than one plane to contain a given pair of parallel straight lines.
And since points P and R both lie in the plane containing the parallels AB and
CD, therefore the line PR lies in that plane, too (Princ. 1).
Q.E.D.
272
THEOREM 2 Remarks:
A pair of lines that never meet, but are not in the same plane as each other, are called
skew lines.
I say that PM is at right angles to the line GMH drawn through M randomly in the plane.
[1] Since ∠AMD and ∠BMC are vertical and are contained by equal lines, hence
rMAD ≅ rMBC, so ∠MAD = ∠MBC.
[2] Now ∠MAG = ∠MBH (being the same as ∠MAD and ∠MBC)
but ∠AMG = ∠BMH (being vertical)
and AM = MB (we made them so)
so rMAG ≅ rMBH (Angle Side Angle)
[4] Again ∠PAG = ∠PBC (being the same as ∠PAD and ∠PBC)
and PA = PB (rMAP ≅ rMBP)
and AG = BH (rMAG ≅ rMBH; Step 2)
273
so rPAG ≅ rPBH (Side Angle Side)
[6] Since PM is thus at right angles to any straight line drawn through M in the plane
of AB and CD, therefore PM is perpendicular to that plane.
Q.E.D.
THEOREM 3 Remarks:
1. If GH is drawn through M so that it does not cut AD and BC, then it will cut AC and
DB, and we use them for the proof instead.
2. A kind of converse to this Theorem is: All perpendiculars to one point on a straight
line lie in one plane. All the perpendiculars to PM drawn from M lie in the plane of AB
and CD.
3. Prove that the line drawn perpendicular to a plane from a point above it is the shortest
straight line that can be drawn from that point to the plane.
4. Prove that only one straight line can be drawn from a given point perpendicular to a
given plane.
274
Join BE, AE, AD.
[4] So ED is perpendicular to DA
but ED is perpendicular to DB (by construction)
so ED is perpendicular to the plane through DA and DB (Thm.3), i.e. the
plane containing points A, B, D.
[5] Now, there is only one plane containing points A, B, D (Thm.1), but the plane
containing parallels AB and CD (Thm.2) contains points A, B, D, and therefore the plane
containing points A, B, D is the same as the plane containing parallels AB and CD. Thus
ED is perpendicular to the plane of the parallels, i.e. to the plane containing triangle
BDC. Therefore ∠EDC is a right angle (see Def.2).
Q.E.D.
THEOREM 5: If two straight lines are perpendicular to the same plane, they are
parallel.
G
Prove: AB is parallel to CD.
B D
Suppose, if possible, that AB is not parallel to CD.
K
Then since B, D, C are all in one plane, draw BE in
this plane parallel to CD. Therefore BE is X
275
Now, A, B, E are all in one plane. Let the intersection of their plane with plane X
be called GK.
Since BE is perpendicular to plane X, therefore ∠GBE is right.
Since AB is perpendicular to plane X, therefore ∠GBA is right.
Thus ∠GBE = ∠GBA, i.e the whole is equal to the part, which is impossible.
Thus our initial assumption was impossible – AB in fact is parallel to CD.
Q.E.D.
THEOREM 5 Remarks:
From this it is clear that You can't have two straight lines perpendicular to the same point
on a plane (except, of course, on opposite sides of the plane, i.e. one above it and one
below it).
Q.E.F.
276
THEOREM 7: How to set up a straight line perpendicular to a plane from a
given point on it.
R T
Q.E.F.
E C A H
Given: AB is perpendicular to plane X,
EHKG is a containing through AB
X
Prove: Plane EHKG is perpendicular to plane X.
G R B K
Choose any random point R on GK, the intersection of plane EHKG and plane X.
Draw RC perpendicular to GK in plane EHKG.
We already know that AB is also perpendicular to GK, since AB is perpendicular to all
straight lines through B in plane X.
For the same reasons, any straight line (in plane EHKG) drawn perpendicular to GK will
be perpendicular to plane X. Therefore plane EHKG is perpendicular to plane X (Def. 3).
Q.E.D.
277
THEOREM 8 Remarks:
THEOREM 9: If three straight lines are not all in one plane, and yet one of them
is parallel to the other two, then the other two are also parallel to each other.
A G
B
Given: AB, CD, EF are three lines not all
in one plane. R F
AB is parallel to EF. E
CD is parallel to EF.
D
Prove: AB is parallel to CD. K
C
278
[3] Now AG is parallel to ER (given)
and ER is perpendicular to plane K, R, G (Step 2)
so AG is perpendicular to plane K, R, G (Thm.4)
[5] Since AG and CK are both perpendicular to the same plane, namely the plane of
points K, R, G, therefore AG and CK are parallel to each other (Thm.5).
Q.E.D.
THEOREM 10: If one straight line is perpendicular to two planes, the planes
are parallel.
X Given: AB is perpendicular to
K
A plane X and to plane Z.
If possible, suppose planes X and Z are not parallel, but eventually meet each other – let
KG be the line of their intersection. Pick point R at random on KG.
Join AR.
Join BR.
[2] Since BA is perpendicular to plane X (given), therefore any straight line in plane
X passing through A is at right angles to BA. But AR is in plane X (Step 1), and it passes
through point A. Therefore AR is at right angles to BA.
Thus ∠BAR is right.
279
[3] Since AB is perpendicular to plane Z (given), therefore any straight line in plane
Z passing through B is at right angles to AB. But BR is in plane Z (Step 1), and it passes
through point B. Therefore BR is at right angles to AB.
Thus ∠ABR is right.
[4] Thus ABR is a triangle two of whose angles are right angles – which is
impossible. Therefore our initial assumption was impossible, namely that planes X and Z
should meet. Therefore planes X and Z never meet – and so they are parallel.
Q.E.D.
THEOREM 11: If two intersecting lines in one plane are parallel to two
intersecting lines in another plane, the two planes are parallel.
X
B
A C Given: AB and BC intersect in plane X,
DE and EF intersect in plane Z,
AB is parallel to DE,
BC is parallel to EF.
E Z
D G F Prove: Plane X is parallel to Plane Z
H K
280
Thus ∠CBG is right (since ∠BGK is right; Step 1)
[5] Therefore BG is at right angles to both AB and BC (Steps 3 and 4), which are two
lines intersecting in plane X. Therefore BG is at right angles to plane X (Thm.3). But
BG is at right angles to plane Z (we dropped BG at right angles to plane Z; Step 1).
Therefore planes X and Z have a common perpendicular, namely BG, and thus these two
planes are parallel to each other (Thm.10).
Q.E.D.
A
Prove: ∠ABC = ∠DEF.
D
Cut off AB = DE, and cut off BC = EF.
Join AC, DF, AD, BE, CF.
[1] AB and DE are parallel (given), and so they are in one plane.
But we have just cut off AB and DE equal to each other.
Therefore the lines joining their endpoints are also parallel and equal (Ch.1).
i.e. AD and BE are parallel and equal to each other.
[2] BC and EF are parallel (given), and so they are in one plane.
But we have just cut off BC and EF equal to each other.
Therefore the lines joining their endpoints are also parallel and equal (Ch.1).
i.e. BE and CF are parallel and equal to each other.
And so the lines joining their endpoints are also parallel and equal (Ch.1), i.e. AC is
parallel and equal to DF.
281
[4] Now AB = DE (we cut them off equal)
and BC = EF (we cut them off equal)
and AC = DF (Step 3)
thus ΔABC ≅ ΔDEF (Side-Side-Side)
so ∠ABC = ∠DEF
Q.E.D.
THEOREM 12 Remarks:
If we extend FE to T, then TE is parallel to BC, too, but ∠TED will not be equal to
∠ABC (unless ∠TED and ∠FED are both right angles). Still, ∠TED is supplementary to
∠DEF, and therefore also supplementary to ∠ABC.
THEOREM 13: If one plane intersects two parallel planes, the two lines of
intersection are parallel.
B
Given: Plane X is parallel to plane Z, each is cut X
by plane ABCD, namely at AB and CD. A
So AB is parallel to CD.
Q.E.D.
282
THEOREM 14: Straight lines cut by parallel planes are cut in the same ratios.
X A
C
Z B D
Q.E.D.
283
THEOREM 15: The intersection of two planes each perpendicular to a third
plane is a straight line perpendicular to the third plane.
A
N B
[3] Therefore there is a perpendicular to plane X standing on point P that lies in plane
A (Step 1), and again there is a perpendicular to plane X standing on point P that lies in
plane B (Step 2). But there is only one perpendicular to plane X standing on point P
(Thm.5 Remark). Therefore the line perpendicular to plane X, standing on point P, must
be a line common to planes A and B. But the only line common to them is their line of
intersection (Princ. 2), namely NP. Therefore the line perpendicular to plane X, standing
on point P, is NP.
So PN is perpendicular to plane X.
Q.E.D.
284
THEOREM 16: In a solid angle formed by three rectilineal angles, any two of
those angles together are greater than the third.
D
[5] Now ∠DVT > ∠QVT (the whole is greater than the part)
so ∠DVT > ∠KVT (∠KVT = ∠QVT, Step 4)
285
So these two given angles are greater than the third. Since there was nothing special
about the two angles we chose among the given three, it follows the same way that any
two of them will be greater than the third.
Q.E.D.
THEOREM 16 Remarks:
D
2. What if K lands outside angle AVB?
Then the proof is identical up to Step 4,
where we said ∠DVT > ∠KVT. Now
extend KV through ∠AVB. N B
A
Thus ∠KVT = ∠NVB (vertical) Q
so ∠DVT > ∠NVB. V
And since ∠DTV is right, hence ∠DVT is T
acute (in rDTV), and so its supplementary K
angle, ∠DVB, is obtuse.
Hence ∠DVB > ∠DVT
so ∠DVB > ∠NVB (since ∠DVT > ∠NVB above)
and ∠DVA > ∠NVA by the same reasoning. And the remainder of the proof is the
same as in the Theorem.
286
THEOREM 17: Any solid angle is contained by plane angles adding up to less
than four right angles.
B
[4] Adding together all these inequalities, keeping the greater things on one side,
1 + 2 + 3 + 4 + 5 + 6 > ∠CAB + ∠ABC + ∠BCA
but ∠CAB + ∠ABC + ∠ΒCA = two rights (triangle ABC)
so 1 + 2 + 3 + 4 + 5 + 6 > two rights
[5] Now angles 1 through 9, added together, equal all the angles in three triangles,
and so all together they add up to three times the angle-sum of a triangle, i.e. three times
two rights, i.e. six rights. So
1 + 2 + 3 + 4 + 5 + 6 + 7 + 8 + 9 = six rights
[6] Thus, if we subtract more than two rights from these nine angles, less than four
rights will remain. But 1 + 2 + 3 + 4 + 5 + 6 is more than two rights (Step 4). Therefore,
when subtracted from the nine angles, less than four rights remain, i.e.
7 + 8 + 9 < four rights.
So the three plane angles forming a trihedral angle must add up to less than four right
angles.
Q.E.D.
287
THEOREM 17 Remarks:
288
THEOREM 18: If among three angles in a plane any two are greater than the
third, and they are made the peak angles of three isosceles triangles of the same leg-
length, then likewise for the bases of these triangles, any two together will be greater
than the third.
P
Given: Three isosceles triangles whose legs
1
2
3 are all equal, i.e. PA = PB = PC = PD, and
A D whose peak angles (1, 2, 3) are such that any
two are greater than the third.
Since there was nothing special about AB and BC, the same proof works just as well to
show that BC + CD > AB, and again that AB + CD > BC. To show that AB + CD > BC,
just rearrange the triangles so that angles 1 and 3 are next to each other, and 2 is on the
outside.
So whenever three isosceles triangles of the same leg-length are formed with three
peak angles any two of which are greater than the third, likewise for their bases any two
of them together will be greater than the third. Q.E.D.
THEOREM Remarks:
A quick corollary follows from this Theorem: we can make a triangle out of lengths AB,
BC, CD, since any two of them are greater than the third. Thus we conclude: When
three isosceles triangles of the same leg-length are formed with three peak angles any
two of which are greater than the third, then it will be possible to make a triangle out of
the lengths of their bases. For short, call such a triangle a “base triangle.”
Obviously, this Theorem is simply a matter of plane geometry, but we will need it
for the upcoming Theorem 20, here in solid geometry, where we shall construct a solid
angle.
289
THEOREM 19: If the peak angles of three isosceles triangles with a common
leg-length L add up to less than four right angles, then L is greater than the radius of the
circle circumscribing their “base triangle.”
Q.E.D.
THEOREM 19 Remarks:
290
THEOREM 20: How to make a solid angle out of three plane angles. Thus it is
required that they add up to less than four right angles, and that any two of them are
greater than the third.
[3] Draw a semicircle on PW. Setting your compass to length MA, make a circle (not
shown) around center W, and where it cuts the semicircle call K. Thus WK = MA. This
can be done because MA is less than diameter WP (by Thm.19).
291
[6] But AB, BC, CA are equal to the bases of our isosceles triangles WX, XY, YZ
(Step 2). So the three triangles standing on AB, BC, CA from point V are congruent to
the three isosceles triangles (SSS), and hence the three peak angles forming solid angle V
are equal to the given angles 1, 2, 3.
Q.E.F.
THEOREM 20 Remarks:
This Theorem is the converse of Theorems 16 and 17. In 16 and 17 we learned that any
trihedral angle must be made of plane angles which add up to less than four rights and
any two of which add up to more than the third one. But we were left wondering: are
there more conditions required for three plane angles to be able to form a solid angle, or
are those two conditions sufficient? Also, we might wonder this: the three angles must
be less than four right angles – but do they in fact have to be less than three right angles,
too? Or is it enough for them to be less than four right angles? This Theorem answers all
those questions: as soon as the three plane angles are such that they are less than four
right angles (by whatever amount you like), and such that any two of them are greater
than the third, we can make them into a solid angle. Those conditions are not only
necessary, but sufficient.
[2] Since BC and AD are the intersections of plane AC with the parallel planes BH
and AK, therefore BC is parallel to AD (Thm.13).
292
[3] Since AB is parallel to CD (Step 1)
and BC is parallel to AD (Step 2)
thus ABCD is a parallelogram.
Likewise the remaining 5 faces are parallelograms.
[6] And thus A, D, G, H are all in one plane (Thm.2). And their plane intersects the
parallel planes BE and CK at AG and DH, and therefore AG is parallel to DH (Thm.13).
But AD was just proved parallel to GH (Step 5), and therefore AGHD is a parallelogram.
[8] But ABGE is just two of rABG, and DCHK is just two of rDCH, similarly
arranged. Therefore
ABGE ≅ DCHK.
Likewise the other opposite parallelograms containing the solid are congruent to each
other.
Therefore if a solid is contained by 3 pairs of parallel planes, then its six faces are
three pairs of congruent parallelograms, and such a solid is called a parallelepiped.
293
[1] Place a solid B, identical to A, right next to it, and a solid Y, identical to X, right next
to it. And thus multiply solids A and X however many times you like. Say you double
A, and triple X.
[2] Because of the identical shape and size of solids A and B, it is clear that the base of
the whole solid A + B is double the base of A.
Likewise the base of the whole solid X + Y + Z is triple the base of solid X.
[3] Now, because they lie inside the same parallels and have identical angles, if the solid
A + B is equal in volume to the solid X + Y + Z, this can only be because they stand on
equal bases, i.e. the base of A + B must be equal to the base of X + Y + Z.
But if the solid A + B is bigger than solid X + Y + Z, then A + B must stand on a
bigger base than X + Y + Z does. And if the solid A + B is smaller than solid X + Y + Z,
then A + B must stand on a smaller base than X + Y + Z does.
[4] Therefore, whatever multiple we take of solid A (and therefore of its base), and
whatever multiple we take of solid X (and therefore of its base), the multiple solids must
compare the same way as the corresponding multiple bases.
Q.E.D.
THEOREM 23: Parallelepipeds standing on the same base and having the same
height are equal (i.e. they have the same volume).
K P
Given: Parallelepipeds AE and ME, both A M
standing on base BCE and having their
G N
tops in the same plane. D L
3
1
Prove: AE and ME have the same B 2
volume.
E
First, suppose solids AE and ME not only C
have their tops in the same plane, but also
that some other pair of their faces lie in the same plane, say CG and CN lie in the same
plane – and therefore also the parallel faces BK and BP lie in the same plane on the
opposite side.
294
But CDA and EGK do not coincide with CLM and ENP (if they did, the two solids would
coincide entirely).
[1] For since CDGE and CLNE are both parallelograms, therefore
DG = LN (each is equal to CE)
so DL = GN (subtracting part LG from both sides)
but DC = GE (in parallelogram CDGE)
and CL = EN (in parallelogram CLNE)
so rDCL ≅ rGEN (Side-Side-Side)
[3] Clearly, then, the two triangles and three parallelograms containing prism 1 are
congruent with and arranged similarly to the two triangles and three parallelograms
containing prism 3 (Steps 1 and 2). And thus they can be made to coincide and therefore
have equal volumes.
P
T
K Next, suppose that solids AE and ME
N have only their tops and bottoms in the
Z
G S
A
M same planes, and the front face of ME,
L namely CRSE, does not lie in the same
plane as CDGE, the front face of solid
D R AE.
295
Let MRST be the top face of solid ME, in the same plane as ADGK, the top face of solid
AE.
[2] Now ZLNP is a part of the top plane, and the top plane is parallel to base BCEX
(given). Thus
plane ZLNP is parallel to plane BCEX.
[3] And CLNE is a part of the face plane CDGE, which is parallel to the back plane
BAKX (in solid AE). But BZPX is a part of the back plane. Thus
plane CLNE is parallel to plane BZPX.
[4] And ZLCB is a part of the side plane MRCB, which is parallel to the opposite
side plane TSEX (in solid ME). But PNEX is a part of that opposite side plane. Thus
plane ZLCB is parallel to plane PNEX.
[6] Since solid ZE has its face CLNE in the same plane as CDGE, the face of solid
AE, therefore solid ZE = solid AE, by the first part of this Theorem.
[7] Again, since solid ZE has its face ZLCB in the same plane as BMRC, the face of
solid ME, therefore solid ZE = solid ME, by the first part of this Theorem.
[8] Therefore solid AE = solid ME (each being equal to solid ZE; Steps 6 and 7).
Therefore, no matter what, when two parallelepipeds have the same base and stand under
the same height, they have the same volume.
Q.E.D.
296
THEOREM 24: Parallelepipeds which are of the same height and on bases of
equal area are equal.
[2] We place a solid identical to TX in line with AD, that is, letting DEGH (identical
to base QRST) be its base, we place DE in a straight line with AD. Complete
parallelogram CDEW in the base plane, and build a “building” on it with the same height
again as the solids on ABCD and DEGH.
[5] Notice that the buildings on DEKL and CDEW together make up one big
parallelepipedal building, since they are in line with each other. Therefore, by Thm.22,
building on DEKL : building on CDEW = area of DEKL : area of CDEW,
297
[6] But, looking just at the parallelograms in the base plane,
DEKL = DEGH (both stand on DE, and are in the same parallels)
but DEGH = QRST (we made DEGH identical to QRST)
and QRST = ABCD (given)
so DEKL = ABCD
[7] So, substituting ABCD for DEKL in the proportion from Step 5, we have:
Since we have two ratios the same as a third ratio, they are the same as each other, i.e.
Notice in this proportion the buildings on DEKL and ABCD both have the same ratio to
the building on CDEW. From this, it follows that they are equal. Thus
[9] Now what if the solids on ABCD and QRST, although having their tops and
bottoms in the same planes, yet have their walls tilted in different ways? Will they still
be equal? Yes.
Just build the solids on
F J
V X those same bases whose walls are
perpendicular to the bases, having
their tops also in the same top-
C
R plane as the “tilty” solids. Then,
by Theorem 23, each upright solid
A D T S
is equal to the tilty solid whose
base it shares. But, by the proof we just gave, the two upright solids are equal to each
other – since they stand on equal bases and between the same parallel planes. Therefore
the tilty solids are equal, too.
Q.E.D.
298
THEOREM 25: Parallelepipeds of the same height are to each other as their
bases.
1 2 V 3 Z
T X
F B C
G P
E K A D Q
Given: Parallelepipeds 1 and 2 of the same height, standing on bases EFGK and ABCD.
Prove: Solid 1 has to solid 2 the same ratio that base EFGK has to base ABCD.
[1] Extend base ABCD so that parallelogram DCPQ, while having the same angles as
parallelogram ABCD, nonetheless has the same area as EFGK.
[2] Complete the parallelepipedal solid on DCPQ by extending the planes of solid 2,
and by capping it off with plane QXZP parallel to plane DTVC. Thus we have solid 3,
and solids 2 and 3 together form one big parallelepiped.
[5] But DCPQ = EFGK, by Step 1. Substituting EFGK for DCPQ in the
proportion, we now have
solid 1 : solid 2 = EFGK : ABCD,
which is what we sought to prove.
Q.E.D.
299
THEOREM 25 Remarks:
[2] Draw LER parallel to AB and CD. Join RC. Extend RC and FG until they meet at
N. Extend DC to M. Complete parallelogram DMNQ. Extend BC to P.
G B
D
E
Prove: Solid AB : solid CD is the ratio triplicate of
A
L AE : ED.
M
C
300
[1] Place solids AB and CD so that they have a common corner at E, and the
corresponding sides AE and ED lie in a straight line. Thus the corresponding sides LE
and EK will also line up (since ∠LED = ∠KEA in the similar solids).
[3] Because of the similarity of the solids, AE, KE and HE are proportional to ED,
EL, and EM. Hence
AE : ED = KE : EL = HE : EM
[4] Now, because parallelograms under the same height are to one another as their
bases (Ch.6, Thm.1), it follows that:
AE : ED = AK : KD
and KE : EL = KD : DL
and HE : EM = HD : DM.
Because of Step 3, the first in each of these pairs of ratios are all the same ratio.
Therefore the second in each of these pairs of ratios are also all the same,
i.e. AK : KD = KD : DL = HD : DM.
[5] But since parallelepipeds under the same height are to each other as their bases
(Thm.25), it follows further that:
AK : KD = solid AB : solid EG
and KD : DL = solid EG : solid LQ
and HD : DM = solid LQ : solid CD
Because of Step 4, the first in each of these pairs of ratios are all the same ratio.
Therefore the second in each of these pairs of ratios are also all the same,
i.e. solid AB : solid EG = solid EG : solid LQ = solid LQ : solid CD
[6] Since that proportion is continuous, and contains four terms, therefore the first has
to the last the triplicate ratio of the first to the second, i.e.
solid AB : solid CD is the triplicate ratio of solid AB : solid EG.
So similar parallelepipeds have to each other the triplicate ratio of their corresponding
sides.
Q.E.D.
301
THEOREM 26 Remarks:
The most important instance of this, of course, is with cubes. All cubes are similar
parallelepipeds, and so it follows that they are to each other in the ratio triplicate of their
corresponding sides.
For example, suppose you had a pair of cubes, and the side or edge of one was
double the side or edge of the other, i.e. their sides were in the ratio of 1 : 2. Then what
is the ratio of their volumes? It will be 1 : 8, since
1 : 2 = 2 : 4 = 4 : 8,
and thus 1 : 8 is the ratio triplicate of 1 : 2.
This Theorem should make you wonder about the ratios of other kinds of similar
solids, such as curved ones. Do spheres have to each other the triplicate ratio of their
diameters?
302
[3] But OUP is a straight line, and therefore CUF is also a straight line, since the
vertical angles OUC and PUF are equal.
Likewise ASH is a straight line.
And since AC and FH are equal and parallel lines, ACFH is a parallelogram.
[4] Thus SU lies in the plane of parallelogram ACFH, since it joins points U and S
which lie on its opposite sides. Thus CH and SU must meet, say at T.
Q.E.D.
THEOREM 27 Remarks:
C U F
2. Obviously, this Theorem is true about cubes in particular – if the sides of a cube
are bisected by two planes, the intersection of those planes will bisect the diagonal of the
cube, and be bisected by it.
3. In parallelepipeds other than cubes, the four diagonals can be unequal to each
other. But that doesn't make any difference to this Theorem – take any diagonal you like,
the proof did not require that we choose a special one.
303
THEOREM 28: If a triangular prism lies on one of its parallelogram sides, and
in this position has the same height as another triangular prism lying on its triangular
base, and if the parallelogram is double the triangle, then the prisms will have the same
volume.
N Z
Imagine a prism with triangular
R P
bases ABM and DCN, lying on M O
L
one of its parallelogrammic sides D T
ABCD, and another prism with
C K
triangular bases EGK and OLP, A E
[1] Complete the parallelepiped AR contained by the angles ADC, ADN, NDC.
Complete parallelogram EGKT, and
Complete the parallelepiped GZ contained by the angles GKT, GKP, PKT.
[2] Since ABCD is double triangle EGK in area, and EGKT is also double triangle
EGK in area, therefore ABCD = EGKT.
[3] But that means that solids AR and GZ stand on equal bases. And yet they also
have the same height, since it is given that the height of the prisms is the same, and we
made the parallelepipeds to have that same height. Therefore AR and GZ have the same
volume (Thm. 24).
[5] Since AR and GZ are the same volume, therefore also their halves have the same
volume. But the triangular prisms are obviously their halves. Therefore the two prisms
are equal in volume, too.
Q.E.D.
304
THEOREM 28 Remarks:
We assumed in this Theorem that each prism is obviously half the volume of the
parallelepiped of which it is a part. Why is that obvious?
Consider the prism contained by triangles OLP and EGK. It makes up a
parallelepiped by being combined with another prism, the one contained by triangles
OZP and ETK. Now EGKT and OLPZ are parallelograms, and so are OZTE and all the
other faces of the parallelepiped.
Thus rOLP ≅ rOZP
and rEGK ≅ rETK
and LPKG ≅ OZTE
and OLGE ≅ ZPKT
and, of course, OPKE is a common face for both prisms.
So the two prisms are contained by an equal number of congruent and similarly
arranged faces. Therefore they are congruent and contain equal volumes.
Does that mean that these prisms can coincide? Not necessarily.
Consider your right hand and your left hand. Even if they were perfectly
symmetrical, and of a ghostly quality so that they could pass through each other, they
would not be able to coincide with each other and form one self-same hand. A right hand
simply can't be a left hand!
Now, can the two prism halves of a parallelepiped be like that? Can they be
perfect mirror images of each other, and yet not be able to coincide? Yes. It is almost
impossible to represent this in a two-dimensional diagram in a clear and convincing way,
so the best thing to do is to make a pair of such prisms. It is best not to use paper, since
that is too flimsy – you need something more rigid like cardstock or a manila folder.
Transfer the diagrams below onto a piece of manila: each consists of a square, a rhombus
with angles of 60° and 120° (it is made of two equilateral triangles), and two isosceles
triangles with peak angles of 105° (i.e. 60° + 45°) placed at the bottom corners of the
square. The legs of the isosceles triangles are equal to the sides of the square.
After you have transferred the diagrams, cut out the two figures along the solid
lines. Next, with all the labeling face up on the table, fold up the triangles and square
along all the dotted lines. Bring together the edges marked with the same letters, such as
“A”, and tape them together. When you are done, you will have two triangular prisms,
each with one open face. If you place the square faces down on the table and turn H and
Z toward you, you will see that the prisms are symmetrical, but, like a right hand and a
left hand, cannot be made to coincide. Their corresponding faces can be made to
coincide one at a time, but not all of them simultaneously. If you pick them up in your
hands, and place edges X and Z together, and in that position bring together the two open
faces of the prisms, you will be holding a parallelepiped.
What makes the equality of these two prisms obvious, then, is not that they could
be made to coincide. Rather, like your two hands, it is their perfect symmetry – one is a
perfect mirror image of the other.
305
H
A B
105
105
A
LEFT
C D
105
105
D
RIGHT
306
“HOOK”: TRIANGULAR SECTIONS OF A CUBE.
If you are given a cube and a triangle abc, will it be possible to slice the cube with a
plane so that there will be formed a triangular facet which is similar to abc? Not if abc
is right or obtuse. But if abc is acute, it can always be done.
Z
K
E
A B
a D
b
C G
307
Chapter Ten
2. An infinite series is said to APPROACH a quantity that is not a member of it if, every
time we are given an assigned amount, it is possible to find a member of the series
differing from the quantity by less than that amount.
For example, take a series of lengths beginning with one foot:
First Term: 1
1
Second Term: 1 +
2
1 1
Third Term: 1+ +
2 4
1 1 1
Fourth Term: 1 + + + etc.
2 4 8
These lengths constitute an infinite series, since we can always form the next new term by
adding half of the last thing added in the previous term. Now, two feet, or 2, is not a
member of this series – no matter how far we go in it, every term will always be less than
two feet long. But each new member of the series gets us closer to two feet, and in fact
the terms come as close to two feet as you want (as we will prove in the Theorems). For
example, take one millionth of an inch – there will be a term in the above series that falls
short of being two feet long by LESS than a millionth of an inch. And so this series is
said to approach two feet. It never gets there, but it gets closer than any assigned
difference.
3. A GROWING series is one each new member of which is greater than the one before
it. A SHRINKING series is one each new member of which is less than the one before it.
Note: you can also have oscillating series, e.g. where all the odd terms are
growing but all the even terms are shrinking. It is not within the scope of this book to
exhaust all the kinds of series that are possible.
308
THEOREMS
B
Recall from Chapter 8 that a magnitude is
any quantity which is infinitely divisible, Z
such as a line, or a surface, or a solid. Now
consider any two unequal magnitudes, A and B, and suppose A is the greater one. What I
wish to prove amounts to this:
1 1 1
The process A – A – A – A etc. will eventually leave a remainder that is
2 4 8
less than B.
[1] Since B has a ratio to A (A being greater than B), therefore some multiple of B is
greater than A. Thus if we double B, and then double its double, and double this again,
etc., we will eventually arrive at a magnitude Z that is greater than A.
1 1
so A < Z (obviously)
8 8
1
so A < B (B equals one eighth Z by Step 2)
8
1
[4] But A is a part of A that remains after repeatedly halving A, and halving what
8
remains, etc. That is,
1 1 1 1
A = A – A – A – A
8 2 4 8
[5] Therefore, by repeatedly halving A, and halving its half, etc., we must eventually
arrive at a remainder that is less than B.
Q.E.D.
309
THEOREM 1 Remarks:
1 1 1
1. In Step 3 we mentioned of A, and also of Z. of Z poses no problem,
8 8 8
because that is just B – we started with B, and got Z by taking B 8 times. But with A we
actually started with A, not with something which, taken 8 times, equals A.
1
So how do we make of A? Do we know how to find exactly one eighth of any
8
random magnitude? No. But this theorem does not assume we know how to do that – it
1
only says that if we can take half and half again as often as we like (and thus leave , or
8
1 1
, or , etc.) then we will by this process eventually leave a remainder that is less
16 32
than any given magnitude.
2. Even if we don't know how to take exactly half of any magnitude, as long as its
parts always have a ratio to each other we can easily take more than half of it. Divide it
at random, and take the larger piece (if they happen to be equal, then you did divide it in
half, after all).
And clearly, if repeatedly taking just half of what remains of A gets us to a
remainder less than B, then all the more quickly will repeatedly taking more than half of
what is left get us to a remainder less than B. So suppose we have a growing series of
magnitudes Q, R, S, T etc., and another greater magnitude X. Suppose further that each
new term in the series takes up more than half of the difference by which X exceeded the
last term, i.e. X – R is less than half of X – Q, and X – S is less than half of X – R
etc. Then the series approaches X.
3. Can you prove that repeatedly taking one third of A, and then one third of what
remains of A etc., will eventually leave a remainder less than B? Remember, we are not
subtracting one third of A each time (we could only do that 3 times, and we would have
nothing left): we are subtracting one third of each new remainder, so what we are
subtracting is always getting smaller. Do you think this will get us to less than B? How
about repeatedly taking one millionth of what remains each time? Will that get us down
to less than B, regardless of how small B is? Believe it or not, the answer is yes. But I
leave it to the reader to find proof – it is a digression from the goals of this book.
310
THEOREM 2: If some multiple of magnitude W is greater than magnitude Q,
and a series approaches W, then the same multiple of some term in that series is also
greater than Q.
W
...
A B C T (We are bothering with this only because
we need it for the next Theorem. Don't
W W W worry, though, it's easy.)
3W
Q _
Q
Suppose we are given that 3W > Q, and we are also given a series of magnitudes A, B,
C etc., which approaches W (i.e. there is no limit to how close the terms in the series get
to being equal to W, even if none of them actually equal it).
I say that there is some term T in the series A, B, C such that 3T > Q.
[1] Take any part of the difference between 3W and Q which is less than a third of
that difference, and call it d.
Thus 3d < 3W – Q (we chose d this way)
[2] Since A, B, C etc. approaches W (given), therefore there is always a term in that
series differing from W by less than any specified amount. So take any term T in the
series which differs from W by less than d.
Thus W – T < d
Q.E.D.
THEOREM 2 Remarks:
1. We chose 3W and then took less than a third of 3W – Q. There is nothing special
about 3 and one third. The exact same argument would work for 5W, as long as we also
take less than one fifth of 5W – Q, etc.
311
2. In Step 1 we “take less than a third of 3W – Q.” How do we do that? As a matter
of fact, as with Theorem 1, we will not be applying this Theorem except to magnitudes
that we can do this with. So all this Theorem needs to assert (for our purposes) is that
whenever we can find a way to take less than one third of the difference (or whatever
fraction, depending on the multiple of W we start with), there must be a term in series A,
B, C such that 3T > Q.
X
A B C
...
Z
c
a b
...
Prove: X : Z = A : a
312
[3] Thus 3t < 3Z (multiplying both sides of the inequality by 3)
but 5T > 3Z (Step 1)
so 5T > 3t
That is, any random multiples of X and Z must compare the same way as the
corresponding multiples of A and a. Therefore
X:Z = A:a (Ch.5, Def.8)
Q.E.D.
THEOREM 3 Remarks:
I chose to speak about growing series in this Theorem not because there is something
special about them, but because we will be looking only at growing series in this Chapter.
The Theorem, in fact, would also apply as well to other kinds of approaching series.
313
[1] Join AC, ac, CM, cm.
[2] Because similar polygons are made of similar triangles (Ch.6, Thm.14, Remarks),
therefore rABC is similar to rabc
so ∠BAC = ∠bac
Q.E.D.
R
D
C E d
c e Take any two circles. Call their diameters
T
AB and ab. I say that the circles are to
A B a b each other in the same ratio as the squares
on their diameters, i.e. as £AB to £ab.
m g
M G
k
K
[1] Bisect the semicircumferences in the circle AB at D and K, and inscribe square
ADBK. Now bisect the quarter circumferences in circle AB at C, E, G, M, and inscribe
the regular octagon ACDEBGKM. Thus we are making a series of inscribed regular
polygons, each having twice the number of sides as the one before it.
314
[2] Each new polygon takes up more than half of what was left of the circle by the
last polygon. For example, the square ADBK leaves 4 pieces of the circle such as the one
contained by straight line AD and arc ACD. But the octagon removes ΔACD from that
piece, which is more than half of it – because ΔACD is half of the rectangle ATRD (Ch.1,
Thm.33), and since this rectangle is greater than the circle's segment ACD, it follows that
rACD is more than half segment ACD. So each polygon in the series leaves some
amount of the circle left over, but the next polygon takes up more than half of that
leftover. Therefore the series of polygons is approaching the area of the circle (Thm.1,
Remark 2).
[3] Likewise the series of regular polygons inscribed in circle ab, made by repeatedly
bisecting arcs, is approaching the area of circle ab. And just as the square in circle AB is
similar to the square in circle ab, so every polygon in circle AB is similar to the
corresponding polygon in ab.
[4] But similar polygons inscribed in circles are as the squares on their diameters
(Thm.4). Therefore all the corresponding polygons in the two series have the ratio of
£AB : £ab. And therefore the two magnitudes approached by these two series also
have that ratio (Thm.3). That is
circle AB : circle ab = £AB : £ab.
Q.E.D.
THEOREM 5 Remarks:
1. In Step 2 I asserted that rectangle ATRD is more than the segment ACD. How do
I know that? I form the rectangle by drawing TCR tangent to point C. See if you can
complete the proof by doing the following:
(a) Prove that TR is parallel to AD. (This allows you to complete a rectangle
between TR and AD.)
(b) Argue from the fact that TCR is tangent that segment ACD of the circle must
be less than that rectangle.
D C
2. From this Theorem we can show how to make a L
square equal to an interesting curvilinear figure called a S
“lunule,” or little moon. Q
(i) Consider a circle with center M, diameter AMB, and CM A B
M
drawn perpendicular to AMB. Join AC and circumscribe a
circle about triangle ACM.
315
(ii) Since ∠AMC is right, therefore AC is the diameter of the circle ADCM (Ch.3). So
circle ADCM : circle M = £AC : £AB (by the present Theorem)
(iii) But £AC is the square ACBE, and £AB is the square on its diagonal, so
£AC : £AB = 1 : 2
thus circle ADCM : circle M = 1 : 2 (because of Step ii)
(iv) Thus circle M is double circle ADCM,
so one quarter circle M = one half circle ADCM
i.e. quadrant MAC = semicircle ADC
or areas S + Q = areas S + L
thus area Q = area L (subtracting S from each)
i.e. rAMC = lunule L
3. Since we can make a square equal to any rectilineal figure, we can thus make a
square equal to the lunule L. This is called quadrature, or squaring an area. You can see
why the quadrature of this and other kinds of lunules gave the ancient Greeks great hopes
of finding a way to make a circle equal to a square. The various attempts at the
“quadrature of the circle” over the centuries make up an interesting part of the history of
mathematics. The end of the story came in modern mathematics (only about a couple
hundred years ago), with a proof that it is actually impossible to construct a square equal
to a circle using nothing but straight lines and circles (the tools we are using in this
geometry book). Worse than that, even if you allow yourself all kinds of curves
described by algebraic equations, you still cannot make a square equal to a circle!
V
Conceive a pyramid on triangular base ABC,
vertex V.
K
[2] Since the sides of the pyramid’s triangular
faces are all cut proportionally by these lines
T B joining the midpoints, therefore these lines are
A parallel to the edges of the pyramid. For example,
M DE is parallel to AB.
L
316
So rVDE is similar to rVAB
but rDAT is similar to rVAB
so rVDE is similar to rDAT
And the corresponding sides AD and DV are equal,
so rVDE ≅ rDAT.
[6] Hence all the triangles containing pyramid VDKE are congruent to those
containing pyramid DALT. So these pyramids are congruent. And since they are
contained by triangles similar to the triangular facees of the whole pyramid on base ABC,
hence they are similar to the whole pyramid.
[11] Since rDLT and rKCM are congruent, and their corresponding sides are sides
of parallelograms, therefore they contain a prism on LTMC as base.
[12] Likewise rDKE and rTMB are congruent, and their corresponding sides are
sides of parallelograms, so they contain a prism on rTMB as base.
317
[13] Now rTMB is half parallelogram LTMC, since they stand on equal bases CM
and MB, and in the same parallels LT and CB. Hence the two triangular prisms standing
on these bases, being under the same height (since the plane of DKE is parallel to the
plane of CLTB), are equal. (Ch.9, Thm.28)
[14] So the whole pyramid is composed of the two congruent pyramids and these two
equal triangular prisms
Q.E.D.
V
E
K
T D E
A B
B
L M
M
A B
C T
C
318
[4] Since the corresponding sides in these congruent triangles are equal,
hence MT = DK
and TE = DV
and EM = VK
so rTEM ≅ rDVK (SSS)
[5] Hence all the triangles containing pyramid ETMB are congruent to those
containing pyramid DALT,
so ETMB ≅ DALT.
Likewise KLCM ≅ DALT.
Now pyramids ETMB and KLCM are only parts of the two equal prisms, and so
pyramids VDKE and DALT, equal to those pyramids, are less than the two prisms. Since
VDKE and DALT, together with those two prisms, exhaust the whole pyramid, hence the
two prisms are more than half of it.
Q.E.D.
THEOREM 8: If two triangular pyramids under the same height are divided
each into their two prisms and two pyramids (as in the last Theorem), then the two prisms
in one are to the two prisms in the other as the base to the base.
[1] Now the prism on TBRN with top edge DE is half the parallelepiped on that base
and with its top in the plane of DEK (Ch.9, Thm.28, Remarks). So too, the prism on
tbrn is half the parallelepiped on tbrn. So
prism TBRN : prism tbrn = parallelepiped TBRN : parallelepiped tbrn
319
[2] Since the original pyramids are under the same height, therefore the planes cutting
their edges in half are also of the same height, i.e. planes DEK and dek. Therefore the
parallelepipeds just mentioned are under the same height, and therefore they are to each
other as their bases (Ch.9, Thm.25). And therefore, the prisms which are their halves are
also as their bases. So
prism TBRN : prism tbrn = TBRN : tbrn
[3] And likewise the prism on NRC (with top DEK) is to the prism on nrc (with top
dek) as the base NRC is to the base nrc. That is,
prism NRC : prism nrc = NRC : nrc
[4] Now if we join TR, then rABC is divided into four congruent triangles ATN,
NTB, BRN, NRC. Likewise if we join tr, then Δabc is divided into its four congruent
triangles.
So TBRN : rABC = tbrn : rabc (both are the ratio 2:4
thus TBRN : tbrn = rABC : rabc (alternating)
and NRC : rABC = nrc : rabc (both are the ratio 1:4)
thus NRC : nrc = rABC : rabc (alternating)
since the sums of things in the same ratio remain in the same ratio (Ch.5, Theorem 15).
And so the two prisms in the one whole pyramid are to the two prisms in the other whole
pyramid in the same ratio as the bases of the whole pyramids.
Q.E.D.
320
THEOREM 8 Remarks:
If we now divide the small pyramids on DEK and dek in the same way, the sums of their
corresponding prism-parts will be as their bases DEK and dek. So
2 prisms in pyramid DEK : 2 prisms in pyramid dek = DEK : dek (this Thm.)
But since rDEK is identical to rNRC, and rdek is identical to rnrc, therefore
DEK : dek = NRC : nrc
Therefore, putting together these two proportions,
2 prisms in pyr. DEK : 2 prisms in pyr. dek = NRC : nrc
But, as we saw, NRC is one fourth of ABC, and nrc is one fourth of abc. So
2 prisms in pyr. DEK : 2 prisms in pyr. dek = rABC : rabc
So even the little prisms in the leftover little pyramids also have to each other the ratio of
the original base ABC to the original base abc. Likewise, if we now take the little
pyramids into which DVEK and dvek are divided, and divide them, the equal prisms in
them will be as DEK to dek, and hence as ABC to abc. And therefore all the prisms so
made in pyramid ABC have to all the prisms so made in pyramid abc the ratio of rABC
to rabc.
THEOREM 9: Pyramids on triangular bases and under the same height are to
each other as their bases.
V X
I say that O Q R T
B E
[1] Divide each pyramid into two congruent pyramids, similar to the whole, and two
equal triangular prisms, as before. In each pyramid, the 2 prisms take up more than half
the whole (Thm.7). And so if we now divide the smaller leftover pyramids in the same
way, such as pyramids VGHK and GAOP, their prisms will also take up more than half
of them. And they, too, will have two left over pyramids, and so on. So, continuing in
this way we will have a series of magnitudes approaching pyramid V, namely:
321
1. The 2 prisms in pyramid V
2. The 2 prisms in pyramid V plus the 4 prisms in the two leftover pyramids
3. The 2 prisms in pyramid V plus the 4 prisms in the two leftover pyramids,
plus the 8 prisms in the four leftover pyramids etc.
In each step of this process, we take what we had before and add more than half of what
remained of pyramid V. Thus this series is approaching pyramid V (Thm.1, Remark 2).
So, too, there is a corresponding series of prisms approaching pyramid X.
[2] Now since, at any step in the series, all the prisms in pyramid V have to all the
corresponding ones in pyramid X the same ratio as ABC to DEF (Thm.8, Remarks),
therefore the magnitudes approached by these two series of prisms also have that same
ratio (Thm.3). That is
Pyramid V : Pyramid X = ABC : DEF.
Q.E.D.
THEOREM 9 Remarks:
In particular: Pyramids under the same height which are on equal triangular bases are
equal. For they must be as their bases (by this Theorem), which are equal.
THEOREM 10: Pyramids of the same height are to each other as their bases.
V X
E
L
Take any two pyramids V and X whose bases (ABCDE and GHKL) are in the same plane
and whose vertices are in a parallel plane, and it will follow that
Pyramid V : Pyramid X = ABCDE : GHKL.
322
[1] Pick any vertex on base ABCDE, say A, and join AC, AD, dividing the base into
triangles 1, 2, 3, and thus dividing pyramid X into three triangular pyramids on 1, 2, 3.
Similarly, divide base GHKL into triangles 4, 5, thus dividing pyramid X into two
triangular pyramids on 4, 5.
For shorthand, let P1 mean “The Pyramid on triangular base 1,” let P2 mean “The
Pyramid on triangular base 2,” and so on with the other triangular bases.
And thus, adding each consequent to its antecedent (Ch.5, Thm.15), we have
[4] Similarly, we can prove that all the triangular pyramids in Pyramid X have to any
one of them the same ratio as the whole base to the triangular base of that one, i.e.
[5] But the consequents of this proportion and in the proportion from Step 3 form a
proportion, since
P3 : P4 = Base 3 : Base 4 (Thm.9)
And therefore the antecedents of the two proportions also form a proportion, and in the
same order (Ch.5, Thm.17). That is,
P1 + P2 + P3 : P4 + P5 = Base 1 + Base 2 + Base 3 : Base 4 + Base 5
which is the same as saying
Pyramid V : Pyramid X = ABCDE : GHKL.
Q.E.D.
THEOREM 10 Remarks:
Again, note the particular case that Pyramids under the same height and on equal bases
are equal.
323
THEOREM 11: Any triangular prism is composed of three triangular pyramids
of equal volume.
B
E
Q.E.D.
324
THEOREM 11 Remarks:
But pyramid ABC*K is one third of prism DEK (by this Theorem).
So pyramid ABC*K is one third of Prism X, too.
2. More generally, though, any pyramid on any polygon as its base is one third of
the prism sharing that same polygon base and under the same height.
Take any pyramid, say on base ABCDE. Divide its base into triangles. Thus the
pyramid, too, is divided into three pyramids, one on each triangular part of the base. But
a prism standing on base ABCDE will likewise be divided into three prisms, one on each
triangular part of the base.
So if the prism has the same height as the pyramid, each triangular pyramid will
also have the same height as each triangular prism. And therefore, by the above Remark,
each triangular pyramid will be one third of the triangular prism sharing its base, and thus
all the triangular pyramids will be a third of all the triangular prisms, i.e. the whole
pyramid on ABCDE is one third of the whole prism on that base and under the same
height.
3. Since pyramids under the same height, regardless of what kind of bases they stand
on, are to each other as their bases (Thm.10), and since the prisms standing on their bases
and under the same heights are as those pyramids (being triples of them), it follows also
that Prisms standing under the same height are to each other as their bases.
325
THEOREM 12: Any cone is one third the cylinder sharing its base and height.
[2] As we saw in Theorem 5, each successive polygon (made by bisecting more arcs)
takes up more than half of what remained of the circle from the previous polygon, since,
for example, rADE is more than half of the segment of the circle contained by AD and
arc DEA.
[3] But since prisms under the same height are as their bases, therefore the right
prism on rADE is half the right prism on rectangle DMPA, each one having the height
of the cylinder. And since the portion of the cylinder standing on the segment contained
by AD and arc DEA is inside the right prism standing on rectangle DMPA, therefore it is
less than that prism. Therefore the prism on rADE is more than half that portion of the
cylinder. Thus the prisms standing on ABCD, AGBKCLDE, etc., constitute a series of
prisms each taking more than half of what was leftover of the cylinder by the previous
prism, and so this series of prisms approaches the volume of the cylinder (Thm.1
Remarks).
[4] Again, since pyramids under the same height are as their bases, therefore the
pyramid on rADE is half the pyramid on rectangle DMPA with that same vertex. And
since the portion of the cone standing on the segment in AD and arc DEA is inside the
pyramid on rectangle DMPA, therefore it is less than that pyramid. Therefore the
pyramid on rADE is more than half that portion of the cone. Thus the pyramids
standing on ABCD, AGBKCLDE, etc., constitute a series of pyramids approaching the
volume of the cone.
[5] But the pyramids on those polygon bases always have to the prisms on the same
bases the ratio of 1 to 3 (since any pyramid is one third of the prism sharing its base and
height). Therefore also the magnitude approached by the pyramids has to the magnitude
approached by the prisms the ratio of 1 to 3 (Thm.3). That is, the cone is one third of the
cylinder.
Q.E.D.
326
THEOREM 12 Remarks:
R V T
If we take a cross-section of the cone and cylinder through their axis,
we see that the cross-section of the cone is triangle AVC, and that of
the cylinder is rectangle ARTC. The cross-section of the cone is half
that of the cylinder. So
Base of Cone : Base of Cylinder = 1 : 1
Cross-Section of Cone : Cross-Section of Cylinder = 1 : 2
A C
Volume of Cone : Volume of Cylinder = 1 : 3
THEOREM 13: Cones of the same height are to each other as their bases.
[2] Since the corresponding polygons in the two circles are always similar, therefore
they always have the ratio of the squares on the diameters (Thm.4).
[3] And since the pyramids on these similar polygons as bases, having the same
height, are to each other as their similar bases (Thm.10), therefore they are also always in
the ratio of the squares on the diameters (by Step 2).
[4] Now we saw in Theorem 12 that the series of pyramids in each cone approaches
the volume of the cone, and therefore the cones also have the ratio of the squares on the
diameters (Thm.3).
[5] But the squares on the diameters of the circles are in the same ratio as the circular
bases themselves (Thm.5). Therefore the cones are in the same ratio as their bases.
Q.E.D.
327
THEOREM 12 Remarks:
Since each cone is a third of the cylinder standing on its base and under the same height,
it likewise follows that Cones of the same height are to each other as their bases.
THEOREM 14: If a cylinder is cut by a plane parallel to its bases, then the two
resulting cylinders are to each other as their axes.
B A O X Y Z
Imagine a cylinder with axis AX, and suppose it is cut by a plane parallel to its bases,
resulting in two cylinders, one with axis AO, another with axis OX. I say that
cylinder AO : cylinder OX = AO : OX.
[1] Take any multiple of cylinder AO (and thus of its axis), say double it,
as cylinder BO.
Take any multiple of cylinder OX (and thus of its axis), say triple it,
as cylinder OZ.
[3] Therefore, taking any multiples of cylinders AO and OX, they will always
compare the same way as the corresponding multiples of their axes.
Therefore
cylinder AO : cylinder OX = AO : OX
Q.E.D.
328
THEOREM 15: Cylinders on equal bases are to one another as their heights.
Likewise for cones.
A
Q
X Z
Take any two cylinders on equal bases, one with axis (and thus height) AX, another with
a greater axis, BZ. I say that
[2] Since cylinder QZ has the same height as cylinder AX, and their bases are equal
circles, therefore cylinder QZ is congruent to cylinder AX.
Q.E.D.
[6] As for cones, let AX and BZ be cones. Then if we complete the cylinders on their
bases and with heights AX and BZ,
Cone AX : Cone BZ = Cylinder AX : Cylinder BZ
since the cones are each a third of the cylinders (Thm.12).
But cylinders are to each other as their axes (Step 5 above), and so
Cone AX : Cone BZ = AX : BZ.
Q.E.D.
329
“HOOK”: SPHERICAL RINGS.
Take any pair of spheres, however unequal in size. Next inscribe a right cylinder in the
smaller of the two, as BCDE. Excluding the “caps” of the sphere, such as BAE, and also
the cylinder itself, what remains is a sort of ring with a bulging exterior face. Next,
inscribe a cylinder in the larger sphere, having the same height as that in the smaller (so
that GH = BC). Thus we will have formed a “ring” in the larger sphere, too. Now the
fun part: The volumes of the two “rings” are the same.
B E G L
C D H K
330
Chapter Eleven
The Five
Perfect Solids
DEFINITIONS
1. A PERFECT SOLID is a convex polyhedron whose solid angles are equal and whose
faces are congruent regular polygons.
331
THEOREMS
In this Chapter we will make the 5 perfect solids, prove that there are only 5 of them, and
learn some of their relationships and properties. We must begin with 7 preliminary Theo-
rems of plane geometry, however, which also happen to be of some interest in them-
selves.
THEOREM 1: If a line cut in mean and extreme ratio has added to it its greater
segment, the result is a whole line cut in mean and extreme ratio whose greater segment
is the original line.
(AB + AS) : AB = AB : AS
That is, ZAB is cut in mean and extreme ratio at A, and AB is the greater segment.
Q.E.D.
332
Remarks
B E
Given: ABCDE is a regular pentagon.
Prove: BE is parallel to CD, and ∠ABC = 108°.
P
C D
[3] Let P be the center of the circumscribed circle. Thus the 5 triangles such as APB
are congruent (Side-Side-Side).
333
[4] Now the total angle-sum of these triangles is 10 right angles (i.e. 2 rights for each
triangle times 5, the number of triangles). If we subtract the angles around P, i.e. 4 right
angles, the remainder is the sum of the pentagon's angles, namely 6 right angles.
Since the 5 angles of the pentagon are all equal, each one is a fifth of 6 right an-
gles, or one and one fifth of a right angle.
[5] Since a right angle is 90°, therefore a fifth of a right angle is 18°, and so one right
angle and a fifth is 108°.
Thus the angle of a regular pentagon is 108°.
Q.E.D.
THEOREM 3: In a regular pentagon, if two diagonals cut each other, they cut
each other in mean and extreme ratio, and their greater segments equal the side of the
pentagon.
A
1 Given: Regular pentagon ABCDE. Diagonals AC
and EB cut each other at S.
2 3
E B
4 S Prove: AC and EB are cut in the golden ratio at S,
and ES = EA.
[1] Now, by the previous Theorem, EB║DC and AC║ED, so that DESC is a paral-
lelogram. Thus
∠5 = ∠4 (opp. angles in a parallelogram)
but ∠3 = ∠4 (vertical angles)
so ∠5 = ∠3
or ∠EAB = ∠3 (∠5 = ∠EAB since the pentagon is regular)
[2] Notice ∠ABS is common to rEAB and rABS. Also, ∠EAB = ∠3.
So two angles in rEAB are equal to two angles in rABS.
Therefore rEAB is similar to rABS (Ch.6 Thm.4),
i.e. EB : BA = BA : BS
334
[3] Now since ∠1 and ∠6 are each at the circumference, standing on two of the 5
equal arcs, therefore
∠1 = ∠6 (Ch.3, Thm.21)
but ∠2 = ∠6 (since ES║DC)
so ∠1 = ∠2 (making rAES isosceles)
thus AE = ES
[4] So AE = ES (Step 3)
but AE = BA (being sides of the regular pentagon)
so BA = ES
Therefore, substituting ES for BA in our proportion from Step 2, we have
EB : ES = ES : BS
That is, ESB is cut in mean and extreme ratio at S (Ch.6 Def.9), and ES is the greater
segment. And we saw in Step 3 that ES is equal to EA, the side of the pentagon. Thus it
is clear that in a regular pentagon, the side has to the diagonal the golden ratio.
Q.E.D.
THEOREM 4: The sides of the hexagon and decagon inscribed in the same cir-
cle, when added together, make a whole straight line cut in mean and extreme ratio.
335
[1] Since ∠BEC is one central angle of the regular decagon, of which there are 10 in
the whole decagon, and 5 in each semicircle, therefore ∠CEA contains 4 such angles.
Thus 4∠BEC = ∠CEA
but 2∠ECB = ∠CEA (∠CEA is exterior to isosceles triangle ECB)
so 2∠ECB = 4∠BEC
Q.E.D.
Remarks
K
1. Since BC and CD are related as lesser and greater segments B E
2. Looking back at the diagram for the Theorem, one can see that CE bisects angle
BED as follows.
CD = CE (given)
so ∠CED = ∠2 (since rDCE is isosceles)
but ∠1 = ∠2 (Step 3 in the proof of the Theorem)
thus ∠CED = ∠1
i.e. CE bisects ∠BED, and thus CF is also an arc cut off by a side of the deca-
gon, and BC = CF.
336
THEOREM 5: In one circle, the square on the side of the regular hexagon plus
that on the side of the decagon equals the square on the side of the pentagon.
L
A Let ABCDE be a regular pentagon in a circle with
G center M. Bisect arcs AB, CD at G, T. Thus we
F
get arcs of the decagon, and AG is a side of the
decagon. Bisect arc AG at L, join ML, cutting
B E
AB at F. Join GB. Now I say that the square on
M
the side of pentagon ABCDE is equal to the
square on the regular hexagon in circle M, plus
the square on the side of the regular decagon, that
is
C D
T
£AB = £BM + £AG
[1] ∠BMF (or ∠BML) is at the center and stands on 1 ½ decagon arcs. Thus it is
double an angle at the circumference standing on that same arc (Ch.3, Thm.20), and equal
to an angle at the circumference standing on double that arc, i.e. standing on 1 ½ penta-
gon arcs. But ∠BAM (or ∠BAT) stands on 1 ½ pentagon arcs, and thus
∠BMF = ∠BAM.
Q.E.D.
337
Remarks
1. From this fact, by the converse of the Pythagorean Theorem, it follows that BM and
AG, if placed at a right angle to each other, will form a right triangle whose hypotenuse is
equal to AB.
D
2. So if we cut the radius MC of a circle in mean and ex-
treme ratio at K, MK being the greater segment, and if
E K C ABCDE is a regular pentagon inscribed in the circle, then
M MK = the side of the regular decagon in the circle
(Thm.4, Remarks)
MC = the side of the regular hexagon
A B and £MK + £MC = £AB (by the present Theorem).
3. Also, since in one circle the side of the decagon is to the side of the hexagon in mean
and extreme ratio, i.e. as the greater segment is to the whole (Thm.4, Remarks), and since
the side of a regular pentagon is to its diagonal in mean and extreme ratio, i.e. as the
greater segment is to the whole (Thm.3), therefore, in a single circle,
Q.E.D.
338
Remarks
339
THEOREM 7: The square on the diagonal of a regular pentagon, plus the
square on its side, equals five times the square on the radius of the circumscribing circle.
F
A C
E
[1] Join BD, extend it to E. Since AGBKC is a regular pentagon, thus diameter BDE
bisects AC at F, and so DF is perpendicular to AC (Ch.3, Thm.3).
Join EA. Thus EA is the side of the decagon.
[5] But the square on the side of the decagon plus that on the side of the hexagon
equals the square on the side of the pentagon,
i.e. £AE + £DE = £AC (Thm.5)
Q.E.D.
340
Remarks
For the sake of brevity, let's use some shorthand in this remark:
Or, spelled out in words, Three times the square on the side of the regular pentagon plus
three times the square on its diagonal is equal to 5 times the square on the side of the
equilateral triangle inscribed in the same circle.
L
[2] Set up MP perpendicular to the
B base plane.
A Thus angles PMA, PMB, PMC
M
are all right angles.
C
341
[3] In the plane PMA, using A as your center and AB as your radius, draw a circle,
cutting MP at V. (Since AB is greater than AM, your radius will hit MP at some point V
above M).
So VA = AB.
[6] Bisect AV at K.
In plane AVM, draw KL perpendicular to AV, hitting VM at L.
Thus ΔLVK ≅ ΔLAK (Side Angle Side)
so LV = LA.
Q.E.F.
342
Remarks
1. If it wasn't clear by itself, what I mean by “the sphere containing the tetrahedron” is
the sphere whose surface passes through the 4 corners of the tetrahedron.
∠VKL = ∠VMA L
and ∠AVM is common
so rVKL is similar to rVMA A
B
M
so VL : VK = VA : VM
thus £VL : £VK = £VA : £VM C
[2] But VA is the side of an equilateral triangle, and the radius of the circle around it
is equal to MA. Therefore
£VA = 3£MA (Thm.6)
343
[5] Thus £VL : £VK = 3 : 2 (Steps 1 & 4)
so 4£VL : 4£VK = 3 : 2
i.e. the square on 2VL (the diameter of the containing sphere) is to the square on 2VK
(the side of the tetrahedron) as 3 to 2.
Therefore the square on the diameter of the containing sphere is one and a half times the
square on the side of the tetrahedron.
Q.E.D.
Remarks
In Step 1 we assumed that if four straight lines are proportional, then the squares on them
are also proportional. Let's prove that. Suppose A, B, C, D are four straight lines, and
A:B = C:D
Then I say that £A : £B = £C : £D.
Q.E.D.
344
THEOREM 10: How to construct an octahedron, and prove the square on the
diameter of the containing sphere is two times the square on the side of the octahedron.
B
[2] Set up XV perpendicular to the
plane of ABCD, cutting off XV = XA.
[5] And since VX = XA = XR, therefore X is the center of the sphere containing it,
and AC is the diameter.
Q.E.D.
345
Remarks
1. You can make this solid figure out of manila using the accom-
panying pattern.
2. Notice that the octahedron is just two identical pyramids joined at their common
square base.
346
THEOREM 11: How to construct a cube, and prove the square on the contain-
ing sphere's diameter is three times the square face of the cube.
H
[1] Make a square ABCD in the base
E G
plane.
F
H G
[5] Now bisect EF & AB, HG & DC, and
M pass a plane through these midpoints.
E Bisect EH & FG, AD & BC, and pass
F
a plane through these midpoints.
Call the intersection of these 2 planes
K
ML. Each of the 4 diagonals of the cube is
bisected by K, the midpoint of ML (Ch.9,
D
C Thm.27). Therefore the 4 diagonals of the
A
L cube all pass through K, and K is equidistant
B from the 8 corners of the cube.
[7] So the square on the sphere's diameter is three times the square on the side of the
cube, which is one face of the cube. Q.E.D.
347
Remarks
The icosahedron is a bit more complicated, so we are going to build it in separate stages.
STAGE ONE: we will build the top and bottom "caps" of the icosahedron, each
being a pyramid built on a regular pentagon as base with 5 equilateral triangles as walls.
STAGE TWO: we will build the midsection or “drum” of the icosahedron, con-
tained by two pentagons and 10 equilateral triangles.
STAGE THREE: we will put these 3 parts together, assembling our icosahedron.
D
[1] Draw a circle with center M, inscribe
regular pentagon ABCDE (Ch.4, Thm.7).
Draw MV perpendicular to the plane of
V
E
the pentagon.
C Cut off MV equal to the side of the dec-
agon (Ch.4, Thm.9) inscribed in the circle cir-
M cumscribing pentagon ABCDE. Of course, we
already know that MA, being the radius of that
circle, is equal to the side of the hexagon in-
A B
scribed in it.
[2] Since MA is the side of the hexagon, and VM is the side of the decagon, and since
MA and VM are drawn at right angles to each other, it follows that their hypotenuse, VA,
is equal to the side of the pentagon in the circle, namely AB (this Chapter, Thm.5).
So VA = AB.
[3] But MB, MC, MD, ME are also sides of the hexagon (i.e. radii of the same circle),
and therefore the hypotenuses VB, VC, VD, VE are also all equal to AB, the side of the
pentagon.
348
[4] Therefore ABV, BCV, CDV, DEV, EAV are all equal equilateral triangles (SSS).
And that is one of the "caps" to the icosahedron. We will need one for the top, and one
for the bottom.
D
E C
[5] Using the circle circumscribing
ABCDE, and using the radius of that cir-
A B cle (MA) as a height, complete a cylin-
der with circle ABCDE as the top of it.
349
STAGE THREE: Assembly of the icosahedron.
V
[10] We have made a "cap" in Stage One,
and added beneath it a "drum" in Stage Two.
Now just add another "cap" identical to the
D
E C
one made in Stage One underneath the
A
drum, with vertex Q.
B
Thus we have a complete solid con-
tained by 20 equal and equilateral triangles,
all having a side equal to AB, the side of the
L K pentagon with which we began. And every
solid angle on it is formed by 5 plane angles,
N H
G each of 60° (the angle of the equilateral tri-
angle). Thus the icosahedron is made.
Q
Q.E.F.
1
2
3 5
4 6
Remarks
7
8
The accompanying pattern can be used to make an icosahe-
9 dron. Draw your own larger version of it. Then cut it out,
10
and fold along the lines. Tip: triangles 1 through 5 will
11 make one "cap," just as triangles 16 through 20 will make
12 the other "cap." Triangles 6 through 15 will make the
13
"drum."
14
15 17
16 18
19
20
350
THEOREM 13: How to contain an icosahedron in a sphere.
V
D
E C Now let’s see how to wrap a sphere around our icosa-
A B hedron. First “imagine away” all the edges of it, re-
taining just the 12 vertices ABCDE and GHKLN and
L K
V and Q. That simplifies things!
N
G
H [1] Now, join VQ and bisect it at S.
I say that point S is the same distance from
Q every vertex of the icosahedron.
Choose any vertex, C. I say SC = SV.
V
[2] Clearly, if M is the center of circle ABCDE,
E D and J is the center of circle GHKLN, then MJ is the
M C axis of the cylinder, and VQ lies in line with it. And
A B
because our “caps” are of identical heights,
thus VJ = MQ.
S
L K [3] Also, VQ, being in line with the axis of the
J cylinder, is perpendicular to the planes of the circles,
N
G
H and therefore to every line in them that it cuts. Thus
VQ is at right angles to MC.
Q
[4] Since VM = side of decagon in circle ABCDE (made thus in Step 1 of Thm.12)
and MJ = side of hexagon in circle ABCDE (made thus in Step 5 of Thm.12)
thus VMJ is cut in mean and extreme ratio at M (Thm.4 of this Chapter)
i.e. VJ : JM = JM : MV
Q.E.F.
351
Remarks
V
3. Let's compare the radius of the circle around the icosahedron's
M C
pentagon (MC) to the diameter of the containing sphere (VQ).
Recall, first, that we made the height of the icosahedron's midsec-
S
tion equal to the radius of the circle around the pentagon, i.e. MJ
= MC. And since S bisects MJ, it follows that MS is half of MC.
J
352
Now £SC = £MS + £MC (Pythagorean Theorem)
so £SC = £(½ MC) + £MC (MS is equal to half of MC)
so £SC = ¼ £MC + £MC,
since the square on half of MC is one quarter of the square on the whole of MC.
5
Thus £SC = £MC (adding)
4
or 4 £SC = 5 £MC (multiplying both sides by 4)
i.e. 4 £SV = 5 £MC (SV = SC, being radii of the sphere)
or £VQ = 5 £MC (since VQ = 2SV)
So the square on the diameter of the containing sphere is equal to five times the square on
the radius of the circle around the icosahedron's pentagon.
D D
E E C E C
A A B A B
B P
L L M
O
N N G N G
K K F
H H
R
[1] Since the angle of a regular pentagon is 108° (Thm.2), therefore 3 of these is still
less than 4 right angles (i.e. less than 360°). So we can make a solid angle out of three of
them (Ch.9, Thm.20). Let it be done: ∠EAB, ∠BAN, ∠NAE are each 108°, the angle of
a regular pentagon, and they contain a solid angle at A.
[2] Cut the legs off equally, and complete the regular pentagons in each of our 3 an-
gles, namely ABCDE, ABGHN, ANKLE (Ch.4, Thm.7 Remarks)
353
[5] Complete new pentagons in these angles, namely GBCMF, KNHSR, LEDPO.
But there can be only one plane through straight line GH parallel to the plane of
LED (Ch.9, Thm.2 Remark). Therefore the planes of SGH and FGH, both parallel to the
plane of LED and both passing through GH, are in fact the same plane. Thus S, H, G, F
all lie in one plane parallel to the plane of LEDPO.
And SH = HG = GF, since they are sides of our pentagons,
And ∠SHG = ∠HGF = 108° (by the same reasoning as in Step 4),
So we are free to complete the pentagon in SHGF, namely SHGFT.
[9] Likewise XOPQU is a regular pentagon (reasoning the same way as in Step 8).
354
[10] Now RS is parallel to KH (in pentagon KNHSR)
and KH is parallel to EB (since KE = BH, & both parallel to AN)
so RS is parallel to EB
but EB is parallel to DC (in pentagon ABCDE)
so RS is parallel to DC
and likewise every side of RSTUX is parallel to a side of ABCDE. Therefore RSTUX,
like ABCDE, is a regular pentagon (and it is in a plane parallel to ABCDE).
Q.E.F.
Remarks
2. In Step 8 I said that DCMQP are all in one plane, and that this can be proved similarly
to the reasoning in Step 6. Since it is complicated, you might want to see it all done out.
Well, all right then! Here goes.
So PD, DC are parallel to RN, KH. But RN, KH intersect in the plane of pentagon
KNHSR. Therefore PDC are in a plane parallel to the plane of KNHSR (Ch.9, Thm.11).
355
So QM, MC are parallel to RH, NS. But RH, NS intersect in the plane of pentagon
KNHSR. Therefore QMC are in a plane parallel to the plane of KNHSR.
Since PDC and CMQ are all in a plane parallel to KNHSR, and only one plane
through C is parallel to the plane KNHSR, therefore D, C, M, Q, P are all in one plane.
D
E
C
A B
Take the dodecahedron we just made, and
L
M join EC, CG, GN, NE.
I say that ECGN is a square.
N
K G
H F
R
T
S
C
[2] From the symmetry of the regular pentagon, it is
L
E obvious that
A K B NAKV ≅ GBKV
so ∠AKV = ∠BKV
Thus ∠AKV is right (since ∠AKV & ∠BKV are equal
G
and adjacent). Again, ∠AKL is right by a similar ar-
N
V gument.
356
[5] Likewise NGTR is a square for all the same reasons, and it is equal to ECGN,
since they share a common side NG.
And thus, in fact, where two faces of the dodecahedron meet, such as at AB or
SH, they meet above a square. Since there are 6 pairs of faces on the dodecahedron,
therefore there are 6 equal squares that can be traced out along its surface by joining the
diagonals of its pentagons, and these 6 squares each share a side with four others, i.e. they
form a cube.
Q.E.D.
D
E C
Remarks A B
L M
With equal reason, ACFH is a square, and
if we pair off the faces differently, we get
another cube. There are, in total, five cu- K N G F
bes hiding in the dodecahedron, namely
one for every diagonal in pentagon H
ABCDE. R T
S
THEOREM 16: The diameter of the sphere containing the dodecahedron is the
diagonal of the cube hidden in it.
D
E C Consider the dodecahedron we have already
A B made. We saw in Theorem 15 that every diago-
M
nal in pentagon ABCDE is the side of a cube
L
hidden in the dodecahedron.
K N G F
[1] Thus RC is a diagonal of such a cube, with
H AC as its side. But LF is also a diagonal in it,
R T
and they bisect each other (Ch.9, Thm.27).
S
357
[2] But LF is also a diagonal of the cube with BD as a side, and SD is another diagonal
of that cube. Therefore LF and SD also bisect each other (Ch.9, Thm.27).
[3] And since LF has only one midpoint, which is also the midpoint of RC (Step 1), it
follows that RC, LF, SD all bisect each other.
[1] The fewest number of sides a face of a perfect solid can have is 3 sides, i.e. an
equilateral triangle. For there is no rectilineal plane figure with 2 sides or 1.
[2] But the most is 5 sides, i.e. a regular pentagon. For the angle of a regular hexa-
gon, having 6 sides, is 120° (double the angle of an equilateral triangle). And the fewest
number of faces which could form a solid angle is 3. But 3 of these angles of the hexa-
gon would add up to 360°, or 4 rights, and no solid angle can be made out of plane angles
that add up to 4 rights (Ch.9, Thm.17). So no solid angle can be made out of 3 regular
hexagons, and much less could any be made out of more than 3 regular hexagons.
And any regular polygon of more than 6 sides would have an angle more than
120°. And so no solid angle could be formed out any number of such angles, either. So
the greatest number of sides that can be found on the face of a perfect solid is 5.
[4] The fewest number of equilateral triangles that form a solid angle is 3, and this is
the angle of the TETRAHEDRON.
[5] The next is 4, and 4 equilateral triangles form the angle of the OCTAHEDRON.
358
[6] The next is 5, and 5 equilateral triangles form the angle of the ICOSAHEDRON.
But it is not possible to form a solid angle out of 6 or more equilateral triangles,
since 6 × 60° = 360°, or four rights.
[7] The fewest number of squares that form a solid angle is 3, and this is the angle of
the CUBE. But 4 or more right angles cannot form a solid angle, since 4 × 90° = 360°, or
four rights.
[8] The fewest number of pentagons that form a solid angle is 3, and this is the angle
of the DODECAHEDRON. But 4 or more cannot form a solid angle, since the angle of
the regular pentagon is 108°, and 4 × 108° = 432°, which is more than four rights.
Q.E.D.
Remarks
It is astonishing that when we limit ourselves to the use of only straight lines and circles,
we cannot make all the regular polygons in the world (we cannot, for example, make a 9-
sided regular polygon with only straight lines and circles), but we can make all the per-
fect solids!
THEOREM 18: A comparison of the five perfect solids regarding the number of
their vertices, edges, and faces.
For once, we will not need to prove anything, but only count. If you count the number of
vertices, edges, and faces in each solid, you can verify the entries in this table:
359
Notice that the cube and the octahedron have the same numbers, but in reverse order, and
the dodecahedron and icosahedron also form a symmetry that way. The tetrahedron’s
numbers are symmetrical by themselves.
This symmetry has an interesting consequence. In one way, we got a cube out of
a dodecahedron in Theorem 15. In another way, using the symmetries above, we can also
get an octahedron out of a cube. If we find the centers of the circles circumscribed about
each square face of the cube, the 6 resulting “centers” of the square faces are also the 6
vertices of an octahedron. This is clear from the uniformity with which those six points
are spread out from each other.
This works in reverse, too. Consider the eight faces of the octahedron, which are
equilateral triangles. If we find the “centers” of these triangles, namely the centers of the
circles circumscribed about them, we get 8 points spread apart in a uniform way, i.e. we
get the 8 vertices of a cube.
If we find the 4 centers of the 4 equilateral triangular faces of the tetrahedron, of
course we get the 4 vertices of another smaller tetrahedron.
If we take the 20 centers of the equilateral triangular faces of the icosahedron, we
get 20 points uniformly spread out, i.e. we get the 20 vertices of a dodecahedron. And if
we take the 12 pentagonal faces of the dodecahedron, finding the center of the circum-
scribed circle about each one, we get 12 points uniformly spread out, i.e. we get the 12
vertices of an icosahedron.
We can also get a tetrahedron out of a cube in much
B
the same way as we found a cube hidden in a dodecahe-
dron. Pick a vertex T on a cube. Across the three squares
meeting at T, draw their diagonals from T, namely TA, TB,
T
TC. And AB, BC, CA are three more diagonals on the re-
maining square faces. Now since the squares are all equal,
therefore these six diagonals are all equal, and therefore
C they contain four equal equilateral triangles. Therefore
A
ABCT is a tetrahedron. The other four vertices of the cube
are the vertices of another tetrahedron.
360
THEOREM 19: If an icosahedron and a dodecahedron are contained in the
same sphere, the circle circumscribing the pentagonal face of the dodecahedron is equal
to the circle circumscribing the triangular face of the icosahedron.
M R
G H
A B
Prove: The circles around ABCDE and GHK
T
are equal.
P S
[1] Join EC. So EC is the side of the cube inscribed in the sphere (Thms.15 - 16).
Therefore £MR = 3£EC (Thm.11)
[2] Let PS be the radius of the circle around “the pentagon” of the icosahedron, that
is, the pentagonal base of one of its “caps,” which is a pentagon with side equal to GK.
Therefore £MR = 5£PS (Thm.13, Remark 2)
[4] Now cut PS in the golden ratio at T, with PT the greater segment (Ch.6, Thm.22).
Since the diagonal of a regular pentagon is to its side as a whole line is to the
greater segment of itself when it is cut in mean and extreme ratio (Thm.3 Conclusion)
Thus EC : CD = SP : PT
Therefore £EC : £CD = £SP : £PT (Ch.11 Thm.9, Remark)
So 3£EC : 3£CD = 5£SP : 5£PT (Ch.5, Thm.12)
[5] Now, taking the last proportion from Step 4, we can add the antecedents to the
consequents and still have a proportion (Ch.5, Thm.14, Remark 2). That is,
3£EC : 3£EC + 3£CD = 5£SP : 5£SP + 5£PT
[6] But in Step 3, we saw that 5£PS = 3£EC. So in the proportion of Step 5, we can
replace 3£EC with 5£PS. Let's do it:
5£SP : 3£EC + 3£CD = 5£SP : 5£SP + 5£PT
361
[7] Now PS is the radius of the circle in which GK is a side of the regular pentagon
(that is how we made PS, in Step 2). And PS is therefore the side of the hexagon in that
circle. And since PT is the greater segment of PS when it is cut in the golden ratio, PT is
the side of the decagon in that same circle (Thm.4 Remarks).
Therefore £PT + £SP = £GK (Thm.5)
or 5£PT + 5£SP = 5£GK (both sides × 5)
[9] Now, in one and the same circle, 3 times the square on the diagonal of the in-
scribed pentagon plus 3 times the square on the side of that pentagon equals 5 times the
square on the inscribed equilateral triangle (Ch.11, Thm.7 Remarks). But EC is the di-
agonal of a pentagon, and CD is its side, so if Z is the side of the equilateral triangle in-
scribed in circle ABCDE, then
3£EC + 3£CD = 5£Z
But we have just shown that
3£EC + 3£CD = 5£GK (Step 8)
And therefore it follows that
GK = Z
That is, GK is equal to the side of the equilateral triangle inscribed in circle ABCDE. But
GK is the side of the equilateral triangle inscribed in circle GKH. Therefore circles
ABCDE and GKH must be equal.
Q.E.D.
THEOREM 20: When the five solids are all inscribed in the same sphere, their
order, from longest edge-length to shortest, is: tetrahedron, octahedron, cube, icosahe-
dron, dodecahedron.
362
3
[1] Now £Diam = £Tet (Thm.9)
2
So ⅔ £Diam = £Tet (double both, then one third both)
[3] So, since the square on the side of the tetrahedron is two thirds the square on the
diameter (Step 1), whereas the square on the side of the octahedron is only half the square
on the diameter (Step 2), it follows that
£Tet > £Oct
thus Tet > Oct
i.e. the side of the Tetrahedron is greater than that of the Octahedron.
Let AGEHC be one pentagonal face of our dodecahedron. Draw a circle around
it, with center K, and inscribe equilateral triangle ABL in it. Join KA, KG, KB, KE.
Thus AE, being a diagonal of the dodecahedron’s pentagonal face, is the side of
the cube inscribed in our sphere, and AB is the side of the icosahedron.
Since ∠AKB stands on one third of the circumference from the center of the cir-
cle, therefore ∠AKB = 120°. But ∠AKE stands on two fifths of the circumference from
the center of the circle, and therefore ∠AKE = 144°. And yet both stand on less than a
semi-circumference, and therefore it follows that
AE > AB
i.e. the side of the Cube is greater than the side of the Icosahedron.
[6] But ∠AKG is only one fifth of 360°, i.e. 72°, whereas ∠AKB is 120°. Therefore
AB > AG
i.e. the side of the Icosahedron is greater than the side of the Dodecahedron.
Q.E.D.
363
Remarks
The order of the 5 solids in this Theorem also happens to put them in order of (1) in-
creasing surface area, and (2) increasing volume, when all are inscribed in the same
sphere. Two more interesting Theorems, whose proofs I leave to the reader, are these:
(a) When inscribed all in the same sphere, the surface of the Icosahedron is to that of the
Dodecahedron as the edge of the Cube is to the edge of the Icosahedron.
(b) When inscribed both in the same sphere, the volumes of the Dodecahedron and Ico-
sahedron have the same ratio as their surface areas.
Given a tetrahedron ABCV, can you see how to cut it with a plane so that the section is a
square?
B
H
A
P
R G
364