0% found this document useful (0 votes)
31 views14 pages

CH 03

Economía

Uploaded by

ladyVite
Copyright
© © All Rights Reserved
We take content rights seriously. If you suspect this is your content, claim it here.
Available Formats
Download as PDF, TXT or read online on Scribd
0% found this document useful (0 votes)
31 views14 pages

CH 03

Economía

Uploaded by

ladyVite
Copyright
© © All Rights Reserved
We take content rights seriously. If you suspect this is your content, claim it here.
Available Formats
Download as PDF, TXT or read online on Scribd
You are on page 1/ 14

Chapter 3

PREFERENCES AND UTILITY

Copyright ©2005 by South-Western, a division of Thomson Learning. All rights reserved. 1

Axioms of Rational Choice


• Completeness
– if A and B are any two situations, an
individual can always specify exactly one of
these possibilities:
• A is preferred to B
• B is preferred to A
• A and B are equally attractive

Axioms of Rational Choice


• Transitivity
– if A is preferred to B, and B is preferred to
C, then A is preferred to C
– assumes that the individual’s choices are
internally consistent

1
Axioms of Rational Choice
• Continuity
– if A is preferred to B, then situations suitably
“close to” A must also be preferred to B
– used to analyze individuals’ responses to
relatively small changes in income and
prices

Utility
• Given these assumptions, it is possible to
show that people are able to rank in order
all possible situations from least desirable
to most
• Economists call this ranking utility
– if A is preferred to B, then the utility assigned
to A exceeds the utility assigned to B
U(A) > U(B)

Utility
• Utility rankings are ordinal in nature
– they record the relative desirability of
commodity bundles
• Because utility measures are not unique,
it makes no sense to consider how much
more utility is gained from A than from B
• It is also impossible to compare utilities
between people

2
Utility
• Utility is affected by the consumption of
physical commodities, psychological
attitudes, peer group pressures, personal
experiences, and the general cultural
environment
• Economists generally devote attention to
quantifiable options while holding
constant the other things that affect utility
– ceteris paribus assumption
7

Utility
• Assume that an individual must choose
among consumption goods x1, x2,…, xn
• The individual’s rankings can be shown
by a utility function of the form:
utility = U(x1, x2,…, xn; other things)
– this function is unique up to an order-
preserving transformation

Economic Goods
• In the utility function, the x’s are assumed
to be “goods”
– more is preferred to less
Quantity of y
Preferred to x*, y*

y*

?
Worse
than
x*, y* Quantity of x
x* 9

3
Indifference Curves
• An indifference curve shows a set of
consumption bundles among which the
individual is indifferent
Quantity of y
Combinations (x1, y1) and (x2, y2)
provide the same level of utility

y1

y2 U1

Quantity of x
x1 x2 10

Indifference Curve Map


• Each point must have an indifference
curve through it

Quantity of y

Increasing utility

U3 U1 < U2 < U3
U2

U1
Quantity of x
11

Transitivity
• Can any two of an individual’s indifference
curves intersect?
The individual is indifferent between A and C.
Quantity of y The individual is indifferent between B and C.
Transitivity suggests that the individual
should be indifferent between A and B

But B is preferred to A
C
because B contains more
B x and y than A
U2

A U1

Quantity of x
12

4
Marginal Rate of Substitution
• The negative of the slope of the
indifference curve at any point is called
the marginal rate of substitution (MRS)
Quantity of y

dy
MRS  
dx U U1
y1

y2 U1

Quantity of x
x1 x2 13

Marginal Rate of Substitution


• MRS changes as x and y change
– reflects the individual’s willingness to trade y
for x
Quantity of y At (x1, y1), the indifference curve is steeper.
The person would be willing to give up more
y to gain additional units of x

At (x2, y2), the indifference curve


is flatter. The person would be
y1 willing to give up less y to gain
additional units of x
y2 U1

Quantity of x
x1 x2 14

Utility and the MRS


• Suppose an individual’s preferences for
hamburgers (y) and soft drinks (x) can
be represented by
utility  10  x  y
• Solving for y, we get
y = 100/x

• Solving for MRS = -dy/dx:


MRS = -dy/dx = 100/x2
15

5
Utility and the MRS
MRS = -dy/dx = 100/x2
• Note that as x rises, MRS falls
– when x = 5, MRS = 4
– when x = 20, MRS = 0.25

16

Marginal Utility
• Suppose that an individual has a utility
function of the form
utility = U(x,y)
• The total differential of U is
U U
dU  dx  dy
x y

• Along any indifference curve, utility is


constant (dU = 0)
17

Deriving the MRS


• Therefore, we get:
U
 x
dy
MRS  
dx Uconstant
U
y
• MRS is the ratio of the marginal utility of
x to the marginal utility of y

18

6
Diminishing Marginal Utility
and the MRS
• Intuitively, it seems that the assumption
of decreasing marginal utility is related to
the concept of a diminishing MRS
– diminishing MRS requires that the utility
function be quasi-concave (no linear
segments)
• this is independent of how utility is measured
– diminishing marginal utility depends on how
utility is measured
• Thus, these two concepts are different 19

Convexity
• A set of points is convex if any two points
can be joined by a straight line that is
contained completely within the set
Quantity of y
The assumption of a diminishing MRS is
equivalent to the assumption that all
combinations of x and y which are
preferred to x* and y* form a convex set

y*
U1

Quantity of x
x* 20

Convexity
• If the indifference curve is convex, then
the combination (x1 + x2)/2, (y1 + y2)/2 will
be preferred to either (x1,y1) or (x2,y2)
Quantity of y
This implies that “well-balanced” bundles are preferred
to bundles that are heavily weighted toward one
commodity

y1
(y1 + y2)/2

y2 U1

Quantity of x
x1 (x1 + x2)/2 x2 21

7
Monotonic transformation of
utility funcitons
• Suppose that the utility function is

utility  x  y
• We can simplify the algebra by taking the
logarithm of this function
U*(x,y) = ln[U(x,y)] = 0.5 ln x + 0.5 ln y

22

Monotonic transformation of
utility funcitons
• Thus,

U * 0.5
MRS  x  x 
y
U * 0.5 x
y y

23

Monotonic transformation
of utility funcitons
• Suppose that the utility function is
utility  x 2  y 2

• For this example, it is easier to use the


transformation
U*(x,y) = [U(x,y)]2 = x2 + y2

24

8
Monotonic transformation
of utility funcitons
• Thus,

U *
2x x
MRS  x  
U * 2y y
y

25

Examples of Utility Functions


• Cobb-Douglas Utility
utility = U(x,y) = xy
where  and  are positive constants
– The relative sizes of  and  indicate the
relative importance of the goods

26

Examples of Utility Functions


• Perfect Substitutes
utility = U(x,y) = x + y
Quantity of y
The indifference curves will be linear.
The MRS will be constant along the
indifference curve.

U3

U2
U1
Quantity of x
27

9
Examples of Utility Functions
• Perfect Complements
utility = U(x,y) = min (x, y)
Quantity of y
The indifference curves will be
L-shaped. Only by choosing more
of the two goods together can utility
be increased.

U3

U2

U1
Quantity of x
28

Examples of Utility Functions


• CES Utility (Constant elasticity of
substitution)
utility = U(x,y) = x/ + y/
when   0 and
utility = U(x,y) = ln x + ln y
when  = 0
– Perfect substitutes   = 1
– Cobb-Douglas   = 0
– Perfect complements   = -
29

Examples of Utility Functions


• CES Utility (Constant elasticity of
substitution)
– The elasticity of substitution () is equal to
1/(1 - )
• Perfect substitutes   = 
• Fixed proportions   = 0

30

10
Homothetic Preferences
• If the MRS depends only on the ratio of
the amounts of the two goods, not on
the quantities of the goods, the utility
function is homothetic
– Perfect substitutes  MRS is the same at
every point
– Perfect complements  MRS =  if y/x >
/, undefined if y/x = /, and MRS = 0 if
y/x < /
31

Homothetic Preferences
• For the general Cobb-Douglas function,
the MRS can be found as
U
x  1y   y
MRS  x   
U x  y 1  x
y

32

Nonhomothetic Preferences
• Some utility functions do not exhibit
homothetic preferences
utility = U(x,y) = x + ln y

U
1
MRS  x   y
U 1
y y

33

11
The Many-Good Case
• Suppose utility is a function of n goods
given by
utility = U(x1, x2,…, xn)
• The total differential of U is

U U U
dU  dx1  dx 2  ...  dx n
x1 x 2 x n

34

The Many-Good Case


• We can find the MRS between any two
goods by setting dU = 0
U U
dU  0  dxi  dx j
xi x j

• Rearranging, we get
U
dx j x i
MRS( x i for x j )   
dx i U
x j 35

Multigood Indifference
Surfaces
• We will define an indifference surface
as being the set of points in n
dimensions that satisfy the equation
U(x1,x2,…xn) = k
where k is any preassigned constant

36

12
Multigood Indifference
Surfaces
• If the utility function is quasi-concave,
the set of points for which U  k will be
convex
– all of the points on a line joining any two
points on the U = k indifference surface will
also have U  k

37

Important Points to Note:


• If individuals obey certain behavioral
postulates, they will be able to rank all
commodity bundles
– the ranking can be represented by a utility
function
– in making choices, individuals will act as if
they were maximizing this function
• Utility functions for two goods can be
illustrated by an indifference curve map
38

Important Points to Note:


• The negative of the slope of the
indifference curve measures the marginal
rate of substitution (MRS)
– the rate at which an individual would trade
an amount of one good (y) for one more unit
of another good (x)
• MRS decreases as x is substituted for y
– individuals prefer some balance in their
consumption choices
39

13
Important Points to Note:
• A few simple functional forms can capture
important differences in individuals’
preferences for two (or more) goods
– Cobb-Douglas function
– linear function (perfect substitutes)
– fixed proportions function (perfect
complements)
– CES function
• includes the other three as special cases
40

Important Points to Note:


• It is a simple matter to generalize from
two-good examples to many goods
– studying peoples’ choices among many
goods can yield many insights
– the mathematics of many goods is not
especially intuitive, so we will rely on two-
good cases to build intuition

41

14

You might also like