Picturesque
Picturesque
I. INTRODUCTION
I n the last chapter I argued that eighteenth-century English gardens, though declared sisters to
painting as well as poetry, neither copied landscape paintings nor functioned like them. I
should like now to explore two further relations that may have held between gardens and
paintings in the eighteenth century: (1) gardens remind us of particular paintings or of the style
of a particular painter, and (2) gardens are created using the principles and techniques of
painting.
The first relationship, that gardens remind us of paintings, or that we see gardens in terms
of paintings, leads to an exploration of the picturesque, an aesthetic category first popularized in
England in the last third of the eighteenth century. The term picturesque was applied to
landscapes in many guises---to landscape poems and landscape paintings, as well as to gardens
and natural scenes. I should like to begin my discussion of the picturesque by singling out two
gardens that seem to require us to take painting into account when we interpret them.
Charles Hamilton's Painshill Park, described in detail at the beginning of chapter 4, is the
first garden that I want to mention in the context of the picturesque. Recall that Painshill
resembled Stourhead in layout. Circling a central lake, viewers encountered stylistically varied
assortment of structures and an artfully designed set of vistas. Despite its similarities to
Stourhead, I offered evidence that Painshill should be classed as "painterly" rather than a poetic
garden. First, particular sections of the garden were said to copy particular paintings by Salvator
Rosa and Gaspard Dughet; second, no obvious iconographic program links Painshill's
architectural and sculptural components in the way that so many of Stourhead's features refer to
the Aeneid; and finally, contemporary viewers commented predominantly on visual aspects of
the garden, emphasizing the composition and sequence of scenes rather than some underlying
meaning conveyed.
Painshill engages the art of painting and the concept of the picturesque in both of the
ways set out at the beginning of this chapter: (1) portions of the garden seem to remind
viewers of the work of particular artists, setting in motion trains of association that link scenes in
the garden to paintings visitors have seen in the past; and (2), Hamilton seems to have employed
the principles of painting to construct the scenes, landskips, and vistas mentioned earlier.1
Before assessing these claims, let us consider one more English eighteenth-century
garden. In 1758 Thomas Duncombe improved his Yorkshire estate by carving a half-mile long
grassy terrace atop a steep hillside. The hill overlooked the sprawling ruins of Rievaulx Abbey, a
thirteenth-century Cistercian monastery, and Duncombe's terrace was intended to provide a
panoramic overview of that site. Visitors walking along the slope encountered a changing set of
stunning vistas as different portions of the monastic complex came into view. The skeletal
remains of the chapter church dominated the ruins. Ghostly ranks of clerestory windows topped
the Gothic arches of its lower bays. Each end of Duncombe's terrace was marked by a temple,
one round and in the Tuscan style, the other square with an Ionic portico. The latter temple was
equipped as a "banqueting room," with frescoed walls and ceiling, elaborately carved woodwork,
ornate furniture, and a subterranean kitchen.
Rievaulx Terrace was clearly a marvelous pleasure ground for its owner and his guests.
In designing the terrace, Duncombe was guided by a number of precedents. His grandfather, the
first Thomas Duncombe, had commissioned a similar terrace after completing his new house,
Duncombe Park, in 1713,2 while the idea of including actual ruins may well have come from
John Aislabie's neighboring Yorkshire estate, Studley Royal, which incorporated the Gothic
ruins of Fountains Abbey.3 Despite these influences, Rievaulx Terrace is unique. While other
English gardens had incorporated actual ruins or built artificial ones, Duncombe dispensed with
the garden altogether and provided nothing but a view. In creating his terrace he appropriated
that view and framed it in a way that controlled and orchestrated each viewer's experience. If we
consider Rievaulx Terrace as the limiting case of an English landscape garden, we can see that it
marks the culmination of an aesthetic revolution. It epitomizes eighteenth-century taste for the
picturesque.
2. THE PICTURESQUE
The side-screens will be Ewe-Cragg, the rising ground in Gowbarrow park, and
some other less striking objects on the right hand: on the left, a small coppice,
Sandwich-Dod, Sandwich-Cascade, and Birk-Fell: the front screen will take in
Glencoyn-House, Lyulph's Tower, and the picturesque ground on which they
stand; whilst Glencoyn Pike, Common-Fell, Catesby Pike, and Helveylin, suc-
ceeding each other in just degrees of distinctness, close the distances (30).
Consider one more example, instructions from R. H. Newell's Letters on the Scenery of Wales
(1821) for capturing Llaugharne Castle: "Bring the Castle exactly within the angle made by the
sloping hill and woody steep before it. Then ascend or descend, till the water and three of the
promontories appear above the castle. In this station the sea bounds the distance" (30).
Such a rigid approach to the appreciation and representation of landscape scenery could
not but become formulaic and stultifying. Andrews explains that English landscape painters
embraced principles derived from the works of Claude and Dughet. These principles included an
"obligatory, mellow master-tint," a structural division of the painted scene into three distances---
"a background, a strongly lit middle or second distance, and a darkened foreground"---and "the
device of the repoussoir object, the foreground framing trees, or the tree and ruin, or mountain
sides, to prevent one's eye from straying outside the canvas and to push it into the middle
distance" (29).10 Strict reliance on conventions of this sort had a deleterious effect on both
landscape painting and landscape appreciation. Andrews comments, "The limitations of the
Claudean orthodoxies had important consequences for the Picturesque tourist, whether or not he
was himself a painter. It limited the kinds of landscape eligible for praise and study" (34).
A tension should be evident in even the limited account of the picturesque sketched so
far. If "picturesque" is glossed according to Gilpin's usage to mean "whatever might look good in
a picture," then any and every landscape scene is potentially picturesque. That is, the term is so
all-inclusive as to be almost meaningless. If, on the other hand, the ideal landscape to be imitated
and appreciated is that which exhibits the structure of a painting by Claude, then many other
sorts of appealing landscapes are overlooked, for instance, those that would be represented by
Dutch and Flemish masters, by Rosa and Girtin, and so on. In sum, our initial approach to the
picturesque via Gilpin's guidebooks and the tourist tradition they generated has led to a standoff
between two equally unhelpful interpretations. The first---"like a picture" [any picture]---is too
broad, while the second---"like a Claude"---is too narrow. I would like to begin again and
examine a more theoretical take on the picturesque, one generated by the debate later in the
century between Sir Uvedale Price and Richard Payne Knight. While neither theorist in the end
provides us with a more satisfactory link between literal landscapes and pictured ones, the details
of their disagreement are interesting in and of themselves and illuminate garden history in a
number of ways.
Let me briefly set the scene. Born three years apart, Sir Uvedale Price (1747--1829) and Richard
Payne Knight (1750-1824) became neighbors and friends. Price was educated at Eton and at
Oxford. Knight, sickly as a child, was educated at home and never went to university. As young
men both inherited Herefordshire seats and both embarked on grand tours. Price came into the
estate of Foxley at the age of fourteen, the same age at which Knight inherited Downton.11 From
1774 to 1778 Knight built Downton Castle, a crenellated, irregular country house whose
asymmetrical plan Nikolaus Pevsner declares "extremely unusual" for the time. Moreover,
Downton's medieval exterior with round and polygonal towers and battlements belied its Grecian
interior with classical orders throughout and a round dining room in imitation of the Pantheon.12
Price described the three major preoccupations of his life as "pictures, scenery, and
music."13 Pevsner calls him a "one-book author" compared to Knight who wrote on topics
ranging from the worship of Priapus to the Greek alphabet to judgments of taste---though
Pevsner says of three publications on the picturesque that appeared in 1794, "One of these was a
masterpiece: Uvedale Price's Essay on the Picturesque. "14 Knight became a member of the
prestigious Society of Dilettanti in 1781 and was proud of his independent status as a scholar.15
Both men wrote more than one work on landscape and the picturesque. Knight's initial effort,
The Landscape (1794), a "didactic poem," was followed by a much more ambitious aesthetic
treatise, An Analytic Inquiry into the Principles of Taste (1805), while Price revised his Essay on
the Picturesque (1794) for expanded editions in 1796-98 and 1810,16 and he published A
Dialogue on the Distinct Characters of the Picturesque and Beautiful (1801) to counter a note
Knight had added to the second edition of The Landscape.17
Although their discussions of the picturesque became increasingly acrimonious, Price and
Knight initially agreed in their judgments of landscape and of art. In fact, Knight invited Price to
publish his Essay jointly with The Landscape. Price declined and the two works appeared
separately in 1794. In the ensuing years doctrinal differences drove the two theorists apart. While
they may have agreed in admiring rugged scenes, busy paintings, and "unimproved" gardens, the
reasons behind their judgments differed significantly. Let me compare their theories as presented
in Price's Essay on the Picturesque (1794) and Knight's Analytic Inquiry into the Principles of
Taste (1805).
I have argued that Price's Essay suggests two accounts of the picturesque and that neither one is
satisfactory. The fact that painters and gardeners share compositional concerns and techniques
does not explain the sudden vogue for the picturesque. And Price's fascination with irregular and
intricate objects and scenes does not link the picturesque to the art of painting. I want to turn now
to the opposing theory of Richard Payne Knight to see whether it provides a more helpful
understanding of eighteenth-century taste. Knight shared Price's disdain for the work of
Capability Brown, yet his Analytical Inquiry into the Principles of Taste offers a definition of the
picturesque quite unlike that of Price's Essay. It was written from very different motives and
reflects very different influences.
Even a brief examination will show that the Inquiry and the Essay differ in scope.
Knight's work is much more ambitious than Price's. Knight was not addressing the relatively
narrow issue of garden improvements; he was attempting to construct a full-fledged theory of
taste, in the tradition of Gerard, Allison, Shaftesbury, and (ultimately) Kant. Accordingly, he
organized the Inquiry by mental faculties, beginning with chapters on each of the five senses,
followed by others on the association of ideas, imagination, judgment, and the passions. In
addition, Knight's work is much more erudite than Price's. While Price's debt to Burke is clear,
Knight's treatise is scattered with references to such figures as Plato, Aristotle, Locke, Berkeley,
Hume, Reid, Newton, and more. Overall, Knight set out to answer the question "Is there a
standard of taste?" And his attempt incorporated many of the intellectual currents of his time,
among them associationism, subjectivism, and theories of the operations of the mind.
Knight discussed the picturesque in his long central chapter on the imagination. He
differed most strikingly from Price in denying the picturesque a distinct objective character.30
Declaring that Price's "great, fundamental error" was "seeking for distinctions in external objects
which only exist in the modes and habits of viewing and considering them" (196), Knight located
the picturesque not in the external world but in the observer's mind. That is to say, for Knight the
picturesque was a mode of association.
Knight ascribed all intellectual pleasures to the association of ideas. He enunciated the
basic principle of association as follows: "To a mind richly stored, almost every object of nature
or art that presents itself to the senses, either excites fresh trains and combinations of ideas, or
vivifies and strengthens those which existed before" (143). He offered various examples to
illustrate this thesis. A peasant and a scientist, he claimed, would respond to the natural world
quite differently. "Every insect, plant, or fossil, which the peasant treads upon unheeded, is, to
the naturalist and philosopher, a subject of curious inquiry and speculation" (143). An
uninformed observer would see the heavens as a blue vault with twinkling fires, while a learned
viewer would be aware of "unnumbered worlds, distributed through the boundless vacuity of
unmeasurable space; and peopled, perhaps, with different orders of intelligent beings" (144).
And finally, mention of London or Paris would raise very different ideas in the minds of those
who had only heard of these cities, those who had visited them briefly, and those who had
resided a long time in either capital (145).
While taste, for Knight, was based on feeling and sentiment rather than belief and opinion
(3), a similar relativity applied with regard to judgments of taste.31 That is, people differently
versed in the arts could be expected to appreciate painting, music, and poetry in different
degrees. This was because "much of the pleasure, which we receive from painting, sculpture,
music, poetry, etc. arises from our associating other ideas with those immediately excited by
them. Hence the productions of these arts are never thoroughly enjoyed but by persons, whose
minds are enriched by a variety of kindred and corresponding imagery" (145).32
Knight defined picturesque objects and circumstances as those so connected to other
objects in nature and circumstances in society as to "be enabled to excite similar or associated
trains of ideas, in minds so enriched, and consequently to afford them similar pleasures" (146).
He also claimed that such objects and circumstances would only afford pleasure to perceivers
conversant with the art of painting (146). The following long passage spells out the mechanism
by which association constitutes the picturesque:
This very relation to painting expressed by the word picturesque, is that which
affords the whole pleasure derived from association; which can, therefore, only be
felt by persons who have correspondent ideas to associate; that is, by persons in a
certain degree conversant in that art. Such persons being in the habit of viewing,
and receiving pleasure from fine pictures, will naturally feel pleasure in viewing
those objects in nature, which have called forth those powers of imitation and
embellishment .... The objects recall to the mind the imitations, which skill, taste,
and genius have provided; and these again recall to the mind the objects
themselves (154--55).
6. TRANSFER OF TECHNIQUE
While neither Price nor Knight favored squinting women with pimpled faces, both undoubtedly
preferred Rievaulx Abbey in ruins just as they preferred lanes rutted and woods overgrown.
Their attempts to justify these preferences and support them in theory comprise an interesting
and important episode in the history of taste. I have tried to show that their efforts to identify the
category picturesque pulled in different directions. While they may have agreed in their
assessments of landscape gardeners and landscape paintings, they did not agree regarding what
was picturesque and why. Moreover, Price's and Knight's theories of the picturesque, once their
details are set out, have no essential connection to the art of painting. Price defined the
picturesque in terms of objective qualities---roughness, irregularity, intricacy, sudden variation,
and the like-which aren't possessed by each and every painting, and which characterize many
objects that are not paintings. Knight defined the picturesque in terms of subjective qualities---
individuals' associations---but these may be mistaken or idiosyncratic and thus fail to pick out
any paintings at all.
There remains one interesting eighteenth-century debate which grew out of the pre-
occupation with the picturesque; this debate has consequences for garden history and for the
proposal that gardening and painting are sister arts. I have in mind a dispute between Sir Uvedale
Price and the garden designer Humphry Repton concerning the claim that gardening and painting
share principles and technique. This claim represents the weakest possible interpretation of the
view that painting and gardening are sister arts. The debate between Price and Repton became
quite convoluted. In this final section I will try to outline and critique its main twists and turns.
We have already met Sir Uvedale Price. Humphry Repton, born in Bury St. Edmunds in 1752,
came to the profession of landscape gardening late in life. After trying various ways to earn his
living-textile manufacturer, merchant, civil servant, essayist, art critic---he suddenly decided,
some five years after the death of Capability Brown, to set himself up as a landscape gardener.
Repton was skilled at drawing and sketching, and his circle of acquaintance from his earlier
years included experts in botany and horticulture.41 Dorothy Stroud writes that within two years
Repton "had firmly established himself as the leading landscape designer of his day.”42
A hallmark of Repton's practice were his Red Books, leather-bound volumes in which he
outlined his suggestions for potential clients. The Red Books described the improvements
Repton had in mind and illustrated them through an ingenious system of flaps and slides that
allowed comparison of each scene before and after its proposed alteration.
Some garden historians go so far as to identify a picturesque style of gardening, with
Repton as its main proponent. In many respects, Repton carried on the design traditions of his
predecessor Brown, whose gardens helped spark the picturesque movement by generating such
antipathy in Price and Knight. Fleming and Gore report that after his father's death (in 1783),
"The son of Capability Brown gave Repton access to his father's papers, tacitly admitting him as
his successor; and, to an extent, Repton did consider himself in this role.”43 There were,
however, stylistic differences between Brown's and Repton's creations. Comparing the two
designers, Dorothy Stroud notes that Repton's "plantations tended to be thicker, while the small
buildings in the grounds frequently assumed a rustic rather than a classical character."44 Repton
also objected to placing a belt of trees all around an estate; he planted groups of trees atop hills in
a manner quite different from Brown's clumps;45 also, he advocated a formal treatment,
including flowers, terraces, and fountains, in the area directly around the house.46 Though
initially enthusiastic about the design principles defended by Price and Knight, Repton soon had
second thoughts and distanced himself from their views. In the end, both his gardens and his
gardening principles seem too eclectic and too conciliatory to merit the label "picturesque.”47
Nevertheless, his debate with Price regarding the applicability of principles of painting to the art
of gardening illuminates one last, attenuated sense of that term---one highlighting similarity not
of form, nor of association, but of technique.
Repton and Price began discussing gardens, painting, and the picturesque because Repton
felt that both he himself, as well as Brown, with whose work he was identified, had been unfairly
attacked in Price's Essay. Price sent him an early copy of that work, and Repton was so
distressed that he wrote "A Letter to Sir Uvedale Price, Esq.," of which he says that
this letter, which has been written at various opportunities during my journey into
Derbyshire, has insensibly grown to a bulk which I little expected when I began
it: I shall therefore cause a few copies to be printed, to serve as a general defense
of an art which, I trust, will not be totally suppressed, although you so earnestly
recommend every gentleman to become his own landscape gardener.48
Repton also included the letter as a footnote to the Appendix of his volume Sketches and
Hints on Landscape Gardening (1794). Price in turn responded with a book-length "Letter to H.
Repton, Esq., on the Application of the Practice As Well As the Principles of
Landscape-Painting to Landscape-Gardening" (subtitled "Intended as a Supplement to the Essay
on the Picturesque").49 The subject of the exchange between the two authors was the extent to
which the principles of painting could be applied to the art of gardening. In his Essay, Price
defined the "great leading principles" of painting as general composition, grouping the separate
parts, harmony of tints, and unity of character (64). He went on to add "breadth and effect of
light and shade" to the list, noting that it is essential to painting but "at first sight hardly seems
within the province of the improver" (64). A good deal farther on in the Essay, Price adds one
last item to his list---connection---declaring that the "defect, the greatest of all [of the present
system of improving] and the most opposite to the principles of painting, is want of connection---
a passion for making everything distinct and separate" (179).50
These are the principles on which Price believes landscape gardening should be based.
I shall discuss the principles themselves---and the underlying assumption that each art has
a set of leading principles---in more detail below. In exhorting gentlemen to be their own
improvers, Price is urging them to study the masterpieces of landscape painting, extract these
principles, and apply them in designing their estates. Thus he states in the Essay that:
If a taste for drawing and painting and a knowledge of their principles made a part
of every gentleman's education; if, instead of hiring a professed improver, to
torture his grounds after an established model, each improved his own place
according to general conceptions drawn from nature and pictures, or from hints
which favorite masters in painting, or favorite parts of nature suggested to him,
there might in time be a great variety in the styles of improvement, and all of
them with peculiar excellences (230).
Price returns to this same theme in the Letter: "It is true that I have very earnestly and generally
recommended it to gentlemen who have places, that they should qualify themselves for
becoming their own landscape gardeners, by one of the most pleasing and liberal of all studies;
that of the principles of painting, the works of painters and of nature" (119--20). Elsewhere Price
notes that men of liberal education who pass time at their country seats are continually among
landscapes (120--21), and he predicts that "with the least attention to pictures and to
composition, the principles of landscape gardening would insensibly press themselves upon their
minds" (Letter, 121).
Price does qualify his advice to this extent: he doesn't recommend that improvers study
art exclusively; they must also study nature. Thus he remarks that "nothing can be farther from
my intention... than to recommend the study of pictures in preference to that of nature, much less
to the exclusion of it. Whoever studies art alone, will have a narrow pedantic manner of
considering all objects" (Essay, 3).
Repton initially agreed with Price's views. Some time before publication of Price's Essay
and Repton's Sketches and Hints, the two had taken a tour together down the Wye River
valley.51 Both allude to the journey in their letters. Price recalls advising Repton, as they
admired the striking scenery, to study "what the higher artists have done, both in their pictures
and their drawings" (43). He also notes that Repton seemed not sufficiently acquainted with the
work of the great masters, since he did not make the sorts of references to paintings that might
have been expected:
I will frankly own, that from all the conversations which have passed between us,
I had (perhaps rashly) conceived that you were not very conversant in them: I
cannot recollect, amidst all the romantic scenes we viewed together, your having
made any of those allusions to the works of various masters which might naturally
have occurred to a person who had studied, or even observed them with common
attention (43).
Repton himself remarks that "During the pleasant hours we passed together amidst the romantic
scenery of the Wye, I do remember my acknowledging that an enthusiasm for the picturesque
had originally led me to fancy greater affinity between Painting and Gardening than I found to
exist after more mature consideration and greater experience" (70 n.). He places a similar
disclaimer in a later edition of Sketches and Hints: "The want of duly considering the affinity
between painting and gardening is the source of those errors and false principles which I find too
frequently prevailing in the admirers or connoisseurs in painting: and I do not hesitate to
acknowledge that I once supposed the two arts to be more intimately connected than my practice
and experience have since confirmed" (57).52 The contemporary garden historian Edward
Hyams admiringly quotes his predecessor, Marie-Louise Gothein, who in her work Geschichte
der Gartenkunst (1928) declared Repton "the first man to free himself from the exaggerated idea
of a similarity between painting and landscape gardening" (131).
In Sketches and Hints Repton identifies four principles of landscape gardening. These
include such recommendations as "display the natural beauties of every situation" and "disguise
the boundary to give an appearance of extent."53 Interestingly, there is no overlap between these
and the principles of painting cited by Price. This may be because Repton's principles are
taxonomic rather than practical. They do not tell us how to design gardens---
where to dig, what to plant, what architectural features to incorporate. Rather, Repton offers his
principles in order to distinguish the modern style of landscape gardening from what he calls the
ancient style. (These differ above all in their degree of what we would deem naturalness.)
Overall, Repton offers three arguments in the course of his writings for rejecting the theoretical
relationship Price proposes between painting and gardening. The first argument concerns
differences between painted scenes and natural ones; the second concerns a conflict between
aesthetic or picturesque values, on the one hand, and comfort and convenience, on the other; the
third concerns claims of expertise. These arguments are convoluted, and they tend to blend into
one another. Let me outline the first two.54
Here is Repton's first argument. In chapter 8 of Sketches and Hints, he lists five differ-
ences between scenes in nature and pictures on canvas, all of them owing to technical facts about
optics, vision, and linear perspective. They are:
(1) The painter paints each view from a fixed spot, while the gardener
"surveys his scenery while in motion" (53).55
(2) A garden or a scene in nature encompasses a "quantity of view, or field
of vision.. . much greater than any picture will admit" (53).
(3) The prospect or view down a steep hill is one of the most pleasing of
all scenes, but one that cannot be painted.
(4) The painter's light can come from any point of the compass but "can
only be made strong by contrast of shade” (54).
(5) Foregrounds are treated differently in gardening and in painting: "the
neat gravel walk or close-mown lawn would ill supply the place, in painting, of a
rotten tree, a bunch of docks, or a broken road, passing under a steep bank, cov-
ered with briers, nettles, and ragged thorns" (54).56
In addition to these five conditions, which guarantee that our experience of gardens will
be quite unlike our experience of painted landscape scenes, Repton notes some further
differences in the knowledge required of painters, on the one hand, and garden designers, on the
other. He claims that gardeners' practical knowledge in "planting, digging, and moving earth"
will rein in the painter's luxuriant imagination. He also points out that the garden designer must
have "competent knowledge of surveying, mechanics, hydraulics, agriculture, botany, and the
general principles of architecture" (iv). Having established that the experience of a garden is
unlike the experience of a painting, and that an artist who can paint a marvelous landscape scene
may not have the knowledge needed to design a landscape garden, Repton sarcastically proposes
that "If... the painter's landscape be indispensable to the perfection of gardening, it would surely
be far better to paint it on canvas at the end of an avenue, as they do in Holland, than to sacrifice
the health, cheerfulness, and comfort of a country residence to the wild but pleasing scenery of a
painter's imagination" (70 n.).
Repton's remarks about sacrificing health, cheer, and comfort to wild scenery may seem
both hysterical and beside the point, but his debate with Price eventually becomes focused on
comfort and convenience, two "emotional" consequences of landscape. Here is how their debate
becomes reoriented. Technically, Repton's claims are correct. (We have seen earlier that no
painting can provide the exact same experience as viewing, in the normal way, the scene it
represents.) But the fact that painted and natural landscapes yield different experiences does not
establish that the principles of painting have no application to landscape gardening. That claim
would be a non sequitur. So, Repton hasn't yet established his point.
For a time, the exchange between Repton and Price shifts to Repton's point 3, above, the
one concerning scenes that can't be painted. Near the end of his "Letter to Price," Repton
expands on this example, saying "I trust the good sense and good taste of this country will never
be led to despise the comfort of a gravel walk, the delicious fragrance of a shrubbery, the soul
expanding delight of a wide extended prospect, or a view down a steep hill because they are all
subjects incapable of being painted" (18--19). In his reply, Price devotes considerable space to
discussing painted prospects. He concedes there is a technical sense in which a view from a high
prospect cannot be painted. While "the general effect of looking down from a height on lower
objects" (143) has been "perpetually expressed" in painting, no painting can capture "the
immediate and uninterrupted progress of the descent" (143). But this, he argues, no more
undermines the claims of painting to represent landscape than does the painter's inability to
express the warbling of birds, the fragrance of flowers, or the motion of deer. Price closes the
discussion with an apology: "Had I not so often heard this circumstance mentioned, and with
great triumph, by the adversaries of painting, I should be ashamed of having said so much about
an impossibility, that seems to have no more to do with the application of the principles of
painting to objects of sight, or with the affinity between painting and gardening, than the
impossibility of painting real sounds, real smells, or real motion" (144).
Initially, this looks like another flawed argument. I suppose the position Price sets out to
topple is this: if there are certain scenes that can't be painted, then the principles of painting don't
apply to all varieties of natural landscape and so can't serve as principles of landscape gardening.
But Price soon changes his tune. The new claim is not that such scenes can't be painted, but that
they don't make good paintings (140)! Unlike views from prospects, gravel walks, shrubberies,
and close-mown lawns can be painted. But because they lack interesting texture and detail, they
are not suitable for the foreground of a landscape painting. (In fact, Price includes prospects in
this category as well. Noting that the view from a prospect generally comes from the highest and
most open part of a hill, he claims that such a view necessarily lacks the sort of foreground and
second distance required in a good landscape painting [130].)57
One further change is rung on this theme as the debate continues. Good paintings, for
both Repton and Price, exhibit three distances; the foreground is textured, not bare. But if we
imagine a garden which realizes or reconstructs such a painting, our preferences suddenly
change. Burdocks and rotting trees, briers, thorns, and nettles are the best occupants,
aesthetically, of the foreground of a landscape painting. By contrast, trimmed shrubs, cropped
lawns, and gravel walks are best suited to surround (constitute the "foreground" of) a house or its
outbuildings. Similarly, what makes for a good foreground in a painting does not make for a
good foreground in a garden .58
Repton makes this point repeatedly. In chapter 7 of the 1794 edition of Sketches and
Hints he derides Knight, saying "the enthusiasm for picturesque effect seems to have so
completely bewildered the author of [The Landscape] that he not only mistakes the essential
difference between the landscape painter and the landscape gardener; but appears even to forget
that a dwelling-house is an object of comfort and convenience" (59). Comparing Downton and
Foxley, the estates of Knight and Price, Repton notes that Price is more willing to sacrifice
picturesque beauty to neatness near the house, but points out that "by this very concession [Price]
acknowledges, that real comfort, and his ideas of picturesqueness, are incompatible."59
For his own part, Repton states "I am not less an admirer of those scenes which painting
represents; but I have discovered that utility must often take the lead of beauty, and convenience
be preferred to picturesque effect, in the neighborhood of men's habitation" (60). In the "Letter to
Price," Repton reiterates that "in whatever relates to man, propriety and convenience are not less
objects of good taste, than picturesque effect" (70 n.). Declaring that both he and Brown were
admirers of wild scenery, Repton claims that the lesson Brown took from his studies in
Needwood forest, and that he himself took from his experiences in the forest of Hinault, was this:
"that the landscape ought to be adapted to the beings which are to inhabit it---to men, and not to
beasts" (77). While the landscape painter may treat people as mere "staffage" to balance or fill
his composition,60 "The landscape gardener does more:---he undertakes to study their comforts
and convenience" (77).
In a sense Repton and Price are arguing at cross-purposes. There are few particular
claims on which they would disagree. Neither author would sacrifice safety or comfort to
picturesque effect. Neither would mass rotting wood, beetling rocks, and clusters of thorns at the
foundations of a house or the forefront of a garden. And both would admire landscape paintings
in various styles---by Claude, Poussin, and Wilson as well as Rosa, Gainsborough, and Dughet.
Do the principles of painting in fact apply to landscape gardening? Repton concludes his
letter with an extended and awkward trope. He claims that painting and gardening are not "sister
arts, proceeding from the same stock, but rather congenial natures, brought together like man and
wife; while, therefore, you exult in the office of mediator betwixt these two 'imaginary
personages,' you should recollect the danger of interfering in their occasional differences, and
especially how you advise them both to wear the same articles of dress" (74 n.). Whether we
construe painting and gardening as sisters, or as husband and wife with a tendency to cross-dress,
the claim that they share a set of principles turns out to be rather empty. Price tries to defend this
claim by showing that Repton is caught in a pragmatic contradiction. That is, Price suggests that
Repton's practice belies his principles. Since he sketches the proposed changes for each garden
commission in a Red Book, he is using painting (and thereby its principles) to design each
garden. But this too seems in error. We must distinguish here painting as a system of
representation, and painting as a set of aesthetic principles. Repton's practice employs painting in
the first sense, to portray gardens. Nothing follows about the use of the principles of painting to
compose or design gardens.
In fact, there is a deeper question here---are there principles of painting in the second
sense? Presumably, such principles would guide artists in the creation of excellent paintings.
Would they guarantee such results? Rules regarding composition and technique can be followed
in creating, say, a landscape painting. Here as in the other arts, no set of rules can guarantee
success. In fact it was a common eighteenth-century belief, supported by both Pope and Hume,
that genius shouldn't be constrained by rules.61 Setting aside the question of quality, what role
might remain for rules or principles of landscape painting?
Repton defines landscape as "a view capable of being represented in painting," and goes
on to add that it has two, three, or more well-marked distances.62 But this is too general to
differentiate among landscapes. Compositional principles, if they can be formulated at all, would
operate at one of two levels, that of of particular genres, or that of what Wollheim called general
and individual style. Thus John Barrell, in his book The Idea of Landscape and the Sense of
Place, isolates what he considers the structural principles which characterize landscapes by
Claude. Claude's landscapes, he argues, share a fairly high viewpoint, tremendous depth, an area
of light set just below the horizon which immediately attracts the eye, framing trees or buildings
in the foreground, a series of planes alternating light and dark, the penultimate one in sunlight,
and a road or bridge running diagonally and linking the planes.63 Would following such
compositional principles yield a Claudean painting? Surely one would also have to make
stipulations about subject matter, color and tone, brushwork, and so on.
Similar comments apply if we pick other landscape styles or genres. Consider, for
example, what Anne Bermingham in her book Landscape and Ideology calls the rustic landscape
tradition, associated with the work of Gainsborough and Constable. Bermingham defines this
genre by saying that "Rustic landscapes differ from topographical studies in that their main
intention is not to portray a famous spot, view, or monument but instead to evoke the countryside
and rural life. The rustic landscape is not easily or satisfactorily assimilated into
classical-romantic polarities.”64 The principles delimiting this genre would primarily address
subject matter and its treatment rather than formal or technical matters.65 Note that in each case
(1) identifying a style or genre of painting, and (2) instructing painters in the creation of works of
that type are correlative tasks guided by the same set of principles.
I have been suggesting that there are not principles of painting per se, but rather prin-
ciples that delimit one or another genre or style of painting. Few of these would seem to be
principles that would translate readily to garden design. As discussed in chapter 4, it is possible
to create gardens that imitate, model, or allude to particular paintings or to particular genres or
styles of painting. But each such garden would be singular, and the method of establishing this
referential connection to a particular painting or group of paintings would most likely not be
repeated. That is, it would not be a necessary or regular aspect of garden design.
If this is correct, then it follows that any principles shared by the arts of gardening and
painting would be extremely general. They would be at the level of "Pay attention to color,
balance, and texture; use perspective to create an illusion of depth; achieve unity of com-
position." Note that we are now at the level of principle cited by Price in his Essay. I suggest that
such principles are without guiding force. That is, knowing that general composition, harmony of
tints, breadth of light and shade, and connection are factors that we attend to in viewing paintings
and that painters attend to in painting them, tells us nothing about what sort of composition and
which varieties of tonal harmony, light and shade, and connection are desirable. Inevitably all
paintings have some composition or other, some tonal relationships---harmonious or not, some
degree of connection. But to grant this is to say nothing about whether the paintings in question
are landscapes or portraits, linear or painterly, representational or abstract, excellent or appalling.
Since features like those listed by Price have no normative force, I propose reconstruing them as
elements of painting, reserving the term "principles" for rules or features that guide our actions in
important ways.
I believe that an equivalent result holds for the art of gardening. That is, there are no
principles of gardening, per se. There are principles or rules of thumb that guide the design of
specific types of gardens---water gardens, terrace gardens, knot gardens, Zen gardens, shade
gardens, desert gardens. And, at a more general level, there are elements of gardening that
correspond to the elements of painting noted above. These claims can be supported by browsing
through any contemporary books on garden design. For example, Alice Recknagel Ireys, in a
volume entitled Garden Design, lists the following six principles of garden art: scale, proportion,
unity, balance, rhythm, and focal point.66 (I would once again denominate these elements rather
than principles, since every garden possesses them to some degree---except perhaps for unity---
and since merely having some scale or other, some proportion or other, and so on, doesn't
guarantee quality.) A more ambitious text, also entitled Garden Design, by five authors aided by
the Publication Board of the American Society of Landscape Architects, lists the following as
elements of the garden: paving, turf and ground covers, steps, walls, and fences, gates and
windows, structures, seats and benches, water, ornaments, light, and the plant palette.67 These
are not shared with painting in the way that Price's elements are; they are more garden
ingredients than garden techniques. An earlier chapter of the same text breaks the garden down
into experiential units---landmarks, landings, entries, corridors, vertical changes, water---and
opportunities---places for exploration, gathering, dining, play, contemplation, and work.
In sum, these and other primers instructing readers in garden design do not make any
explicit comparisons with painting. They do not mention particular principles or techniques of
that art, nor do they invariably mention elements shared by painting and gardening. One final
way to test Price's claim about the transfer of technique is to look at the actual practice of
particular garden designers. Russell Page, for example, in his book The Education of a Gardener,
first published in 1962, says "I know now that one cannot be taught to design gardens
academically or theoretically. You have to learn the ways and nature of plants and stone, of
water and soil at least as much through the hands as through the head.”68 (Compare this claim
with the discussion of academies of gardening in chapter 2.) Yet at the same time, he says
"Whether I am making a landscape or a garden or arranging a window box I first address the
problem as an artist composing a picture; my pre-occupation is with the relationships between
objects" (Preface). Later he notes "At the drawing-board, I work out my composition in terms of
levels" (70). Yet do these procedural remarks indicate any deep relationship between the arts we
are examining? Page lists the following as "timeless elements" of gardens: light and shade, earth,
stone, and water, foliage and flowers (49). Thus the elements of gardens differ from the elements
of paintings, and the transfer of technique that we have been exploring in this second chapter on
gardening and painting turns out to be at a level so general as to have no effect on the actual
process of garden design.69 All one can conclude is that certain basic elements attended to by
painters---color, texture, form, balance, composition, perspective, light and shade---also play a
role in the creation of gardens.
7. CONCLUSION
Let us return now to the eighteenth-century concept of the picturesque, with which we opened
this chapter. While this concept figured in and enhanced the appreciation of certain types of
landscape, and also fueled the criticism of a particular style of landscape garden-that associated
with Capability Brown-the picturesque did not figure centrally in garden design .70 I believe that
no particularly revealing connection between gardens and painting emerges from a study of the
picturesque. Yet there has been considerable interest in this aesthetic category. Why did it
flourish in the period we have been examining, and why did it decline?
In assessing the apparent popularity of the picturesque, we must realize that the concept
has been greatly stretched. So far we have been examining the picturesque primarily as it applied
to landscape aesthetics, and derivatively to garden design. Yet even in this regard, the label
"picturesque" has been extended to such chronological extremes as to become almost
meaningless; this is in addition to the strain imposed by internal tensions and inconsistencies like
those in the theories of Price and Knight.
The chronological difficulties I have in mind are exemplified by a book by Morris
Brownell taking Pope as a paradigm example of a picturesque gardener.71 For instance,
Brownell writes that Pope's treatment of landscape reveals "a sensibility to picturesque landscape
in natural scenery explicit enough to allow us to infer his adherence to something like an
aesthetic of picturesque scenery."72 Of the interpretations of the picturesque we have canvassed
so far, Brownell's approximates the last and weakest, the one I have labeled "transfer of
technique." Given that Pope was gardening some seventy-five years before the publication of
Price's Essay, and thirty-eight years before the publication of Burke's Inquiry, to which Price's
work was indebted, it seems very unlikely that Pope was gardening in a style that fitted the late
eighteenth-century use of the term "picturesque.”73 Again, Edward Hyams, in his book The
English Garden, labels all English gardens in the first half of the eighteenth century
"picture-gardens."74 The eighteenth-century travel literature discussed in chapter 2 above further
blurred the boundaries of the picturesque, since rugged mountain scenes like those along the
Welsh border---scenes reminiscent of the paintings of Salvator Rosa, and worthy, therefore, of
the label "sublime"---were called picturesque, as were those in the lake country.
Hunt gives a simple account of the rise of the picturesque. He attributes it to loss of
learning. Hunt claims that as patronage for the arts expanded in the eighteenth century, viewers
were increasingly less equipped to puzzle out the meanings of complex emblematic works.
Expressive and, ultimately, picturesque works were much more accessible to audiences no longer
schooled in the classics.75
Hunt's interpretation recalls passages quoted earlier in this chapter from Christopher
Hussey and David Watkin. These authors identified the picturesque with the discovery and
celebration of visual values. Yet celebration of the visual can cause other concerns and values to
be downplayed or expunged. For some commentators, the picturesque as characterized by Price
and Knight is morally problematic, since it singles out humble, rustic scenes (although the
picturesque requires variety, a variety of jewels, baubles, and silks would not do) without any
concern for their origins or limitations. Malcolm Andrews, in The Search for the Picturesque,
suggests that "the Picturesque enterprise in its later stages, with its almost exclusive emphasis on
visual appreciation, entailed a suppression of the spectator's moral response to those very
subjects which it could least hope to divest of moral significance-the ruin, the hovel, and rural
poverty" (59).76
Andrews takes his analysis one step farther, proposing a link between the characteris-
tically humble picturesque subjects and the viewpoint from which they were painted:
"The social descent---palace to ruin to hovel---has an interesting analogy with the painter's
changing viewpoint in the eighteenth century" (61). The picturesque viewpoint was a low one,77
in direct contrast with the high prospects and panoramic vistas of earlier topographical paintings.
For Andrews, this change is psychologically revealing. He concludes that the picturesque
fixation testified to a crisis of sorts throughout England: "The repudiation of the high viewpoint
in late-eighteenth century Picturesque theory suggests a failure of confidence" (63). That is, in
repudiating the synoptic point of view characteristic of earlier prospect poems and topographical
paintings, practitioners of the picturesque were also repudiating the certainties of the Augustan
Age, expressing their douhts about man's ability to conquer and harness nature.
Other theorists offer similarly deep readings of the eighteenth-century psyche. For
example, Anne Bermingham, drawing on the work of John Barrell, argues that the cult of the
picturesque arose just when enclosure of the English countryside was accelerating. The natural
world was romanticized precisely when it was in fact disappearing. Bermingham suggests that
"In its celebration of the irregular, preenclosed landscape, the picturesque harkened back
nostalgically to an old order of rural paternalism" (70). Later, she claims that the picturesque
"mystified the agency of social change so that fate, and not the economic decisions of the
landowning classes, seemed responsible. In this respect, the picturesque represented an attempt
to wipe out the fact of enclosure and to minimize its consequences" (75). To some extent she
concurs with Andrews, stating "A profound pessimism lay at the root of picturesque theory"
(70).
With these last accounts of the picturesque we have come quite far from Price’s and
Knight's criticisms of the bald, monotonous gardens of Capability Brown; far, too, from the Rev.
Mr. Gilpin's enthusiasm for the actual sights and scenes of his native land. These
later theories, linking the picturesque with enclosure and sweeping economic change. with
insecurity and malaise, assume a close connection between landscape and well-being. In fact, the
way we relate to landscape can both determine and reveal our mental and emotional states, as
well, of course, as our social class, politics, and ideology. These connections raise questions that
will be explored in subsequent chapters. How do we experience landscape, and in particular,
gardens, given that they do not function precisely like their sister arts, painting and poetry? And,
what is the fate of gardens today, given that many of the social and economic changes cataloged
by Hunt, Andrews, and Bermingham have continued apace?