(2017) (Enfield) Distributed Agency
(2017) (Enfield) Distributed Agency
Distributed Agency
ii
Series Editorial Board:
Michael Tomasello (Max Planck Institute Leipzig)
Dan Sperber (Jean Nicod Institute)
Elizabeth Couper-╉Kuhlen (University of Helsinki)
Paul Kockelman (Yale University)
Sotaro Kita (University of Warwick)
Tanya Stivers (University of California, Los Angeles)
Jack Sidnell (University of Toronto)
Distributed Agency
Edited by N. J. Enfield
and
Paul Kockelman
1
iv
1
Oxford University Press is a department of the University of Oxford. It furthers
the University’s objective of excellence in research, scholarship, and education
by publishing worldwide. Oxford is a registered trade mark of Oxford University
Press in the UK and certain other countries.
9 8 7 6 5 4 3 2 1
Paperback printed by WebCom, Inc., Canada
Hardback printed by Bridgeport National Bindery, Inc., United States of America
╇ v
CONTENTS
[ vi ] Contents
vii
Contents [ vii ]
ix
S E R I E S E D I T O R P R E FA C E
E D I T O R S ’ P R E FA C E
We never really act alone. Our agency is enhanced when we cooperate with
others, and when we accept their help. We benefit when we take credit
for people’s achievements, or when we free-╉ride on their ideas and their
strengths. And not only is our agency shared through action in these ways,
but we often have agency without having to engage in action at all. Even
when at rest, we are bound up in networks of cause and effect, intention
and accountability. The distribution of agency, for better or worse, is every-
where, and our species has perfected its arts.
This book presents an interdisciplinary inroad into the latest thinking
about the distributed nature of agency: what it’s like, what are its condi-
tions of possibility, and what are its consequences. The book’s 26 chapters
are written by a wide range of scholars, from anthropology, biology, cogni-
tive science, linguistics, philosophy, psychology, geography, law, econom-
ics, and sociology. While each chapter takes up different materials using
different methods, they all chart relations between the key elements of
agency: intentionality, causality, flexibility, and accountability. Each chap-
ter seeks to explain how and why such relations are distributed—╉not just
across individuals, but also across bodies and minds, people and things,
spaces and times. To do this, the authors work through empirical studies
of particular cases, while also offering reviews and syntheses of key ideas
from the authors’ respective research traditions.
All creatures have some form of agency, but agency in humans is argu-
ably unique. Humans have a special capacity to share agency through joint
commitment and cooperation toward common goals, as well as through
coercive and parasitic practices by which we co-╉opt the capacities, and take
credit for the consequences, of others. We are the most flexible and creative
xii
• Why and how do we excerpt agents at certain scales, and how do differ-
ent understandings of agency alter such scales?
• When we cooperate with others, when is our agency weakened, and
when is it enhanced?
• In what ways is material culture an extension of the person?
• While artifacts and technologies increase our flexibility in obvious ways,
how do they affect our accountability?
• What are the causal forces that determine the scope and constraints of
our agency? How are these forces related to norms?
CONTENTS
The ten parts of the book each group together essays that overlap in regard
to their empirical topics and analytic commitments. Part One, “Agency as
Flexible and Accountable Causality,” introduces key themes through four
interrelated chapters. In the first two chapters, Enfield theorizes some ele-
ments of agency, broadly understood as flexible and accountable causality;
and then describes how agency, thus framed, is distributed across actors
and activities. In the second two chapters, Kockelman reviews and synthe-
sizes some classic texts that lead to such an understanding of agency; and
then describes a variety of other possible ways of framing it.
The next nine parts take up interrelated questions from a variety of
stances, partly deriving from the cross-╉ disciplinary commitments of
authors, and partly from the empirical contents they analyze and the theo-
retical questions they answer.
In Part Two, “The Agency of Institutions and Infrastructure,” Bernstein
takes up agency in actual state agencies—╉in particular, legal and political
institutions that promulgate laws and regulations shaping the actions of
citizens—╉and Elyachar takes up agency in the context of political revolu-
tions, when critical energies are used to create, use, and destroy key forms
of infrastructure.
Part Three presents perspectives on “Language and Agency.” While
much previous work on language and agency has focused on the repre-
sentational and meta-╉representational capacities of humans, these four
chapters take us into the trenches of interaction: talk-╉in-╉interaction as it
unfolds in real-╉time practices, in face-╉to-╉face encounters. Dingemanse uses
the science fiction fantasy of brain-╉to-╉brain interfaces to shed light on the
natural distribution of agency in human communication; Floyd focuses
on requests as a key means for instigating and negotiating the sharing of
agency; also on this theme, Rossi and Zinken focus in more closely on the
fine-grained grammatical categories that languages provide as tools for
mobilizing other people; and Sidnell focuses on a particularly important
but overlooked element of the shared construction of action in interaction,
namely the accountability that comes with our impositions on others.
In Part Four, “Economy and Agency,” Guyer examines the ethics of debt
as a way of distributing agency both across people and through time, and
Maurer looks at the infrastructures of monetary accounting, where the act
of “recording” an exchange can in fact be seen as effecting the very exchange
itself. In Part Five, “Distributing Agency within Selves and Species,” Parry
explores the distribution of agency in moving the human body in profes-
sional therapy sessions, and d’Ettorre—on a very different scale—shows
how agency is distributed across masses of individual bodies in the case of
eusocial organisms such as ants.
In Part Six, “Social Bonding Through Embodied Agency,” the theme of
agency in human groups is further developed, with an overview by Cohen
of some elements of social bonding through group exercise in humans, and
a focus by Tarr on the same in dance and music. And in Part Seven, “Agency
and Infancy,” Rączaszek-Leonardi highlights the importance of differ-
ent timescales in an exploration of the understanding of agency between
infants and caregivers, and Tunçgenç stresses the importance of close tem-
poral coordination in the bodily movements of infants and caregivers as a
crucial step on the path from individual to collective agency in the lifespan.
Part Eight, “The Agency of Materiality,” presents three studies of how
agency gets into, and out of, inanimate objects: Crossland discusses the
agency of human remains, as understood through forensic anthropology;
Smith considers the agentive role of marbles in the lives of children; and
Wilf explores how computerized algorithms can be a source of contingen-
cies that are harvested to cultivate artistic creativity. In Part Nine, “The
Place of Agency,” Adams takes up agency through the eyes of a geographer
focused on spatially distributed selves, and Lahlou looks at it through the
lens of installations—or spatially arranged ensembles of affordances that
shape the activities of those who act and think inside them. And in Part
Ten, “From Cooperation to Deception and Disruption,” Schweikard outlines
the central importance of intentionality and normativity in the coopera-
tive framework of joint action, while Umbres turns our attention to decep-
tion—a decidedly antisocial form of distributed agency—and Zuckerman
delves further into the dark side of agency, with a study of attempts to
sabotage others’ courses of action, and the post hoc framings and attribu-
tions of agency that then emerge.
ENVOI
NOTE
1. The forum for most of these discussions was a retreat held at Ringberg Castle,
Tegernsee/╉Kreuth, Germany, April 13–╉17, 2014, attended by most of the book’s
contributors, and several others. The retreat was funded by a European Research
Council grant “Human Sociality and Systems of Language Use” (Grant number
240853, to Enfield). The discussion continued by correspondence and led to the
further invitation and inclusion of several authors whose work was important
to the project. We are grateful to all participants and contributors for their
invaluable input. We thank Angela Terrill at Punctilious Editing (http://www.
punctilious.net/) for first-class indexing. Please note the following conventions
for transcripts in a number of chapters: underline = stress; [ = beginning of
overlap; ] = end of overlap; (4.4) = 4.4 seconds of silence; text in ((double
brackets)) refers to visible bodily behavior; text in (single brackets) = not clearly
audible.
CONTRIBUTORS
[ xviii ] Contributors
1
PART ONE
Agency as Flexible
and Accountable Causality
3
CHAPTER 1
Elements of Agency
N. J. ENFIELD
The expectant crowd fell hush in front of me. The hecklers across the street
ceased their ranting and watched silently. An eerie stillness settled upon our
canyon as the last rays of the fall sun clung to the tops of the buildings. I said the
first thing that came to my mind. “I am not going to give my prepared speech.
I am going to let this action speak for itself. I know that you people across the
street really know what is happening in Vietnam. I am opposed to the draft and
the war in Vietnam.”
I pulled my draft classification card from my suit coat pocket along with a
book of matches brought especially for the occasion since I did not smoke. I lit a
match, then another. They blew out in the late afternoon breeze. As I struggled
with the matches, a young man with a May 2nd Movement button on his jacket
held up a cigarette lighter. It worked just fine.
The draft card burned as I raised it aloft between the thumb and index finger
of my left hand. A roar of approval from the rally crowd greeted the enflamed
card. This awakened the momentarily mesmerized hecklers and they resumed
their shouts.
As the card burned, I discovered that I had made no preparation for the card
to be completely consumed. I dropped the card as the flame reached my finger-
tips. At my trial in federal court, the unburnt corner of my draft card, with a
4
bit of my signature, was introduced into evidence. The FBI had been Johnny-
on-the-spot in retrieving the charred remains of my card so as to assist in their
prosecution even though I never denied that I burned my card. Future card
burners used tongs or cans in order to complete the job.
… Three days later the FBI swooped in on me in Manchester, New
Hampshire… . I made bail the next day. I remained free till June 1968 when
the draft-card burning case finally lost in the U.S. Supreme Court. I served
22 months in federal prison in Pennsylvania from 1968 to 1970.
E l e m e n t s of Ag e n c y [ 5 ]
6
(my question) will be to tell me the person’s address, which I will then be
already prepared to write down. Another way to measure subprehension in
this sense is to monitor the accountability involved. Is a person surprised
by or disposed to sanction certain interpretants? If I ask What’s his address?
and you look at me and say nothing, I might repeat the question or say Hey
I asked you something. An agent subprehends interpretants of a sign event
to some degree (especially the potential accountability): being prepared
for some interpretants and not others; being surprised by, or disposed to
sanction, some interpretants and not others. As noted above, Miller was
surely not surprised by the heckling, the arrest, the conviction; nor was
he presumably surprised by the praise, support, and imitation from other
activists. This indicates that his degree of agency on the measure of subpre-
hension was high.
With an agent’s flexibility comes accountability, as Miller anticipated or
at least subprehended:
E l e m e n t s of Ag e n c y [ 7 ]
8
ACKNOWLEDGMENTS
Thanks go to Paul Kockelman for his significant input to this work. Note that
this chapter draws partly on sections of my 2013 book Relationship Thinking
(Oxford University Press). I gratefully acknowledge support from the Max
Planck Society (through MPI Nijmegen), the European Research Council
(through grant 240853, “Human Sociality and Systems of Language Use”),
and the University of Sydney (through Bridging Grant ID 176605).
NOTES
REFERENCES
Ahearn, Laura M. 2010. “Agency and Language.” Society and Language Use 7: 28.
Bourdieu, Pierre. 1977. Outline of a Theory of Practice. Cambridge: Cambridge
University Press.
Duranti, Alessandro. 2004. “Agency in Language.” In A Companion to Linguistic
Anthropology, edited by D. Alessandro, 451–473. Malden, MA: Blackwell.
Enfield, N. J. 2013. Relationship Thinking: Agency, Enchrony, and Human Sociality.
Oxford: Oxford University Press.
Kockelman, Paul. 2007. “Agency: The Relation Between Meaning, Power, and
Knowledge.” Current Anthropology 48(3): 375–╉401.
Kockelman, Paul. 2013. Agent, Person, Subject, Self: A Theory of Ontology, Interaction,
and Infrastructure. Oxford: Oxford University Press.
Miller, David. 2001. “Reclaiming Our History: Memoirs of a Draft-╉Card Burner.”
Reclaiming Quarterly (82). http://╉www.reclaimingquarterly.org/╉82/╉rq-╉82-╉
draftcard.html Retrieved March 12, 2011.
CHAPTER 2
Distribution of Agency
N. J. ENFIELD
I t is easy to think that “an agent” should coincide exactly with an individ-
ual. But this is seldom, if ever, the case. One reason agents do not equal
individuals is that the elements of agency can be divided up and shared out
among multiple people in relation to a single course of action. When I get
you to pass the salt, it is me who plans the behavior but you who executes
it. Or when I report what a candidate said in yesterday’s speech, it is me
who speaks the words but the candidate who is accountable for what was
expressed. With distributed agency, multiple people act as one, sharing or
sharing out the elements of agency.
One person may provide the flexibility needed for meeting another per-
son’s ends—as in slavery, factories, and armies—or for meeting shared
ends—as in team sports, co-authorship, and joint enterprise. Similarly,
one person may bear the accountability entailed by another person’s flex-
ibility. It is hardly rare for a person to inherit the blame for someone else’s
punishable actions. Howitt (1904), writing on Aboriginal Australia, “men-
tions the case of an accused man pointing to his elder brother to take the
blame, because an elder brother stands for and should, ideally, protect a
younger” (Berndt and Berndt 1964:299). In law of this kind, “people are
categorized in units the members of which are interdependent … [and]
relations both within and between those units may not be framed only, or
predominantly, in kinship terms” (Berndt and Berndt 1964:303). This non-
modern approach has difficulty fitting into today’s world. In 2009, there
was a campaign in the Australian Aboriginal community at Lajamanu in
10
A family living in a village outside Bajram Curri … came under a new threat,
even though the man from their family who had committed a blood feud killing
had himself died seventeen years ago. The perpetrator’s death did not satisfy
the indebted family who sent a warning that they expected “blood payment” in
the form of the life of a male member of the remaining family. The family under
threat consisted of a widow living with her two sons, their wives, and several
children. The family had already adjusted to the threatening situation: the eldest
son had gone into hiding elsewhere, and the younger remained indoors, unable
to leave the house. Obviously this situation had a drastic effect on the earning
capacity of the family.
Cases like this take us to the heart of distributed agency. One man commits
a misdeed against another, and yet revenge is taken years later between
the two men’s grandchildren, neither of whom was involved in the original
transgression. Here, someone is held to account for something that some-
one else chose to do. Here, agency, with its components of flexibility and
accountability, is divided and shared out among multiple individuals while
still being anchored in a single, sometimes decades-long course of action.
Cases like this highlight one of the key reasons why agents do not equal
individuals: the locus of agency is the social unit, and social units are not
confined to individual bodies.
Di s t r i b u t i o n of Ag e n c y [ 11 ]
12
by the anthropologist Ralph Linton: sets of rights and duties that hold with
respect to certain others. Much of social life is about managing changes of
status. The navigation of status often involves moving in and out of mem-
bership in composite units of agency. Changes of status, at all levels of
grain, are closely associated with fission-fusion agency.
For joint action, there needs to be joint commitment (Clark 2006). In
the philosopher John Searle’s terms, joint commitment might be defined
as a status function declaration of one’s acceptance of some form of shared
accountability (Searle 2010). Psychologist Herb Clark uses this notion to
reanalyze the notorious experiments conducted by Stanley Milgram in New
Haven in the 1960s (Milgram 1974). Volunteers in an experimental setting
were instructed to administer electric shocks to another volunteer when-
ever he made an error in a memory task. They were surprisingly willing to
inflict harm in this experiment, a fact that has been analyzed as having
to do with obedience to authority. Clark reinterprets the finding, suggest-
ing that joint commitment is what really accounts for why volunteers in
these experiments ended up behaving in ways they would otherwise have
abhorred. These volunteers were not merely doing what they were told. By
agreeing to participate in the experiment in the first place, they had made
a pact with the experimenter, and people are—evidently—deeply reluc-
tant to withdraw from social pacts. Clark uses Milgram’s extreme example
of joint commitment for illustration, but his point is that these pacts are
being made by all of us, all the time. They are a constant and essential part
of social life and they are implicit in our every move. But when you jointly
commit, what are you committing to? The answer is that you are agreeing
to merge, on some level, with another individual in carrying out a single
course of action. Clark’s point is that you then become socially and mor-
ally accountable for reneging on that agreement. This is cognitively under-
pinned by what students of human sociality, from philosophy (e.g., John
Searle, Raimo Tuomela) to biology (e.g., Michael Tomasello, Josep Call),
refer to as shared intentionality (Tomasello et al. 2005).
Distributed cognition (Hutchins 2006) is a type of distributed agency
in the sense meant here. Often, distributed cognition encompasses physi-
cal action and not just cognitive processes like reasoning. But since cog-
nition is more generally a kind of goal-directed flexible behavior, then
distributed cognition can also be analyzed in terms of the three elements
of flexibility in agency: animating, authoring, and subprehending (and
their interpreter corollaries: perceiving, ascribing, and interpreting). We
should be able to improve our accounts of distributed cognition by explor-
ing implications of the ideas that sometimes the distribution of cognition
is in the realm of what we do with our bodies (controlling and executing);
Di s t r i b u t i o n of Ag e n c y [ 13 ]
14
ACKNOWLEDGMENTS
Thanks go to Paul Kockelman for his significant input to this work. Note that
this chapter draws partly on sections of my 2013 book Relationship Thinking
(Oxford University Press). I gratefully acknowledge support from the Max
Planck Society (through MPI Nijmegen), the European Research Council
(through grant 240853 “Human Sociality and Systems of Language Use”),
and the University of Sydney (through Bridging Grant ID 176605).
REFERENCES
CHAPTER 3
Gnomic Agency
PAUL KOCKELMAN
T here are many different ways of framing agency, and thereby fore-
grounding different kinds of agents. My point in what follows is not to
endorse any particular frame, but merely to sketch some of the key features
of several pervasive frames. Such frames—as ways of understanding and
interrelating flexibility, causality, and accountability—have grounded the
intuitions of many influential thinkers. And so it is useful to understand, if
only to undermine, their characteristic assumptions.
ARISTOTELIAN AGENCIES
Aristotle (2001) famously described four kinds of causes that may underlie
any entity. There is the material cause (the substance something is com-
posed of, however heterogeneous), the formal cause (the way this substance
has been shaped, organized, or patterned), the final cause (the functions
such a formed substance may serve), and the efficient cause (that which
gives form to substance, often for the sake of some function). Aristotle’s
word for cause was aition, which is closely linked to notions of responsi-
bility. In some sense, such causes are responsible for the existence of an
entity. This is not to say that they should be held accountable in any legal
or moral sense, but only to say that we may make reference to such causes
when we try to account for such entities.
Such causes, broadly construed, provide one useful way of framing
agency. In particular, we might define (Aristotelian) agents as causes that
16
we can take account of. Acting alone, or in concert, they are a salient condi-
tion of possibility for the existence of entities, or the occurrence of events.
Natural selection is thus an agent. A worker is an agent. A tool is an agent.
An enzyme is an agent. Oxidation is an agent. Even lightning bolts, and
chance phenomena more generally, are agents. Note, then, that while it
is easy to make a splash by calling some non-intentional actor an “agent”
(a land mine, dust, concrete, continental drift, worms, the trade winds,
a comet, etc.), this is only because so many people have a limited sense
of what an agent is. In this Aristotelian framing, in contrast, anything of
causal account is an agent and, indeed, interestingly so. Such a framing is
thus not limited to the kinds of causes enumerated by Aristotle, but may
include whatever causes are (deemed) worthy of account: ghosts and grav-
ity, sieving and serendipity, witches and wishes, global warming and politi-
cal apathy, semiotic practices and thermodynamic processes, and much
else besides.
Needless to say, most entities and events have many causes (each of
which can itself be an entity or event with many causes, and so on, ad infi-
nitum). And so agency is necessarily distributed in depth (each cause of
some effect is itself the effect of some cause), and necessarily distributed
in breadth (each effect has many causes; each cause has many effects). This
is not to say that all such causes are salient enough to show up in some
account: causal accounting, as the figuring (out) of agency, tends to focus on
those causes that are particularly relevant to the agents who are doing the
accounting: for example, those causes that are least expected; those causes
most easy or difficult to intervene in; those causes that are most powerful,
marketable, or useful; those causes most amenable to our intuitions; those
causes that seem most intentional; those causes with the most dire effects;
and so forth. To study agency is to study causal understandings, and imag-
inings, of the world: not just the conditions for, and consequences of, enti-
ties and events; but also the conditions for, and consequences of, particular
accountings (of such conditions and consequences). There is no interesting
account of agency that is not simultaneously an account of those agents who are
trying to account for agency.
BACONIAN AGENCIES
We may extend this framing, and get a better sense of its stakes, by apply-
ing some categories of Bacon (2000) to those of Aristotle. If knowledge
turns on the discovery of causes, power turns on the directing of causes.
Knowledge and power are thus necessarily coupled: in directing known
causes, we may discover new causes; and we may use such discoveries in
our subsequent directings. From this standpoint, a Baconian agent exhib-
its a kind of meta-agency: whatever has knowledge about, or power over,
the sorts of causes described above. Such an agent can offer an account of
such causes, so far as it can discover them; and it may make such causes
count, so far as it can direct them. Indeed, for such agents, we can often
invoke accountability in the strong sense. That is, not only can we account
for such agents (e.g., thematize them, characterize them, reason about
them), but we can also hold such agents accountable for their actions and
effects (e.g., hinder them or hasten them, reward them or punish them,
praise them or shame them). Finally, and reflexively, it is often the case
that such Baconian agents have yet to discover all the causes that direct
them. Such “blind spots” constitute one key sense of the unconscious: we
often have limited knowledge over precisely those causes that have power
over us.
This way of framing agency foregrounds not only the recursive and
reflexive nature of agency, but also the relative nature of agency. In partic-
ular, different agents have different degrees of knowledge and power, and
so different degrees of agency. But, that said, because there are so many
different kinds of causes, most kinds of power and knowledge are incom-
mensurate, so that it makes little sense to contrast them by degree. For
example, while we might compare the strength of two men, it is difficult
to compare the strength of one man with the speed of another. Similarly,
while we might compare how much you know about chemistry with how
much I know, it is difficult to compare your factual knowledge (know that)
with my practical knowledge (know how). And so on, and so forth. That is,
it only really makes sense to talk about different degrees of agency when
we can isolate out a shared dimension of agency (for example, how much
money, or credit, one has at one’s disposal). And for many, if not most,
kinds of agents, with their potentially heterogeneous suites of context-
specific and event-contingent causal capacities, that is impossible. Modes
of agency are as heterogeneous and incommensurate as the causes they
direct and discover, as the entities such causes enable, and as the events
such causes occasion.
INSTRUMENTAL AGENCIES
G n o m i c Ag e n c y [ 17 ]
18
EVALUATIVE AGENCIES
Just as any effect may itself be a cause that gives rise to another effect, any
end may itself be a means to a further end. And so we again find a rela-
tively recursive pattern: a means-ends chain that stretches on indefinitely
in two directions at once. Or does it? We just saw how many affordances,
like the branch one uses to climb a tree, are means (insofar as one may
use them to undertake an action), but not themselves ends (insofar as the
branches were not made for the sake of climbing). Nature is often romanti-
cally understood to be constituted by this bottoming out of instrumental-
ity. Conversely, Aristotle argued that such means-ends chains had to stop
somewhere, and thus “top in.” In particular, there must be some end that
is not itself the means for further ends. He called such a final end eudai-
monia, which is often translated as human flourishing, or happiness. And
he thought that this highest good, or supreme value, was of utmost impor-
tance to philosophy and politics.
Whether or not such higher goods are crucial to philosophy and politics,
they are certainly crucial to many understandings of agency, which are just
as prone to promote value-oriented agents as they are to demote derivative
agents. In particular, a related tradition understands each of us instrumen-
tal agents as having too many ends, in that we have more desires than we
might ever hope to attain (given our finite time on this earth, and the finite
means at our disposal). And so a key question arises: how do we decide
which desire we want to act upon, or which end we hope to achieve? To
which final end, or at least more distal end, should our intermediate ends
be oriented? Such a question presumes that we are not just instrumental
agents, who have some flexibility in regard to our means and ends, but that
we are also selecting and/or economizing agents. That is, not only is there
more than one way to skin a cat, but there are more ways to spend our time
than skinning cats; and so we need to choose not just how to do things, but
what things to do. And so the question of evaluating agents arises: agents
who not only act instrumentally, but also evaluate instrumental acts in
reference to values and, in particular, in reference to values that could be
otherwise.
Such values are often understood to constitute some kind of relatively
shared standard that allows us to order means and ends according to their
relative desirability (Taylor 1989). Such standards help us determine which
course of action is more just, honorable, or efficient—and hence which
course of action we should pursue if we are to be a just, honorable, or effi-
cient actor. Such a process is also recursive: one kind of agent may be rela-
tively flexible in regard to the means and ends it has at its disposal; another
G n o m i c Ag e n c y [ 19 ]
20
The foregoing tradition tends to focus on a certain class of final causes: those
that turn on the relatively self-conscious strivings of intentional agents,
and hence teleological processes of a stereotypic sort. Just as interesting
are what philosophers like Mayr (1992) calls teleonomic agents: instincts,
traits, organs, and automata. For present purposes, teleonomic agents are
adaptive agents: they not only exhibit means-ends behaviors (or character-
istics), but they were also selected, and thus shaped, for the sake of those
behaviors. Such agents that are selected (but cannot themselves select, or
“choose,” in the strong sense just described) are also considered derivative
agents—insofar as their key characteristics are understood as having been
imposed by another agent (and not just by seemingly intentional agents
such as artists and engineers, but also by seemingly unintentional agents
like natural selection). Mayr thought that such teleonomic processes were
guided by an internal program (such as DNA, an algorithm, or some kind
of intricate engineering mechanism). And he characterized such programs
as being more or less “open” insofar as they were more or less sensitive to
contextual inputs. In this tradition, universal Turing machines are radi-
cally open (in that they can run any program you give them); and mem-
bers of the species homo sapiens are radically open (in that they have the
capacity to inhabit any culture they inherit, with each such culture having
distinctive suites of means and ends, distinctive modes of knowledge and
power, and distinctive causal capacities and evaluative rationalities). The
relative “openness” of such agents is, of course, yet another way of imag-
ining their relative agentiveness. And again, such an agentiveness is not
necessarily agentive in any stereotypic sense insofar as it might have been
“programmed” by an external agent—your parents or teachers, your cul-
ture or society, a particular religion or ideology, and so forth. (Recall the
admonishments of Marx.)
This sense of agency usefully points to another sense of accountability.
All of the products of natural selection can be held accountable in the first
sense: we can account, if only partially, for their coming to be. The world
itself, in the sense of an “environment,” can hold organisms accountable
for their adaptations—selecting the most fit from the least fit, and thereby
changing the adaptiveness of a population of organisms over time. And a
few such organisms, which like to think of themselves as being on the top
of a ladder, are uniquely accountable in the moral sense (or so they tell
themselves, in their self-accounts). Of course, many try to offer evolution-
ary accounts (and, perhaps more often, non-evolutionary accounts, often
by reference to some kind of god, qua meta-meta-agent) of the origins of
G n o m i c Ag e n c y [ 21 ]
22
that seemingly unique kind of moral accountability. But, that said, many
will argue that teleological processes (that undergird moral accountability)
are themselves the products of teleomatic processes (which are distinctly
non-╉intentional), which are themselves the products of non-╉telic processes
of various kinds (such as sieving and serendipity). In other words, it is not
clear, once various forms of selection have been properly understood (from
selecting among different values, qua choice, to natural selection of dif-
ferent variants, qua evolution), that all agents are not derivative agents
somehow—╉so far as their own agency is causally distributed in such ways.
There seems to be an enormous contingency underlying the complex,
non-╉intentional causalities that lead to reflexively-╉instrumental, meta-╉
evaluational, and self-╉accounting modes of agency.
AGENCY ENCLOSED
Given all these different ways of framing agency, and thereby figuring
different kinds of agents, we may ask why human agents are so prone to
frame and figure in particular ways. Why do they ascribe agency along
specific dimensions—╉the causal, the flexible, the reflexive, the evaluative,
the teleological, the moral? Why do they order (along such dimensions)
by reference to particular degrees—╉more or less causal, flexible, reflexive,
evaluative, teleological, moral, and so forth? Why is it so easy to excerpt
agentive figures from multi-╉causal backgrounds? Look, there is an agent,
qua figure (all else becoming background, and so of “no account”). Why do
they excerpt and enclose particular units—╉drawing figures within particu-
lar boundaries: skin, self, team, society, and so forth?
Different collectivities, with different histories and cultures, frame and
figure in different ways; and, indeed, are framed and figured in different
ways by themselves and others. To some degree, a large chunk of politics
turns on who gets to determine the relevant dimensions and degrees of
agency, what causes and capacities are considered important, what order-
ings are appropriate, what units can be excerpted, where to draw boundar-
ies between figures and grounds. In some sense, the most consequential
forms of agency reside in who or what determines what counts as agency,
and thus who or what should be held accountable as an agent.
When we stress these kinds of inherently reflexive, political, and gene-
alogical concerns alongside the foregoing and more canonical kinds of
questions and commitments regarding teleonomic processes, and their
conditions and consequences, we are opening up inquiry into what might
best be called “teleognomic agency,” or simply gnomic agency.
REFERENCES
Aristotle. 2001. Physics. The Collected Works of Aristotle, edited by Richard McKeon,
214–╉394. New York: The Modern Library.
Bacon, Francis. 2000. The New Organon. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
James, William 1918. The Principles of Psychology. Vol. 1. New York: Dover.
Mayr, Ernest W. 1992. “The Idea of Teleology.” Journal of the History of Ideas
53: 117–╉135.
Taylor, Charles. 1989. Sources of the Self. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.
G n o m i c Ag e n c y â•… [â•›23â•›]
25
CHAPTER 4
Semiotic Agency
PAUL KOCKELMAN
S I
Vervet monkeys are semiotic agents. Upon sensing a predator, one such
monkey can instigate an alarm call. And upon sensing the call, another
such monkey can instigate an escape. Here there are at least two semiotic
agents engaged in overlapping semiotic processes. See Figure 4.2. For the
first semiotic agent (A1), the object (O1) is the predator (say, an eagle). The
sign (S1) is an iconic index of that eagle (say, a characteristic wing shape
silhouetted against the sky). And the interpretant (I1) is the alarm call. For
the second semiotic agent (A2), the object (O2) is still the eagle, but now
at some degree of indexical remove. The sign (S2) is the alarm call. And the
interpretant (I2) is the action of running into the underbrush. Instead of
one agent simply seeing and running; we have two coupled agents, the first
seeing and calling, and the second hearing and running.
Crucially, we may also consider the object (qua predator) to be a rela-
tively derivative agent (A3)—╉one who is not just seen and pointed to (by
the first agent), but also looked at (or “heard”) and run from (by the second
agent). Such a predatory agent can, of course, also sense and instigate in
its own right. Indeed, its ability to see and swoop is one of the key reasons
it constitutes such an important object in the semiotic processes of the
vervet monkeys.
There is also a fourth agent (A4) in this scenario—╉one that is inher-
ently distributed, insofar as it is not just composed of the first two agents,
but also partially created by the third agent. In particular, the first two
agents arguably constitute a genetic unit of accountability, by reference to
processes like inclusive fitness, and thus function as a kind of extended
organism.
Moreover, so much of the sensing and instigating behavior of this dis-
tributed agent (framed as an organism, qua bottom ellipse) makes sense
only in reference to the sensing and instigating behavior of the third agent
A3/O3
O1 O2
S1 I1/S2 I2
A5
A1 A2
A4
Se m i o t i c Ag e n c y [ 27 ]
28
Se m i o t i c Ag e n c y â•… [â•›29â•›]
30
1. Indices (and signs more generally) may change an individual’s kind irrespective of an agent’s
ontological assumptions.
2. Indices may change an agent’s ontological assumptions regarding the kinds that constitute a
particular individual.
3. Indices may change an agent’s ontological assumptions regarding the indices that constitute
a particular kind.
4. Indices may change an agent’s ontological assumptions regarding the indices, individuals,
kinds, and agents that constitute a particular world.
5. Changes in an agent’s ontological assumptions about a world (in the foregoing ways) may
change the world about which the agent makes assumptions.
over time. For example, such agents can be more or less sensitive to the fact
that their assumptions are in error and thereby come to update them.
For any such agent, we can thereby inquire into the range of indices it
can perceive, the richness of the kinds it can entertain, the diversity of
the individuals onto which it can project such kinds, and the number of
different worlds it can imagine. Concomitantly, we may inquire into the
complexity of the inferences such an agent can engage in, the ease with
which it may update its ontological assumptions, the degree to which it
can detect and correct errors in its assumptions, and the extent to which
its assumptions can change the world. And we can inquire into its access to
forms of media that extend such capacities (or buffer itself from the effects
or limits on such capacities).
Crucially, such an agent can itself be an individual that exhibits indi-
ces that are perceivable to other agents (including itself); and these other
agents can project kinds onto it, and thereby come to interact with it in
particular ways. That is, such an agent is not just a source of perception
and projection; it is also a site of perception and projection. And just as
its own ontological assumptions about the world can transform (through
its indexical encounters with various individuals), the ontological assump-
tions that other individuals have about it can transform (via their indexical
encounters with it). And, indeed, as per transformativity number 5, such
an agent might even be able to internalize the ontological assumptions
that other agents have about it, and thereby come to behave according to
their beliefs about its various kinds. Note, then, how radically “distributed”
such agents can be.
Finally, this whole framework easily scales to a meta-╉level, for we have
just described a particularly important kind in our own ontology—╉the
agent. And we can project such a kind (or power) onto various individuals
as a function of the indices they express (as the evincing and exercising of
that power). Such agents are a particular kind of kind: one that can per-
ceive and project in ways that conform to ontologies and transform ontolo-
gies. In short, and to return to our opening concerns, such agents not only
ontologize entities in the world, but they are also ontologized as entities
in the world.
Se m i o t i c Ag e n c y â•… [â•›31â•›]
32
Table 4.3 RESIDENTIAL AGENCY
Table 4.4 ╇REPRESENTATIONAL AGENCY
Se m i o t i c Ag e n c y â•… [â•›33â•›]
34
(a)
C E
E1 C1
(b) E2 C2
C E
E3 C3
(c)
C1 E1/C2 E2/C3 E3/C4
E2
C2
causal process. See Figure 4.3c. Which specific events, force fields, and
scales an agent attends to are, in part, a function of what events it can
sense and instigate, and what force fields it is aware of. And they are, in
part, a function of what it is currently engaged in—either instrumentally
or inferentially.
Second, just as semiotic processes can incorporate causal processes
(i.e., a sign-object relation, in Figure 4.1, can be a cause-effect rela-
tion), causal processes can incorporate semiotic processes (i.e., a sign-
interpretant relation, in Figure 4.1, can be a cause-effect relation). As
an example of the first case, I can infer fire from smoke (and thereby
use a causal process to engage in a semiotic practice). As an example of
the second case, I can raise my hand in order to get you to answer my
question (and thereby use a semiotic process to engage in a causal prac-
tice). Indeed, the key objects of many semiotic processes are precisely
causal processes: many semiotic agents can signify and interpret such
processes; and thereby communicate, collaborate, and compete in regard
to such processes; and thereby help or hinder others in their ability to
direct or discover such processes.
Finally, a particularly important kind of effect (E2) is the setting up,
removing, or rechanneling of a force field that links two other events (E3
and E4). See Figure 4.3d. In particular, an agent that instigates E1 in order
to cause E2 may thereby ultimately govern the instrumental and inferen-
tial processes of other agents (who are caught up in E3 and E4). Causing
SPHERES OF INFLUENCE
Se m i o t i c Ag e n c y â•… [â•›35â•›]
36
ACCOUNTABILITY
Those events that an agent can sense and instigate, instrumentally direct
or inferentially discover, via the causal processes it is caught up in, do
not—╉by themselves—╉delimit the agent, or even its sphere of influence.
This is because a significant chunk of agency rests in accountability: of all
the effects an agent can have in the world, given all the causes it is caught
up in, only some are directly attributed to it (by other agencies), such that
it can be held accountable for them. We are punished or rewarded only
for particular events and through particular events, even if we are causally
(inferentially, instrumentally) entangled in a much wider range of pro-
cesses. And so such particularly consequential events loom large in and for
our ontology. That is, such events (for which we are accountable) are not
just key objects in our ontologies (as part of their contents, so to speak);
they are also a key condition of possibility for our ontologies (whatever
their particular contents).
NOTE
1. Not necessarily aware in the sense of “conscious of,” but rather in the sense of
“has ontological assumptions regarding.” For more on each of these accounts
of agency, see Kockelman (2012, 2014a, 2014b, 2015). For more on vervet
monkeys, see Cheney and Seyfarth (1990). See Gell (1992) for a different take on
spheres of influence.
Se m i o t i c Ag e n c y â•… [â•›37â•›]
38
REFERENCES
Cheney, Dorothy L., and Robert M. Seyfarth. 1990. How Monkeys See the World.
Chicago: University of Chicago Press.
Gell, Alfred. 1992. Art and Agency. Oxford: Oxford University Press.
Kockelman, Paul. 2012. “The Ground, The Ground, The Ground: Why Archaeology Is
So ‘Hard.’” Yearbook of Comparative Literature 58: 176–183.
Kockelman, Paul. 2014a. Agent, Person, Subject, Self. Oxford: Oxford University Press.
Kockelman, Paul. 2014b. “The Anthropology of an Equation: Sieving Spam,
Algorithmic Agents, and Ontologies in Transformation.” Hau: Journal of
Ethnographic Theory 3 (3):33–61.
Kockelman, Paul. 2015. “Four Theories of Things: Aristotle, Marx, Heidegger, and
Peirce.” Signs in Society 3 (1):153–192.
PART TWO
CHAPTER 5
Here there is no room for conduct that creates, starting off the uncon-
trollable iterations of response and reinterpretation that characterizes true
political action (Arendt 1958). It would be a travesty to conflate the agonis-
tic, agentive sphere of politics, where any answer is always subject to further
contestation, with that of administration, which reduces human activity to
a striving for smooth functioning and conclusive answers (Honig 1993).
So, another oddity: administration has world-changing effects, but
seems bereft of agents. Infuriatingly— yet conveniently— bureaucracy
appears as an undifferentiated entity exerting power that cannot be held
to account. It is the decider’s enforcer: an implementing thug who carries
out orders but lacks any creative abilities of his own.
This common image, it turns out, distorts our understanding of both
agencies and agency. It conceals the complex distribution of possibility and
responsibility within bureaucracy, which involves individual subjectivi-
ties, interpersonal relations, and socially structured decision-making (Blau
1963; Bernstein 2008). And it obscures the varied ways that accountability
for bureaucratic action is structured by different social arenas. What kind
of accountability is available, it turns out, depends on the position from
which one does the accounting. Here, I unpack one administrative process
to show how units of agency emerge and blend in the ongoing process of
differentiation and subsumption that characterizes bureaucratic action.
I then explain how one particular social arena—litigation—provides a
scaffolding for bureaucratic accountability that, like all scaffoldings, both
enables and constrains.
Bureaucracy’s complex distribution of agency and the legal scaffoldings
for its accountability have two linked implications. One, bureaucracy may
be a paradigmatic case of distributed agency. If we conceive of agency not
as a heroic individual exerting power over others, but as an always inter-
dependent social activity, then bureaucracy’s subsumption of individual
impulses in mass results looks less like agency’s nemesis and more like its
instantiation. Rather than seeing agency in agencies as an oddity, then, we
may see in it an oddly forthright presentation of the nature of agency itself.
Two, identifying legal scaffoldings that enable and constrain bureau-
cratic accountability suggests that accountability is perspectival not only
in agencies, but in general. Whether accountability is available, and what
it looks like when it is, depends not on some underlying relation between
actor and action, but on the scaffoldings that structure the interpretation
of action in particular social arenas. Understanding accountability scaffold-
ings in particular social realms is thus central to understanding the nature
of accountability generally. Indeed, it may be more accurate not to speak of
accountability generally, but only of local tropes of accountability.
STRUCTURING ACCOUNTABILITY
NOTES
1. Recent historical work shows that this was the case even in the early
United States, generally considered a latecomer to the administrative game
(Mashaw 2012).
2. The doctrine of sovereign immunity prevents governments from being
sued without their consent. The FTCA provides this consent for the limited
circumstances it specifies.
REFERENCES
CHAPTER 6
“We never really act alone,” Enfield and Kockelman remind us in the pref-
ace to this volume. When millions of people come to the street from their
homes and workplaces to fight for a political goal, that fact is easy to see.
But who (or what) has agency in situations that seem to be the opposite
of “acting alone”? Who (or what) has agency in a revolution forestalled?
Millions of Egyptians took to the street in 2010–11 during the January 25
Revolution in Egypt to overthrow President Hosni Mubarak and to demand
bread, freedom, and social justice. They succeeded in forcing Mubarak to
resign, with the support of the armed forces. Debates immediately began
about whether this was really a revolution and whether it had succeeded
or failed. Egyptians called it the January 25th Revolution after Mubarak
resigned and continue to do so. Four years later President Morsi of the
Muslim Brotherhood had been elected and deposed; chief of the Egyptian
armed forces under President Morsi, General Sisi, had become president
in turn. Opinions about what had happened, how it had happened, how
events should be named, and who was to be credited—and blamed—for the
ensuing course of events remain heated and will for years to come. In this
brief chapter I do not try to explain these historic events, ask whether the
revolution succeeded or failed, or pass judgment on the political agenda or
methods of any party. Rather I ask: what can the January 25th Revolution
and its aftermath teach us about agency and about distributed agency in
50
never available for all. Postcolonial movements held out the promise of
infrastructure as a public good for all citizens. Failures of infrastructure
in the postcolonial era, in turn, made visible—and came to symbolize—
failures of the postcolonial state. Privatization of infrastructure began
in postcolonial states under structural adjustment policies in the 1970s.
Infrastructure began to be privatized in wealthy countries under neoliberal
policies of the 1990s. All this makes infrastructure a terrain and object of
political contestation.
Revolts are collective, willed, and condensed events. They are the out-
come of many different kinds of social action and political intent. This is
different from the kind of hacking into infrastructure on a daily basis that
is a normal part of life in poor countries and communities. During mass
revolts, infrastructure is repurposed by groups or actively broken down.
Roads, phones, subways, and wires become channels through which people
are persuaded to act and bodies are motivated to move. Infrastructure is
also rendered visible in revolt when people are blocked from moving—
when streets are blocked off or squares suffused with people—or when
signals cannot be transmitted across computer or mobile phone networks.
Many early commentators on the January 25th Revolution in Egypt
gave agency to technological infrastructure. They called it a “Facebook
Revolution.” This notion went together well with Orientalist stereotypes
of the Egyptian people as endlessly and forever patient. Patience is indeed
a virtue, as the Egyptian saying goes. But the virtue of patience in popular
Egyptian culture had never stopped Egyptians from political action in the
past. Years of organizing went into making the January 25th Revolution
as well. Many unions, individuals, leaders and parties were involved. Hosni
Mubarak and his advisors also thought that the internet had agency—if
less than their own agency. They tried to “turn off” the internet during
the revolution in an effort to stop social action. While others might have
tried in the past to throttle or shut down parts of the internet that reach a
particular polity, no government had ever been able to turn off the internet
in an entire country and to go off the digital map. Egypt came close, sup-
pressing 91 percent of internet networks and all mobile phones by January
29th (Peterson 2011).
Communications infrastructures had been nationalized in Egypt
together with banks and large industry nine years after the 1952 Free
Officers Coup. Egypt began to espouse open market policies in the mid
1970s, and free market neoliberal economics in the 1990s and 2000s.
Through all of this, Egypt kept tight control over banking and telecommu-
nications. It instituted a private sector telecommunications industry only
in the mid-2000s, when it granted mobile phone licenses to two private
U p e n di n g I n f r a s t r u c t u r e i n T i m e s of Re volt [ 51 ]
52
U p e n di n g I n f r a s t r u c t u r e i n T i m e s of Re volt [ 53 ]
54
REFERENCES
Bayat, Asef. 2009. Life as Politics: How Ordinary People Change the Middle East.
Stanford, CA: Stanford University Press.
Elyachar, Julia. 2010. “Phatic Labor, Infrastructure, and the Question of
Empowerment in Cairo.” American Ethnologist 37(3): 452–464.
Horst, Heather, and Daniel Miller. 2006. The Cell Phone: An Anthropology of
Communication. Oxford, UK: Berg.
Kockelman, Paul. 2007. “Agency: The Relation Between Meaning, Power, and
Knowledge.” Current Anthropology 48(3): 375–401.
Larkin, Brian. 2013. “The Politics and Poetics of Infrastructure.” Annual Review of
Anthropology 42: 327–343.
Peterson, Mark Allen. 2011. “Egypt’s Media Ecology in a Time of Revolt.” Arab
Media and Society 14 (Summer). Accessed August 10, 2016. http://www.
arabmediasociety.com/?article=770.
U p e n di n g I n f r a s t r u c t u r e i n T i m e s of Re volt [ 55 ]
57
PART THREE
Language and Agency
╇ 59
CHAPTER 7
A VISION OF THE FUTURE
culture but also offers practical applications, for instance in the form of neu-
rally controlled prosthetic devices that enable paralyzed patients to regain
limb functions. A more ambitious program is to link such brain-╉to-╉machine
interfaces together to yield brain-╉to-╉brain interfaces (Nicolelis 2013). The
applications, medical or otherwise, are somewhat less clear here, but a com-
monly stated interest is to bypass verbal communication in order to avoid
its articulatory bottlenecks and expressive limitations (Rao et al. 2014) or
indeed its possibilities for selectivity and deception (Gell-╉Mann 1994).
Implicit in these ideals of sidestepping the constraints of bodies and
language is a narrow view of human agency and communication, and
a limited recognition of how material and cultural artifacts have long
extended our minds (Clark and Chalmers 1998). “Can information that
is available in the brain be transferred directly in the form of the neu-
ral code, bypassing language altogether?” ask Rao et al. (2014:1). This
reveals a sender-╉receiver model of communication in which externaliza-
tion is seen as a mere obstacle to the goal of sharing private processes—╉
the possibility that it may provide much-╉needed filters and calibration
mechanisms is not considered. Rao et al.’s experiment consists of record-
ing brain activity in one person using electro-╉encephalography and
delivering it to another person using a transcranial magnetic stimula-
tion device positioned such that a pulse results in an involuntary upward
jerk of the hand. The other has no choice, but is controlled by brute force.
This is communication stripped of any possibilities for negotiating joint
commitment or shared intentionality (Gilbert 1989). It is akin to push-
ing someone out of the room rather than persuading him or her to leave.
Current conceptions of brain-╉ to-╉
brain interfaces thus appear to be
more about the involuntary unloading of information than about the co-╉
construction of shared understanding, and more about control by brute
force than about cooperation by consent—╉all at a loss of individual agency.
Collaboration, of course, always involves some redistribution of individual
agency to a larger social unit, creating joint agency. How is this achieved?
A brain-╉to-╉brain interface implements it physically; language does it socially.
The two need not exclude each other. A goal of this chapter is to put forward
some insights about human language that may be incorporated in the design
of ethically responsible brain-╉to-╉brain interfaces (Trimper et al. 2014).
conversation. The following fragment was recorded in Ghana, but its anal-
ysis draws on insights that apply to social interaction everywhere (Sacks
1992). Some family members have just finished processing some newly
harvested maize and are now preparing to play a board game. A large metal
tub holding the maize is still in the way, making it hard for others to join
the game.
Siwu (Neighbours_3093575)
1 ((Ben is holding a board game for four; a large metal tub with
processed maize stands in the way of others joining))
2 Sesi kãrãnpɔ laa puta lò yedza ìyo katɔ̃ mmɔ.
right I’ll lift this and put it in storage there
3 Ben be tè mì puta mì yedza iyo:?
what are you going to put in storage?
4 Sesi àtita
the maize
5 Ben ta mà ba mà su àtitabi wangbe kɔ̃rɔ̃kɔ̃rɔ̃.
this maize will be picked up right away
6 Sesi ã, ma kɛlɛ̀ gu kala
ah, they’re taking it down ((to the lower end of the village))
((some intervening turns omitted))
12 Sesi ɛ̀h, nyua bò Afua.
uh, wait, Afua
13 Afua ((looks up))
14 Sesi mi mɔɛ gu mɛ̀ si bò su bò sia ngbe.
grab this with me so we put it right here
15 ((1.6 seconds of silence))
16 Sesi bò su bo yedza i kuruɛ nɛ te mi ba mia sɛ ngbe mi pɛ iraɔ̀ ni.
let us put this to the side so you can come and play this thing
17 ((Sesi & Afua lift tub together and place it one meter to the side))
18 Sesi kailɛ.
that’s good.
19 ((people sit down to play the game))
Sesi offers to put away the tub in the storage room. Ben asks for clarifica-
tion, and when Sesi makes clear he refers to the maize, Ben notes that it
will be taken elsewhere soon. This leads to a slight change of plans. Now
all Sesi needs to do is move the tub to the side. He recruits the help of his
sibling Afua. Once the obstacle is out of the way, people sit down to play
the game. Exchanges like this happen all over the world every day—and it
is in this kind of context that we see some of the most fundamental roles
of language in social life.
Most importantly, language helps distribute agency. Take Sesi’s request
for help (lines 12–18): he addresses Afua by name to secure her attention,
then produces a first version of the request. When there is no immediate
uptake, he reformulates his request, adding a reason which turns it from a
mere practical matter into a joint project that may also benefit her (“let’s
put this to the side so you can come and play this thing,” line 16). His
actions show that language provides a systematic organization of linguis-
tic resources to interactively manage the many concerns at play when one
person asks another to do something. The ultimate effect is that Sesi suc-
ceeds in recruiting Afua’s body as a “tool” for carrying out a joint action.
This is somewhat like the participants in the Rao et al. (2014) experiment,
but with the crucial difference that it is jointly negotiated rather than
achieved by brute force. Two features in particular help language distribute
agency: its selectivity and its negotiability.
The selectivity of language manifests itself in two ways. First, speakers
can select the linguistic means for making their ideas public, allowing them
to foreground or background certain informational or relational concerns.
To this end, language offers a large and renewable supply of words, expres-
sions, and conversational structures. Sesi can refer to the tub of maize with
“this” (relying on shared context) or with “the maize” (spelling out the under-
specified reference). He can refer to his sister as “Afua” (highlighting her sta-
tus as an individual) but also include her in the pronoun “us” (highlighting
her status as part of a joint social unit created in that very moment). This
selectivity makes language highly efficient by enabling it to be underspeci-
fied when possible, yet specifiable when necessary (Levinson 2000). A sec-
ond sense in which language is selective is that speakers can select what to
make public and what to keep private. Language provides us with ways to
control and filter what we share with whom. Perhaps it is this sense of selec-
tivity that Gell-Mann deplored, as it opens up the possibility for deception.
However, this is easily outweighed by the social benefits: some things are
better left unsaid. More generally, sharing and withholding information are
among the most important ways in which we manage our social relation-
ships. The selectivity of public language means that it offers a set of filters
through which we can efficiently and tactfully connect private worlds.
The other key feature of how language distributes agency is its negotia-
bility: the fact that meaning and mutual understanding are always open to
it. A recurrent dream in this work is the prospect of a “mind meld,” in which
a super-╉network of brains may come to be the substrate for something like
a meta-╉consciousness (Nicolelis 2013). From a biological perspective this is
not novel. Mind melds —╉or complex networks in which large numbers of
individual agents together achieve a form of sentience—╉have independently
arisen several times in evolution, for instance in eusocial insect societies and
in cellular slime molds, the latter capable of impressive feats in maze-╉solving.
The real challenge for brain-╉to-╉brain interfaces is not to achieve some inter-
linking of brains; it is to harness this technology in a way that does not reduce
human participants to the level of amoeba in a slime mold.
Seen in this light, the selectivity and negotiability of language are not
bugs, they are features. Thanks to these features of language, we can main-
tain a complex web of social relations by managing what we share with
whom, and we can join forces in larger social units without indefinitely
relinquishing individual agency. To throw this into sharper relief, con-
sider what happens when selectivity and negotiability are systematically
diminished or punished, as in religious indoctrination or interrogation
under torture. Here, the very defining features of individual agency are
taken away, and it is no coincidence that we describe such circumstances
as dehumanizing or inhumane. Language is what makes us human. It is
not merely a conduit for information. We might try exchanging it for a
high-╉throughput physical connection to optimize the flow of some types of
information—╉but we would do so at the tremendous cost of throwing away
a rich infrastructure for organizing social agency.
Could brain-╉to-╉brain interfaces be designed in a way that incorporates
this infrastructure? None of the points made above logically depend on the
spoken, face-╉to-╉face version of language that is its most prevalent form
today. In fact, language is modality-╉independent to some degree, as shown
by the fact that it can be realized wholly visually as in the signed languages
of the deaf. So it is not inconceivable that there can be some useful form
of social interaction in the substrate of brain-╉to-╉brain interfaces. Whatever
the modality of communication, the two design features that matter most
for creating a truly humane form of brain-╉to-╉brain interfaces are: (1) selec-
tivity, giving people control over the relation between public words and
private worlds; and (2) negotiability, giving people systematic opportuni-
ties for calibrating and revising joint commitments.
CONCLUSIONS
The Hitchhiker’s Guide to the Galaxy records the case of the Belcerebon
people of Kakrafoon, who were inflicted by a Galactic Tribunal with “that
ACKNOWLEDGMENTS
Thanks to Nick Enfield, Steve Levinson, and Paul Kockelman for helping me
develop my thinking on the topics raised here. I received helpful comments
on draft versions from Nick Enfield and Roel Willems, and I thank other
contributors to the Foundations of Social Agency meeting at Ringberg
Castle for stimulating interactions. I gratefully acknowledge the support
of an NWO Veni grant and of the Max Planck Society for the Advancement
of Science.
REFERENCES
Dingemanse, Mark, Seán G. Roberts, Julija Baranova, Joe Blythe, Paul Drew,
Simeon Floyd, Rosa S. Gisladottir, Kobin H. Kendrick, Stephen C. Levinson,
Elizabeth Manrique, Giovanni Rossi, N. J. Enfield. 2015. “Universal Principles
in the Repair of Communication Problems.” PLOS ONE 10(9): e0136100.
doi:10.1371/journal.pone.0136100.
Enfield, N. J. 2013. Relationship Thinking: Agency, Enchrony, and Human Sociality.
Oxford: Oxford University Press.
Gell-Mann, Murray. 1994. The Quark and the Jaguar: Adventures in the Simple and the
Complex. New York: W. H. Freeman.
Gilbert, Margaret. 1989. On Social Facts. London/New York: Routledge.
Grau, Carles, Romuald Ginhoux, Alejandro Riera, Thanh Lam Nguyen, Hubert
Chauvat, Michel Berg, Julià L. Amengual, Alvaro Pascual-Leone, and Giulio
Ruffini. 2014. “Conscious Brain-to-Brain Communication in Humans Using
Non-Invasive Technologies.” PLOS ONE 9(8): e105225. doi:10.1371/journal.
pone.0105225.
Levinson, Stephen C. 2000. Presumptive Meanings: The Theory of Generalized
Conversational Implicature. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.
Nicolelis, Miguel. 2013. Beyond Boundaries: The New Neuroscience of Connecting Brains
with Machines—and How It Will Change Our Lives. New York: Henry Holt and
Company.
Rao, Rajesh P. N., Andrea Stocco, Matthew Bryan, Devapratim Sarma, Tiffany M.
Youngquist, Joseph Wu, and Chantel S. Prat. 2014. “A Direct Brain-to-Brain
Interface in Humans.” PLOS ONE 9(11): e111332. doi:10.1371/journal.
pone.0111332.
Sacks, Harvey. 1992. Lectures on Conversation. 2 vols. London: Blackwell.
Trimper, John B., Paul Root Wolpe, and Karen S. Rommelfanger. 2014. “When
‘I’ Becomes ‘We’: Ethical Implications of Emerging Brain-to-Brain
Interfacing Technologies.” Frontiers in Neuroengineering 7: 4. doi:10.3389/
fneng.2014.00004.
CHAPTER 8
People frequently achieve goals that they are unable (or sometimes unwill-
ing) to accomplish alone by requesting assistance from others. This possibil-
ity for distributing agency across multiple individuals, some expressing the
goals and others accomplishing the actions, is a basic ingredient of human
sociality. It makes possible all types of collective action, from the macro-
level of large-scale institutions to the micro-level of face-to-face interaction.
Much of our collective action is managed by pre-existing arrangements; for
example, nobody needs to be specifically asked to report to work on a given
day if there is already a contract establishing the required activities over a
period of time. However, at the micro level of co-present social coordination,
it is often necessary for a person to use some explicit semiotic means, lin-
guistic or otherwise, to tell another that he or she wishes for something to
be done at a given time (see Dingemanse, chapter 7 in this volume). In such
cases, people make requests. A “request sequence”1 in face-to-face interac-
tion can be identified on the basis of two moves2 involving two participants:
MAKING REQUESTS
One common way that people formulate requests is by using the mor-
phosyntactic resources made available to them by the different lan-
guages they speak. While grammatical systems vary to some degree,
they usually organize the types of formulations they make possible
into “sentence types” that are useful for cross-linguistic comparison.6
Languages tend to distinguish making a statement (“declarative”),
asking a question (“interrogative”), and making a command (“impera-
tive”). This last type is primarily dedicated to expressing a desire to
direct the actions of others, and as such it is the most frequently used
sentence type for requests in many languages (e.g., “Pass the salt”).
Speakers also use the other major sentence types for requests: inter-
rogatives (“Can I have the salt?”), declaratives (“I need the salt”), and
sometimes other formats including utterances with no verb and thus
no sentence type, strictly speaking (“Salt!”). Languages commonly allow
for different sentence types to be used flexibly for requesting, often
with relation to more “indirect” interrogative and declarative strategies
of requesting that may be considered more polite,7 but languages may
also vary greatly with respect to the different frequencies with which
the different sentence types are used for requests. The types of indirect
request strategies that have been observed for English are also seen in
Cha’palaa, but are relatively rare, and imperatives are the most common
format (71% of cases).
Give me the
old razor.
Figure 8.1 Different types of multimodal request formats. Left: Holding out the hand
(16%). Middle: Holding out an object (27%). Right: Pointing (42%).
Re q u e s t i n g a s a Mea n s f or Ne g o t i at i n g Ag e n c y [ 69 ]
70
or things involved in the request. Under certain conditions, people are also
able to successfully accomplish requests entirely nonverbally, such as when
there is an already agreed upon joint activity.8
RESPONDING TO REQUESTS
How people formulate their requests is only half of the issue, however.
While most work on requesting has focused on request formats in iso-
lation, cues from work in conversation analysis points toward seeing
requesting as a sequence of moves in which the initial move provides an
opportunity for a subsequent, responsive move. One important aspect
of these contingent moments is that they are socially delicate, as the
addressee is in a position to potentially reject the request. Work on
politeness and “face” in interaction notes how people actively avoid and
mitigate this type of face-╉threatening act.9 Indeed, looking at the differ-
ent ways Cha’palaa speakers responded to requests, fulfilling the request
is by far the most frequent type of response while rejection is the least
frequent.
One way to interpret this finding, which is surely appropriate to some
degree, is that people share a generally cooperative stance, and so they max-
imize the potential for affiliative interactions with no “face-╉threatening”
consequences. People aim for request sequences like those in (1), (2), and
(3), above, in which the next move is B accomplishing the requested action,
and avoid sequences like (4), in which A’s request is not fulfilled.
80
70
60
50
40
30
20
10
0
Response
The few rejections that do occur are often, like this one, managed through
indirect requests and mitigating, polite answers (in this case, with the
use of a diminutive), and rarely is there any overt contention. However,
there may be more behind this surface of apparent pervasive cooperative,
affiliative behavior. One of the options in Brown and Levinson’s original
formulation of how people manage face in social interaction is to avoid
the face-threatening act in the first place, if there are potential negative
consequences.10 For the study of requesting, this means that in addition
to reflecting a cooperative stance, the low rate of overt rejection may also
reflect the fact that in most instances people only make requests that have
a high chance of success.
Not all members of a society have equal rights to request others to do
things in any given time or place, and these rights are tied to the nature
of the activity at hand, the setting, and the participants involved.11 In the
context of everyday interaction under discussion here, the different rights
and duties expected of individuals are in part structured by their household
and community roles. In the collaborative project that the investigation of
Cha’palaa requests was part of, each field researcher, based on long-term
experience in the communities where the natural speech data was recorded,
was asked to provide ethnographically grounded information about the
social (a)symmetry of each dyad involved in a given request sequence,
when possible. These rationales for identifying such asymmetries varied.
In Chachi households in Ecuador, where men often rest in hammocks while
women attend to cooking, cleaning, and childcare, husband-wife dyads
often show dynamics of gender inequality. Children and adolescents are
also expected to take orders from adults to do different household tasks. In
other cultural contexts, gender or age might not be as relevant in commu-
nity contexts as status as host versus guest, for example, or the birth order
Re q u e s t i n g a s a Mea n s f or Ne g o t i at i n g Ag e n c y [ 71 ]
72
120
100
80
60
40
20
0
(A)symmetry
Re q u e s t i n g a s a Mea n s f or Ne g o t i at i n g Ag e n c y [ 73 ]
74
actions: an action upon an action, on existing actions or on those which may arise
in the present or the future…â•›.[A]â•„power relationship can only be articulated
on the basis of two elements which are each indispensable if it is really to be a
power relationship: that “the other” (the one over whom power is exercised) be
thoroughly recognized and maintained to the very end as a person who acts; and
that, faced with a relationship of power, a whole field of responses, reactions,
results, and possible inventions may open up.20
NOTES
Re q u e s t i n g a s a Mea n s f or Ne g o t i at i n g Ag e n c y [ 75 ]
76
modify others. Which is to say, of course, that something called Power, with or
without a capital letter, which is assumed to exist universally in a concentrated
or diffused form, does not exist. Power exists only when it is put into action,
even if, of course, it is integrated into a disparate field of possibilities brought to
bear upon permanent structures.” Foucault 1982:788, author’s emphasis.
20. Foucault 1982:789, author’s emphasis.
REFERENCES
Re q u e s t i n g a s a Mea n s f or Ne g o t i at i n g Ag e n c y [ 77 ]
78
79
CHAPTER 9
Greta has asked Sergio to remove a “thingy” from her forehead, which he
identifies as a wisp of hair (line 1). Sergio realizes that the hair has glued up
because some dye has run down on Greta’s forehead. This leads him to state
that: “it is necessary also to wipe away the dye from the forehead.”
Sergio’s statement presents wiping away the dye as the right thing to do
for anyone in the current situation. Here, the action could be done by any
of the three participants, including Sergio himself. He is the person who
is most directly involved in the dyeing process, and who is responsible
for having let the dye drip on Greta’s forehead, for which he apologizes
(“sorry”). While saying bisogna “it is necessary to,” Sergio moves his hand
in the direction of the table, possibly toward the kitchen paper, but then
hesitates. At the same time, he gazes at Dino, and in so doing prompts him
to get involved. Dino is arguably in a better position to wipe Greta’s fore-
head, because Sergio’s hands are stained with dye. Also, Dino has already
assisted Sergio more than once earlier in the interaction. Here again, Dino
volunteers his help (“I’ll do it,” line 4). But, as he reaches for the kitchen
paper, Greta gets to it before him and goes on to wipe her own forehead.
In this case, two recipients of an impersonal deontic declarative find
themselves “competing” for the animatorship of the necessary action.
Although Dino makes an explicit bid for it (“I’ll do it”), it is Greta who
S o c i a l Ag e n c y a n d G r a m m a r [ 81 ]
82
As Ilona begins the statement (“juice … l”), she reaches across the table
toward the juice jug, thus making a bid to take charge of the need she is in the
process of formulating. As Ilona continues the statement (“ … it is neces-
sary … ”) and her hand reaches the jug (line 6), Jacek begins responding by
saying that he will do the necessary action “right now” (line 7). Immediately
after this, while Ilona lifts the jug and completes the statement (“ … to
take”), Jacek continues his response by explicitly volunteering to pour the
juice (“I’ll pour it,” line 7). Ilona then accepts the offer (“good,” line 9) and
puts the jug back down (line 10). Meanwhile, Jacek has started to retract
(‘you pour it?,” line 11), but after Ilona’s acceptance he repeats his offer (“I’ll
pour it,” line 12), which is then ratified by Ilona (line 13). While proceeding
to pour the juice, Jacek adds an explanation for why he is taking over the job
from Ilona: “it will be more convenient for me” (line 15).
An impersonal deontic declarative doesn’t constrain participation in
the necessary action, but leaves it open to any relevant contributor. In
fragment 2, the interaction initially favors a certain individual to take
on the action (Ilona), but its subsequent development leads to a change
of animatorship. When Ilona begins the statement, she is projectably
engaged in pouring the juice. At the same time, however, the preface to
her statement “you know what” (line 4) marks it as relevant for Jacek and
calls for his attention to what is happening. This complex configuration
leads to an explicit negotiation of who will pour the juice. The result is that
S o c i a l Ag e n c y a n d G r a m m a r [ 83 ]
84
REFERENCES
S o c i a l Ag e n c y a n d G r a m m a r â•… [â•›85â•›]
86
Floyd, Simeon, Giovanni Rossi, and N. J. Enfield, eds. Under review. Getting Others to
Do Things: A Pragmatic Typology of Recruitments. Berlin: Language Science Press.
Goffman, Erving. 1981. Forms of Talk. Philadelphia: University of Pennsylvania Press.
Malchukov, Andrej Lvovich, and Anna Siewierska, eds. 2011. Impersonal
Constructions: A Cross-Linguistic Perspective. Amsterdam/Philadelphia: John
Benjamins.
Rossi, Giovanni. 2015. “The Request System in Italian Interaction.” Ph.D. dissertation,
Radboud University, Nijmegen, the Netherlands.
Rossi, Giovanni and Jörg Zinken. 2016. “Grammar and Social Agency: The Pragmatics
of Impersonal Deontic Statements.” Language 92(4).
Vinkhuyzen, Erik, and Margaret H. Szymanski. 2005. “Would You Like to Do It
Yourself? Service Requests and Their Non-Granting Responses.” In Applying
Conversation Analysis, edited by K. Richards and P. Seedhouse, 91–106.
New York: Palgrave Macmillan.
CHAPTER 10
understands the first speaker to have done, saying, for instance, “thank you
for offering” and so on.2
So by making it recognizable to a recipient what action(s) one intends
to accomplish, a speaker thereby necessarily becomes accountable for hav-
ing done that action. But are there ways to achieve some interactional goal
without having to do the action that would lead to that outcome by virtue
of a recipient’s recognition? Relatedly, is there a way to achieve an interac-
tional goal without, in the process, becoming accountable as the agent who
effected it? In what follows I will describe three kinds of cases that suggest
an affirmative answer to these questions—there are indeed methods by
which a participant in interaction can accomplish interactional goals while
flying beneath the radar of accountability.3
may I help you?” may be a way of getting the other person to provide her
name, but it is not an accountable action in that respect; one cannot say
in response “Why do you want my name?” because the name was never
asked for.
(1) NB:II:2:R
01 Nancy: Hel-lo:,
02 Emma: .hh HI::.
03 (.)
04 Nancy: Oh:’I::: ‘ow a:re you Emmah:
05 Emma: FI:NE yer LINE’S BEEN BUSY.
06 Nancy: Yea:h (.) my u.-fuhh h-.hhhh my fa:ther’s wife ca:lled me,h
07 .hhh So when she ca:lls me::,h .hh I always talk fer a lo:ng
08 ti:me cz she c’n afford it’n I ca:n’t.hhh[hhh]°huh°]
09 Emma: [OH:] : : : : : ]:=
10 =my [go:sh ah th ]aht my phone wz outta order:
11 Nancy: [--Ah :::::::, ]
Emma is able to elicit information without having to ask for it and thus
without having to do something that might be characterizable as “nosey”
and so on. Where the telling of limited access does not elicit the information
A g e n c y a n d A c t i o n u n de r Rada r of Ac c o u n ta b i l i t y [ 89 ]
90
(2) Geri-Shirley
01 Geri: Oka:y d’dju just hear me pull up?=
02 Shirley: =.hhhh -NO:. I wz -TRYing you all day.’n the LINE wz busy
03 fer like hours.
04 Geri: Ohh:::::::, ohh:::::. .hhhhhh We::ll, hhh ah’m g’nna c’m
05 over ‘n a li’l while help yer brother ou:t,
06 Shirley: Goo[:d.
07 Geri: [.hh Cz I know he needs some he::lp, ((mournfully))
08 Shirley: .khh Ye:ah. Yeh he’d mention’ that t’day.=
09 Geri: =M-hm,=
10 Shirley: =.hhh Uh:m, .tch.hhhh Who w’yih -ta:lking to:
11 (0.6)
12 Geri: Jis no:w?
13 Shirley: .hhhh No I called be-like between ele[ven en
14 Geri: [I: wasn’talkeen tuh
15 a:nybuddy. (b) Bo-oth Marla’n I slept ‘ntil about noo:n,=
16 Shirley: =O[h.
17 Geri: [.hhhh en w’n I woke up, I wannid tih call my mother.
18 Shirley: Mm-[hm,
19 Geri: [.hhhh en I picked up the pho:ne, e:n I couldn’t dial
20 out.’n[I thought ar phone wz out’v order.[‘n I-.hhh
21 Shirley: [Oh: ( ), [Yeh,
22 Geri: said w’l oyll I: bet I know w’t happened,=
23 =[(so) I walked-]
24 Shirley: =[Marla left th’]phone o[ff the hook,]=
Here, when Shirley’s initial conveyance of limited access does not elicit
information about Geri’s use of the phone, she eventually formulates a
direct inquiry, asking, at line 10, “Who w’yih -ta:lking to:.” Sticking with
examples in which one participant reports trouble in reaching or find-
ing another, we can see that not only is this utterly pervasive, it is also
quite tightly structured. And so when, in example (3), Penny reports,
“I triedju all morning long’n it wz really busy,” prompting Pat’s “Yeh I
wz sleeping my mother wz answering,” Penny then goes on to elaborate
her “side.”
(3) Houseburning
01 Penny: =.hh I said tih myself I triedju all morning long’n it
02 wz really busy. .hhhh[hhh]=
03 Pat: [Yea][h,
04 Penny: [=en: : :[d,
05 Pat: ╅╅╅╅╇[Yeh I wz sleeping my
06 mother wz answering, hh[hh
07 Penny: [.hh So-╉Uhri:ght.
08 Then, right, that’s good.That’s good. .hh
09 But so I’ve been trying all along en I thought maybe thet
10 chih took the phone off the hook.
Finally, we can see a similar kind of pattern across quite different examples
in which rather than make a request, a speaker merely describes a trou-
ble, thereby inviting the other to offer what is wanted (see, for discussion,
Pomerantz and Heritage 2012). Routinely, description of a trouble leads
the recipient to offer a remedy, but again, if the offer is not made or is not
sufficient, the speaker can then “go on record” and make the request, as in
the following case in which a landlady initially establishes the presence of
a laundry machine in her basement apartment before going on to report
the problem of having “no water” to the tenant. When the tenant offers a
solution that would merely fix the immediate problem, Alice ends up going
on record with the request saying, “Well I don’t want you to shut it off mid-╉
load, just don’t run it anymore.”
And in the following well-known case, Donny sets up his telling of a trou-
ble with the pre-announcement “Guess what” in line 6. The problem is
then described in incremental fashion (lines 8 and 10), but this does not
elicit more of a response than the information receipt in line 11. At line
15 Donny seems to be on the way to formulating a request but leaves this
unfinished in order to continue with the telling of the trouble. It is at
this point that Marcia interjects, indicating that she has understood what
Donny wants and that, if possible, she would comply.
A g e n c y a n d A c t i o n u n de r Rada r of Ac c o u n ta b i l i t y [ 93 ]
94
(6) xtr. 1
01 Ann: =Hello::
02 Janet: Oh=hi:_╉=it’s Janet_╉ [Shelby’s mo]m
03 Ann: [hi: Janet]
04 How eryou(h) .h hh
05 Janet: I’m goo:d,how are y [ou
06 Ann: â•…â•…â•…â•…â•…â•…â•…â•…[I’m fi:ne.h[we’re actually: uhm
07 Janet: â•…â•…â•…â•…[ogoodo
08 (0.2)
09 Ann: we’re running bit late=but we’re
10 (.)
11 on our wa(h)y:
12 Janet: Do you want me to come an’ get her?
13 Ann: Uhm:, it doesn’t matte:r, like(hh)
14 (0.4)
15 .hhhhh
16 Janet: I-╉ I could.it’s very easy.
17 so rather than you h:av(h)e(h)
18 (.)
19 you know (.) tuh get everybody ou[t
20 â•…â•…â•…â•…â•…â•…â•…â•…â•…â•…â•…â•…â•…â•…[.hhh
21 I’ll justa
22 (0.2)
23 come dow:n.=
Across these examples then we see that the telling of a trouble or even the
mere hint of one (as in the last example) can prompt from the recipient an
offer of assistance or at least an account for not producing such an offer.
CONCLUSION
Examples such as these show us then that participants are acutely aware of
the accountability that attaches to the actions they are recognized as doing
and, in certain circumstances at least, seek to avoid that accountability by
achieving their interactional goals by alternate means. Across all the cases
discussed here there seems to be an interactional short-╉circuit whereby
speakers are able to bypass the action/╉recognition node of the [practice] -╉>
[action/╉recognition] -╉> [interactional goal] chain such that they are able to
recruit the agency of another without being accountable for having done
so. Recruited others provide their own names, provide information, or pro-
vide offers of assistance and thereby commit themselves as agents to some
joint venture.
I have suggested that much of what gets done in interaction is accom-
plished by the use of practices of speaking that, when deployed in some
specific sequential context, are recognized as implementing a particular
action. So when Janet says, “Do you want me to come and get her?” this is
understood to implement an offer rather than as merely asking about what
Anne wants or desires. When speakers implement actions in this way, using
practices that are designed to be recognizably implementing them, they “go
on record” and are thus accountable for having done the action in question.
Recipients, or nonrecipient participants, can thus ask why this action is
being done (“why do you ask?,” “why do you say that?,” “why do you want
to know?,” etc.), or they can report that the action has been done (“she
asked if I was going,” “she complained that it was too hot,” etc.). Obviously,
formulations of prior actions can be challenged or contested (see Sidnell
and Enfield 2014) but that does not change the underlying fact that par-
ticipants become accountable for the actions that they are recognized as
having done. Now of course there are various circumstances in which a
participant might want to “fly under the radar of accountability”—╉that is,
achieve some interactional outcome or goal without doing the action that
would effect this and thus without being accountable for having done it.
In this chapter I have briefly considered some cases in which we see how
participants are able to do this.
ACKNOWLEDGMENT
NOTES
REFERENCES
PART FOUR
Economy and Agency
99
CHAPTER 11
INTRODUCTION: MODERN TIME
1995: 77, 107). Of the awkward incompatibilities that can arise from such
entanglement, the most obvious is between the homogeneous empty time
of modernity, and the temporal micro-rhythms and indeterminacies of
life in biological and social mode. People gain and lose employment and
income, fall ill, age, organize and disorganize their social relationships,
and live with sudden shifts in general conditions (war, disease, disaster,
windfalls). And they may come together in existentially challenging ways.
None of them—alone or in combination—can easily be calculated as “risk”
and entered into debt contracts as such. It is in life, rather than debt law,
that causation, intention, assessment, responsibility, blame, the source
of ongoing momentum and the implications of failure to sustain it, work
out. Whereas in life, they all refer, in ways that vary with philosophical
principles, to a supple grid of ongoing interactions in textured time, to
which people commit themselves, without knowing what contingencies
may arise in life, and intersect with each other, in barely manageable ways.
The attempt to recalculate, and to live, these as calculable probabilities may
remain intractable to the abstract model, either by authorities, by experts,
or by people themselves. In many philosophies of life, it is ritual, of both
collective and intimate kinds, that mediates such temporalities and may
well distribute agency within the life processes between the abstract T1
and T2 of modern time.
The recent expansion of debt regimes, framed in empty homogeneous
time, meets these philosophies and exigencies in zones of tension. Debt
management is at least 5,000 years old, according to Graeber (2011), and
is fundamental to the financial regimes of present-day capitalism. It can
therefore serve as an example of the modern effort to make the world of T1
and T2, and the intractable human realities and philosophical legacies, con-
sonant with each other in an ever-expanding range of debt relationships.
For example, under American law, personal bankruptcy can be declared,
subject to the person’s submission to a “reorganization plan” mediated
by experts (United States Code, Chapter 13, Title 11). Such a law defines
agency and responsibility in exact, individuated, modeled terms; the con-
cept of “default” puts the individual at “fault,” even if life became contin-
gently intractable for them. My chapter suggests that this is one deeply
consequential aspect of the individuation of modernity proposed by Max
Weber in The Protestant Ethic and the Spirit of Capitalism: an important,
although under-examined, entailment of the entrepreneurial proposition
that Weber developed most strongly. Within debt practices, the older, intu-
itive, and culturally varied traditions of distributed agency face those of the
present formalized world.
Di s t r i b u t ed Ag e n c y a n d De b t [ 101 ]
102
The social historical and anthropological records show that all temporal
regimes are comprised of multiple durations of varying length, running
concurrently. Most obviously, there are diurnal, lunar, seasonal/annual,
and life cycles, nested within each other, with key moments of conver-
gence, whose ritual marking is often managed and celebrated in complex
calendrics that presume that people’s trajectories intersect, and often
apprehend and anticipate the possibility—day to day, or eventually at the
end of time—intervention by non–human beings, whether spiritual enti-
ties or an all-present God. Probably only a fundamentalist faith in sover-
eignty of some kind—either “everything happens for a (divine) reason,”
or “the individual is master of his fate”—could remove all cultural and
political framing of T1 and T2. Prospective imagination, in both cases, may
invoke fate: “what will be, will be,” and individuated responsibility. The pas-
sage of time itself, then, is so imbued with propositions of agency that its
study can show the full range of the beings that are accorded, or deprived
of, agency, and their mutuality of accompaniment, interruption, support.
and failure.
The anthropological study of how T1 and T2 are mutually entailed is
implicit in the ethnography of moments of convergence, such as the ritual-
ized performances of the life cycle through which a person, him/herself,
is transformed. Certain entailments of personhood in a past stage of life
are abrogated, and new capacities are crafted into the enactment of social
and ethical life for the next phase. In western law, by contrast, a person
is defined as a child, a juvenile, or an adult on abstract calendrical time
rather than social and biological time. For the ethnographic examination
of agency, we first establish the parameters for personhood, and then turn
to their implications for the T1/T2 mutual entailments among people.
General ethical precepts may be explicitly evoked to make things work and
to sanction people’s failures, but for us to examine the distributed agency
question closely, full immersion in the temporal process itself is required,
with respect to what I have termed “durational ethics” (Guyer 2014).
Commitment. Promise. Responsibility. Perseverance, that is, Fortitude,
in classic Christian thought. Fortitude is one of the four cardinal virtues,
alongside Prudence, Justice, and Temperance, without which these other
three are impossible to realize.
By requiring a person to take on durational ethics, he/she creates an
entailment between the T1 in which he or she is now living and the T2 when
the agency will be fulfilled. A promise usually refers only to the two moments
that are explicitly named, whereas a commitment or responsibility may be
in play all the time, between any two moments. Parental responsibility for a
child’s safety is continual, not intermittent. In popular practice, both nec-
essarily assume processes that continue alongside, and contribute to, real-
ization: the durational cycles of life, the knowledge that others have taken
on comparable commitments, under known material circumstances, and
that the gods are still in the heavens. I may be accountable individually, but
the place of others in “aiding and abetting,” or “confounding” is always in
the picture, in ways that vary by culture and philosophy. In a sense, distrib-
uted agency is the common-╉sense philosophy of most, if not all, durational
ethics. That I can repay my debts depends on you fulfilling your promises to
me, which you may neglect due to moral lapse or you may simply be unable,
due to illness or other unforeseen demands. Do I make generous allow-
ances for your difficulties? Do I explain them to my own creditor? Where
does the responsibility rest: on those who seek for a narrow definition of
contractual justice, or on those whose behavior most affects social har-
mony at large? By being aware of philosophies of distributed agency with
respect to the temporality of debts, we may then focus on the history of
the modern measures to shear off popular legacies of distributed agency, in
order to produce a sparse definition and legal precision: individuals make
choices, in neutral time, for which they are solely responsible.
Di s t r i b u t ed Ag e n c y a n d De b t â•… [â•›103â•›]
104
Di s t r i b u t ed Ag e n c y a n d De b t [ 105 ]
106
closest focus is on the process of living in this debt regime. In nuanced and
particular accounts, she shows how the temporality of debt increasingly
fails to inter-╉digitate smoothly with the other temporalities of life. Indeed,
its shaping power at T1, and its insistent threat of inflexibility at T2,
actively disorganize relationships that unfold on another durational ethic.
“The self is simultaneously enmeshed in different relations that entail dif-
ferent demands and desires” (Han 2012:20). “Monthly debt payments took
up half of Rodrigo’s income” (36), and bus fare to his job took up one-╉third
of his income (38). And “this ‘made time’ rubbed against the temporal-
ity of monthly debt payments and the uncertainty of unstable wages that
impinged on the home” (38). Regular commitments to children became dis-
rupted: “You need to buy gifts for children” (49); the children don’t under-
stand debt. In our own terms here, this would imply that accountability for
failure could be attributed by children to their parents, even when adults
would see the fault elsewhere. Clearly the conditions of an inflexible debt
version of T1 and T2 are incompatible with the temporalities of commit-
ment in the current economy and in other domains of durational ethics, as
understood by other participants in the nexus. The mutual implication of
intimate lives is a key theme of this ethnography of debt in a world where
different parties, different dimensions of life, different projections of what
counts as T1 and T2, are examined in detail.
These two works show clearly how the specific distribution of agency
is defined and shaped by different parties, living different temporalities
and different durational ethics, in relation to regimes of “modern time.”
Both call attention to temporal phenomena as the ground on which agency
and responsibility are built. As Augé argued for places, so also for tempo-
ralities: “Modernity does not obliterate them but pushes them into the
background”: they “survive like the words that express them” (1995:77),
“intertwine[d]â•„and tangle[d]” together (1995:107). With respect to debt
regimes, the word “tangled” can be literally true rather than a meta-
phor: debts that are modeled in modernist time tie them in knots when
it comes to living with their own conditions and the durational ethics of
distributed agency and responsibility.
REFERENCES
Amato, Massimo, and Luca Fantacci. 2011. The End of Finance. Cambridge,
UK: Polity Press.
Augé, Marc. 1995. Non-╉Places: Introduction to an Anthropology of Supermodernity.
London: Verso.
Di s t r i b u t ed Ag e n c y a n d De b t [ 107 ]
109
CHAPTER 12
M oney has always had agency, or, rather, has been an expression of
agency, or even is agency itself, or … well, this is precisely the prob-
lem of money.
People have certainly imagined money objects to possess agency. Who
among us has not thrown a coin into a fountain or picked one up imagin-
ing it would bring us luck, would change our destiny? Eighteenth-century
English tracts on money, somewhere between didactic pamphlets and the
early serialized novel, imbued both notes and coins with the ability to wit-
ness the affairs of humans around them, and to remark on questions of
morality and social order as they were passed from hand to hand—unless,
unfortunates, they ended up in someone’s safe, or misplaced somewhere.
Saved or lost money lost its powers of action and narration. Money in cir-
culation, even counterfeit, chronicled the world of men and women, boys
and girls, from every station of life and every corner of the world. And
seemed to enjoy doing so, too.
In telling their tales, these coins and notes reflected upon the economies
of which they were a part and which they were creating in their travels.
They served as a distributed, collective memory bank, to use Keith Hart’s
(2000) phrase, each note or coin testifying to its transit during human
exchange and, in the process, forming a collectivity having the potential
to record all of human intercourse—or at least those aspects of it in which
money was quite literally brought to bear. Money was not inert but nor was
110
do what it will, whatever people will do with it, from underground to dark
economies, to adornment and decoration and magic tricks. Private or pub-
lic credit, money is regardless a record of all manner of relationships of
credit and debt across time and space, and not just economic relationships
of credit and debt.
In arguing that money is a “means of collective memory,” a distributed
record of all human intercourse, Hart (2005) implicitly poses the question
of the relationship between those records and the infrastructures that pro-
duce and maintain them. It is not just cash circulating hand to hand that
constitutes this great database; it is also all the systems for transferring
money, recording those transfers, and creating great globally expansive
ledgers into which human collectivity finds a kind of rhetorical and mathe-
matical expression. This is the matter of money that matters, and the sense
in which that matter matters: it affords a carriage across space-time and
between other agents. Hart wondered whether the infrastructures—the
internet, the electronic payment card networks like Visa and MasterCard—
could be seized for “human,” rather than simply corporate, purposes. Could
they be decentralized rather than held in walled gardens, shared with the
many whose everyday economic activity made them repositories of collec-
tive memory in the first place rather than enclosed for the profit of the few?
Early 21st-century experiments with digital currencies like Bitcoin
respond to this challenge, despite the at times incoherent perspective on
money they evince (Maurer, Nelms, and Swartz 2013). The center of the
confusion is whether people understand, and then seek to create, money
as “cash-based” or “ledger-based.” For central banks, this is a primary
preoccupation, since money in circulation and money on the books must
be measured if the bank is to intervene in monetary affairs: cash money
has to be ledgered. Eduard de Jong (2014), a pioneer in the development
of digital currency systems—and the toll road payment network for the
Netherlands!—uses these terms to distinguish between moneys that are
emitted by a central source and then embedded in objects that leave no
record of their passage from one agent to another, and moneys that by
design record their passage in a database, the authority of which all accept.
For a toll road, you might want what de Jong calls a cash-based system,
if you are worried about the prying eyes of the state into your travels, or
you just didn’t care about the massive amounts of data generated at the
toll booth about people’s comings and goings every day, day after day, on
their regular commutes. In such a system of value embedded in token,
however, people can pour too much power into the money object. Some
Bitcoin proponents thus evince a kind of digital metallism, imagining that
the value of the bits in Bitcoin derives wholly from their scarcity, a scarcity
M o n e y a s T ok e n a n d M o n e y a s Re c or d [ 111 ]
112
built into the design. With the latter, the ledger-based system, people pon-
der whether the database must be centralized for it to have its authority.
Must it be maintained and verified by a trusted, or simply overwhelmingly
powerful, third party—a temple, a corporation, a notary, a government?
Or can there be a democratically decentralized database, owned by none or
owned by all, without the intercession of any scribes, bookkeepers, banks,
or governments? Just how far can the distribution of agency go?
Bitcoin and other so-called cryptocurrency experiments rely on the
existing network infrastructures of the internet and the electrical grid.
On top of those systems—which are more or less centralized, depending
on how you look at it—Bitcoin creates a database. This database has a spe-
cific structure. Imagine a great ledger book. Imagine further that every-
one—everyone!—has a copy of that ledger. Anyone can make an entry
of a debit or credit into that ledger. I credit you, while debiting myself.
But then everyone has the opportunity to verify that entry (though not
everyone does). Those who do the work of authenticating transactions
are rewarded with a new credit line in the ledger. They can also levy a fee,
in the form of an additional incremental credit, for their work of verifi-
cation. A verified set of transactions—a complete ledger page—is called
a block. The entire database is called the blockchain, a chain of groups
of verified transactions. A great database, distributed among all partici-
pants, public yet pseudonymous, written by the collective, collaborative
and competitive effort of the participants in the system. A Visa network
without Visa, banks, or the government. Just computers and people (and
electricity … and the internet). At least, this is the theory, anyway.
In one of the 18th-century money narratives, money objects possess
distinct agencies, and multiple agencies within themselves, too, which the
money objects can send out of their bodies and into the world, and into
other bodies. In one story, a coin, an Indian gold rupee, describes itself
as having multiple spirits, though it names only three. They are Ductility,
Malleability, and Fusibility. “Men have foolishly called them qualities,” he
says (Scott 1782, in Bellamy 2012:36). But they are not qualities, in the
conventional sense of the term. They are different aspects or externaliza-
tions of its core self: agents. They are also among the properties of pre-
cious metal that Enlightenment philosophers and, earlier, the Greeks had
imagined to be perfectly suited to serve as money. But the story suggests
that what matters is not their matter in itself but the agency the qualia
afford, to carry value across time and space and between persons. They are
also infrastructure, then—something that transports or transmits other
things. Again, this is the sense in which the matter of money matters—it
bestows the ability to act over distances, but it does not possess by virtue
of those qualities any intrinsic value in itself.
The rupee is able to dispatch its spirits and send them into people’s
minds, or, more precisely, into their brains. There, the spirits can peer into
a person’s history by reading the literal inscriptions on a specific region
of the brain where memories are recorded. Or, not memories exactly: the
word our rupee uses is transactions:
One of my subordinate spirits immediately mounted his cella turcica [the struc-
ture in the skull holding the pituitary gland] by my command, from which spot
the brain above may be seen marked with impressions, like figures on a celestial
globe. These impressions are nothing but the scratches made by objects which
have been presented to the senses, and of which memory makes use in her oper-
ations. By reading these, we can discover all the transactions of any consequence
in which a man has been engaged. (Scott 1782, in Bellamy 2012:51)
M o n e y a s T ok e n a n d M o n e y a s Re c or d [ 113 ]
114
ACKNOWLEDGMENTS
I would like to thank Geoffrey Bowker for bringing the Indian rupee tale
to my attention. I would also like to thank Lana Swartz, Taylor C. Nelms,
and Scott Mainwaring for many productive hours and days of fieldwork,
conversation, writing, and thinking together. Mrinalini Tankha, Ursula
Dalinghaus, and Nathan Coben offered helpful criticism and advice, as did
Paul Kockelman. Research in the payments industry has been supported by
the US National Science Foundation (SES 0960423 and SES 1455859). The
opinions presented here are the author’s own and do not reflect those of
the National Science Foundation or any other organization.
REFERENCES
M o n e y a s T ok e n a n d M o n e y a s Re c or d [ 115 ]
116
PART FIVE
CHAPTER 13
1. The body (or body part) and the self are constructed as agents separate
to one another, disaggregated, capable of “independently”: acting one
upon the other.
2. The self and body (or body part) are constructed as connected: with the
self possessing the body or body part and having an associated control,
flexibility, and accountability for bodily actions.
3. The self and body are constructed as one and the same entity and
agent: an integrated, accountable, flexible individual.
• Ways that body parts get referred to: whether, for example, we refer to
the thumb, or to your or my thumb.
• What we put in the subject and object position of our utterances: for
example, whether I say that I do something, or that my leg does
something.
• Eye gaze—through which we can show ourselves to be talking to a part
of our interlocutor’s body—and thus separating it out from a larger
whole. Conversely, we can show that we are talking to the “inner” or
whole person by looking him or her in the eye.
• Meanings (i.e., semantics) and metaphors that provide for different con-
figurations of the person, body, and self.
It’s worth briefly mentioning that the first practice is available in English
but not in all languages—although it seems likely that in different lan-
guages, other practices are available to do the same kind of work. It is also
worth noticing that these configurations have a dualist character, some-
thing I will consider as I go along.
As well as describing how people manage to construct different body/
self configurations, I examine when and why they do so. In the context
of this book, it should come as no surprise that this has to do with
how humans attribute and convey capacity and responsibility for their
actions, failings, and endeavors. In a final section, I outline some impli-
cations for how we understand and conceptualize distributed agency,
and consider how the dualist character of personhood so prevalent in
our talk makes sense in social terms. That is, whatever the material
discoveries of neuropsychology, and their echoes in linguistic under-
standings of inalienable possession (Kockelman 2007b), I am going to
show you that when we talk and interact with one another, we do and
we can make self and body more, less, or completely—for all practical
purposes—separate.
First though, I need to attend to two terminology issues. Frustratingly
for me, English does not currently provide a word that signifies, exclu-
sively, the particular part or aspect of a person that is other than the per-
son’s body. Soul might once have been used, but has lost some of its value
in the context of current understandings that brain, consciousness, and
body are utterly intertwined in physical terms. In this piece though, I need
Di s t r i b u t i o n of A g e n c y a c r o s s B o d y a n d Se l f â•… [â•›121â•›]
122
As she continues her description (line 3), the therapist uses another
means to separate or distance the self of the patient and his pelvis. The
subject/object arrangement is different, the patient—you—is now the sub-
ject and thus agent over the shoulders. The distancing here is done through
the pronoun the. In extracts to follow, I will demonstrate and examine how
people recurrently use impersonals such as the, this, or a when naming a
body part, and the way that this distances the body part from the self.
Why do people talk in ways that distance, disaggregate a self and their
body (or body parts)? Recurrently, as above, they do so when referring to
something that is a problem—an undesirable physical state or movement.
By talking in a way that makes the body part a separate agent acting on the
self, or in a way that avoids using possessives such as my or your, one can
camouflage the connection—sometimes referred to as “inalienable posses-
sion”—between the person whose physical state is referred to and his or
her body/part. One thereby implies that the person neither controls, nor
bears accountability, fault, and responsibility for the undesirable bodily
state or action. One can sever, so to speak, the connection—physically as
much as psychologically.
The next case once again illustrates use of the rather than your, and also
introduces another way people can do this disaggregation: through their
gaze patterning.
When giving instructions (lines 1, 3, 4), the therapist looks to the back of
the patient’s hips. She moves on to give a reason for her “this one especially”
instruction (lines 6, 8). By the time she starts this talk about a reason, she
has shifted her body enough to allow her to direct her gaze to the patient’s
face and make eye contact. Through this conduct, the therapist treats the
patient’s body and self as separate agents: the body as agent of the physical
action, and the self—or consciousness—as agent with regard to hearing
and understanding a reason for the action. This gaze patterning is recur-
rent in the physical therapy data (Parry 2013), with therapists using their
gaze and associated body positioning in a way that disaggregates patients’
body parts from their reasoning minds—their selves. As noted, this case
also features use of an impersonal pronoun: the therapist talks of this right
one, not your right one (line 6). This brings us neatly to case 3, in which an
impersonal pronoun the, and the personal pronoun your, are used in rapid
succession.
Di s t r i b u t i o n of A g e n c y ac r o s s B o d y a n d Se l f [ 123 ]
124
6 T: Now
7 (0.4)
8 T: ‘S not bad
9 (0.6)
10 T: ‘Part from, part from the thumb it’s fine Andrew
11 (0.2)
12 T: And can you take your hand away from my hand?
13 (1.9)
14 T: See if you can try again but making more
15 of a space for your thumb.
16 (2.4)
17 T: Yeah. That’s-that feels-that feels better to me.
18 P: I got the thumb splint.
19 (0.7)
20 T: Yeah, and whe-how long are you wearing that for.
The therapist says the thumb (line 10) when your thumb would be equally
grammatical, and in a context where it is perfectly clear which of his two
thumbs she is referring to. As in the other cases, she does this when referring
to a physical shortcoming. The thumb is, for all practical purposes, conveyed
as a separate entity at this point: the patient’s self and thumb are disaggre-
gated, and this reduces the implication that he is responsible or accountable
for the physical failure being talked of. This case also illustrates a counter-
part: when she moves into instructions the therapist says, can you take your
hand away and [make] more of a space for your thumb. By using your at this junc-
ture, she foregrounds the patient’s connection with—in other words, his con-
trol over—his hand and thumb. So now, the thumb is portrayed as under the
patient’s control.
In the physical therapy recordings, both therapists and patients fre-
quently use possessives in situations where controlled, purposeful action
is talked about and/or encouraged. Using your or my (when alternatives are
possible) treats self and body as connected, and people do so when there is
good reason to emphasize someone’s control, responsibility, and physical
agency in relation to their body.
The rapidity with which one can move between different configurations of
the body/self/person relationship is particularly evident in this case, as is
the fact that in doing so, a speaker does not need to do anything extra as it
were—one does not need to provide talk that, for instance, cancels out an
earlier meaning or gives some reason for the change.
At line 2, the therapist’s it refers to the patient’s left knee and leg. Her talk
ascribes this as the entity that collapsed. When she describes the recent
successful controlled performance of the exercise, the patient and her body
are construed as a single unified agent: you. The therapist is thereby able to
praise the patient and treat her as responsible for the success.
A series of shorter cases now supplement the detailed analysis above by
demonstrating that not just therapists but also patients construct different
body/self configurations via the same resources; also that the same kind
of phenomena arise in other healthcare settings and in informal conversa-
tions between friends.
Di s t r i b u t i o n of A g e n c y ac r o s s B o d y a n d Se l f [ 125 ]
126
Here the patient makes my brain the subject of his talk, and his left side the
object. This subject/object arrangement has parallels to case 1, in which
the therapist’s talk constructed the patient’s pelvis as an agent that was
making the patient rounded. There are differences though: rather than self
and body part, the patient disaggregates two body parts: brain and left
side. Nevertheless, it is reasonable to hear him treating my brain as in some
sense his controlling self, and the left side as separate to this brain/self.
Here, the patient uses both an impersonal pronoun, a, and a verb phrase
that I can’t get well. These work to disaggregate her self, as an agent, from
her foot—upon which she has been attempting to act.
Emma switches from the personal my toenails (line 1), to the imper-
sonal those (line 2) in the context of escalating from “terrible” to nau-
seating. She also moves from describing a situation—it’s terrible—to
conveying what she sees as she looks at those big toenails. The imper-
sonal pronoun those adds to the conveyed sense of an external view. By
line 6, she reaches a further configuration: her whole self is conveyed
as ossified.
Di s t r i b u t i o n of A g e n c y ac r o s s B o d y a n d Se l f [ 127 ]
128
Erma builds a sense of connection but also a distinction between the inner,
private Ilene (behind her—╉line 6) and Ilene’s physical aspect—╉gorgeous
eyes, and a pretty face. This sense is built both through the design of her
description—╉Ilene has physical attributes, and the semantic and meta-
phoric use of prepositions to indicate this character of selfhood.
CONCLUSIONS
People can allocate to the body, or parts thereof, agency that is more or less
separate from the agency of the self. In our social lives at least, while the
body and self can be a unified and fused entity, the body and self can also
be disaggregated, fissioned, divided. That is, in our interactions, we commit
to a form of dualism. This is not a strict “here is body, there is mind” type
of dualism, but rather a continuum that can be cut in a variety of places.
We commit to this form of dualism as a way of understanding ourselves,
our personhood. This enables us to manipulate—╉to shape—╉the meaning
of our own, and other people’s, physical successes, failures, and features.
As I have shown above, these kinds of allocation of agency are accom-
plished via rather basic design features of body movement and talk, includ-
ing gaze, and grammatical and semantic resources. Through the meanings
we thereby build, we can encourage others to hear matters of fault, respon-
sibility, endeavor, and achievement with regard the physical as more or less
attributable to the body or body part, or to the “true,” “inner” self (the
soul, or even the brain). It is noticeable that the more distancing configu-
rations are noticeably charitable—╉we might even say compassionate; the
person talking can absolve the person/╉self being talked about. Being able
to allocate responsibility and even blame for physical problems to the body
(and therefore as less—╉or even not at all—╉the actual person’s fault) helps
us to limit negative emotional and relationship consequences of criticizing
or blaming another’s physical state or behavior. Conversely, being able to
convey that positive performances and attributes are integral to the person
him-╉or herself allows us to emphasize that person’s personal competence,
and thus praise, motivate, and encourage him or her, facilitating align-
ment in terms of both local actions and the ongoing sense of relationship
between the people involved.
My analysis has shown that people locally constitute agency and rela-
tions between selves and bodies in a moment to moment way that is fitted
to social circumstances and also highly flexible. Previous research that has
shown that the way one refers to another person is not random; rather, it
does work—╉it performs social actions—╉such as conveying another person
as more or less close to the speaker (Enfield and Stivers 2007; Stivers 2007).
My analysis shows that the way we refer to our bodies and our selves is also
not a random or haphazard matter, but a socially shaped means of working
up distinct embodied identities fitted to interpersonal circumstances and
relationships. Finally, the evidence I have presented shows that in order to
understand fully the distribution of agency, we need not only to recognize
the ways and means through which it can be distributed, fissioned, and
fused “across and among individuals” (Enfield 2013:104), but also to add
the recognition that people also distribute agency within individuals.
REFERENCES
Enfield, N. J. 2013. Relationship Thinking: Enchrony, Agency, and Human Sociality. New
York: Oxford University Press.
Enfield, N. J., and T. Stivers. 2007. Person Reference in Interaction: Linguistic, Cultural,
and Social Perspectives. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
Kockelman, P., 2007a. “Agency.” Current Anthropology 48(3): 375–╉401.
Kockelman, P. 2007b. “Inalienable Possession and Personhood in a Q’eqchi’-╉Mayan
Community.” Language in Society 36(3): 343–╉369.
Parry, Ruth H. 2013. “Giving Reasons for Doing Something Now or at Some Other
Time.” Research on Language & Social Interaction 46(2): 105–╉124.
Stivers, T. 2007. “Alternative Recognitionals in Person Reference.” In Person Reference
in Interaction—╉Linguistic, Cultural and Social Perspectives, edited by N. J. Enfield
and T. Stivers, 73–╉96. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
Di s t r i b u t i o n of A g e n c y a c r o s s B o d y a n d Se l f â•… [â•›129â•›]
131
CHAPTER 14
(a) (b)
Food Food
Nest Nest
Figure 14.1 A colony of Argentine ants selecting the branches of a bridge between the nest
and the food area: (a) four minutes after the placement of the bridge ants choose branches
randomly; (b) eight minutes after the placement of the bridge ants choose the shortest
route between the nest and the food.
(Modified from Gross et al. 1989)
Di s t r i b u t ed Ag e n c y i n A n t s [ 133 ]
134
trail pheromone both when leaving and when returning to the nest. At the
beginning of the experiment, explorer ants use both branches randomly
(Figure 14.1a); however, after a few minutes, additional ants are recruited
to the food source and the shortest route is suddenly selected by the vast
majority of ants (Figure 14.1b).
How is this possible? Each ant leaves a pheromone mark both ways (from
and to the nest); ants that take the shortest route arrive earlier to the food
and come back earlier to the nest, compared to ants that take the longest
route. Therefore, it takes less time to the shortest branch to be marked by
an increasing amount of pheromone left by the ants. The chemical signal
on the shortest route will be amplified quicker and, as a consequence, more
and more ants will be recruited on this shortest route. It is a simple positive
feedback mechanism based on an indirect communication between nest-
mate ants (via the trail pheromone), which results in an intelligent collective
decision. This is a relatively flexible, context-dependent, adaptive solution.
In such cooperative tasks based on self-organized processes, the agency
is totally distributed and gives rise to an emergent phenomenon: the sud-
den collective choice of the shortest path from the nest to the food. In this
process, each individual ant has very little flexibility, particularly because the
response to pheromones is typically “hardwired” (so-called innate). An ant
has no other choice than responding to the highest concentration of pher-
omone, and therefore she will follow the path that has been marked more
heavily by her nestmates. This lack of flexibility results in little accountabil-
ity. It might well be that there is individual variation among the various ants,
with some individuals being, for instance, less sensitive to the trail phero-
mone and thus not able to perceive the difference in concentration between
the two trails when this difference is still small. These individuals may choose
the long path when the majority of ants go for the short path. Nevertheless,
the ants on the short path will continue being faster in coming back to the
nest, and soon the pheromone trail will reach a concentration that will be
attractive to every ant. In a cooperative collective task, it does not matter
if few individuals do not participate: the system is automatically buffered.
Indeed, there are usually more ants coming to a food source than the number
required to bring that particular amount of food back to the nest.
In a social group characterized by extreme cooperation, agency is distrib-
uted beyond the individuals (the single units forming the group) and there
is a very low individual level of flexibility and accountability. Ants, and other
social insects, are a paramount example of distributed agency because they
pushed the division of labor to its extreme form: the partitioning of repro-
duction. In many ant species, such as the Argentine ant, workers are totally
sterile and the only way they can pass on their genes to the next generation
(a) (b)
100
90
80
Observed
Number of workers
70
60
50
Police force
40 Expected
30
20
10
0
0 1 2 3 4 5 6 7 8 9 10 11 12 13 14
Number of aggressive policing acts per worker
Di s t r i b u t ed Ag e n c y i n A n t s [ 135 ]
136
policing workers act for the collective interest of the workers as a whole
(the colony) and they are not moved by selfish benefits since none of the
policing workers showed developed ovaries, suggesting that they do not
kill other workers’ eggs or attack reproductive workers (so that they cannot
reproduce) to be able to reproduce themselves.
This ant example shows that when individual units are allowed some
degree of flexibility (e.g., the possibility to develop ovaries), they might
attempt to act in their best selfish interest (e.g., by reproducing), but they
are held accountable for their behavior and therefore punished by other
members of the community. When the risk of destabilization is high—╉if
many workers reproduce, the colony as a whole would collapse—╉societies
should evolve specialized units (e.g., the ant policing force) to restore and
maintain social cooperation. Coercion, defined as a social pressure in the
form of punishment of group members to prevent them from acting self-
ishly and thereby harming the group as a whole, has been described in a
variety of species, including humans (review in Ratnieks and Wenseelers
2008). Indeed, levels of cooperation across human societies are correlated
with the degree to which uncooperative individuals are punished (Henrich
et al. 2006), suggesting that coercion plays a key role in the evolution and
maintenance of cooperative systems.
In conclusion, I argue that when individual units of a social group are
prevented from acting selfishly by drastically reducing their flexibility,
agency becomes better distributed and individual units cannot be consid-
ered accountable for their behavior. On the other hand, when some flex-
ibility is retained in a cooperative system, individual units may pursue their
direct benefits and cause a “tragedy of the commons.” Cooperative systems
that have survived natural selection are likely those that have found effec-
tive strategies to make individuals accountable for their behavior, thus
enforcing cooperation. The more sophisticated the social organization, the
higher the level of cooperation, the wealthier the common good, and the
more specialized the retaliation system against free riders should be. Some
ant species have solved the problem by evolving individual units that are
totally sterile and act as cells in a body. As a consequence, flexibility was
obliterated, giving rise to completely distributed agency.
ACKNOWLEDGMENTS
Many thanks to the editors N. J. Enfield and P. Kockelman for having
invited me to join this project and for their insightful comments on a pre-
vious version of the manuscript.
REFERENCES
Di s t r i b u t ed Ag e n c y i n A n t s â•… [â•›137â•›]
139
PART SIX
CHAPTER 15
INTRODUCTION
SOCIAL HIGH
SOCIAL SYNC
Sports and exercise in group settings typically entail the tight coordina-
tion of bodies and minds in time in space, both intra-and interpersonally.
Coordinated, synchronous behavior with others in ritual, dance, singing,
and drill has long been thought to enhance social solidarity (e.g., Durkheim
2012), and similar effects may be integral to the most intimate human
activities (e.g., in mother-infant interaction, lovemaking). Experimental
G r o u p E x e r c i s e a n d S o c i a l B o n di n g [ 143 ]
144
evidence shows that synchronous marching, singing, and even simple fin-
ger tapping significantly increase cohesion, liking, affiliation, perceived
similarity, and generosity among participants. In a seminal study on syn-
chrony and cooperation, Wiltermuth and Heath (2009) found that people
who marched and sang with one another under controlled experimental
conditions cooperated more in subsequent economic exercises than those
who participated in similar, non-synchronous activities.
This interpersonal synchrony effect is thought to derive in part from the
tight attentional union that occurs between individuals when they match
the content and timing of their actions. By performing the same action at
the same time, interpersonal similarity is enhanced and self-other bound-
aries become blurred in action processing and recall. In a recent study by
Miles et al. (2010), pairs of participants were instructed to sit opposite one
another and perform arm-curling movements while alternately pronounc-
ing aloud a series of country names that were played through personal
headphones. They were then individually asked to identify who had said
which country names. When participants had performed the same arm-
curl movements in synchrony with one another, their recall accuracy for
who had said what was significantly poorer than when they had performed
the same movements in anti-phase synchrony (i.e., when participants
raised and lowered arms in opposite alternating order). The self-memory
advantage that strangers normally exhibit in such tasks was eliminated
via a simple and subtle behavioral synchrony intervention that appears to
have shifted participants’ attentional focus from self to other. This effect
on memory was similar to that commonly observed among people who
have long-standing interpersonal connections.
Self-other blurring may be central to the “magnifying” effect described
by the team rower in the anecdote at the beginning of this chapter. In expe-
rienced crews, all oars touch and exit the water at the same precise instant.
Multiple bodies—legs, backs, arms, and wrists—bend in perfect unison
to generate a singular force propelling the boat forward. In this moment,
crew members’ relative efforts and effects on the boat they all occupy are
individually indistinguishable. The resultant blurring of self-other bound-
aries potentially generates a physical-proprioceptive illusion that one’s
own effort and output are exponentially magnified. This sensation, in turn,
appears to give rise to unique psychological states variously described
by those who have experienced them as “pure pleasure” and “exultation”
(Brown 2013: 161, 269).
It is unlikely that all group exercise activities achieve these psycho-
logical effects to the same degree, or that they are associated with such
intense psychological reward. Indeed, long and hard hours of training are
SOCIAL DRIVE
G r o u p E x e r c i s e a n d S o c i a l B o n di n g [ 145 ]
146
SOCIAL BOOST
Participants in sports and exercise often experience pain, stress, and physi-
cal discomfort in the pursuit of their goals. In many competitive sports, the
person or team who can go harder, faster, and longer, conquering fatigue
G r o u p E x e r c i s e a n d S o c i a l B o n di n g [ 147 ]
148
CONCLUSION
NOTE
1.
http://╉usatoday30.usatoday.com/╉educate/╉college/╉careers/╉hottopic7.htm,
accessed October 11, 2014.
REFERENCES
G r o u p E x e r c i s e a n d S o c i a l B o n di n g â•… [â•›149â•›]
150
CHAPTER 16
INTRODUCTION: SOCIAL GROUPS
S o c i a l B o n di n g T h r o u g h Da n c e a n d ‘ M u s i k i n g ’ â•… [â•›153â•›]
154
Music adds to the social bonding effects that can arise in situations of group
coordination in various ways. First, people spontaneously synchronize to
music (Janata et al. 2012), and as a consequence music encourages and
facilitates occurrences of synchrony. People naturally entrain to a rhythmic
beat embedded in music, and are capable of doing so from a very young age
(discussed in more detail in Koelsch 2014). Music can therefore establish a
shared and predictable, rhythmic scaffolding, thereby facilitating synchro-
nization of timing between multiple individuals. In large groups, it is dif-
ficult to coordinate synchrony and observe the movements of all the other
participants simultaneously, arguably making “self-╉other” merging a less
likely prospect. Rhythmic music can facilitate synchrony for large numbers
of people, perhaps by providing a central “other” to which each participant
can direct their attention (e.g., drill marching), thereby leading to the social
closeness described above.
Indeed, synchrony with music itself appears to improve interpersonal
affiliation. Demos et al. (2012) found that participants who performed a
chair-╉rocking task to music reported feeling more connected to each other
than those who performed the task without background music. This inter-
personal connectedness was predicted by synchrony with the music, and
not by synchrony with one another. Accordingly this study suggests that
synchrony to music is sufficient to cause bonding effects, and synchrony
between people may be irrelevant when they are engaging with a shared
external source of rhythm as provided by the music.
But the effects of music go beyond its capacity for facilitating synchro-
nous movement. In addition to the predictability provided by a rhythmic
beat, listening to music induces strong emotional and pleasurable effects.
These arise via core brain regions generally involved in processing affect
(including areas that are responsible for releasing endorphins), and those
S o c i a l B o n di n g T h r o u g h Da n c e a n d ‘ M u s i k i n g ’ â•… [â•›155â•›]
156
the musical stimuli. Indeed, in many cultures, music and dance are consid-
ered indistinguishable and some languages do not have separate words to
describe them (Blacking 1995).
This close link between movement and music fits with Christopher
Small’s term “musiking,” defined as “[taking] part, in any capacity, in a
musical performance, whether by performing, by listening, by rehearsing
or practicing, by providing material for performance (what is called com-
posing), or by dancing” (Small 1998:9). Given that dance most likely co-
evolved with music as a means of generating rhythm and sound (Cummins,
2009), it is understandable that music tends to make us want to move,
and specifically synchronize, with the musical beat. In matching our move-
ments in time to a musical rhythm, we are simulating the timing of move-
ments that could have conceivably contributed toward the production of
that rhythmic beat.
The ability to have agency over the production of musical sounds
through movement has been shown to have significant physiological and
psychological effects. For example, varying the degree of musical agency for
people exercising in a group can influence their ability to perform strenu-
ous exercise and their mood. In a high agency condition, exercise machines
were linked to musical output software such that a musical sound resulted
from each movement, and consequently individuals “created” music as
they exerted themselves (Fritz et al. 2013). This experiment (and others
by the same authors) demonstrated that when movement (during group
exercise) results in musical feedback, participants perceived exertion to be
lower, reported enhanced mood, and felt a greater desire to exert them-
selves further, in comparison to when they were exercising while listening
(passively) to independently provided music not connected to their move-
ments (Fritz et al. 2013). According to these results, musical agency (i.e.,
executing purposeful movement that results in musical sounds) feels good
and improves the capacity to withstand strenuous exercise.
Although the exercise scenario described above is clearly a contrived case
of musical agency, the findings likely reflect the fact that we are wired to
engage with music in a context in which we do in fact have agency over the
production of sound. In reality, unless we are a member of a band or play
a musical instrument, we more frequently engage passively with music,
which rarely involves a context in which our movements directly contrib-
ute to the music. We frequently enjoy prerecorded music, which involves
a decoupling of our engagement with that music from the social context
and movement evident at its source. Under these modern circumstances,
and in the absence of having any of our music-induced movements actually
result in some direct contribution to the music, perhaps when we move
CONCLUSION
REFERENCES
S o c i a l B o n di n g T h r o u g h Da n c e a n d ‘ M u s i k i n g ’ â•… [â•›157â•›]
158
PART SEVEN
CHAPTER 17
Timescales for Understanding
the Agency of Infants and Caregivers
JOANNA R ĄCZA SZEK-L EONARDI
THE PROBLEM
TIMESCALES FOR AGENCY
So let us look at an episode like the one mentioned above more closely.
Here I describe in detail an interaction from the corpus of video data gath-
ered by Iris Nomikou and Katharina Rohlfing in Bielefeld (Nomikou and
Rohlfing 2011). This useful data set consists of a defined event (changing
the diaper) videotaped in 17 mother-infant pairs in natural settings (home)
longitudinally, at five time points between the third and eighth months
of the baby’s life (for more detailed analysis of these data from the point
of view of tuning attention for coaction and development of routines, see
Rączaszek-Leonardi, Nomikou, and Rohlfing 2013).
The interaction chosen for illustration involves a three-month-old baby
and his mother. The baby is lying on his back and the mother is going to
change his diaper. At one point the baby turns the head to the right, where,
approximately 7 centimeters from the baby’s face (probably much too close
for him to focus on), there is a colorful soft toy cube. The mother imme-
diately (within 1 second)1 shifts her gaze to the cube, at the same time
asking, “What is there?” Then, within the next second, she looks into the
baby’s eyes, repeating the question, but this time leaning over the baby. In
the meantime she is taking the diaper off, which eventually requires her to
move back to see what she is doing. However, with her words, in a steady
rhythm, she keeps the “topic” of the cube in focus, addressing the baby
T i m e s c a l e s i n A g e n c y of I n fa n t s a n d Ca r e g i v e r s [ 163 ]
164
T i m e s c a l e s i n A g e n c y of I n fa n t s a n d Ca r e g i v e r s [ 165 ]
166
In this small example I wanted to convey the intricacy of the mesh of indi-
vidual, social, and cultural factors and forces bearing on a simple movement
in an interaction. Let us return to the original question: Who moved the
object? The infant? The mother? An infant-╉mother interactive system? An
encultured and socialized infant-╉mother interactive system? The mother
did perform the decisive move, but her actions were evoked by a gaze of
a child and constrained by the ontogenetic process of tuning for coaction,
which, in turn, involves re-╉enacting cultural scripts. The re-╉enactment of
the cultural scripts does not necessitate planning and conscious action on
her part. Constrained by living in a particular culture, slowly and appropri-
ately for the infant’s age she brings up the child, through co-╉movement,
basing on biological adaptations, into a culturally established coaction.
Connected to the question of agency and equally important for this
volume is the question of accountability. The dynamic shifts in account-
ability for behavior as developmental and socialization processes progress
is a particularly interesting issue. It requires philosophical, moral, and cul-
tural level analyses that are far beyond the scope of this short contribution.
Yet the identification of the threads of agency, unfolding within multiple
systems and on multiple timescales, which help recognize the sources of
agency in a particular action, seem to be an important step in the analysis
of accountability.
Even though most cognitive psychology in the last five decades has
tended to neglect the slower scales, and systems larger than an individual,
obviously sciences such as sociology or anthropology never did. For them,
the points raised here may be rather banal: it is obvious that in every deed
we are constrained by our culture, shaped in development, and driven
by our social relations. Yet the notion of timescales and the methods of
dynamic systems give us tools and a framework within which studying
mutual dependencies among the systems and reciprocal causality between
levels can become easier.
NOTE
1. The times given here are approximate. It is sufficient for the illustrative purposes
of this paper. However in the investigations of the emergence of coaction
patterns within dynamical framework, recording the exact timing is crucial.
REFERENCES
Brooks, R., 1990. Elephants don’t play chess. Robotics and Autonomous Systems 6, 3–15.
Chomsky, N. 1980. Rules and Representations. Oxford, UK: Basil Blackwell.
Costall, A. 1995. “Socializing Affordances.” Theory and Psychology 5: 467–╉481.
Dumas, G., J. A. S. Kelso, and J. Nadel. 2014. “Tackling the Social Cognition Paradox
Through Multi-╉scale Approaches. Frontiers in Psychology 5: 882. doi: 10.3389/╉
fpsyg.2014.00882.
Enfield, N. J. 2014. Natural Causes of Language: Frames, Biases, and Cultural
Transmission. Berlin: Language Science Press.
Johnson, M. H., S. Dziurawiec, H. Ellis, H. and J. Morton. 1991. “Newborns’
Preferential Tracking of Face-╉like Stimuli and Its Subsequent Decline.”
Cognition 40: 1–╉19.
Kelso, J. A. S. 1995. Dynamic Patterns: The Self-╉Organization of Brain and Behavior.
Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.
Kirby, S., H. Cornish, and K. Smith. 2008. “Cumulative Cultural Evolution in
the Laboratory: An Experimental Approach to the Origins of Structure
in Human Language.” Proceedings of the National Academy of Sciences
105(31):10681–╉10686.
MacWhinney, B. 2005. “The Emergence of Linguistic Form in Time.” Connection
Science 17(3–╉4): 191–╉211.
Nomikou, I., and K. J. Rohlfing. 2011. “Language Does Something. Body Action
and Language in Maternal Input to Three-╉Month-╉Olds.” IEEE Transactions on
Autonomous Mental Development 3(2): 113–╉128.
Rączaszek-╉Leonardi, J. 2003. “The Interrelation of Time Scales in a Description of
Language.” Views & Voices 1(2): 93–╉108.
Rączaszek-╉Leonardi, J. 2009. “Symbols as Constraints: The Structuring Role of
Dynamics and Self-╉Organization in Natural Language.” Pragmatics and
Cognition 17(3), 653–╉676.
Rączaszek-╉Leonardi, J. 2010. “Multiple Time-╉scales of Language Dynamics: An
Example from Psycholinguistics.” Ecological Psychology 22(4): 269–╉285.
Rączaszek-╉Leonardi, J., I. Nomikou, K. J. Rohlfing. 2013. “Young Children’s Dialogical
Actions: The Beginnings of Purposeful Intersubjectivity.” IEEE Transactions in
Autonomous Mental Development 5(3): 210–╉221.
Smith, K., H. Brighton, and S. Kirby. 2003. “Complex Systems in Language
Evolution: The Cultural Emergence of Compositional Structure.” Advances in
Complex Systems 6(4): 537–╉558.
T i m e s c a l e s i n A g e n c y of I n fa n t s a n d Ca r e g i v e r s â•… [â•›167â•›]
╇ 169
CHAPTER 18
INTRODUCTION
S y n c h r o n y, J o i n t A c t i o n s , a n d Ag e n c y i n I n fa n c y [ 171 ]
172
Recall the example of a person reaching for the water bottle and the com-
mon inference that the person would be reaching for the bottle to drink
some water. There are, indeed, many other sub-╉goals involved in that
action: holding the water bottle, bringing it closer to one’s mouth, pouring
water into the mouth, so on and so forth. It seems, however, that the human
mind often ignores these middle steps in reading the behavior. Depending
on what that particular circumstance brings, we identify an ultimate inten-
tion behind the action being performed—╉for example, quenching thirst—╉
and focus on that instead. How, then, do infants understand the intentions
of agents? When and how does this understanding transform into infants’
sharing attention and engaging in joint actions with others?
Reading the intentions of others might be tricky, partly because differ-
ent intentions might motivate similar action-╉outcome sequences. Still, an
adult would hardly ever miss the difference between a person purposefully
throwing a water bottle on the floor and a person dropping it accidentally.
Similar comparisons were made to investigate infants’ understanding of
intentional and accidental actions. In one study, nine-╉month-╉old infants
interacted with an adult who was not giving them the toy that they wanted
(Behne, Carpenter, Call, and Tomasello 2005). Crucially, the adult was
either teasing the infants and was unwilling to give them the toy (inten-
tional action) or actually wanted to give them the toy but was unable to
do so due to clumsiness or other physical obstacles (accidental action).
Although the adult’s actions looked very similar in both conditions, infants
reacted with more frustration and impatience when the adult was unwill-
ing as opposed to unable to give them the toy. This indicates that at nine
months, infants understand the intentions of agents, even if the observed
actions and outcomes may look similar. This understanding influences the
infants’ emotional state and how they respond to the actor of the inten-
tional/╉accidental actions. Understanding others’ intentions is a crucial step
in starting to share intentions with others. Sharing intentions on objects
of mutual interest is what makes joint actions possible. Hence, a closer look
at infants’ developing abilities to share intention with others is important.
A well-╉studied method for sharing attention and intention with others
is using the pointing gesture. As soon as someone points to an object with
an index finger, most people automatically turn their heads and look at the
object being pointed out to. Although young infants may use the pointing
gesture merely to attract attention, a more advanced use of it is communi-
cative and involves the intention to share attention with others. At least
from 12 months of age, infants can use the pointing gesture for the lat-
ter purpose, for example, to inform adults of the locations of objects that
they have been looking for (Liszkowski, Carpenter, and Tomasello 2008).
A more detailed analysis further reveals a bidirectional developmental
pattern between infants’ comprehension and production of the pointing
gesture. From 8.5 months of age onward, those infants who comprehend
others’ pointing gestures as directed at objects also point themselves to
direct others’ attention to objects they find interesting (Woodward and
Guajardo 2002). This indicates that infants already start sharing atten-
tion before the age of one. This can be considered as a preliminary form
of joint action, where the infant and the adult act jointly, by looking in the
same direction and sharing the intention to attend to this object of mutual
interest.
More elaborate forms of joint actions are also observed within the first
year. They usually take place in infants’ interactions with their mothers as
they play together or engage in give-╉and-╉take type relations, such as when
a mother feeds her baby. One notable feature of these joint actions is the
high coordination observed among the interactants. Coordinating the tim-
ing of actions can ease attention sharing, action prediction, and thereby
expand the scope of joint actions the infants can perform (Reddy, Markova,
and Wallot 2013). In the following section, we will examine this issue more
closely to highlight the role of highly coordinated, synchronous move-
ments in infants’ joint actions.
Adding some more detail to our water bottle scenario, let us assume that
there is another individual, a baby, in the storyline, and that the person
reaching for the bottle is a mother who wanted to feed her baby. In this case,
the baby’s behaviors would suddenly be pivotal as well. It would be crucial
that the mother’s and the baby’s movements are well coordinated: the baby
should open his mouth as the mother reaches toward him, and the mother
should start the pouring action at the right time to avoid any accidents.
Although such precise coordination in movements might require highly
developed skills, infants and mothers do nevertheless coordinate their
behaviors with each other in various forms from very early on. Coordinated
interactions feed into children’s later abilities to work together with oth-
ers on a shared goal, communicate in socially acceptable ways, and develop
a sense of what is entailed in collective actions. Due to these significant
consequences on social development, coordinated interactions offer a
S y n c h r o n y, J o i n t A c t i o n s , a n d Ag e n c y i n I n f a n c y â•… [â•›173â•›]
174
in more elaborate joint action settings. One study has revealed that fol-
lowing a face-╉to-╉face bouncing phase with an adult, 14-╉month-╉old infants
helped the adult more if they had bounced to the same rhythm (synchro-
nously) than if they had bounced to different rhythms (asynchronously)
with the adult (Cirelli, Einarson, and Trainor 2014). Importantly, moving
synchronously with others does not induce a general state of helpfulness.
Instead, infants were shown to help only those individuals who have moved
synchronously with them and those who were close affiliates of their syn-
chronizing partners (Cirelli, Wan, and Trainor, 2016), but not to neutral
observers (Cirelli, Wan, and Trainor 2014). This suggests that performing
synchronous movements might serve as a cue for social bonding and coop-
erative behavior among interactants.
To date, how synchronous, coordinated movements produce these social
outcomes is largely unknown. It might be that moving in similar ways with
another person gives rise to the inference that the interactants are simi-
lar to one another in other respects as well. The contingency involved in
coordinated movements might ease predicting the future actions of oth-
ers. This, in return, may imply a potential for being good cooperation part-
ners in future joint action settings. Overall, increase in perceived similarity
and closeness toward one’s interaction partner might blur the boundaries
between self and other, ultimately reinforcing the emergence and mainte-
nance of collective agency.
CONCLUSION
Adapting to a world filled with agents who continuously share goals and
perform collective actions is not trivial. Accurate interpretation of a simple
action, such as reaching for a water bottle, requires the development of a
suite of social, cognitive, and motor skills. Still, infants in the first year of
life already demonstrate an understanding of others’ goals and intentions
and point to objects to share attention with other people. Elaborate forms
of joint actions can also be observed in infants’ interactions with their
mothers from birth onward. One prominent feature of these actions is the
high coordination of movements performed by the interactants.
The effects of performing synchronous, coordinated movements on
children’s social development have recently attracted attention from
researchers. Evidence is accumulating on the importance of action timing
for social cognition and joint action development. Although far from being
conclusive, these new findings suggest that the similarity and contingency
of movements involved in synchronous, coordinated interactions might
S y n c h r o n y, J o i n t A c t i o n s , a n d Ag e n c y i n I n fa n c y â•… [â•›175â•›]
176
REFERENCES
Saxe, R., T. Tzelnic, and S. Carey. 2007. “Knowing Who Dunnit: Infants Identify
the Causal Agent in an Unseen Causal Interaction.” Developmental Psychology
43: 149–158. doi:10.1037/0012-1649.43.1.149.
Tunçgenç, B., E. Cohen, and C. Fawcett. 2015. “Rock with Me: The Role of Movement
Synchrony in Infants’ Social and Non-social Preferences.” Child Development
86(3): 976–984. doi:10.1111/cdev.12354.
Woodward, A. L., and J. J. Guajardo. 2002. “Infants’ Understanding of the Point
Gesture as an Object-Directed Action.” Cognitive Development 17(1):
1061–1084. doi:10.1016/S0885-2014(02)00074-6.
S y n c h r o n y, J o i n t A c t i o n s , a n d Ag e n c y i n I n fa n c y [ 177 ]
179
PART EIGHT
CHAPTER 19
T h e Ag e n c y of t h e Dead [ 183 ]
184
conflicted emotions that work with the dead entails—emotions that are
foreclosed to scientists working within a legal context.
The image of the speaking corpse folds together different evidential
fields, including law, science, medicine, history, and biography. Each field
has its own determinants of what counts as evidence, and how it should
be assessed. Evidence is here situated within different regimes that gov-
ern what is allowed to enter in as material fact and how it is evaluated.
Drawing on Peirce, we can conceptualize evidence not as something that
stands alone, but as a semiotic relation. So in this sense evidence is always
for something—for prosecution, for historical narrative, for medical train-
ing. Yet at the same time, it is also evidence of something. Evidence for
prosecution might be evidence of violent events in the past. Evidence
for medical training might be of pathological changes in bodily tissues.
In thinking about the ways in which the dead are presented as evidence,
we need to attend both to how the different relationships between these
elements are composed and to the evidential regimes that govern how,
when, and for whom or what something acts as evidence. These may be
more or less explicitly formulated. Moving away from the problematic fact-
value distinction, Peirce’s triadic sign relation offers a means to unpack
the evidential relation as specified under different regimes, and hence
to explore the axes along which the corpse might be understood to act.
Below I briefly sketch out three different evidential configurations, before
returning to consider the image of the speaking corpse. To do this I map
the material evidence of the dead onto the Sign that stands at the heart
of Peirce’s sign relation. The sign of the body stands for a number of dif-
ferent possibilities, events and processes (“Objects” in Peirce’s terms). So
bodily traces may be narrowly construed within a forensic sphere as signs
of injury or harm, or understood in ways that are less closely specified. The
body may act as a sign of possibility, of things that may have happened, or
indeed as a sign of things that should have happened, as I explore below.
What is this relationship for, however? For whom or for what does the
body stand as a forensic trace of violence, or as a sign of potential? What
is evidence if it is not marshaled in the service of a truth-finding project?
Peirce directs us to the insight that evidence is ineluctably triadic. A third
term (Peirce’s “Interpretant”) is necessary to complete the evidential rela-
tion, so that material traces can be understood as both signs of something
and signs for different possibilities, goals, and projects.
For relatives of the dead, the corpse presents ambivalently as their fam-
ily member, but also as the necessary evidence of death. It is common in
the popular literature on forensic exhumation to hear reported claims that
friends and families cannot find a measure of peace without the presence
of the body. The recovery of the dead shifts the status of those who are
missing from possibility to actuality. The here-and-now-ness (or haecceity)
of the body acts as a concrete sign of death. What is important for families
in this context is recognition. Are these remains recognizable? Is this the
sought-for family member? This recognition is often based on a relation of
similitude or iconicity that might not stand up in a law court. For example,
in the search for those killed from Srebrenica, in the former Yugoslavia,
photographs of clothing and possessions found with the dead were com-
piled by human rights organizations. These were meant for display to rela-
tives in order to mediate their experience with the traces of the dead, and
to aid identification. However, DNA analysis showed that some identifica-
tions carried out this way were mistaken (Huffine et al. 2001:274; Wagner
2008: 99–100). Here we see the weaknesses of a purely iconic relation for
forensic inquiry. Ewa Klonowski (2007:167) describes how, in early exhu-
mations before DNA testing was introduced, she observed traumatic situ-
ations “in which two different families claimed the same remains because
of recognition of familiar clothing or shoes.” For a legal case, much hinges
on the ability to demonstrate a specific causal relationship between past
events and present traces. Certainly, iconic elements are important in
these claims. For example, if a jacket can be shown to resemble one worn
by a missing individual, this iconicity has a powerful visual force, useful
in a law court for evoking a feeling of recognition and convincing a jury.
However, to be accepted as evidence within science and law, an indexical
relationship has to be demonstrated; it is not enough that the traces are
the same. Even when the relation of resemblance is idiosyncratic and spe-
cific to the individual—the torn pocket that was never fixed; the button
sewn back on with mismatched thread—the connection with the miss-
ing must be demonstrated. Clothing acts as a powerful potential marker
of identity because of its indexical relation with the person who wore it.
Clothes take on something of the person who inhabited them and in cases
such as these can come to stand metonymically for the missing. Such
indexical traces may link crime scene and perpetrator, or human remains
and the missing, but the chain of evidence must always be preserved so
that the nature of this indexical trace can be maintained and assessed.
Sarah Wagner (2008:99) recounts how men who fled from the violence
at Srebrenica swapped clothing or were given identity cards and photos
by the wounded. These actions led to confusion over presumptive identi-
fications made on the basis of clothing. Here the sequence of events was
unclear and the nature of the indexical sign was misjudged: the clothes
and personal items did indeed point to their owners, but they had become
separated from them at some point. The particularities of a forensic sign
T h e Ag e n c y of t h e Dead [ 185 ]
186
relation are fundamental to its efficacy and authority. However, the spe-
cific indexical or causal link between the trace and the thing that made it
has to be carefully documented and preserved. In the legal context this
translates into a concern with the chain of evidence, which itself testi-
fies to the indexicality of the trace, and to the claim that no tampering
has taken place. It is only on the basis of an undisturbed and confirm-
able indexical trace, as interpreted as a fact, that a forensic argument can
be made about what happened at a specific moment and locale. Family
members may be relatively unconcerned with the evidential strictures of
science and law. Rather, recognition often seems to take place in an affec-
tive and relatively unexamined way. Yet this form of immediate perceptual
judgment certainly has its place and is operational within scientific and
legal inference. The difference lies not so much in the feeling of recogni-
tion, as the way in which these semiotic domains assess such judgments
and specify the nature of the relation of material evidence to its referent
(or Object).
Finally, moving to wider historical narratives, another evidential dimen-
sion comes into view. Whether constructing stories of nationalism and
reconstruction, or narrating anthropologists’ work around the dead body,
corpses come to stand for a range of meanings established through conven-
tion. The dead are often used to evoke larger entities: a group, an event,
the body politic, or indeed facts themselves. These conventions are often
embedded in perceived similarities and connections between the corpse
and the kind of narrative being told. For example, the work of exhuma-
tion, of revelation, offers a powerful and commonly used metaphor for the
recovery of history in situations of political repression, a symbolic rela-
tion that also draws upon iconic and indexical elements for its potency. In
such narratives the individual often drops out of view, subsumed within
a broader accounting. The conventional or symbolic relation between the
sign of the dead and the thing that it stands for brings me back to the
speaking corpse as a complex metaphor for fact. Although, before return-
ing to this theme, I should note that the above discussion presents a highly
schematized sketch of the field of shifting evidential relationships in foren-
sic work. Claims that center on the signs of the dead draw on all of these
dimensions, but may at different moments privilege one element of the
sign relation more than another.
Turning back to the speaking corpse, we can see that it provides a useful
way of imagining the different dimensions of forensic inquiry, and of think-
ing about forensic evidence. In its restricted speech the image acknowl-
edges the way in which the dead body can constrain particular readings
within certain evidential regimes. The figure of the speaking corpse also
T h e Ag e n c y of t h e Dead [ 187 ]
188
evidence, but it is not simply waiting to be activated, it also shapes the ways
in which it is acted upon.
This is to move away from a view of agency as inhering only in the liv-
ing, and instead to view it as a collaborative semiotic project that is also
shaped and constrained by the dead. The goals of prosecution and justice
cannot be carried out without them. The image of the testifying corpse
recognizes these agentive dimensions. But where does this leave the idea
of fact as something that stands alone and speaks for itself? When facts
speak for themselves they act as Signs that have been conflated with their
Objects and prescinded from the Interpretant relation. This is to fetishize
the power of the indexical relation and to underplay the different interpre-
tive possibilities to which it gives rise. To move away from a folk under-
standing of the agency of the dead and to fully engage with the ability of
the dead to intervene in the lives of the living needs a theory of agency
that is fundamentally relational, while also able to recognize the ways in
which that relationality can be hewn and circumscribed. Bruno Latour has
approached this question by considering how facts are treated as stable
“black boxes” when they are enrolled successfully into scientific work. At
moments of breakdown or challenge such facts are revealed to be composed
of relational networks in which many different actors are involved (Latour
1999). However, in considering the agency of the forensic dead, our atten-
tion is drawn not only to the relational constitution of the corpse as fact,
but also to the different regimes under which certain evidential relations
are brought into view or removed from the realm of possibility. Here it
seems most helpful to think of agency as an adjective rather than a noun,
reconceptualizing it in terms of agentive constellations that permit differ-
ent forms of action (Crossland 2014:100–137). This opens the way to more
fully decenter agency as well as to acknowledge that it is always a project
that is grounded in particular material conditions, and which unfolds over
time relative to certain goals.
REFERENCES
Bass, William, and Jon Jefferson. 2003. Death’s Acre: Inside the Legendary Forensic Lab
the Body Farm, Where the Dead Do Tell Tales. New York: Penguin.
Crossland, Zoë. 2014. Ancestral Encounters in Highland Madagascar: Material Signs and
Traces of the Dead. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
Ferllini, Roxana. 2002. Silent Witness: How Forensic Anthropology Is Used to Solve the
World’s Toughest Crimes. Willowdale, Ontario: Firefly Books.
Huffine, Edwin, John Crews, Brenda Kennedy, Kathryn Bomberger, and Asta Zinbo.
2001. “Mass Identification of Persons Missing from the Break-up of the Former
T h e Ag e n c y of t h e Dead [ 189 ]
191
CHAPTER 20
INTRODUCTION
When Alberto and his brothers go out to play marbles, they can’t help
but do other things. In the Peruvian, Aymara-speaking Andes, they must
take their family’s alpacas and sheep out to far-flung grazing areas. And,
once there, Alberto—the oldest brother—occasionally keeps an eye on the
animals as they drift toward uneaten pastorage. The area where they play
marbles, then, is part and parcel of a landscape that is quite unlike, for
example, the radically transformed, angular spaces where games like bas-
ketball and football (ideally) get played. Although treeless and shrubless,
it is a landscape that is dense with rocks small and large, thick clumps of
grass, short twigs, holes, eroded gulleys, and inclines and declines. In such
a case, marbles play must go where alpacas and sheep go, and virtue must
be made of this necessity. And, frankly, it is. When Alberto and his brothers
play marbles, they must shoot them through this thicket of things, aiming
for a series of small holes dug into the ground. Much of the intrigue of
the game consists, then, of whether and how these material things serve
as agents in marbles, and whether and how boys contend with the way in
which these things act. Does a rock divert a marble’s path? Does it do so
across several turns of play? What does a boy do in response? From the
perspective of an Aymara boyhood imagination, the stakes here are quite
high. Is a marbles player who cannot contend with a rock really a boy? How
might rocks make and unmake men?
192
When boys head out to herd animals and play marbles, they must, at
some point, transform some patch of ground into a playing field. This is a
moment that, however brief, most clearly reveals the connection between
the semiotic agency of material things and social categories like masculine,
human, and nonhuman. When carving out a playing field, boys must first
of all create a space that can accommodate the set of physical relations pro-
jected by the rules of the game. In this local variety of marbles, there must
be four spots that serve as the goals or targets for a boy striking a marble.
These are, typically, four holes that are created to have a diameter just a
bit wider than the width of a marble. Three of these holes must conform
to a line that is more or less straight, and the fourth sits off to one side
of this line. In order to play, a boy must first advance a marble through
these holes, ending in the fourth one off to the side. Advancing a mar-
ble means striking it with one’s pointer finger and having it successfully
land inside of the targeted hole. A boy has two marbles and may continue
advancing them until he misses a target with each marble. Once a marble
has reached the fourth hole, it attains a new status. It now has venom (or
wininu). Once it has venom, it can, upon striking another marble, kill it
(literally, jiwayaña, “to kill”). Once all of one’s opponent’s marbles are dead,
this player—the one who has at least one marble still alive—wins, and the
game is over. Although a game of marbles technically ends when all but one
or two marbles are dead, games more frequently than not end before this
moment arrives. This happens for a number of reasons: alpacas and sheep
drift towards other places, it’s time to bring everyone home, or it’s time to
eat, etc.
The act of creating an actual playing field happens quickly, and it is man-
aged by the oldest boy in a group (in most cases, an oldest brother).2 There
is a balance that must be achieved. On the one hand, there are plenty of
sites where it would be essentially impossible to play a game of marbles
(e.g., steep hillsides, boulder-strewn areas, areas too thick with grass). On
the other hand, there are at least a couple of areas where it would be too
easy (e.g., the flat road that runs through the community). To put it in a
semiotic idiom, finding and making an appropriate marbles playing field
is an act of phatic labor, to use Elyachar’s (2010) term.3 It is a task of find-
ing a field in which there are number of possible channels through which
the sort of thing that is a marble can be struck towards a series of holes
dug about four feet apart from one another. It must be a field in which
not all possible channels are available, but certainly a majority of possible
ones. More often than not, the challenge of creating a playing field—at
least, for the first three of the holes—requires a marbles player to remove
certain things that would gum up too many of the possible channels. In
the moments before a game begins, for example, an oldest boy will direct
a younger one to dig the four holes, and he himself will start to groom the
playing field. If there is a rock too large, a twig too thick and long, a piece
of trash too large (e.g., a two liter plastic bottle), then he will pick it up
and throw it aside. There is an implicit logic to this kind of act: these are
things that would likely enclose or surround a marble struck toward them
(a large rock, a long, thick stick, etc.), and these are the things that must be
Di s t r i b u t ed Ag e n c y i n P l ay [ 193 ]
194
removed. To the extent that some number of channels are made more fully
available, then the communicative value of the flicking of the marble—i.e.,
its value as a strategic act within the game—is more likely to be legible to
marbles players, onlookers, and anthropologist.
In these moments of designing a field, players are just as invested in
making sure that at least some possible channels are closed off, made less
fully available or, at least, made more challenging to traverse. Although this
is true with respect to the entire playing field, it becomes a matter of spe-
cial concern with respect to the fourth and final hole, the one that gives
a marble its venom. In the moments before play, for example, an oldest
boy—the engineer of the field, if you will—takes special care to locate this
last hole in an area that is more fully dense with debris or higher or lower
up on a slope, among other possibilities. If the already existing landscape
does not provide such possibilities, he will toss some rocks, twigs or trash
into the area of the fourth hole (sometimes drawing on things collected
from the other areas of the playing field). These moments are ones in which
it becomes especially clear that a playing field—in other words, this net-
work of possible channels—is something that is at least partly engineered
or designed. And, it is designed as a kind of sieve, in Kockelman’s sense
(2013). Depending on the specific area within the playing field, it is an
artifact that is designed to more or less easily let certain things through
(i.e., a marble) or to have those things either get stuck or be diverted. In
other words, it has been engineered to select for a certain kind of sign
(again, a marble),4 and it has been made to bring about certain kinds of
consequences—in other words, interpretants, in Peirce’s (1955) sense—
for that kind of thing (diverting marbles, getting them stuck, letting them
pass through). It is in this sense that the playing field counts as a complex,
internally differentiated semiotic agent, albeit one whose peculiar form of
agency has been partly embedded in it through processes of engineering
or design. In acting as such an agent, a skillfully designed marbles playing
field helps to reveal marbles shots that are more or less skillful and more
or less strategic.
The marbles field, then, is designed to act and to signify, but it also gets
understood, symbolically or ideologically, as an agent. This is implicit, even,
to the narrative arc that it instantiates. This is most fully apparent in the
design of the field that surrounds the fourth hole. The region around the
fourth hole, after all, is designed to make available fewer and more chal-
lenging channels for marbles to cross. It is strewn with debris or located on
a slope. However, it is also serves, narratively, as a moment of culmination
or, even, as a rite of institution (Bourdieu 2001). Once a marble lands in
this fourth target, after all, it attains a new status: it acquires venom, and
it can thereby kill other marbles. In this case, then, the semiotic agency of
the playing field—╉that is, its design as a sieve—╉comes to be understood
relative to a game sequence that is framed, narratively or symbolically, as a
kind of quest. A boy and his marble encounter their greatest challenge (that
is, the dense sieve that surrounds the fourth hole), and a marble is thereby
rendered a more potent and indeed venomous instrument. There is, in
other words, an analogy that is made across the kind of embedded semiotic
agency that the playing field exerts and the symbolic, narrative-╉like render-
ing of that agency. In this area of the playing field, the sieve is dense and
the challenge great. There are additional reasons for this interpretation.
When boys add rocks, twigs, and trash to the area around the fourth hole,
they often describe these things as qhincha, or “bad luck.” These things
are explicitly framed, in other words, as challenges for players:5 qhincha is,
after all, something that, according to Urton, is a “principal cause of the
emergence of a state of imbalance and disequilibrium” (1997:147). These
observations suggest a more sweeping analogy or relation of iconicity. The
playing field is not just a sieve for marbles. It is a sieve for men who con-
front the challenge of qhincha. The interpretive (or, better: interpreting)
world that is embedded in the marbles play field is fully “commensurable”
with (Latour 2005:74)—╉or, more strongly, compatible with and necessary
for—╉the sociocultural meaningfulness of the game. Or, to capture the
insight in an aphorism: only the skillful marbles shot shall pass, and only
the tough man shall win.
CONCLUSION
Marbles is one among many games that implicate material things as agents.
A quick perusal of Avedon and Sutton-╉Smith’s edited compendium on
games (1971) reveals a bewildering number of examples. In Brewster’s arti-
cle on games in Shakespeare, for example, he describes games that involve
seeds, dice, a leather belt, knives, an object “thrown onto the ground” (39),
a “wooden image (usually of a Turk or a Saracen) mounted on a pivot” (42),
cards, plates, a table, a shilling, marbles, and a game that consisted of “roll-
ing small balls into holes at one end of the game-╉board” (47). In a more
anthropological contribution, Erasmus describes forms of play that require
shews, bowls, beans, and small sticks, a series of “twenty holes separated
in the middle by a wider space called a river” (119), and, more familiarly,
boards that provide a flat surface. Few of these material things exert an
agency that is like the one described here: that is, as a field of material
things that acts as a sievelike catcher of marbles and men. This does not
Di s t r i b u t ed Ag e n c y i n Pl ay â•… [â•›195â•›]
196
contravene the analysis I’ve provided, but it does suggest that the problem
at stake is a tremendously larger one. How can we theorize the full variety
of ways in which material things (are designed to [Murphy 2013]) select
and act in games and play?
How much do these “missing masses” (Latour 1992)—╉in other words,
the material things that are not visible in many accounts of play—╉matter?
This is a question that has as many answers as there are approaches to the
study of play and games in childhood. In the case of Aymara marbles, for
example, an analysis of these missing masses is necessary for the anthro-
pological project of understanding the form of masculinity that is at stake
for Aymara boys. A number of other, more general possibilities stand out.
How do material things provide an anchor and model for forms of “make-╉
believe” or “fantasy play” in childhood? To what extent are processes of
“design” and “engineering” a part of play, and how might such processes
mediate the kinds of sociocultural worlds and cognitive processes that are
at stake in play? What kind of object is an object-╉for-╉play, and how might
its artifactuality differ from other kinds of objects and technologies? What
role do material things and other nonhuman agents play in producing the
category “human”? Piaget might have also asked: how might the relative
adaptability and design-╉ability of material things in play help to socialize
the kind of negotiability that Piaget—╉and, increasingly, anthropologists—╉
see as being central to our moral and social lives?
NOTES
REFERENCES
Avedon, Elliott M., and Brian Sutton-╉Smith. 1971. The Study of Games.
New York: Wiley.
Bourdieu, Pierre. 2001. Masculine Domination. Stanford, CA: Stanford
University Press.
Brembeck, Helene. 2011. “Toys Matter. McDonald’s Toys and Nordic Childhoods.”
Revue D’Histoire Nordique 12: 161–╉178.
Brewster, Paul. 1971. “Games and Sports in Shakespeare.” In The Study of Games,
edited by Elliott M. Avedon and Brian Sutton-╉Smith, 27–╉47. New York: Wiley.
Elyachar, Julia. 2010. “Phatic Labor, Infrastructure, and the Question of
Empowerment in Cairo.” American Ethnologist 37(3): 452–╉464.
Erasmus, Charles J. 1971. “Patolli, Pachisi, and the Limitations of Possibilities.” In The
Study of Games, edited by Elliott M. Avedon and Brian Sutton-╉Smith, 109–╉129.
New York: Wiley.
Goodwin, Marjorie H. 2006. The Hidden Life of Girls: Games of Stance, Status, and
Exclusion. Malden, MA: Blackwell.
Jakobson, Roman. 1960. “Closing Time: Linguistics and Poetics.” In Style in Language,
edited by Thomas Sebeok, 350–╉359. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.
Kockelman, Paul. 2013. Agent, Person, Subject, Self: A Theory of Ontology, Interaction,
and Infrastructure. Oxford: Oxford University Press.
Latour, Bruno. 1992. “Where Are the Missing Masses? Sociology of a Few Mundane
Objects.” In Shaping Technology, Building Society: Studies in Sociotechnical
Change, edited by Wiebe Bijker and John Law, 225–╉258. Cambridge,
MA: MIT Press.
Latour, Bruno. 2005. Reassembling the Social: An Introduction to Actor-╉Network Theory.
Oxford: Oxford University Press.
Murphy, Keith M. 2013. “A Cultural Geometry: Designing Political Things in Sweden.”
American Ethnologist 40(1): 118–╉131.
Peirce, Charles S. 1955. “Logic as Semiotic: The Theory of Signs.” In Philosophical
Writings of Peirce, edited by Justus Buchler, 98–╉119. New York: Dover.
Piaget, Jean. (1932) 1965. The Moral Judgement of the Child. New York: Free Press.
Smith, Benjamin. 2010. “Of Marbles and (Little) Men: Bad Luck and Masculine
Identification in Aymara Boyhood.” Journal of Linguistic Anthropology
20(1): 225–╉239.
Smith, Benjamin. 2014. “Metacultural Positioning in Language
Socialization: Inhabiting Authority in Informal Teaching among Peruvian
Aymara Siblings.” Linguistics and Education 25: 108–╉118.
Urton, Gary. 1997. The Social Life of Numbers: A Quechua Ontology of Numbers and
Philosophy of Arithmetic. Austin: University of Texas Press.
Di s t r i b u t ed Ag e n c y i n Pl ay â•… [â•›197â•›]
199
CHAPTER 21
Sign Interpretant
correspondence
Object
Sign Interpretant
(“false” playing) (not knowing if
sign and “true”
object align)
“True” Object
(internal auditory representations)
Sign Interpretant
(playing) (knowing if sign
and object align)
Object
(from internal auditory representations to
publicly available random sonic input)
Sign Interpretant
(playing) (disappointment)
Object
(standardized ideas)
Sign Interpretant
(playing) (inspiration)
Object
(from standardized to novel ideas
inspired by computerized algorithms)
Sign Interpretant
(smile) (being fooled)
Sign Interpretant
(smile) (revealing
another’s “true”
intensions via
mechanical
divination)
NOTES
1. At the time of my fieldwork these algorithms were a work in progress and not
always successful in achieving their goal. I remember many instances of playing
with the system they animated and being uninspired by its responses to my own
(frequently uninspiring) improvisations. Lack of inspiration typically resulted
when the system generated responses that were either too predictable or too
unpredictable (Wilf 2013:614–╉615).
2. At the same time, “A Zande does not readily accept an oracular verdict which
conflicts seriously with his interests,” and “apart from criminal cases, there can
be no doubt that a man takes advantage of every loop-╉hole the oracle allows him
to obtain what he wants or to refrain from doing what he does not want to do”
(Evans-╉Pritchard 1991:163).
3. As one tennis training machine manufacturer puts it, “Random oscillation is
where the tennis ball machine replicates a match situation by shooting balls
randomly around the court. Rather than groove a particular shot, this allows a
player to … practice shots in a more realistic environment.” See http://╉www.
spinshot-╉sports.com/╉Knowledge.html, accessed April 5, 2015.
REFERENCES
PART NINE
CHAPTER 22
We also say that actions are undertaken or carried out, implying that places
are fields for the externalization of knowledge, expectation, understand-
ing, and other elements of self. Combining these phrases, action seizes and
appropriates places while necessarily externalizing phenomena and quali-
ties originally perceived as internal.
FOUNDATIONS OF EMPLACED AGENCY
As Robert Sack has argued, the intimate relationship between person and
place is reciprocal: “Places need the actions of people or selves to exist and
have effect. The opposite is equally true—╉selves cannot be formed and
sustained or have effect without place” (1997:88). To offer a few concrete
examples: an orator is subject to the visual and acoustic properties of a
lecture hall; a soldier fights on a battlefield structured in terms of sight
lines, slopes, and cover; a chemist needs a laboratory that permits the iso-
lation and recombination of precise amounts of various elements; an art-
ist’s studio provides tools and space for making objects of aesthetic value.
I offer the term emplaced action to designate action involving place in an
integral fashion. Emplaced action integrates the concrete and the abstract,
the subjective and the objective, the local and the global. All actions involv-
ing people are emplaced, although not all emplaced actions involve people.
Geographers increasingly follow Doreen Massey (1993) in conceptualiz-
ing places as constellations of flows rather than bounded areas. In analogous
fashion, people can be understood as extensible beings who both sense the
world at a distance and act on distant places, dynamically extending them-
selves outward through space-╉time (Adams 1995, 2005). Thus, emplaced
action is not contained action. Rather it links near and far aspects of the
world in particular ways that fluctuate from moment to moment. The ora-
tor speaking in the lecture hall incites a protest in a public square, against
a war fought in a distant country, according to orders signed in a legislative
chamber, involving a chemical weapon developed in a laboratory, inspiring
an artist cloistered in a studio, whose painting will circulate from gallery
to gallery. Every phase of action is linked to other actions through places,
and places connect actions to other actions in particular topologies and
configurations. Some of this action is physical, like fighting and painting,
while some of it is verbal, like orating and legislating. In either case, human
action becomes extensible through space by virtue of its active appropria-
tion of place.
To think of place in this way requires us to “get back into” place (Casey
1993), to recognize ourselves as fundamentally geographical in nature.
then asserting the right of one’s own state to carry out punishment on that
foreign state. The nation is to its territory as the self is to the human body,
and this parallel is so strong that bodies and nations symbolically overlap.
Righteous indignation subsumes human casualties. People learn to iden-
tify the nation as an immense megabody in which their personal agency
can be aligned with the agency of many other people and take on superhu-
man proportions while absolving individuals of accountability for causing
suffering and death to members of that set of humans labeled “the enemy.”
Popular culture can make this idea strikingly literal through nationalist
superheroes like Captain America, a graphic “rescaling icon” internalized by
children to form “a bridge between collective identity and the individual”
(Dittmer 2007:401). This cartoon literalizes the body politic, a notion that
dates from the 15th century and is evident in Hobbes’s writings. In modern
critiques such processes of internalization and externalization are linked
to bio-╉power (Foucault 1978). Not only is agency distributed to a place, but
personal interests are deemed to be subordinate to a “national interest” that
is equated with enforcing certain geographical boundaries (Newman and
Paasi 1998). The needs of this collective body may be imagined/╉imaginary
(Anderson 1991), but they guide militaristic and nationalistic actions that
destroy hundreds, thousands, or even millions of real human bodies.
SUMMARY
REFERENCES
P l a c e a n d E x t e n ded A g e n c y [ 219 ]
220
Tuan, Y.-F. 1982. Segmented Worlds and Self: Group Life and Individual Consciousness.
Minneapolis: University of Minnesota Press.
Tuan, Y.-F. 1977. Space and Place: The Perspective of Experience. Minneapolis: University
of Minnesota Press.
Tuan, Y.-F. 1974. Topophilia: A Study of Environmental Perception, Attitudes, and Values.
Englewood Cliffs, NJ: Prentice-Hall.
Woolf, V. (1929) 2002. A Room of One’s Own. New York: RosettaBooks.
CHAPTER 23
ACTION IS DISTRIBUTED
Artifacts will help, support, or guide users in their activity through their
culturally constructed properties. This idea emerged in various forms in
history (Leroi-╉Gourhan 1965); philosophy (Simondon 1969); psychology
(Gibson 1950, 1982, 1986; Uexküll 1925; Vygotsky 1978), design (Norman
1991), cognitive science (Pea 1994), and so on. Hutchins (1995), observ-
ing jet pilots, demonstrated that what flies the plane is not pilots alone
but the whole cockpit, including instruments, checklists, maps, and so on.
Cognition is “distributed” in its content as well as in its process. Objects
that possess agency are called “actants” (Akrich, Callon, and Latour 2006),
a term including acting humans and material objects alike. When describ-
ing activity emerging from subject-╉ object interaction, some (Gibson,
Norman, Latour) focus more on properties of the object, while others
(Vygotsky, Uexküll) start from the subject. This chapter proposes a larger
systemic view.
Over the last two decades, I analyzed human activity recorded from
a first-╉
person perspective, with “subcams”—╉ miniature video cameras
attached to glasses of volunteers performing their usual activity, at work or
elsewhere. With participants we analyzed their recordings to make explicit
their cognitive processes and the various elements involved in their action
(Lahlou 2011, 2014).
222
In doing so, it appears obvious that action is distributed and its deter-
minants as well. For example, in the activity of preparing breakfast, we
can observe that, as Mother sets the table, Father goes to buy croissants,
Coffee-╉
Machine brews Coffee, Bottle contains Orange-╉ Juice, Alarm-╉
Clock wakes up Daughter, while Thermostat maintains House warm, and
so on.
To clarify the distribution of agency, let us look in detail at the determi-
nants of action.
INSTALLATION THEORY
When you manage to cycle in heavy traffic, this is the result of simultane-
ously using the affordances of the road; of mobilizing embodied skills; of
protection by the traffic rules that prevent cars from driving you off the
road. Society has constructed the built environment (the road), trained you
to embody skills (cycling, traffic sign reading), and runs control institu-
tions (police, traffic lights, rules of the road). On one hand these three lay-
ers guide and scaffold your individual behavior, enabling you to safely reach
your destination. On the other hand they make you a predictable road user
to others, so we all together co-╉construct a “normal” traffic flow at societal
level. The same mechanism that nudges and empowers you is also a mecha-
nism of control at aggregate level.
The urban street is an “installation”; this installation is not located
within the physical world only or inside your nervous system alone; it is
distributed in the built environment, in educated and disciplined bodies,
in institutions and their enforcing agents. Our everyday environment is
built by humans; centuries of gradual construction have produced “instal-
lations” such as kitchens, conference rooms, or cockpits that make activity
simple, so simple in fact that even novices can perform satisfyingly. Barker
described of such setups as “behavioral settings”: “stable, extra-╉individ-
ual units with great coercive power over the behavior that occurs within
them” (Barker 1968:17). But we must also include the individuals in the
installation.
Installation theory considers how societies guide individual activity by
constructing “installations,” in which individual subjects operate. Subjects
are moved by individual motives and intentions, but an installation has
a momentum of its own. An installation is “a socially constructed system
locally guiding a specific activity, by suggesting, scaffolding and constrain-
ing what society members can/╉should do in this specific situation” (Lahlou
2015). Installation theory is a theory for nudging, but also for more intru-
sive control.
As for most important phenomena, a plethora of concepts and theo-
ries have been proposed in the literature, for example, “affordances,”
“disciplining institutions,” “structures,” “assemblages,” “environments,”
“niches,” “infrastructure,” “channels,” “codes,” “norms,” “habitus,” and so
forth. Installation theory tiles three layers of determinants that were so far
separated by disciplinary approach, even though in practice they operate
as a bundle. The various components of an installation are not located in
the same medium; they emerge visibly as a functional unit only when they
locally assemble in action; as a bundle they were gradually constructed in
practice, and only as a bundle can they be understood. The example of the
road above illustrates this: the installation is not limited to the visible set-
ting of the pavement; it includes the representations and driving skills of
the participants, as well as the institutions that regulate the traffic. Each is
meaningless without the others.
Within an installation, behavior is funneled simultaneously by (a) affor-
dances of the physical setting, (b) subjects’ embodied competences, and
(c) social control. What characterizes human installations is their inten-
tionality. Their design fits a specific purpose: they support a project of activ-
ity. Humans make installations for all kinds of activities: roads, houses,
armchairs, hospitals, cradles, graves, and so on.
Individuals do have free will (e.g., they chose to get into the traffic),
but their agency is limited. Clearly, installations have a momentum of
their own. Installation theory considers that humans usually act in such
settings (roads, homes, restaurants, hospitals, etc.) where activity is
channeled by the cultural installation. Depending on how we want to
see it, we can consider that individuals use installations as instruments
to reach their goals; or that installations use individuals to produce an
outcome. For example, the traffic installation (roads, signs, lights, traffic
rules, police, etc.) uses drivers to produce smooth transport at societal
level; the roller coaster or the night club uses Albert as “a client” and as
“a participant” to produce “experience” for users, and profit. Both per-
spectives are valid to a certain extent.
In other words, while Hutchins noted the environment contains medi-
ating structures that process parts of the cognitive operations necessary to
complete tasks, Installation theory considers more radically that our envi-
ronment contains constructed “installations” which coproduce and funnel
activity with the human actors as components. It must be clear here that
installations are not just the context: individuals are part and parcel of
H o w A g e n c y I s Di s t r i b u t ed T h r o u g h I n s ta l l at i o n s [ 223 ]
224
them. Society does not only install physical artifacts, it also installs inter-
pretive structures (the manual) in individuals so the physical layer is used
“as it should.” For smooth traffic, drivers should know how to drive their
vehicle and there should be rules that are enforced. And this is indeed
the case: society has set up systems to embody competences in individu-
als (e.g., driving lessons, license) and sets of rules of the road, with an
enforcing body (the Police). These are neither independent nor accidental:
the three sets of determinants are obviously part of one single societal
project: smooth traffic. In practice, what the subject can do is the remain-
ing intersection of what is objectively possible (affordances), subjectively
possible (embodied competences), and socially enabled (social control).
Amazingly, while this is common sense, the three layers tend to be studied
independently by different disciplines. In the study of accidents, though,
it becomes clear that problems occur only when the loopholes of the vari-
ous layers of defense of the system combine (Reason 2000).
Installation theory has two aspects. The first is an operational frame-
work to describe the determinants of activity. This framework, above, is
simplistic, with three layers of components; it can be used for analysis and
for change management. It is practical because the layers indicate where
one can act to change the system.
The theory’s second aspect addresses the evolution of installations.
It describes the interactions between the components of the model, and
genetic, functional, and historical mechanisms that produce sustainable
systems. During education individuals will internalize not only various rep-
resentations and practices, but also social rules. Foucault (1975) described
how this embodiment of social rules makes individuals “docile bodies” and
as a result each actor becomes his own controller. Other society members
will also encourage and control others into behaving (from smiling or frown-
ing to giving directions or orders); societies also have specific control forces
(e.g., Police) to ensure enforcement. The rules themselves may be reified
into artefacts which can become actants. Embodied interpretation systems
(e.g., mental representations of objects) and physical objects themselves are
taken in a chicken-and-egg reproductive cycle, with dual selection operat-
ing in each of the two forms (embodied and material). Institutions are in
charge of designing, operating, maintaining, and evolving the installations;
they monitor the dual selection process that make the installation a single,
coherent, functional unit. In this short chapter we will use only the first part
to provide a framework distinguishing three types of agency.
Installation theory considers three types of components that determine
action: affordances in the physical context, embodied competences of the sub-
ject, and social influence—direct or through institutions. Affordances afford;
H o w A g e n c y I s Di s t r i b u t ed T h r o u g h I n s ta l l at i o n s [ 225 ]
226
that Croissants should be shared equally, one per person, so if Son wants
to take an extra one, other participants will prevent him from doing so.
Another example in a hospital installation: a cancer patient may afford sev-
eral treatments among which the competent doctor will make a choice; but
hospital rules will force the doctor to ask the patient’s consent.
In short, Installation theory states action is supported and guided at three levels:
affordances planted in the environment, competences embodied in the subject, other
people and institutions. It suggests that sustainable behaviors are the ones that are
simultaneously supported by and compatible with these three layers altogether.
Agency, as the potential for action, is therefore distributed in these three layers.
H o w A g e n c y I s Di s t r i b u t ed T h r o u g h I n s ta l l at i o n s [ 227 ]
228
ACKNOWLEDGMENTS
This chapter benefited from a residency at Paris Institute for Advanced Study
(France) as a EURIAS senior fellow, with support of the European Union
7th Framework Programme for research (grant agreement no. 246561),
and from constructive reviews from Paul Kockelman and Nick Enfield.
NOTE
1. Stoetzel (1963) defines role as the set of behaviors that can be legitimately
expected from the subject, and status as the set of behaviors the subject can
legitimately expect from others.
REFERENCES
H o w A g e n c y I s Di s t r i b u t ed T h r o u g h I n s ta l l at i o n s [ 229 ]
231
PART TEN
CHAPTER 24
action. I shall lay out such an approach by appealing only to actions human
agents normally can and do perform (together). This will serve to narrow
the scope of the following reflections without denying the significance of
classifying and understanding the cooperative behaviors of animals or the
actions of and interactions with technical systems.
That said, it seems helpful to distinguish between actions human agents
can perform on their own and actions they can only perform together. The
action of going for a walk, for instance, can be performed by a single agent
and by two or more agents; by contrast, actions such as playing tennis or
lifting a heavy object can (under normal conditions) be performed only by
two or more agents. If we call actions performed by two or more agents
joint actions, we can capture this difference between types of action by say-
ing that contingently joint actions are those that could also be performed by a
single agent, and that necessarily joint actions are those that require the par-
ticipation or contribution of two or more agents. Joint actions come in a
vast variety, ranging from spontaneous and one-╉time cooperation to regular
and highly structured collective agency. I shall return to core characteristics
of joint actions in due course, although not without mentioning that it has
proved helpful to treat questions of group agency separately from analyses of
joint action (cf. Pettit and Schweikard 2006). Even though it is quite common
to refer to actions performed by two or more agents as actions of a group, the
design and structure of some groups raises the question whether they qualify
as agents in their own right. Corporations, for instance, are complex social
entities whose internal makeup and structures of decision making justify
treating their ways of operating as decisively different from that of random
collectives or pairs of cooperating agents. Interest in the structure of groups
that may count as agents in their own right may be prompted primarily by
issues of collective responsibility, but there are certainly also fundamental
questions in action theory and social ontology that deserve attention.
In what follows, I shall set aside questions raised by complex social for-
mations and concentrate instead on small-╉scale cooperative joint action.
Prototypical cases such as two agents going for a walk together or lifting a
heavy object together can be used to illustrate two central challenges in the
philosophy of joint action, and in the theory of distributed agency more
generally.
asking what is special about joint action and what joint action implies nor-
matively. In a nutshell, the question “What is special?” refers to those ele-
ments of joint actions that set them off against parallel individual actions,
and the question concerning normative implications is aimed at the mutual
obligations and entitlements that may (or may not) hold between cooper-
ating agents. The issues thus brought to the fore are the intentionality and
the normativity of joint action.
Starting with intentionality, let us consider the following case. Imagine
three agents (A, B, and C) walking next to each other in the same direction
and that from what is observable it is unclear whether they or a subset of
them are walking together or not; imagine further that we know that two of
them (A and B) are going for a walk together, while the third (C) is just acci-
dentally walking in parallel to them. With respect to this imagined case, we
may ask what makes for the difference between A’s and B’s walking together
(or jointly) and B’s and C’s walking in parallel, where A and B perform a joint
action and B and C (in abstraction from A’s presence) perform parallel, but
otherwise unrelated, individual actions. A minimal consensus about this
issue among philosophers of action is best captured in John Searle’s sloga-
nesque formulation “If there is anything special about collective behaviour,
it must lie in some special feature of the mental component, in the form
of the intentionality” (Searle 1990:402). But how should this specific form
of intentionality be described? Which specific intentional attitudes guide
and serve to explain joint actions in contrast to coincidentally parallel indi-
vidual actions?
Once it is accepted that the intentional attitudes that are in play in joint
action cannot be simply the same as those that guide solitary individual
action, a familiar move in the debate is to guard against postulating a form
of group mind that hovers above, as it were, and controls the individuals
involved. It seems just obvious that explaining joint action does not call for
such a postulate of a supra-individual entity. What is required, instead, is
an account of how exactly the intentionality characteristic of joint action
differs from ordinary individual intentionality; put differently, what is
sought is an answer to the question “What is collective about collective
intentionality?” (cf. Schweikard and Schmid 2013). In short, the specific
jointness or collectivity of the intentionality in play can rely in its content,
its mode, or its subject. I take this last “or” to be inclusive and shall go on
to sketch a relational account of joint intentions that takes all three aspects
to take a specific collective form.
In order to intentionally guide their joint walk, A and B in our previous
example both have to intend their joint walk, in other words, their joint
walk has to be represented in the content of their intentions. On a first
C o op e r at i o n a n d S o c i a l O b l i g at i o n s [ 235 ]
236
But whose intention is the intention that guides the joint walk? Who is
the subject of this intention? Having set aside the postulate of a mysterious
supra-mind that could be the subject of this intention, we should be drawn
to the conclusion that the intending individuals together form the subject
of this intention. With respect to both the content and the mode of the
intentions of the individual agents involved, we noted that (1) collectivity
has to feature in both of these aspects, and (2) it has to feature by high-
lighting the relations between the agents involved. In a two-person case,
only both of them can give sense to their each intending the joint activity
and to their using the first person plural indexical “we” in verbalizing these
intentions. And if it takes two to set up these interrelated intentions, then
the same two, together, should be viewed as the subject of the intention
that guides the joint walk.
This result calls for (at least) one immediate clarification regarding the
number of intentions involved. I have referred to the individual agents’
intentions and to the intention that guides the joint walk, possibly as
if those were simply on a par. If we view as intentions only such mental
phenomena that are had and embodied by individual agents, then only
the participatory intentions of the individual agents qualify as inten-
tions. This individualistic picture runs the risk of losing sight of the ana-
lytic and explanatory task set out at the beginning of this section. On the
other hand, if we allow all structures of attitudes that guide and explain
actions to be intentions, then specifically related intentions, such as
those of cooperating agents, can play that role together. In line with the
latter understanding, we can call the structure of interrelated attitudes
that guides A’s and B’s joint walk the joint intention whose subject A and
B are together.
Strictly speaking, the analysis of joint intentions should not be lim-
ited to the actual intentions regarding the joint activity, as these will typi-
cally be accompanied by further intentions and beliefs on the part of the
agents involved. In these respects it seems plausible to demand that the
agents’ further intentions, for example, other goals A may have in mind
in relation to the walk with B, do not conflict with their joint endeavor;
that they each exhibit a sufficient degree of readiness to follow through
with their endeavor; and that they each are aware that what and how they
intend together is out in the open between them. Requiring an elaborate
form of common knowledge among the participants may seem inadequate
or overly intellectualized in some contexts, but a weaker “no conflict”–
condition regarding their awareness and understanding of the situation
may nevertheless be necessary for the attitudinal nexus to adequately pro-
vide guidance.
C o op e r at i o n a n d S o c i a l O b l i g at i o n s [ 237 ]
238
existed between them even though their agreement was nonverbal. But
some authors have remained unconvinced by some of the aforementioned
details of the account and by the view that normative structure that comes
with joint commitments is indeed fundamental to all kinds of joint action.
For instance, below the level of highly organized group agency, and unless
a somehow emergent subject of the relevant intentional states is appealed
to, it does not seem plausible to claim that the intention that explains a
joint action can diverge from the participatory intentions of the individual
agents involved. And the feature of joint intentions Gilbert terms the “con-
currence criterion” (2014:106–108), which is meant to capture that joint
intentions can only be modified or annulled unanimously, also seems too
demanding to be a general feature of joint action. For even if a degree of
unanimity, a shared belief as to what they are doing together, is required to
keep the cooperators on track, as it were, it would seem exaggerated to hold
that in all cases of joint action one participant is entitled to hold all others
to the original joint commitment. Gilbert’s view thus represents phenom-
ena of joint action as in principle akin to scenarios in which agents have
entered a contract or exchanged promises, with all the normative impli-
cations involved by that. Without disputing that some cases exhibit that
sort of normative structure, it seems doubtful that all cases are like that
and thus that joint commitments are essential to joint action (cf. Bratman
2014: ch. 5).
Do we have to conclude that joint action generally does not involve
mutual obligations? Or does joint action imply a weaker sort of norma-
tive relationship? Against proponents of the view that only certain kinds
of joint action involve mutual obligations, such as Michael Bratman (2014),
others have suggested to regard practical attitudes such as reliance (Alonso
2009) or trust (Schmid 2013) as grounding normative interpersonal rela-
tionships and as being fundamental to joint action. The normative bonds
grounded in these attitudes can be described as weaker than the relation-
ship Gilbert conceives of in terms of joint commitments. The unifying idea
behind accounts that refer to reliance or trust is that if one agent forms (and
exhibits or expresses) this kind of attitude regarding one’s partner’s contri-
bution to a joint action, the other is led to form and endorse the same kind
of attitude. To illustrate this, assume that A and B are in a position to move
the piano across the room, where this is something neither can do alone,
but perfectly doable in unison. Assume further that each of them not only
intends to move the piano, as in the analysis outlined in the previous sec-
tion, but that in addition each of them relies on the other doing his or her
bit, in other words, push at his or her end of the piano (cf. Alonso 2009). Or
assume that each of them, besides intending to move the piano, trusts that
C o op e r at i o n a n d S o c i a l O b l i g at i o n s [ 239 ]
240
the other will in fact push at his or her end (cf. Schmid 2013). The relevant
contention put forth with these accounts is that, characteristically, cooper-
ating agents create mutual obligations—or, in other words, give each other
normative reasons to contribute—by forming attitudes of reliance or trust
regarding the other’s contribution. Thus, in our example, A’s relying on (or
trusting) B to push his or her end of the piano creates a reason for B to do
so, and vice versa; let us assume that this reason is comparatively strong,
so that it corresponds to an obligation for B to contribute. Obviously, not
all instances of reliance or trust can generate reasons and obligations in
this way, but under normal conditions, and especially in cases of mutual
reliance and mutual trust, in which the attitudes can be understood as
mutually reinforcing, the generative effect seems to occur. And it should be
emphasized that the obligations in question are not moral, but only social
obligations, which means that their force is explained by reference to the
particular social situation, including the attitudes and relations that fea-
ture in it, and not by reference to more general moral principles or norms.
However, the question remains whether it is necessary to posit the pres-
ence of a different kind of attitude as fundamental in order to explicate a
basic normative relationship implied by joint action. Defenders of accounts
that refer to reliance or trust seem to answer in the affirmative, but an
account that builds on the notion of an individual social commitment can
confine the conceptual resources to fulfill this task to attitudes more closely
related to the intentions and beliefs that accompany joint action. Abe Roth
(2004) has developed a variant of such an account, but I shall conclude by
outlining the main elements of a different variant. These regard the con-
ceptual resources made use of in this account, the way it explains the nor-
mative relationship involved in joint action, and the connection it draws
between commitments and obligations.
First off, talking of commitment in relation to intentions does not intro-
duce an additional type of attitude; it rather highlights another element
of the structure of intentional activity. In the case of joint intention, this
amounts to making explicit that the socially oriented intention of the form
“We intend that we … ” implies a specific type of commitment, a social
commitment. Whenever an agent intends to do something, they commit,
inter alia, to choosing means appropriate to their end and to avoiding any-
thing that could render their attaining that goal impossible. Building on
this, we can say that when an agent intends a joint action, as in the cases
considered above, they assume a social commitment that regards both
(1) their own contribution to the joint action and (2) the other agent(s)
involved. The first aspect of this commitment captures the aformentioned
implication of intending; the second reveals the social orientation of these
C o op e r at i o n a n d S o c i a l O b l i g at i o n s [ 241 ]
242
REFERENCES
CHAPTER 25
W hen we deceive others, are we using them as tools? After all, when
we deceive, we use others as means to our ends, irrespective of their
intentions and welfare. But I argue that such a view is only superficially
valid once we consider the mechanisms of deception as a form of social
agency. A more insightful understanding of deception must account for
the interlocking of agency between deceiver and deceived at several levels,
based on uniquely human meta-representational capacities.
The idea that deception means using humans as tools has widespread
intuitive appeal. Often, people deceived by others feel “used” or “played
with” or “powerless,” attributes better fitting an inanimate object than an
active, intentional agent. One of its guises, manipulation, strongly evokes
a puppeteer handling the mechanics of a tool-like puppet. In slang, a “tool”
is an individual deemed too slow-witted to realize that he is being taken
for a fool. The link between deception and tool use has even more presti-
gious advocates. Immanuel Kant opposed any form of lying (even when
the lie would save an innocent life) because it would contradict the first
formulation of the categorical imperative (to act only in accordance with
the maxim through which you can at the same time will that it become a
universal law) but also, and more relevant to our point here, the second
formulation—that we are to treat others as ends in themselves, and not
only as means: “The one who has it in mind to make a lying promise to
another will see right away that he wills to make use of another human
being merely as means, without the end also being contained in this other.
244
For the one I want to use for my aims through such a promise cannot possi-
bly be in harmony with my way of conducting myself toward him and thus
contain in himself the end of this action” (Kant 1993:429–╉430). While Kant
is making a moral point about deception, the liar’s conduct (and hence his
moral failure) toward the other evokes exactly the use of a device for one’s
own ends, without acknowledging the humanity of the victim.
Intuition and moral metaphysics aside, this chapter explores aspects of
deception that clearly distinguish it from mere tool use and bring it con-
ceptually closer to other forms of social agency. It is argued that decep-
tion builds upon co-╉opting several aspects of the victim’s agency, whereas
no agentive qualities are needed from a tool aside from its affordances.
Moreover, although deception feeds on an asymmetry of agency, it is not
merely a unilateral process. The target of deception may fend for himself in
ways that are unthinkable for an object. Together, these facets reveal the
entangled, reciprocally responsive agency of actors involved in deception
and counterdeception.
The first thing about deception that sets it apart from treating others as
mere tools is its constitutive social nature. Few scholars if any would dis-
agree with the fact that deception is a form of social agency, yet it is con-
spicuously absent or undervalued in major works in the philosophy and
psychology of social agency. As illuminating as they are, developments
in the burgeoning field of studies and theoretical proposals dealing with
shared agency might suggest an unwarranted identity between “shared”
and “social” agency by overlooking a vast realm of sociality. Since the point
made here is a fairly general one, the umbrella-╉term “shared” covers many
forms of social agency. They may share only a “family resemblance,” includ-
ing concepts such as “shared,” “joint,” “collective intentionality,” “joint
action,” “common ground,” “joint commitment,” “group,” or “collective
agency” (Gilbert 1990, Searle 1990, and Tomasello et al. 2005; Bratman
2014 is an exception, but even he tries to demonstrate how types of decep-
tion may still count as shared agency).
Deception and coercion are exemplary cases of those other forms of
agency that are irreducibly social but have features that set them apart from
the “shared agency” family. These different forms are ontologically based on
asymmetry rather than symmetry, on exploitation rather than mutuality,
on opposition rather than convergence, on competition rather than coop-
eration, on the circulation of incomplete or misleading information and
De c e p t i o n a s E x p l o i tat i v e S o c i a l Ag e n c y [ 245 ]
246
DECEPTION AS SOCIAL AGENCY
agency in your favor by means of misinformation, but you did not deceive
anyone—╉the workers are simply mistaken. Contrast this with the case
of, for example, a Nigerian inheritance scam, where the victim acts and
(falsely) interprets the situation as a cooperative event, apparently acting
jointly with the deceiver, but in reality playing into his or her hands.
In contrast, tool use may be considered a part of an individual’s agency.
Through its affordances, its embodied history and origin, an object may be
part of the distributed agency of an individual or a collective of individu-
als (Hutchins 1995). The elements of the cockpit form a constitutive part
of the pilot’s agency in flying a plane as a ship may be part, and mediate,
the social agencies of a crew. The tool becomes part of individual or social
agency as long as it is engaged into cognitive and physical work by at least
one human being. Deception, on the contrary, is essentially social. It takes
(at least) two to create a deception (leaving “self-╉deception” aside), just as
it takes two to have a conversation or to jointly carry an object. This cre-
ates a discrepancy at the level of flexibility, as the tool, unlike the victim of
deception, may only be co-╉opted passively, while the deceived is induced
to make choices, comprehend, and communicate. If I push you in front
of a trolley (perhaps to save five people as a good utilitarian), I am not
engaged in any social agency, but merely use your body as a tool for derail-
ing the trolley. A different event happens if I persuade you that it is safe
to lay on the tracks by your own volition. Between victim and perpetrator
there is an imbalance of epistemic power, but they are still ultimately cog-
nizing actors, while a tool is not. From the second perspective on agency,
the proper accountability of tools is usually derived from their users. An
Azande granary is the tool used by the sorcerer to kill its victim, but the
legal and causal actor is the (invisible) sorcerer.
The previous section argued that deception is a form of social agency whose
flexibility involves the imbalanced relationship at the level of knowledge
between the agencies of two actors. The epistemic asymmetry is key to the
success of deception, as the deceiver controls the event and adjusts his or
her inputs according to how he or she anticipates the behavior of the vic-
tim. Yet the victim is not a simple tool, as he or she contributes with his
own interpretation of facts, his or her own sources of information, and
his or her own capacity for choice and control. Moreover, deception is not
the automatic outcome of a single agent—╉the deceiver—╉since the target is
never just a sitting duck.
by his peers, the deceiver would have failed. In a way, the deceiver did what
is expected of most people—to further his or her interests even at the
expense of others, using such means as possible and useful. To try a com-
parison, deception flies in the air just as your inbox swells with Nigerian
scam letters. One could hardly stop feeling that the unfortunate client of
such scams is at least an active party to the deception with inadequate
epistemic vigilance in this day and age. The same apportioning of blame is
used in ritual pranks of initiation, in which the incompetence of the victim
justifies and legitimates the social and epistemic power of the tricksters
(Umbres 2013).
But, to return to our initial problem, why do people feel that deception
involves them as mere tools of the deceivers? I conclude with a specula-
tion about the accountability of deception. In modern, centralized societies
driven by the universalistic morality of religion, or citizenship, or Kantian
ethics, people do not expect fellow humans to deceive them, at least not
as a rule. The norms of social interaction prescribe (at least minimally)
cooperative agents, engaged in true and relevant communication. They feel
obligated to speak the truth (or at least not to tell a lie knowingly) and feel
entitled to the same reciprocal treatment. The social contract of everyday
interaction punishes deceivers, either formally or informally, from jail sen-
tences to social ostracism. Not all social settings, of course, require such
a social norm. Strudler (2009) argues that deception is socially accepted
when used as legitimate self-defense. The norm of trust1 does not apply
automatically and exhaustively in legitimate negotiation maneuvers such
as communicating a false reservation price when buying a house.
In high-trust societies, the sentiment of reciprocity in truth-telling
makes everyone lower their epistemic guards, leading to huge savings in
the transaction costs of communication and social interaction, and fur-
thermore to successful and efficient cooperation (compare with Keenan
1976 for a culture in which truth and relevance are not conversational
postulates). But the reverse of this generalized amnesty of distrust is ced-
ing part of our agency to others. When we trust someone, we give him
or her power over our behavior, over our representations, over the flex-
ibility of our agency. We do this in the expectation that her or she (1) will
be benevolent and cooperative and (2) would do the same for us. This is
why deception appears, for such enlightened altruists, as a way of using
people as tools, as means to private, egoistic ends. The comparison helps
us understand the way deception is accounted for in some societies, but it
is misleading as a metaphor or theoretical inspiration. In deception, as in
any form of social agency, it takes more than one individual to act and to be
responsible for their actions.
De c e p t i o n a s E x p l o i tat i v e S o c i a l Ag e n c y [ 249 ]
250
ACKNOWLEDGMENTS
The writing of this chapter began while I was Fyssen Foundation postdoc-
toral fellow at Institut Jean Nicod, Paris. I am grateful to Nick Enfield and
Dan Sperber for their comments on draft versions, and I thank the partici-
pants of the “Foundations of Social Agency” scientific retreat organized by
the Max Planck Institute for Psycholinguistics for their suggestions.
NOTE
1. Strudler also links trust with a yielding of autonomy, and deception as breach of
trust with a compromise of autonomy, lending further support to the idea that
deception is a form of intertwining social agency between parties.
REFERENCES
De c e p t i o n a s E x p l o i tat i v e S o c i a l Ag e n c y [ 251 ]
253
CHAPTER 26
INTRODUCTION
One afternoon in Luang Prabang, Laos, I was gambling with three men
over a game of pétanque. For the unfamiliar, pétanque is a game played
like bocce or lawn bowling and it is a common way for people—especially
men—to gamble in Luang Prabang.1 On this day, I filmed as we played.
Our game had drawn an audience of a dozen or so. The spectators lined
the benches—some of them gambling, some of them just passing the time
and enjoying the show. About an hour into the game, my teammate Bii
began to take a shot when one spectator named Can2 wandered from his
seat on the bench and onto the court. Can then suddenly lifted his arms
and screamed. Startled, Bii missed his shot. He glared at Can and barked
accusatively, “You!”3 The audience burst into laughter and Can scampered
back to his seat as the two exchanged threats.
Clearly, Can was trying to distract Bii and make him miss the shot. His
scream was not merely a scream but an especially aggressive heckle in a
match already brimming with trash talk. A few seconds after Can’s heckle,
two audience members imitated Bii flinching in reaction: one man jerked
his head, mimicking Bii’s shaking body, while the other commented, “He
was surprised, all right, he went like this,” twitching his own arm to reenact
Bii’s flinching arm.4
To everyone, there was no doubt that Can’s heckle had caused Bii to miss
the shot, that it had affected Bii’s body and surprised him in ways beyond
254
his control. But when I watched the video recording of the event, matters
became less clear. Despite my repeated viewings, the recording showed no
signs of Bii flinching. Instead, the evidence that Bii was startled resided
entirely within Bii’s and the spectators’ own reactions. Bii had responded to
the heckle in a manner implying it was effective and audience members had
said that the heckle was effective, that it had made Bii flinch. While Can’s
scream was so loud, well-timed, and explicitly addressed toward Bii that it
seems unlikely the scream did not affect Bii’s shot, we cannot know with
any certainty whether it did have an effect. Put another way, it is impos-
sible to know whether Bii would have made the shot—which he only barely
missed—had Can not screamed.
There is an inevitable and irresolvable uncertainty here; one that is, in
fact, helpful to better understanding agency. Acknowledging that we can-
not always know what causes what guides us to move away from concep-
tualizing agency in terms of moments of causality isolated from human
interpretation. The question worth asking becomes not did Bii cause Can
to miss the shot, but how did Bii and the spectators make this causal
relationship—real or fictive—visible? In other words, how are causal rela-
tions understood and made apparent in interaction?
In this chapter, I explore the prevalence and subtlety of attributions of
agency on the pétanque court. By unpacking a video recording of a differ-
ent pétanque game, I show that a player can respond to a heckle such that,
through his response, he helps to frame it as effective or ineffective. In
other words, I show how people can retroactively attribute and (re)distrib-
ute agency through their responses to events. I argue that we should study
agency not as a static, perspective-free property of the world (e.g., “In this
moment of heckling, agency is distributed across three actors”), but as part
of an ongoing semiotic process through which actors ascribe agency. To put
it simply, this chapter argues for an interactional approach to distributed
agency that treats the “distributed” in “distributed agency” as more verb
than adjective.
Di s r u p t i n g A g e n t s , Di s t r i b u t i n g Ag e n c y [ 255 ]
256
Saj jaa
What I have been calling “heckling” is what Lao pétanque players most
often call saj jaa.6 Saj jaa literally means “to apply medicine” or “to dose”
and it is a local label for actions on the pétanque court that disrupt and
destroy the ability of others to focus, play properly, or control their bod-
ies and minds. The trope is that saj jaa can affect its victims with the same
efficacy that a pill cures a headache or a dose of methamphetamines keeps
one awake. Although there is a range of techniques for saj jaa—being loud,
standing too close, bickering about the score, telling an opponent he will
miss his shot, even betting—the techniques all presumably share a goal:7
to disrupt the attention, focus, and calm of the targeted player; to affect his
“heart;” and to make him lose, both the game and his cash.
All players are vulnerable to saj jaa, but most agree that some are more
susceptible than others. The most vulnerable are said “not to have the heart
for it” (caj3 bòø-daj4) or to be “weak-hearted” (caj3 qòòn1). They “tremble”
(san1 kathùan2) in response to trash talk like “spring chickens” (kaj1 qòòn1)
with “soft, porous skin” (nang3 pùaj1). Hecklers make them feel “angry”
(caj3 haaj4) and “rushed” (caj3 hòòn4, literally, “hot-hearted”), and they play
poorly as a result. Those better at resisting saj jaa are said to have stron-
ger, more capable hearts (caj3 khaw2 daj4). They are tough and inured, like
“experienced, older chickens” (kaj1 kêê1) with “tight, rubbery skin” (nang3
niaw3) and stay “calm and cool” (caj3 jèn3, literally, “cool-hearted”) under
pressure, allowing them to play their best. A strong heart, as one longtime
pétanque coach told me, is a key trait in good athletes. Being invulnerable
to saj jaa is, thus, both valued and valuable.
While players are sometimes said to be habitually “hot” or “cool-
hearted,” the terms “hot” and “cool-hearted” are also used to describe tran-
sitory emotional states.8 People often comment upon how others appear to
be feeling. Does he look “cool” and relaxed, or does he seem “hot” and dis-
tracted? Observing players’ emotional states like this can provide valuable
information. For example, take a moment from a money-gambling game: a
player rushed his way through multiple shots and his opponents howled
and heckled after each poor shot. Seeing this, one spectator remarked to his
friend, “Don’t bet on him, he’s hot!”9 Monitoring a player’s emotions can
also inform a heckler’s use of saj jaa. As one man put it, a good pétanque
player should observe his opponent’s “heart” to map out his weaknesses
and discover what kind of “dose” might best affect him.
One way a player can display his “heart” is in his responses to saj jaa.
These responses also can display his autonomy as an agent. If a player
maintains a “cool heart” in the face of medicine, he is likely to be seen as
Di s r u p t i n g A g e n t s , Di s t r i b u t i n g Ag e n c y [ 257 ]
258
Figure 26.1 Scene 1.
From lines 3 to 11b, Phuumii addresses Taa multiple times but Taa
never engages him. As Phuumii becomes more animated, Taa stares only
at the pétanque balls. When Taa does talk, he seems to address the court
generally, rather than Phuumii. Take, for example, his frustrated cry, “Oh!”
in line 6. This cry happens immediately after the miss and is apparently
a reaction to it. It suggests Taa’s surprise and seems to be a kind of “self-
remarking,” addressed to no one in particular (Goffman 1981b:97).20 That
this frustration is not addressed to Phuumii distributes responsibility for
Figure 26.2 Scene 2.
Di s r u p t i n g A g e n t s , Di s t r i b u t i n g Ag e n c y [ 261 ]
262
Figure 26.3 Scene 3.
that if Taa can knock the target ball off the court, he will score five points,
which is not true. Phuumii floods the court with stimuli addressed to Taa,
and retreats from where the pétanque balls sit only just before Taa takes
his shot.
During Taa’s second turn in the game (Figure 26.4), when he successfully
hits the target ball, he continues to ignore Phuumii and again does several
things that tacitly attribute responsibility for his initial missed shot to him-
self and not Phuumii. For example, as he throws his ball and it flies through
the air, he and Phuumii yell simultaneously: Taa yells, “[Knock] the little
ball [out]!” (line 11a), and Phuumii yells, “Hah!” (line 11b). Phuumii’s “Hah!”
again floods the court with stimuli directed toward Taa. Taa’s shout, in con-
trast, works more subtly: in this situation, Taa would not want to knock the
little ball, also called the jack, out at all (as this would score him fewer points
than if he knocked his target ball out); he is thus shouting a kind of anti-
wish, expressing what he does not wish to happen. Anti-wishes like this are
not uncommon on the pétanque court and function to anthropomorphize
and challenge Taa’s pétanque ball as it flies through the air; perhaps akin to
telling a problematic copy machine, “Jam again, I dare you.”21
Figure 26.4 Scene 4.
When Taa does make his shot (Figure 26.5), he walks back to the other
end of the court and says (line 8), perhaps a bit tongue-in-cheek, “Ohhh, [I
was] scared of hitting the little ball.” As he says this, and for the first time in
this segment of the interaction, he briefly glances at Phuumii. Like much of
what Taa has done, this utterance implies the ineffectiveness of Phuumii’s
Di s r u p t i n g A g e n t s , Di s t r i b u t i n g Ag e n c y [ 263 ]
264
Figure 26.5 Scene 5.
doses. Even though Taa might not actually have been “scared of hitting the
little ball,” his utterance nevertheless functions to foreclose the interpreta-
tion that he was scared of, or even attending to, Phuumii’s talk—he was
scared only of hitting the little ball. This utterance also seems to explain
away Taa’s first, missed shot. Perhaps, it implies, Taa had missed that shot
because he had overcompensated in fear of hitting the “little ball.”
That Taa successfully made his second shot helps him tell a “story” about
his first, missed shot. Because Phuumii heckled Taa during both shots,
Taa’s ability to make his second shot while being heckled implies that the
cause of his first, missed shot, was something other than heckling.
In the interaction as a whole, Taa and Phuumii are talked about, and
treated as, different kinds of agents. While Taa comes off as cool and in
control, Phuumii exhibits a kind of frantic “hotness” aimed at sensorial
overload. During my research stint more generally, I noticed that Phuumii
tended toward such states; others said so as well. During this game, in fact,
a number of spectators commented on the ragged state of Phuumii’s heart.
One man shouted out, for instance, just before Phuumii was offering to
bet Taa and the above interaction began, that Phuumii’s heart was “con-
fused” and “disordered,” that he “couldn’t even sit still.”22 Later during the
game, Phuumii was again accused of losing his cool. He had just shouted
and missed a shot when a spectator called out that in using medicine on
Taa, Phuumii had dosed himself instead. Like a chemist organizing danger-
ous chemicals and accidently spilling them on his skin, Phuumii was falling
victim to his own medicine.23 According to the spectator, Phuumii was an
agent of self-destruction, “hot” and uncontrollable. Of course, ascriptions
of agency and responsibility like these can in and of themselves be effec-
tual. In saying Phuumii was “hot,” the spectators were perhaps themselves
“dosing” Phuumii; compare the frustration one feels when repeatedly told
to “calm down” during an argument.
CONCLUSION
“Stories” are told not only on pétanque courts. Much like a man stumbling
on a sidewalk can “tell a story” about why or how he tripped, people—with
varying degrees of explicitness—often frame what has happened and who
is responsible. This sometimes has serious consequences. As it does, for
example, in a court of law, often the most ritualized and important venue
for attributing agency. Take the state trial of the officers who beat and bru-
talized the late Rodney King, which resulted in the officers’ acquittal. In the
trial, the defense used a number of visual and linguistic devices to guide how
people viewed the video of King’s body being beaten. As Charles Goodwin
(1994:621) writes, the video of the beating was framed such that “a rise in
King’s body [was] interpreted as aggression, which in turn justifie[d]an
escalation of force [by the officers]”. In this case, the defense “told a story”
about the beating, and attributed responsibility for it to King, not the offi-
cers. They presented King’s writhing body not as the victim of the officers’
force, but as the entity with agency, in control of the situation.
If we take attributions of agency seriously, some dimensions of agency
rise to the fore. First, attributions of agency are often contested. People can
and often do disagree about who or what is responsible for an act, and, thus,
about how agency is distributed (see Hill and Irvine 1993). Furthermore,
some people may be better at telling their “side of the story,” because actors
have differential access to authority and the resources to represent agency
(e.g., legal training, ownership of a projector, etc.—see Kockelman 2007
and Kockelman this volume for a discussion of the agency of representa-
tion itself). Would Taa’s “story,” for instance, be as convincing if he had not
made his second shot? Second, “stories,” or whatever we might want to
call attributions of agency, often distribute agency differently across time
and space. That is, agency and the distribution of agency are interactionally
Di s r u p t i n g A g e n t s , Di s t r i b u t i n g Ag e n c y [ 265 ]
266
ACKNOWLEDGMENTS
NOTES
1. Because of limitations in space, I am here not addressing the way in which the
game fits into broader life in Laos—its sociological, economic, and historical
context, its gendered dimensions, the discourses about its unseemliness, and so
on. These topics are, obviously, hugely important to fully understanding what
is happening on the court. Note, too, that all of my examples come from games
in which men are playing for money (as opposed to beer, which is also often
gambled).
2. This name, along with all the other names of players in this chapter, is a
pseudonym.
3. In Lao, “caw4 nii4 naq1.” For transcription of Lao in this paper, I am following
the system outlined in Enfield (2007).
4. In Lao, “tùùn1 qoo1 con3 vaa1 hèt2 cang3 sii4 leej2 mùù4 kii4 naq1.”
5. See Duranti (2004:454) and Hill and Irvine (1993) for discussion of the
discursive construction of responsibility and the relation between responsibility
and evidence. Generally, the argument in this chapter builds on some prevalent
arguments in linguistic anthropology concerning “metapragmatics” and
“reflexivity” (e.g., Silverstein 1993). Others, especially Ahearn (2010), have built
on these arguments somewhat differently. Note that, in contrast to some classic
statements on agency from Ahearn (2001) and Duranti (2004), and in line with
the work of the editors of this volume, my argument moves beyond a primary
focus on grammatical categories (e.g., ergatives) and explicit framings of agency
to include the alleged suburbs of language: gesture, gaze, and so on.
6. Saj1 jaa3 is a verb, and the nominal form is kaan3 saj1 jaa3. For ease of reading,
I will refer to it as simply saj jaa, without tone markers.
7. This is a slight simplification, because sometimes actions that could be
considered medicine are claimed to be “only a joke.” In the final analysis, what
counts as saj jaa is, like agency, negotiated in interaction.
8. For further discussion of “hot” and “cool” heartedness in a similar context, see
Cassaniti (2009).
9. Emotional moments like this shape players’ reputations, but, of course,
reputations are not merely an aggregate of these moments. Some moments are
inevitably more lasting, salient, or important than others.
10. Or at least autonomous vis-à-vis the heckler.
11. Note that this is a simplification for multiple reasons. First, people can interpret
these signs in very different ways. Second, the distribution of agency is often
gradient. Players or audience members can, for example, downplay a heckler’s
agency by saying the heckler “joked just a tiny bit,” implying the missed shot
was due to the player’s heart, not the strength of the medicine used. In contrast,
people can characterize medicine as being so powerful that anyone would be
affected. In fact, this is what happened later in the interaction between Bii and
Can when Can screamed in Bii’s face. The scream was so intense, people said,
that of course Bii was affected, no matter the state of his heart.
12. See the concept of “conditional relevance” for further discussion (Schegloff
2007:20).
13. In regard to the ebb and flow of sports, I asked one man what he might say to
calm a friend down who is feeling “hot-hearted.” He offered: “Don’t worry about
whether or not you are going to make the shot, who could possibly make every
shot in sports?”
14. Of course, players do at times deny that a heckle is getting to them—sometimes
explicitly—by directly engaging with the heckler.
15. In Lao, “bòò1 khòòj5 bòø-son3 caj3 khòòj5-qaq1 khòòj5 tang4 caj3 khaw5 tang4 caj3
tii3 lêqø-kaø-lêêw4 khòòj4 bòø-son3 … son3 caj3 ñang3.”
Di s r u p t i n g A g e n t s , Di s t r i b u t i n g Ag e n c y [ 267 ]
268
16. These “cartoons” are not meant, in any sense, to be accurate portrayals of the
people involved; in fact, their main appeal, besides the ease with which they can
be read, is that they preserve anonymity as the drawings look quite different
from the people they represent.
17. Although each player has a teammate, neither of their teammates talk during
the course of this segment.
18. That is, Taa treats Phuumii’s actions as medicine, as should become clear below.
19. This is not unusual in sports, as players are generally expected to focus their
attention on the game; cf. Goffman’s (1981a: 134–135; 1981b:112) notion of an
“open state of talk.”
20. Nor is this discourse-oriented response cry generally used in situations in which
one is scolding or chastising another’s actions, but instead, as Nick Enfield
writes, it tends to be used as “a news receipt which expresses disappointment or
concern” (2007:313).
21. Players often shout commands at the balls, addressing them with directives
like “Stop,” “Go,” and so on. For some similar themes, see Benjamin Smith’s
discussions of marbles and bad luck among Aymara children (2010:230;
chapter 20 in this volume).
22. In Lao, “cit2 caj3 … ñung3 ñaak5 leej2 nòq1 laaw2 bòø-saang1 juu1 lêq1.”
23. In Lao, “saj1 jaa3 khaw2 bak2 haajø-haaj4 lêq1 tuaø-qèèng tùùn1.”
24. I do not have space to address this question here, but merely point the reader to
the introductory chapters by Enfield and Kockelman of this volume and some
popular arguments that deal with the possibility of nonhuman agents (Gell
1998; Latour 2005).
REFERENCES
Di s r u p t i n g A g e n t s , Di s t r i b u t i n g Ag e n c y [ 269 ]
271
AUTHOR INDEX
[ 272 ] Author Index
273
Author Index [ 273 ]
274
[ 274 ] Author Index
275
SUBJECT INDEX
[ 276 ] Subject Index
277
Subject Index [ 277 ]
278
Exodus, 105 hardwiring, 134
explicit negotiation, 82, 103 help, 68, 153, 215, 221
accepting, xi
face, 70, 71 requesting, xii, 62, 79
Facebook, 51, 52, 53, 54, 115 See also assistance
family, 73, 131, 186, 227 high-trust societies, 249. See also trust
and death, 184, 185 Hitler, 245
and interaction, 61–62, 82–83, Hobbes, 218
225–226 homo sapiens, 21
internal dynamics, 75 honor, 19, 248
and payback, 10 human body. See bodies
feud, 10 humanity, 110, 113, 155, 244
financial crisis, 114
fission, 11 imagination, 18, 29, 102, 191
food, 18, 132, 133, 134, 146, 225 imitation, 6, 60
foraging, 132, 133, 135, 141, 152 immediate and mediate spheres, 36
force fields, 35 impositions, xiv
formal cause, 15, 17 improvisation, 199–209
Foucault, 25, 73, 74, 76, 218, 224 independent action, 119, 227, 236
framing, 33, 99, 105, 200, 102 indigenous law, 10
and accountability, 6, 217 inductive reasoning, 30
and agency xiii, xiv, 15–17, 22, 32 infants, xiv, 131, 143, 163–167,
free will, xv, 223 169–176. See also babies;
friendship, 63 children
fusion, 11, 13, 113, 128, 129 inferential agency, 33, 35, 36, 37,
75
games, 191–197 infrastructure, 49–55, 111, 114,
gaze, 120, 128 223, 227
gaze patterning, 122, 123 and agency, 35, 64–65
in mother-child interaction, 161, and interactions, 32
163–166, 174 and the internet, 112
generativity, xv installations, xiv, 221–228
geographic theories, 213 instigation, 26, 28, 36, 37
Ghana, 61 instincts, 21
goal-directed behavior, 7, 12, 170, 171 institutions, 32, 67, 222, 223–226, 245
goals instrumental acts, 19
assistance in, 67 instrumental agency, 18, 19, 22,
and installations, 223, 226 33, 36, 37
and intentions, 145 intentionality, xi, xiv, xv, 225
interactional, 88, 94 and agency, 233
others’ goals, 170, 171, 227 shared, 12, 60, 234–235, 244
shared, xi, 13, 65, 169, 175 internet, xii, 51, 52, 53, 111, 112
God, 21, 102. See also Christianity; interpretants, 28, 34, 206, 207, 257
religion anticipation, 8
Google, 110, 115 definition, 25, 26, 27, 87
government, 10, 45, 105, 112 non-anticipated, 4, 8
grammar, 79–86 Peirce, 184, 194, 200
Greece, 245 sign-object relations, 201, 202,
grounding, 63, 239 204, 205
group exercise, xiv, 141–150, 156 and subprehension, 5–6
group size, 11, 152 interpreting, 12, 43, 195, 225
[ 278 ] Subject Index
279
Subject Index [ 279 ]
280
[ 280 ] Subject Index
281
Subject Index [ 281 ]
282
[ 282 ] Subject Index
283
284
285
286