Realism in Practice
Realism in Practice
Realism in
Practice
An Appraisal
If you enjoy our free e-books, please consider leaving a small donation to
allow us to continue investing in open access publications:
http://www.e-ir.info/about/donate/
i
Realism in
Practice
An Appraisal
ED IT ED BY
DAV I D E OR S I, J . R . AV GU S T IN & MA X N U R N U S
ii
E-International Relations
www.E-IR.info
Bristol, England
2018
This book is published under a Creative Commons CC BY-NC 4.0 license. You
are free to:
Any of the above conditions can be waived if you get permission. Please con-
tact [email protected] for any such enquiries, including for licensing and translation
requests.
Other than the terms noted above, there are no restrictions placed on the use
and dissemination of this book for student learning materials/scholarly use.
A catalogue record for this book is available from the British Library
iii
Editors
Acknowledgments
This collected edition would not exist without the support and guidance from
Stephen McGlinchey, Editor-in-chief of E-International Relations. We would
also like to thank Robert W. Murray for his efforts with bringing clarity of
concept to this collection. Most of all, we would like to thank all the
contributing authors for their work and their patience.
Abstract
The purpose of this collection is to appraise the current relevance and validity
of realism as an interpretative tool in contemporary International Relations. All
chapters of the book are animated by a theoretical effort to define the
conceptual aspects of realism and attempt to establish whether the tradition
still provides the necessary conceptual tools to scholars of International
Relations. The chapters address important issues in contemporary world
politics through the lens of realist theory such as the refugee crisis in Europe
and the Middle East; the war against ISIS; the appearance of non-state actors
and outlaw agents; the rise of China; cyberwarfare; human rights and
humanitarian law. The collection also provides insights on some of the
theoretical tenets of classical and structural realism. Overall, the collection
shows that, in spite of its many shortcomings, realism still offers an incredibly
multifaceted understanding of world politics and enlightens the increasing
challenges of world politics.
vii
viii Realism in Practice
Contents
INTRODUCTION
Davide Orsi, J. R. Avgustin and Max Nurnus 1
Contributors
Koldo Casla earned his PhD at King’s College London in July 2017, where
he has studied why Western European states promote international human
rights norms. His most recent publications are ‘The rights we live in:
protecting the right to housing in Spain’ (IJHR, 20:3, 2016) and ‘Dear fellow
jurists, human rights are about politics, and that’s perfectly fine’ (chapter in
edited volume Can human rights bring social justice?, 2015).
Evolution of the Antarctic Treaty Regime (1988) and The General Assembly
in World Policies (1986). She has also authored articles in the American
Political Science Review, the American Journal of International Law,
International Organization and Review of International Organizations.
Brandon Valeriano is the Donald Bren Chair of Armed Politics at the Marine
Corps University and a Reader in the Department of Politics and International
Relations at Cardiff University. He also serves as an adjunct fellow for the
Niskanen Center. His two most recent books are Cyber War versus Cyber
Reality at Oxford University Press (2015) and Russia’s Coercive Diplomacy
at Palgrave (2015).
Introduction
The Practice of Realism in International
Relations
DAV I DE O R S I, J . R . AV GU S T IN A N D MA X N U R N U S
The purpose of this collection is not to solve this dilemma; it is not to establish
whether realism should be considered as the bearer of eternal truths
regarding world politics or whether it should be abandoned. This book takes
instead a more limited and nuanced approach, by appraising the current
relevance and validity of realism as an interpretative tool in contemporary
International Relations. In this spirit, all chapters of the book are animated not
only by a theoretical effort to define the conceptual aspects of realism, but
also by the aim of finding whether the tradition still provides the necessary
conceptual tools to practitioners and scholars of International Relations.
In the chapter that opens the volume Lebow and Rösch present some of the
perennial ideas that have shaped the realist tradition in international thought.
By challenging the common reading that sees profound differences among
various schools of realism (structural, classical, neo-positivist, and more),
Lebow and Rösch find some essential elements of realism. These are the
‘tragic vision of life’ and the controversial relation between ethics and power.
However, Lebow and Rösch not only offer this important interpretation but
also claim that, on this ground, realism can still enlighten our understanding
of world politics, by offering critical insights on the refugee crisis in Europe
and the Middle East.
In the second chapter, Beer and Hariman show the persistent relevance of
realist thinking in International Relations with regard to the rise of ISIS. To this
end, they take a different approach from that of Lebow and Rösch and
present an updated version of realism: post-realism, which seeks to offer a
much more accurate account of the immaterial and cultural aspects of
international politics.
War has always been at the centre of realist theory. The activities of hackers
during elections and the disruptions they caused against public services and
governments (for example the attack against the NHS in Britain in May 2017)
show the growing importance of this new important level of confrontation
among states, which is examined in the contribution (Chapter 7) by Craig and
Valeriano on cybersecurity.
All the chapters included in this volume rise from an urgent practical need:
that of understanding the changing landscape of contemporary international
politics. The relative decline of American power, the ambivalent Russian
return and the rise of China, as well as the threats posed by non-state actors
and new forms of military might are the problem felt by scholars in
Introduction 4
References
Cole, Phil. 2017. “Trumpism and the Future of International Politics: The
Return of Realism.” E-International Relations (http://www.e-ir.info/2017/01/29/
trumpism-and-the-future-of-international-politics/) accessed 25/06/2017.
Legro, Jeffrey W and Andrew Moravcsik. 1999. “Is Anybody Still a Realist?”
International Security 24(2): 5–55.
Morgenthau, Hans. 1985. Politics among Nations. The Pursuit of Power and
Peace. Chicago, IL: Chicago University Press.
Sutch, Peter and Juanita Elias. 2007. International Relations: The Basics.
London: Routledge.
Realism: Tragedy, Power and the Refugee Crisis 6
1
Realism: Tragedy, Power and
the Refugee Crisis
FE L IX R ÖSC H & R IC H A R D N E D LE B OW
Since the end of the Cold War realism has returned to its roots. Realist
scholars show renewed interest in their paradigm’s foundational thinkers, their
tragic understanding of life and politics, their practical concern for ethics, and
their understanding of theory as the starting point for explanatory narratives
or forward-looking forecasts that are highly context dependent. In this
chapter, we do not attempt to map these recent re-readings. Despite their
different perspectives on world politics, the writings of Thucydides, Niccolò
Machiavelli, E. H. Carr, Reinhold Niebuhr, Arnold Wolfers, John Herz, Hans
Morgenthau, and Hannah Arendt demonstrate a remarkable unity of thought,
as they have been driven by similar concerns about ‘perennial problems’
(Morgenthau 1962, 19). One of these problems is the depoliticisation of
societies. Realists were concerned that, in modern societies, people could no
longer freely express their interests in public, losing the ability to collectively
contribute to their societies. Consequently, realism can be perceived as a
critique of and ‘corrective’ (Cozette 2008, 12) to this development.
John Herz (1951) argued that the drive for self-preservation, which ensures
that people care about their survival in the world by seeking food and shelter,
provokes a security dilemma because people can never be certain to avoid
attacks from others. Morgenthau (1930), by contrast, was more concerned
about people’s drive to prove themselves, achieved by making contributions
to their social-political life worlds. Success is difficult because people have
incomplete knowledge about themselves and their life-worlds. Any political
decision must always be temporary and subject to revision if circumstances
change or knowledge is being advanced. In realising that their ambitions are
in vain, another tragic aspect of life comes to the fore. For Morgenthau,
accepting this tragic aspect is a first step toward transcending it; people can
reflect critically about their existence and come to understand that only
through their own efforts can life become meaningful.
Given that these drives affect people on every level, realists do not
distinguish between domestic and international politics. Rather, they focus on
political communities however they may be conceived because it is through
peoples’ relations that these human drives start to affect politics.
In these relations, power plays a decisive role. Due to the drive to prove
oneself, a balance of power evolves in interpersonal, intergroup, and
international relations to counter the development of hegemonic power
(Morgenthau 1948). This balance of power is not stable but evolving because
actors face a security dilemma (Herz 1951). Due to uncertainty, actors live in
fear and they are constantly striving to amass further power only causing the
same reaction in their potential adversaries. Hence, it is less physical or
9 Realism in Practice
For realists, ideologies aim to retain the socio-political status quo and any
human activity has to be geared towards sustaining this reification. The
current socio-political reality is being perceived as given and it cannot be
fundamentally altered. The development of the political as an ‘arena of
contestation’, however, endangers this socio-political status quo, as it enables
people to voice their interests and share their thoughts about the composition
and purpose of their political community, eventually opening up the potential
of socio-political change. To cope with this depoliticisation, realists advertised
what can be called an ‘ethics of responsibility’ – to use Max Weber’s term.
Although realists were convinced that most people would be unwilling or
incapable of taking responsibility for their lives, they still argued for an ethics
in which decision-making is guided by ‘intellectual honesty’ (Sigwart 2013,
429). Thoughts and beliefs have to be contextualised in a self-critical process
that demonstrates empathy towards the position of others. The resulting
‘discourse ethic’, as Arendt called it, can only happen in collectivity and
Realism: Tragedy, Power and the Refugee Crisis 10
American town hall meetings provided the perfecting setting for Arendt, as
they allow all people who share a common interest to congregate. As a
consequence, however, people have to be prepared to change their positions
and be willing to take responsibility for the moral dilemmas of (inter)national
politics.
Given that classical realists were sceptical of the promises of modern nation-
states, they argued for the establishment of a world community, eventually
leading to a world state. Such a global community can help to transcend the
11 Realism in Practice
Realist Epistemologies and the Refugee Crisis in Europe and the Middle
East
which was first published in 1929. One of the key concepts that we find in this
book is the conditionality of knowledge which means that knowledge is
always bound to the socio-political environment in which it operates, stressing
that universal knowledge is impossible. Applying this notion on the current
refugee crisis, we understand that perceiving refugees as a threat to security
is the result of human will and political agency. For example, the refugee
crisis was one of the dominant drivers of British Brexit-discourses, although
the UK received less than 40,000 asylum seekers in 2015. By comparison,
more than 400,000 refugees chose Germany as their destination and Sweden
received more than 160,000 in the same period, making the latter the
European country that has accepted most refugees in relation to the overall
population (British Red Cross 2016).
This is not to say that this process always takes place consciously, as we can
never be entirely sure how our writings or actions are perceived by others, but
classical realism can help us to understand that humans are not only the
objects of security, but also its subjects. In public discourses, they have to
have the possibility to redefine the substance of security, instead of leaving it
to (inter)national foreign policy elites. As mentioned, these discourses have to
include all involved people, and given that different interests morph into a
common good, they evolve antagonistically without causing violent outbreaks,
if, following Morgenthau, all interests are taken into account. To make this
process work, however, dialogical learning is required, as contemporary
scholarship calls it. This form of learning is based on continuous possibilities
of exchange between refugees and local people and it requires refugees and
locals to demonstrate open-mindedness and empathy as well as the
willingness to challenge one’s own positions. As a result, security can be
redefined and what is perceived to be a crisis can be eventually understood
as an opportunity to create something ‘which did not exist before, which was
not given, not even as an object of cognition or imagination’ (Arendt 1961,
151).
Conclusion
they are made into a question of security which in turn justifies the use of
extraordinary means to police this threat. Rather, realism encourages to
transform the differences that are perceived as a security issue into a
potential to create more inclusive societies. Realism is therefore far from
being a case for the dustbin of the history of international political thought, as
some commentators on realism suggest, but it can serve as a stepping stone
to question some of the common assumptions held in the discipline.
References
Arendt, Hannah. 1961. Between Past and Future. Six Exercises in Political
Thought. London: Faber & Faber.
Herz, John. 1951. Political Realism and Political Idealism. Chicago: University
of Chicago Press.
Realism: Tragedy, Power and the Refugee Crisis 14
Herz, John. 1984. Vom Überleben. Wie ein Weltbild entstand. Düsseldorf:
Droste.
Lebow, Richard N. 2003. The Tragic Vision of Politics. Ethics, Interests, and
Orders. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
Morgenthau, Hans J. 1930. Über die Herkunft des Politischen aus dem
Wesen des Menschen (Container 151, Manuscript Division, Library of
Congress, Washington, D.C.).
Morgenthau, Hans J. 1979. Human Rights and Foreign Policy. New York:
Council on Religion and International Affairs.
2
Realism, Post-Realism and ISIS
FR A N C IS A . BE ER & R OBE RT H A R IMA N
Post-realism, like realism, begins with states as actors. At the same time, it
goes beyond states to include a wide variety of non-state actors within the
mix of players on the world stage. These comprise various networks of
governmental and non-governmental actors combined in supra-national,
national, sub-national forms.
One set of such actors include militant groups such as Al Qaeda, Boko
Haram, Hamas, Hezbollah, Shabab, the Taliban — and ISIS, the Islamic State
of Iraq and Syria, also known by other names including Daesh or ISIL (see
Gerges 2016; Nance 2016, 20). We focus specifically on this last group, to
which we shall refer as ISIS, which is a multidimensional, quasi-state/national
actor. It has its own global, regional, and local networks with links to other
networks. It emphasises specific issues; it combines acts of violence against
enemies with social services to its clients. It has created a distinctive
presence in global media and discussions of foreign policy.
ISIS aspires to be a state; the Islamic State in Syria, Iraq, the Levant, and
elsewhere. But it has much larger ambitions. The Caliphate, if successful,
would eventually expand to the ummah, the entire community of the Islamic
faithful. It harkens back to the past as it points toward the future; it is thus pre-
national and post-national, pre-colonial and post-colonial, pre-realist and
post-realist. In this quest, ISIS aims at continuing the deconstruction and
reconstruction of the remains of the old empires. The most immediate target
includes the vestiges of the former Ottoman Sultanate. But ISIS also aims to
demolish the remains of the Sykes–Picot Agreement of 1916 between Britain
and France, with the consent of Russia. This agreement, together with the
Balfour Declaration of 1917, from the United Kingdom’s Foreign Secretary
Realism, Post-Realism and ISIS 18
Post-realism, like realism, suggests that political actors are driven, if they are
to survive, by national self-interest defined primarily by considerations of
power. Post-realism, however, goes beyond self-interest and power to include
many other motivations, goals, and intentions implicit in economics, society,
and culture as well as multiple other frames — metaphors and narratives;
ideas, ideologies, and identities; mentalities and cognitions; emotions and
attitudes — that surround and give meaning to the actions of political leaders.
It does so by taking communication seriously: especially the discourses,
images, and public arts that constitute collective identity and public opinion.
These can be analysed not merely to identify self-interest and perceptions of
power and balance, but also to identify multiple other drivers of political action
(cf. Rice 2008).
the standard realist narrative. Its massed attacks have seized and held
territory such as Mosul in Iraq and al-Raqqah in Syria, at least temporarily. Its
suicide bombers recall the Japanese kamikaze pilots of World War II. The
Western response to ISIS’ use of force also has had a strong military
component, including advisors, special forces, drone strikes, conventional air
and missile bombardment, and military assistance to allied groups. In
domestic settings, standard and special police, counterinsurgency, and
intelligence units have conducted operations with varying degrees of armed
physical force (see, for example, Hayden 2016).
For post-realists, as for realists, military action does not exist for its own
sake, but is necessarily embedded in a larger political context. In the
formulation of the Prussian strategist Carl von Clausewitz (1984, 87), war is
not ‘a mere act of policy but a true political instrument, a continuation of
political activity by other means.’ Post-realism embraces a complex politics
with a three-tiered model of strategic analysis and political management.
First, leaders must compete and cooperate with other political actors to
achieve their aims. Second, they must also maintain self-control, managing
their own political reputations and identities before many different audiences.
Third, leaders must juggle multiple incommensurable political discourses to
balance and attain their diverse objectives (Beer and Hariman 1996, 387-
414).
Post-realism includes more than military actions. Hard and soft power coexist
inside a wider envelope of smart power. The leader’s toolbox includes not
only conflict but also cooperation, not only physical but also verbal behaviour.
Post-realism recognises the need to adapt to the evolving political, economic,
social, and technological complexities of asymmetric interaction in physical
and media environments, and in cyberspace. A wide variety of modalities —
military, political, diplomatic, economic, communicative, rhetorical, and
cultural — are available for use.
Economics
Culture
Radical Islam pits the dar al-Islam, the house of Islam, against the territory of
chaos or war. The leading realist of our time, Henry Kissinger, suggests that
one of the main global tensions is the conflict between radical Islam, based
on this vision, and the Westphalian state-based structure of world order. The
continuing viability of the existing state system, in his view, depends on more
than the material power of state elites. As the collapse of American foreign
policy in Vietnam clearly showed, the exercise of power ultimately depends
on the domestic and global legitimacy on which it is perceived to rest. ‘To
strike a balance between the two aspects of order — power and legitimacy,’
Kissinger (2014, 367, 371) says, ‘is the essence of statesmanship.’
Post-realism follows this realist concern and expands it. ISIS simultaneously
appears as radically illegitimate within the Western cultural system while also
confronting the legitimacy of the system itself. Western leaders must
simultaneously oppose ISIS within the existing political order while also
defending its cultural values. The apparent illegitimacy of ISIS helps leaders
to mobilise popular opposition to it. At the same time, ISIS’ outlaw status
reduces its legibility for outsiders and diminishes the ability of Western
leaders to analyse and negotiate interactions short of war. Nuanced Western
responses can be perceived as liberal weakness; excessive reactions as
imperial hypocrisy and overreach. Post-realism’s strategic emphasis on
balancing conflict and cooperation, self-presentation, and incommensurable
interpretations illuminates the deep cultural tensions embedded in such
legitimation conflicts and the delicacy of responding to them.
23 Realism in Practice
Responding to ISIS
Although elite analysts are of course aware of these dangers, they may not
recognise specific susceptibilities to entrapment in muscular realism. Western
political leaders are tempted to respond to ISIS’ violent assaults with hard
military and police power — iron fists with or without velvet gloves. When
bombs or bombers explode, and both domestic and international audiences
clamour for a response, realist scripts are activated, and can-do military
solutions are easily oversold. The clamour for ‘boots on the ground’ can soon
lead to a large occupying force, which is exactly what ISIS and similar groups
would want. Occupation confirms every claim being made about the
continued domination of the region by imperial powers enforcing a corrupt
Realism, Post-Realism and ISIS 24
It seems clear from both its publications and occupying practices that ISIS is
dedicated to the destruction of civil society — or at least the liberal
democratic civil society that now is established or developing across much of
the globe. This is the society of global news media, entertainment, and
advertising; of market economics, uniform transportation technologies, and
globalised cultures of consumption, and also rule of law, individual liberty, and
tolerant civic habits. It is the most direct threat to ISIS, and its central target:
first, in the region, but elsewhere as well, as when terrorist actions can
degrade social trust, civic habits, and political discourse in Europe and the
US. A commitment to the defence of civil society has to be undertaken with
care, however, as the same cultural habitus comes with all the baggage of
colonial domination, economic exploitation, and assertions of cultural
superiority, as well as the destruction of traditional cultures still vitally
important in daily life. The post-realist emphasis on reflexive analysis applies
directly here.
The focus on civil society encompasses several other post-realist themes that
are also relevant to the struggle against ISIS. The distinction between inside/
outside, the domestic and the international sphere, obviously is set aside not
due to an idealist temperament, but for strategic reasons. Across national
boundaries, economic development and corresponding social justice
concerns become crucial - and a potential advantage against an adversary
whose primary economic opportunity is military service. Although economic
progress is not a complete solution, it is essential.
ISIS has revealed that a productive stability probably needs more than the
brokering of existing national interests by outside powers and local elites.
This awakening has been purchased at a horrific price — and made worse by
the fact that it was unnecessary, had others been willing to do more than
manage an impoverished status quo. The vision of modernisation had died —
in both its Soviet and American emplotments — but all that had replaced it
was the calculation of interests and balancing of power. That is not enough.
It never was, nor will be.
References
Bacevich, Andrew J. 2016. America’s War for the Greater Middle East: A
Military History. New York: Random House.
Beer, Francis A. 2013. “NATO Now and Then: Alliance Agents and Structures
in Anarchical International Society.” E-International Relations, 27 August.
(http://www.e-ir.info/2013/08/27/nato-now-and-then-alliance-agents-and-
structures-in-anarchical-international-society/ accessed 21 August 2017)
Beer, Francis A. and Robert Hariman (eds). 1996. Post-realism: The rhetorical
turn in international relations. East Lansing: Michigan State University Press.
27 Realism in Practice
Bew, John. 2015. Realpolitik: A History. New York: Oxford University Press.
Bull, Hedley. 2012. The Anarchical Society: A study of order in world politics.
4th ed. New York: Columbia University Press.
Cohen, Shuki J., Arie Kruglanski, Michele J. Gelfand, David Webber, and
Rohan Gunaratna. 2016. “Al-Qaeda’s propaganda decoded: A
psycholinguistic system for detecting variations in terrorism ideology.”
Terrorism and Political Violence 5(9): 1–30.
Elman, Colin and Michael Jensen (eds). 2014. The realism reader. 1st
edition. London: Routledge.
Harris, David. 2014. “The Islamic State’s (ISIS, ISIL) Magazine.” Clarion
Project. (http://www.clarionproject.org/news/islamic-state-isis-isil-propaganda-
magazine-dabiq accessed 10 September 2016)
Realism, Post-Realism and ISIS 28
Kendall, Elisabeth. 2015. “Al-Qa’ida & Islamic state in Yemen: A battle for
local audiences”. (https://www.academia.edu/15757466/Al-Qaida_and_
Islamic_State_in_Yemen_A_Battle_for_Local_Audiences accessed 21 August
2017)
Legro, Jeffrey W. and Andrew Moravcsik. 1999. “Is Anybody Still a Realist?”
International Security 24(2): 5–55.
Murray, Robert W. (ed). 2016. System, Society & the World: Exploring the
English School of International Relations. 2nd edition. Bristol: E-International
Relations Publishing.
Nance, Malcolm. 2016. Defeating ISIS: Who They Are, How They Fight, What
They Believe. New York: Skyhorse.
Simpson, Emile. 2013. War From the Ground Up: Twenty-First Century
Combat as Politics. Oxford: Oxford University Press.
29 Realism in Practice
3
The Past, Present and Future of
Realism
A R A SH H E YD AR IAN PA SH AK H A N LOU
The leading proponent of defensive realism, Kenneth Waltz, and the most
influential advocate of offensive realism, John Mearsheimer, both maintain
that their respective theories continue to be the most powerful lenses for
understanding international politics in the post-Cold War world (Waltz 1997,
916; Waltz 2004, 6; Mearsheimer 2001, 168, 361). The present chapter will
put this proposition to test by evaluating the merits of Waltz’s defensive
1
Kenneth Waltz’s defensive realism only considers global hegemony where there is
only one great power in the international system. Under such conditions, the
international system is said to be unipolar as there are no other ‘poles’ or states that
can balance the power of the hegemon. John Mearsheimer’s offensive realism however
makes a distinction between global and regional hegemons. The former dominate the
entire planet while the latter rules over a continent (Mearsheimer 2001, 40).
The Past, Present and Future of Realism 30
realism and Mearsheimer’s offensive realism in this new order where the
United States has clearly emerged as the leading power (Pashakhanlou
2009; Pashakhanlou 2013; Pashakhanlou 2014; Pashakhanlou 2016).2
Specifically, this chapter will examine the theories of Waltz and Mearsheimer
against their own empirical analysis of the post-Cold War era to verify
whether they can account for contemporary international relations.
The result of this inquiry indicates that none of these theories could have had
any explanatory power in the post-Cold War world, if assessed on their own
terms. This is because neither Waltz’s defensive realism nor Mearsheimer’s
offensive realism is equipped to account for interstate relations under
hegemony3 and unipolarity4, a condition which both scholars argue has
characterised the international system with the ascendency of the United
States after the end of the Cold War in their later writings.
This argument is advanced over the remainder of this chapter. The first
section explains how the theories of Waltz and Mearsheimer will be assessed
and highlights the utility of this approach. The second section is dedicated to
the defensive realism of Waltz. Here, his theory is outlined along with his
empirical analysis of the post-Cold War world. The inability of Waltz’s
defensive realism to account for international politics under hegemony and
unipolarity are also highlighted here. The ensuing section is devoted to the
offensive realism of Mearsheimer. This segment provides an overview of his
offensive realism, empirical assessment of the post-Cold War era and an
explanation of why hegemony and unipolarity invariably create anomalies for
his theory. A conclusion that briefly summarises the preceding points and
argues for the need of new theories of international politics brings this chapter
to a closure. At this point, it is however appropriate to take a closer look at
how the defensive and offensive realism of Waltz and Mearsheimer will be
assessed.
2
Although there has been a debate on whether the post-Cold War world has been
unipolar, multipolar or something else, there is a widespread agreement that the United
States has been the most powerful state in the international system ever since the fall
of the Soviet Union.
3
As has been noted, Mearsheimer’s offensive realism makes a distinction between
regional and global hegemony. In the former case, only the region dominated by a
hegemon becomes an anomaly to Mearsheimer’s theory. In the presence of a global
hegemon, the entire world however becomes incomprehensible to his offensive realism.
Since Waltz’s defensive realism only considers global hegemony, the entire
international system becomes an anomaly to his theory in the presence of a hegemon.
4
As will be demonstrated, the enduring features of the international system (such as
anarchy) are not enough to save either Waltz’s defensive realism or Mearsheimer’s
offensive realism. Hegemony and unipolarity pose inherent difficulties for both theories
that make them defunct irrespective of other structural features of the system.
31 Realism in Practice
Theory Assessment
First, as has already been mentioned, this investigation puts to test what
Waltz and Mearsheimer themselves claim for their theory – that their theories
still retain their explanatory power in the post-Cold War era. The great
advantage of this approach is that it can no longer be claimed that the criteria
for evaluation is not suitable for the theories in question as could have been
the case if the theories would have been examined against externally derived
criteria from the works of Karl Popper, Imre Lakatos, Thomas Kuhn, etc. (see
Jackson and Nexon 2009; Moravcsik 2003 and Waltz 1997).
Third, the explanatory power of both theories are evaluated against Waltz’s
and Mearsheimer’s own empirical analysis of the post-Cold War world rather
than my own interpretation of this era or that of others. Altogether, this
evaluation of the explanatory power of Waltz’s defensive realism and
Mearsheimer’s offensive realism presents an easy test for their theories. This
is evident as they are evaluated against the principles of the theorists
themselves and their own empirical analysis of the post-Cold War era. If the
theories cannot pass such an easy test, their validity is seriously called into
question (George and Bennett 2005, 122). With that said, we can now turn
our attention to the theories themselves, starting with Waltz’s defensive
realism.
5
For other influential defensive realist statements, see for example Jervis 1976; Walt
1987; Snyder 1991.
The Past, Present and Future of Realism 32
capabilities from his theory (Waltz 1979, 99). Moreover, Waltz (1979, 91–2,
118–9) only makes two explicit assumptions regarding states: that they are
unitary actors and that they, at minimum, pursue policies to ensure their own
survival.
Since Waltz (1979, 105, 118) assumes that states are unitary actors that only
differ in their capabilities and have to take care of themselves in the anarchic
system, the balance of power becomes an ‘iron law’ as states can only assure
their survival by making sure that none of their rivals grow too powerful. The
balance of power is the dynamic part of Waltz’s otherwise static theoretical
model as he contends that the number of great powers, who possess the
greatest capabilities, makes up the balance or the poles of the international
system and shape its character (1979, 129–130, 144). In this regard, the
differentiations are between a bipolar system where the balance is maintained
by two great powers and a multipolar system in which the anarchic system is
inhabited by three or more great powers (Waltz 1979, 161). In Waltz’s view, a
bipolar world is more stable than a multipolar world since ‘uncertainties about
who threatens whom, about who will oppose whom, and about who will gain
or lose from the actions of other states accelerate as the number of states
increases’ (1979, 165).
It is not hard to see why Waltz consistently points out that unipolarity will be
short-lived and that the world will become multipolar in the future. His theory
does, after all, assume that states will balance against a preponderant power
no matter how benign the hegemon might be (Waltz 2000b, 30).
Consequently, Waltz (2000b, 30, 36–8) maintains that American power will be
checked in the blink of an eye, historically speaking. Waltz (2000b, 36–8) is
also careful to point out that the United States cannot do anything to solidify
33 Realism in Practice
its hegemony, as a new balancing coalition will be formed against it, no matter
what measures the US takes to prevent such an outcome.6 Waltz himself
specifically acknowledges that the balancing principle that his theory is based
on suggests that American hegemony and unipolarity will be replaced by a
multipolar system (2000b, 30). Waltz asserts that the European Union or a
German-led coalition, China, Japan, and in a more distant future Russia will
be the most likely balancers in this new constellation.
6
In this regard, Waltz writes: ‘the task will exceed America’s economic, military,
demographic, and political resources; and the very effort to maintain a hegemonic
position is the surest way to undermine it. The effort to maintain dominance stimulates
some countries to work to overcome it (2000b, 38).’ Waltz also notes that ‘[t]he United
States cannot prevent a new balance of power from forming. It can hasten its coming
as it has been earnestly doing.’ (2000b, 36–7)’
The Past, Present and Future of Realism 34
balanced the might of the other and moderated the behaviour of both of them.
Now the only superpower left in the field is free to act on its whims and follow
its fancies’ (2004, 5). Waltz goes on to postulate that in a unipolar world there
are no longer any checks and balances on the hegemon. Its behaviour is
instead determined by its own internal policies rather than external structural
pressures (Waltz 2003, 5).
This revelation suggests that Waltz’s (2004, 3) theory that ‘explains how
external forces shape states’ behaviour, but says nothing about the effects of
internal forces’ as he himself points out, cannot account for the hegemon in
unipolarity. If we consider Waltz’s own arguments – that a) there are hardly
any external forces on the hegemon in a unipolarity and that its behaviour is
instead determined by its own internal forces and b) that his defensive
realism can only explain how external forces affect state behaviour and have
nothing to say about the effects of internal forces, the only conclusion that
can be drawn is that his theory is inherently unequipped to account for the
behaviour of the hegemon.
It is also important to note that it is not only the behaviour of the sole great
power in the international system – the hegemon – that becomes an anomaly
to Waltz’s defensive realism under unipolarity but the entire system as a
whole. This is evident when Waltz maintains that: ‘[i]n systems theory,
structure is a generative notion; and the structure of a system is generated by
the interactions of its principal parts [the great power(s)]’ as the ‘fates of all
the states … are affected much more by the acts and the interactions of the
major ones than of the minor ones’ (1979, 72). For this reason, Waltz claims
that his general theory of international politics is based on the great powers
but applies to lesser states ‘insofar as their interactions are insulated from the
intervention of the great powers of a system’ (Waltz 1979, 73).
Hence, since Waltz’s theory is admittedly based on the great powers and can
only account for the behaviour of other states in so far as they can be induced
from that of the great power(s), it must consequently mean that his defensive
realism cannot account for smaller states either in unipolarity as it is
incapable of explaining the behaviour of the only great power in the system
under these conditions. As such, Waltz’s state-centric theory of international
politics becomes inherently unable to account for any state behaviour under
unipolarity. This is why the entire system becomes unexplainable by his
theory. Indeed, since Waltz has argued that the international system has in
fact been characterised by American hegemony since the end of the Cold
War in his writings after 1993, this must mean that his theory cannot have had
any explanatory power in the post-Cold War world, if assessed on its own
terms.
35 Realism in Practice
In sum, the entire post-Cold War period has thus far been anomalous to
Waltz’s defensive realism and it has been unable to account for what it is
designed to do: explain ‘international outcomes’ or ‘a small number of big and
important things’ (Waltz 1986, 329; Waltz 1996, 54–7).
Offensive realism can, however, not explain international politics under the
condition of hegemony. Mearsheimer makes this point clear when he writes
that; ‘[i]f one state achieves hegemony, the system ceases to be anarchic and
7
For other offensive realist publications, see for example Elman 2004; Labs 1997;
Layne 2000.
The Past, Present and Future of Realism 36
In his earlier work prior to 2012, Mearsheimer does however not acknowledge
that the United States has been the global hegemon. It can thus not be
argued that offensive realism has been unable to explain the entire world on
basis of these writings. In these publications, Mearsheimer (2001, 40, 141,
381) maintains that the post-Cold War era has been multipolar rather than
unipolar, with the United States, China and Russia as the great powers. This
assertion however creates major inconsistencies between Mearsheimer’s
theoretical and empirical analysis of international politics.
First, Mearsheimer posits that a state must have the military might ‘to put up a
serious fight against’ the most formidable power in the international system to
qualify as a great power (2001, 40, 528 n. 60). Mearsheimer however claims
that the main competitor of the United States in the post-Cold World, China,
‘does not possess a formidable military today and it is certainly in no position
to pick a fight with the United States … even in the Asia-Pacific region’ (2010,
384–5). As such, Mearsheimer’s own empirical analysis suggests that China
does not satisfy offensive realism’s defining criterion of a great power. If
China cannot be regarded as a great power, then neither can Russia, since
Mearsheimer considers Russia as the weaker of the two (2006, 119–120).
Mearsheimer’s offensive realism, see for example Donnelly 2006; Lake 2009.
37 Realism in Practice
The only explanation that could account for these major discrepancies
between Mearsheimer’s theoretical and empirical analysis of international
politics is that the United States is the sole great power in the international
system and that the post-Cold War world has been unipolar rather than
multipolar. This could explain why the US has managed to dominate the world
and the reason why China and Russia have not balanced against the United
States. For these reasons, it is not hard to see why even Mearsheimer has
endorsed the view that America is the global hegemon on numerous
occasions from 2012 and onwards. This is apparent when Mearsheimer
(2012, 5–6, emphasis added) suggests that
[w]hat’s happened over the past 23 years [after the end of the
Cold War in 1989] is that the distribution of power—call it
unipolarity, American primacy, or whatever you want—has left
the US free to misbehave… A world with the Soviet Union or
its equivalent is fundamentally different from the post-Cold War
world. As I said before, the architecture of the system doesn’t
discipline the US anymore. So, it’s free to run around the world
doing all sorts of foolish things.
As has been demonstrated, unipolarity means that the entire world becomes
hierarchic by the standards of offensive realism, which is a condition that
Mearsheimer himself acknowledges that his theory is unable to explain. This
means that the offensive realism of Mearsheimer cannot have had any
explanatory power at all in the post-Cold War world, if evaluated on its own
terms.
Conclusion
This chapter has evaluated the explanatory power of the two main theories of
structural realism, Waltz’s defensive realism and Mearsheimer’s offensive
realism, in the post-Cold War world. The findings of this inquiry suggest that
neither Waltz’s defensive realism nor Mearsheimer’s offensive realism could
have had any explanatory power in the post-Cold War era, if assessed on
their own terms. Indeed, both of these scholars have themselves
acknowledged that the post-Cold War environment has been characterised by
American hegemony and unipolarity, a condition which their structural realist
theories are admittedly incapable to account for. It is thus clear that although
both of these realist statements purport to focus on great power politics, they
are ironically unable to explain international politics once a state reaches the
pinnacle of power, hegemony, as the United States managed to do after the
end of the Cold War according to both Waltz and Mearsheimer. The inability
of these structural realist theories to shed light on international relations will
also continue as long as unipolarity ensues. For these reasons, new general
realist theories of international politics need to be developed that can succeed
where the defensive realism of Waltz and the offensive realism of
Mearsheimer have failed.
References
George, Alexander and Andrew Bennett. 2005. Case Studies and Theory
Development in the Social Sciences. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.
Labs, Eric. 1997. “Beyond Victory: Offensive Realism and the Expansion of
War Aims”. Security Studies 6(4): 1–49.
Layne, Christopher. 2002. “The ‘Poster Child for Offensive Realism’: America
as a Global Hegemon”. Security Studies 12(2): 120–164.
Mearsheimer, John. 2001. The Tragedy of Great Power Politics. New York:
WW Norton and Company.
The Past, Present and Future of Realism 40
Mearsheimer, John and Stephen Walt. 2013. “Leaving Theory Behind: Why
Simplistic Hypothesis Testing Is Bad for International Relations” European
Journal of International Relations 19(3): 427–457.
Walt, Stephen. 1987. The Origins of Alliances. Ithaca, NY: Cornell University
Press.
Waltz, Kenneth. 1959. Man the State and War: A Theoretical Analysis. New
York: Columbia University Press.
Waltz, Kenneth. 2000b. “Structural Realism after the Cold War”. International
Security 25(1): 5–41.
4
When Hard Power Shrinks: The
Midlife Crisis of Realism
TON Y C . L E E
This chapter scrutinises the midlife crisis of realism through its most essential
theoretic construct: power. Having identified several problems in realism’s
conception of power, I argue that the theory has lost its momentum as a
dominant theory in international relations. This chapter starts by reviewing the
concept of power advocated by several schools of realism. This review is
followed by a critique exposing realism’s major ‘power issues.’ The case of
China is then analysed as it seems to particularly challenge the realist
concept of power. The analysis leads to a discussion about the (uncertain)
future of realism.
1
However, recent interpretations regarding Machiavelli and Hobbes’s perspective of
power are more nuanced. For example, some authors suggest that Hobbes’s notion of
international anarchy refers to the anarchy of pre-political societies outside the ordered
system of European states, instead of that of interstate relations later posited by
realism (Moloney 2011).
When Hard Power Shrinks: The Midlife Crisis of Realism 44
If both classical and structural realists share the view that international politics
is a continuous struggle for power, the two camps show divides when it
comes to the driving force behind this struggle. For the latter, it is the anarchic
system in international relations, and not human instinct, which prompts
states to pursue power in order to ensure their security (Waltz 1989, 43).
criteria enable Waltz to rank the overall capabilities of states and display the
distribution of power in the international system. Despite his resistance
against a relation-oriented power definition, he proposes that ‘an agent is
powerful to the extent that he affects others more than they affect him’ – a
notion close to Deutsch’s (1953) relational power approach (Baldwin 2013,
285). Structural realists, like their classical counterparts, also privilege
military force in their conception of power. Waltz argues that ‘in international
politics [military] force serves not only as the ultimate ratio, but also as the
first and constant one (Waltz 1979, 113).’ States’ differences in military forces
and other secondary elements result in a relative distribution of capabilities in
the international system, which is the major independent variable explaining
dependent variables such as wars, alliances, and the balance of power
(Schmidt 2007, 54). As a result, power is a means to the end of security
(Waltz 1989, 40).
The above view divides structural realists into two branches: ‘defensive
realism’ because it perceives states to be ‘security maximising-oriented’ and
as only seeking sufficient power to maintain this security; and secondly,
‘offensive realism’ because it sees states to be ‘power maximising-oriented’ in
order to assure their survival in an anarchic international system. The latter
branch goes so far to claim that all great powers have revisionist aims and
pursue expansionist policies (see Mearsheimer 2001). Consequently,
offensive realists embrace military power even more (e.g. the size and
strength of the army) than their defensive counterparts do.
Several variants of realism maintain the assumption that the struggle for
power and the anarchic world are states’ motives for pursuing power, but they
are on different level of analysis and independent variables when explaining
international outcomes such as wars. Neoclassical realists, for instance,
argue that the analysis of states’ behaviours (mainly foreign policy) should
take into account both domestic and structural levels (Walt 2002). Hence,
Schweller believes that ‘complex domestic political processes act as
transmission belts that channel, mediate, and (re)direct policy outputs in
response to external forces (i.e. changes in relative power) (2004, 164).’
Neoclassical realists also insist that military force is the major constituent of
power. However, unlike their classical and structural counterparts, neo-
classical realists claim that it is decision-makers’ perception of power – rather
than power itself - that matters in international politics (Wohlforth 1993, 2;
Rose 1998, 147). Neoclassical realists moreover elaborate on the notion of
‘state power’ in reference to the ability of the government apparatus to
‘extract national power for its ends (Zakaria 1998, 38-9).’ Neoclassical
realists inherit the idea from classical realism that a nation defines its interest
When Hard Power Shrinks: The Midlife Crisis of Realism 46
in accordance to its power. That is, when the overall capability of a state
increases, the state will pursue greater power in order to control the external
environment, and vice versa. The struggle for power, to the neoclassical
realists, is one important means permitting states to influence and control
their living and external environment. In this sense, states are more
‘influence-maximising oriented’ than ‘power-maximising oriented’ or ‘security-
maximising oriented’ (Zakaria 1998).
Several scholars (Baldwin 2013; Schmidt 2007; Grieco 2007) have pointed
out severe deficiencies in realism’s conception of power, which results in the
debate about the worthy existence of realism as a theory. While some evoke
the death of realism (Kapstein 1995, 149), I would suggest that realism is
experiencing a midlife crisis. This view is related to realism’s incomplete
achievement and the decreasing importance of military power.
2
The term ‘midlife crisis,’ first coined by the psychologist Elliot Jaques in 1965, is
employed here in a metaphoric fashion to depict the struggling state and the
dysfunction of power in realism. After all, midlife crisis ‘commonly involves reflection on
what the individual has done with his or her life up to that point, often with feelings that
not enough has been accomplished (Mendez 2008, 565; see also Edwards and Byrd
2008).’
3
Some scholars disagree that hard power equates to military force because hard
power is mostly a contrary concept of soft power. For the concept of soft power and its
comparison to hard power, see Nye (1990; 2004; 2011). They also suggest that military
force is only one form of power. However, given the supreme role of military force in
realism’s conception of power, I use hard power and military force in an
interchangeable fashion.
47 Realism in Practice
and air forces, etc. Some branches of realism value military force as the only
means in a country’s offensive policies.
Today’s states do not abandon hard power, but they no longer prioritise it as
they did before. Since the end of Cold War, major powers in the West have
tended to limit their military expenditure to less than 3% of their GDP.4 There
is a prevailing belief that building mutual trust is more effective to retain peace
than engaging in armament competition that leads to security dilemma.
Moreover, imposing economic sanctions—and not resorting to military
forces—stands as a frequent measure for major powers to deal with
international conflicts. Such a tendency can be observed in the international
community’s reaction regarding North Korea’s continuous development of its
nuclear arsenal in 2013 and 2016, or to Russia’s invasion of Ukraine/Crimea
in 2014.
4
See SIPRI Military Expenditure Database, https://www.sipri.org/databases/milex
When Hard Power Shrinks: The Midlife Crisis of Realism 48
is where soft power can better justify its existence and legitimacy than hard
power. Soft power, a term coined by Joseph Nye, is a concept inspired by
Bachrach and Baratz’s (1962; 1963) ‘second face of power.’ Nye (1990, 31)
sees soft power as ‘an indirect way to exercise power other than resting on
inducements (carrots) or threats (sticks).’ He defines soft power to be ‘getting
others to want what you want’ and explains that ‘co-optive [soft] power can
rest on the attraction of one’s ideas or on the ability to set the political agenda
in a way that shapes the preferences that others express.’ For the difference
between soft power and hard power, Nye argues that
Governments now are more willing to develop their soft power by designing
relevant policy tools such as establishing overseas cultural institutes,
propagating ideology through global broadcasting services, exporting higher
education, promoting tourism, etc. Soft power has also become one of the
major indexes when analysts attempt to measure a state’s general capacity
(Treverton and Seth 2005). In a sense, the struggle for power today has a
new meaning: to use soft power to attract more allies is a better approach to
secure a state’s survival than to use hard power to annihilate enemies.
Even today, China continues to go astray from the power trajectory posited by
realism. Looking back at its historical account of wars, the People’s Republic
of China (PRC) can hardly be qualified as a ‘rational actor’ in the way realism
understands the term. The Sino-Vietnamese War in 1979 well illustrates
China’s uncommon behaviours in world politics. The war, also surnamed as
‘The Punishing War,’ was driven by China’s intention to punish Vietnam for
attacking its protégé, the communist Cambodia of Pol Pot, and for siding with
the Soviet Union. In the war, the Chinese People’s Liberation Army (PLA)
dominated the Viet Cong army and seized several important sites in both
North and South Vietnam within a month. Once it had declared victory,
however, China surprisingly withdrew itself from the occupied regions. Similar
patterns can be discerned in the Sino-Indian War in 1962 and China’s quasi-
war over Zhenbao Island against the Soviet Union in 1969 (Shih 1993).
Nevertheless, China’s conduct in world politics so far does not allow realists
to qualify it as a ‘revisionist state’5 who, following their logic, should always
have been seeking to overturn the American hegemony; nor does the rising of
China result in instability in East Asia or beyond. Overall, the rising of China
does not affect the stability of the current unipolar international system. The
‘China threat’ evaluated by much of the realist analyses is mainly grounded
on China’s building-up of hard power. However, in recent years, China’s
enthusiasm for developing soft power programs implies that hard power is no
longer the sole priority in Chinese foreign policy.
Since 2003, China has been undertaking even more efforts on developing its
soft power in order to shape an image of peaceful rising. In 2014, the annual
report made public by the Chinese People’s Political Consultative Conference
(CPPCC) explained that the PRC’s military expenditure only occupied 1.4% of
the country’s GNP (gross national product).6 Meanwhile, China has been
developing tools to increase its soft power in the world. These efforts include
support for infrastructure-related projects in Africa and Latin America, the
creation of the Confucius Institutes for promoting the Chinese language and
culture worldwide, media such as the CCTV and China Radio International to
broadcast about the ‘good’ China, and the hosting of important international
events such as Olympic Games or World Exhibitions to increase international
exposure. Comparing to the past, contemporary China is also more inclined
to conform to international norms on issue areas like free trade, nuclear non-
proliferation and environmental protection.
Overall, the rise of China does not follow the scenario of realism, for two
reasons. First, military forces are not the most important means to exercise
power for China. Soft power comes as an important strategy in China’s recent
foreign policy-making. In addition, China’s use of military force can be
somehow irrational, as we have observed from its historical track. Second,
China does not act like a ‘revisionist state.’ It does not strive to change the
current balance of power; nor is it keen on immediately becoming the next
superpower by engaging in war with the US.
5
Structural realist uses the term ‘revisionist state’ to portray a state’s intention to use
forces in order to alter the balance of power. It opposes to a ‘status-quo state’ who
prefers to maintain the current balance.
6
See http://news.xinhuanet.com/english/special/2014-03/05/c_133161044.htm
(accessed 20 June 2016). However, many countries, international organisations, and
think tanks contest the transparency of this report and believe that the PRC’s military
budget already reached 2.3% of its GNP in 2003 and grows at a rate of 7% to 10%
annually, although such rate is still far behind that of the United States. See http://www.
globalsecurity.org/military/world/china/budget.htm (accessed 20 June 2016)
51 Realism in Practice
Can realism cope with the struggle of achievement and solve the midlife
crisis? Despite significant amendments of several ‘neo’ schools, realism still
suffers from empirical inconsistency. The reason is straightforward – its
fundamental principles of power never change: neo-classical realists still
favour the concept of the balance of power when explaining international
conflicts, structural realists still believe in a bipolar international system
headed by the US and China in the future, and offensive realists never give
up the superior means of hard power in world politics. Consequently, there is
no room for optimism regarding the future of realism. Kapstein (1995)
acknowledges that the dissidents of realism point out several fatal flaws of the
theory, but he also argues that the theory cannot be overthrown as long as
there is no better theory to replace it thoroughly. However, such an argument
is irrelevant. For the very existence of a theory depends on its ability to
explain and to predict the occurrence of a phenomenon, and not on the
existence (or not) of another (dominant) theory. A problematic theory will
eventually lose its attraction in front of its public with or without the
emergence of a better theory. If realism is unable to readjust its conception of
power by theoretically taking into account the equal importance of other faces
of power and by empirically looking at the international outcomes beyond the
Western sphere, it will be difficult to expect a rejuvenation after the midlife
crisis.
References
Carr, Edward H. 1964. The Twenty Years’ Crisis: 1919–1939. New York:
Harper & Row.
Cohen, Warren I. 2000. East Asia at the Center: Four Thousand Years of
Engagement with the World. New York: Columbia University Press.
Gilpin, Robert. 1981. War and Change in World Politics. New York:
Cambridge University Press.
Grieco, Joseph M. 2007. “Structural Realism and the Problem of Polarity and
War”. Power in World Politics, edited by F. Berenskoetter and M. J Williams,
64–82. New York: Routledge.
Knorr, Klaus. 1966. On the Uses of Military Power in the Nuclear Age. New
Jersey: Princeton University Press.
Mearsheimer, John J. 2001. The Tragedy of Great Power Politics. New York:
W. W. Norton.
Morgenthau, Hans J. 1954. Politics among Nations: The Struggle for Power
and Peace. 2nd ed. Chicago, IL: University of Chicago Press.
Nye, Joseph. 2004. Soft Power: The Means to Success in World Politics. New
York: Public Affairs.
Nye, Joseph. 2011. The Future of Power. New York: Public Affairs.
Roy, Denny. 1996. “The ‘China Threat’ Issue: Major Arguments”. Asian Survey
36(8): 758–771.
Shih, Chih-Yu. 1993. China’s Just World: The Morality of Chinese Foreign
Policy. Colorado: Lynne Rienner Publisher.
Stiglitz, Joseph E. and Linda Bilmes. 2008. The Three Trillion Dollar War: The
True Cost of the Iraq Conflict. New York: Norton.
When Hard Power Shrinks: The Midlife Crisis of Realism 54
Wills, John E. 2010. Past and Present in China’s Foreign Policy: From ‘Tribute
System’ to ‘Peaceful Rise’. Portland, ME: Merwin Asia.
5
Realism and Power Transition
Theory: Different Branches of
the Power Tree
C AR ST E N R AU C H
After the end of the Cold War, realism or, to be more precise, almost all power
based approaches to International Relations, have been largely written off by
scholars for their failure to predict the conflict’s ending, as well as for their
inability to deal with the phenomena that became most relevant for IR in the
decades that followed, for example norms, ideas, the impact of regime types
and so on.
However, the comeback of great power conflicts and the blatancy of global
power shifts has led to a kind of resurgence of theoretical approaches that
focus on the role of power. In Syria and Ukraine the US and Russia are
supporting different sides, and Cold War frontlines seem to re-emerge.
Considering the fate of Ukraine (a country that voluntarily gave up its nuclear
weapons after the Cold War for security assurances by the great powers
including Russia), some scholars have even begun to wonder whether
realists who praised nuclear deterrence (and thus warned countries that had
already acquired nuclear weapons not to give them up) were not right after
all. And considering the meteoric rise of China, scholars are increasingly
beginning to utilise the theoretical lens of power transition theory (PTT) to
evaluate its potential impact on international security (Lee 2015; Kim and
Gates 2015; Lim 2014; Jeffery 2009; Levy 2008; Lemke and Tammen 2006).
But even though both, realism and PTT, emphasise the influence of
international power constellations, it makes a stark difference which of the
two approaches one uses for assessing the international situation. While both
are often merged together (mostly by scholars who subscribe to neither), it is
Realism and Power Transition Theory: Different Branches of the Power Tree 56
important to regard and embrace them as different branches of the power tree
that, most of the time and despite some common roots, lead to quite different
analyses and policy prescriptions.
Realism and power transition theory are both well-known approaches to the
study of international politics, so it might suffice to summarise them in a
nutshell here. Realism can be traced back to thinkers like Machiavelli and
Hobbes. Modern proponents include scholars like Hans Joachim Morgenthau
(1954), Kenneth Waltz (1979) and John J. Mearsheimer (2001), among many
others. After classical realism had put much emphasis on human nature and
the animus dominandi, more recent versions have rather focused on the
structure of the international system (anarchy), the functionality of the units
(same) and the distribution of capabilities. Waltz famously explained that only
two requirements are necessary for his theory to work: ‘that the order be
anarchic and that it be populated by units wishing to survive’ (Waltz 1979,
121). Whenever these conditions are met, Waltz maintained, balance-of-
power politics prevail. Balance-of-power theory in turn can be summarised as
arguing ‘that changes in the distribution of power are often dangerous’ (Lobell
2016, 33).
‘realist power transition theory’ (see for example Silvius 2014; Khoo 2013; He
and Feng 2013; Herrington 2011; Changhe 2008; Christensen 2001). On the
following pages I challenge this view and highlight the differences between
realism (more specifically balance-of-power realism) and power transition
theory.
The first central difference that I want to highlight in this article concerns the
question of how a system should be configured to achieve the highest
possible stability and peacefulness. All kinds of realism are united in that they
believe that a harmony of interests between the differing powers in the
international system is only an illusion and that interests are rather colliding
constantly. In order to ensure peace among these conflicting interests, a
stable balance of power is necessary. ‘From the perspective of balance-of-
power theorists, the power preponderance of a single state or of a coalition of
states is highly undesirable because the preponderant actor is likely to
engage in aggressive behavior’ (Paul 2004, 5). When this balance of power is
disturbed or when one power strives to (and succeeds in) enhancing its
power position disproportionately, war becomes likely (Lobell 2016, 33).
Thus, those who want to preserve peace would be wise to organise their
foreign policy (and choice of alliance partners) in a way that preserves or
restores the balance of power in the international system.
imbalance and the most powerful state is predominant. Only in such a case is
the result of an armed conflict clearly foreseeable and it thus does not make
sense for either side to risk it. ‘A preponderance of power on the one side [...]
increases the chances of peace, for the greatly stronger side need not fight at
all to get what it wants, while the weaker side would be plainly foolish to
attempt to battle for what it wants’ (Organski 1968, 294–5). In cases where
predominance is not established and either side can conceivably hope for
victory (or at least for preventing defeat), war is a much more attractive
option. Therefore, a main difference between balance-of-power realism and
PTT is, as Tammen and Kugler put it: ‘Under balance of power, relative power
equilibrium insures the peace. Under power parity or power transition, relative
power equilibrium increases the probability of war’ (Tammen and Kugler 2006,
40, Footnote 6).
Parity – in the sense of PTT – means that in a dyad or group of states all
participating states have a comparable amount of power (usually +/- 20%
constitutes the corridor of parity, that is a power A with 100 units of power is in
parity with all other powers that have between 80 and 120 units of power).
The (political) relations between these powers are not relevant. A balance, on
the other hand, is in effect in the international (or a regional) system when
there is equilibrium between the most important alliances taken together,
while the power-relation between single protagonists might be subject to
grave disparities. Figure 1 illustrates this with different models or ideal-types
of power constellations.
59 Realism in Practice
Model 1 in the upper left shows four great powers with a similar amount of
power. As all great powers are in the 80% corridor of the dominant power,
there is a situation of parity between them. As they are also organised in two
opposing alliances of equal strength we can also say that the system is
balanced. Model 2 in the lower left shows a system with five great powers.
There is one power (state A) that is clearly predominant. No other state
reaches at least 80% of its power capacity; thus there is no parity. At the
same time, A is allied with the weakest power (state B) so that the combined
capacity of their alliance equals that of the alliance made up of C, D and E.
The system is thus in balance.
In Model 3 in the upper right we have five powers again, but this time of equal
strength, thus creating a five-way parity. However, as the alliance of A and B
is much weaker than the alliance of C, D and E, the system is in imbalance.
Finally, Model 4 in the lower right shows a system where there is neither
balance, nor parity. Among the five great powers in the system, state A is
clearly predominant. This mirrors Model 2. However, differing from Model 2,
the two alliances in this system are not balanced. A is not allied with the
Realism and Power Transition Theory: Different Branches of the Power Tree 60
weakest power (as in model 2) but with the second strongest power (state B).
The alliance of A and B is thus much more powerful than the opposing
alliance of C, D and E; the system is therefore in imbalance.
The four models in Figure 1 thus show different possibilities for relating parity
and balance to each other under different configurations of power and
alliances. As we can see, there are configurations that can be seen as both
(Model 1) or neither (Model 4) in balance and/or in parity. Models 2 and 3
furthermore show that there are situations possible in which a power
configuration is in balance, but not parity – or vice versa. Depending on which
concept (and underlying theoretical reasoning) one uses, differing valuations
of these configurations become possible. If we do not properly differentiate
between the two concepts, proponents of PTT, for example, might accuse
realists of certifying Model 3 a relatively high peacefulness, given the
distribution of power among the five actors shows a situation of parity.
However, Model 3 might show parity but still no real balance of power as the
alliance CDE is clearly stronger than alliance AB.
Ceteris paribus – and in a simplified way – realism and PTT agree on the
relative peacefulness of these models in two of the four cases, that is when
parity and balance do not concur (Model 2 and 3). In Model 2 with no parity
but balance both would suggest that the system will likely be rather peaceful;
in Model 3 with no balance but parity both would suggest that conflict is likely.
Regarding the other two models, however, realism and PTT come to contrary
conclusions. In Model 1 where we can speak of both parity and balance, PTT
expects conflict between the dominant power and at least one of the other
powers in parity, while realism expects peace through a stable balance of
power. In Model 4 where we have neither parity nor balance, PTT expects the
preponderance to foster peace, while realism fears that the imbalance might
lead to conflict.
The second central difference between the theories that I want to discuss
here relates to the fact that realism is notorious for treating the state as a
unitary actor and, even more, a black box. States are essentially the same
and only differ because of their different placement in the international system
and their different amount of capabilities (Frankel 1996, 321; Waltz 2008).
While it is true that classical realists have worked with concepts like
revolutionary and status quo powers (Aron 1966; Wolfers 1962; Kissinger
1957) and some modern realists have striven to ‘bring the revisionist state
back in’ (Schweller 1994; also see Rynning and Ringsmose 2008),
revisionism and dissatisfaction remain out of the purview of balance-of-power
61 Realism in Practice
logic. According to this logic, it is not the properties of any given state that
decides how it behaves internationally but rather the existing distribution of
power or, maybe, the distribution of threat (Walt 1987).
Power transition theory, on the other hand, depends on the unit level variable
of satisfaction with the status quo which – in order for the theory to prevent
becoming self-referential – cannot be dependent on the state’s placement in
the international order a.k.a. its amount of capabilities (Rauch 2014, 209–15).
It belongs to the core of PTT that rising powers are often (but not always)
dissatisfied with the international order, an order that – according to PTT –
has been created by the dominant power (Lemke 2004, 56–7). This
dissatisfaction stems from the fact that the order in many ways benefits its
creator along with its allies, while rising powers are being disadvantaged or at
least perceive themselves so (Tammen et al. 2000, 9). For this reason,
dissatisfied rising powers become challengers to the international order,
striving at least to reform and at most to shatter the existing order and to build
a new one. The dominant power, on the other hand, is not inclined to give up
‘its’ international order voluntarily. In order to establish a new order, the rising
power thus has to resort to the use of force (Rauch 2014, 49–52). This is why
great power war happens according to PTT. Peaceful power transitions, on
the other hand, are possible if the rising power is satisfied with the status quo
(Kim and Gates 2015, 220; Paul and Shankar 2014; Tammen et al. 2000, 26).
The power constellation thus only tells us half of the story according to PTT. It
is the combination of opportunity and motivation, of a parity-situation and
dissatisfaction that constitutes a danger for the stability of the international
order (Nolte 2010, 888; Lemke 2004, 57). (Dis-)Satisfaction is thus a variable.
Realists, on the other hand, often regard dissatisfaction – if they consider it as
all – as an analytical constant. Mearsheimer (2001, 35), for example, posits
that ‘states do not become status quo powers until they completely dominate
the system’, thereby rendering all non-dominant great powers necessarily
dissatisfied. And even if state preferences are not regarded as fixed, the logic
of the security dilemma demands to always assume the worst from your
neighbours as non-aggressive intentions might a) change quickly and b)
might diminish one’s own security (even if unintentionally).
To sum up: The most important differences (among some others) between
balance of power realism and power transition theory concern a) the different
meaning of balance and parity, which leads to differing evaluations
concerning the conflict-proneness of the same power constellation in two out
of four ideal types; and b) the different significance both approaches ascribe
to the factor of satisfaction with the status quo of the international order.
Realism and Power Transition Theory: Different Branches of the Power Tree 62
What do these differences imply for the analysis and interpretation of global
power shifts in general and the emergence and rise of powers like China and
India in particular? Utilising gross domestic product as a crude power
indicator we can describe the current global power constellation as follows.
If we take nominal GDP ratings as indicator for state power, as of 2015 the
United States is still in a leading position globally. Its GDP of 17,946,996
million current US Dollars is only slightly lower than that of the following three
powers (China, Japan and Germany) combined. Additionally, two of these
three powers (Japan and Germany) are allied with the US. Even if we look at
the rest of the top ten-ranked countries according to GDP, we find a number
of powers allied or on good terms with the United States (France, United
Kingdom, Italy and India), no committed ally of China and two powers whose
allegiance is as of yet unclear (Brazil and Russia). An imbalance of power
thus exists and it favours Washington.
The rise of China in particular (but also India and to a lesser extent Brazil)
63 Realism in Practice
becomes even more pronounced when these growth rates are projected into
the future. Taken together, the BRICS (Brazil, India, Russia, China, South
Africa) will – according to a UNDP report – surpass the combined GDP of the
Europe and the United States by 2020 (Lobell 2016, 34). China alone will –
according to Goldman Sachs – match the United States GDP by the end of
the 2020s (O’Neill and Stupnytska 2009, 24). The BRICS, however, are not a
stable alliance that would support China under all circumstances (Nossel
2016, van Agtmael 2012, Bosco 2011). While Moscow might lean closer to
Beijing given its conflicts with Washington (Sputnik News 2016), New Delhi
has in the recent years rather strengthened its ties to the United States
(Müller and Schmidt 2009, Rauch 2008). The US itself, on the other hand,
has – as has been pointed out above – a number of powerful allies in all parts
of the world, from other NATO members up to Japan and Australia. Let us try
to situate the current and expected future power constellations within the
typology introduced above: The current situation (US still much more powerful
than China, US alliance much more powerful than China and its friends) might
resemble most closely model 4 (no balance, no parity). If the rise of China
goes on as expected this might change into a situation that rather resembles
Model 2 (no balance but parity).
taken into consideration), one policy advice of PTT for the United States
would be to ensure that this power gap does not close. Preponderance brings
peace and parity is prone to war. Hence, Washington should do everything it
can to prevent a peer competitor to emerge or, at a minimum, strengthen its
own power position. On the other hand, PTT, while being alarmed by the
impending conversion of the power trajectories of the dominant and the rising
power, would also ask whether the rising powers are satisfied with the status
quo of the international order. Herein lies the key to conflict and peace. If the
rising powers are found to be extremely and irredeemably dissatisfied, then
PTT proper would suggest counter measures in the same as does balance-
of-power theory. If, however, the rising powers are found to be only slightly or
not at all dissatisfied, PTT would counsel not to risk causing dissatisfaction by
alienating the rising powers but rather to put measures in effect that mitigate
dissatisfaction and make the rising powers share and stakeholders of the
international order (Paul 2016; Rauch 2014, 275–80).
Unfortunately, not all PTT research and PTT-driven commentaries take the
centrality of the satisfaction variable seriously. All too often one finds
perspectives that I call PTT light camouflaging for PTT (Rauch 2014, 65–8).
PTT light is characterised by its focus on power transitions (often even
between great powers as such and not only at the top of the international
order) and its careless to total neglect of satisfaction with the status quo.
While this is a mere nuisance in academia (for example when ‘PTT’ is tested
without including satisfaction in the research design) it can become
dangerous when it transgresses into actual politics. Slogans like ‘history
teaches us that rising powers are likely to provoke war’ (Shirk 2007, 4) or ‘[t]
hroughout the history of the modern international state system, ascending
powers have always challenged the position of the dominant (hegemonic)
power in the international system – and these challenges have usually
culminated in war’ (Layne 2008, 16) may sound pronounced but have little in
common with a sophisticated PTT perspective and risk turning into a self-
fulfilling prophecy.
Conclusion
constellations in which balance and parity fall together, yet there are likewise
constellations in which a balance exists but no parity and vice versa. Thus,
their joint focus on power does not lead balance-of-power realism and power
transition theory to similar conclusions.
Applying this to the current power shifts and, most notably, the rise of China, I
have argued that balance-of-power realism and power transition theory not
only come to differing evaluations concerning the perilousness of the situation
but also prescribe quite different policy choices to deal with the situation. This
article is not about which of these perspectives is (analytically, empirically or
normatively) more sound, but about highlighting that these differing
perspectives exist and that it matters a great deal whether one regards
current events through balance-of-power or power-transition glasses.
References
Global Security Newswire. 2014. “Should Ukraine Have Gotten Rid of Its Cold
War Nukes?”. Accessed 30 May 2016. http://www.nti.org/gsn/article/should-
ukraine-have-gotten-rid-its-nukes/
He, Kai, and Huiyun Feng. 2013. Prospect Theory and Foreign Policy
Analysis in the Asia Pacific: Rational Leaders and Risky Behavior. New York,
NY: Routledge.
Herrington, Luke M. 2011. “Why the Rise of China Will Not Lead to Global
Hegemony”. (http://www.e-ir.info/2011/07/15/why-the-precarious-rise-of-china-
will-not-lead-to-global-hegemony/ accessed 16 October 2016).
Jeffery, Renée. 2009. “Evaluating the ‘China threat’: Power Transition Theory,
the Successor-State Image and the Dangers of Historical Analogies”.
Australian Journal of International Affairs 63(2): 309–324.
Kim, Woosang, and Scott Gates. 2015. “Power Transition Theory and the
Rise of China.” International Area Studies Review 18(3): 219–26.
Kugler, Jacek, and Douglas Lemke (eds.). 1996. Parity and War - Evaluations
and Extensions of the War Ledger. Ann Arbor, MI: University of Michigan
Press.
Lee, Sang-Hwan. 2015. “Global and Regional Orders in the 21st Century in
Terms of Multi-Layered Power Transition Theory: The cases of US-China and
China-Japan Relations”. International Area Studies Review 18(3): 266–279.
67 Realism in Practice
Legro, Jeffrey W. 2008. “Purpose Transitions: China’s Rise and the American
Response” in China’s Ascent: Power, Security, and the Future of International
Politics, edited by Robert S. Ross and Feng Zhu, 163–190. Ithaca, NY:
Cornell University Press.
Lemke, Douglas. 2004. “Great Powers in the Post-Cold War World: a Power
Transition Perspective” in Balance of Power: Theory and Practice in the 21st
Century, edited by T. V. Paul, James J. Wirtz, and Michel Fortmann, 52–55.
Stanford, CA: Stanford University Press.
Lemke, Douglas and Jacek Kugler. 1996. “The Evolution of the Power
Transition Perspective” in Parity and War – Evaluations and Extensions of the
War Ledger, edited by Jacek Kugler and Douglas Lemke, 3–34. Ann Arbor,
MI: University of Michigan Press.
Levy, Jack S. 2004. “What Do Great Powers Balance Against and When?” in
Balance of Power: Theory and Practice in the 21st Century, edited by T. V.
Paul, James J. Wirtz, and Michel Fortmann, 29–51. Stanford, CA: Stanford
University Press.
Levy, Jack S. 2008. “Power Transition Theory and the Rise of China” in
China’s Ascent - Power, Security, and the Future of International Politics,
edited by Robert S. Ross and Feng Zhu, 11–33. Ithaca, NY: Cornell University
Press.
Liegl, Markus and Reinhard Wolf. 2016. “Home Alone? EUrope’s Dilemmas in
an Age of Growing Sino-American Rivalry.” Paper presented at the 57th
Annual Convention of the International Studies Association, 13–16 March
2016, Atlanta/Georgia USA.
Mearsheimer, John J. 2001. The Tragedy of Great Power Politics. New York,
NY: Norton.
Mearsheimer, John J. 2014. “Why the Ukraine Crisis Is the West’s Fault”.
Foreign Affairs.
Morgenthau, Hans J. 1954. Politics Among Nations: The Struggle for Power
and Peace. New York: Knopf.
Nossel, Suzanne. 2016. “The World’s Rising Powers Have Fallen”. (http://
foreignpolicy.com/2016/07/06/brics-brazil-india-russia-china-south-africa-
economics-recession Accessed 16 October 2016)
O’Neill, Jim and Anna Stupnytska. 2009. The Long-Term Outlook for the
BRICs and N-11 Post Crisis. Global Economics Paper No. 192. London:
Goldman Sachs.
Organski, A. F. K. and Jacek Kugler. 1980. The War Ledger. Chicago, IL:
University of Chicago Press.
69 Realism in Practice
Paul, T.V, James J. Wirtz, and M. Fortmann, eds. 2004. Balance of Power:
Theory and Practice in the 21st Century. Stanford, CA: Stanford University
Press.
Rynning, Sten, and Jens Ringsmose. 2008. “Why Are Revisionist States
Revisionist? Reviving Classical Realism as an Approach to Understanding
International Change”. International Politics 45(1): 19–39.
Siverson, Randolph M., and Ross A. Miller. 1996. “The Power Transition:
Problems and Prospects” in Parity and War: Evaluations and Extensions of
the War Ledger, edited by Jacek Kugler and Douglas Lemke, 57–73. Ann
Arbor, MI: University of Michigan Press.
Tammen, Ronald L., and Jacek Kugler. 2006. “Power Transition and China–
US Conflicts”. Chinese Journal of International Politics 1(1): 35–55.
Tammen, Ronald L., Jacek Kugler, Douglas Lemke, Allan C. Stamm, III, Mark
Abdollahian, Carole Alsharabati, Brian Efrid, and A. F. K. Organski. 2000.
Power Transitions: Strategies for the 21st Century. New York, NY: Seven
Bridges Press.
van Agtmael, Antoine. 2012. “Think Again: The BRICS”. Accessed 16 October
2016. http://foreignpolicy.com/2012/10/08/think-again-the-brics
6
China’s Military Modernisation:
International Systemic Change
through Internal Balancing?
L AY L A D AWOOD
Accordingly, balancing can take two main forms: internal balancing and
external balancing. The employment of the first concept often implies
economic, technological and especially military efforts taken by a state using
its own means to counter the accumulation of military capabilities by a
possible opponent; the second refers to the creation of military alliances to
deal with the possibility of war (Waltz 1979). Nonetheless, scholars diverge
when empirically identifying balancing behaviours (Martin 1999, 2003; Nexon
2009).
1
This being the case, the opposite systemic situation involves the concentration of
power by a single actor, which can take the form of unipolarity (when there is an
especially powerful actor in the system), hegemony (when international rules are
determined by a single actor) or empire (when the less powerful units lose autonomy to
the most powerful) (Nexon 2009, 334–5).
73 Realism in Practice
In sum, this chapter intends to contribute to the debate concerning the current
state of Realism by exploring an underdeveloped realist concept: internal
balancing. Subsequently, China’s rise, more specifically the recent naval
modernisation efforts, will be analysed as a possible illustrative case of
internal balancing. The chapter tests the hypothesis that China is changing
the current unipolar systems by means of internally balancing the US.
2
For examples of this kind of theory, see the works of Walt (1990), Schweller (1994)
and Christensen and Snyder (1990), who elaborate on the frequency of balancing
behaviour and the conditions under which it is expected to occur.
3
Imperial overstretch refers to the loss of economic dynamism and the consequent
decline of a hegemon due to excessive spending on defence (Wohlforth 1999).
China’s Military Modernisation 74
With that in mind, this chapter argues that global internal balancing (that is,
balancing directed towards the poles of a system) refers to a process
comprising a group of actions which, over the years, have the potential to
reduce the capabilities gap between the balancer and existing opponent
poles. In the current unipolar system, to qualify as global internal balancing, a
group of behaviours must increase the balancer’s capabilities to deal with the
US in case of a major war. Obviously, the same efforts and capabilities used
to balance the US could also help the balancer deal with other possible
regional adversaries. By major war, this chapter means a war involving vital
interests of all sides, that is: a war of life and death to all parties.
When carried out by states that qualify as poles in multipolar and bipolar
systems, internal balancing can lead to various results. When it is
unsuccessfully performed, it might transform bipolar systems into unipolarities
and multipolar systems into bipolarities due to the decline of the state which
75 Realism in Practice
To sum up, the internal balancing model herein developed assumes that the
continued economic and political improvements achieved by a pole or a pole
candidate (and the maintenance of these achievements in time) enable the
occurrence and continuation of the second component of the internal
balancing process (which is military in nature). In addition, successful internal
balancing necessarily comprises a military build-up which increases the
balancer’s prospects of winning a major war against the pole(s) of a system.
4
In this respect, various theories drive attention to different domestic and economic
features which inspire the characterisation of the first component of the model on the
global internal balancing process. Power Transition Theory (PTT) stresses that
transformations in productivity and population are related to the rise of global powers
and Gilpin (2002) drives attention to transformations in sectors such as transportation,
communications, and in the economic system itself. In addition, Long Leadership Cycle
Theory (LLCT) highlights the causal relation between economic innovations and the
rise and fall of great powers. According to the supporters of this last theory, the rise of a
dominant power is the result of some sort of invention related to the leading sectors of
world economy which provides the inventor with the sort of advantages that usually
derive from monopolies. In contrast, the decline of a dominant power is caused by the
diffusion of its economic innovations to other states (Rasler and Thompson 1994;
Tammen et al. 2000). In terms of political features, PTT and Gilpin (2002) work with the
concept of political capacity, which relates to the distinction between state power and
national power: the latter being the sum of a country’s assets and the former being
comprised by what state authorities can really use for public purposes. As indicators of
political capacity, PTT suggests the use of fiscal and tax policy numbers.
China’s Military Modernisation 76
China and the US disagree especially in what concerns the Taiwan issue and
America’s influence over seas and oceans near China. Therefore, Chinese
authorities have been trying to improve their naval capabilities, which would
be essential to respond to the set of capabilities at the disposal of the US in
case of a war in Asia (O’Rourke 2012). In view of the Chinese current focus
on naval capabilities6, this chapter attempts to check if these modernisation
efforts provide China with better chances of victory in case of an armed
conflict against the US. In other words, the next sections verify if the Chinese
naval improvements can be understood as internal balancing and analyse if
these behaviours have the potential to change the current unipolar system.
The naval capabilities acquired by China during the 1990s and 2000s reflect a
new emphasis by the Chinese authorities and scholars on the development of
naval power.7 China’s naval modernisation began during the 1990s and was
5
For the complete test of this model against China´s economic, political and military
rise, see Dawood (2013).
6
This does not mean that naval modernisation is China’s sole means of balancing.
Nonetheless, this chapter concentrates on naval modernisation due to the attention the
Chinese government has been giving to these efforts.
7
Surely, this new focus would be better characterised if one could show increases in
naval spending over the years, but no official breakdown of defence spending by
service is available for China. However, various Chinese publications seem to confirm
this new emphasis. According to Fravel and Liebman (2011), Chinese navy officials are
increasingly casting the PLAN (People’s Liberation Army Navy) as the protector of
China’s economy. It is often argued that the heart of China’s economy is more and
more concentrated in coastal areas and that China’s dependence on maritime shipping
is growing, turning the protection of China’s sea lines of communication (SLOCs) to a
priority (Fravel and Liebman 2011, 74–5). Chinese official sources also point to this
new focus. A White Paper published in 2006 states that the country aims at extending
77 Realism in Practice
boosted after 1996, when the United States deployed two aircraft carriers to
Taiwan’s surroundings in response to Chinese missile tests and naval
exercises near Taiwan (Cole 2009, 2010). The modernisation efforts
‘comprise a broad array of weapon acquisition programs, including programs
for anti-ship ballistic missiles (ASBMs), anti-ship cruise missiles (ASCMs),
land-attack cruise missiles (LACMs), surface-to-air missiles, mines, manned
aircraft, unmanned aircraft, submarines, aircraft carriers, destroyers, frigates,
patrol craft, amphibious ships, mine countermeasures (MCM) ships, hospital
ships, and supporting C4IS8 (O’Rourke 2012, 3).
the strategic depth of offshore defensive operations and at enhancing its capabilities in
integrated maritime operations. Another White Paper published in 2008 for the first time
referred to the ground forces as a service equivalent to the navy, air force, and second
artillery. It emphasises the objective of developing the navy’s capabilities to conduct
cooperation in distant waters (Erickson and Goldstein 2009, 47–8; Hartnett and Vellucci
2011). In 2013, a new White Paper stated the objective to develop blue water
capabilities (the capability to operate globally, that is in open oceans and deep waters)
(O’Rourke 2016).
8
C4IS stands for Command, Control, Communications, and Computers Information
System.
9
In defining network centric warfare, scholars emphasise the use of new
technologies to produce information and improve results in war. In other words, there is
a focus on ‘the new technologies used to create more effective sensor and
communications architectures. These architectures, it is argued, will enable us to create
and exploit a common situational awareness, increase our speed of command, and “get
inside the enemy’s OODA [observe, orient, decide, and act] loop”’ (Smith 2001, 59).
China’s Military Modernisation 78
missiles, once fired, could not change trajectory to account for target motion.
However, the PLA is reportedly trying to place seekers in high-explosive
missile warheads that would activate as the warhead descends into the target
area and guide the warhead to the moving ship. If the Chinese succeed in
achieving such innovation, it could pose a huge challenge to US forces
(McDevitt 2011).
This sea denial strategy is also referred to as near-seas active defence (in
opposition to the near-coast defence strategy adopted during the Cold War)
since the aim is to cover a much larger sea area than the coast. The near-
seas active defence covers the first island chain (which stretches from the
Kurile Islands through the islands of Japan, the Ryukyu Archipelago, Taiwan
and the Philippines to Borneo Island), the Yellow Sea, East China Sea, and
South China Sea, sea areas adjacent to the outer rims of this island chain
and those of the North Pacific. The concept does not cover the South Pacific
and the Indian Ocean (Li 2011, 116).
It is important to emphasise that ‘anti-access’ and ‘area denial’ are US terms and
10
not Chinese ones. Those terms, first employed by the US Department of Defense in the
2001 Quadrennial Defense Review, are often used interchangeably by analysts to
characterise the attempt to prevent a US military intervention if China attacks Taiwan. In
particular, the assumed Chinese objective is to impede US aircraft carriers from getting
within tactical aircraft operating distance from China (McDevitt 2011, 192).
79 Realism in Practice
The submarine forces are the most important PLAN (People’s Liberation
Army Navy) capability to perform the sea-denial strategy. Assuming it takes
three submarines to keep one on station (one on station, one going home,
one getting ready to go), McDevitt (2011) estimates that a sea-denial strategy
requires around 60 to 75 modern submarines to deal with US carriers. The
PLAN has currently 39 modern attack boats. That means that it is not
unequivocal that China’s forces can effectively perform the strategy of sea-
denial (McDevitt 2011, O’Rourke 2016).
On the other hand, in terms of far seas operations, China has been slow to
increase its navy’s ability to remain at sea for extended periods. At the same
time, it has been working to overcome some of its limitations. In 2013, two
new FUCHI replenishment oilers were added to the force. These ships rotate
in support of Gulf of Aden (GOA) counter-piracy deployments. Also, the
amphibious force is being modernised; yet China has not significantly
expanded its capacity in this area yet.
Conclusion
In conclusion, the behaviours which are part of the military component of the
internal balancing process (off-setting, emulation and/or military innovation)
can be identified among China’s naval modernisation efforts. Moreover, the
timing of China’s actions in what regards naval capabilities indicates a
correlation between the Chinese naval modernisation and US unipolarity.
11
This theory was a creation of a 2004 study commissioned by the US Department of
Defense entitled Energy Futures in Asia and is broadly accepted as true in the US and
India.
China’s Military Modernisation 80
Nonetheless, it is not clear if all the criteria herein proposed to qualify a group
of actions as internal balancing are met: Chinese efforts are potentially
directed at diminishing the gap between the US and China’s capabilities, but
the Chinese efforts do not considerably increase its chances of winning a
major war against the US. Nevertheless, Chinese maritime modernisation
efforts have improved its ability to deter a possible US intervention in the
Taiwan Strait. If a war breaks out near Taiwan, Chinese capabilities might be
enough to coerce the US out of this conflict, especially in case the American
authorities do not consider the defence of Taiwan as a vital American interest.
Nonetheless, naval modernisation still fails to provide China with the
resources necessary to project power outside the so called ‘first island chain’.
Particularly, China has the disadvantage of relying on SLOCs for vital
products such as energy sources. Consequently, the capability of protecting
its SLOC is essential to raise China’s chances of winning a major war against
the US, since the latter, in case its vital interests were at risk, could impose a
naval embargo on China that would damage Chinese war efforts, making
victory a lot harder.
References
Christensen, Thomas. J. and Jack Snyder. 1990. “Chain Gangs and Passed
Bucks: Predicting Alliance Patterns in Multipolarity”. International Organization
4: 137–168.
Cole, Bernard. 2009. “More Red than Expert: Chinese Sea Power During the
Cold War” in China Goes to Sea: Maritime Transformation in Comparative
Historical Perspective, edited by Andrew S. Erickson, Lyle J. Goldstein, and
Carnes Lord, 320–340. Annapolis: Naval Institute Press.
Cole, Bernard D. 2010. The Great Wall at Sea: China’s Navy in the Twenty-
first Century. 2nd ed. Annapolis: Naval Institute Press.
Erickson, Andrew S., and Lyle S. Goldstein. 2009. “Gunboats for China’s New
Grand Canals? Probing the Intersection of Beijing’s Naval and Oil Security
Policies”. Naval War College Review 62(2): 43–76.
Fravel, Taylor M. and Alexander Liebman. 2011. “Beyond the Moat: The
PLAN’s Evolving Interests and Potential Influence” in The Chinese Navy:
Expanding Capabilities, Evolving Roles, edited by P. C. Saunders et al.,
41–80. Washington: National University Press.
Gilpin, Robert. 2002. War and Change in World Politics. New York:
Cambridge University Press.
Kostecka, Daniel J. 2011. “Places and Bases: The Chinese Navy’s Emerging
Support Network in the Indian Ocean”. Naval War College Review 64(1):
59–78.
Li, Nan. 2011. “The Evolution of China’s Naval Strategy and Capabilities: from
“Near Coast” and “Near Seas” to “Far Seas” in The Chinese Navy: Expanding
Capabilities, Evolving Roles, edited by P. C. Saunders et al., 109–140.
Washington: National Defense University Press.
Rasler, Karen A. and William R. Thompson. 1994. The Great Powers and
Global Struggle. 1490–1990. Lexington: The University Press of Kentucky.
Tammen, Ronald et al. 2000. Power Transitions. Strategies for the 21st
Century. New York: Chatham House Publishers.
7
Realism and Cyber Conflict:
Security in the Digital Age
A NT HO N Y J .S. C R A IG & B R A N D O N VA LE R IA N O
although realism can help in raising key issues in cyber security, overall the
perspective lacks the ability to explain the dynamics of cyber conflict.
Realism has been challenged for its inability to explain state behaviour or
offer productive policy guidance. For example, several studies point to the
lack of evidence that states act in accordance with balance of power logic, a
prominent hypothesis within the realist literature (Rosecrance and Stein 1993,
10, 17–21; Schroeder 1994). Its contradictory predictions and lack of emp-
irical progress leads Vasquez (1997) to condemn realism as a ‘degenerative’
rather than ‘progressive’ paradigm. Furthermore, statistical studies suggest
the factors that realists argue increase national security, such as military
build-ups and alliances, are often counterproductive and increase the
likelihood of conflict (Senese and Vasquez 2008). Nevertheless, with its focus
on security and conflict issues, realism appears to be the natural go-to theory
for elucidating pressing cyber security issues.
The study of cyber conflict is generally thought to have begun when Arquilla
and Ronfeldt (1993) developed the concepts of ‘cyberwar’ and ‘netwar’ and
predicted a transformation of warfare in line with rapid advances in ICT. This
form of conflict takes place within cyberspace, an environment defined simply
as ‘all of the computer networks in the world and everything they connect and
control’ (Clarke and Knake 2010, 70). Cyber conflict refers to ‘the use of
87 Realism in Practice
security; this process is often termed the spiral model with each action forcing
a reaction (Glaser 2004, 44). The spiral model is at the heart of traditional
conceptualisations of an escalating arms race which are said to cause rapid
shifts in the balance of power, an increase in international tension, and a
greater risk of miscalculation and conflict (Richardson 1960; Vasquez 1993).
In many ways, anarchy and its effects describe cyberspace well. Liberal IR
theorists argue that the dangerous effects of anarchy can be ameliorated by
global institutions which mediate interstate disputes and reduce uncertainty
through increased information (Russett and Oneal 2001, 163–4). However,
the cyber domain lacks effective global institutional governance. Relevant
organisations include the International Telecommunications Union (ITU) and
the Internet Corporation for Assigned Names and Numbers (ICANN), but their
functions and competencies do not extend to conflict management.
Media reports of a cyber arms race are frequent (Paletta et al. 2015; Corera
2015), and this increased militarisation of cyberspace is evident through the
creation of new military organisations, the drafting of cyber-military doctrines,
the increase in cyber security budgets, and the hiring of cyber ‘warriors’
(Craig and Valeriano 2016a). A more secretive development is the suggested
stockpiling of malicious code which can be used as weapons (Rid and
McBurney 2012). Furthermore, Craig and Valeriano (2016a) provide empirical
evidence demonstrating a relationship between build-ups in cyber capabilities
and mutual perceptions of threat and competition between states in a select
number of cases.
Realism can help explain the source of cyber arms racing behaviour as a
response to threat in an anarchic world. Jervis (1978, 187–194) notes that the
security dilemma is at its most intense when a build-up in offensive
capabilities is more cost-effective than a build-up in defensive capabilities.
The security dilemma is also more severe when offensive and defensive
capabilities are indistinguishable. If so, states are unable to signal benign
intentions and any build up in capability will be seen as a potential threat
(199–206). In cyberspace, capabilities are very difficult to distinguish. For
one, it is impossible to verify the offensive zero day exploits governments
possess since they are, by definition, unknown. Moreover, cyber military
organisations like US Cyber Command tend to have both defensive and
offensive roles and if they are said to be increasing their budgets or personnel
it is not obvious whether an offensive or defensive investment is being made.
This fuels uncertainty and competition between states as they seek security
in cyberspace.
For some realists, arms races increase the likelihood of war (Jervis 1978,
89 Realism in Practice
188; Van Evera 1998, 13), yet for others, military build-ups are a necessary
means of deterring a revisionist power (Glaser 2004). A critical question is
therefore whether security competition will escalate to actual conflict.
Previous scholarship has demonstrated a relationship between arms races
and both militarised interstate disputes and war (Sample 1997; Gibler et al.
2005). The concern here is whether cyber arms races will lead to a similar
outcome. As Lord and Sharp (2011, 29) argue: ‘conflict in cyberspace is
uniquely predisposed to escalation given uncertainties about what constitutes
an act of war and the growing number of state and non-state actors seeking
offensive capabilities.’
Cyber Power
Cyber power is defined by Nye (2011, 123) as ‘the ability to obtain preferred
outcomes through use of the electronically interconnected information
resources of the cyber domain’, and its potential to transform international
relations has become a prominent debate. Although there is no theory of
cyber power within the realist literature, realism offers a framework to think
about the distribution of power between actors and how this relates to conflict.
Realism and Cyber Conflict: Security in the Digital Age 90
A core assumption of realism is that states are the most powerful and
therefore most important actors in international politics. The information
revolution challenges the primacy of the state, however, due to the greater
involvement of non-state actors threatening traditional power dynamics
(Eriksson and Giacomello 2006, 229). Non-state actors are increasingly
important in international relations as Nye’s (1990, 160) theory of power
diffusion argues, and this is especially true in the cyber domain in which
individual criminals, organisations, and terrorist groups can take advantage of
the accessibility of the internet to threaten the dominance of the state, and
where private firms play a role, both as providers of security and as sources
of vulnerability.
We should not overstate this issue though because states are still the most
dominant actors when it comes to cyber conflict. Non-state actors and
terrorists do play a role, but their tactics have generally been ineffective or
used as cover for nation-states seeking to hide their actions (Valeriano and
Maness 2015, 164–187). It appears that states remain ultimately best placed
to leverage the tools of cyber warfare with resources to invest in the
manpower, research and development, and education that are unlikely to be
rivalled by non-state actors.
It is hypothesised that due to the relative low cost of entry into the cyber
warfare domain, traditionally weaker states challenge stronger states and
reconfigure the power distribution in the system (Lango 2016, 12). For
example, much attention has been paid to North Korea’s training of
thousands of hackers (Mulrine 2015), China’s Unit 61398, accused of
continual cyber espionage campaigns against the United States (Mandiant
2013), and the increasing sophistication in Iran’s cyber warfare tactics (Aitel
2015). Traditional power dynamics are also undermined by the paradoxical
idea that the most technologically advanced countries are also the most
dependent on digital infrastructure and thus the most vulnerable to a crippling
cyber-attack (Kolet 2001, 282). On the other hand, Lindsay (2013) argues
that only the technological superpowers possess the ability to develop the
most sophisticated cyber weaponry which suggests the cyber domain’s
asymmetric nature may be overstated.
Realism also raises the question of whether cyber capabilities give states’
coercive power, referring to the capacity to induce compellence to one’s will
through inflicting or threatening damage upon an enemy (Schelling 1966,
1–34). There are serious doubts about the efficacy of cyber coercion,
however, since the technology lacks the destructiveness of conventional
military operations and is less likely to be taken seriously by the target state.
Gartzke (2013, 2) highlights the limitations of internet-based warfare writing
91 Realism in Practice
The idea that attacking is cheaper, easier, more effective, and therefore a
more prevalent strategy than defending features prominently in the cyber
security discourse (Lieber 2014). This is based on the offense-defence
balance theory which is used by defensive realists to explain why status quo
powers are sometimes incentivised to go to war, postulating that when the
prevailing military technology favours offensive over defensive operations, the
prospects for interstate conflict increase (Quester 1977, Jervis 1978, Lynn-
Jones 1995, Van Evera 1998). The offense is dominant in the international
system, as Jervis (1978, 187) explains, when ‘it is easier to destroy the
other’s army and take its territory than it is to defend one’s own’, and defence
is dominant when ‘it is easier to protect and to hold than it is to move forward,
destroy, and take.’
When the advantage lies with the attackers, status quo powers are given
strong incentives to increase their offensive capabilities and seek expansion
or else risk being attacked themselves (Jervis 1978, 187–194). Technological
factors are considered to shape the offense-defence balance in various ways.
For instance, mobility enhancing technologies are said to favour the
attackers, whereas technologies that increase firepower make defending
more effective (Glaser and Kaufmann 1998). The theory has been used to
explain the onset or absence of war in history, such as World War I, where the
revolution in small arms and artillery created a widespread, albeit mistaken,
belief among European leaders in the ‘cult of the offensive’ that encouraged
them to launch pre-emptive wars or risk being attacked themselves. In reality,
technology heavily favoured the defence as trench warfare demonstrated
(Van Evera 1984). The theory has been thoroughly criticised, however, for its
flawed logic and lack of parsimony (Davis, Finel, and Goddard 1998). More
Realism and Cyber Conflict: Security in the Digital Age 92
Despite the challenges, the theory has found a resurgent popularity in the
cyber security debate. The cyber offense is widely assumed to be more
effective than defence due to its relative ease and cheapness, the potential
damage it could inflict on society, its instantaneous nature, and because
attacks need only target a single vulnerability to succeed, whereas defence
involves securing entire networks and patching vulnerabilities that the
defender is unaware of before they have been exploited (Lieber 2014, 100–
3). Libicki (2009, 32) claims that offensive capabilities are a more cost-
effective investment in that ‘another dollar’s worth of offense requires far
more than another dollar’s worth of defence to restore prior levels of security’.
Going further, Saltzman (2013, 43–4) reconceptualises the offense-defence
theory to fit the non-territorial nature of cyber technologies with ‘versatility’
and ‘byte-power’ replacing mobility and firepower as the key determinants of
the offense dominance of cyberspace.
There are two important reasons to argue that these claims are overstated.
Real-world cases can help demonstrate that, first, the utilisation of cyber
weapons is not as easy or cheap as is often assumed, therefore casting
doubt on one of the main determinants of the offense-defence balance, and
second, that the utility of cyber weapons as a coercive tool of warfare is likely
overstated, suggesting that offensive cyber operations are not necessarily
advantageous.
Rather than being an easy operation, the ‘Stuxnet’ virus, that was developed
and implemented by the United States and Israel and discovered in the
networks of an Iranian nuclear power facility in 2010, was, according to
experts, a complex operation that took several years to develop, costing as
much as $300 million, and which likely required a human operative (Valeriano
and Maness 2015, 151). The incident, which had intended to hold back Iran’s
enrichment of nuclear material, destroyed one fifth of the facility’s centrifuges
(Sanger 2012, 205). However, the rate of enrichment actually increased
during this episode, highlighting the limited impact of even the most advanced
of offensive cyber actions (Lindsay 2013, 391).
Similar conclusions can be drawn from the December 2015 hack of the
Ukrainian power grid which caused a blackout for over 230,000 residents in
Western Ukraine. The incident involved Russian hackers disabling power
93 Realism in Practice
Cyber Deterrence
states maintain over them. Second, unlike nuclear weapons, cyber weapons
do not have the same destructive capacity and so, to have a sufficient
deterrent effect, would have to be used repeatedly and to great effect. This is
difficult, however, because each cyber weapon is designed for a specific
vulnerability which could be subsequently patched. Third, attributing the
source of cyber incidents can be difficult and perpetrators often deny
involvement. In such cases, therefore, a state cannot be certain of whom to
respond against (Libicki 2009, 39–73). These arguments suggest that
deterring aggression through cyber means is an unworkable policy in practice.
Conclusion
In many ways, the cyber domain resembles a realist world with its anarchical
nature and lack of institutional governance where states fear one another and
95 Realism in Practice
Prudence, a foundation of classical realism, may offer the most viable policy
advice. As Machiavelli notes, the Prince ‘should proceed moderately and with
prudence and humanity, so that an excess of confidence may not make him
incautious’ (Vasquez 1995, 17). Due to the uncertainty surrounding the use of
cyber technology as an offensive weapon, states should proceed with caution
in the cyber domain and focus on creating resilient defences. Indeed, by
refraining from outright cyber war, many states have so far remained rather
prudent in their behaviour in cyberspace and this is an outcome that realist
theorists would find appealing and an area for further theoretical elaboration.
Given the issues raised here, we encourage the development of new theories
based on empirical observation or the deductive logics of the cyber domain
rather than automatically falling back on realist theories that were developed
to explain kinetic forms of warfare. With further empirical research, we can
gain more precise understandings of key issues such as the impact of cyber
arms races on interstate relations, the distribution of cyber capabilities among
state and non-state actors, and the reasons for restraint despite the intense
security competition and perceptions of an offensive advantage. More precise
answers to these questions can help us formulate better policy guidance for
governments.
References
Aitel, Dave. 2015. “Iran is emerging as one of the most dangerous cyber
threats to the US”. Business Insider UK, 2 December. http://uk.
businessinsider.com/iran-is-emerging-as-one-of-the-most-dangerous-cyber-
threats-to-the-us-2015-12?r=US&IR=T
Realism and Cyber Conflict: Security in the Digital Age 96
Bumiller, Elisabeth and Thom Shanker. 2012. “Panetta Warns of Dire Threat
of Cyberattack on U.S.”. The New York Times, 11 October. http://www.
nytimes.com/2012/10/12/world/panetta-warns-of-dire-threat-of-cyberattack.
html
Clarke, Richard A. and Robert K. Knake. 2010. Cyber War: The Next Threat
to National Security and What to Do About It. New York: Ecco.
Corera, Gordon. 2015. “Rapid escalation of the cyber-arms race”. BBC News,
29 April. http://www.bbc.co.uk/news/uk-32493516
Elgot, Jessica. 2016. “UK must build cyber-attack capability, chancellor says”.
The Guardian, 1 November. https://www.theguardian.com/politics/2016/
nov/01/uk-must-build-cyber-attack-capability-chancellor-says-cybersecurity
Gartzke, Erik. 2013. “The Myth of Cyberwar: Bringing War on the Internet
Back Down to Earth”. International Security 38(2): 41–73.
Gibler, Douglas M., Toby J. Rider, and Marc L. Hutchison. 2005. “Taking Arms
Against a Sea of Troubles: Conventional Arms Races During Periods of
Rivalry”. Journal of Peace Research 42(2): 131–147.
Glaser, Charles L. 2004. “When Are Arms Races Dangerous? Rational versus
Suboptimal Arming”. International Security 28(4): 44–84.
Glaser, Charles L., and Chaim Kaufmann. 1998. “What is the offense-defense
balance and can we measure it?”. International Security 22(4): 44–82.
Lord, Kristin M. and Travis Sharp. 2011. “America’s Cyber Future: Security
and Prosperity in the Information Age”. Center for a New American Security,
1: 1–62. https://s3.amazonaws.com/files.cnas.org/documents/CNAS_Cyber_
Volume-I_0.pdf
Lieber, Kier. 2014. “The Offense-Defense Balance and Cyber Warfare”. Cyber
Analogies, edited by Emily O. Goldman and John Arquilla. Monterey,
California: Naval Postgraduate School.
Lindsay, Jon R. 2013. “Stuxnet and the Limits of Cyber Warfare”. Security
Studies 22(3): 365–404.
McGraw, Gary. 2013. “Cyber War is Inevitable (Unless We Build Security In)”.
Journal of Strategic Studies 36(1): 109–119.
Mearsheimer, John J. 1990. “Back to the Future: Instability in Europe After the
Cold War”. International Security 15(1): 5–56.
Mearsheimer, John J. 2001. The Tragedy of Great Power Politics. New York:
W. W. Norton & Company.
Morgenthau, Hans J. 1948. Politics among Nations: The Struggle for Power
and Peace. New York: Alfred A. Knopf.
99 Realism in Practice
Mulrine, Anna. 2016. “How North Korea built up a cadre of code warriors
prepared for cyberwar”. Christian Science Monitor, 6 February. http://www.
csmonitor.com/World/Passcode/2015/0206/How-North-Korea-built-up-a-
cadre-of-code-warriors-prepared-for-cyberwar
Nye, Joseph S. 2011. The Future of Power. New York: Public Affairs.
Rid, Thomas. 2013. Cyber War Will Not Take Place. London: C Hurst & Co
Publishers Ltd.
Rosecrance, Richard, and Arthur Stein. 1993. The Domestic Bases of Grand
Strategy. Ithaca: Cornell University Press.
Sample, Susan G. 1997. “Arms Race and Dispute Escalation: Resolving the
Debate”. Journal of Peace Research 31(1): 7–22.
Sanger, David E. 2012. Confront and Conceal: Obama’s Secret Wars and
Surprising Use of American Power. New York: Random House.
Schelling, Thomas C. 1966. Arms and Influence. New Haven, CT: Yale
University Press.
Senese, Paul D. and John A. Vasquez. 2008. The Steps to War: An Empirical
Study. Princeton: Princeton University Press.
Sternstein, A. 2016. “US Homeland Security’s $6B Firewall Has More Than a
Few Frightening Blind Spots”. Defense One, 29 January. (http://www.
defenseone.com/technology/2016/01/us-homeland-securitys-6b-firewall-has-
more-few-frightening-blind-spots/125528/?oref=DefenseOneFB, Accessed
06/06/2017)
The Economist. 2010. “War in the fifth domain: Are the mouse and keyboard
the new weapons of conflict?”. 1 July. (http://www.economist.com/
node/16478792, accessed 06/06/2017)
Valeriano, Brandon and Ryan C. Maness. 2015. Cyber War versus Cyber
Realities: Cyber Conflict in the International System. New York: Oxford
University Press.
101 Realism in Practice
Van Evera, Stephen. 1984. “The Cult of the Offensive and the Origins of the
First World War”. International Security 9(1): 58–107.
Van Evera, Stephen. 1998. “Offense, Defense, and the Causes of War”.
International Security 22(4): 5–43.
8
Realism and Peaceful Change
A N D ER S W IV EL
This does not mean that realists are unconcerned with peace. Acting as policy
advisors or foreign policy commentators, realists have often been among the
most vocal critics of war. Hans Morgenthau and Kenneth Waltz, arguably the
two most prominent realists in the latter half of the twentieth century, were
both highly critical of US military intervention in Vietnam (Rafshoon 2001;
Humphreys 2013). More recently, ‘almost all realists in the United States –
except for Henry Kissinger – opposed the war against Iraq’ in 2003
(Mearsheimer 2005), and realists have been highly critical of the US military
interventions during the Obama administration from 2009 to 2017 (Walt
2016). However, despite this concern with peace, war remains the primary
mechanism for change in realist theory, and realists have been surprisingly
103 Realism in Practice
This chapter seeks to remedy this shortcoming by exploring how the logic(s)
of realism may help to explain peaceful change. The intention is not to test
realist hypotheses on peaceful change, but rather discuss what dynamics of
peaceful change we see when we look through the realist lens (cf. Smith
2007; Sterling-Folker 2006). I develop my argument in five steps. First, I
define what peaceful change is when looking through realist lenses. Second, I
explain why realists should be concerned about peaceful change and explain
why peaceful change has until now played a marginal role in realist analyses.
Third, I challenge what is typically perceived as a mission impossible in
structural realism arguing that even offensive realist logic leaves room for
peaceful change and may explain why peaceful change is a useful strategy
for power-maximising states. Fourth, I take this argument further by exploring
how increased interaction capacity has changed the power-calculus of
interest maximising states, and fifth, in the last section before the conclusion,
I explore how structural incentives interact with domestic politics.
Realists agree with most standard definitions that peace entails the ‘absence
of war and other forms of overt violence’ (Anderson 2004, 102). However, to
the realist, ‘peaceful’ does not equal power free. In contrast, realists find that
the prospects for peace are conditioned on the distribution of power, although
they do not provide clear guidance as to which distribution will most
effectively promote peace. Highly asymmetrical distributions of power such as
bipolarity and unipolarity may underpin peace understood as the absence of
war, because of the clarity of signals and information when there is little doubt
on which actors are the strongest and there is little chance of challenging the
most powerful states (Waltz 1979; Hansen 2011).1 However, while bipolarity is
highly asymmetric when we look at the great powers vis-à-vis the rest, it is
highly symmetric when we look at the balance between the two great powers.
The balance of power, in bipolar and multipolar systems, has been viewed as
a major source of peace in realist theory, because the actors in this system
are expected to deter each other from attacking (Doyle 1997, 167). Within any
distribution of power, states may pursue various strategies for maintaining or
changing the status quo by violent or peaceful means or by seeking to ‘pass
the buck’, i.e. getting another state to bear the costs of maintaining or
changing the status quo. Realists have typically focused on violent means of
change, i.e. the use or threat of military action. To the realist, peaceful change
1
For a realist discussion of the importance of systemic clarity of signals and
information, see Ripsman, Taliaferro and Lobell (2016, 46–52).
Realism and Peaceful Change 104
What does ‘change’ mean in this context? Realists agree with Martin Wight
that international relations is the ‘realm of recurrence and repetition’ (Wight
1960, 43). International anarchy and power politics will remain inescapable
features of international relations, because any policy-maker who refuses to
obey the self-help logic of anarchy runs the risk of endangering the security or
even survival of the state he or she represents. As noted by Joseph Grieco:
‘states recognise that in anarchy there is no overarching authority to prevent
others from using violence, or the threat of violence, to dominate or destroy
them. This is in fact the core insight of realism concerning international
politics’ (Grieco 1990, 38). This understanding leaves only a limited role for
peaceful change as a strategy or outcome softening, but not eradicating,
power politics. Thus, foreign policy decision-makers may pursue strategies of
peaceful change as a prudent way of promoting change and achieving a
peace in accordance with their own values and interests, but with only limited
impact on transforming the international system or the nature of international
relations (Gilpin 1981, 209).
There are two reasons why realists should be concerned with peaceful
change. First, a realist focus on interstate war as the primary mechanism of
change seems increasingly out of synch with the empirical record. The
number of interstate wars has decreased significantly since 1946 making it
one of the most profound trends in international relations in the latter half of
the twentieth century and the first decades of the twenty-first century
(Themnér and Wallensteen 2014). Moreover, the end of the Cold War in 1989
and the subsequent collapse of what had been one of the two dominant
powers for the past 45 years, the Soviet Union, in 1991 did not trigger a great
power war. The Soviet Union’s successor state Russia largely accepted the
single most significant loss of power by any great power without a war in the
2
See, e.g. Drezner (2013), Gruber (2000) and Thompson (2009) for discussions of
these types of diplomatic strategies (although not in the specific context of peaceful
change).
105 Realism in Practice
history of the modern state system. The loss reduced Russia to the size it had
had until the successful expansion by Katharina the Great in the eighteenth
century and cut off access to some of the most prosperous parts of what had
previously been the Soviet Union (Hansen, Toft and Wivel 2009; Wohlforth
2002). Likewise, in Europe, the reunification of Germany in 1990 was
accepted by the other states in the region even though a united Germany had
been a significant source of unrest and conflict on the continent in the first
half of the twentieth century. More recently, the rise of China has not resulted
in military confrontation with the declining US superpower despite structural
realist expectations that this will almost inevitably happen (Sørensen 2013).
In essence, understanding peaceful change is important if we are to
understand some of the most important trends and events in international
relations over the past decades.
But if realism has potentially a lot to say about peaceful change, then why
have realists told us so little? This blind spot stems from an unfortunate
dichotomising of potential international realms into (existing) anarchy and
(utopian) hierarchy. To be sure, a distinction between international anarchy
and domestic politics is a useful and necessary assumption of realist
theorising on international relations. However, the structural realist stylised
account of international relations as not only a state of nature but a constant
state of emergency to be contrasted with rule-governed domestic politics has
important, and unnecessary, consequences for the ability of realism to
3
Lieber’s discussion is explicitly focused on the contributors to The Review of
Politics, but it is here seen as a general trait of political realism. For an attempt to
formulate a general ‘ethical realism’ based on these pragmatic premises, see Lieven
and Hulsman (2006).
Realism and Peaceful Change 106
‘The problem of peaceful change’, writes E.H. Carr, ‘is, in national politics,
how to effect necessary and desirable changes without revolution, and, in
international politics, how to effect such changes without war’ (Carr 1981,
191–192). In domestic politics, the spread of liberal democracy and the rule of
law have created mechanisms for change such as parliamentary and
presidential elections and secured a regulated use of tools for change such
as strikes and political protest. However, as Carr notes, ‘in international
4
For an example of this understanding for world politics, see e.g. John Mearsheimer,
who notes that ‘[s]tates […] are fated to clash as each competes for advantage over the
others. This is a tragic situation, but there is no escaping it unless the states that make
up the system agree to form a world government. Such a vast transformation is hardly
a realistic prospect. However, so conflict and war are bound to continue as large and
enduring features of world politics’ (Mearsheimer 2001, xi-xii).
107 Realism in Practice
The United States and Germany have both successfully achieved hegemony
peacefully but under the implicit – and sometimes explicit – threat to the
economic survival of the states dominated and taking advantage of their
weakness after a war or crisis. In the aftermath of the Second World War, the
United States made economic aid to the war-torn European states dependent
on political and economic cooperation among them in the OEEC. By
combining strong support for European integrations with a US security
guarantee for Western Europe and conditional economic aid, the United
States succeeded in creating an ‘“empire” by integration’ (Lundestad 1998). In
the aftermath of the 2008 financial crisis, Germany (supported by a coalition
of smaller EU member states) demanded a set of economic reforms and
policies of Southern European EU member states, Greece in particular. If
Greece would not comply with strict austerity measures, the country would be
forced to leave the Economic and Monetary Union (EMU), thereby closing off
lending opportunities and most likely triggering an economic collapse of the
country. This was a credible threat as the Greek economy accounts for only
two percent of the Eurozone economy and a collapse of the country’s
economy was unlikely to trigger a collapse in any other economy or the
dissolution of the EMU. In effect, the crisis solidified German economic and
political hegemony within the Union and support for Germany from a number
of small North European countries viewing German hegemony as a bulwark
against economic chaos.
Like offensive realism, the defensive realist variant of structural realism starts
from an assumption of security seeking states in an anarchic international
system. However, rather than power-maximising buck-passing, they predict
that states tend to act as ‘defensive positionalists’ (Grieco 1990, 40). They
guard the status quo by balancing power in order to maximise the chance of
securing survival in a system without a legitimate monopoly of violence, i.e.
an anarchic system (Waltz 1979, 117–23), and war is typically the result of
either overreaction or miscalculation (Waltz 1979, 172–3). Based on this
logic, defensive realism has a hard time explaining not only peaceful change,
but change in general: if international relations are characterised by states
defensively balancing any rising power then it is difficult to explain any
109 Realism in Practice
5
Even Kenneth Waltz, the most prominent structural realist, is careful to stress that
his theory cannot explain ‘why state X made a certain move last Tuesday’ (Waltz 1979,
121; for a discussion, see Wivel 2005). Neoclassical realists take this point further by
exploring the interaction between international and domestic politics (Ripsman,
Taliaferro and Lobell 2016).
6
For discussions of the international system from a realist perspective, see Buzan
(1993), Jervis (1998), Ripsman, Taliaferro and Lobell (2016) and Snyder (1996)
7
Thus, we come close to what English School theorists term an international society:
‘a group of states (or, more generally, a group of independent political communities)
which not merely form a system, in the sense that the behaviour of each is a necessary
factor in the calculations of the others, but also have established by dialogue and
consent common rules and institutions for the conduct of their relations, and recognise
Realism and Peaceful Change 110
Following this logic, we might argue that the violent change, i.e. annexation of
new land if necessary by the use of military means, associated with the
expansion of international society through European colonisation under the
condition of low interaction capacity has today been replaced by peaceful
change underpinned by high interaction capacity, leading to the creation of
one global market. Viewed through the realist lens, nineteenth century
colonisation and twenty-first century globalisation are both essentially a case
of great powers expanding their economic base and sphere of dominance,
but expansion now takes the form of peaceful change due to technological
developments making peaceful change more effective than war in most
cases. The high interaction capacity of the present system intensifies
socialisation by speeding up market integration and thereby, at the same
time, increasing competition and socialisation (Wivel 2004, 14). Therefore,
one global marketplace makes competition fiercer, and it is more transparent
who is winning and who is losing. Moreover, the high interaction capacity has
raised the costs of warfare making security less scarce and replacing security
competition with geo-economic competition as the main parameter for great
power competition (Mastanduno 1999; Schweller 1999).8
Also, the change in interaction capacity may help us to explain the shift in
state practices from hard balancing, i.e. military build-up and alliances, to soft
balancing, i.e. restraining the power of other states by institutional and
their common interest in maintaining these arrangements’ (Bull and Watson 1985, 1).
For a discussion of the English School and realism, see Mearsheimer et al. (2005).
8
Although, in the anarchic world depicted by realists, there is no guarantee that
resources accumulated by geo-economic competition will not one day be used in a
geopolitical military conflict.
111 Realism in Practice
‘[T]he basic task of peaceful change’, writes Robert Gilpin, ‘is not merely to
secure peace, it is to foster change and achieve a peace that secures one’s
basic values. Determining how this goal is to be achieved in specific historical
circumstances is the ultimate task of wise and prudent statesmanship’ (Gilpin
1981, 209). Thus far, we have focused on peaceful change as change by
peaceful means illustrating how the logic(s) of realism may help us to
understand why even interest-maximising states in an anarchic international
realm dominated by power politics may choose to pursue change by peaceful
rather than violent means. However, for the individual decision-maker or
government, peaceful change, like any foreign policy decision or strategy, is a
complex task of navigating between structural incentives and domestic values
and interests. Therefore, neoclassical realists argue that the response to
structural incentives of any given state is conditioned by the clarity of the
incentives. Clarity is affected by systemic process variables such as
interaction capacity (as discussed in the previous section), and domestic level
intervening variables such as strategic culture, the images and perceptions of
foreign policy decision-makers, domestic institutions and state-society
relations (Ripsman, Taliaferro and Lobell 2016).
Conclusion
Two points about the nature of peaceful change as seen through the realist
lens should be noted. Depending on one’s philosophical worldview and
theoretical disposition, they may be seen as either caveats of the realist
perspective on peaceful change or alternatively as important reminders about
the need to respect the logics of necessity in international relations providing
the raison d’etre of realism and proving its continued relevance. First, realist
logics of peaceful change may help us to understand peaceful change, but
not peaceful transformation, i.e. the end of power politics. The realist logics of
peaceful change may bring peace but this peace is always conditioned by
power. It is always a peace serving the interests of some actors and going
against the interests of others. In that sense realism may be used as a critical
theory of peaceful change reminding us that whenever we encounter what
Carr termed ‘salutary’ recognitions of peaceful change, these are rarely
outside the realm of power and interest but an integral part of power politics
(Carr 1981, 197). However, secondly, and following logically from the first
point, the discussion points to no escape from power politics. Any order and
any change of order is based on power politics. In that sense, realism seems
stuck as what Robert Cox termed a problem-solving theory: ‘it takes the world
as it finds it, with the prevailing social and power relationships and the
institutions into which they are organised, as the given framework for action’
(Cox 1986, 208). For these reasons, the quest for peaceful change is at the
same time fundamental to the realisation of the practical morality of realists
seeking to reconcile their values with the interests of accommodating to the
lesser evil, and under-researched by realists blinded by the perceived state of
emergency following from anarchy.
*Author note: My research for this chapter began when I was a visiting fellow
at the Centre for International Peace and Security Studies, McGill University. I
would like to thank T.V. Paul and the editors of the book for useful comments
on an earlier draft.
References
Cox, Robert W. 1986. “Social Forces, States and World Orders: Beyond
International Relations Theory”. In Neorealism and Its Critics, edited by
Robert O. Keohane, 204–254. New York: Columbia University Press.
Doyle, Michael W. 1997. Ways of War and Peace. New York: W. W. Norton.
Gruber, Lloyd. 2000. Ruling the World. Princeton, NJ: Princeton University
Press.
Hansen, Birthe. 2011. Unipolarity and World Politics: A Theory and its
Implications. London: Routledge.
Hansen, Birthe, Peter Toft, and Anders Wivel. 2009. Security Strategies and
American World Order: Lost Power. London: Routledge.
115 Realism in Practice
He, Kai. 2015. “Contested Regional Orders and Institutional Balancing in the
Asia-Pacific”. International Politics 52(2): 208–222.
Jervis, Robert. 1998. System Effects: Complexity in Political and Social Life.
Princeton: Princeton University Press.
Kydd, Andrew. 1997. “Sheep in Sheep’s clothing: Why security seekers do not
fight each other”. Security Studies 7(1): 114–155.
Lieven, Anatol and John Hulsman. 2006. Ethical Realism, New York: Vintage
Books.
Mearsheimer, John J. 2001. The Tragedy of Great Power Politics. New York:
W. W. Norton.
Mearsheimer, John J. 2005. “Hans Morgenthau and the Iraq War: realism
versus. neo-conservatism”. Open Democracy. Last modified 19 May.
https://www.opendemocracy.net/democracy-americanpower/
morgenthau_2522.jsp
Mearsheimer, John, Paul Rogers, Richard Little, Christopher Hill, Chris Brown
and Ken Booth. 2005. “Roundtable: The Battle Rages On”. International
Relations 19(3): 337–360.
Pape, Robert. 2005. “Soft Balancing against the United States”. International
Security 30(1): 7–45.
Paul, T.V. 2005. “Soft Balancing in the Age of U.S. Primacy”. International
Security 30(1): 46–71.
Schweller, Randall L. 1999. “Realism and the present great power system:
growth and positional conflict over scarce resources”. In Unipolar Politics:
Realism and State Strategies after the Cold War, edited by Ethan B. Kapstein
and Michael Mastanduno, 26–68. New York: Columbia University Press.
Wivel, Anders. 2004. “The Power Politics of Peace Exploring the Link
between Globalization and European Integration from a Realist Perspective”.
Cooperation and Conflict 39(1): 5–25.
Wivel, Anders. 2005. “Explaining why state X made a certain move last
Tuesday: the promise and limitations of realist foreign policy analysis”.
Journal of International Relations and Development 8(4): 355–380.
Realism and Peaceful Change 118
9
Realism, Small States and
Neutrality
AR C H IE W. S IM PS ON
Since the end of the Cold War, the policy and practice of neutrality has
become unfashionable. Neutrality is an institution of non-partisanship that has
been commonly practiced by many small states through the ages, ostensibly
as a means to opt-out of the power politics of other states. In essence,
neutrality ‘is a legal condition through which a state declares non-involvement
in a conflict or war, and indicates its intention to refrain from supporting or
aiding either side’ (Heywood 2015, 144), but it is also a political strategy. In
tautological terms, neutrality means not becoming involved in wars either
directly or indirectly. Yet, neutrality retains some relevance in the 21st century
in three important respects: there are several small states that retain
neutrality, including Ireland and Switzerland; neutrality still provides some
manifestation of security; it remains an option to avoid becoming embroiled in
violent conflicts. Realists generally accept that neutral states exist but, ‘are
unable to provide a convincing explanation for the influence of neutrality’
(Austin 1998, 39). This is because the practice of neutrality falls outside
mainstream realist thought relating to the role of institutions. Realists follow a
number of basic assumptions about international politics involving the
centrality of the state and of state sovereignty, the importance of power, the
political inducement of national interests, and the need for state survival. In
times of conflict then, realists believe that states should balance or
bandwagon following these assumptions, but neutrality sometimes provides a
third option.
There are many ways to define small states (Amstrup 1976; Archer and
Nugent 2002; Hey 2003; Maass 2009; Steinmetz and Wivel 2010; Archer and
Bailes et al. 2014) and this means there is no scholarly agreement on what
constitutes a ‘small state’. This results in a variety of definitions of small
states usually relating to quantifiable criteria such as geographic size,
population size, economic outcomes, and military spending. However, other
means of defining small states exist, including self-perception, analysis of
behaviour in international relations or by a combination of factors. Importantly,
smallness is a relative term in which some states can be said to be ‘small’ in
relation to others. For example, Luxembourg is small compared to Belgium
and Belgium is small compared to France, and so on. David Vital (1967)
argued in favor of a two-fold means of defining small states, suggesting that
those advanced, industrial states with populations of 10–15 million people or
underdeveloped states with populations of 20–30 million people could be
categorised as ‘small states’. In Europe, most states are small, including the
Benelux members, the Nordic states, the Baltic States, the island states of
Europe, and others such as those in the Balkans.
This chapter will review the contemporary status of neutrality through the lens
of realism and the examples of small states. The chapter will first outline the
Melian Dialogue from The History of the Peloponnesian War by Thucydides
(Warner 1954). The Melian Dialogue is a seminal piece of realist writing that
has retained a resonance throughout history as it establishes many of the
problems associated with neutrality. The chapter will then assess the realist
position on neutrality including an outline of different types of neutrality and
the four guiding principles that shape neutrality. This will be followed by a
discussion concerning small neutral states during the Cold War. A number of
states adopted neutrality during the Cold War for various reasons largely
relating to geo-political circumstances. The contemporary position of
neutrality in the post-Cold War period will be discussed which will show how
unfashionable neutrality has become at the start of the 21st century.
121 Realism in Practice
In the book, Thucydides explains the position of Melos, a small island that
was formerly a Spartan colony. Melos adopted a position of neutrality when
the war began ‘and at first remained neutral and took no part in the struggle’
(Crawley 2006, 336). However, Athenian generals calculated that Melos could
become of strategic importance if it decided to join Sparta due to its location,
and this perspective lead Athens to threaten Melos. Negotiations between the
Melians and Athenians are carried out, and the Melians see occupation of
Realism, Small States and Neutrality 122
Melos as a form of slavery. The Athenians argue: ‘you would have the
advantage of submitting before suffering the worst, and we should gain by not
destroying you’ (2006, 338). The Melians ask whether ‘you would not consent
to our being neutral’ (2006, 338), but the Athenians reject this as they see
acceptance of Melos as a neutral state as a strategic vulnerability. The two
sides debate the situation, each with legitimate concerns. For Melos,
neutrality means trying to stay out of the war, but for Athens the slightest
possibility that Melos might align with Sparta is too alarming a prospect that
cannot be ignored. As Kolodziej writes, ‘the Melian wish for neutrality is now
viewed as a threat to Athens’s security’ (2005, 63). From a realist perspective,
this is not about ‘right’ and ‘wrong’ but is instead about national security on
both sides. The Athenians send in their army and lay siege to Melos, and
while there were a few skirmishes, the superior power and size of the
Athenian forces leads to an Athenian victory. The Athenians are ruthless as
‘[they] put to death all the grown men whom they took, and sold the women
and children for slaves, and subsequently sent out five hundred colonists and
inhabited the place themselves’ (Crawley 2006, 343).
The Melian Dialogue exhibits many realist themes such as the security
dilemma, the utility of military force, the transformative nature of warfare, and
that national security is of prime concern to states (large and small). It also
demonstrates that neutrality is a practice that goes back to ancient times but
this is partly contingent upon the acceptance of ‘larger’ powers. Before the
war, Melos was a trading nation that had good relations with Athens and thus
its neutrality was accepted. However, the war with Sparta changed the
political context making neutrality unacceptable to Athens. The small size of
Melos coupled with its geographic location made it vulnerable to larger states
such as Athens. The Athenian strategic logic is to eliminate a potential threat
leading Thucydides to assert that ‘The strong do what they can and the weak
suffer what they must’ (Warner 1954, 302). For many realists reading the
Melian Dialogue, it is the logic of Athens as a ‘great’ power that is important,
not the position of Melos. The inherent bias (or certainly interest) towards
larger states (or ‘Great Powers’) is clearly demonstrated by Thucydides,
though this is perhaps a natural outcome for many studying international
politics. It also illustrates that neutrality is sometimes ignored, or indeed
pushed aside, when the risks associated with war are interpreted by
belligerents as overwhelming. Dougherty and Pfaltzgraff write that, ‘to the
realist, politics is not a function of ethical philosophy. Instead, political theory,
is derived from political practice and historical experience’ (1990, 83). With
the Melian Dialogue, it is clear that the neutrality of Melos has become
strategically inconvenient for Athens and so military might is used to eliminate
a perceived vulnerability. This is about the practical realities of war and not
about ethical considerations, and thus Melos is crushed. The ‘might’ over
‘right’ argument clearly prevailed in the case of little Melos.
123 Realism in Practice
whether a small state adopts neutrality. For a number of small states, such as
Austria and Finland, their location in relation to others was a factor in
becoming neutral (Hakovirta, 1983). Finland was a neighbour of the Soviet
Union but a democratic, capitalist-based state, and so it was neutralised to
appease the Soviets in 1948. Austria was occupied by the Allied powers after
the Second World War for about ten years and became neutral in order to
regain its sovereignty after occupation. Other states like Sweden, Switzerland
and Liechtenstein were also part of this neutral bloc in the middle of Europe
with Yugoslavia, in addition, becoming part of the non-aligned movement.
did not want to align with the Americans or the Soviets during the Cold War
period. India, as a non-aligned state, was involved in three wars with Pakistan
during the Cold War period illustrating that it was not neutral. While the non-
alignment movement still exists, it is a largely redundant organisation now.
For the most part, states adopt various forms of neutrality contingent upon
their own political objectives, geographic position, and security needs.
The Cold War divided the world for over four decades in the second half of
Realism, Small States and Neutrality 126
While Austrian and Finnish neutrality became part of the Cold War balance of
power in Europe, Irish neutrality had a different genesis. Ireland had gained
independence in the 1920s partly after a period of violent turmoil against the
British which accelerated during the First World War. Ireland adopted
neutrality partly because of domestic political reasons (there was a brief civil
war in Ireland following independence) but also as a sign of pacifism following
years of political violence and civil war. This neutrality was maintained
throughout the Cold War period though Ireland maintained good relations with
the USA and it was able to join the Common Market (now European Union) in
1973. Ireland was part of the ‘big five’ neutral states of Europe alongside
Austria, Finland, Sweden and Switzerland, and some of the lesser known
127 Realism in Practice
The Cold War provided a framework in which neutrality was a viable and
sometimes useful diplomatic mechanism for maintaining the status quo. For
example, the International Atomic Energy Agency (IAEA) was based in
Vienna because of Austrian neutrality; and the UN has its European
headquarters in Switzerland. However, neutrality became less relevant in the
post-Cold War period. This is perhaps shown by Austrian, Finnish and
Swedish membership of the European Union. During the Cold War, the EEC/
EU was viewed by the Soviets as part of the Western Alliance in tandem with
NATO (Tarschys 1971; Hakovirta 1983). In practical terms, this meant Austria,
Finland and Sweden could not apply for membership fearing this would
negate their neutrality; this applied to Swiss membership of the United
Nations until 2002. With the end of the Cold War and the dissolution of the
Soviet Union in 1991, neutrality was a more-or-less redundant concept in
Europe. Neutrality had ‘lost most of its significance’ (Goetschel 1999, 122).
The enlargement of the European Union in the post-Cold War period was
mirrored by NATO. Since the end of the Cold War, NATO developed a number
of new structures and programmes including the establishment of the Euro-
Atlantic Partnership Council and the ‘Partnership for Peace’ programme.
Such developments were partly designed as part of a new security
architecture for Europe, and partly to legitimise NATO in the post-Cold War
period. The five main neutral states in Europe have joined the Euro-Atlantic
Partnership Council, which would not have been possible during the Cold
War. For realists, this indicates that the so-called aberration of neutrality has
been seriously undermined in the post-Cold War period to the point at which it
is now an irrelevant concept. Goetschel writes: ‘the neutrals quickly shifted to
a policy aimed at becoming as ‘normal’ as possible’ (1999, 115).
Conclusions
During the Cold War period, neutrality was sui generis for a number of small
states in Europe. As a political strategy it was designed to offer a form of
insulation from the power politics of the Superpowers to protect the
sovereignty of these small states. Neutrality set in play a number of
constraints for these small states with the proviso that they would gain a
greater sense of security. However, neutrality is contingent upon the
acceptance of other states as shown by the case of Melos in ancient times,
and by the Soviet Union during the Cold War, especially regarding Austria and
Finland. For realists, neutral states can play a marginal role in the balance of
Realism, Small States and Neutrality 128
power, but with the end of the Cold War there has been a lack of such a
balance. Morgenthau writes, ‘neutrality of the small European states is
essentially a function of the balance of power’ (Morgenthau 1939, 482). For
small states, neutrality is motivated by national security concerns, but realists
(and especially neo-realists) see neutrality as an outcome of the balance of
power. Since the end of the Cold War, the world has seen a period of US
hegemony (Layne, 1993) and neutrality has become less relevant. However,
with the rise of China, the re-emergence of Russia and the economic
emergence of others, like India and Brazil, a multi-polar balance of power is
currently evolving. For realists and neo-realists, a global balance of power
might mean a return to normal international politics, but it might also provide
space for some small states to adopt neutrality.
References
Archer, Clive and Neill Nugent. 2002. “Introduction: Small States and the
European Union.” Current Politics and Economics of Europe 11(1): 1–10.
Archer, Clive, Alison Bailes, and Anders Wivel. 2014. Small States and
International Security: Europe and Beyond. London: Routledge
Hakovirta, Harto. 1983. “The Soviet Union and the Varieties of Neutrality in
Western Europe.” World Politics 35(4): 563–585.
Hey, Joanne A.K. 2003. Small States in World Politics. Boulder and London:
Lynne Rienner.
Karsh, Efraim. 1998. Neutrality and Small States. London and New York:
Routledge.
Layne, Christopher. 1993. “The Unipolar Illusion: Why New Great Powers Will
Rise”. International Security 17(4): 5–51.
Mearsheimer, John J. 2001. The Tragedy of Great Power Politics. New York:
Norton.
Realism, Small States and Neutrality 130
Williamson Murray, Knox MacGregor, and Alvin Bernstein. 2009. The Making
of Strategy: Rulers, States and War. Cambridge and New York: Cambridge
University Press.
Rickli, Jean-Marc. 2010. “Neutrality Inside and Outside the EU: A Comparison
of Austrian and Swiss Security Policies After the Cold War”. Small States in
Europe, edited by Robert Steinmetz and Anders Wivel, 181–198. Farnham
and Burlington: Ashgate.
Steinmetz, Robert and Anders Wivel. 2010. Small States in Europe. Farnham
and Burlington: Ashgate.
Tarschys, Daniel. 1971. “Neutrality and the Common Market: the Soviet
View”. Cooperation and Conflict 6(2): 65–75.
Waltzer, Michael. 2000. Just and Unjust Wars. New York: Basic Books.
Wight, Martin. 1978. Power Politics. New York and London: Continuum/Royal
Institute of International Affairs.
131 Realism in Practice
10
The Reluctant Realist: Jimmy
Carter and Iran
RO B E RT W. MU R R AY & ST E PH EN MC GLIN C H E Y
This approach by Carter was a marked departure from the initial tenets of
what Carter had intended his foreign policy to be. Early in his tenure, Carter
wanted to take focus away from the strategy of containment and to move
American focus to issues such as human rights. Upon taking office, however,
Carter realised just how difficult such a move would be, and more, that
abandoning or eroding containment would threaten America’s interests
abroad and provide the Soviet Union with the opportunity to spread its sphere
of influence into key areas of US geostrategic interest. In essence, Carter
quickly understood that foreign policy could not ignore the realities of the
international system, and that realism rather than idealism would have to be
the driving force behind foreign policy decisions. The Carter Doctrine in many
ways epitomised realism by identifying an area of American national interest
and promising to effectively balance against Soviet aggression if the Soviets
demonstrated an intention to expand into the region. Further, the bolstering of
The Reluctant Realist: Jimmy Carter and Iran 132
regional allies through economic payoffs, arms deals, and the promise of
American military intervention if regional allies were threatened heralded back
to the ideas originally proposed in National Security Council Report 68 (NSC-
68) and the Truman Doctrine, but Carter updated both the language and
context for his own time.
This chapter seeks to explore one key aspect of Carter’s realism, being
American relations with Iran. The decisions made during the Carter
Administration regarding arms sales towards Iran more broadly reflect the
balancing act that leaders must navigate in the divide between domestic and
international politics. It is not enough to dismiss Carter’s foreign policy as a
tale of utopian beliefs in human rights becoming scattered in the midst of the
Cold War. Instead, closer study of the Iran case demonstrates a foreign policy
that was motivated by a realist sense of strategic necessity far more than
domestic, or personal, political ideology. In this light, this chapter shows but
one example that regardless of the circumstance, all leaders’ decisions are
limited in foreign policy-making due to the constraints posed by the anarchic
structure of the international system. Regardless of personal ideology, party
affiliation, or driving personal motivation, realist ideas about the role of the
system in foreign policy decision making have timeless value, and Carter’s
sale of the Airborne Warning and Control System (AWACS) to Iran – used as
an example later in this chapter – is a valid example of realism’s core tenets.
Together with the broader focus on Carter advanced here, the AWACS case
opens up a new understanding of Carter as a president who displayed realist
tendencies, albeit reluctantly, much earlier in his tenure than is typically
observed. In assessing Carter’s approach to Iran through a realist lens, it
becomes clear that, despite an overall expectation that he would reduce arms
sales, his grander ambitions for arms limitation would be doomed.
Consequently, Carter’s Iran policy, rather than resembling one of a liberal
mind-set, came to reflect the more strategically minded policy path inherited
from his predecessors.
Iran had become America’s largest arms customer long before Carter’s
emergence as a presidential candidate. Due to Iran’s geographical location it
became a focal point in US containment policy in the 1940s. It was a frontier
state that stood between the Soviet Union and the oil reserves of the Persian
Gulf. A US–UK coup was staged in 1953 to ensure that Iran remained
governed in a way favourable to the western powers, with the Shah at the
centre of affairs. Soon afterward, a pattern of economic and military aid
became entrenched with Iran becoming a client state of the US. This support
for the Shah’s regime was enhanced by a series of arms sales in the mid
133 Realism in Practice
1960s as the Shah began to use his growing oil income to build beyond prior
arrangements (McGlinchey 2013a, 2014). Two decades after the coup, in
1972, Richard Nixon travelled to Tehran with Henry Kissinger and agreed to
unlimited and unmoderated arms sales with Iran – with the exception of
nuclear weapons. This gesture, the so-called blank cheque, gave the Shah
the freedom to buy whatever advanced US weaponry he chose, so long as he
could pay for it. It was a unique arrangement for a foreign leader due to the
lack of any effective domestic oversight for the arrangement in the US. It was
also a test case for Nixon’s reimagining of US Cold War strategy based on
outsourcing the costs of Cold War containment to able allies and clients – the
so-called Nixon doctrine (McGlinchey 2013b). The agreement catapulted
Iranian arms purchases from approximately $150 million dollars in the late
1960s to being measured in the multi-billions per annum from 1972 onwards
(State Department Report). Nixon’s imperial style of leadership left Congress
in the dark for several years on the finer details of arming Iran, something that
would eventually haunt Carter as Congress sought to exercise its advice and
consent role more effectively in later years.
The pattern Nixon set in place was cognisant of the strategic realities the US
found itself in during the 1970s. The Vietnam War had shown the limits of the
direct application of US military power. It had left America overstretched
militarily, and also economically due to structural problems in the US
economy that would fester through the 1970s. Passing the costs of US
security to able allies in selected cases, such as Iran, was therefore a sound
strategic decision. Nixon’s successor Gerald Ford agreed and continued the
multi-billion dollar arms sales pattern that Nixon had established with Iran.
This cemented a path that a new president would find hard to break. As a
result, Carter’s general predilection towards arms control was overruled in the
case of Iran, as were his human rights concerns. Both these positions were
the cornerstones of Carter’s election campaign, a signal that he was a
different candidate. Hence, the seemingly contradictory picture of the Carter
administration continuing a high profile arms relationship with the Shah can
be accounted for due to Carter’s willingness to overrule his principles in the
face of a policy that had become deeply entrenched.
In a more general sense, much has been said about the nature of Carter’s
foreign policy behaviour, and its failure both in terms of achieving objectives
the president himself valued, such as human rights, and its overall
ineffectiveness. Sometimes characterised as a liberal in the midst of a very
realist Cold War, reflection actually tells a different story. Carter’s foreign
policy was very much built on the realist assumptions of his predecessors,
whether it was intentional or not. Selling vast quantities of advanced arms to
Iran is only one example of a foreign policy developed on assumptions of
American self-interest and containment, rather than the rhetorical values of
human rights and détente espoused by Carter during his presidency. The
Carter era of foreign policy was supposed to be different, or at least that was
what Carter wanted to believe. What became evident during the Carter years
was the difficulty he would have in trying to promote an international policy
package that mirrored his personal liberal beliefs during the constraints of the
Cold War. Paul Kennedy summarises this notion by arguing:
To put it another way: due to the structural constraints of the Cold War, Carter
‘came in like a lamb and went out like a lion’ (see Lebow and Stein 1993;
Aronoff 2006).
135 Realism in Practice
The arms trade was a particularly sensitive area for US policy during the
Carter era and the administration’s approach to arms, and its juxtaposition to
other normative issues, are a key aspect of Carter’s policy failure. As Gaddis
stresses:
The difficulty here was that Carter never related his moral and
domestic political commitment to human rights to his
geopolitical and (given the alternative) humane commitment to
arms control. (Gaddis 1982, 348)
As such, Carter’s policy towards Iran during the final phase of the Shah’s rule
has been referred to as his ‘most glaring and costly [foreign policy]
inconsistency’ (LaFeber 1985, 288). This is best encapsulated in the New
Year’s Eve toast Carter delivered in 1977 in Tehran in which he toasted the
Shah for turning Iran into an ‘island of stability’ and for deserving ‘the respect
and the admiration and love which your people give to you’ (Carter 1977). It
was a fateful moment for Carter as one year later the Shah was forced to flee
his own country, and Iran quickly turned into a revisionist, and regionally
destabilising, force. The lack of translation from domestic attitudes to the
international realm is certainly not unique to the Carter Administration. All
national leaders are forced to make decisions and make policy in a system
that often provides little opportunity for novelty or significant change. The
strategic environment in which Carter was making decisions was not very
different at all from his predecessors’. It is certainly easy to claim that
changes were necessary in campaign rhetoric but the issue remains that
presidents have a limited ability to radically alter foreign policy, especially
considering that the US was one of two superpowers dominating a bipolar
international system. Like all national leaders, Carter was constrained by the
Cold War balance of power that was successful in preventing the outbreak of
major war between the two superpowers.
For many years, the Carter arms trading policy was a topic of insult and the
go-to case for successive administrations in cautionary tales about arms
sales. The Reagan administration was quick to start the effort to paint Carter
as naively ideal-based on its own desire for a more liberal arms sales policy.
In a 1981 address to the Aerospace Industries Association, Undersecretary of
State for Security Assistance James Buckley argued that Carter’s policy
‘substituted theology for a healthy sense of self-preservation’ (Hartung 1993,
58). What is most interesting about the vilification of Carter’s policy is that
arms sales were actually not restrained in any large-scale manner, and in the
case of Iran, actually increased to record levels during Carter’s presidency.
Even as the Shah entered his final days in mid-1978, another multi-billion
dollar arms deal was being tabled with Iran – and the Cold War was once
The Reluctant Realist: Jimmy Carter and Iran 136
The key to understanding why Carter was so vested in selling arms to Iran is
found in American perceptions of regional and international balances of
power. At the international level, Carter and his advisers knew they needed to
maintain Iran as a strong ally in a tumultuous region where the US had few
other reliable allies of note. The regional dynamics were naturally a part of the
US’ larger view of the international balance of power, where the Soviets and
Americans did their best to establish and maintain respective spheres of
influences. With both Israel and Iran as militarily strong allies in the region,
and Saudi Arabia as a powerful economic ally, the Americans felt secure
knowing they had strategic assets in the region. There was also a perception
that the US had a responsibility to promote democratic values, and the Shah
appeared willing to at least appease the US when it made demands regarding
the Shah’s actions (Moens 1991, 221). Going back to the early 1960s, the
Shah had established a series of domestic reforms to overcome growing
questions in Washington over the validity of his autocracy. When that proved
successful in winning the support of the liberal-minded Kennedy
administration, despite it being no more than a token gesture in reality, the
Shah became confident that he could rule largely as he saw fit and maintain
his autocratic style of governance (McGlinchey 2014, 22–38). It was
reassuring to the ego of certain liberal minded presidents – such as Kennedy
and Carter – when the Shah appeared to make gestures towards
liberalisation and reform. It made the realisation more palatable that it was
more important than anything else that Iran remained pro-Western and an
instrument of containment via its advanced military. The Shah, with all his
faults, was the best way to ensure that – and that is why he endured through
eight US presidencies.
The Airborne Warning and Control System (AWACS) was a modified Boeing
707 jet that served as a high altitude airborne command centre. The system
did not carry weapons and was outwardly defensive, allowing for the
monitoring and location of enemy stationing and battlefield movements, both
ground and airborne. Yet, implicitly (and simultaneously) it enabled the
offensive coordination of the user’s forces. For example, Iran could use the
system to direct a squadron of fighter jets to an attack target. The AWACS
137 Realism in Practice
was the most advanced system of its kind available at the time and was a
generational leap in terms of technology when compared with rival systems.
Despite placing arms sales on hold in the first half of 1977 pending the
launch of a wholesale arms policy review, Carter decided to sell Iran a fleet of
AWACS in May. In allowing the sale, Carter was riding roughshod over two
key pillars of his arms policy rethink which were subsequently outlined in
Presidential Directive 13 (PD-13) (1977). Firstly, one of the central controls
introduced in PD-13 was the decision not to introduce paradigm changing
military technology into a region, thereby setting the precedent for arms
escalation. The AWACS sale clearly violated this principle. Secondly, the
heart of PD-13 was the establishment of a progressively lowering annual
arms ceiling. To retain flexibility, NATO nations, plus Japan, Australia, and
New Zealand were exempted due to existing US treaty obligations. PD-13
also excluded Israel, albeit abstrusely, but Iran was conspicuous via its
absence from the policy paper as America’s largest arms customer. Despite
this, Cyrus Vance, Carter’s Secretary of State, privately reassured Iran that it
would also be exempted from PD-13. This led to arguments and frustration
within the administration. NSC Staffer Leslie Denend summed it up in a
memorandum to Carter’s National Security Adviser, Zbigniew Brzezinski, as
follows:
Though this may seem like a good way to ease the Shah’s
disapproval of our policy, it seems to me shortsighted in the
extreme. Either we mean what Vance has said, in which case
we are never going to decrease arms transfers…or else we
don’t mean it. (Memorandum for Brzezinski from ‘Global
Issues’ 1977)
What these points highlight is the extent of the realist attitudes embedded at
the upper end of the Carter administration – and how early in the
administration that foreign policy realism had set in. Whilst the staffer levels
were getting their collective heads around the new arms regime and working
hard to establish the policy momentum for PD-13, Vance - and as it would
later turn out Carter and Brzezinski - were already introducing fluidity into the
process as the structural constraints of the Cold War pressed upon them.
This begged the question of why Carter bothered to add the specific countries
listed in PD-13 as exceptions when he intended to exempt more nations on
an ad-hoc basis, such as Iran. The language and attitude towards PD-13 and
the exemption of states such as Iran again drove home the fundamental idea
of conflict within the Carter Administration about arms sales and foreign
policy decisions more broadly. Regardless of what PD-13 said, Carter was
fully aware of the fact that the US would be forced to break his own directive
The Reluctant Realist: Jimmy Carter and Iran 138
to achieve the regional goals in the Persian Gulf to protect American interests.
When Carter approved the sale of the AWACS to Iran he not only went
against the spirit and the letter of his own arms control doctrine, he also found
himself acting as an advocate for a foreign leader against a hostile Congress.
Congress blocked the sale on concerns of the technology falling into the
hands of the Soviets and of the aircraft being too advanced for Iranian crews
to operate. Iran was still a developing nation and was suffering from
underinvestment in infrastructure and education, thanks to the Shah’s
preference for military expenditure. However, Carter successfully resubmitted
the deal after an intense lobbying effort. The episode placed Carter in strange
waters considering the anti-arms rhetoric of his 1976 campaign. Few would
have expected Carter and Congress at this time to fall on opposing sides of
an arms issue. Yet, the AWACS issue was the first in what would become a
series of battles Carter fought with Congress over significant arms sales to a
range of Middle Eastern nations. After less than one year in office, the new
President had come to appreciate the value, and often the strategic necessity,
of arms sales as tools of US policymaking.
Much like his predecessors, Carter used the power of the executive to
manoeuvre successfully around Congressional roadblocks. However, the
AWACS affair exposed a climate of doubt over US relations with Iran, and did
so in a very public setting on Capitol Hill as the AWACS hearings played out.
That ambiguity seriously threatened US relations with Iran, and most probably
contributed to the Shah’s decline by exposing cracks in his armour and
allowing domestic opposition groups to gain traction. In addition, Carter
subjected himself to an ordeal that indicated strongly that his team approach
– which had been engineered to re-establish administrative diversity in
decision-making – could be inefficient and burdensome. This can be best
seen by members of Carter’s own administration, principally CIA Director
Stansfield Turner, expressing doubts in private testimony to Congress over
the sale, giving Congress more ammunition to initially oppose it. Following the
AWACS episode, Carter gradually dissolved his team approach in favour of
one reminiscent of the Nixon/Ford system where decision making was ever
more controlled from within the White House. This eventually allowed the
strategically minded Brzezinski to reorient the administration towards a more
traditional East/West mind-set that fitted with the realist bipolar view of the
Cold War. While scholars recognise this shift, the AWACS case shows that
Carter was already displaying a reluctant realism mere months into his
tenure, as he assumed office and fully recognised the challenge of making
foreign policy decisions in the bipolar context of the Cold War.
July 1977 where he noted apathetically (as the AWACS sale had been initially
rejected by Congress) that he did not care whether or not the Shah bought
the AWACS. He added that the Shah was welcome to pursue alternative
systems that he was considering (Carter 1982, 435). If such a sale occurred,
those alternatives would not contravene PD-13’s controls, as they were not
paradigm changing systems. Carter’s curious reflection, when examining the
reality of the intense administration scramble to push the AWACS sale
through the summer of 1977 is therefore contradictory and outwardly
confusing. What can be said for sure is that Carter’s professions to Congress,
to the Shah, and to his cabinet were quite the opposite from the position
noted in his diary. The fact that Carter chose that one diary entry to carve his
own history of the AWACS affair may be attributed to the proximity of the
Iranian revolution at the time of writing and Carter’s desire to give the
appearance that he had maintained objectivity in his dealings with the Shah.
However, the historical record shows this account to be less than accurate
and perhaps highlights Carter’s own unease with the choices he had to
reluctantly make, given the constraints facing him in this case. Further adding
to the discrepancies found in Carter’s personal account, he prefaced the
decision to approve the AWACS sale in the following way:
This statement is interesting in two ways: Firstly, he does not refer to the
AWACS as a defensive weapon. Yet, this was a central defence of the sale to
Congress despite the spurious nature of that claim. Presumably this had
become a frail position to remain insistent on. Secondly, there were no
contracts in existence in any sense for an Iranian purchase of the AWACS
prior to Carter’s offer in mid-1977. The AWACS was not ready for sale until
1977.
Conclusion
Carter’s reluctant realism, and his pragmatism towards Iran, speaks volumes
about how he came to understand regional stability and security once in
office. Carter was content to openly admonish regimes in Brazil, Argentina
and Chile for their rights records and to reduce aid to those states in an effort
to compel better behaviour on human rights protection. But, when push came
to shove with more valuable allies, the ‘absoluteness’ of Carter’s human rights
agenda quickly became fickle. In the case of Iran, the cause of human rights
ranked lower than a strong ally in a tumultuous region, and thus Carter did
what he could to maintain the pattern of relations with the Shah in the hopes
of ensuring the continuation of a strong sphere of influence in the region.
Carter’s approach toward Iran, exemplified by the AWACS sale, demonstrates
that he ultimately became more concerned with perpetuating the strategy of
containment than following through on his liberal tendencies. The fact that it
took only months in office for Carter to make that transition from a principled
liberal to a reluctant realist is testament to the binding that the Cold War, and
the structural constraints of bipolarity, placed on US presidents and foreign
policy making more generally.
141 Realism in Practice
References
Aronoff, Yael S. 2006. ‘In Like a Lamb, Out Like a Lion: The Political
Conversion of Jimmy Carter’, Political Science Quarterly vol. 121, no. 3, pp.
425–449.
Carter, Jimmy. 1977. ‘Tehran, Iran Toasts of the President and the Shah at a
State Dinner’, The American Presidency Project, 31 December. (http://www.
presidency.ucsb.edu/ws/?pid=7080 accessed 22 July 2017).
Hartung, William. 1993. ‘Why Sell Arms? Lessons from the Carter Years’,
World Policy Journal vol. 10, no. 1, pp. 57–64.
Kennedy, Paul. 1987. The Rise and Fall of the Great Powers, Random
House, New York. 409–410.
LaFeber, Walter. 1985. America, Russia and the Cold War, Alfred A. Knopf,
New York.
Lebow, Richard Ned & Stein, Janice Gross. 1993. ‘Afghanistan, Carter, and
Foreign Policy Change: The Limits of Cognitive Models’, in Dan Caldwell and
Timothy J. McKeown, (eds), Diplomacy, Force and Leadership: Essays in
Honor of Alexander L. George, pp. 95–127, Westview Press, Boulder.
Memorandum for Brzezinski from ‘Global Issues’ 1977. Jimmy Carter Library,
31 May. RAC: NLC-28-36-2-25-3.
The Reluctant Realist: Jimmy Carter and Iran 142
Moens, Alexander. 1991. ‘President Carter’s Advisers and the Fall of the
Shah’, Political Science Quarterly vol. 106, no. 2, pp. 211–237.
Morgenthau, Hans 2006. Politics Among Nations: The Struggle for Power and
Peace, 7th edn, McGraw-Hill, New York.
11
Realism: Human Rights Foe?
KOL D O C A SL A
This chapter appraises Realism from a human rights perspective. The first
section introduces the conventional view according to which realism, with its
focus on the state, material power and international anarchy, would dismiss
the idea that human rights could matter at all in global politics. The second
section provides an alternative perspective. There are at least three ways in
which human rights can survive and indeed flourish in a world guided by
classical realist parameters. I contend, first, that realism creates the space for
a political critique of international law, which helps us understand the political
reasons why certain claims get framed in the language of human rights law.
Secondly, realism advises restraint in the use of military force, leading
potentially to better human rights outcomes. Finally, realism can also allow us
to theorise about a certain idea of order guided by international rules defined
by states themselves.
For realists, normative values and international regimes do not have power in
themselves. The proclamation of human rights lacks analytical or explanatory
value to account for state action. Hence, international human rights law
(IHRL) does not deserve much attention. After all, IHRL is an international
regime made of normative values. An international regime matters only
insofar as it reflects the pre-existing ‘distribution of power in the world’
(Mearsheimer 1994/95, 7), and norms get subsumed ‘in the material structure
of the international system’ (Mearsheimer 1995, 91). In other words, for
realists, either the international human rights regime does not make a
difference, so states will not be really bothered about it; or it does make a
difference, but only as one more tool at the hands of the strong to impose
their hegemonic power over the weak.
Realism is present among legal scholars. For legal realists, the proclamation
of human rights in international law has very little connection with the actual
improvement of human rights around the world, which has more to do with
more interdependent trade relations and with the end of the Cold War. It is
true that liberal democracies keep drafting, signing and ratifying human rights
treaties, but in their opinion, this is only because they can do so at a very little
cost, and the opposite would make them look like ugly outliers, since most
other countries would not disembark from the international human rights
regime (Goldsmith and Posner 2005, ch. 4; Posner 2014).
With sporadic exceptions (like Schulz 2001 and Mahanty 2013), for most
human rights academics and practitioners realism remains anathema and
realists are seen as intellectual adversaries.
145 Realism in Practice
The narrative above remains the general view about realist thinking on human
rights in global politics. This view is very much spread within and beyond
realism. Yet, I believe an alternative realist reading of human rights is
possible, particularly within the more classical and pre-Waltzian realism
(before the 1970s), less constrained by the international structure and more
interested in counter-arguing what was seen as reckless idealism.
The dialogue is not only possible with authors long gone, like E. H. Carr, who
adopted an ambivalent position about the marriage between ideals and
power: ‘The characteristic vice of the utopian is naivety; of the realist, sterility’
(Carr 2001, 12). Well-known contemporary realists have also made the case,
albeit feebly, to let human rights into the equation of hard politics. From the
United States, both John Mearsheimer (2014) and Stephen Walt (2016) have
sustained that abuses committed by American forces abroad pose a serious
risk to national security, and that the best strategy to promote democracy and
human rights abroad is to do a better job at protecting them at home.
Realism and human rights stem from very different starting points, but they do
not necessarily speak untranslatable languages. Their respective positions
and agendas are not intrinsically irreconcilable. The next paragraphs will give
examples in three areas where human rights analysis and advocacy could
benefit from some realist thinking.
Liberals assume that the legal system regulates behaviour within the political
system as a whole. This premise is not shared by one of the most influential
legal realists of the 20th century, Carl Schmitt. Realism reminds us that the
legal and the political spheres do not match inside out.
movement of foreigners, and came up with a new category of fighter, the so-
called enemy combatant, to whom international humanitarian law would not
apply. The underlying idea, Schmitt taught us, is that society’s enemies
should not enjoy the rights and benefits society bestowed upon itself. The
enemy manages to get into the political sphere but remains outside the legal
one.
The Finnish legal scholar Martti Koskenniemi (2005) offers interesting insight
on this. For him, international law in general, and IHRL in particular, is a
double-edged sword that serves two opposite purposes at once, ‘from
Apology to Utopia’, as the title of his book goes. On the one hand,
international law is based on states’ will and has the virtue of concreteness,
but when it is too closely related to actual state practice, and fails to create
new obligations for states, it becomes ‘apologetic’ of existing power, providing
an excuse or a justification for it. On the other hand, international law
constitutes an ideal or a plurality of ideals of state behaviour, and it can assert
the autonomous normative power of the law; its potential vice, however, is
that it risks being ‘unreal’ if it remains too disconnected from actual practice.
the powerless and right holders at large. This is what Stammers (2009) refers
to as the ‘paradox of institutionalisation’, or what Koskenniemi calls the
‘colonisation of political culture by a technocratic language’ (1999, 99).
That said, international law could also be counterproductive for social justice.
On the one hand, international law is meant to have universal appeal and
enjoys the good standing of governmental level commitment. On the other
hand, some advocates may not feel entirely comfortable with the potential
trade-offs of working for material equality, fair taxation and collective
bargaining within the confines of international law. Campaigns may lose out if
they depend too much on international treaties drafted and negotiated by
powerful elites, court rulings concerning individuals and perhaps even
isolated cases, and well-intentioned reports by unaccountable UN experts
published in Geneva or New York. The revolutionary strength of these tools is
considerably limited, and they are unlikely to energise individuals and
communities left out from an unfair distribution of global resources (find an
insightful debate on this in the volume edited by Lettinga and van Troost
2015). When drawing their strategic priorities, social justice advocates may
Realism: Human Rights Foe? 148
ESCR remain second-class rights in international law, and there are not
theoretically compelling reasons to explain it. The reasons have to do with the
Cold War context in which IHRL emerged, but also with the fact that most
Northern human rights NGOs only started to work on issues related to ESCR
in the 21st century. In other words, the reasons are political. Human rights
analysts could use some realism to unravel the politics behind the different
form of institutionalisation of ESCR and CPR in international law, but also to
reconsider the pitfalls of IHRL-based advocacy for social justice.
Realists see states as functionally equal. For them, states’ relative power vis-
à-vis each other does not depend on their role in the system, but on their
economic weight and military strength. Taking functional equality as a given,
realists are particularly interested in the balance of power. Realism is static,
prone to the status quo, suspicious of change. In one word: realism is
prudent.
Since the 1990s, liberal interventionism has taken hold within a big part of the
global human rights community. Liberal interventionists pushed the agenda of
the use of force to pursue humanitarian goals like democracy promotion.
Liberal interventionists were also behind the idea of the ‘Responsibility to
Protect’ (R2P), initially formulated by an independent group of experts
gathered in Canada (ICISS 2001), and partly embraced later in the UN World
Summit Outcome of 2005 (UN General Assembly 2005, A/RES/60/1, para.
138–9). There is no single definition of R2P, but the bottom line is that
humanity as a whole has a shared responsibility to protect civilians, militarily
if need be, in case of serious human rights violations, like genocide, war
crimes and crimes against humanity. For some R2P-promoters, this global
responsibility would outplay other legal obligations, including the procedural
requirements of Chapter VII of the UN Charter, which regulates when and
how the UN Security Council can decide on the deployment of armed forces
to restore international peace and security. This means that governments
should feel legitimised to send their troops to countries where serious human
rights abuses are taking place, even without a clear mandate from the
Security Council. Although this possibility was envisioned by the ICISS, the
UN General Assembly made clear in the World Summit Outcome Document
that R2P could not bypass the UN Charter.
With the Rwandan genocide of 1994 still in mind, a number of observers felt
compelled to justify NATO’s intervention in Kosovo in 1999, despite the
Security Council’s failure to authorise it due to the Russian veto. For some,
Kosovo would be one case only. For others, however, it would pave the way
to other interventions. For example, Michael Ignatieff (2003), who had been
part of the group of experts that came up with the idea of R2P, publicly
defended US and British intervention in Iraq on humanitarian grounds. The
R2P would later be explicitly mentioned in UN Security Council Resolution
1973 (2011) that authorised NATO’s operation in Libya, which ended up in
regime change. Considering the persistent instability in the country and in the
region, President Obama would later regret the American decision in relation
to Libya (Goldberg 2016), which pushed him not to intervene against
President al-Assad in Syria, even though credible reports confirmed that he
had used chemical weapons against defenceless civilians.
For two decades, part of the human rights community has relied excessively
on the military. The lessons from Iraq and Libya do however suggest a
change in course. Human rights advocates may prefer not to recommend the
use of military force in the future. And with their stress on national interests,
balance of power and prudence, realists may march by their side on this.
Realism: Human Rights Foe? 150
E. H. Carr wrote his Twenty Years’ Crisis (2001) to warn about what he saw
as an excess of wishful thinking among the idealists of the inter-war period.
Yet, he did not dismiss ideals and morality entirely. He only advocated
framing them within a political structure defined mostly by national interests.
Realism allows for a nuanced view of international law as the product of a
pluralist international society. This was basically the idea put forward by
Hedley Bull and the first generation of the English School of the 1960s and
70s, which Fred Halliday (1992, 438) liked to call ‘English Realism’.
The English School accepted the realist premise of the logic of anarchy, but
claimed that an international society can emerge out of that anarchy. Bull
sees an international society ‘when a group of states, conscious of certain
common interests and common values, form a society in the sense that they
conceive themselves to be bound by a common set of rules in their relations
with one another, and share in the working of common institutions’ (2002, 13).
Order would be the axis of the international society. Bull defined order as ‘a
pattern that leads to a particular result, an arrangement of social life such that
it promotes certain goals or values’ (2002, 3–4). Order would be highly
desirable because it is ‘the condition of the realisation of other values’,
including justice (Bull 2002, 93). Order is not necessarily states’ only goal, but
it must outdo justice insofar as its maintenance is the primary goal. Other
goals can be pursued as long as order is not put at risk.
One can indeed see international law as part of a certain idea of order in
international society. Carl Schmitt himself defended this idea in The Nomos of
the Earth (2006), where he contended that, at least since the 16th century,
international law has derived from the progressive expansion of a Eurocentric
notion of nomos, order, from the freedom of the seas, to the international law
of armed conflict and the notion of state sovereignty and non-intervention.
States may negotiate, draft and ratify international human rights treaties
inasmuch as they do not breach the fundamental tenets of international order,
among them the principle of national sovereignty. States may also set up
independent human rights mechanisms (courts, criminal tribunals,
committees, individual experts, etc.), but they would not necessarily feel
obliged to share the interpretation of these bodies, which is likely to be
inspired by a loose idea of global justice more so than by international order.
Not that far from classical realism, in the English School terminology, IHRL
can be seen as the product of a political tension between a certain idea of
international order, defended by some states, and a certain view of global
justice, advocated by independent UN experts, scholars and NGOs. Both
151 Realism in Practice
government officials and human rights advocates would use the same
terminology of IHRL (the same standards, the same provisions of the same
treaties, etc.), but they would mean different things in the above-mentioned
dialectics for hegemonic contestation between utopia and apology of state
action (Koskenniemi 2004 and 2005).
The implications are clear in relation to the two examples given previously.
While some states will resist the expansion of the international human rights
regime, some others are willing to promote it to the extent that the norms are
sufficiently ambiguous and do not impose heavy burdens. For example,
European states were willing to adopt the International Covenant on
Economic, Social and Cultural Rights with its Article 2(1), which makes clear
that obligations will depend on ‘available resources’ and rights are only to be
fulfilled ‘progressively’. Likewise, European states endorse the R2P
programmatically, provided it is made compatible with the procedures of the
UN Charter, and knowing that they would not have to suffer the
consequences of a foreign intervention on their soil. While scholars and
practitioners in general are moved by a sense of justice, solidarity and a
genuine concern for the well-being of others, the hedged realism of the
English School recommends them not to disregard the fact that governments
are motivated by different factors linked to order.
Conclusion
This paper has advocated a measured change for human rights defenders
and academics to open up to what realism has to offer. For the most part,
realism and human rights have at the very least ignored each other. This
paper, however, has shown three ways in which human rights could do better
with a pinch of realism. Realism invites us to reflect on the political reasons
why some claims are more salient than others in IHRL. Realism advises
prudence in the use of military force. And adjacent to realism, we can
conceptualise IHRL as the product of a political tension between order and
justice in international society.
I do not intend to twist realism to make it say what most realists would not
feel comfortable with. This paper is not denying that realists are sceptical of
normative values in global politics. Regardless of their personal beliefs and
preferences, as academics, realists would only care about the human rights
situation in other countries if that situation may result in regional instability or
a shift in the balance of power. I also believe realists have a hard time
explaining why states agree to the creation of independent human rights
bodies they have no control over, as weak as these bodies are. I cannot
imagine how they could explain the high degree of state compliance with the
Realism: Human Rights Foe? 152
Realism is not well placed to explain the international human rights regime,
and at least in their role of interpreters of global politics, realists will not
become human rights activists unless they stop being realist first.
However, this paper has argued that there are areas of potential strategic
interaction between human rights and realism. As noted by Rosenberg (1990,
299), realists grow stronger when criticised on ethical grounds, because such
criticism gives realism the opportunity to proclaim its alleged value-free
condition. Let us not criticise realism for not doing what it never intended to
do. As human rights scholars and practitioners, we should instead focus on
engaging with realism if only to get a better sense of the different
understandings of the world we intend to change. Paraphrasing Cox, ‘to
change the world, we have to begin with an understanding of the world as it
is, which means the structures of reality that surround us’ (1986, 242). Simply
ignoring the reality one seeks to transform is a guarantee of failure.
References
Bull, Hedley. 2002. The Anarchical Society: A Study of Order in World Politics.
London: Palgrave.
Cox, Robert. 1986. “Social Forces, States and World Orders: Beyond
International Relations Theory”. Neorealism and Its Critics, edited by Robert
Keohane. 204–254. New York: Columbia University Press.
Goldberg, Jeffrey. 2016. “The Obama Doctrine”. The Atlantic 317(3): 70–90.
Goldsmith, Jack, and Posner, Eric. 2005. The Limits of International Law.
Oxford: Oxford University Press.
Kennan, George. 1985. “Morality and Foreign Policy”. Foreign Affairs 64(2):
205–218.
Lettinga, Doutje, and van Troost, Lars (eds.). 2015. Can human rights bring
social justice? Twelve essays. Amsterdam: Amnesty International
Netherlands.
Realism: Human Rights Foe? 154
Mahanty, Daniel. 2013. “Realists, Too, Can Stand for Human Rights”. The
National Interest, October.
Mearsheimer, John and Walt, Stephen. 2003. “An unnecessary war”. Foreign
Policy, January (http://foreignpolicy.com/2009/11/03/an-unnecessary-war-2/,
accessed 31/05/2017)
Morgenthau, Hans. 1965. “We Are Deluding Ourselves in Vietnam”. The New
York Times, 18 April.
Morgenthau, Hans. 1979. Human Rights and Foreign Policy. New York:
Council on Religion and International Affairs.
Posner, Eric. 2014. The Twilight of Human Rights Law. Oxford: Oxford
University Press.
Schmitt, Carl. 2006. The Nomos of the Earth: In the International Law of the
Jus Publicum Europeaum. New York: Telos Press.
Schmitt, Carl. 2007. The Concept of the Political. Chicago: The University of
Chicago Press.
155 Realism in Practice
Schulz, William. 2001. In Our Own Best Interest: How Defending Human
Rights Benefits Us All. Boston: Beacon Press.
Stammers, Neil. 2009. Human Rights and Social Movements. London: Pluto
Press.
12
Why IR Realism Persists
M.J . PE T ER SON
Humans
Contemporary realists are also much less likely to invoke generalised notions
of ‘human nature’ in their arguments, though can identify enough greed,
aggressiveness, cheating, and other forms of bad behaviour in both inter-
individual and inter-group activity to maintain their view of politics as highly
conflictual. They can sidestep debates about whether there is some overall
‘human nature’ and what it might be by focusing on results of recent work in
human cognition to emphasise how processes of perception and
misperception affect governments’ choices and themselves encourage
conflict (e.g., Jervis 1976, Wohlforth 1993). Thus, contemporary realists have
backed away from some of the very strong assumptions about human
cognition and conduct prevalent in earlier decades without discarding their
overall expectation that interactions among states are likely to be competitive
and conflictual.
Government Decision-Making
Conditions changed later. The late 18th and early 19th centuries were marked
159 Realism in Practice
by the rise of democracy and nationalism. The mid and late 19th century were
a period of increasing cross-border interactions in trade, finance, travel,
science, and culture, and greater ideological divergence as the international
workers movement posed strong challenges to established ways. The 1930s
were dominated by an intense three-sided ideological contention culminating
in total war among democratic, fascist, and Leninist blocs. All these
developments meant that the neat separation between ‘domestic politics’ and
‘foreign policy’ prevailing in the mid-18th century progressively weakened and
even the governments of great powers were no longer as uniformly insulated
from domestic or transnational influences as they had been.
Not all IR theorists are satisfied by either the Waltzian ignoring of domestic
factors nor the claims that the primary causes of state behaviour exist at the
domestic level. IR theorists inspired by historical sociology have focused
analysis on the country-specific processes by which governments address the
dual challenge of maintaining themselves domestically through a strong state-
society connection and adjusting to challenges emanating from changing
external political and economic developments (e.g. Hobson 1997). Another
group, taking inspiration from Antonio Gramsci, understands international and
state levels as linked by contentions over governing ideas shaping politics at
both levels (e.g. van Apeldoorn 2002, Gill 2003). Rationalist theorists (e.g.
Why IR Realism Persists 160
The current debates about how and how far domestic politics and the
economic and other interconnections among societies pose serious
challenges to realist theorising by increasing the salience of the politics within
161 Realism in Practice
International System
Analysts who continue to view security and political concerns as primary have
developed a wider variety of ideas about international-level processes. For
realists, the political decentralisation of the world puts states into a
competitive situation in which governments are impelled to focus on ‘interests
defined as power’ (Morgenthau 1954, 5). This competitive milieu requires
state leaders who want to maintain their state over the long haul to analyse
Why IR Realism Persists 162
their situation, choose, and behave in broadly similar ways (e.g. Mearsheimer
2001; Walt 2005). While agreeing that the international system remains
decentralised, other groups of IR theorists have developed other visions of
system level process that challenge the realist emphasis on an enduring logic
of security-focused competition. English school theorists launched their notion
of a ‘society of states’ to argue that certain fundamental practices of
international politics guide government decisions more than typically assumed
in realist thinking (e.g., Bull 1977; Wight 1977) and are maintained through
processes of mutual socialisation indicating what is or is not acceptable
conduct (e.g., Clark 2005). Constructivist theorists, drawing to varying
degrees on linguistic and cognitive theories of meaning, argued that the
system process is malleable – or, as Alexander Wendt put it, ‘anarchy is what
states make of it’ (1992). Though disagreeing on the precise pathways
through which meanings are formed, constructivists, ranging from those
influenced by sociological institutionalism (e.g. Finnemore 1996) to those
inspired by critical theory (e.g. Fuchs and Kratochwil 2002), all agree that
there is no intrinsic reason political decentralisation is always marked by thin
sets of shared norms; governments and other actors can shape those norms
as they remake their view of the world. For constructivists, then,
decentralisation is compatible with the operation of thicker sets of norms that
provide more limits to choices and conduct than does the Realist version of
unending and unremitting security competition. Feminist theorists agree on
the malleability of system process, attributing much of its current highly
competitive form to the predominance of masculine notions of how the world
works (Tickner 2001, Shepherd 2010, Goldstein 2011).
Two changes receive the most attention. There is wide agreement that the
level of interconnection prevailing before 1914 was not attained again until
the 1970s, and has been exceeded today because the interconnections are
not just in trade and finance. Movements of individuals and families from
place to place occurred earlier, but the later 20th century provided
transportation and communication technologies more conducive to
maintaining contact and organising ‘diasporas’ to influence home country
developments or cross-border relations. The intensifications of economic
connections through global supply chains and global marketing have inspired
Why IR Realism Persists 164
claims about the rise of the trading state (Rosecrance 1986), and of a global
culture or polity (e.g., Meyer et al. 1997, Boli and Thomas 1999). Nor can
contemporary analysts of international relations ignore the steep reduction in
international war and the significant reduction in the total number of
casualties inflicted in both international and internal armed conflict since
1945. This has inspired claims that war is obsolescent (Mueller 1989,
Goldstein 2001) and that this obsolescence strongly influences the conduct of
territorial states. The strength of these developments explain why, as William
Wohlforth (2011) noted, most IR theorists now regard realism with its
emphasis on war in a state-centric world as outdated and irrelevant.
Yet, as the current example of Syria reminds us, there is nothing inevitable
about the post-1945 developments. The reduction in warfare and war-caused
human suffering is notable, and the literature on security communities (e.g.,
Adler and Barnett 1998,) suggests that there are ways states can remove
resorting to armed force from their foreign-policy repertoires vis-a-vis one
another. However, what Deutsch (1957) called ‘non-amalgamated security
communities’ – groups of non-fighting states in which the participating states
remain independent – take a long time to build and do not expand easily
beyond regional borders. Economic and social interconnection do matter, but
it remains unclear whether interconnections would now prove to be a bulwark
against a world war or would be broken up as easily as they were in 1914 and
after the Great Depression. Feminist arguments about the strong differences
between ‘male’ and ‘female’ ways of thinking have also been challenged by
arguments that many of the gender differences presented as ‘hardwired’ are
more the products of social expectations than of intrinsic working of human
brains (e.g., Fine 2011). Optimism about the spread of democracy has been
replaced by worry about revivals of xenophobic forms of nationalism in many
parts of the world.
*Author note: Thanks to Vinnie Ferraro, Jane Fountain, Peter Haas, Ray
LaRaja, Paul Musgrave and Kevin Young for helpful conversations, and to J.
R. Avgustin and Max Nurnus for encouragement and comments on earlier
drafts.
References
Angell, Norman. 1909. The Great Illusion: A Study of the Relation of Military
Power to National Advantage. London: William Heinemann.
Baylis, John, Steve Smith, and Patricia Owens, eds. 2008. The Globalisation
of World Politics. 4th edition. Oxford: Oxford University Press.
Boli, John and George M. Thomas, eds. 1999. Constructing World Culture:
International Nongovernmental Organizations since 1875. Stanford, CA:
Stanford University Press.
Booth, Ken and Steve Smith, eds. 1995. International Relations Theory
Today. Cambridge: Polity Press.
Bull, Hedley. 1977. The Anarchical Society. London: Macmillan and New York:
Columbia University Press.
Chase-Dunn, Christopher K., and Thomas D. Hall. 1997. Rise and Demise:
Comparing World – Systems. Boulder, CO: Westview Press.
Carr, E.H. 1939. The Twenty Years’ Crisis 1919–1939. London: Macmillan.
Chirot, Daniel. 1986. Social Change in the Modern Era. San Diego: Harcourt
Brace Jovanovich.
Deutsch, Karl. 1957. Political Community and the North American Area.
Princeton: Princeton University Press.
167 Realism in Practice
Doyle, Michael W. 1997. Ways of War and Peace. New York: W.W. Norton.
Fine, Cordelia. 2011. Delusions of Gender: How Our Minds, Society, and
Neurosexism Create Difference. New York: W.W. Norton.
Fuchs, Doris and Friedrich Kratochwil, eds. 2002. Transformative Change and
Global Order. Berlin: LIT Verlag.
Gill, Stephen. 2003. Power and Resistance in the New World Order. London:
Palgrave.
Gilpin, Robert. 1981. War and Change in World Politics. Princeton, NJ:
Princeton University Press.
Goldstein, Joshua. 2001. War and Gender: How Gender shapes the War
System and Vice-Versa. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
Goldstein, Joshua. 2011. Winning the War on War: The Decline of Armed
Conflict Worldwide New York: Dutton Penguin.
Grotius, Hugo. 1625. De Jure Belli ac Pacis (On the Law of War and Peace).
Ikenberry, John G. 2001. After Victory: Institutions, Strategic Restraint and the
Rebuilding of Order after Major Wars. Princeton, NJ: Princeton University
Press.
Kaldor, Mary. 2004. Global Civil Society: An Answer to War. Cambridge: Polity
Press.
Mann, Michael. 1988. States, War, and Capitalism. Oxford: Basil Blackwell.
169 Realism in Practice
Mansfield, Edward D. and Helen V Milner. 2012. Votes, Vetos, and the
Political Economy of International Trade Agreements. Princeton, NJ:
Princeton University Press.
Mearsheimer, John J. 2001. The Tragedy of Great Power Politics. New York:
W.W. Norton.
Meyer, John W., John Boli, George M. Thomas, and Francisco O. Ramirez.
1997. “World Society and the Nation-State”. American Journal of Sociology
103(1): 144–181.
Morgenthau, Hans. 1954. Politics among Nations. 2nd edition. New York:
Alfred A. Knopf.
Nowak, Martin A. 2006. “Five Rules for the Evolution of Cooperation”. Science
314(5805): 1560–3.
Pufendorf, Samuel von. 1672. De iure naturae et gentium (On the Law of
Nature and of Nations).
Rosecrance, Richard. 1986. The Rise of the Trading State: Commerce and
Conquest in the Modern World. New York: Basic Books.
Vattel, Emerich de. 1758. Le Droit des gens; ou, Principes de la loi naturelle
appliqués à la conduite et aux affaires des nations et des souverains (The
Law of Nations; or, Principles of the Law of Nature, Applied to the Conduct
and Affairs of Nations and Sovereigns).
Walt, Stephen. 2005. Taming American Power: The Global Response to U.S.
Primacy. New York: W.W. Norton.
Waltz, Kenneth. 1959. Man, The State, and War: A Theoretical Analysis.
New York: Columbia University Press.
Wohlforth, William. 1993. The Elusive Balance: Power and Perceptions during
the Cold War. Ithaca, NY: Cornell University Press.
Wohlforth, William. 2011. “No One Loves a Realist Explanation: The Cold
War’s End Revisited”. International Politics, 8(4/5): 441–459.
Note on Indexing 172
Note on Indexing
E-IR’s publications do not feature indexes. If you are reading this book in
paperback and want to find a particular word or phrase you can do so by
downloading a free PDF version of this book from the E-IR website.
View the e-book in any standard PDF reader such as Adobe Acrobat Reader
(pc) or Preview (mac) and enter your search terms in the search box. You can
then navigate through the search results and find what you are looking for. In
practice, this method can prove much more targeted and effective than
consulting an index.
If you are using apps (or devices) such as iBooks or Kindle to read our
e-books, you should also find word search functionality in those.
The purpose of this book is to appraise the current relevance and validity of realism as
an interpretative tool in contemporary International Relations. All chapters of the book are
animated by a theoretical effort to define the conceptual aspects of realism and attempt to
establish whether the tradition still provides the necessary conceptual tools to scholars.
The chapters address important issues in contemporary world politics through the
lens of realist theory such as the refugee crisis in Europe and the Middle East; the
war against ISIS; the appearance of non-state actors and outlaw agents; the rise of
China; cyberwarfare; human rights and humanitarian law. The collection also provides
insights on some of the theoretical tenets of classical and structural realism. Overall, the
collection shows that, in spite of its many shortcomings, realism still offers a multifaceted
understanding of world politics and enlightens the increasing challenges of world politics.
Edited by
Davide Orsi, J. R. Avgustin & Max Nurnus
Contributors
Francis A. Beer, Koldo Casla, Anthony J.S. Craig, Layla Dawood, Robert Hariman, Richard
Ned Lebow, Tony Chih-Chi Lee, Stephen McGlinchey, Robert W. Murray, Arash Heydarian
Pashakhanlou, M.J. Peterson, Carsten Rauch, Felix Rösch, Archie W. Simpson, Brandon
Valeriano and Anders Wivel.
www.E-IR.info