Modal and Modality by Besga PDF
Modal and Modality by Besga PDF
AND MODALITY
IN ENGLISH
Universidad de Zaragoza
1. INTRODUCTION
Modals in English (can, could, may, might, must, will, would, shall,
should, ought and need) are considered to be auxiliary verbs with a high
degree of grammaticalization which is reflected in some morphosyntactic
characteristics, such as the fact that they have no -s endings for the third
person singular, and no infinitives, or past forms (except the forms could
and would in some instances). In addition, many of them also have weak
and contracted forms.
However simple their morphosyntactic functioning has become, a
corresponding simplification and reduction of their meaning has not taken
place. Let us take for instance the modal can. With this verb we can form
sentences like the following:
We can see that there are many different possible senses for this verb
([5], [6], and [7] are pragmatically motivated, but [1], [2], [3] and [4] are
clearly different meanings of the same modal). It could be argued that this
is not a good example, since there are other modals which are more
grammaticalized. Such is the case of will or would. But, still, we can
distinguish different senses, as we can see in these examples for will:
The following are examples of how these schemas have evolved in dif-
ferent European languages:
Now, if we look at the way in which these schemas have given rise to
modals in English, it is interesting to note that verbs with full semantic
content have become emptied of their semantic load. This phenomenon has
also run parallel to a shift in grammatical category, word-class,
morphosyntactic properties and even phonetic form. In a schematic way,
we can say that modals have followed the shift from being in a structure
[X-verb-complement] to a structure of the form [X-grammatical concept-
main verb] (as postulated for all kinds of auxiliaries in Heine 1993: 47).
Heine calls this shift the Verb-to-TAM3 chain, in which several processes
work at the same time: Desemanticization, decategorialization,
cliticization, and (phonetical) erosion (Heine 1993: 54-58). This is well
conceptualized by means of 'overlap' models, such as the following:
Stage: I II III
---------------------------------------------------------------------------------
---
Type of
concept: Source Source Target
Target
Overlap model of morphosyntactic shift:
Stage: I II III
---------------------------------------------------------------------------------
---
Morphosyntax: Verbal Verbal Grammatical
Grammatical
Stage: I II III
---------------------------------------------------------------------------------
---
Phonological
form of Full Full Reduced
expression: Reduced
Overall stage A B C D E F G
----------------------------------------------------------------------------------
-
Desemanticization I II III
Decategorialization I II III IV V
Cliticization I II III
Erosion I II III
If we try to fit the evolution of English modals into this general schema and
look for the stages that correspond to some of them, we find that they are
in stage E in most of their uses, which means that, according to the
specifications provided by Heine (1993: 54-56) for every stage, they have
the following properties:
In the preceding section, we have seen that there exists a clear, systematic
account of how different senses of the same modals are etymologically
related. However, their coexistence in a given moment is something that
needs a synchronic formulation. Owing to the fact that modality is closely
related with tense/aspect in most linguistic descriptions, it is fair to treat
them here together, as constitutive parts of the so-called TAM (Time-
Aspect-Modality) system. With this in mind we could start by referring to a
grammatical model in which tense, aspect and modality have provided
evidence for a complex, multilayered description of the clause: S. C. Dik's
Functional Grammar (from now on, FG).
In FG, following suggestions by Hengeveld (1989), which were in turn
based on the layered structure of the clause proposed in Foley and Van
Valin's (1984) RRG,4 utterances can be analysed in terms of a multilayered
structure with this form:
LAYERS
Clause: (E1 : [ILL (S) (A) (x1 : etc. (x1 ))] (E1))
Proposition: (x1 : [(e1: etc. (e1))] (x1 ))
Predication: (e1: [Pred (x 1)n ] (e1 ))
Term: (x1 : PredN (x1 ))
There are operators (p) for each of the four levels, so that the total
representation would be something like
(E1 : [4 ILL (S) (A) (3 x1 : (
2 e1: [1 Pred(x1 : pred(x 1)) ...
(xn )] (e1 )) (x1 ))] (E1))
1 : Predicate operators
3 : Proposition operators
2 : Predication operators 4 : Illocution
operators
Van Valin's original proposal found justification for its tripartite divi-
sion of clause structure in evidence from expressions for the TAM system.
This is also the case with FG; we shall therefore look at how FG treats
TAM questions in its description, in order to see what can be used for an
adequate treatment of modality interactions.
Tense and aspect are traditionally considered to deal with the expression of
time. Tense concerns its "external" configuration, that is, the distribution of
events along a temporal line, whereas aspect concerns its "internal"
structure, that is, how time is organized inside a situation. Tense, according
to Hengeveld (1989: 132), is represented by level-2 2 operators. This is
so because it tends to be further away from the verb nucleus than aspect
(level-1 and level-2 operators; see below). Aspect, however, is a more
complicated matter. Aspectuality encompasses many distinctions that are
categorized under different labels in different linguistic traditions. In
Functional Grammar, according to Dik (1989: 186-187), who reserves the
term "aspect" only for those aspectuality distinctions which are
grammatically rather than lexically expressed, aspectuality covers the
following sub-areas:
Of the utmost interest is the fact that, regardless of their concrete value
as judgements, all these possible modalities can easily be explained in
logical terms by means of a possible worlds approach.6 Modality expressed
logically in terms of possible worlds (certainty and probability) has been
extended in order to interpret obligation/permission (deontic logic), and
knowledge/belief (epistemic logic); all these different logical models
account for the opposition realis/irrealis, which Givón (1993: 172 and ff.)
uses to denote a characteristic feature of modality. The logical approach
therefore provides us with an instrument which explains deontic modality
as a special variety of epistemic modality, the subsumption of the former
by the latter being plausible in the kind of explanatory schema suggested
below. Obligation implies certainty and permission possibility; in a similar
way, knowledge implies certainty and belief possibility.
3.4. Interactions
High
Impossibility Low possibility FUTURE
possibility
PRESENT
Present (R = E = S)
Past (R = E) < S
Future (R = S) < E
Present Perfect E < (R = S)
Past Perfect E<R<S
Future PerfectS < E < R
The three parameters can now be used not only as points in temporal
space, but also as points in hypothetical space. Thus, the expression of hy-
pothesis can be compactly explained together with time. If we look at fig. 1
again, we can see that in the PAST cone there is an actual path (certainty),
some other paths that could have been possible since they could have led
to the PRESENT point (possibility), and an area outside the cone in which
no path could have led to that point (impossibility). In the FUTURE cone
the picture is pretty much the same, although, as we are now in the irrealis
mode, there is no certainty path but only a highest possibility one. A
convenient way of stating three parameters for modality would be to
consider at least three degrees of "reality" (certainty, possibility, and
impossibility or uncertainty). Again, we can set three parameters: reality of
event (Er), reality of reference (Rr), and reality of speech (Sr). The reality
of event stands for the degree of reality that the main event has; the reality
of reference may be the certain condition or assumption that is used for
assigning realis or irrealis status to the event; finally, the reality of speech
has to do with the utterance itself.
Some examples of how this representation is to be applied are the fol-
lowing:
4. CONCLUSION
NOTES
1. Dirven points out that "there is a long tradition in the descriptive grammar writing
of English which concentrates solely or predominantly on the modal auxiliaries, excluding
the other expressions of modality" (1989: 60). We acknowledge the fact that this is true;
moreover, there are even expressions in which modals themselves use adverbials to grade
their meaning. Consider, for instance, the following sequence of expressions for epistemic
modality:
Our consideration of only modal auxiliaries here does not imply that there are not other
resources for the expression of modality.
2. It is customary in research on modals and modality to refer to the work carried out by
authors like Palmer (1979, 1986), Twaddell (1963), and others. The interested reader may go
to these sources for more information. Basically, Sweetser (1990) and Heine (1993) give a
very up-to-date (although less extense) account of this topic, enriched with a more cogni-
tively-oriented perspective.
4. Foley and Van Valin propose three levels: the nucleus (predicate and predicate
operators - aspectual inflections and adverbials), the core (nucleus and verbal arguments, as
well as some modal operators), and the periphery (adjuncts, tense, subjective markers,
evidential modalities, and indicators of illocutionary force).
5. A core predication has the form [[1pred (arg)n ] (1)n ] in FG, corresponding to a
level-1 structure.
7. Van Benthem (1988: 36) makes a connection with tense logic systems and also refers
to a partial tense logic system developed by Goldblatt (1980), but the use of these cones for
the study of modality in natural languages is unknown to me.
9. A structured world model assumes that the world is structured in a certain way and
that some events are incidental whereas others are regular and predictable. When it is the
case that we are referring to manifestations of the normal course of events, then we may do
so by using strong probability or habituality.
WORKS CITED