The Practice of Time Time and Practice PDF
The Practice of Time Time and Practice PDF
148
Margus Ott & Alari Allik | 149
Time
The First Aspect: Contemplation and Contraction
In our experience of time, the present is not an ideal, vanish-
ing point between the past and the future. Rather, it possesses a cer-
tain “volume,” a quantity of implicit content that has been condensed
or “contracted” in its interior (mm, 69–71, 137–9, 205–8). Bergson gives
the example of the perception of light, where billions of light waves are
concentrated to produce a single perceptual act (mm, 205). For us, the
act is an indivisible whole, but of itself it contains a myriad light waves
which we contract and construct. Thus the quality (for example, the per-
ception of the color red) is essentially the result of the contraction of a
certain quantity (light waves of 405–80 thz). In order to contract those
light-waves, we must have a kind of automatic “memory” that “remem-
bers” huge quantities of elementary oscillations and accumulates them,
so that before we perceive light, we have already amassed an enormous
number of small events (light-wave oscillations or photon impacts). The
first oscillations have vanished, but for us, they have been preserved; they
are “remembered” and combine to produce the perception.
Deleuze calls the place of this process of accumulation or contrac-
tion the “contemplative soul” (dr, 74) or “larval subject” (dr, 78). The
function of the contemplative soul is to contract events to suit its capaci-
ties. We may say that for every kind of event there is a particular self:
150 | The Practice of Time
an acoustic self for contracting auditory signals, a visual self for ocular
stimuli (or perhaps various visual selves for different aspects of vision,
such as shape, color, movement, faces, and so forth.). These are percep-
tual examples, but Deleuze goes on to say that our bodies themselves
are collections of contractions: every cell and every organ is the result
of contractions of nutrition, energy, and forces (cf. dr, 73). Before light
can be perceived by the eye, the eye itself has to be created. Those bodily
contractions give birth to our “living presents,” and time as duration is
generated. In the living present, previous contractions are retained and
subsequent ones are anticipated, and in this way, habits from the past
and predilections for the future are formed (and the stronger the habit,
the greater the predilection). However, they are both “dimensions of the
present itself” (dr, 71).
Contraction and contemplation is the first aspect of time. Deleuze
calls it a “passive synthesis” which is not yet subject to the require-
ments of action. This is pure presence—the experience of itself and its
surroundings—before it is divided into action (motor system) and per-
ception (sensory system). After this division, we enter “active synthesis,”
the dynamic counterpart of the first aspect of time, which entails the
reconstruction of time, no longer as duration, but rather as a succession
of equal moments in an intellectualized “space of time.” At this point,
we distinguish and organize moments that were previously contracted
and fused together in passive synthesis (dr, 71). According to this spatial
concept of time, moments are made exterior to each other and become
homogeneous and equal1 (Bergson 1960, 124–5). This is abstract or
intellectual time, where future, past, and present are reified as sections of
an ideal “timeline.”
2. This theory could also explain the phenomenon of “life review” in near-death
experiences: because death seems inevitable and attention to life is suddenly diverted,
the filtering aspect of memory is removed, and all of the past suddenly becomes acces-
sible, for us as it is in itself.
152 | The Practice of Time
3. This is Deleuze’s favorite topic of analysis, which he repeats over three decades,
beginning with an essay in 1956, “Bergson’s Conception of Difference” (Deleuze
1999), and extending to a 1985 essay entitled “Cinema 2” (Deleuze 1989). It is one
of very few motifs that recur frequently in his thinking and writing.
154 | The Practice of Time
But the idea of the pure past requires further development. The whole
of the past is not limited to one being, but extends to all of being. We
may think back in time and ask, When does contemplation begin? Let us
suppose that my first memories are from my third birthday party. But the
fact that I remember this shows that at the time I was already a subject
of contemplation. Did this contemplative system begin with the acquisi-
tion of language? Language seems to be related to the capacity to recall
memories at will, but it clearly did not create my momentary duration,
my living present, out of nothing. I already existed, and language only
transformed my way of existing, my particular “melody.”
This concept may be applied to all prior phases of ontogenesis. Neither
birth nor the moment of conception may be considered the point at
which contemplation is created; they merely transform previous forms
of contemplation. In the case of conception, the oocyte and the sperma-
tozoon that come together are themselves contemplations and contrac-
tions, so that conception may be described as a mere transformation of
the mode of contemplation, not its creation.4 I am composed of parts of
my parents’ bodies, from their “subconscious.” In this sense, individual-
ity is not absolute and all living beings, from the very beginning of life,
are engaged in a web of interconnections (as shown, for example, by
Ruyer 1946, 1).
The pure pasts that enable the duration of different subjects cannot
be separated from each other; otherwise, contact with them would be
impossible. They must be identical, forming the basis of an immense cos-
mic memory (dr, 83; b, 100). But in fact, every individual actualizes only
a certain level of contraction or relaxation of this virtual memory-cone
(b, 101), which itself actualizes only a small part of its own virtual mem-
ory (namely, that which is related to its present behavior). Therefore for-
getting is an essential characteristic of human being. It is not something
that “happens” to us as a matter of chance, but is a foundational act that
distinguishes our mode of being from others. We forget because we have
to pay attention to life, as Bergson says, we have to act in our surround-
ings. For Bergson, therefore, the brain is more an organ for forgetting
than remembering: it holds most of the past at bay and allows only cer-
tain memories to pass through its filter, by adopting an attitude which in
some respects resembles (by similarity or contiguity) the memory that we
recall. “Such is the brain’s part in the work of memory: it does not serve
to preserve the past, but primarily to mask it, then to allow only what is
practically useful to emerge through the mask” (Bergson 1920, 71).
5. The Chinese teaching of the five elements—wuxing (五行) did not regard the
formation of the senses and sense-objects in exactly the same vein and depth as the
Buddhist tradition. We would nevertheless like to point out that because the element
“moves” (行), it may be said to “practice.”
160 | The Practice of Time
The meaning of the term gyōji is to eternally maintain the path of the
Buddha’s ancestors (zd, 221). But it is significant that there is no one
“individual” who upholds the practice, as if carrying the weight of the
whole world on his shoulders. Practice upholds itself; it is the constant
movement, the constant unfolding of the “leaves” of practice that main-
tains the world in its ten directions. From this perspective, we can also
take Dōgen quite literally when he states in the Sansuikyō:
[A] mountain always practices in every place. (md, 98)
When your learning is immature, you are shocked by the words “flow-
ing mountains.” (md, 99)
ing its implicit parts explicit and unfolding them in an intellectual space
of time. This image of time is actually space, because its components
are treated as identical and homogeneous. It is only in the secondary
“active” modality that one can conceive of different possibilities of being,
such as birth and death (md, 74–75 and elsewhere); or “for a while I was
three heads and eight arms” and “for a while I was an eight- or sixteen-
foot body” (md, 77); or “there is delusion and realization, practice, and
birth and death, and there are buddhas and sentient beings” (md, 69).
In other words, one conceives of birth and death, practice and realiza-
tion as different points in time.
It might be argued that the spatialization of time gives us the capacity
to distance ourselves from our immediate surroundings, to take a step
back. We become capable of voluntarily delaying our actions. But in so
doing, we lose immediate contact and interaction with our surroundings
and thus lose sight of the essence of time, the temporal whole.
Oneself (ego)
birth-and-death
Human beings (human dimension
generation-and extinction
Living beings (living dimension
appearance-and-disappearance
being and nonbeing
All beings (being dimension)
saṃsāra-qua-nirvāna
buddha-nature buddha-nature is
(no buddha-nature) impermanence impermanence — buddha-nature
all beings are the buddh-nature
nirvāna
saṃsāra-qua-nirvāna
Realization of imperma-
Human beings nence qua realization of
buddha-nature
True Self
saṃsāra
1. The cone of actuality stands upright. The whole of being (the cos-
mos) is the base and the ego is the tip. This cone is saṃsāra.
2. The inverted cone of virtuality has buddha-nature as its base. This
cone is nirvāna. Abe does not provide a label for the tip of this
cone. We would like to suggest the “image or figure of Buddha,”
the “intention to become Buddha,” or the “no-self” (which we will
discuss later).
3. The awakened self is situated at the intersection of the two cones (on
the level of human beings, in conformity with the Buddhist tradition
that enlightenment is accessible only at the human level and not at
higher or lower levels). This is samsara qua nirvana.
According to the logic of the scheme, the difference between an awak-
ened and unawakened individual is that for the unawakened, the two
dimensions (buddha-nature and whole-being, nirvāna and saṃsāra) are
not distinguished but objectified in the sense that the individual reduces
them to his or her own size (an intermediate section of the cone). The
authentic or “true” self contracts that section to a single point (identified
on the scheme), and in so doing, achieves the pure ontological distinction
between buddha-nature and whole-being. The awakened individual also
amplifies them and realizes their infinite nature (the bases of the cones
are portrayed as dotted lines, to indicate bottomlessness). The unawak-
ened individual inhabits a small cone whose base is “human beings” and
whose tip is “ego.” The authentic self breaks through the human plane
with the help of the “image or figure of Buddha,” the “intention to
become the Buddha,” or the “no-self” that we have suggested as the tip
of the inverted cone. This testifies to the actuality of the virtual buddha-
nature and provides a guideline for breaking through the purely human
circle by drawing attention to the conditions for the possibility of this
circle, namely, the pure dimensions of ground and occasion.
In this way a human being is able to overcome egoism, to avoid shrink-
ing the cones to the constrained, deluded world, and thus to live at the
intersection of the cones—the one serving as a ground and the other as
an occasion. Abe cites Hegel’s Science of Logic to argue that these dimen-
sions are distinct but not separate or separable: “The truth is not their
lack of distinction, but that they are not the same, that they are abso-
Margus Ott & Alari Allik | 165
By taking a step back7 and turning the light inwards, one goes beyond
thinking (shiryō) and not-thinking (fushiryō), and moves toward with-
out-thinking (hishiryō). The thinking “I” is not eradicated, but made
transparent—in the mode of without-thinking, it becomes an organ of
the “true self,” which constantly generates as well as negates thoughts.
Ordinary thinking revolves around intentions and plans; without-think-
ing is free from intentionality:
Without-thinking is distinct from thinking and not thinking precisely
in not assuming any intentional activity whatsoever: it neither affirms
7. The “step back” has also been a recurrent theme in the Western philosophical
tradition, from Plato to Heidegger (cf. Heidegger 2002).
166 | The Practice of Time
nor denies, accepts nor rejects, believes nor disbelieves. In fact, it does
not objectify implicitly or explicitly. (Kasulis 1985, 72–3)
During everyday activities, we sometimes experience breaks where
without-thinking suspends our usual state of mind. Kasulis gives the
example of a man taking a short rest while mowing his lawn. The man
“simply is as he is without any intentional activity at all” (73). For a
moment, he is not doing anything, yet he is completely present. Kasulis
tells us that without-thinking is a pre-reflective state of mind that “sup-
plies the raw material out of which the later reflective thinking act devel-
ops” (74). The “full and self-contained” present moment is the time
when the raw data of experience is collected:
Consequently, the present moment of experience is always full and
self-contained. Only when we engage in thinking or not-thinking and
objectify the experience of a past moment does that experience seem
limited and capable of being fully analyzed. (Kasulis 1985, 76)
For Kasulis, without-thinking occurs at the moment when we are
detached from immediate action and volition. During this moment a
“receptive intuition” behind the thinking self emerges and enables one
to fully experience time in its “suchness.” (The present moment in this
context means the suchness of time or the “empty form of time” in
Deleuze’s terms.)
In Kasulis’s example, the thinking self is suspended and resumed when
the pure experience of suchness is replaced by intellectual understand-
ing. In the context of zazen, it makes more sense not to separate these
processes in time but to affirm their contemporaneity in the experiencing
self. In zazen one experiences the “true form of self ”’ in the without-
thinking mode. The thinking “I” is experienced in the without-thinking
mode as the self’s Other. Dōgen states that: “There is someone in non-
thinking and this someone maintains us” (Bielefeldt 1988, 189). In
this statement, we can detect a fracture similar to the one that Deleuze
discusses in the third synthesis of time.
Dōgen tells us that buddhas do not necessarily know that they are
enlightened beings (md, 69), because if such a thought appeared in their
consciousness, it would immediately drop away. Enlightenment is an
unopposed movement of difference itself. It is the constant process of
Margus Ott & Alari Allik | 167
dropping away, which leaves only traces, the empty shells of something
that has already moved beyond:
To study the buddha way is to study the self. To study the self is to
forget the self. To forget the self is to be actualized by myriad things.
When actualized by myriad things, the body and mind as well as the
bodies and minds of others drop away. No trace of realization remains,
and this no-trace continues endlessly. (md, 70)
I am not only the “thinking I” who is a being in time, and the self who
is the “receptive intuition” (dr, 86) behind the thinking, but I am also
a contemplation of the buddhas themselves. The receptive intuition of
the passive self connects my being with the contemplation of the dharma
body of the self.
Thus the “whole of time” is present in the experience of sitting still,
and in the fracture of the self as the self confronts the Other within itself.
What makes zazen the activity of the “true self ” is that it does not try
to overcome this fracture by filling it with a new identity, (as did Kant,
according to Deleuze, see dr, 87). The fracture is not seen as a “fault,”
but rather as the source of non-dual activity. The fracture itself is the
“true form of self,” and the separation created by the fracture is exposed
as an illusion when the true form of difference is understood.
tice and the not-yet-enlightened self becomes identical with the already-
enlightened self in the “present of metamorphosis,” to borrow Deleuze’s
term (dr, 89). The entire event is thus described later as “killing Bud-
dha”:
At the very moment that we are seated Buddha we are killing Bud-
dha [...]. Although the word “kill” here is identical with that used
by ordinary people, [...] its meaning is not the same. Moreover we
must investigate in what form it is that a seated Buddha is killing Bud-
dha. Taking up the fact that it is itself a virtue of the Buddha to kill a
Buddha (殺仏), we should study whether we are killers (殺人) or not.
(Bielefeldt, 32; sg 1, 133)
As soon as the small self becomes buddha, it turns against the self (see
dr, 89) and erases both sides of the symbolon—the image of the self
and the image of the Buddha. Killing is an event that takes place in the
without-thinking mode of practice, and it eradicates both sides of the
symbolon, the ego as well as the figure of Buddha (in Abe’s scheme).
These sides are figured in the process of buddha-production.
Could “figuring” be considered an activity of “without-thinking”? In
figuring to become a buddha, we do not really intend to become a bud-
dha, but we are making both the goal and its negation visible; we are
making the conditionality of such “maps” or “figures” transparent by
introducing the empty form of time into the practice.
The division of the self disappears as soon as the practitioner takes
a step back. In stepping back, both sides of the symbolon of the self
become visible and are immediately discarded as empty shells. In this
act of stepping back and dropping away, the repetition of the difference
itself is affirmed: all acts are seen as non-acts in the non-doing of zazen.
As we have seen, in the Chan/Zen tradition there are some similarities
to the “enormous act” (killing Buddha) on the rhetorical level, but the
practice of seated meditation itself constitutes the “figuring” of the Bud-
dha in the mode of without-thinking and non-doing, where the fracture
of I and Self is continuously reenacted in its numerous manifestations.
The faces constantly return, the images are formed again and again, but
as soon as they appear, they drop away. It is this incessant process of
stepping back and dropping away that enables the “true return” of the
170 | The Practice of Time
practitioner to the pure past, which in turn enables the eternal return of
the old buddhas:
Although all forty Buddhist patriarchs are old buddhas—they have a
mind, they have a body, they have a state of brightness and a national
land, they have passed away some time ago and they have not yet
passed away. Both the “already passed away” and “not yet passed
away” should be seen as the virtue of old buddhas. Studying the path
of old buddhas is authenticating the path of old buddhas. From one
generation to the next the old buddhas [emerge]. Although the “old”
in old buddha appears to be same as “old” in the expression “new and
old” it completely overcomes the past and present by directly con-
necting them [...].
The self that does not abide in the old buddhas would not know
whence the old buddhas emerge. The one who knows where the old
buddhas abide is the old buddha. (sg, 123)
Dōgen hereby circumvents the historical past of the Buddhist patri-
archs and the buddhas of the “present of metamorphosis” by claiming
that all buddhas and patriarchs appear in the time of the “authentica-
tion of the path.” Therefore, enlightenment is the convergence of two
sources: practicing zazen and transmitting the teaching from the direct
lineage of Shakyamuni Buddha. Only by sitting still can you actually
“know” the old buddhas, and you will become at home in the place
from which the buddhas emerge. This is the place where the passive self
becomes the active self of the Buddha who constantly generates bud-
dhas. But, paradoxically, since this place is only accessible through the
practice of dropping away, one can only abide in the presence of the old
buddhas through the dropping away of the mind of the old buddhas:
Standing before the different buddhas, the mind of the old buddhas
blossoms, standing behind the different buddhas the mind of the old
Buddhas forms its fruits, standing before the mind of the old buddhas
the mind of the old buddhas will drop away (古仏心脱落). (sg, 117)
Dōgen admonishes us against attaching ourselves to the present moment,
since this would create a fixed center and suspend the eternal return of
the Buddhas. In practicing zazen, we disengage time and liberate its pure
empty form, so that time becomes the essence of practice.
Margus Ott & Alari Allik | 171
Practicing time
10. This is a pleonasm, but one cannot overemphasize the sense in which the tem-
porality of life calls us back us from the “eternal” world of ideas.
172 | The Practice of Time
11. Spinoza (Ethics, iii, prop. 53) states that when the mind contemplates itself and
its power of activity, it is affected by joy (Cum Mens se ipsam, suamque agendi poten-
tiam contemplatur, laetatur, Spinoza 1999: 286).
Margus Ott & Alari Allik | 173
references
Abbreviations
b Gilles Deleuze, Bergsonism. (New York: Zone Books, 1991).
dr Gilles Deleuze, Difference and Repetition (New York: Columbia Uni-
versity Press, 1994).
md Moon in a Dewdrop: Writings of Zen Master Dōgen, ed. by Kazuaki
Tanahashi (New York: North Point Press, 1985).
mm Henri Bergson, Matter and Memory, trans. by Nancy Margaret Paul
and W. Scott Palmer (New York: Zone Books, 1991).
sg 『正法眼蔵』, 寺田透 Terada Tōru et al., eds.『日本思想大系』(Tokyo: Iwa
nami Shoten, 1970–1982), vols. 12–13.
sz 『正法眼蔵随聞記』, ed. by 山崎正一 Yamazaki Masakazu (Tokyo: Kōdan
sha Gakujutsu Bunko, 2003).
zd 『禅学大辞典』[Dictionary of Zen studies] (Tokyo: Komazawa Univer-
sity, 1985).
Kasulis, Thomas P.
1985 Zen Action/Zen Person (Honolulu: University of Hawai‘i Press).
Keizan Jōkin 螢山紹瑾
2004 “Zazen Yojinki: Notes On What To Be Aware of in Zazen,” in John
Daido Loori, ed., The Art of Just Sitting (Boston: Wisdom Publica-
tions).
Lysenko, Viktoria G.
2009 “Mahābhūta,” in M. T. Stepanyants, ed., Indiiskaya filosofia: entsiklope-
dia (Moscow: Vostochnaya Literatura).
Matsunaga, Daigan and Alicia
1992 Foundations of Japanese Buddhism (Los Angeles and Tokyo: Budhist
Books International).
Nishijima Gudō and Chodo Cross
1994 Master Dōgen’s Shōbōgenzō: Book 1 (London: Windbell Publications).
Okumura, Shohaku
2004 Shōbōgenzō-zuimonki: Sayings of Eihei Dōgen Zenji recorded by Koun Ejō
(Tokyo: Sotoshu Shumucho).
Stone, Jacqueline I.
1999 Original Enlightenment and the Transformation of Medieval Japanese
Buddhism (Honolulu: University of Hawai‘i Press).
Ruyer, Raymond
1946 Éléments de psycho-biologie (Paris: Puf).
Spinoza, Baruch
1999 Éthique. Texte bilingue latin/grec-français (Paris: Seuil).
Suzuki, Shunryū
1999 Branching Streams Flow in the Darkness: Zen Talks on Sandokai (Los
Angeles: University of California Press).