Chapter One - What's The Problem?
Chapter One - What's The Problem?
Co
ons
nsci
ciou
ciou
usn
snes
esss
es
For this first exercise I shall give you more detailed guidance than for future ones. All the rest
build on the same foundation, so you should find that if you practise this one frequently all
the others will be easier.
The task is simply this.
As many times as you can, every day, ask yourself ‘Am I conscious now?’.
The idea is not to provide an answer – for example ‘Yes’ – twenty or a hundred times a day,
but to begin looking into your own consciousness. When do you answer ‘Yes’ and when
‘No’?. What does your answer mean?
You might like to ask the question and then just hold it for a little while, observing being
conscious now. Since this whole book is about consciousness, this exercise is simply
intended to get you to look at what consciousness is, as well as to think and argue about it
intellectually.
This sounds easy but it is not. Try it and see. After a day of practising or, if you are working
through the book, before you go on to the next chapter, make notes on the following:
● How many times did you do the practice?
● What happened?
● Did you find yourself asking other questions as well? If so, what were they?
● Was it difficult to remember to do it? If so, why do you think this is?
You may have found that you had intended to do the practice but then forgot. If you need
reminding you might try these simple tricks:
● Ask the question whenever you hear or read the word ‘consciousness’.
● Always ask the question when you go to the toilet.
● Write the question on stickers and place them around your home or office.
● Discuss the practice with a friend. You may help remind each other.
These may help. Even so, you may still find that you forget. This is odd because there is
no very good excuse. After all, this little practice does not take up valuable time when you
could be doing something more useful. It is not like having to write another essay, read
another paper, or understand a difficult argument. You can ask the question in the middle
of doing any of these things. You can ask it while walking along or waiting for the bus, while
washing up or cooking, while cleaning your teeth or listening to music. It takes no time away
from anything else you do. You just keep on doing it, pose the question and watch for a
moment or two.
You must be interested in consciousness to be reading this book. So why is it so hard just
to look at your own consciousness?
Are you conscious now?
10
that the two interacted through the pineal gland in the centre of the brain,
but proposing a place where it happens does not solve the mystery. If
thoughts can affect brain cells then either they work by magic or they
must be using some kind of energy or matter. In this case they are also
physical stuff and not purely mental.
Dualism does not work. Almost all contemporary scientists and philos-
ophers agree on this. In 1949 the British philosopher Gilbert Ryle derided
dualism as ‘the dogma of the Ghost in the Machine’ – a phrase that has
entered into common parlance. He argued that when we talk of the mind
as an entity that does things we are making a category mistake – turning
it into something it is not. Instead he saw mental activities as processes,
or as the properties and dispositions of people.
This kind of view is apparent in many modern descriptions of mind
and self: ‘Minds are simply what brains do’ (Minsky, 1986, p 287); ‘“Mind”
is designer language for the functions that the brain carries out’ (Claxton,
1994, p 37); mind is ‘the personalization of the physical brain’ (Greenfield,
2000, p 14) and self is ‘not what the brain is, but what it does’ (Feinberg,
2009, p xxi). Such descriptions make it possible to talk about some mental
Figure 1.3 Gilbert Ryle activities and mental abilities without supposing that there is a separate
dubbed the Cartesian view mind. This is probably how most psychologists and neuroscientists think
of mind ‘the dogma of the of ‘mind’ today, and they do not agonise about what ‘mind’ really is. But
Ghost in the Machine’. there is much less agreement when it comes to ‘consciousness’.
There are very few dualists today. In the last century, philosopher of
‘Human science Sir Karl Popper and neurophysiologist Sir John Eccles (1977) pro-
consciousness is posed a theory of dualist interactionism. They argued that the critical
just about the last processes in the synapses of the brain are so finely poised that they can be
influenced by a non-physical, thinking and feeling self. Thus the self really
surviving mystery.’ does control its brain (Eccles, 1994). How it does so they admit remains
(Dennett, 1991: 21) mysterious. More recently, Benjamin Libet (1916–2007) proposed that
a non-physical ‘conscious mental field’ is responsible for the unity and
continuity of subjective experience and for free
will (Libet, 2004). Somewhat like known physi-
Activity y – What is consciousness? cal force fields it emerges from brain activity
but can then communicate within the cerebral
There is no generally recognised definition of con-
sciousness, which is why I have not given one here. See cortex without using the neural connections
whether you can find your own. and pathways. But how it does this he does not
First get into pairs. One person proposes a definition of explain.
consciousness. Then the other finds something wrong It seems that dualism, in its many forms,
with it. Don’t be shy or think too long – even the silliest
always arrives in the end at magic, or mystery,
suggestions can be fun to try. So just throw up one idea
and wait for it to be knocked down. Then swap over. Do or something that science can never approach.
this as quickly as you reasonably can until each of you As Dennett puts it, ‘accepting dualism is giv-
has had several turns. ing up’ (Dennett, 1991, p 37). But avoiding it
Get back together into the group and find out what is not easy.
kinds of objections you all came up with.
Given the lurking spectre of dualism it
Why is defining consciousness so hard when we all is not surprising that psychology, as a disci-
think we know what it is?
14 pline, has had such trouble with the concept of
consciousness.
Figure 1.4 When the rat presses the lever it may receive a food pellet or a sip of water. Rats,
pigeons and many other animals can easily learn to press a certain number of times, or only when a
green light is on, or when a bell sounds. This is known as operant conditioning. Many behaviourists
18 believed that studying animal learning was the best way to understand the human mind.
Further Reading
Bayne, T., Cleeremans, A. and Wilken, P. (2009) The Oxford Companion
to Consciousness, Oxford, Oxford University Press. Hundreds of short
entries by over 200 authors on everything from access consciousness to
zombies; provides an idea of the scope of consciousness studies. 21
22