Introduction Two Kinds of Proportion
Introduction Two Kinds of Proportion
Matthew A. Cohen
The diverse collection of essays presented in this volume grew out of the international
conference “Proportional Systems in the History of Architecture,” held in Leiden in
March 2011 (Fig. 1).1 The conference was scheduled to commemorate the sixtieth
anniversary of the last international conference on proportional systems in the arts,
held in Milan in 1951 and titled “De divina proportione,” which similarly gathered
leading thinkers of its day (Fig. 2).2 This anniversary thus offers a valuable opportunity
to reflect on where the study of proportional systems has gone over the past sixty
years, and where it might most productively go from here. Although the premises
of the two conferences were fundamentally different from one another—the Milan
conference promoted the contemporary use of proportional systems in the arts
for the aesthetic and spiritual betterment of society, while the Leiden conference
promoted the historical study of specifically architectural proportional systems for
the advancement of scholarly knowledge—certain noteworthy attitudes toward the
subject of proportional systems manifested in the Milan conference are still prominent
today.3 Both conferences together demonstrate a sustained recognition of the
importance of the multidisciplinary study of proportional systems as integral parts of
human culture across time and geography. Less productively, while sympathy with the
overtly mystical beliefs that drove the Milan conference is substantially more subdued
in the scholarly community today, a fundamental ambiguity inherent in the concept
of proportion that enabled those beliefs to flourish in 1951 continues to characterize
much scholarly thinking about this subject today: when architectural historians use
the word “proportion,” whether they intend it to signify a ratio, architectural beauty, or
both simultaneously, is often unclear to author and reader alike.
13
Reprint from "Proportional Systems in the History of Architecture" - ISBN 9789087282776 - © Leiden University Press, 2018
Matthew A. Cohen
14
Reprint from "Proportional Systems in the History of Architecture" - ISBN 9789087282776 - © Leiden University Press, 2018
Two Kinds of Proportion
15
Reprint from "Proportional Systems in the History of Architecture" - ISBN 9789087282776 - © Leiden University Press, 2018
Matthew A. Cohen
root-2 rectangle intended or not? If so, why was it intended? If one was intended but not
executed precisely, why was it not? There can be no logical justification for a modern
viewer to accord higher visual-aesthetic value to a geometrical figure for which we
have a name, such as a root-2 rectangle, than to one for which we have no name, such
as a slightly stretched root-2 rectangle, if we recall that aesthetic preference (including
intellectual satisfaction) would be an emotional, not a logical, justification for such
judgments. Thus, a root-2 rectangle (or any other rectangle, for that matter) cannot
have more intrinsic beauty than a slightly stretched one, because neither of them has
any universally recognizable beauty at all. All rectangles, as mathematical-geometrical
constructs, are aesthetically neutral.17 It logically follows, therefore, even from this
brief discussion, that a proportional system per se, which is but a set of proportional
relationships, cannot contribute beauty to architecture.18
16
Reprint from "Proportional Systems in the History of Architecture" - ISBN 9789087282776 - © Leiden University Press, 2018
Two Kinds of Proportion
17
Reprint from "Proportional Systems in the History of Architecture" - ISBN 9789087282776 - © Leiden University Press, 2018
Matthew A. Cohen
18
Reprint from "Proportional Systems in the History of Architecture" - ISBN 9789087282776 - © Leiden University Press, 2018
Two Kinds of Proportion
19
Reprint from "Proportional Systems in the History of Architecture" - ISBN 9789087282776 - © Leiden University Press, 2018
Matthew A. Cohen
20
Reprint from "Proportional Systems in the History of Architecture" - ISBN 9789087282776 - © Leiden University Press, 2018
Two Kinds of Proportion
between the vertical ribs of the Pantheon dome and the elements below as an aesthetic
tour de force of Roman design.46
Perrault’s inability to understand the second of his two kinds
of proportion as a subjective aesthetic assessment rather than as a
universal “...that everyone can readily recognize,” was his blind spot,
and helps to explain why the distinction he also made between two
kinds of beauty, arbitrary (i.e., learned) and positive (i.e., universal)—
according to which he controversially associated architectural
proportional systems with the former—created no significant
impediment to the continuation of the beauty-in-proportion belief
system into the present day. In modern scholarship Perrault is typically
characterized as the pivotal figure in architectural history whose
association of proportional systems with arbitrary beauty initiated a
new non-aesthetic attitude toward proportional systems that would
remain dominant in mainstream culture thereafter. Perrault’s place
in the history of this subject, however, is in fact considerably more
nuanced. His theory about proportional systems, though radical in his
day, did not attack the core of the beauty-in-proportion belief system,
or, the notion of positive beauty. Indeed, it was never his intention
to undermine this notion itself, but only the belief that proportional
systems could be sources of positive beauty in architecture.47
Perrault’s notion of positive beauty, which understands beauty as an objective
entity not unlike a mathematical principle, unreliant on subjective human judgment Fig. 4. The Pantheon, Rome,
for its existence yet universally recognizable by all human beings, happens to be the interior view.
necessary precondition for the belief that particular proportional systems create beauty Photo: Emilio Labrador.
in architecture, or, the very belief that he developed the notion of arbitrary beauty
to combat.48 Perrault could very well claim that the proportional systems of the past,
and for that matter his own new proportional system for the orders presented in the
main body of the Ordonnance, only create beauty arbitrarily, through the familiarity of
custom; but his affirmation of the existence of positive beauty has only affirmed the core
belief of beauty-in-proportion believers from his day to our own: that a metaphysical
well of ideal beauty exists somewhere outside of architecture, and that architects can
learn various ways in which to tap into it in order to create works of universal appeal.
Perrault attacks the efficacy of one of those ways—the use of proportional systems—
but not the core of the belief itself.
Perrault’s notion of positive beauty is similar to Leon Battista Alberti’s notion of
innate beauty, and might strike most modern readers as a contradiction in terms, for
beauty, it would seem, can never be positive (i.e., non-subjective).49 All assessments of
beauty are arbitrary aesthetic opinions—or so it would seem in light of this discussion.
Perrault’s particular conception of positive beauty is based on a blend of quantitative
and qualitative architectural qualities, or “convincing reasons,” that to him signal the
presence of positive beauty. He provides four examples of such qualities: “...richness
of materials, the size and magnificence of the building, the precision and cleanness
of the execution, and symmetrie....” The first and third of these examples can be
interpreted as primarily subjective judgments. The second combines a measurable
quality, size, with a subjective judgment, magnificence, and is thus best interpreted as
a pair of words referring to the subjective quality of magnificence. Perrault describes
21
Reprint from "Proportional Systems in the History of Architecture" - ISBN 9789087282776 - © Leiden University Press, 2018
Matthew A. Cohen
his fourth example, symmetrie, as the same as his second kind of proportion, or, a
quality that produces “...an unmistakable and striking beauty” (une beauté evidente
& remarquable) that all people recognize.50 It is thus also subjective, and Perrault’s
entire conception of positive beauty would seem to consist of but a series of arbitrary
aesthetic assessments.
Perrault, however, did not consider qualities such as magnificence and
symmetrie to be subjective aesthetic judgments, even though today we have no
other reliable way to characterize them because their properties cannot be confirmed
with the predictability and repeatability that the scientific method requires. Indeed,
he based his assumptions not on scientific standards of verifiability, but on the then
seemingly irrefutable approbation of expert opinion—the consensus among those
who had the education and training to judge art and architecture. Another century
would pass before Kant would state that
there is no Science of the Beautiful, but only a Critique of it.... For...if it could be
decided scientifically, i.e. by proofs, whether a thing was to be regarded as beautiful
or not, the judgment upon beauty would belong to science and would not be a
judgment of taste.51
Perrault did not have the benefit of the fully mature scientific revolution to help him sort
out these distinctions, but no matter, because the concept of beauty-in-proportion,
which depends on the illogical and unscientific assumption of a causal relationship
between proportion-as-ratio and proportion-as-beauty, ignored the scientific
revolution in its uninterrupted passage from Perrault’s day to our own.52
By codifying the notion of positive beauty, and thus the positive/arbitrary
beauty dichotomy, Perrault’s writings may have contributed to maintaining the beauty-
in-proportion belief system in subsequent centuries as much as those of François
Blondel.53 In Part V of the Cours d’architecture of 1683, Blondel replies to Perrault’s
denial, in Perrault’s preface to the Ordonnance, that proportional systems can be
sources of beauty with what Anthony Gerbino calls a “defense of proportion.”54
Blondel’s defense focuses on “harmony” (harmonie), an adjunct to the word and
concept of proportion that for architectural theorists had carried the ambiguous
double signification of proportion-as-ratio and proportion-as-beauty since at
least 1485, when Alberti published his celebrated promulgation of harmonic
architectural proportions in Book IX of De re aedificatoria.55 Thus Blondel sees
no contradiction in using both of these terms, proportion and harmony, in one
sentence qualitatively, to describe the beauty of “...old and modern buildings...,
[and] the beautiful proportions that their parts have between them...which have...
[an] agreeable harmony that gives so much pleasure to the eyes”; and, in another
sentence on the following page quantitatively, in reference to the musical-numerical
proportions (i.e., proportions-as-ratio) of a specific building as “...a continual harmonic
proportion....”56
Blondel emphasizes his belief that an inherent beauty of harmonic ratios in
music is directly transferable to architecture in an unsubtle graphic comparison
between the horizontal lines of a column base, annotated with numerical dimensions
that form harmonic ratios, and the lines of a musical staff. The staff poignantly includes
a bass clef (Fig. 5).57 Blondel’s claim that musical harmonies contain inherent beauty
22
Reprint from "Proportional Systems in the History of Architecture" - ISBN 9789087282776 - © Leiden University Press, 2018
Two Kinds of Proportion
23
Reprint from "Proportional Systems in the History of Architecture" - ISBN 9789087282776 - © Leiden University Press, 2018
Matthew A. Cohen
survey, however, is his conclusion that beginning in England in the late 18th century,
“...the whole structure of classical æsthetics was overthrown from the bottom,” and that
...in this process man’s vision underwent a decisive change. Proportion became a
matter of individual sensibility and in this respect the architect acquired complete
freedom from the bondage of mathematical ratios. However, mathematical ratios
survived in a degenerated form as a teaching expedient for architectural students
and without any connection with their original meaning.61
24
Reprint from "Proportional Systems in the History of Architecture" - ISBN 9789087282776 - © Leiden University Press, 2018
Two Kinds of Proportion
are able to perceive the harmony and the exact proportions in which the several
parts of the Universe are linked together, we feel an intellectual pleasure, arising
perhaps from an original impression on our minds of what appear to be the essential
attributes of a perfect work.68
25
Reprint from "Proportional Systems in the History of Architecture" - ISBN 9789087282776 - © Leiden University Press, 2018
Matthew A. Cohen
26
Reprint from "Proportional Systems in the History of Architecture" - ISBN 9789087282776 - © Leiden University Press, 2018
Two Kinds of Proportion
of World War II.75 In his introduction to the abridged proceedings of the conference,
Fulvio Irace describes this yearning as follows:
In the same publication James S. Ackerman—as of this writing the only living contributor
to the 1951 conference and also a contributor, via video interview, to the 2011 Leiden
conference—similarly notes a spiritual dimension to the conference:
The interest that arose in 1951 was perhaps born, in a Europe that was still searching
to recover from the devastation of the war, from a desire to return spirituality to the
arts and to life through the geometry of a pure architecture, free of ornament and
consisting of rectangular surfaces and openings.77
Ackerman later notes that the manner in which the conference participants approached
their subject, if not the idealism that motivated them, marked the beginning of a new
scholarly seriousness in the study of proportion:
Before that time [1951] it [proportion] really hadn’t become a reliable [area of]
study. There was a lot of mysticism around it. Some of the mystics were part of the
conference too, which is only fair, but it was really the end of the mystical phase and
the [beginning of the] effort to set it onto reliable, academic, practical grounds.78
Only tangentially, however, did the conference engage the academic study of
the history of proportional systems. Those contributors who incorporated historical
observations with supportive textual references into their presentations, in particular
Wittkower and Giedion, only did so in support of the overwhelmingly mystical,
reformist agenda of the conference, which Giedion rather grandiosely described as
“revolutionary.”79 Wittkower, one of the conference organizers, justified that agenda
in his opening remarks by decrying as “an illusion” what he saw as the predominant
contemporary attitude toward artistic production based on “...the nineteenth
century idea that the artist, in his creative act, should be guided only by his personal
intuition....” On the contrary, he declared, “...the search for harmony and order is a
basic part of human nature.”80 Such harmony and order, he believed, transcended the
individual, and had the potential to be perceived collectively, by all human beings.
Indeed, for Wittkower and the other conference participants, a general notion of
proportional order, which could be manifested in proportional systems and which they
called the divina proportione (the divine proportion), after Luca Pacioli’s 16th-century
book of that title (1509), constituted a kind of demiurge, existing independently of
human culture but occasionally interacting with it. Seemingly endowed with agency
and thus more assertive than a passive set of Platonic ideals, the divina proportione,
these participants believed, periodically appeared in history, demanding expression in
the arts and compelling human beings to serve as its sometimes unwitting collaborators
toward some mysterious but ultimately beneficent purpose. Thus Giedion provocatively
asked in his conference paper, “...can we assert that the divina proportione has made
27
Reprint from "Proportional Systems in the History of Architecture" - ISBN 9789087282776 - © Leiden University Press, 2018
Matthew A. Cohen
its appearance again?,” and obliquely answered in the affirmative, citing as examples
Le Corbusier’s Modulor and “...the difference between the static proportions of the
past and the dynamic proportions of the present epoch....”81 Even the thirty-two-year-
old Californian and recently discharged US Army enlistee James S. Ackerman got into
the spirit of the conference, alongside his elder European colleagues, concluding his
summary analysis of the Cathedral of Milan proportions by interpreting the various
geometrical schemes documented in the cathedral archives as medieval expressions
of the “Divina Proportione.”82
Wittkower shaped the conference around the goal of identifying an appropriate
expression of the divina proportione in the arts for the modern age. Since “...the
artist reflects the culture in which he lives,” he posited, the central objectives of the
conference were, first, to answer the question “What is the character of our culture...”
in light of “...the substitution of the absolute measure of space and time with the new
dynamic space-time relationship...” introduced by Einstein?; and, second, to determine
what effect this substitution “...has and will have on proportion in the arts....”83 Thus, at
the Milan conference Wittkower played the role of the activist-historian, applying his
historical knowledge toward the purpose of influencing rather than merely studying
history. Through the conference he strove to encourage artists and architects of
the time to develop new proportional systems that would reflect the contemporary
modern condition, to use those proportional systems in their creative works, and to see
themselves as the torch bearers of a dynamic, centuries-long tradition of proportional
exploration that had been, in his view, temporarily interrupted by misguided 19th-
century attitudes toward creative production.84
In his 1960 essay “The Changing Concept of Proportion,” Wittkower reveals
his disappointment with the 1951 conference, lamenting that it had failed to advance
its reformist agenda with tangible results. He also reveals his belief that proportional
systems constituted not merely opportunities for aesthetic expression, but moral
imperatives. The Milan conference, he notes, “...brought together philosophers,
painters, architects, musical historians, art historians, engineers and critics from many
countries.” These thinkers and practitioners had gathered because, he continues,
“...they agreed on one point: that some kind of controlling or regulative system of
proportion was desirable.” The conference nevertheless “...fizzled out...,” he claims,
“...without making an appreciable impact on the younger generation.”85 The true depth
of his disappointment, however, becomes apparent as his essay continues.
“The bankruptcy of the Milan meeting...,” Wittkower inveighs, “...was publicly
sealed at a historic meeting of the Royal Institute of British Architects...where a debate
took place on the motion ‘that systems of proportion make good design easier and
bad design more difficult’—a motion that was defeated with forty-eight voting for and
sixty voting against.”86 This “bankruptcy” was for Wittkower not merely intellectual, but
moral. In the essay he appeals for a return to the high ideals of the failed conference,
advocating adherence in contemporary art and design to “absolute” and “universal”
values based in “thought” rather than “sensations,” lest modern society succumb to
ignoble pragmatism and opportunism. Wittkower continues:
28
Reprint from "Proportional Systems in the History of Architecture" - ISBN 9789087282776 - © Leiden University Press, 2018
Two Kinds of Proportion
In most periods of history artists were convinced that their specific system of
proportion had universal validity. These systems derived their all-embracing character
from thought processes rather than from sensations. It is now two hundred years since
the belief in absolute values was shaken, perhaps for all time; it can surely not be won
back by an act of majority decision. As long as a broad foundation for a resurrection
of universal values is lacking, one cannot easily predict how the present dilemma
can be resolved. The very formulation of the motion put before the R.I.B.A. meeting
shows that we have left far behind the realm of the absolute, and are submitting to
pragmatic and opportunistic motivations.87
With the emphasis of martial and religious metaphors (“won back” and
“resurrection,” above), a rather militant-evangelical Wittkower here presents a moral
choice between good and bad: design with proportional systems is based on thought
and thus reason, and is therefore good; design without proportional systems is based
on aesthetic judgments that are in turn based only on stimuli received by the senses
in the absence of thought, and is therefore bad. He goes on to lament the “...quick
rise and easy victory of abstract expressionism...,” which he deprecates as “splash-
and-dribble style,” and the “absolute subjectivism” that he believed characterized the
state of society nearly a decade after the Milan conference, and that he considered
antithetical to the use of proportional systems.88
With these comments Wittkower takes his place in a long line of similarly-
minded thinkers. He might have fit in comfortably, for example, with those who in
1750 Alexander Gottlieb Baumgarten anticipated might have raised objections to
his proposed new field of aesthetics on the basis that “...impressions received from
the senses, fantasies, emotional disturbances, etc., are unworthy of philosophers and
beneath the scope of their consideration.”89 In earlier centuries Wittkower might have
found sympathetic company with François Blondel or Daniele Barbaro.
This tendency to think of proportional systems, and the buildings that contain
them, as good because they are based on mathematics, and the absence of proportional
systems as less good, if not outright bad, because it leaves the architect’s whims
unfettered, is still common today. Indeed, this tendency, along with the proportional
aestheticism of which it is a symptom, carries the risk of encouraging moral-aesthetic
judgments of architecture, along the lines of Wittkower’s above-quoted comments
of 1960 pertaining to the Milan conference. If buildings that contain proportional
systems are good according to beauty-in-proportion believers, can buildings that lack
them ever be as good, of equal overall value, and more than merely “pragmatic” and
“opportunistic?” Such proportional aestheticism could lead some scholars to believe
that all good buildings must necessarily have interesting proportional systems, and to
insist on finding them even where they do not exist. As the Old Sacristy of San Lorenzo
suggests, however, many good buildings may very well lack interesting proportional
systems, and that lack constitutes valuable historical information rather than grounds
for censure.90
29
Reprint from "Proportional Systems in the History of Architecture" - ISBN 9789087282776 - © Leiden University Press, 2018
Matthew A. Cohen
Note that in order to satisfy this definition, either kind of proportional system
(belief-based or certainty-based) must consist of a set of intentional correspondences.
This definition thus excludes complex geometrical constructions that historians might
overlay onto drawings, photographs or computer models of buildings (Fig. 6), unless
those overlays can be convincingly demonstrated, through building (or historic
drawing) measurements or other evidence, to represent the architect’s intentions.94
This definition thus furthermore assumes that proportional systems cannot wander
into architecture of their own volition, without the architects’ knowledge, as for
example golden sectionists have tended to believe.95 Since unintentional patterns of
geometry and number can always be found in architecture, the preceding definition
distinguishes between mere physical description of the object, which might include
such patterns, and the scholarly identification and analysis of the creative intentions of
the architect.96
The use of certainty-based proportional systems is standard practice today, in
the forms of structural engineering size specifications (which must be combined with
specifications for materials, techniques and other construction factors), standardized
sets of dimensions for building components (in terms of the meter or the foot), zoning
regulations (such as floor area ratio) and other conventions, but these are not the kinds
of proportional systems of primary interest to us here.97 Engineering specifications,
dimensional standardization and zoning formulae, as certainty-based proportional
systems, are designed to guarantee measurable, practical outcomes, repeatedly and
predictably. The proportional systems of primary interest to us here are decidedly
impractical and not founded on the certainty of guaranteed outcomes.98 These
belief-based proportional systems either date to the pre-engineering period prior to
1742–1743 or, if later, retrogressively retain the technological innocence of that earlier
30
Reprint from "Proportional Systems in the History of Architecture" - ISBN 9789087282776 - © Leiden University Press, 2018
Two Kinds of Proportion
period, together with some degree of the metaphysical orientation that characterized
much of the thinking of that period.99
The differences between belief-based and certainty-based proportional systems
can be rather subtle. For example, upon first consideration one might think that the San
Lorenzo nave arcade bay proportional system, which is a pre-engineering proportional
system, guarantees the outcome that a root-2 rectangle will be inscribed in the space
between the column shafts (Fig. 3, left), and that therefore at least in this respect it
is no different than any typical engineer’s specification from the post-1742–1743
period. Upon closer consideration, however, we can see that this proportional system
is thoroughly belief-based rather than certainty-based, for two reasons. First, it does
not in fact guarantee the physical presence of the root-2 rectangle in the nave arcade
bays—indeed, this rectangle is not physically present there at all—and, second, this
root-2 rectangle could serve no practical purpose whether it were present or not. This
rectangle only exists as an idea in the minds of observers who understand that the
horizontal distance between the column plinths, and the intended height of the column
shafts, not including the astragals (which in this basilica are physically integral with the
capitals), together correspond to the proportions of an imagined root-2 rectangle.
To mentally perceive this rectangle observers must disregard not only the significant
curvilinear gaps between the sides of this imaginary rectangle and the surfaces of the
column shafts and bases (Fig. 3), but also the construction error that caused the column
shafts to have been made slightly too tall to mark the top of this imaginary rectangle.100
Furthermore, the root-2 rectangle in question could not have guaranteed any
of the outcomes that the architects, probably both Dolfini and Brunelleschi, hoped to
achieve by specifying it, which surely consisted of more than simply creating a root-2
rectangle as an end in itself.101 These architects might very likely have intended, for
example, that it would confer ordine, specifically including structural stability (see
above). Today, however, we know that it is scientifically impossible for a root-2 rectangle
per se to establish structural stability in architecture; and that neither ordine nor other
notions of beauty, being subjective qualities, can ever be guaranteed. Engineering
or zoning specifications, conversely, being based on immutable scientific and
municipal laws (the latter being immutable at least for the duration of construction),
guarantee predictable and measurable outcomes such as structural stability (when
used in conjunction with other specifications, as noted above) or conformance with
established building regulations.
An illuminating example of an early conflict between belief-based and certainty-
based proportional systems is found in the 1867 edition of Gwilt’s Encyclopedia of
Architecture. Gwilt promotes what he calls the “interaxal system,” a grid proportional
system that he openly borrowed from Jean-Nicolas Louis Durand’s Preçis des leçons
d’architecture of 1802-1805. Durand’s proportional system still represented the belief-
based approach, and Gwilt defended it against the then new, engineering-based
technology of cast iron, which threatened to deprive Durand’s system of the structural
justification with which Gwilt associated it.102 Gwilt writes:
Not the least important of the advantages resulting from the method of designing
just submitted to the reader is the certain symmetry it produces, and the prevention,
by the use of these interaxal lines on each floor, of the architect falling into the error
of false bearings, than which a greater or more dangerous fault cannot be committed,
31
Reprint from "Proportional Systems in the History of Architecture" - ISBN 9789087282776 - © Leiden University Press, 2018
Matthew A. Cohen
more especially in public buildings. The subterfuge for avoiding the consequence of
false bearings is now a resort to cast iron, a material beneficially enough employed
in buildings of inferior rank; but in those of the first class, wherein every part should
have a proper point of support, it is a practice not to be tolerated.103
Thus, according to Gwilt, not only does the interaxal system provide a “certain
symmetry,” by which Gwilt evidently means a kind of comprehensive beauty similar
to Perrault’s symmetrie, but it ensures that walls and columns will always be stacked
directly atop other walls and columns, in a system of structural support that Gwilt finds
more satisfactory than one that has columns bearing on transfer beams of cast iron,
even though the two systems could be made equally strong. Similar to Wittkower’s
above-quoted objections of 1960 to any neglect of belief-based proportional
systems in favor of artistic intuition, Gwilt considers the replacement of a belief-based
proportional system with an engineer’s certainty-based one (i.e., the mathematical
specifications for the cast iron members) to be morally unacceptable. The interaxal
system, Gwilt maintains, provides structural support that is “proper,” while cast iron
provides the same degree of support but only though “subterfuge.” For Gwilt, the
engineer’s cold calculations, which merely satisfy the practical objective of making
a building stand up, can never distinguish architecture—i.e., buildings of “the first
class”—from mere “buildings of inferior rank” or, for that matter, from pure works of
engineering such as bridges.104 Gwilt’s protestations notwithstanding, 19th-century
engineers indeed succeeded in robbing belief-based proportional systems of their
one ostensibly practical purpose, that of ensuring structural stability, by fulfilling that
purpose effectively and reliably using proportional systems based on the science of
physics, which the old proportional systems based on the mysticism of metaphysics
never could do.
The advent of engineering, however, brought about only a partial demise
of belief-based proportional systems in architecture. Since such systems, like those
used in the designs of the Cathedral of Milan and the basilica of San Lorenzo, never
had any more influence over structural stability than magic or prayer, the advent of
engineering merely proved what many architects already knew—that in determining
the sizes and dispositions of crucial structural members an architect could use all
the proportional systems he wanted, but in the end, in the words of the 16th-century
Spanish architect Rodrigo Gil de Hontañon, he could only use “...his own judgment...
and dare to have confidence.”105 The advent of engineering thus robbed belief-based
proportional systems of their always-questionable claims to have helped ensure
structural stability, but did not touch the only purpose that such proportional systems
have ever fulfilled successfully—that of imbuing buildings with meaning. Some of that
meaning may be considered aesthetic, for example, when observers thought about
proportional systems in order to help themselves make sense of sense perception, or
when architects used proportional systems to establish certain forms like entasis that
they considered to be beautiful; and some may be considered metaphysical but not
necessarily aesthetic, such as when observers thought about proportional systems to
help themselves imagine architecture as a reflection of a larger, macrocosmic order
that, in the words of Alfred W. Crosby, “lay beyond the scrim of reality.”106
32
Reprint from "Proportional Systems in the History of Architecture" - ISBN 9789087282776 - © Leiden University Press, 2018
Two Kinds of Proportion
33
Reprint from "Proportional Systems in the History of Architecture" - ISBN 9789087282776 - © Leiden University Press, 2018
Matthew A. Cohen
34
Reprint from "Proportional Systems in the History of Architecture" - ISBN 9789087282776 - © Leiden University Press, 2018
Two Kinds of Proportion
Architects have always had the artistic license to explore whatever pragmatic
or metaphysical inclinations they may choose, but architectural historians need to
strive for objectivity in order to interpret this creative production accurately. The
study of proportional systems in the history of architecture presents a rich variety of
subject matter, very important among which is the exploration of the meanings they
communicate. Scholars have to take care to examine these proportional systems, and
the meanings they originally communicated, as historical artifacts created to serve as
objects of belief, while avoiding any temptation to have them serve as objects of their
own beliefs. Some of the following essays examine proportional systems composed of
proportions-as-ratio, or, sets of proportions as measurable, verifiable products of artistic
production. Others examine proportion-as-beauty, from historical or historiographical
viewpoints. The distinction between proportion-as-ratio and proportion-as-beauty
outlined in this introduction is intended to help readers distinguish between historical
and aesthetic approaches to understanding proportional systems, and to avoid
ambiguity by keeping these two approaches strictly separated.
The essays
The essays presented in this volume provide explorations of current scholarly thinking on
the varied problem of proportional systems in the history of architecture, with emphasis
on developments in northern Europe, Italy, and Greece. They invite a reinvigorated
discussion of this broad topic extending beyond these regions and these pages. The
preceding introduction examines the inherent contradiction between proportion-as-
ratio and proportion-as-beauty that resides within the word “proportion,” and the long
history of this contradiction. As a manifestation of a general human impulse to conjoin
the imagined with the observed, the abstract with the measured, and the ideal with the
contingent, this contradiction has many guises. Some of these guises are explored in the
six essays that form Part II of this volume, which focuses on ways in which proportional
systems have been, and can yet be, understood as conceptual tools for pondering
various intellectual or visual conundrums pertaining to architecture.
Mario Curti (Chapter 2) discerns a common undercurrent in the long history of
proportional systems in the form of a recurring conflict between canons and nature.
This conflict, he contends, is driven by the inevitable incongruities between what the
“champions of ideal proportions” have sought and the imperfect reality of the world as
it is. Indeed, such incongruities can be found between the ideals of these champions
and natural phenomena such as optical perspective distortions or the non-scalable
nature of the strength of materials, or between an observer’s expectations of the
way architecture should be and its imperfect reality. Thus Caroline van Eck (Chapter
3) proposes that proportional systems are constructs of the mind, invented to help
people “...make sense of, and judge, the objects of sense perception.” In this role, she
argues, proportional systems have helped to resolve conflicts between expectations
of normative classical forms and occasionally jarring deviations therefrom, such as
those that have long perplexed viewers of Michelangelo’s San Lorenzo Ricetto (of
the Laurentian library). Through analysis of the Ricetto and its reception over time,
van Eck proposes that the assumption of proportional systems constitute one of two
strategies—the other being anthropomorphic projection—by which human beings
35
Reprint from "Proportional Systems in the History of Architecture" - ISBN 9789087282776 - © Leiden University Press, 2018
Matthew A. Cohen
36
Reprint from "Proportional Systems in the History of Architecture" - ISBN 9789087282776 - © Leiden University Press, 2018
Two Kinds of Proportion
explores ways in which ancient Roman and Renaissance architects might have
determined the sizes of their modules, and whether they were even fully responsible
for making these decisions. The Roman system of delivering column shafts in standard
sizes and the possible demise of this system during the Renaissance, Bosman argues,
may have exerted decisive influence over the determinations of modules.
Mark Wilson Jones (Chapter 10) and Franco Barbieri (Chapter 11) continue
the exploration of modular design methods before and after the periods covered by
Bosman, respectively. In his study of the Parthenon proportions Wilson Jones proposes,
like Bosman, that the predetermined dimensions of materials, in this case recycled
column drums from the pre-Parthenon, played a critical role in determining the module
size. Indeed, he finds that the Parthenon proportions are overall modular in character—
or, “modulated”—and as such, based whenever possible on simple ratios related to
the dimensions of the triglyph frieze in a subtle variety of ways. Through analysis of
previous studies, furthermore, he maintains a healthy skepticism of overly complex
theories that lack modulated consistency. If the modular proportions of the Greeks
survived as “echoes” in Vitruvius’s De architectura as Wilson Jones suggests, by the
time of Vincenzo Scamozzi’s L’idea dell’architettura universale of 1615 architects had an
accumulated clatter of modular design theories ultimately based on interpretations of
Vitruvius to sort through. Barbieri shows us how Scamozzi sorted through them in the
latter’s meticulous, deductive analysis of the proportions of columns, windows, rooms,
and other architectural elements. Scamozzi’s systematic method reflects Galilean
scientism, while also acknowledging individual judgment and changes in fashion, as
exemplified by the taller and more elongated proportions that he recommends over
Palladio’s choices. Similar to the observations of other authors in this volume, Barbieri
notes numerous instances in which Scamozzi confronts contradictions between his
preferred ideal proportions and the necessary accommodations to the contingencies
of practice. Nevertheless, Scamozzi’s eventual abandonment of the orders and their
proportional systems in his later works evidences his restless idealism, and his first
steps toward Enlightenment thinking.
Steps toward Enlightenment thinking and insights into the uses of proportional
systems in practice are also evident in the next three essays, which importantly contribute
to the hitherto under-studied subject of historic uses of proportional systems in the
Low Countries. These studies shed new light on what appears to have been a distinctly
pragmatic approach to proportion that, beginning in the 16th century, assimilated into
the northern European context an incursion of Vitruvius-influenced Renaissance texts
from Italy. Krista De Jonge (Chapter 12) shows how Pieter Coecke van Aelst, among
others, produced publications gauged to appeal to artists trained in the Gothic culture
of design, and that introduced new notions of proportion and the orders in ways that
were graphically comprehensible in both numerical and geometrical terms. Coecke,
she notes, thereby strove to “...establish a new, universally understood terminology of
architecture.” Konrad Ottenheym (Chapter 13) reveals a different kind of pragmatic
approach that perhaps also aspired to universal applicability in his studies of Dutch
architectural drawings from the 17th century. These drawings reveal an emphasis
on frameworks consisting of grids or occasionally more complex geometrical
constructions, and whole number dimensions expressed in local units of measure.
In these drawings we see basic proportional frameworks serving as a strict design
system that for most practitioners was probably devoid of metaphysical association.
37
Reprint from "Proportional Systems in the History of Architecture" - ISBN 9789087282776 - © Leiden University Press, 2018
Matthew A. Cohen
38
Reprint from "Proportional Systems in the History of Architecture" - ISBN 9789087282776 - © Leiden University Press, 2018
Two Kinds of Proportion
39
Reprint from "Proportional Systems in the History of Architecture" - ISBN 9789087282776 - © Leiden University Press, 2018
Matthew A. Cohen
the 1951 Milan conference, as well as his detailed insights into Wittkower’s working
methods, sets the stage for an interview with James S. Ackerman (Chapter 24), who
reflects on the legacies of Wittkower, Le Corbusier, and the 1951 Milan conference of
which he was a participant, among other topics.
With regard to Wittkower’s legacy, it is perhaps prescient that six of our
authors—Francesco Benelli, Krista De Jonge, Anthony Gerbino, Marvin Trachtenberg,
Caroline van Eck, and the present author—adopt highly critical positions. These new
contributions, together with the previous contributions of Robin Evans, George Hersey
and Richard Freedman, Deborah Howard and Malcolm Longair, Branko Mitrović,
Alina Payne, Manfredo Tafuri, and others represent an increasing contextualization of
Wittkower’s writings on architectural proportional systems as artifacts of the mid-20th
century. They thus indicate the waning influence of these writings today, and highlight
the new opportunities before us to reconceive the subject matter of this volume.
This volume concludes (Chapter 25) with a synthesis of the findings presented in
these chapters, in the form of a proposed set of ten principles to serve as guidelines
and points of debate for continued study of proportional systems in the history of
architecture.
Notes
1
In the preparation of this introduction I have benefited from the thoughtful comments of Anthony
Gerbino, Caroline van Eck, and Mark Wilson Jones. This introduction is a revision of: Matthew A. Co-
hen, “Introduction: Two Kinds of Proportion,” Architectural Histories 2(1) Art. 21 (2013), in the Special
Collection “Objects of Belief: Proportional Systems in the History of Architecture,” edited by Mat-
thew A. Cohen and Maarten Delbeke. DOI: http://doi.org/10.5334/ah.bv. The 2011 conference was
titled: “Proportional Systems in the History of Architecture: An International Conference Hosted by
Leiden University, March 17–19, 2011,” and was organized by Matthew A. Cohen, Eelco Nagelsmit
and Caroline van Eck. The speakers were: James S. Ackerman (via pre-recorded video interview),
Francesco Benelli, Robert Bork, Lex Bosman, Howard Burns (keynote), Jean-Louis Cohen, Matthew
A. Cohen, Mario Curti, Sigrid de Jong, Krista de Jonge, Elizabeth den Hartog, Sara Galletti, Anthony
Gerbino, Jeroen Goudeau, Gerd Graßhoff, Volker Hoffmann, Frédérique Lemerle, Emanuele Lugli,
Stephen Murray, Werner Oechslin, Konrad Ottenheym, Andrew Tallon, Marvin Trachtenberg, Caro-
line van Eck, Caroline Voet, and Mark Wilson Jones.
2
The 1951 conference had two titles: “Il Primo Convegno Internazionale sulle Proporzioni nelle Arti,”
and the subtitle “La divina proportione.” It was held from September 27–29, 1951 as part of the
ninth Triennale di Milano, in the Palazzo dell’Arte. Three publications report the contents of the con-
ference: Wittkower, “International Congress on Proportion in the Arts,” 52–55; an anonymous article
titled “Il primo convegno internazionale sulle proporzioni nelle arti”; and Cimoli and Irace, La divina
proporzione: Triennale 1951. Of them, “Il primo convegno” names the most speakers and other
contributors, but Cimoli and Irace publish the largest selection of texts of the papers, many of them
abridged. Of the thirty-two relazioni and communicazioni presented at the conference, Cimoli and
Irace publish twenty-five, and “Il primo convegno,” fourteen. The following list of participants (re-
taining all titles and spelling) is derived from the latter: James Ackermann (sic), Arch. Cesare Bairati,
Arch. Max Bill, Luigi Cosenza, Prof. Dekkers, Dott. Gillo Dorfles, Prof. Giusta Nicco Fasola, Scultore
Lucio Fontana, Dott. Charles Funck-Hellet, Arch. Ignazio Gardella, Prof. Matila Ghyka, Prof. Sigfried
Giedion, Mad. Carola Giedion-Welker, Prof. Hans Kayser, Arch. Mario Labò, Le Corbusier, Arch. Carlo
Mollino, Gino Levi Montalcini, Ing. Pier Luigi Nervi, Prof. Roberto Papini, Prof. Giovanni Ricci, Prof.
Salvatore Caronia Roberti, Arch. Ernesto N. Rogers, Arch. Alfred Roth, Arch. Piero Sanpaolesi, Pittore
Gino Severini, Prof. Andreas Speiser, Prof. Eva Tea, Dott. Adrien Turel, Pittore Georges Vantongerloo,
Prof. Rudolf Wittkower, and Arch. Prof. Bruno Zevi. The following participated in a panel discussion
on the third day of the conference: Arch. Annoni, Prof. Caronia, Ing. Enrico Castoldi, Dott. Melino,
Arch. Moretti (Luigi Moretti?), Arch. Pasqué, and Arch. Sotsas junior. At the end of the conference
the following were nominated and unanimously elected to serve on the “Comitato internazionale di
studio sulle proporzioni nelle arti” (in the order listed in “Il primo convegno”): Le Corbusier (Presi-
dent), Arch. Phillip Johnson, Arch. Ernesto N. Rogers, Arch. Josè Luis Sert, Prof. Andreas Speiser, Prof.
Rudolf Wittkower, Scultore Berto Lardera, Dott. Mario Melino and Signora Carla Marzoli (“Il primo
convegno,” 119–121). According to Wittkower the name of this committee was the “Comité Interna-
40
Reprint from "Proportional Systems in the History of Architecture" - ISBN 9789087282776 - © Leiden University Press, 2018
Two Kinds of Proportion
tionale pour l’Etude (sic) et l’Application des Proportions dans les Arts et l’Industrie Contemporains,”
and its purpose was to organize a second conference on proportion in the arts to be held in New
York in 1953, which never took place (Wittkower, “International Congress on Proportion in the Arts,”
55). On the Milan conference, see also Mattei, “Geometria e struttura,” 257–269.
3
The announcement for the Leiden conference stated: “The purpose of this conference is to frame a
rigorous new scholarly discussion of this subject [proportional systems in the history of architecture],
and in the process, to help define appropriate methods, standards and limits for it. The conference
will explore this subject during any period, and from both historical and historiographical points of
view.” For the stated purposes of the Milan conference, see Wittkower’s opening comments quoted
below, page 27.
4
According to Mainstone, “The first recorded application of...[the present theories of equilibrium,
deformation and strength] in structural practise in 1742–43 may be said to mark the birth of the
present art of structural design.” This comment is in reference to a structural analysis undertaken in
those years of cracks in the dome of St. Paul’s Cathedral in London. Mainstone, “Structural Theory
and Design Before 1742,” 303.
5
Cf. the opening paragraph of Pevsner, Outline of European Architecture, 23 and 25: “A bicycle shed
is a building; Lincoln Cathedral is a piece of architecture.... [T]he term architecture applies only to
buildings designed with a view to aesthetic appeal,” though I expand here upon Pevsner’s formula-
tion, even beyond his concluding sentence that the history of architecture is a history “...primarily of
spatial expression,” by proposing that a defining quality of architecture is its capacity to communi-
cate iconographically. Proportional systems have served some limited visual purposes in history,
such as helping to maintain certain stylistic conventions, but such purposes were mere conven-
iences rather than primary functions. Corinthian column proportions look Corinthian, for example,
because their proportions-as-beauty fall within a particular normative range established by custom
(a range that can be quite large), whether or not a proportional system was used to establish them. A
proportional system for the design of columns can communicate iconographically, however, when
it can be identified as participating in a particular ideology of proportion, such as, for example,
Vitruvius’s, or Alberti’s, or da Vignola’s column proportions. On the potential use of proportional
systems to maintain stylistic conventions, see Cohen, Beyond Beauty, 26-31, and the Conclusion to
this volume (Chapter 25), pages 538-539.
6
The prescribed proportions for streets and lots imposed by the governing authorities of Florentine
new towns (Friedman, Florentine New Towns), are different than modern urban design guidelines
for building morphology in that they appear not to have been intended primarily to produce prac-
tical outcomes such as health and safety. The same may be said of the urban design guidelines for
the architecture of late medieval Florence noted by Trachtenberg, Dominion of the Eye. On the im-
portance of harmonic proportions in medieval conceptions of beauty as expressed in urban design,
see Flanigan, “The Ponte Vecchio,” 9.
7
The term “paradigm” here follows the fourth definition in the Oxford English Dictionary Online, which
generalizes Thomas S. Kuhn’s definition to apply to non-scientific disciplines, such as architectural
history, as well as scientific ones. Kuhn, The Structure of Scientific Revolutions (1962), 10. The OED
thus defines “paradigm” as “a conceptual or methodological model underlying the theories and
practices of a science or discipline at a particular time; (hence) a generally accepted world view.” For
Kuhn’s brief acknowledgement of the applicability of his paradigm theory to art history, see Kuhn,
The Structure of Scientific Revolutions (1970), 121. See also Cohen, Beyond Beauty, 36 n. 41.
Wittkower, Architectural Principles (1949); Wittkower, “Systems of Proportion,” 9–18; Wittkower, “The
8
Changing Concept of Proportion,” 199–215; and Cohen, Beyond Beauty, 36–51. The term “Witt-
kower paradigm” as used here is independent of Payne’s undefined reference to “Wittkower’s para-
digm.” Payne, “Rudolf Wittkower and Architectural Principles,” 332; and Payne, Rudolf Wittkower
(2011), 46–50.
9
The term “proportion” is used here in the cursory sense of “proportion-in-general,” leaving intact
all the ambiguities that result from combining the notions of “proportion-as-ratio” (proportion as a
quantitative, mathematical ratio, such as 1:2), “proportion-as-beauty” (a qualitative aesthetic assess-
ment of an identified object), and “proportional system” (a set of quantitative proportional corres-
pondences), as discussed in Cohen, Beyond Beauty, 19-24, and below, pages 17 and 30.
10
These anecdotal observations of common opinions today about beauty and proportional systems
are similar to those reported by Edward Lacy Garbett in the 19th century (see below, pages 24-25)
and Claude Perrault in the 17th century with regard to architects’ opinions, as in Perrault’s comment
(italics added): “…what most architects claim when they would have us believe that what creates
beauty in the Pantheon…is the proportion of that temple’s wall thickness to its interior void, its width
to its height, and a hundred other things that are imperceptible unless they are measured and that,
even when they are perceptible, fail to assure us that any deviation from these proportions would
have displeased us.” Perrault, Ordonnance des cinq espèces de colonnes, v–vi; Perrault, Ordonnance
for the Five Kinds of Columns, 49–50; and cf. Perrault, Les dix livres d’architecture, 105 n. 7. On the
41
Reprint from "Proportional Systems in the History of Architecture" - ISBN 9789087282776 - © Leiden University Press, 2018
Matthew A. Cohen
risks of claiming to know what “most architects” thought at any point in the early modern period,
see Gerbino, “Were Early Modern Architects Neoplatonists?,” Chapter 5 herein, pages 113-114. See
also the opinion polls of 1672 and 1957 discussed in note 86, below.
See, however, Mark Wilson Jones’s contribution to this volume (Chapter 10), and note 19 below. In
11
the scientific literature, conversely, numerous attempts have been made to determine whether a
natural human proclivity generates universal aesthetic preferences for particular proportional ratios
in the visual arts (not specifically architecture). For a sampling of such studies, see Cohen, Beyond
Beauty, 285. Recently, Cinzia Di Dio, Emiliano Macaluso and Giacomo Rizzolatti used functional
magnetic resonance imaging (fMRI) to observe localized regions of brain activity in test subjects
who were shown sets of proportionally-manipulated photographs of classical and Renaissance fig-
ure sculptures, and asked to judge them aesthetically. Di Dio, Macaluso and Rizzolatti “The Golden
Beauty.” The authors’ claim that their fMRI images demonstrate not merely that certain areas of the
brain activate when performing certain tasks, but the existence of an objective beauty based on
the golden section, appears to be an example of a current tendency in the fields of neuroscience
and psychology to make, according to Senzeni Mpofu, “…overly enthusiastic claims about fMRI’s
credibility in explaining social science phenomena.” Mpofu, “Debunking Science: fMRI”; and simi-
larly, Satel and Lilienfeld, Brainwashed. Also of concern is that the authors use these scientific tools
in combination with a limited understanding of art history and aesthetic theory. Thus, regardless
of the authors’ interpretation of their fMRI data, this study is compromised at the outset by the
authors’ unsupported assumptions that 1) “it is...rather implausible to maintain that beauty has no
biological substrate and is merely a conventional, experientially determined concept” (p. 8); 2) test
subjects who are “...naïve to art criticism...” would also be naïve to other cultural factors that might
subjectively influence their opinions about art, or indeed about this particular experiment (p. 1); and
3) the golden section “...is considered to represent the ideal beauty...” (pages 1 and 8). The authors
associate the latter assumption with linear overlays that they applied to a photograph of the Greek
Doryphoros sculpture by Polykleitos, dividing the height of this figure at the navel into two main
parts, the relative proportions of which they claim correspond to the golden section, without any ref-
erence to verifiable measurements of the actual sculpture, or to the issue of photographic distortion
(p. 2). The authors thus bring 19th century pseudo-scientific golden-sectionism into a 21st-century,
peer-reviewed scientific journal. These and other methodological shortcomings (including the lack
of sufficient engagement with recent literature on art history and aesthetic theory) provide ample
reason to doubt the authors’ conclusion that the brain activities observed in their fMRI scans affirma-
tively answer their main research question of “...whether there is an objective beauty, i.e., if objective
parameters intrinsic to works of art are able to elicit a specific neural pattern underlying the sense
of beauty in the observer” (p. 8). This study thus serves both as an example of the difficulty—and
perhaps futility—of applying scientific tools to the study of subjective aesthetic judgments, and
as a reminder that scientific training is not necessary for the critical evaluation of such studies. For
similar, arbitrarily golden-sectioned images of the human figure found in numerous unscientific and
unscholarly publications of a metaphysical orientation, see for example Zeising, Neue Lehre von den
Proportionen, especially 282, Fig. 188; Hagenmaier, Der Goldene Schnitt, 29; Doczi, The Power of
Limits, 104–105; and Le Corbusier, Le Modulor, ch. 2. On the 19th-century origins of aesthetic claims
pertaining to the golden section, see Payne, “Rudolf Wittkower and Architectural Principles,” 327
n. 30; Van der Schoot, De ontstelling van Pythagoras; Frings, “The Golden Section in Architectural
Theory,” 9–32; Herz-Fischler, A Mathematical History, 167-169; Padovan, Proportion, 304-323; and
Curti, “Canons of Proportion,” Chapter 2 herein, pages 65 and 67.
See, for example, the numerous survey text claims that a perceived beautiful (or “harmonious”)
12
appearance of the basilica of San Lorenzo in Florence results from proportional systems (Cohen,
Beyond Beauty, 18). In a 2008 television documentary, Jeffrey Hurwit states: “The Parthenon, like a
statue, exemplifies a certain symmetria; a certain harmony of part to part, and of part to the whole.
There is no question that the harmony of the building, which is clearly one of its most visible charac-
teristics, is dependent upon a certain mathematical system of proportions” (Glassman, Secrets of the
Parthenon, time marker 35, 11-30). In scholarly publication, however, Hurwit offers a more subdued
articulation of this position with no overt reference to visual ramifications of proportional systems,
noting that the Parthenon “…is remarkable, above all, for the harmony of its carefully calculated
proportions and for its so-called refinements.” Hurwit, The Acropolis in the Age of Pericles, 118.
Similarly, in his 1980 film on Andrea Palladio, James S. Ackerman remarks: “In Palladio’s work, it is the
refinement of proportions—a fixing of precise ratios of length to width to depth and height—that
gives one a sense of equilibrium in and around his buildings.” Ackerman and Terry, Palladio; and
cf. Ackerman and Cohen, “Proportional Systems in the History of Architecture,” Chapter 24 herein,
page 520 n. 20. In scholarly publication, however, Ackerman posits more cautiously: “Palladio’s view
of architecture as natural philosophy helps to explain unique qualities in his design, especially a
subtlety of proportion, composition and equilibrium, that have been praised through the centuries
but seldom examined critically,” and, after quoting Sylvio Belli’s On Proportions and Proportionality:
“Palladio applied a similar aesthetic to designs that give much more importance to proportional
relationships than those of earlier Renaissance architects.” Ackerman, Palladio, 160-161.
42
Reprint from "Proportional Systems in the History of Architecture" - ISBN 9789087282776 - © Leiden University Press, 2018
Two Kinds of Proportion
Cf. Cohen, Beyond Beauty, 24. Although some degree of uniformitarianism is implicit in much re-
13
search in archaeology and the social sciences, there remains little agreement about how or when
this assumption can be reliably applied in these fields, or if it is even logically valid. (Trigger, A Hist-
ory of Archaeological Thought, 29 and 416; Trigger, “Prospects for a World Archaeology,” 2; Bailey,
“Hunter-gatherer behaviour,” 3; and Wallace, Contradictions of Archaeological Theory, 101.) Uni-
formitarianism—the belief that essential qualities of human behavior in the present correspond to
those throughout history and prehistory—is typically associated with inferences about social struc-
tures, economic strategies and cognitive abilities (Bailey, as above). Any attempt to apply uniformi-
tarian principles to aesthetic preferences, however, would seem to be particularly questionable due
to the difficulty of describing such preferences objectively, in a manner that includes all applicable
sensory stimuli; and due to the dramatic developments in aesthetic theory since the eighteenth cen-
tury that have arguably altered human perception. Regardless of one’s opinions on this matter with
regard to proportion, however, any uniformitarian assumptions must be stated explicitly in order to
avoid us/them ambiguity.
Cohen, Beyond Beauty, 281–287.
14
Thus, in the example of the San Lorenzo nave arcade bays, several key dimensions, when expressed
15
in terms of the 15th-century Florentine braccio, end in the fraction 2⁄3. When separated out from the
rest these numbers imply the Boethian number progression 1, 5, 9, 13, 17. These numerical relation-
ships are not visible. They can only be understood mentally. See Cohen, Beyond Beauty, 52–111;
and Cohen, “How Much Brunelleschi?” 18–57.
Cf. Herrmann’s quotation of François Blondel quoting Claude Perrault, probably from one of the lat-
16
ter’s unpublished mémoires, “...that proportions ‘cannot be seen, and therefore, cannot be the cause
of a sensible effect such as the pleasure which beauty gives us’” (Herrmann, The Theory of Claude
Perrault, 133). By this Perrault probably means that minute differences between similar proportions
cannot be seen, as in his assorted comments collected in Herrmann, The Theory of Claude Perrault,
136-137. It follows, therefore, that no proportion can ever be precisely identified through visual
analysis alone.
Cf. note 16, above, and Perrault’s assertion that “...in architecture there are, strictly speaking, no pro-
17
portions that are true in themselves...” (Perrault, Ordonnance for the Five Kinds of Columns, 54); “...à
proprement parler, dans de l’Architecture de proportions véritables en elles-mesmes...” (Perrault,
Ordonnance des cinq espèces de colonnes, xiv). See also Cohen, Beyond Beauty, 281 and 284–285.
See also the discussion below (p. 33) on the limitations of correlation, as in the belief that measure-
18
ments of the proportions of buildings considered to be beautiful can be used in the designs of new
buildings in order to create similar beauty.
Wladyslaw Tartarkiewicz goes so far as to propose that “...the general theory of beauty formulat-
19
ed in ancient times [, which] declared that beauty consists in the proportions of the parts…” or
more narrowly, “…that the relationship of parts which produced beauty could be numerically ex-
pressed[,]…might not unreasonably be called the Great Theory of European aesthetics.” (Tartark-
iewicz, “The Great Theory of Beauty,” 167). Regarding my occasional spiritual-aesthetic enjoyment
of buildings, historic or modern, while contemplating dimensions and proportional systems as an
architect rather than architectural historian, I admire a kind of beauty that I believe results from an
architect’s intense consideration of a design that leads to precise dimensional adjustments, wheth-
er in response to outside contingencies such as site constraints or the self-referential logic of a
belief-based proportional system. Sometimes I even believe I can distinguish a building that has
resulted from such intensity from one that has not. This is a different kind of beauty-in-proportion
belief than the one implied by Hurwit and Ackerman in the informal space provided by educational
films and interviews (see note 12, above). Both kinds deserve respect as genuine human values, but
both must also be acknowledged as subjective and fundamentally illogical—which is why the pre-
ceding reflections are presented in the first person singular. Such aesthetic interpretations, being
untestable and unprovable, belong to the realm of architectural criticism (or perhaps merely pure
enjoyment) rather than architectural history, the latter of which needs to be based on scholarly and
scientific methods. When it enters the scholarship on architectural proportional systems the aesthet-
ic question invariably constitutes but an unresolvable (because subjective) distraction that draws
scholarly energy away from the centrally important problems of how to identify the proportional
systems of the past based on verifiable historical evidence, and how to determine their originally-
intended meanings. In clarifying these thoughts I have benefited from a correspondence with Mark
Wilson Jones. On the distinction between belief-based and certainty-based proportional systems,
see above, and note 99 and its related discussion below.
Pevsner, “Report on a Debate,” 456–457.
20
thus demonstrating that beauty-in-proportion preconceptions and critical thinking about other
issues pertaining to architectural proportional systems are not mutually exclusive. Pevsner, “Report
on a Debate,” 467.
43
Reprint from "Proportional Systems in the History of Architecture" - ISBN 9789087282776 - © Leiden University Press, 2018
Matthew A. Cohen
The Oxford English Dictionary Online refers to taste as “the sense of what is appropriate, harmoni-
22
ous, or beautiful; especially: discernment and appreciation of the beautiful in nature or art; specif-
ically: the faculty of perceiving and enjoying what is excellent in art, literature, and the like” (“taste,
n.1,” entry 8a). This definition merely implies the notion of sensus communis (common sense, or
communal assent), which is explicit in the definition of taste by Kant, Kant’s Critique of Judgment,
169–170, quoted below (see note 31). Like Kant’s definition, this one emphasizes taste as a judg-
ment rather than merely a pleasurable sensory experience.
Harrison, Wood and Gaiger, Art in Theory: 1648–1815, 489. Cf. Oxford English Dictionary Online,
23
“æsthetic” (heading A.1): “Of or pertaining to sensuous perception, received by the senses.” This def-
inition is accompanied by a single example of usage, from the late 18th century. Cf. note 24, below.
Oxford English Dictionary Online, “æsthetic” (heading A.2.). This definition is accompanied by four
24
to a Psychology of Architecture,” 167–171; Scott, The Architecture of Humanism; and Langfeld, The
Aesthetic Attitude; de Jong, “Subjective Proportions,” Chapter 4, page 106 herein; and the conclu-
sion to this volume, Chapter 25, Principle 1.
Ackerman, “‘Ars sine scientia nihil est’”; and Wittkower, Architectural Principles (1949).
26
See, for example, Billings, An Attempt to Define the Geometric Proportions; Penrose, An Investiga-
27
tion; Henszlmann, Théorie des proportions; Gwilt, The Encyclopedia of Architecture; Pennethorne,
The Geometry and Optics of Ancient Architecture; Thiersch, “Die Proportionen in der Architektur,”
vol. IV, section 1.2, 38–77; von Stegmann and von Geymüller, Filippo di Ser Brunellesco, I:18; Mar-
quand, “A Study in Greek Architectural Proportions,” 521–532; Gardner, The Parthenon; Borissav-
liévitch, La science de l’harmonie; and Hambidge, The Elements of Dynamic Symmetry, a reprint
of the 1926 edition, based on lectures delivered around 1916 and published in the journal The
Diagonal in 1919 and 1920. Mystically-inclined studies also continued after 1949, for example, Bair-
ati, La simmetria dinamica; Borissavliévitch, Le nombre d’or; Des Corats, La proportion égyptienne;
Funck-Hellet, De la proportion; Jouven, Rythme et architecture; and Doczi, The Power of Limits. For
an approach to architectural proportion that focuses on the concept of stability, or résistence, see
Lebrun, Théorie de l’architecture grecque et romaine, 19–23; and Lebrun, “Applications du principe
de stabilité,” 205–227. For an extensive but not comprehensive bibliography of proportion literature
up to 1958, see Graf, Bibliographie zum Problem der Proportionen. For an addendum to Graf’s bibli-
ography, see Borsi, Per una storia della teoria delle proporzioni, 119–155.
Wittkower continued to develop and promote these theoretical generalizations in subsequent pub-
28
ciples (1949 and 1962), preface, v. Note that Wittkower, Architectural Principles (1962 and 1971),
introduction, n.p., refers to this passage by Clark as his “...intention in a nutshell,” while Clark had
merely called it a “result” of Wittkower’s book (Clark, “Humanism and Architecture,” 65).
See Abrams, “Art-as-Such,” 8–33 (I thank K. Michael Hays for introducing me to this source); and
30
Oxford English Dictionary Online, “æsthetic,” B.4: “Of or pertaining to a late 19th-century movement
in England of artists and writers who advocated a doctrine of ‘art-for-art’s-sake,’ also known as the
‘aesthetic movement.’”
Kant, Kant’s Critique of Judgment, 173; and later in the same page: “Taste is then the faculty of
31
judging a priori of the communicability of feelings that are bound up with a given representation
(without the mediation of a concept).” Kant’s stipulation that taste involve judgment of “universally
communicable” qualities of feelings is related to his notion of “Taste as a kind of sensus communis,”
or “common sense” (Kant, Kant’s Critique of Judgment, 169–170). Sensus communis for Kant is not a
form of universal, metaphysical beauty (nor “positive beauty,” discussed below), which would con-
tradict the notion of judgment, but rather a presupposition that renders judgments communicable
to others. “The common sense,” John Hicks explains, “must be assumed [in order] to be able to
agree about what the feeling is in the first place” (Hicks, “Sensus Communis,” 111). Regarding Kant’s
stipulation that taste involve judgment “without the mediation of a concept,” Hicks observes: “Kant
...asks us to approach artworks formally, on their own terms, and resists interpretations that would in-
strumentalize their content for the purposes of cultural critique, politics, or philosophy itself” (Hicks,
“Sensus Communis,” 110).
See, for example, Wittkower’s reaction to the Milan conference discussed below, pages 28-29.
32
For a definition of a three-part Wittkower paradigm, see Cohen, Beyond Beauty, 36–51.
33
For classical proportions, see Gwilt, The Encyclopedia of Architecture, 893–921, which comprises
35
Book III: “Practice of Architecture,” Chapter II: “Principles of Proportion”; and for Gothic proportions,
44
Reprint from "Proportional Systems in the History of Architecture" - ISBN 9789087282776 - © Leiden University Press, 2018
Two Kinds of Proportion
Gwilt, The Encyclopedia of Architecture, 963–1020, which comprises Book III: “Practice of Architec-
ture,” Chapter IV: “Medieval Proportion,” Section 6.
Cohen, Beyond Beauty, 47. Wittkower’s use of the Kunstwollen concept in this context appears to
36
have been inspired by Panofsky’s 1921 study of human proportions (translated as Panofsky, “The
History of the Theory of Human Proportions”).
Wittkower, “Systems of Proportion,” 16.
37
Responding to my “equal partners” interpretation reiterated here, Angeliki Pollali proposes that the
39
writings of Francesco di Giorgio Martini “…invest [Wittkower’s medieval geometry vs. Renaissance
number predilection] with a certain qualified validity.” Pollali, “Design Method,” 32. Pollali’s inter-
pretation of these writings, however, is in fact not inconsistent with the equal partners interpretation.
According to Pollali, “Design Method,” 37 (italics are Pollali’s): “Francesco determines an arithmetical
module to approximate incommensurable ratios; the architect’s aim would be to abandon geom-
etry and adopt a numerical system of proportions.” Nevertheless, she notes, Francesco is merely
“…attempting to establish a correspondence between a geometrical and a numerical system,” and
furthermore, “...geometry remains Francesco’s basic tool.” Thus, even if Francesco indeed favors
arithmetic to the point of striving to “abandon geometry” as Pollali suggests, according to Pollali he
in fact does not succeed and instead makes equal use of geometry and number. Cf. Gerbino’s opin-
ion that Francesco saw geometry and number as “complementary” (Gerbino, “Were Early Modern
Architects Neoplatonists?,” Chapter 5 herein, pages 121-122); and Cohen, Beyond Beauty, 36–51,
and ch. 6.
Wittkower, “Systems of Proportion,” 16; cf. Cohen, "Ten Principles," Chapter 25, page 548 n. 68
40
herein.
Cohen, Beyond Beauty, 17–18 and 281-287.
41
Le Clerc, A Treatise of Architecture, 1:29. Cf. Le Clerc, Traité d’architecture, 39: “Par proportion, on
42
n’entend pas ici un rapport de raison à la maniere des Geometres; mais une convenance de parties,
fondée sur le bon goût de l’Architecte.” For a similar use of this term in Italian from the 16th century,
see van Eck’s quotation of Cosimo Bartoli in Chapter 3, p. 73 herein. On proportion-as-ratio see
Cohen, Beyond Beauty, 21.
Cohen, Beyond Beauty, 21–24.
43
Perrault, Ordonnance for the Five Kinds of Columns, 50-51. “Car il y a deux sortes de proportions,
44
dont l’une qui est difficile à apperçevoir consiste dans le rapport de raison des parties propor-
tionnées, tel qu’est celuy que les grandeurs des parties ont les unes aux autres ou avec le tout, com-
me d’etre la septiéme, la quinzieme ou la vingtiéme partie du tout. L’autre proportion qui s’appelle
Symmetrie en françois, et qui consiste dans le rapport que les parties ont ensemble à cause de
l’égalité & de la parité de leur nombre, de leur grandeur, de leur situation, & de leur ordre, est une
chose fort apparente, & dont on ne manque jamais d’appercevoir les deffauts, ainsi qu’il se voit au
dedans du Pantheon, où les bandeaux de la voute ne rapportant pas aux fenestres qui sont au des-
sous, causent une disproportion, & un manque de symmetrie que chacun peut aisement connoitre.”
Perrault, Ordonnance des cinq espèces de colonnes, vii. Cf. Vitruvius: “Symmetry is a proper agree-
ment between the members of the work itself, and a relation between the different parts and the
whole general scheme, in accordance with a certain part selected as standard. Thus in the human
body there is a kind of symmetrical harmony between forearm, foot, palm, finger, and other small
parts; and so it is with perfect buildings.” Vitruvius, The Ten Books on Architecture, 14.
See the preceding note.
45
Perrault’s critique of the Pantheon misalignments continued a tradition of dissatisfaction going back
46
to the 15th century. Francesco di Giorgio Martini and Antonio da Sangallo the Younger produced
sketches correcting this perceived flaw. For images, see Wilson Jones, Principles of Roman Architec-
ture, 188-189. Other critics included Michelangelo, Andrea Palladio, and Antoine Desgodets, while
Gian Lorenzo Bernini may have been a rare supporter. Marder, “Bernini and Alexander VII,” 628-645;
Wilson Jones, Principles of Roman Architecture, 188-190; Marder, “The Pantheon After Antiquity,”
145-153; and Marder, “The Pantheon in the Seventeenth Century,” 296-329. In 1976 MacDonald
noted that the misalignment “…adds a certain restlessness to the design,” but expressed uncer-
tainty as to its rationale. MacDonald, The Pantheon, 72. Loerke’s analysis of 1990 concludes that the
Pantheon architect intended the interior to be read as “discrete horizontal layers” for iconographical
and aesthetic reasons, the dome constituting one layer. Loerke, “A Rereading of the Interior Eleva-
tion,” 35-43. He thus prepared the way for Wilson Jones’s appreciative aesthetic reading that the
misalignment “…contributes to the indefinable, but none the less palpable, impression that the
dome hovers over the drum as opposed to weighing it down.” Wilson Jones, Principles of Roman
Architecture, 191.
Herrmann notes that “if Perrault had not gone further than making a distinction between positive
47
and arbitrary qualities of beauty, there would hardly have been much opposition,” for no one at
45
Reprint from "Proportional Systems in the History of Architecture" - ISBN 9789087282776 - © Leiden University Press, 2018
Matthew A. Cohen
the time questioned the existence of positive beauty. The part of his theory that “was unheard
of,” Herrmann continues, was his inclusion of proportions in the category of arbitrary beauty.
Herrmann, The Theory of Claude Perrault, 138–139. Note that while a strict reading of Perrault’s
remark: “…beauty has hardly any other foundation than fantaisie…” (“…les veritables regles du
beau & du parfait dans les Edifices: car la Beauté n’ayant guere d’autre fondement que la fan-
taisie”; Perrault, Les dix livres d’architecture, Preface, v) with which Herrmann prominently opens
his Chapter II: “Proportions and Beauty,” might seem to contradict Perrault’s later embrace of the
notion of positive beauty, Herrmann plausibly interprets this passage as a “blueprint” for Perrault’s
later inquiries into architectural theory, which emphasize the need for rules in every sphere of hu-
man activity—rules that notably include architectural proportional systems. This early passage thus
seems to anticipate Perrault’s later, more completely developed contention that perceived beauty
in architectural proportions—not merely beauty in general—has no other foundation than fantaisie,
and that such capricious beauty is not the same as positive beauty. Thus, eleven years later Perrault
writes: “…the proportions of architectural members do not possess a beauty that has a foundation
as positive as the condition of natural things, or as the beauty of musical harmonies that please due
to a definite and immutable proportion that does not depend on fantaisie” (Perrault, Les dix livres
d’architecture, 106 n. 12: “…les proportions des membres d’Architecture n’ont point une beauté
qui ait un fondement tellement positif, qu’il soit de la condition des choses naturelles, & pareil à
celluy de la beauté des accords de la Musique, qui plaisent à cause d’une proportion certaine &
immuable, qui ne dépend point de la fantaisie”). See the quotations of these passages in Herr-
mann, The Theory of Claude Perrault 31 and 40, though with incorrect citations.
So strong and widespread was the beauty-in-proportion belief system in Perrault’s day that
Perrault’s radicalism, such as it was, according to Herrmann provides one explanation for Perrault’s
lack of influence on contemporary architectural theory, apart from the lively debate with Blondel
that his ideas engendered. Herrmann, The Theory of Claude Perrault, 140, notes: “Perrault’s unortho-
dox opinions were brushed aside” by his contemporaries, who greeted them with “incredulity.” He
furthermore notes that Perrault’s inclusion of proportions in the class of arbitrary beauty was as
“futile” as Edmund Burke’s later claim “...that ‘proportions are not the cause of beauty.’” Herrmann,
The Theory of Claude Perrault, 139, quoting Burke, A Philosophical Enquiry, 91. Thus according to
Herrmann’s interpretation, it would seem that no serious challenge to the beauty-in-proportion be-
lief system ever had a chance of making it out of either the 17th or 18th century with any significant
following. Cf. discussion of Wittkower’s “Break-away” theory, below.
In his Ordonnance des cinq espèces de colonnes, Perrault occasionally seems to struggle to rec-
48
oncile his own distinction between arbitrary and positive beauty in relation to architectural propor-
tional systems, as in his comments regarding ancient Roman proportions: “ancient usage is not so
much pleasing in itself as pleasing because it is linked to other positive, natural, and reasonable
beauties that make it pleasing by association, so to speak.” Perrault, Ordonnance for the Five Kinds of
Columns, 54 (“les beaux Ouvrages des Anciens...dans lesquels aussi cette maniere ne plaist pas tant
par elle-mesme que parce qu’elle est jointe à d’autres beautez positives, naturelles & raisonnables,
laquelles, s’il faut ainsi dire, la font aimer par compagnie.” Perrault, Ordonnance des cinq espèces
de colonnes, xiii); and in his comments regarding his own proposed proportional system for the
orders that is based on the arithmetical means of comparative measurements of ancient Roman
examples: “even though in architecture there are, strictly speaking, no proportions that are true
in themselves, it still remains to be investigated whether it is possible to establish probable mean
proportions that are founded on positive reasons but that do not stray too far from those that are
accepted and in current use.” Perrault, Ordonnance for the Five Kinds of Columns, 54-55 (“...& que
par consequent il n’y a point, à proprement parler, dans l’Architecture de proportions veritables en
elles-mesmes; il reste à examiner si l’on en peut établir de probables, & de vray semblables fondées
sur des raisons positives, sans s’éloigner beaucoup des proportions reçuës & usitées.” Perrault,
Ordonnance des cinq espèces de colonnes, xiv).
In his footnotes to his translation of Vitruvius published in 1684, Perrault again struggles to rec-
oncile these two kinds of beauty, as in his claim that even though most architects of his day believe that
the proportions of the orders presented by Vitruvius are “...something natural...” (“...quelque chose de
naturel...”), he believes these proportions are established “...by a consent among architects...” (“...par
un consentement des Architects...”), and are preferred not because they possess positive beauty,
“...but only because these proportions are found in works that have other kinds of positive and convin-
cing beauty, such as those of material and correctness of execution, and thus these proportions are
approved and appreciated even though they contain nothing positive themselves” (“...mais seule-
ment parce que ces proportions se trouvoient en des ouvrages, qui ayant d’ailleurs d’autres beautez
positives & convaincantes, telles que sont celles de la matiere & de la justesse de l’execution, ont fait
approuver & aimer la beauté de ces proportions, bien qu’elle n’eust rien de positif.” Perrault, Les dix
livres d’architecture, 105 n. 7). He makes a similar comment in a later footnote, using the term “verit-
able beauté.” Perrault, Les dix livres d’architecture, 80 n. 16. Thus Perrault seems reluctant to separ-
ate the arbitrary beauty that he associates with architectural proportions completely from positive
beauty. Cf. Pérez-Goméz, Architecture and the Crisis of Modern Science, 32; and Herrmann, The
46
Reprint from "Proportional Systems in the History of Architecture" - ISBN 9789087282776 - © Leiden University Press, 2018
Two Kinds of Proportion
Theory of Claude Perrault, 132. On the comparison between beauty and mathematical theorems in
relation to Platonism, see Mitrović, Serene Greed of the Eye, 29-30.
See Alberti’s comments: “But judgment[s] with regard to beauty are not determined by opinion,
49
but rather by an innate faculty of the mind.... For there is in the forms and figures of buildings cer-
tainly a natural excellence or perfection that excites the spirit and is immediately felt.” Alberti, De
re aedificatoria, IX.v, opposite fol. y: “Ut vero de pulchritudine iudices, non opinio, verum animis
innata quaedam ratio efficient.... Est enim in formis profecto et figuris aedificiorum aliquid excellens
perfectumque natur. quod animum excitat evestigioque sentiatur.” This innate or natural beauty is
among the factors contributing to Alberti’s notion of concinnitas which, according to Caroline van
Eck, Alberti introduces “...as a work of research, selection, and inquiry into the factors that produce
beauty, both in nature and in art.” Van Eck, “The Structure of De re aedificatoria Reconsidered,” 286,
in reference to De re aedificatoria 9.15.
Perrault, Ordonnance for the Five Kinds of Columns, 50: “I call beauties based on convincing reasons
50
those whose presence in works is bound to please everyone, so easily apprehended are their value
and quality. They include the richness of materials, the size and magnificence of the building, the
precision and cleanness of the execution, and symmetrie, which in French signifies the kind of pro-
portion that produces an unmistakable and striking beauty” (“j’appelle des beautez fondées sur des
raisons convaincantes, celles par lesquelles les ouvrages doivent plaire à tout le monde, parce qu’il
est aisé d’en connoistre le merite & la valeur, telles que sont la richesse de la matiere, la grandeur &
la magnificence de l’Edifice, la justesse & la propreté de l’execution, & la symmetrie qui signifie en
françois l’espece de Proportion qui produit une beauté evidente & remarquable.” Perrault, Ordon-
nance des cinq espèces de colonnes, vi–vii). Cf. note 47, above.
Kant, Kant’s Critique of Judgment, 185; see also note 31, above.
51
On Perrault’s interest in, applications of, and contributions to the developing scientific knowledge
52
of his day see Gerbino, François Blondel, 118-147; Herrmann, The Theory of Claude Perrault, 70–94
and 193–198; and Picon, Claude Perrault, 29–102. See Monod’s related conclusion that “…the occult
[i.e., alchemy, astrology and ritual magic] was not killed off by science or the Enlightenment. On
the contrary, it coexisted with them, borrowed from them and was rarely the object of attacks from
scientific or enlightened writers.” Monod, Solomon’s Secret Arts, 346.
Although the degree of Perrault’s influence would be difficult to ascertain, it is notable that in 1952
53
Louis Hautecœur, in his “Préface” to Borissavliévitch, Le nombre d’or, 5–6, describes an active de-
bate in his own day about architectural proportional systems “...between defenders of objective
beauty and defenders of subjective beauty” (“...débat entre défenseurs de la Beauté objective et
défenseurs de la Beauté subjective...”), or, terms that correspond to Perrault’s positive and arbi-
trary beauty, respectively. Objective beauty, Hautecœur notes, is “...independent of man himself...”
(“...indépendant de l’homme même...”) while subjective beauty is “...a creation of man” (”...une créa-
tion de l’homme”). Herrmann, The Theory of Claude Perrault, 150, notes that discussions of Perrault’s
“dual nature of beauty” actively continued in the 18th century often under different names than Per-
rault’s positive and arbitrary beauty, such as idées as opposed to sentiments, but always with the
aim of saving absolute (i.e., positive) beauty from being undermined by the growing notion of the
relativity of taste. Consistent with both this practice and the terms of the debate Hautecœur reports,
Picon, Claude Perrault, 153, interprets Perrault’s distinction between arbitrary and positive beauty as a
difference between an appeal to the senses (arbitrary) and to reason (positive): “L’ordonnance d’une
façade peut en effet parler aux sens ou à la raison selon son raffinement plus ou moins grand et le
degré de culture du spectateur qui la contemple.” The recent study by Di Dio, Macaluso and Rizzolatti
“The Golden Beauty,” indicates that interest in this debate is still active today. See note 11, above.
Gerbino, “Were Early Modern Architects Neoplatonists?,” Chapter 5 herein, page 116 and 118.
54
On Blondel’s defense, see Gerbino, François Blondel, 148–165 and 173–178; and Herrmann, The
55
regles pour ce sujet, par les belles proportions que leurs parties ont entr’elles & à leur tout, & qui
sont, comme nous avons dit, cette agreable harmonie qui donne tant de plaisir aux yeux” (Blondel,
Cours d’architecture, V.v.738); and “Et ces trois grandeurs, sçavoir la largeur du tout, la hauteur sous
le toit & la largeur de l’avant-corps sont en continuelle proportion Harmonique suivant ces nombres
6, 4, 3” (Blondel, Cours d’architecture, V.v.739).
Blondel, Cours d’architecture, 5:759.
57
Such as, for example, Perrault’s argument against any analogy between visual and musical beauty
58
in part because pleasing architectural proportions are more variable than pleasing musical propor-
tions (Perrault, Ordonnance des cinq espèces de colonnes, i–v; and Perrault, Ordonnance of the Five
Kinds of Columns, 47–49). See also notes 10, 16 and 17, above; and Gerbino, “Were Early Modern
Architects Neoplatonists?,” Chapter 5 herein, p. 117. For Herrmann’s assessment that Perrault’s Or-
donnance was “not generally a success” in achieving what it set out to do, see Herrmann, The Theory
of Claude Perrault, 130–189; and note 47, above .
47
Reprint from "Proportional Systems in the History of Architecture" - ISBN 9789087282776 - © Leiden University Press, 2018
Matthew A. Cohen
Wittkower, Architectural Principles (1949 and 1952), 124–135; and Wittkower, Architectural Princi-
59
contain his excitement in the second volume of his Lectures, occasionally asking forgiveness as
he digresses into “...a kind of poetick Rhapsody,” as in his poem that begins (italics are Morris’s):
“Proportion! When I name that pleasing Word, // In silent contemplative Raptures lost, // All Nature
seems to start, and say, ‘Tis here.’” Morris, Lectures on Architecture, 2:221, cf. 184–186, 188–191, 200,
205–207, 209, 210–212, 215–216, and 221–223.
Wittkower, Architectural Principles (1949 and 1952), 131, and 134 with note 2; and Wittkower, Archi-
61
tectural Principles (1962 and 1971), 150, and 153 with note 4.
Cf. Branko Mitrović’s rejection of “collectivist methodology,” or the “collectivist fallacy,” the wide-
62
spread influence of which in architectural and art history he ascribes to the impact of Erwin Panofsky
and Wittkower, among others. Mitrović notes: “Collectivist fallacy systematically applied and thus
turned into a methodology, assumes that the totality of an individual’s experience is collective-de-
termined. Typically, a historian who adopts this approach ascribes certain beliefs to a collective, and
then infers that every individual participating in the collective must share these beliefs. Such a histor-
ian first claims to know what ideas an individual belonging to a certain collective...ought to have had
and then imposes this interpretation on all individuals classified into that context.” Mitrović, Serene
Greed of the Eye, 21.
Wittkower, Architectural Principles (1949 and 1952), 134; and Wittkower, Architectural Principles
63
Wittkower refers to: Hogarth, Analysis of Beauty, 1953; Hume, A Treatise of Human Nature, 1739, and
65
Of the Standard of Taste, 1757; and Burke, A Philosophical Enquiry; in Wittkower, Architectural Prin-
ciples (1949 and 1952), 131–132; and Wittkower, Architectural Principles (1962 and 1971), 150–151.
Monod, Solomon’s Secret Arts. The tradition of occultism may also have contributed to creating a
sympathetic environment for the beauty-in-proportion belief system within the neo-Palladian move-
ment, of which Robert Morris and Lord Burlington were leaders each in his own way (see note 60,
above). For mid-19th-century English beauty-in-proportion literature, see for example the following
three books by David Ramsay Hay: The Orthographic Beauty of the Parthenon Referred to a Law of
Nature (Edinburgh and London: William Blackwood and Sons, 1853); The Harmonic Law of Nature
Applied to Architectural Design (Edinburgh and London: William Blackwood and Sons, 1855); and
The Science of Beauty, As Developed in Nature and Applied in Art (Edinburgh and London: William
Blackwood and Sons, 1856). For Herrmann’s characterization of Burke’s efforts to convince his con-
temporaries that “proportions are not the cause of beauty” as futile, see note 47, above.
Garbett, Rudimentary Treatise, 38.
66
Pennethorne, The Geometry and Optics of Ancient Architecture, 45. Cf. Morris’s comment: “Wher-
68
ever Harmony resides, either in Numbers, or Nature, it immediately strikes the imagination, by some
Attractive or Sympathizing Property.” Morris, Lectures on Architecture, 1, Dedication.
Another term that often accompanies “harmony” is “symmetry.”
69
See note 11, above. The seemingly religious devotion that the golden section has sometimes in-
71
spired since the 19th century is evident in The Society of the Golden Section Newsletter, published
in Chicago from November 1975 to May 1983. The eponymous, now-defunct organization promot-
ed the golden section philosophy and drawings of the Swiss-born American architect Abel Faidy, a
self-described follower of Jay Hambidge, Matila Ghyka, and Le Corbusier. According to the society’s
Executive Director, Diana Faidy, writing in the first issue of the newsletter, the society was formed
“...to promote specific knowledge of the golden section and encourage employment of its disci-
plines, so that a new order, harmony and symmetry may pervade the design fabric of man’s needs
and the total environment [may] become a symphony of harmonic spatial relationships, a Unity
achieving ultimate coherence within a mathematical order.” Faidy, “Executive Director’s note,” 1;
and for Abel Faidy’s biographical information, The Society of the Golden Section Newsletter (first
issue as above), 1–2. For a similar attitude toward the golden section, see Doczi, The Power of Limits.
Laurent, “Quand Auguste Perret,” 61–78; Loach, “Le Corbusier and the Creative Use,” 185–215; and
72
“Jeunes Peintres ne vous frappez pas!“ 1–2. I thank Judi Loach for sharing her insights into these
groups with me. On the possible influence of Paul Valéry’s Eupalinos ou l’architecte of 1921 on
this French cultural scene and its interpretations of proportion, see Curti, “Canons of Proportion,”
Chapter 2, page 68 n. 1 herein.
On these German and other influences, see Jean-Louis Cohen, “Le Corbusier’s Modulor and the
73
Debate on Proportion in France,” Chapter 21 herein. Note that the name Modulor combines the
48
Reprint from "Proportional Systems in the History of Architecture" - ISBN 9789087282776 - © Leiden University Press, 2018
Two Kinds of Proportion
contemporary interest in modules with the French name for golden section, section d’or.
A similar conference but with a more general focus was held in Paris in 1937. For the proceedings
74
containing 150 abstracts and papers, see Deuxième Congrès International. In his review of these
proceedings in the American Journal of Sociology of 1939, John T. Mueller notes that while pro-
vocative as a series, “...many of the papers do not justify their scientific appellation.” Mueller, Review
of Deuxième congrès, 153.
See note 2, above.
75
“Nel 1951 il convegno De Divina Proportione si era proposto come l’ecumenico concilio degli uom-
76
ini delle arti e delle scienze chiamato a deliberare le regole dello spirito che avrebbero governato
le nuove aree della ricostruzione democratica” Irace, “La difficile proporzione,” 17.
“L’interesse che suscitò nel 1951 forse nacque, in un’Europa che cercava ancora di riaversi dalle dev-
77
astazioni della guerra, dal desiderio di restituire spiritualità alle arti e alla vita attraverso le geometrie
di un’architettura pura, priva di ornamenti e costituita da superfici e aperture rettangolari.” Acker-
man, “Ricordi della Nona Triennale,” 34.
Ackerman and Cohen, “Proportional Systems in the History of Architecture,” Chapter 25 herein,
78
page 513.
Giedion, “Il tutto e la parte,” 75.
79
Giedion, “Il tutto e la parte,” 73-74. Le Corbusier uses the term “divina proportione” in this manner
81
in his 1927 essay “Un livre opportun,” published in Jean-Louis Cohen, “Le Corbusier’s Modulor,”
Chapter 21, Appendix, 1 herein.
Ackerman, “Le proporzioni nell’architettura gotica,” 51. In 2007 Ackerman noted that in Milan in
82
1951, due to his young age and the authoritativeness of the middle-aged men who dominated the
conference, he “felt like a sergeant assisting in a meeting of generals.” Ackerman, “Ricordi della
Nona Triennale,” 21-22.
Wittkower, “Finalità del Convegno,” 47.
83
Thus Wittkower noted at the end of his conference paper, which addressed historical issues per-
84
taining to the medieval and Renaissance periods: “This examination of a purely historical character
can, I believe, provide a wise lesson for current problems” (“Questa disamina di carattere puramente
storico può, credo, impartire una saggia lezione sui problemi attuali”). Wittkower, “Alcuni aspetti
della proporzione,” 49.
Wittkower, “The Changing Concept of Proportion,” 210.
85
Wittkower, “The Changing Concept of Proportion,” 210; and Pevsner, “Report on a Debate,” 456–463.
86
Wittkower’s dismissal, based on the results of this vote, of the beauty-in-proportion belief system as a
significant cultural phenomenon of the time is another example of his denial of pluralism in European
attitudes toward architectural proportional systems (see above, note 62 and related discussion), for
a 60-48 vote against the belief that proportional systems create beauty in architecture indicates that
nearly half of the RIBA meeting participants were beauty-in-proportion sympathizers, if not believ-
ers. The 1957 RIBA vote had a notable parallel, though a different outcome, in two meetings of the
Académie Royale d’Architecture in January 1672, during which members considered the question of
“whether a positive rule for it [proportion] existed or whether it was arbitrary,” and a majority voted to
affirm that “a positive beauty existed in architecture.” Herrmann, The Theory of Claude Perrault, 32.
Wittkower, “The Changing Concept of Proportion,” 210.
87
Baumgarten, “Prolegomena” to his Aesthetica, translated and quoted in Harrison, Wood and Gaiger,
89
Art in Theory: 1648–1815, 490. To this hypothetical objection Baumgarten replies in part “that the
philosopher is a man amongst men and it is not good for him to think that so great a part of human
perception has nothing to do with him.”
Cohen, Beyond Beauty, 140-145.
90
By associating the word “certainty” with verifiable outcomes, it is here distinguished from Acker-
91
man’s reference to “classical certainty,” which implies confident yet unverifiable certainty. Thus, be-
lief-based proportional systems contributed to “classical certainty” because the adherents of be-
lief-based proportional systems were certain in their convictions, even if those convictions were
based on unverifiable and unscientific beliefs. See Ackerman and Cohen, “Proportional Systems in
the History of Architecture,” Chapter 25 herein.
The concept of ordine appears to be similar to the concept of Gerechtigkeit (“correct proportions”)
92
that the master mason Mathes Roriczer uses in his discussion of the proportions of a Gothic pinna-
cle. Shelby, Gothic Design Techniques, 32–33. On the concept of ordine, see Cohen, Beyond Beauty,
270–276.
49
Reprint from "Proportional Systems in the History of Architecture" - ISBN 9789087282776 - © Leiden University Press, 2018
Matthew A. Cohen
In this definition, numerical correspondences are the numerical qualities of integers as revealed, for
93
additional criteria for distinguishing intentional proportions from coincidental ones, see Cohen, Be-
yond Beauty, 59–60; Cohen, “How Much Brunelleschi?” 19–21; and Fernie, “A Beginner’s Guide,”
229-237.
See for example the comment of Emma C. Ackermann, “The Golden Section,” 263: “Whenever, in
95
the products of art or manufacture, there is no equal division, (symmetry), the artist or workman
unconsciously employs the proportions of the golden section. Irregular inequality and capricious
division is disagreeable to both eye and hand; and the proportion[s] of the golden section seem to
be the only acceptable ones.”
Since even consistent, deliberate-looking proportional patterns can be coincidental, distinguish-
96
ing intentional proportions (proportions-as-ratio) from coincidental ones may be considered one
of the central challenges of the study of architectural proportional systems. Indeed, coincident-
al occurrences of highly-ordered structures must be expected in architecture, as in geometry and
mathematics. This phenomenon is aptly illuminated by Rudolf Arnheim, who notes, “only in a world
based exclusively on the chance combination of independent elements is an orderly pattern a most
improbable thing to turn up; in a world replete with systems of structural organization, orderliness
is a state universally aspired to and often brought about.” Arnheim, Entropy and Art, 37. For a math-
ematical analysis of this phenomenon, see Fischler, “How to Find the ‘Golden Number,’” 406–410.
Cf. note 6, above.
97
For an identification of six purposes of belief-based proportional systems, none of which may be
98
presented in this introduction, there are two kinds of proportion: proportion-as-ratio (quantitative)
and proportion-as-beauty (qualitative); and two kinds of proportional systems: belief-based (meta-
physical) and certainty-based (scientific). Belief-based proportional systems can be based on either
proportions-as-ratio or proportions-as-beauty, singly or in combination—these are the “anything
goes” proportional systems. Certainty-based proportional systems are only based on the verifiabil-
ity of proportions-as-ratio. Note that Le Corbusier worked with engineers who used various cer-
tainty-based proportional systems (such as engineering specifications for concrete and steel con-
struction) in order to ensure the structural stability and code compliance of his buildings, and that
those engineers in all likelihood ignored his belief-based Modulor in practice.
100
Cohen, Beyond Beauty, 104–111; and Cohen, “How Much Brunelleschi?” 33-37.
101
On the conclusion that the church prior Matteo Dolfini appears to have designed the San Lorenzo
nave arcade bay proportional system but died before he could realize it, and that Brunelleschi in-
herited it from him, and modified it to varying degrees for use in both the basilicas of San Lorenzo
and Santo Spirito, see Cohen, Beyond Beauty, 185–207, which expands upon Cohen, “How Much
Brunelleschi?” 41–44.
102
Durand, Précis des leçons d’architecture. Whether or not Durand himself believed that his grid-
based proportional system assisted in establishing structural stability, he promoted the system in
the belief that the grid was somehow beneficial to architecture, a belief for which there can be no
scientific basis. It may thus be considered a belief-based proportional system.
103
Gwilt, The Encyclopedia of Architecture, 894–895.
104
Cf. Pevsner’s remarks in note 5, above.
105
“…Su solo albedrio ... por ciertas lineas ortogonales lo hacen y se osan encomendar a ello.” This
comment was made in the context of determining the proportions of a Gothic buttress for the pur-
pose of ensuring structural stability. Quoted in Kubler, “A Late Gothic Computation,” 146. Thus it
appears that proportional systems as records of constructive experience, such as builders’ rules-
of-thumb, could not be relied upon to ensure or even increase the odds of structural stability. On
the ineffectiveness of proportion-as-ratio for this purpose see also Curti, “Canons of Proportion,”
Chapter 2 herein, page 65; and the conclusion to this volume, Chapter 25, note 44.
106
Van Eck, “The Composto Ordinato,” Chapter 3 herein; Grasshoff and Berndt, “Decoding the Panthe-
on Columns,” Chapter 17 herein; and Crosby, The Measure of Reality, 46-47.
50
Reprint from "Proportional Systems in the History of Architecture" - ISBN 9789087282776 - © Leiden University Press, 2018
Two Kinds of Proportion
Gerbino, “Were Early Modern Architects Neoplatonists?” Chapter 5 herein; and Ottenheym, “Dutch
107
proportion, and the displeasing things fall outside of it, as the music theorists have well and judi-
ciously proven in their science…” (“quanto ogni nostro senso si compiaccia in questa proporzione,
e le cose spiacevoli essere fuori di quella, come ben provano li musici nella loro scienza sensata-
mente”). Da Vignola, Regola delli cinque ordini d’architettura, Prefazione, n.p.; and Palladio’s similar
comment (author’s translation): “just as the proportions of voices are harmony to the ears, so those
of measurement are harmony to the eyes, which according to their habit delights to a great degree,
without it being known why, apart from those who study to know the reasons of things” (“…per-
ciochè, secondo che le proportioni delle voci sono armonia delle orecchie così quelle delle misure
sono armonia degli occhi nostri, la quale secondo il suo costume sommamente diletta, senza sa-
persi il perchè, fuori che da quelli che studiano di sapere le ragioni delle cose,” as transcribed
in Zorzi, Le chiese e i ponti di Andrea Palladio, 88; and with slight differences in Palladio, Scritti
sull’Architettura, 123). Cf. Palladio’s similar comments in Palladio, I quattro libri dell’architettura, iv.
Wittkower, conversely, influentially interpreted these brief and ambivalent references to musical
harmony by da Vignola and Palladio as proof of these architects’ wholehearted commitments to
a neo-Platonic worldview rooted in a belief that musical harmonic proportions created beauty in
architecture. Cohen, Beyond Beauty, 33–35.
Da Vignola, Regola delli cinque ordini d’architettura, Prefazione, n.p.
109
Another example of one of these myriad factors is cultural association, as when government build-
110
ings from the Fascist period in Italy are considered by some to be unsightly due to their historical
associations, even when they display plausibly classical scale and proportions.
Regarding Alberti’s belief in causation, see his comment that those “...numbers by means of which
111
the harmony of voices is very pleasing to the ear, are the same numbers that please the eyes and
the spirit” (“Hi quidem numeri, per quos fiat ut vocum illa concinnitas auribus gratissima reddatur,
hidem ipsi numeri perficiunt, ut oculi animusque voluptate mirifica compleantur”; Alberti, De re
aedificatoria, IX.v, yii [verso]). Tafuri, however, doubts the depth of Alberti’s metaphysical commit-
ment, noting that his musical analogy “…assumes a functionalist implication,” followed as it is by
Alberti’s note that he will dwell on the topic only so long as it is “…of use to architecture.” Tafuri,
Interpreting the Renaissance, 16.
In the pre-engineering period, the notions of structural stability, beauty and ordine all overlapped.
112
Since structural stability constituted such a pressing, pragmatic need that at best could be satis-
fied only some of the time, primarily through the experience and skill of the builders, availability
of high-quality materials, and luck, the then-interrelated notions of structural stability, beauty, and
ordine can in this context be considered to have had pragmatic intentions. Proportional systems
did not contribute to structural successes, but most architects and builders probably thought they
did (see note 105, above.) The motivations of architects who have used belief-based proportional
systems during the post-engineering period, conversely, may be assumed to have been more mys-
tically oriented because, with the availability of modern structural engineering to ensure structural
stability, the motivations for using such proportional systems cannot have been pragmatic. On col-
lectivism, see Mitrović, note 62, above.
See Ackerman’s interpretation of the Milan conference as “...the end of the mystical phase...” of the
113
study of proportional systems, and the beginning of the “...effort to set it onto reliable, academ-
ic, practical grounds.” Ackerman and Cohen, “Proportional Systems in the History of Architecture,”
Chapter 25 herein, page 513.
See Robin Evans’s analysis of the perceived shift in the locus of geometrical innovation from archi-
114
tecture to engineering, where it has remained until very recently. Evans, The Projective Cast.
Thus in their survey of recent developments in the use of mathematics in architecture, Jane Burry
115
and Mark Burry note of the projects they present: “there is a natural division between those in which
the primary mathematical constituent is an idea, and those where mathematics is first and foremost
positioned as a problem-solver. In some, the two roles are balanced or combined, and in all, the
mathematical idea or problem-solver is also instrumental in the design process and to the form of
the architectural outcome.” Burry and Burry, The New Mathematics of Architecture, 13.
Two excellent sources for sampling the great variety of attitudes and approaches to the uses of
116
geometry and mathematics in architecture today are the journals Architectural Design (London) and
the Nexus Network Journal (Turin).
51
Reprint from "Proportional Systems in the History of Architecture" - ISBN 9789087282776 - © Leiden University Press, 2018
Matthew A. Cohen
Compare Wittkower, Architectural Principles (1949) with Wittkower, “The Problem of Movement in
117
Mannerist Architecture” (1933) published in van Eck, “The Composto Ordinato,” Chapter 3, Appen-
dix, herein.
See Murray, “Plotting Gothic” Chapter 6 herein page 129.
118
On Perrault’s now well-known disagreements with Vitruvius on the matter of proportion in relation
119
to the notions of arbitrary and positive beauty, expressed in footnotes to his 1673 translation of De
architectura—comments that represent an unusual departure from his otherwise close commentar-
ies inserted for clarification purposes only—see Gerbino, François Blondel, 150-152.
References
Abrams, Meyer Howard. “Art-as-Such: The Sociology of Modern Aesthetics.” Bulletin of the American
Academy of Arts and Sciences 38 (1985): 8–33.
Ackerman, James S. “‘Ars sine scientia nihil est’: Gothic Theory of Architecture at the Cathedral of
Milan.” Art Bulletin 26 (1949): 84–111.
———. Palladio. 1949. Reprint, New York and London: Penguin, 1966.
———. Art Historian: James S. Ackerman. Interview by Joel Gardner. Art History Oral Documentation
Project, completed under the auspices of the Oral History Program, University of California,
Los Angeles, and the Getty Center for the History of Art and the Humanities, 1994.
———. “Ricordi della nona triennale, de divina proportione.” In La divina proporzione: Triennale 1951,
edited by Anna Chiara Cimoli and Fulvio Irace, 19-35. Milan: Electa, 2007.
———. “Le proporzioni nell’architettura gotica: Milano, 1400.” In La divina proporzione: Triennale
1951, edited by Anna Chiara Cimoli and Fulvio Irace, 51. Milan: Electa, 2007.
———. and John Terry. Palladio: The Architect and His Influence in America. Fogg Fine Arts Films,
Harvard University, and Centro internazionale di studi di architettura “Andrea Palladio:”
Vicenza, 1980.
Ackermann, Emma C. “The Golden Section.” The American Mathematical Monthly 2, no. 9/10 (1895):
260–264.
Alberti, Leon Battista. De re aedificatoria. Florence: Nicolaus Laurentii, 1485.
Arnheim, Rudolf. Entropy and Art: An Essay on Disorder and Order. Berkeley, Los Angeles and London:
University of California Press, 1971.
Bailey, Geoff. “1. Hunter-gatherer Behaviour in Prehistory: Problems and Perspectives.” In Hunter-
Gatherer Economy in Prehistory: A European Perspective, edited by Geoff Bailey, 1-6. Cambridge:
Cambridge University Press, 1983.
Bairati, Cesare. La simmetria dinamica: Scienze ed arte nell’architettura classica. Milan: Tamburini,
1952.
Benevolo, Leonardo, Stefano Chieffi and Giulio Mezzetti. “Indagine sul S. Spirito di Brunelleschi.”
Quaderni dell’istituto di storia dell’architettura 15 (1968): 1–52.
Billings, Robert William. An Attempt to Define the Geometric Proportions of Gothic Architecture, as
Illustrated by the Cathedrals of Carlisle and Worcester. London: Boone, 1840.
Blondel, François. Cours d’architecture enseigné dans l’Académie royale d’architecture. 5 vols. Paris:
Auboin and Clouzier, 1675–1683.
Borissavliévitch, Miloutine. La science de l’harmonie architecturale. Paris: Fischbacher, 1925.
———. Le nombre d’or et l’esthétique scientifique de l’architecture. Preface by Louis Hautecœur. Paris:
for the author, 1952.
Borsi, Franco. Per una storia della teoria delle proporzioni. Florence: Centro Stampa della Cooperativa
Libraria Universitatis Studii Florentini, 1967.
Burke, Edmund. A Philosophical Enquiry into the Origin of our Idea of the Sublime and Beautiful.
Edited by James T. Boulton. London: Routledge and Kegan Paul, 1958. First published 1757
by R. and J. Dodsley (London).
Burry, Jane and Mark Burry. The New Mathematics of Architecture. New York: Thames and Hudson,
2010.
52
Reprint from "Proportional Systems in the History of Architecture" - ISBN 9789087282776 - © Leiden University Press, 2018
Two Kinds of Proportion
Cimoli, Anna Chiara and Fulvio Irace. La divina proporzione: Triennale 1951. Milan: Electa, 2007.
Clark, Kenneth. “Humanism and Architecture.” Architectural Review 109 (1951): 65–69.
Cohan, Steven and Linda M. Shires. Telling Stories: A Theoretical Analysis of Narrative Fiction. New
York and London: Routledge, 1988.
Cohen, Matthew A. “How Much Brunelleschi? A Late Medieval Proportional System in the Basilica of
San Lorenzo in Florence.” Journal of the Society of Architectural Historians 67 (2008): 18–57.
———. “The Lombard Connection: Northern Influences in the Basilicas of San Lorenzo and Santo
Spirito in Florence.” Annali di architettura 21 (2009): 31–44.
———. “Quantification and the Medieval Mind: An Imperfect Proportional System in the Basilica of
Santa Maria del Fiore in Florence.” In Some degree of Happiness: Studi di storia dell’architettura
in onore di Howard Burns, edited by Maria Beltramini and Caroline Elam, 1-30. Pisa: Edizioni
della Normale, 2010.
———. Beyond Beauty: Reexamining Architectural Proportion Through the Basilicas of San Lorenzo
and Santo Spirito in Florence. Venice: Marsilio, 2013.
Crosby, Alfred W. The Measure of Reality: Quantification and Western Society, 1250–1600. Cambridge:
Cambridge University Press, 1997.
da Sangallo, Giuliano. Il libro di Giuliano da Sangallo: Codice Vaticano Barberiniano Latino 4424.
Introduction and notes by Christian Huelsen. 2 vols. Vatican City: Biblioteca Apostolica
Vaticana, 1984.
———. Taccuino senese. Biblioteca Comunale, Siena, n.d.
da Vignola, Giacomo Barozzi. Regola delli cinque ordini d’architettura. Rome: Camera Apostolica for
Vignola, 1562.
Daston, Lorraine and Peter Galison. Objectivity. New York: Zone Books, 2007.
de Honnecourt, Villard. The Sketchbook of Villard de Honnecourt. Edited by Theodore Bowie.
Bloomington and London: Indiana University Press, 1959.
de Jong, Sigrid. “Staging Ruins: Paestum and Theatricality.” Art History 33, no. 2 (2010): 334–351.
des Corats, André Fournier. La proportion égyptienne et les rapports de divine harmonie. Paris: Véga,
1957.
Deuxième Congrès International d’Esthétique et de Science de l’Art. 2 vols. Paris: Alcan, 1937.
Di Dio, Cinzia, Emiliano Macaluso and Giacomo Rizzolatti. “The Golden Beauty: Brain Response
to Classical and Renaissance Sculptures.” PLoS ONE 2, no. 11 (2007): e1201. https://doi.
org/10.1371/journal.pone.0001201.
Doczi, Gyorgy. The Power of Limits: Proportional Harmonies in Nature, Art and Architecture. Boston
and London: Shambhala, 1985.
Durand, Jean-Nicolas-Louis. Précis des leçons d’architecture. Paris: Durand, 1802–1805.
Evans, Robin. The Projective Cast: Architecture and its Three Geometries. Cambridge, MA and London:
MIT Press, 1995.
Faidy, Diana. “Executive Director’s note.” The Society of the Golden Section Newsletter 1, no. 1
(November 1975): 1.
Fernie, Eric. “A Beginner’s Guide to the Study of Gothic Architectural Proportions and Systems of Length.”
In Medieval Architecture and its Intellectual Context: Studies in Honour of Peter Kidson, edited
by Eric Fernie and Paul Crossley, 229-237. London and Ronceverte: Hambledon Press, 1990.
Fischler, Roger. “How to Find the ‘Golden Number’ Without Really Trying.” Fibonacci Quarterly 19
(1981): 406–410.
Flanigan, Theresa. “The Ponte Vecchio and the Art of Urban Planning in Late Medieval Florence.”
Gesta 47 (2008): 1-15.
Friedman, David. Florentine New Towns: Urban Design in the Late Middle Ages. Cambridge,
Massachusetts and London: The MIT Press, 1989.
Frings, Marcus. “The Golden Section in Architectural Theory.” The Nexus Network Journal 4 (2002): 9–32.
Funck-Hellet, Charles. De la proportion: L’équerre des maîtres d’œuvre. Paris: Vincent, Fréal &
Compagnie, 1951.
53
Reprint from "Proportional Systems in the History of Architecture" - ISBN 9789087282776 - © Leiden University Press, 2018
Matthew A. Cohen
Garbett, Edward Lacy. Rudimentary Treatise on the Principles of Design in Architecture. London: Virtue
& Co., 1867.
Gardner, Robert W. The Parthenon: Its Science of Forms. New York: New York University Press, 1925.
Gerbino, Anthony. François Blondel: Architecture, Erudition, and the Scientific Revolution. London and
New York: Routledge, 2010.
Giedion, Sigfried. “Il tutto e la parte nell’architettura contemporanea.” In La divina proporzione:
Triennale 1951, edited by Anna Chiara Cimoli and Fulvio Irace, 68-76. Milan: Electa, 2007.
Glassman, Gary, author and producer. Secrets of the Parthenon. Public Broadcasting Service (PBS),
Nova series, WGBH Educational Foundation. January 29, 2008.
Graf, Hermann. Bibliographie zum Problem der Proportionen: Literatur über Proportionen, Mass und
Zahl in Architektur, Bildender Kunst und Natur. Speyer: Pfälzische Landesbibliothek, 1958.
Gwilt, Joseph. The Encyclopedia of Architecture. With contributions on architectural proportion by
Edward Cresy. London: Longmans, Green, and Co., 1867.
Hagenmaier, Otto. Der Goldene Schnitt: Ein Harmoniegesetz und seine Anwendung. Ulm Donau:
Tapper, 1949.
Hambidge, Jay. The Elements of Dynamic Symmetry. New York: Brentano, 1926. Reprint, New York:
Dover, 1967.
Harrison, Charles, Paul Wood and Jason Gaiger. Art in Theory: 1648–1815. Malden, Massachusetts:
Blackwell, 2000.
Henszlmann, Émeric. Théorie des proportions appliquées dans l’architecture: depuis la XIIe dynastie e
des rois égyptiens jusqu’au XVIe siècle. Paris: Bertrand, 1860.
Herrmann, Wolfgang. The Theory of Claude Perrault. London: A. Zwemmer, 1973.
Herz-Fischler, Roger. A Mathematical History of the Golden Number. Mineola, New York: Dover
Publications, 1987.
Hicks, John. “Sensus Communis: On the Possibility of Dissent in Kant’s ‘Universal Assent.’” Diacritics
40, no. 4 (2012): 106–129.
Huppert, Ann C. “Practical Mathematics in the Drawings of Baldassarre Peruzzi and Antonio da
Sangallo the Younger.” In Geometrical Objects: Architecture and Mathematical Sciences
1400–1800, edited by Anthony Gerbino, 79-106. Dordrecht: Springer, 2014.
Hurwit, Jeffrey M. The Acropolis in the Age of Pericles, Cambridge and New York: Cambridge
University Press, 2004.
“Il Primo Convegno Internazionale sulle Proporzioni nelle Arti.” Atti e rassegna tecnica della società
degli ingegneri e degli architetti in Torino, n.s. 6, no. 4 (1952): 119–135.
Irace, Fulvio. “La difficile proporzione.” In La divina proporzione: Triennale 1951, edited by Anna
Chiara Cimoli and Fulvio Irace, 12-17. Milan: Electa, 2007.
“Jeunes Peintres ne vous frappez pas!” Numéro spécial consacré à l’Exposition de la ‘Section d’Or’. La
section d’or 1:1 (October 9, 1912): 1–2.
Jouven, Georges. Rythme et architecture: les tracés harmoniques. Paris: Éditions Vincent, Fréal &
Companie, 1951.
Kant, Immanuel. Kant’s Critique of Judgment. Translated, and with an introduction and notes, by J. H.
Bernard. London: Macmillan, 1914. (Original edition: Critik der Urtheilskraft. Berlin and Libau:
Lagarde und Friederich, 1790).
Kubler, George. “A Late Gothic Computation of Rib Vault Thrusts.” Gazette des Beaux Arts 26 (1944):
135–148.
Kuhn, Thomas S. The Structure of Scientific Revolutions. Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1962.
———. The Structure of Scientific Revolutions. 2nd ed. Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1970.
Langfeld, Herbert S. The Aesthetic Attitude. New York: Harcourt Brace, 1920.
Laurent, Christophe. “Quand Auguste Perret définissait l’architecture moderne au XXe siècle.” Revue
de l’art 121 (1998): 61–78.
Le Clerc, Sébastien. Traité d’architecture, avec des remarques et des observations tres utiles pour les
jeuns gens qui veulent s’appliquer à ce bel art. Paris: Giffart, 1714.
54
Reprint from "Proportional Systems in the History of Architecture" - ISBN 9789087282776 - © Leiden University Press, 2018
Two Kinds of Proportion
———. A Treatise of Architecture, with remarks and observations necessary for young people, who
wou’d apply themselves to that noble art. Trans. Ephraim Chambers. 2 vols. London: Taylor,
Innys, Senex, and Osborne, 1723–1724.
Le Corbusier. Le Modulor: Essai sur une mesure harmonique à l’échelle humaine, applicable
universellement à l’architecture et à la mécanique. Boulogne: Éditions de l’Architecture
d’aujourd’hui, 1950.
Lebrun, Louis. Théorie de l’architecture grecque et romaine, déduite de l’analise des monuments
antiques. Paris: Joubert, 1807.
———. “Applications du principe de stabilité et des proportions à l’architecture, ou suite des
développements des raisons de cette science.” Annales de l’architecture et des arts (1809):
205–227.
Loach, Judi. “Le Corbusier and the Creative Use of Mathematics.” British Journal for the History of
Science 31 (1998): 185–215.
Loerke, William C. “A Rereading of the Interior Elevation of Hadrian’s Rotunda.” Journal of the Society
of Architectural Historians 49 (1990): 22-43.
MacDonald, William L. The Pantheon: Design, Meaning, and Progeny. Cambridge, MA: Harvard
University Press, 1976.
Mainstone, Rowland J. “Structural Theory and Design Before 1742.” Architectural Review 143 (1968):
303–310.
Manetti, Antonio. Vita di Filippo Brunelleschi. Edited by Giuliano Tanturli. Milan: Il Polifilo, 1976.
Marder, Tod A. “Bernini and Alexander VII: Criticism and Praise of the Pantheon in the Seventeenth
Century.” Art Bulletin 71 (1989): 628-645.
———. “The Pantheon After Antiquity.” In The Pantheon in Rome: Contributions to the Conference,
Bern, November 9-12, 2006, edited by Gerd Grasshoff, Michael Heinzelmann and Marcus
Wafler, 145-153. Bern: Universität Bern, Wissenschaftstheorie und Wissenschaftsgeschichte,
2009.
———. “The Pantheon in the Seventeenth Century.” In The Pantheon: From Antiquity to the Present,
edited by Tod A. Marder and Mark Wilson Jones, 296-329. New York: Cambridge University
Press, 2015.
Marquand, Allan. “A Study in Greek Architectural Proportions: The Temple of Selinous.” American
Journal of Archaeology 9 (1894): 521–532.
Mattei, Francesca. “Geometria e struttura: Rudolf Wittkower, i principi architettonici dell’età
dell’umanesimo, il dibattito sulle proporzioni in Europa e negli Stati Uniti (1949–1975).”
Schifanoia: Notizie dell’Istituto di studi rinascimentali di Ferrara 42/43 (2013): 257–269.
Matteoni, Dario. “Modulor.” In Le Corbusier: synthèse des arts. Aspekte des Spätwerks, 1945–1965,
edited by Andreas Vowinckel and Thomas Kesseler, 17-31. Berlin: Ernst & Sohn, 1986.
Mitrović, Branko. Serene Greed of the Eye: Leon Battista Alberti and the Philosophical Foundations of
Renaissance Architectural Theory. Munich and Berlin: Deutscher Kunstverlag, 2005.
Monod, Paul Kleber. Solomon’s Secret Arts: The Occult in the Age of the Enlightenment. New Haven
and London: Yale University Press, 2013.
Morris, Robert. Lectures on Architecture: Consisting of Rules Founded upon Harmonick and
Arithmetical Proportions in Building. 2 vols. London: Brindley, 1734–1736.
Mpofu, Senzeni. “Debunking Science: fMRI: A Not So Reliable Mind-Reader.” Yale Scientific Magazine,
April 11, 2014. Accessed May 21, 2016. http://www.yalescientific.org/2014/04/debunking-
science-fmri-a-not-so-reliable-mind-reader/.
Mueller, John T. Review of Deuxième congrès international d’esthétique et de science de l’art. American
Journal of Sociology 45, no. 1 (1939): 153.
Murray, Stephen. Notre Dame, Cathedral of Amiens: The Power of Change in Gothic. Cambridge:
Cambridge University Press, 1996.
———. “Narrating Gothic: The Cathedral Plot.” In Gothic Art and Thought in The Later Medieval Period:
Essays in Honor of Willibald Sauerländer, edited by Colum Hourihane, 55–63. University Park:
Pennsylvania State University Press, 2011.
55
Reprint from "Proportional Systems in the History of Architecture" - ISBN 9789087282776 - © Leiden University Press, 2018
Matthew A. Cohen
Padovan, Richard. Proportion: Science, Philosophy, Architecture. London and New York: Spon Press,
1999.
Palladio, Andrea. I quattro libri dell’architettura. Venice: Dominico de’ Franceschi, 1570.
———. Scritti sull’Architettura (1554–1579). Edited by Lionello Puppi. Venice: Neri Pozza, 1988.
Panofsky, Erwin. “The History of the Theory of Human Proportions as a Reflection of the History of
Styles.” In Meaning in the Visual Arts, 55-107. Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1955.
Originally published as “Die Entwicklung der Proportionslehre als Abbild der Stilentwicklung.”
In Monatshefte für Kunstwissenschaft 14 (1921): 188-219.
Payne, Alina A. “Rudolf Wittkower and Architectural Principles in the Age of Modernism.” Journal of
the Society of Architectural Historians 53 (1994): 322–342.
———. Rudolf Wittkower. Trans. F. Peri. Turin: Bollati Boringhieri, 2011.
Pennethorne, John. The Geometry and Optics of Ancient Architecture: Illustrated by Examples from
Thebes, Athens, and Rome. London and Edinburgh: Williams and Norgate, 1878.
———. The Geometry and Optics of Ancient Architecture. London and Edinburgh: Williams and
Norgate, 1878.
Penrose, Francis C. An Investigation of the Principles of Athenian Architecture. London: Nicol, 1851.
Pérez-Gómez, Alberto. Architecture and the Crisis of Modern Science. Cambridge, Massachusetts and
London: MIT Press, 1983.
Perrault, Claude. Les dix livres d’architecture de Vitruve. Corrigez et traduits nouvellement en François,
avec des Notes & des Figures. Paris: J.-B. Coignard, 1673.
———. Ordonnance des cinq espèces de colonnes selon la méthode des anciens. Paris: Coignard,
1683.
———. Les dix livres d’architecture de Vitruve corrigez et traduits nouvellement en François, avec des
Notes et des Figures. 2nd, revised and enlarged ed. Paris: Coignard, 1684.
———. Ordonnance for the Five Kinds of Columns after the Method of the Ancients. Edited and
translated by Julia Bloomfield, Kurt W. Forster, and Thomas F. Reese, introduction by Alberto
Pérez-Gómez. Santa Monica: Getty Center for the History of Art and the Humanities, 1993.
Original edition: Perrault, 1683, above.
Pevsner, Nikolaus. “Report on a Debate of the Motion ‘that Systems of Proportion Make Good Design
Easier and Bad Design More Difficult,’ held at the RIBA on June 18, 1957. The President, Mr.
Kenneth M. B. Cross, in the Chair.” RIBA Journal 64, no. 11: 456–463.
———. An Outline of European Architecture. Baltimore: Penguin Books, 1957.
Picon, Antoine. Claude Perrault, 1613–1688, ou la curiosité d’un classique. Paris: Picard, 1988.
Pollali, Angeliki. “Design Method and Mathematics in Francesco di Giorgio’s Trattati.” In Visual Culture
and Mathematics in the Early Modern Period, edited by Ingrid Alexander-Skipnes, 32-51.
New York: Routledge, 2017.
Saalman, Howard. Filippo Brunelleschi: The Buildings. University Park: Pennsylvania State University
Press, 1993.
Sanpaolesi, Piero. Brunelleschi. Milan: Edizioni per il Club del Libro, 1962.
Satel, Sally and Scott O. Lilienfeld. Brainwashed: The Seductive Appeal of Mindless Neuroscience.
New York: Basic Books, 2013.
Scott, Geoffrey. The Architecture of Humanism: A Study in the History of Taste. New York and London:
W.W. Norton & Company, 1974 (1914).
Shelby, Lon R., ed. and trans. Gothic Design Techniques: The Fifteenth-Century Design Booklets of
Mathes Roriczer and Hanns Schmuttermayer. Carbondale, IL: Southern Illinois University Press,
1977.
———. “The Mathematical Knowledge of Mediaeval Architects.” Journal of the Society of Architectural
Historians 30 (1971): 238.
———. “The Geometrical Knowledge of Mediaeval Master Masons.” Speculum 47 (1972): 395–421.
Tafuri, Manfredo. Interpreting the Renaissance: Princes, Cities, Architects, trans. Daniel Sherer. New
Haven and London: Yale University Press, 2006.
56
Reprint from "Proportional Systems in the History of Architecture" - ISBN 9789087282776 - © Leiden University Press, 2018
Two Kinds of Proportion
Tartarkiewicz Wladyslaw. “The Great Theory of Beauty and Its Decline.” Journal of Aesthetics and Art
Criticism 31 (1972): 165-180.
The Society of the Golden Section Newsletter. Vols. 1(2)–8(3-4). Chicago, 1975–1983. In the collection
of the Frances Loeb Library, Harvard University.
Thiersch, August. “Die Proportionen in der Architektur.” In Handbuch der Architektur, edited by Josef
Durm, e.a., vol. IV, section 1.2, 38–77. Darmstadt: Bergsträsser, 1883.
Trachtenberg, Marvin. Dominion of the Eye: Urbanism, Art, and Power in Early Modern Florence.
Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1997.
Trigger, Bruce G. “Prospects for a World Archaeology,” World Archaeology 18 (1986): 1-20.
———. A History of Archaeological Thought. 2nd ed. Cambridge and New York: Cambridge University
Press, 2006.
Van der Schoot, Albert. De ontstelling van Pythagoras: Over de geschiedenis van de goddelijke
proportie. Kampen: Kok Agora, 1998.
van Eck, Caroline A. “The Structure of De re aedificatoria Reconsidered.” Journal of the Society of
Architectural Historians 57, (1998): 280–297.
———. Classical Rhetoric and the Visual Arts in Early Modern Europe. New York: Cambridge University
Press, 2007.
Vischer, Robert. “On the Optical Sense of Form (1873).” In Empathy, Form, and Space: Problems
in German Aesthetics, 1873–1893, edited and translated by Harry Francis Mallgrave and
Eleftherios Ikonomou, 89–123. Santa Monica: Getty Center for the History of Art and the
Humanities, 1994.
Vitruvius. The Ten Books on Architecture. Trans. Morris H. Morgan. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University
Press, 1914. Reprint, New York: Dover, 1960.
von Stegmann, Carl and Heinrich von Geymüller. Filippo di Ser Brunellesco. Vol. I of Die Architektur
der Renaissance in Toskana. Munich: Bruckmann, 1885.
Wallace, Sandra, The Contradictions of Archaeological Theory: Engaging Critical Realism and
Archaeological Theory. London and New York: Routledge, 2010.
Wilson Jones, Mark. Principles of Roman Architecture. New Haven and London: Yale University Press,
2000.
Wittkower, Rudolf. Architectural Principles in the Age of Humanism. London: The Warburg Institute,
1949.
———. “International Congress on Proportion in the Arts.” Burlington Magazine 94, no. 587 (1952):
52–55.
———. Architectural Principles in the Age of Humanism. 1949. Reprint, London: Tiranti, 1952.
———. “Systems of Proportion.” Architect’s Yearbook 5 (1953): 9–18.
———. “The Changing Concept of Proportion.” Daedalus 89 (1960): 199–215.
———. Architectural Principles in the Age of Humanism. First revised ed., London: Tiranti, 1962.
———. Architectural Principles in the Age of Humanism. 1962. Reprint, New York and London: Norton,
1971.
———. “Finalità del convegno.” In La divina proporzione: Triennale 1951, edited by Anna Chiara
Cimoli and Fulvio Irace, 44-47. Milan: Electa, 2007.
———. “Alcuni aspetti della proporzione nel Medioevo e nel Rinascimento.” In La divina proporzione:
Triennale 1951, edited by Anna Chiara Cimoli and Fulvio Irace, 48-49. Milan: Electa, 2007.
Wölfflin, Heinrich. “Prolegomena to a Psychology of Architecture (1886).” In Empathy, Form, and
Space: Problems in German Aesthetics, 1873–1893, edited and translated by Harry Francis
Mallgrave and Eleftherios Ikonomou, 148-190. Santa Monica: Getty Center for the History of
Art and the Humanities, 1994.
Wurm, Heinrich. Baldassare Peruzzi: Architekturzeichnungen. Tübingen: Wasmuth, 1984.
Zeising, Adolf. Neue Lehre von den Proportionen des menschlichen Körpers. Leipzig: Rudolf Weigel,
1854.
Zorzi, Giangiorgio. Le chiese e i ponti di Andrea Palladio. Venice: Neri Pozza, 1967.
57
Reprint from "Proportional Systems in the History of Architecture" - ISBN 9789087282776 - © Leiden University Press, 2018
Proportional Systems in the History of Architecture:
A Critical Reconsideration
Edited by Matthew A. Cohen and Maarten Delbeke, 2018
Errata Corrige
Chapter 1: “Two Kinds of Proportion,” by Matthew A. Cohen
Page 48, note 65
“Hogarth, Analysis of Beauty, 1753” instead of “1953”
Page 33, sixth line from the bottom
“pure beauty” instead of “the pure beauty”
Proportional Systems
in the History
of Architecture
A Critical Reconsideration
Edited by
Matthew A. Cohen
and Maarten Delbeke
Reprint from “Proportional Systems in the History of Architecture” – ISBN 9789087282776 - © Leiden University Press, 2018
Cover design: Suzan Beijer
Cover image: Jacob Lois, Proportional System of Schielandshuis, from his manuscript Oude en
ware beschrijving van Schieland, 1672, coll. Gemeentearchief Rotterdam.
Layout: Friedemann Vervoort
ISBN 978 90 8728 277 6
e-ISBN 978 94 0060 287 8 (e-pdf)
e-ISBN 978 94 0060 288 5 (e-pub)
NUR 648
All rights reserved. Without limiting the rights under copyright reserved above, no part of this
book may be reproduced, stored in or introduced into a retrieval system, or transmitted, in any
form or by any means (electronic, mechanical, photocopying, recording or otherwise) without
the written permission of both the copyright owner and the authors of the book.
Reprint from “Proportional Systems in the History of Architecture” – ISBN 9789087282776 - © Leiden University Press, 2018
Contents
Acknowledgements 9
Part I Introduction
2
Canons of Proportion and the Laws of Nature:
Observations on a Permanent and Unresolved Conflict
Mario Curti 61
4 Subjective Proportions:
18th-Century Interpretations of Paestum’s “Disproportion”
Sigrid de Jong 91
6 Plotting Gothic:
A Paradox
Stephen Murray 129
Reprint from “Proportional Systems in the History of Architecture” – ISBN 9789087282776 - © Leiden University Press, 2018
Part III Designing with Proportion
Reprint from “Proportional Systems in the History of Architecture” – ISBN 9789087282776 - © Leiden University Press, 2018
18 Leonardo da Vinci:
The Proportions of the Drawings of Sacred Buildings in Ms. B,
Institut de France
Francesco P. Di Teodoro 381
Part VI Conclusion
Index 551
Reprint from “Proportional Systems in the History of Architecture” – ISBN 9789087282776 - © Leiden University Press, 2018
Acknowledgements
This volume first took shape as the Special Collection Objects of Belief: Proportional
Systems in the History of Architecture in the journal Architectural Histories, from 2014-
2016 (journal.eahn.org). That collection was derived from papers presented at the
conference “Proportional Systems in the History of Architecture,” held in Leiden in
March 2011 (see Chapter 1). It is amended here with new essays by Maarten Delbeke
and Mark Wilson Jones, revisions to the Introduction and Conclusion by Matthew A.
Cohen, and various minor corrections and modifications by the other contributors. The
reference system and bibliography have been adapted to the requirements of Leiden
University Press.
Financial assistance for this project has been provided by: Leiden University, Faculty
of Humanities; Washington State University, School of Design and Construction; and
Maarten Delbeke, as principal investigator of the research project “The Quest for the
Legitimacy of Architecture 1750–1850,” funded by a VIDI grant from the Dutch Science
Foundation (N.W.O.), 2011, and as Chair for the History and Theory of Architecture, gta
(Institute for the History and Theory of Architecture), ETH Zürich, 2018.
The editors thank Stefano Guiducci, Haley Ladenburg and Desirée Noser for their
assistance with the final preparation of this volume.
Reprint from “Proportional Systems in the History of Architecture” – ISBN 9789087282776 - © Leiden University Press, 2018
Part I
Introduction
Reprint from “Proportional Systems in the History of Architecture” – ISBN 9789087282776 - © Leiden University Press, 2018