Bakhurst, Shanker - 2001 - Jerome Bruner Culture Language and Self
Bakhurst, Shanker - 2001 - Jerome Bruner Culture Language and Self
On Being Moved
From Mirror Neurons to Empathy
Advances in Consciousness Research
Editor
Maxim I. Stamenov
Bulgarian Academy of Sciences
Editorial Board
David Chalmers Steven Macknik
Australian National University Barrow Neurological Institute
Gordon G. Globus George Mandler
University of California at Irvine University of California at San Diego
Ray Jackendoff Susana Martinez-Conde
Brandeis University Barrow Neurological Institute
Christof Koch John R. Searle
California Institute of Technology University of California at Berkeley
Stephen Kosslyn Petra Stoerig
Harvard University Universität Düsseldorf
Earl Mac Cormac
Duke University
Volume 68
On Being Moved: From Mirror Neurons to Empathy
Edited by Stein Bråten
On Being Moved
From Mirror Neurons to Empathy
Edited by
Stein Bråten
University of Oslo
QP363.5O5 2007
612.8--dc22 2006047978
isbn 978 90 272 5204 3 (Hb; alk. paper)
Table of contents
Contributors ix
Introduction 1
chapter 1
Prologue: From infant intersubjectivity and participant movements
to simulation and conversation in cultural common sense 21
Stein Bråten and Colwyn Trevarthen
chapter 2
Applying developmental and neuroscience findings on other-centred
participation to the process of change in psychotherapy 35
Daniel N. Stern
chapter 3
The ‘Russian doll’ model of empathy and imitation 49
Frans B. M. de Waal
chapter 4
Mirror neurons and intersubjectivity 73
Pier Francesco Ferrari and Vittorio Gallese
chapter 5
Human mirroring systems: On assessing mind by reading brain
and body during social interaction 89
Riitta Hari
JB[v.20020404] Prn:21/03/2007; 16:00 F: AICR68CO.tex / p.2 (116-164)
Table of contents
chapter 6
Cues on the origin of language: From electrophysiological data
on mirror neurons and motor representations 101
Luciano Fadiga and Laila Craighero
chapter 7
Altercentric infants and adults: On the origins and manifestations
of participant perception of others’ acts and utterances 111
Stein Bråten
chapter 8
From speech to gene: The KE family and the FOXP2 137
Faraneh Vargha-Khadem and Frédérique Liégeois
chapter 9
Intersubjectivity before language: Three windows on preverbal sharing 149
Andrew N. Meltzoff and Rechele Brooks
chapter 10
Early speech perception: Developing a culturally specific way
of listening through social interaction 175
Barbara T. Conboy and Patricia K. Kuhl
chapter 11
On theories of dialogue, self and society: Redefining socialization
and the acquisition of meaning in light of the intersubjective matrix 201
Ivar Frönes
chapter 12
The intersubjectivity of imagination: The special case of imaginary
companions 219
Stathis Papastathopoulos and Giannis Kugiumutzakis
chapter 13
When empathic care is obstructed: Excluding the child from the zone
of intimacy 237
Karsten Hundeide
JB[v.20020404] Prn:21/03/2007; 16:00 F: AICR68CO.tex / p.3 (164-197)
chapter 14
Family disseminate archives: Intergenerational transmission
and psychotherapy in light of Bråten’s and Stern’s theories 257
Andrea Cabassi
chapter 15
Reaching moments of shared experiences through musical
improvisation: An aesthetic view on interplay between a musician
and severely disabled or congenital deafblind children 269
Birgit Kirkebaek
chapter 16
To sing and dance together: From infants to jazz 281
Ben Schögler and Colwyn Trevarthen
chapter 17
On circular re-enactment of care and abuse, and on other-centred
moments in psychotherapy: Closing comments 303
Stein Bråten
Contributors
Contributors
Introduction
Introduction
Present Moment in Psychotherapy and Everyday Life in which he lays out in Chapter
5 what he terms ‘The intersubjective matrix’ with reference to recent developmen-
tal and neuroscience findings that invite a revolution in our understanding of the
roots, nature, and implications of intersubjectivity.
A paradigmatic revolution
The intersubjective matrix entails inter alia two radical turnabouts. First, no longer
can be upheld as valid Cartesian and Leibnizian assumptions about monadic sub-
jects and disembodied and self-centred minds without windows to each other
except as mediated by constructed or symbolic representations. Modes of partic-
ipant perception have been identified entailing co-movements with others in felt
immediacy, supplementing perception of others in re-presentational mediacy. Sec-
ond, no longer can be retained the Piagetian attribution of infant egocentricity as a
point of departure for children’s language acquisition and cognitive development.
In the last decades some of the story of human infancy has been re-written, as
it were, replacing earlier theoretical views of infants as a-social and ego-centric
with a new understanding of infant capacity from the outset for interpersonal
communion and learning by altercentric participation.
The first turnabout is partly consistent with what G. H. Mead (1934) empha-
sized when he refused to the take as a point of departure the monad locked in a cell,
and insisted on the priority of the interpersonal. In his posthumous book on Mind,
Self, and Society, he offers a seminal account of the emergence of preverbal and
symbolic intersubjectivity albeit, like J. M. Baldwin (1891) before him, he was not
open to the possibility of imitation in the first months of life. The second radical
turn was announced 45 years later, when Colwyn Trevarthen (1979) puts forward
a description of ‘primary intersubjectivity’ in human infants, which at first was
ignored or contested. Later, pointing out that the human infant’s anticipatory cere-
bral system is prepared for direct perception of the variety of sounds, gestures, and
movements that humans afford, he defined ‘alteroception’, in analogue to propri-
oception, as direct perception of the other’s motivated act (Trevarthen 1986). By
now, in line with his definitions, replacing the previous attribution of egocentric-
ity made in Piagetian theories of child development and acquisition of language,
infant altercentricity or other-centred participation has been identified (Bråten
1998; Stern 2000/2003: xi–xxxix, 2004; Trevarthen et al. 1998). Already in 1985, in
his seminal The Interpersonal World of the Infant, Daniel Stern had emphasized the
infant in interpersonal communion, and introduced his radical multi-layer model
of the four senses of self (and other). This he modifies in an even more radical
direction in the new introduction to the paperback version in the light of new
findings:
JB[v.20020404] Prn:7/03/2007; 16:52 F: AICR68IN.tex / p.3 (170-248)
Introduction
evidence for the presence of mirror neurons and adaptive oscillators along with
the deepening literature on early imitation suggest that probably from the begin-
ning of life, infants have the capacity for what Bråten (1998) terms altero-centric
participation or what Trevarthen (1979) has long called primary intersubjectivity.
(Stern 2000: xx)
The above are some of the keywords for findings and capacities subsumed in terms
of ‘the Intersubjectivity Matrix’ implying a paradigmatic revolution.
Thus, as stressed also in the beginning of the prologue to this volume, the story
of human infancy has been rewritten in the last decades, replacing earlier theo-
retical views of the infant as a-social and ego-centric with a new understanding
of infant capacities for interpersonal communion and altercentricity. In their pro-
logue, Bråten and Trevarthen (this volume (1)) distinguish these three layers of
intersubjectivity remaining operative throughout normal life (Figure 1).
Introduction
Introduction
Introduction
The same year that the proceedings of the first Theory Forum symposium were
published, portraying the original macaque experiment (Bråten (Ed.) 1998: 122,
similar to the top illustration in Fig. 2), Rizzolatti and Arbib (1998) published
their seminal paper “Language within our grasp”, identifying indirect evidence of
a mirror neuron system in the human brain and relating inter alia to Liberman’s
motor theory of speech perception. That had been partly anticipated (in a Centre
of Advanced Study lecture in the Norwegian Academy the preceding year) by this
prediction:
. . . if by way of experimental procedures the neural basis supporting egocentric
perception and the neural basis sensitized to support allocentric perception are
uncovered in humans, then I would expect that neural systems, perhaps even neu-
rons, sensitized to realize altercentric perception will be uncovered in experiments
designed to test and disconfirm this expectation. (Bråten 1997, 1998: 122–123)
Now, while no studies entailing recording of single neurons, can or have been done
on humans, all the indirect neurophysiological evidence afforded (reported and
examined inter alia by Rizzolatti et al. 2002: 37–59; cf. also contributions by Ferrari
and Gallese, by Hari, and by Fadiga and Craighero (this volume (4–6)), indicates
that an adapted and sensitized mirror neuron system is the most likely candidate
for partial neurosocial support of intersubjective attunement in humans, including
participant perception.
Ferrari and Gallese (this volume (4)) present monkey data on grasping and
holding neurons, lip-smacking neurons, and lips protrusion neurons. Examining
the potential of the mirror neuron system for actions in humans, they compare be-
havioural studies on synchrony and imitation in human and nonhuman primates,
and addresses questions concerning primary and secondary intersubjectivity re-
JB[v.20020404] Prn:7/03/2007; 16:52 F: AICR68IN.tex / p.7 (382-444)
Introduction
lated to the mirror neuron system. Their pointed question concerns which neural
mechanisms that may underpin our capacity to capture others’ living experiences
just by watching them, a construction built up in order to respond and re-act
very early in life, such as attested by documentation of infant intersubjectivity
and alter-centred participation. Ferrari and Gallese posit that the mirror neuron
system, together with other mirroring neural clusters outside the motor domain,
constitute the functional mechanism at the basis of intersubjectivity, and which
they consider to entail embodied simulation. By that they mean an automatic,
unwitting and pre-reflective functional mechanism, the function of which is to
model objects, agents, and events. By means of such embodied simulation we are
intentionally attuned to others.
The phylogenetic gap between advanced tertiary intersubjective capacities for
simulation of mind and the mirror neurons discharge in macaques is of course
huge, even though a partial basis for participant perception are afforded by the
impressive capacity for mirror neurons discharge in the macaque upon sight of
another’s grasping act and upon own execution of a similar grasping act (Fig. 2
(top)). In the ventral premotor cortex of the monkey (area F5) there are neurons
that discharge both when the monkey performs a specific hand action and when
it observes an individual making a similar action. The strength of mirror neurons
discharge even varies with the action context in which the perceived grasp act is
embedded; there is a stronger discharge when the food is seen to be grasped and
put in the mouth, than when it is seen to be grasped and put in a bucket (Fogassi
et al. 2005: 662). And then, in connection with a seminar of mine at the Human
Physiology Institute in Parma, Vittorio Gallese showed me the design with a screen
which hides from the sight of the monkey the endpoint of the experimenter’s hand
grasping the object, allowing only the beginning of the reaching and grasping act
to be visible. And yet, even that evokes mirror neurons discharge. This supports
the point made by Ferrari and Gallese on embodied simulation. Is is not only
a demonstration of the activation of mirror neurons upon observation of parts
of another’s partly hidden act, but an indication of the macaque’s being able to
rudimentary simulate the completion of that partly hidden target-oriented act.
This may be seen to resemble the kind of simulated completion, albeit at a higher
layer of intersubjectivity, that the 18-month old toddlers are doing when exposed
to the experimenter who fails to pull the dumbbell apart in Meltzoff ’s behavioural
re-enactment design (cf. Meltzoff & Brooks this volume (9)).
In the proceedings of the Hanse Institute symposium, Stamenov (2002: 249–
271), with a view upon prerequisites for linguistic competence, questions attempts
to account for “higher cognitive capacities of humans” with reference to the mirror
neuron discovery (cf. also Stamenov & Gallese 2002: 7) because even though they
have access to mirror neurons, macaques cannot engage in language, or simulate
another’s mind. True, not only are such higher-order modes of intersubjectivity
JB[v.20020404] Prn:7/03/2007; 16:52 F: AICR68IN.tex / p.8 (444-471)
Introduction
beyond their capacities; there are limitations even in bodily capacities for recipro-
cal resonance and co-movements in the mutual sense of primary intersubjective
attunement. While the macaque is able to resonate with grasping (like in Fig. 2
(top)), it is likely to be unable to resonate with an act of giving, since it cannot do
what is done by the chimpanzee (Fig. 2 (middle)), who in turn is unable to partic-
ipate in the kind of face-to-face exchange that is demonstrated by the 11-month
old in Fig. 2 (bottom), because that would have required a frame of reference shift
in such a face-to-face situation (cf. the contributions by Bråten, and by Billard
& Arbib in Stamenov & Gallese (Eds.) 2002: 273–294, 343–352). Such a mirror
reversal is returned to by Bråten, this volume (7). Still, we may say that expo-
sure to a manual reaching act, or even to mouth grasping act, such as reported
by Ferrari and Gallese, evokes in the macaque a unilateral mode of internal reso-
nance that partly matches that target-oriented act, manifested by the discharge of
the same pre-motor neurons that are activated upon own execution of that uni-
lateral target act. And then, when an object is grasped and then eaten, there is a
stronger discharge than when an object is grasped and then thrown in a bucket.
Even though this is an unilateral target oriented acts, not embedded in bilateral
give-and-take interactions (such as specified for human by Bråten 2002: 290n.),
such experiments demonstrate a primate basis for the kind of phylogenetic adap-
tation of mirror neurons systems that may afford part of the neurosocial support
of participant perception in human, even infants (cf. also Bråten & Gallese 2004).
Reporting from her experimental studies with her co-workers on human mir-
roring systems related to the mirror neurons discovery, Riitta Hari (this volume
(5)) raises questions inter alia about the potential support of predictions and
attribution of goals in social interaction, such as predicting another’s doing or
saying – predicting the opponent’s move in sport, or completing the speaker who
has difficulties in finding the right words, neither of which deserves the term ‘true
imitation’. (Detailed examples of such participant predictions are given in Chap-
ter 7 (this volume) in terms of other-centred participation). While pointing out
that true imitation is likely to require action understanding and to entail learn-
ing of new motor actions, Hari distinguishes true imitation from mere release of
stereotypic motor patterns, and from facilitation of actions that are already in the
observer’s motor repertoire, e.g. in spectators watching an athletic performance.
For mirroring systems studies of the brain basis for social cognition and dynamic
interaction, Hari emphasizes the combination of the temporal accuracy of mag-
netoencephalographic (MEG) recordings with the fine resolution of magnetic
resonance imaging (fMRI). One of the MEG studies reported from was applied
to hand movements; when the subject stretched the right arm and hand towards
a manipulandum, ending the movement with a pinch of the tip, and when an
on-line similar movement was observed, both Broca’s region and the primary mo-
JB[v.20020404] Prn:7/03/2007; 16:52 F: AICR68IN.tex / p.9 (471-542)
Introduction
tor cortex were activated during both hand movement execution and observation,
satisfying one of the criteria for motor mirror neurons being involved.
Broca’s area also relates to speech activation. As for the key question about how
the mirror neurons discovery may relate to our understanding of the emergence
and acquisition of language, Fadiga and Craighero (this volume (6)) afford cues to
the origin of language based on electrophysiological data on mirror neurons and
motor representations. They inter alia report Transcranial Magnetic Stimulation
(TMS) data on how a system in humans motorically ‘resonates’ when they listen to
speech. Their current research is aimed at investigating if and how, during speech
listening, tongue motor representations are activated in the listener as expression
of an acoustically evoked motor resonance, and as to whether such activation has a
role in the perception of speech. According to Liberman’s motor theory of speech
perception, speech is perceived by matching articulatory gestures, embedded in
listened words, on the listener’s motor repertoire, entailing that perception and
production of speech use a common repertoire of motor primitives represented in
the brain as invariant motor commands. Recently this theory has been indirectly
supported by a series of neurophysiological data. Brain imaging studies and elec-
trophysiological investigations of motor cortex excitability show that in humans
the observation of motor actions activates the motor circuits involved in the gen-
eration of the seen movements. Among active areas, the presence of Broca’s region
suggests a possible evolutionary pathway linking hand action related mirror sys-
tem to the birth of spoken language. Fadiga and Craighero point to the homology
between this newly discovered visuo-motor mechanism and the acoustic/motor
matching postulated by the motor theory of speech perception, opening fruitful
windows.
The issue of the phylogenetic origin, as well as manifestations in ontogeny of
participant perception by infant learners and adult listeners, is pursued by Bråten
(this volume (7)). He offers a number of illustrations of how other-centred partici-
pation is manifested by preverbal infants and verbal children and adults alike. Like
adult feeders, for example, who open their mouth when offering the food to the
mouth of the infant or patient their are feeding, when infants reciprocate spoon-
feeding, which they can do in the 11th month of their life, they manifest with their
mouth movements their participation in the other’s intake of the food as if they
were taking part in the eating from the other’s centre, as it were. In contrast to the
Piagetian attribution of an egocentric point of departure for children’s develop-
ment of language, requiring decentration in ontogeny as the child matures, Bråten
advances the hypothesis that the mirror neuron system has been decentred in ho-
minin phylogeny to allow for infant listening and learning by (m)other-centred
participation to cope and take care. In ontogeny, this altercentric capacity for pre-
verbal learning by virtual other participation announces verbal conversation to
come with its reciprocal, participant, and simulational characteristics.
JB[v.20020404] Prn:7/03/2007; 16:52 F: AICR68IN.tex / p.10 (542-573)
Introduction
Introduction
Introduction
This is one of the defining characteristics of what Stern (this volume (2)) terms
a “moment of meeting”, contributing to a qualitative leap in a relationship that
has suffered a mini-crisis. Such a moment of meeting entails “a moment of mu-
tual other-centred participation in which both partners create and undergo a joint
JB[v.20020404] Prn:7/03/2007; 16:52 F: AICR68IN.tex / p.13 (678-732)
Introduction
Introduction
focuses on the pedagogical significance for special education of the new infant
paradigm and of a more open biological orientation. This approach is carried
out in various Danish projects involving severely disabled and/or deaf blind chil-
dren, seeking to establish common experience through improvisation between the
child and a musician. She emphasizes that the findings, by Colwyn Trevarthen and
other researchers, of a connective link between music and communication offers
a promise of helping many children with severe disabilities, afforded behaviour-
oriented training strategies. This is because an aesthetic approach entails that all
expressions be seen and taken seriously.
Thus, Kirkebaek’s intervention approach is inter alia influence by the em-
phasis on musical movements, which Benjaman Schögler pursues with Colwyn
Trevarthen (this volume (16), in their contribution on infants’ voices and jazz,
on singing and dancing together. They are concerned with simple acts of mu-
sicality – the expressive movements of music, their perception, and their power
to create, communicate and consolidate narratives of meaning in human worlds.
They point out how spontaneous musical expression is created and appreciated in
mother-infant play, and give several beautiful examples of the inherent musical-
ity in early protoconversation. They further report the results of musical acoustic
analysis of vocal records, interpreting the findings in terms of communicative mu-
sicality and co-movements. Their basic paradigm for the movement music cycle is
illustrated by a concluding illustration of how a gesture or feeling is translated from
the score to the mind of the player who brings forth the music and to the body of
a dancer. Their leading question is this: There is something measurable in the pat-
terns of communicative flow and expressive behaviour of music and dance that
is measurable – what is it and how is it shared and translated between artists? In
an experiment set up for singing and gesturing, they report the results in terms of
graphs showing the correspondence between recording, with movement in pitch,
and corresponding hand movements. Thereby, they examine how improvisations
of a single musical narrative, with coherent meaning, may be produced by periodic
synchrony of the gestures of jazz players who only hear one another’s intentions
and emotions in the recorded instrumental sound.
The editor’s concluding comments closes the circle to Stern’s contribution
(this volume (2)) concerning the nature and role of the present moment in psy-
chotherapy, and to de Waal’s (this volume (3)) concern with roots of empathy.
Here is first offered an account on how occurrences of altruism by toddlers, such
as reported by Anna Freud after the second world war, may be rooted in other-
centred participation. Then, the question is raised about why abused children may
become abusive towards peers and, later, towards younger victims. Finally, cer-
tain critical elements in patient-therapist conversations are commented upon and
related to Stern’s distinctions and to the three layers of intersubjectivity, distin-
JB[v.20020404] Prn:7/03/2007; 16:52 F: AICR68IN.tex / p.15 (773-816)
Introduction
guished in the prologue (this volume (1)), and in the chapter concluding the first
Theory Forum proceedings (Bråten (Ed.) 1998: 272–382).
In that collective volume, after having referred inter alia to Damasio (1994), Di
Pellegrino et al. (1992), and Le Doux (1993), Trevarthen makes this declaration:
The brain mechanisms that represent the human body of the single subject in all
its intelligent and emotional activities and states are at the same time very ex-
tensive, of ancient linage, and greatly elaborated. The mirror system that enables
the expression of other individuals’ bodies to play a part in regulating emotion
and rational activity and learning intersubjectively, the ‘virtual other’ mechanism
(Bråten 1988a, 1994a, b, this volume) must be similarly extensive. It is interwoven
with self-consciousness, and unconscious embodiment of motives, at every level.
(Trevarthen 1998: 47)
Introduction
References
Introduction
Preston, S. D., & de Waal, F. (2002). “Empathy: Its ultimate and primate basis.” Behavioral and
Brain Sciences, 25, 1–72.
Rizzolatti, G., & Arbib, M. (1998). “Language within our grasp.” Trends in Neurosciences, 21 (5),
188–193.
Rizzolatti, G., Craighero, L., & Fadiga, L. (2002). “The mirror system in humans.” In M.
Stamenov & V. Gallese (Eds.), Mirror Neurons and the Evolution of Brain and Language
(pp. 37–59). Amsterdam/Philadelphia: John Benjamins
Stamenov, M. (2002). “Some features that make mirror neuron and human language fairly
unique.” In M. Stamenov & V. Gallese (Eds.), Mirror Neurons and the Evolution of Brain
and Language (pp. 249–271). Amsterdam/Philadelphia: John Benjamins.
Stamenov, M., & Gallese, V. (Eds.). (2002). Mirror Neurons and the Evolution of Brain and
Language. Amsterdam/Philadelphia: John Benjamins.
Stern, D. N. (1985). The Interpersonal World of the Infant. New York: Basic Books.
Stern, D. N. (2000). “Introduction to the paperback edition.” In D. N. Stern: The Interpersonal
World of the Infant (pp. xi–xxxix). New York: Basic Books. (Also London: Karnac 2003.)
Stein, D. N. (2004). The Present Moment in Psychotherapy and Everyday Life. New York: Norton.
Trevarthen, C. (1979). “Communication and cooperation in early infancy: A description of
primary intersubjectivity.” In M. M. Bullowa (Ed.), Before Speech (pp. 321–347). New York:
Cambridge University Press.
Trevarthen, C. (1986). “Development of intersubjective motor control in infants.” In M. G.
Wade & H. T. A. Whiting (Eds.), Motor Development in Children (pp. 209–261). Dordrecht:
Martinus Nijhoff.
Trevarthen, C. (1998). “The concept and foundations of infant intersubjectivity.” In S.
Bråten (Ed.), Intersubjective Communication and Emotion in Early Ontogeny (pp. 15–46).
Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
Trevarthen, C., Aitken, L., Papoudi, D., & Robarts, J. (1998). Children with Autism (2nd ed.).
London: Jessica Kingsley Publishers.
de Waal, F. B. M. (1996). Good Natured. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.
JB[v.20020404] Prn:26/10/2006; 12:13 F: AICR68P1.tex / p.1 (48-75)
chapter
Prologue
From infant intersubjectivity and participant
movements to simulation and conversation
in cultural common sense
In the last few decades the story of human infancy that has been told by philoso-
phers and medical and psychological sciences has been re-written. In place of the
idea that infants are a-social and ego-centric there is a new understanding that
a baby is born with a lively talent for interpersonal communion. The indulgent
opinion of parents has received abundant confirmation from careful observational
research. Thus micro-analyses of proto-conversations with two-month-olds have
revealed that infants are endowed with a cerebral system that enables direct per-
ception of interests and feelings in an other person and responsive attunement
permitting delicate, emotionally regulated engagements. Like the processes of al-
tercentric participation found by Bråten (1998a, 2002) to be exhibited in early
cultural learning situations, probably subserved by the mirror system recently
discovered by Rizzolatti and his co-workers and identified in the human brain
(Rizzolatti & Arbib 1998), these characteristics break radically with the assump-
tions in Freudian and Piagetian traditions which implied a long developmental
period of de-centration before sociality and intersubjectivity could emerge.
Modes of intersubjectivity
Today, based on the empirical findings of the last three decades, we are able to dis-
tinguish different layers of intersubjective attunement in human development be-
fore language. The innate intersubjectivity defined in the 1970s (Trevarthen 1974,
1979; Bateson 1975, 1979; Stern 1977; Bullowa 1979) helps explain the emergence
of the toddler’s appetite for speech in the mother tongue and indeed for intent par-
JB[v.20020404] Prn:25/01/2007; 12:46 F: AICR6801.tex / p.2 (115-159)
ticipation in the learning of all varieties of cultural habits and manners throughout
childhood (cf. Bråten 1988, 1998; Bråten & Trevarthen 1994/2000; Dunn 1998;
Harris 1998; Hobson 1998); see also Stern’s (2000/2003) new introduction to his
1985-book on The Interpersonal World of the Infant,1 and the literature on cultural
learning, especially Bruner 2003; Rogoff 1995). Tracing the growth of communi-
cation of purposes and concerns through the first two years has brought a richly
nuanced account of how the child uses negotiation with other persons’ awareness
and intentions in the world to grasp meaning (cf. Halliday and others). The follow-
ing summarises the key steps that prepare the way for and support the elaboration
of higher-order competences in communication and thinking, including conver-
sational speech, creation of narrative explanations and sharing myths, beliefs and
scientific ideas afforded by the ambient parental culture:
I. The primary intersubjective dialogues of protoconversation and reciprocal
sympathetic imitation exhibited in the first weeks of life (Bateson, Trevarthen)
lead to more lively jokes and games rich in emotions of ’other awareness’
(Reddy). Initiatives are tested in a teasing and provocative way. Affectionate
attachments are strengthened by this play and build friendships around ha-
bitual ‘formats’ or ‘rituals’ of baby songs and action games (Stern, Bruner) in
which the infants learn to take an active part, for example, by an 11-days-old
on the nursing table in a dance-like interplay with her mother (recorded 1990
by Bråten). An exchange of imitations and expressions of emotion may be
elicited in the first hours after birth (e.g. as recorded 1983 by Kugiumutzakis),
the infant showing initiative as well as copying movements, which reveals that
imitation to reproduce a movement made by another is but one element in the
innate capacity for mutual engagement in two way expression of sympathetic
interest (Nagy and Molnár). The mutual mirroring and turn-taking which we
find in mature verbal conversation is clearly foreshadowed in these first bouts
of sympathetic mimetic play, and the ‘communicative musicality’ entailed in
dyadic protoconversation allows to be captured in terms of the parameter of
musicality such as ‘pulse’ and ‘quality’ (cf. Malloch & Trevarthen in press).
After a few months an infant may show a wider sociability, being capable of
engaging concurrently with more than one other.2
II. Secondary intersubjective attunement in a triangular subject-subject-object
format (Trevarthen & Hubley 1978) in which objects of joint attention and
emotional referencing are brought into play as occurrences of mutual atten-
tion within trusting relations of companionship. The infant displays to others
of knowledge and skill learned by sharing intentions and interests are ani-
mated by emotions of ‘pride’ and ‘shame’. Others’ object-oriented acts elicit
participant perception or re-enactment, for example by infants who learn to
reciprocate their caregivers’ spoon-feeding before their first birthday (e.g. as
JB[v.20020404] Prn:25/01/2007; 12:46 F: AICR6801.tex / p.3 (159-211)
Prologue
We stress the importance of the social-emotional roots and nurture of the de-
velopment of dialogical competence and consciousness. The emotions supported
in affectionate engagements between adult and infants, and soon between peers
and with other acquaintances of all ages, are essential to the regulation of normal
brain development to the development of the mind’s dialogical and creative con-
sciousness, and thus to the common sense of cultural awareness. Emotions are not
merely responsible for the natural control of instinctive appetites and aversions
that serve immediate survival of the body or give regularity to the baby’s feed-
ing and sleep-wake cycles. Emotions that generate the expression in the separate
brains of mother and baby can come together in a confluence of affect that devel-
ops an organization of its own – an organization moreover that is also reflected in
the self-other organization of the developing mind. The shifting between dialog-
ical competence and consciousness manifests itself in intersubjective attunement
at various levels – from confluence of affect at the primary level to advanced self-
other simulation and constructions at a more advanced level involving internal
self-creative and dialogical circles of complementary self-other perspectives.
Thus, a major point here is that such higher-order achievements continue to
be supported by capacities and competencies unfolding in the primary and sec-
ondary steps or layers, which continue to be operational and supportive through-
out life, like the various senses of self distinguished in the multi-layered model by
Stern (1985/2000). The kind of mutually fulfilling processes that we have found
to be exhibited in early protoconversation and cultural learning situations be-
JB[v.20020404] Prn:25/01/2007; 12:46 F: AICR6801.tex / p.4 (211-256)
fore the first year’s birthday may be seen to resemble the key characteristics of
higher-order speech conversation. For example, teenagers in face-to-face conver-
sation often reflect one another’s gestures in much the same way that we observe in
early infant-adult interaction, and sometimes complete one another’s speech acts
akin to patterns manifested also in preverbal object-oriented manual interplay. In
dialogue, for example, between speech-competent participants, the “attunement
to the attunement of the other” (Rommetveit 1998: 360) appears to be prepared
for by the mutual, dance-like interplay which we can observe already in the first
weeks after birth. That fact that neonates, 45 minutes old or even younger, can
imitate facial gestures of the adults to whom they are exposed is evidence of such
early readiness for immediate contact with others.
Of course other non-verbal forms of adult human communion share the
same vital principles and rhythmic foundations, and these are especially clear
in ritual performances, drama, music and dance (see Schögler & Trevarthen this
volume (16)).
In the following we offer a succinct characterization of some of the operating
characteristics pertaining to the various steps or layers.
(I) Newborns’ imitation and protoconversation in the first weeks and months.
Most parents and caretakers have experienced how their babies in the first months
of life complement them in a finely tuned interplay of mutual fulfilling and follow-
up of gestures and expressions. Even in the first weeks after birth mother and child
can achieve such coordination of expressions and movements in a sort of circular
dance of mutually completing and inter-woven bodily motions. There is a primary
intersubjective attunement in a reciprocal subject-subject format of protoconver-
sation and interpersonal communion, in which participants attend and attune
to one another’s emotive expressions and gesture- and sound- producing move-
ments, inviting semblant re-enactment and affect attunement, beginning soon
after birth and preparing for and supporting higher-order competencies later in
life. For example, pertaining to vocal imitation and speech development, some 45
minutes-olds may attempt to imitate /a/, and 20 weeks-olds /a/, /u/ and /i/). At
6 weeks or earlier infants engage with adults in reciprocal protoconversation. In
their early speech perception infants are beginning to ‘prune’ sounds from their
perceptual space that make no sense in the ambient language (Kuhl 1998; Conboy
& Kuhl this volume).
In the first weeks after birth infants have been documented by experimental
studies to imitate a variety of gestures, such as tongue protrusion, brow motions,
and head rotation, finger movements, gestural features used to express surprise,
delight and boredom, and vocal (vowel) productions. Most dramatic is perhaps
the video documentations by Kugiumutzakis (1983, 1998: 74) of how neonates in
the first hour after birth attempt to come up with a semblant response, match-
JB[v.20020404] Prn:25/01/2007; 12:46 F: AICR6801.tex / p.5 (256-311)
Prologue
ing his mouth and brow gestures. Inviting even vocal imitation, respectively, of
the sounds /a/, /m/ and /ang/, newborns (ranging from 14 to 42 minutes of age)
tried to produce a matching /a/, while failing with respect to the other invited
sounds. Trying hard to emit the sound, accompanied by stretching hand move-
ments and closed eyes, the result was usually an intense explosion of a prolonged
and unstructured /a/-sound.
Evidence has been obtained of infants’ musical listening and natural pref-
erence for musical features of the voice. Even a premature newborn baby may
actively contribute to the precise rhythmic exchange of vocal songs with a song-
like regulation of pitch and timbre (Trevarthen 1993; Malloch 1999). Speech to
infants in different languages has universal rhythmic and prosodic features, and
rising pitch contours elicit and maintain infant attention more than falling pitch.
Unlike the sharply rising pitch contour in maternal vocalization that alerts the
infant, the pitch is low and continuous in comforting (Fernald 1992; Papousek
1994). There is a precise regulation of the pitch of a mother’s voice and the infants
have an innate preference for the range of a happy mother’s speech no matter what
language she speaks.
the child, when handed the dumbbell, pulls it apart, usually with a triumphant
smile. Here is demonstrated the child’s capacity to “read the model’s intention”
(Meltzoff & Moore 1998: 50–52), but there is more involved, and which may be
specified in terms of other-centred participation: From having virtually partici-
pated in the model’s effort, evoking simulated completion of the attempted act,
there is circular re-enactment by the child, successfully realizing the target act. By
merely watching someone aiming for the target, they show that they can realize the
unrealized target, from e-motional memory of mental simulation circuits evoked
by participant perception of the model’s effort. Again, these are also operating
processes characteristic of verbal conversation.
Prologue
pacity for virtual participation in what others are doing are likely to support the
kind of inner feedback loops defined by Bråten’s (1974) conversational simulation
of mind model, illustrating how dialogue partners simulating one another’s verbal
production and understanding.
Musicality manifests its fundamental features in the cultivated expressive ways hu-
man bodies move, and also in the ways that infants behave in interaction with the
rhythmic expressions of motive force in the vocalizations and gestures of other hu-
man beings. A newborn knows the mother by the tone and inflections of her voice.
When a six-month-old smiles with recognition of a favourite song, and bounces
with the beat, it is like knowing his or her name, displaying a social ’me’ within the
family’s affectionate pleasure of sharing.” (Trevarthen 2002: 21).
It has been found that happy mothers vocalize through the octave above mid-
dle C, and that a depressed mother’s speech, which fails to engage a young infant’s
interest, falls below this range. Like the rhythm of steps is to the pulse of dance,
the musical pitch range and its expressive modulations in song appear to be innate
attributes of human vocal communication. Music seeks and invite the experience
of moving and expressing life in sound, and its singing and voice-like sound also
appeal to affectionate moral sentiments that draws us into empathic fellow feelings
and moving in sympathy (Panksepp & Bernatsky 2002).
For many years the Papouseks and Daniel Stern and his colleagues have, in dif-
ferent ways, brought our attention to the ‘musicality’ of expressions in communi-
cation with infants. The Papouseks (1981) identified musical forms of expression
produced intuitively by parents and infants with motivation for cultural learning.
Stern (1985) identified the ‘affect attunement’ of a mother’s voice with the essential
affectionate support that an infant depends upon for development of a secure and
expressive personality. An inner sense of time, of kairos, not chronos, is seen in the
spontaneous activity of a newborn baby in calm control of the energy of moving,
‘in the present moment’ (Stern 2004). The baby’s body moves rhythmically and
in flowing cycles of effort. It shows the measured hierarchy of rhythms of a cen-
tral motor control, which has been labeled the Intrinsic Motive Pulse (IMP). The
senses – stimulated among the muscles and joints of the baby’s limbs and inside
the body, as well as in special exteroceptive organs that respond to energy patterns
reflected back from the environment – ride on the movement, efficiently absorbing
effects of pressure, touch, sight and sound. Reflex startles only occasionally break
the pattern when there is an invasion of unexpected, unassimilated, stimulation.
Observations of infants’ active participation in mothers’ nursery songs and
body games show how interested they are and how willingly the babies move with
JB[v.20020404] Prn:25/01/2007; 12:46 F: AICR6801.tex / p.8 (407-455)
the music. Mazokopaki and Trevarthen (2007) report that an infant of 6 months
will still on hearing music, orient, smile and then join in with rhythmic move-
ments as he or she ‘picks up’ the music. Infants of 3 or 4 months and more learn
songs quickly, move to them, and demonstrate to familiar others their pride in
being able to act with the rhythms and melodies.
Malloch (1999) has demonstrated that the sounds of a recorded protocon-
versation between a 6-week-old Scottish girl, Laura, and her mother could be
analyzed in rigorous musical acoustic terms of rhythmic base, qualitative control
of melodic expression in pitch and timbre, phrasing of utterances with bar structure,
and progression over tens of seconds in narrative cycles of energy and excitement.
(cf. also Schögler & Trevarthen this volume).
The mutual attunement and musical ways in which the infant and the adult
in protoconversation or in a conversation-like dance resonate with one another
and complete or fulfil one another’s sounds and moves, attest to ‘the muse within’
(Björkvold 1992) and may be compared to some of the characteristics of intimate
verbal conversations in which the partners complete one another’s utterances.
When the listener completes the talker’s speech act and when the feeder’s mouth
movements match the recipient’s mouth movements, their virtual participation is
overtly manifested. The partial neurophysiological support of such feats has now
been discovered.
The discovery of ‘mirror neurons’ and the electrophysiological experimental
evidences of a mirror system in the human brain inform about the kind of neuro-
physiological system, a virtual mirror system, that is the likely support of the above
processes of participant perception. The mirror neurons, first found in macaque
monkeys to discharge both when another is observed grasping a piece of food and
when the monkey is preparing for grasping the piece by itself, subserve a system
that appear to match the act perceived done by another individual with a sem-
blant, internally generated enactment in the perceiver (cf. Di Pellegrino et al. 1992;
Fadiga et al. 1995; and contributions by Rizzolatti, Fadiga, and others in Stamenov
& Gallese (Eds.) 2002). Further experimental evidence suggests that such a sys-
tem exists also in humans, in the brain region that contains Broca’s area (which
not only serves speech, but appears to come active during execution and imagery
of hand movement and tasks involving hand-mental rotation). Identifying such a
mirror neurons system enabling observed enactment to be matched to semblant,
internally generated enactment in the observer of that enactment, Rizzolatti and
Arbib (1998) refer to Liberman’s (1993) motor theory of speech perception im-
plying a close link between the production and perception of speech. This is partly
JB[v.20020404] Prn:25/01/2007; 12:46 F: AICR6801.tex / p.9 (455-513)
Prologue
Rizzolatti and Arbib suggest that usage of ‘mirror neurons’ may mark the begin-
ning of intentional communication in human phylogeny, the first primitive dia-
logue, as it were, in which the matching mirror system enables intentional meaning
to be assigned to the other’s observed act by virtue of evoking a matching enact-
ment in the observer. They refer to Donald’s (1991) assumption about mimesis as
precursor to language, and speculate on the sequence of events that might have
led from gestural communication to speech. It is likely, they state, that the human
capacity to communicate beyond that of other primates depended on the progres-
sive evolution of the mirror system in its globality. Following up this, Gallese and
Stamenov suggest that with the primate premotor cortex as the common ground,
an evolutionary continuity to language skill may be traced from pre-language
arm- and hand-manual behaviours and, furthermore, that the specialization for
language of human Broca’s region appears to emerge from the mirror system, orig-
inally serving action understanding (cf. the introduction in Stamenov & Gallese
(Eds.) 2002: 1–10).
The mirror system has been located to involve human brain areas that subserve
speech and mental hand rotation. It has been recorded to be evoked in human
subjects when another hand-grasping individual was observed and when the sub-
jects imagined themselves grasping the object without actually moving their hand.
It is highly pertinent that Broca’s area which may be involved in the mirror sys-
tem also become active in tasks involving mental hand rotation. It pertains to the
kind of participant mirroring which may be attributed to intimate dialogue part-
ners who mirror one another’s postures and gestures and sometimes complete one
another’s utterances. And it pertains to preverbal learning by altercentric partic-
ipation which may have afforded a distinct selective advantage in hominid and
human phylogeny (Bråten 2002, 2004).
Donald argues for the transitional role of a mimetic Homo erectus culture to-
wards a narrative (mythic) culture. An evolved capacity for participant perception
in face-to-face learning and warning situations, we submit, may have been precur-
sory and supportive of such conversational speech adaptation in human evolution.
To infants endowed with the capacity for virtual (other) participation in gestic-
ulating and articulating others, an emerging ambient speech language, perhaps
accompanied by a speech-mediated pedagogy, would have afforded opportunities
for their beginning to attune themselves by participant speech perception to the
prosody and rhythm of the emerging language culture into which they were born.
JB[v.20020404] Prn:25/01/2007; 12:46 F: AICR6801.tex / p.10 (513-562)
In view of what we have uncovered about the ontogenesis of speech, this may
be added: While an evolutionary continuity to language skill may be traced from
pre-language arm- and hand-manual behaviours, there appears to be a somewhat
similar continuity also in early ontogeny; i.e. from manual action learning and
understanding to conceptual comprehension and mental understanding. While
the phylogenetic specialization for language appears to emerge from an ancient
mechanism, the mirror system, originally serving only early action learning and
action understanding in human evolution, that system became critical in Hominid
and Human evolution for subserving processes in preverbal learners and verbal
dialogue partners for altercentric mirroring and participation.
One may venture the speculation that the phylogenetic steps towards speech-
mediated teaching and learning may in certain respect parallel the ontogenetic
steps (I, II, III) delimitated above – from intersubjective participation in an imme-
diate sense to higher order modes of intersubjective understanding mediated by
thought, language and symbolic communication. This blurs the distinction, how-
ever, between a speech community evolving as a co-created novelty and as environ-
mentally given in ontogeny to those born into the speech community, nurturing
the impressive speech learning capacity of the very young. While societal evolu-
tion from phylogeny has involved the generation of new cultural lifeworlds in new
domains never before entertained, the child is born into the peculiar rhythms and
musical sounds of a language culture that already exists, nurturing the self-creative
transitions from consensual communion to symbolic, narrative communication.
This would not have been as efficient, we may now claim, were it not supported by
an innate, preverbal virtual-other mechanism enabling participant speech percep-
tion, and subserved by a phylogenetically afforded and adapted resonant mirror
system.
Notes
. While having previously taken exception to Trevarthen’s (1979) attribution of primary in-
tersubjectivity to early infancy, Daniel Stern (2000), in his new introduction to the paperback
edition of The Interpersonal World of the Infant, makes this declaration of a shift in his position:
In light of new evidence of other-centered participation shown by infants in their many
forms of imitation, as well as the new findings on mirror neurons and adaptive oscil-
lators, I am now convinced that early forms of intersubjectivity exist almost from the
beginning of life. (Stern 2000: xxii)
Such recent evidences, he declares, “suggest that, probably from the beginning of life, infants
have the capacity for what Bråten (1998) terms altero-centric participation or what Trevarthen
has long called primary intersubjectivity” (Stern 2000: xx).
. Engagements with more than one may entail experience that leads to complex emotional reg-
ulations that according to Selby and Bradley may establish immediate preferences and aversions
JB[v.20020404] Prn:25/01/2007; 12:46 F: AICR6801.tex / p.11 (562-662)
Prologue
between infant participants in triads, which per formal graph theoretical definition cannot be
anything but imbalanced, entailing a dyadic relation + one excluded from that dyad. Even in the
infant-mother-father triad an initial imbalance may come to be at play dependent, of course,
upon the nature and degree of active parent participation.
References
Akhtar, N., & Tomasello, M. (1998). “Intersubjectivity in early learning and use.” In S.
Bråten (Ed.), Intersubjective Communication and Emotion in Early Ontogeny (pp. 316–335).
Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
Bateson, M. C. (1975). “Mother-infant exchanges: The epigenesis of conversational interaction.
In D. Aaronson & R. W. Rieber (Eds.), Developmental Psycholinguistics and Communication
Disorders. Annals of the New York Academy of Sciences (Vol. CCLXIII) (pp. 101–113). New
York: New York Academy of Sciences.
Bateson, M. C. (1979). “The epigenesis of conversational interaction.” In M. Bullowa (Ed.),
Before Speech (pp. 63–77). Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
Bjørkvold, J. R. (1992). The Muse Within: Creativity and Communication, Song and Play from
Childhood through Maturity. New York: Harper Collins.
Bråten, S. (1974). “Coding simulation circuits during symbolic interaction.” Proceedings of
the 7th International Congress on Cybernetics, 1973 (pp. 327–336). Namur: Association
Internationale de Cybernetique.
Bråten, S. (1988). “Dialogic mind: The infant and the adult in protoconversation.” In
M. Carvallo (Ed.), Nature, Cognition and System, I (pp. 187–205). Dordrecht: Kluwer
Academic Publishers.
Bråten, S. (1996). “Infants demonstrate that care-giving is reciprocal.” Centre for Advanced Study
SHS Newsletter, 2 (November), 2.
Bråten, S. (1998a). “Infant learning by altercentric participation: The reverse of egocentric
observation in autism.” In S. Bråten (Ed.), Intersubjective Communication and Emotion in
Early Ontogeny (pp. 105–124). Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
Bråten, S. (1998). Kommunikasjon og samspill – fra fødsel til alderdom. Oslo: Tano-Aschehoug.
Bråten, S. (Ed.). (1998). Intersubjective Communication and Emotion in Early Ontogeny.
Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. (In 2006 also in paperback issue.)
Bråten, S. (2002). “Altercentric perception by infants and adults in dialogue: Ego’s virtual
participation in alter’s complementary act”. In M. Stamenov & V. Gallese (Eds.), Mirror
Neurons and the Evolution of Brain and Language (pp. 273–294). Amsterdam/Philadelphia:
John Benjamins.
Bråten, S. (2004). “The hominin infant decentration hypothesis: Mirror neurons system adapted
to subserve mother-centered participation.” Commentary Behavioral and Brain Sciences, 27
(4), 508–509.
Bråten, S., & Trevarthen, C. (1994/2000). “Beginings of cultural learning.” (Presented at the
ZiF symposium, organized by Günter Dux, University of Bielefeld, 17–19 November 1994).
In S. Bråten (Ed.), Modellmakt og altersentriske spedbarn. Essays on Dialogue in Infant and
Adult (pp. 213–218). Bergen: Sigma.
Bråten, S., & Gallese, V. (2004). “On mirror neurons systems implication for social cognition
and intersubjectivity” (Interview by the editors L. T. Westlye & T. Weinholdt). Impuls, 58
(3), 97–107.
JB[v.20020404] Prn:25/01/2007; 12:46 F: AICR6801.tex / p.12 (662-786)
Bruner, J. (1995) The Culture of Education. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.
Bullowa, M. (Ed.). (1979). Before Speech. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
Di Pellegrino, G., Fadiga, L., Fogassi, L., Gallese, V., & Rizzolatti, G. (1992). “Understanding
motor events: A neurophysiological study.” Experimental Brain Research, 91, 176–180.
Donald, M. (1991). Origins of the Modern Mind. Three Stages in the Evolution of Culture and
Cognition. Cambridge: Harvard University Press.
Dunn, J. (1998). “Siblings, emotion and the development of understanding.” In S. Bråten (Ed.),
Intersubjective Communication and Emotion in Early Ontogeny (pp. 158–168). Cambridge:
Cambridge University Press.
Fadiga, L., Fogassi, L., Pavesi, G., & Rizzolatti, G. (1995). “Motor facilitation during action
observation: A magnetic stimulation study”. Journal of Neurophysiology, 73, 2603–2611.
Fernald, A. (1992). “Human maternal vocalizations to infants as biologically relevant signals.”
In J. H. Barkow, L. Cosmides, & J. Toby (Eds.), Adapted Mind (pp. 391–426). New York:
Oxford University Press.
Gallese, V., & Goldman, A. (1998). “Mirror neurons and the simulation theory of mind-
reading.” Trends in Cognitive Science, 2 (12), 293–450.
Halliday, M. A. K. (1975). Learning How to Mean: Explorations in the Development of Language.
London: Edward Arnold.
Harris, P. (1998). “Fictional Absorption: Emotional response to make-believe.” In S. Bråten
(Ed.), Intersubjective Communication and Emotion in Early Ontogeny (pp. 336–353).
Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
Hobson, R. Peter (1998). “The intersubjective foundations of thought.” In S. Bråten (Ed.),
Intersubjective Communication and Emotion in Early Ontogeny (pp. 283–296). Cambridge:
Cambridge University Press.
Kugiumutzakis, G. (1998). “Neonatal imitation in the intersubjective companion space.” In S.
Bråten (Ed.), Intersubjective Communication and Emotion in Early Ontogeny (pp. 63–88).
Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
Kuhl, P. (1998). “Language, culture and intersubjectivity: The creation of shared perception.” In
S. Bråten (Ed.), Intersubjective Communication and Emotion in Early Ontogeny (pp. 297–
315). Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
Liberman, A. M. (1993). Haskin Laboratories Status Report on Speech Research, 113, 1–32.
Malloch, S. (1999). “Mother and infants and communicative musicality.” In I. Deliège (Ed.),
Rhythms, Musical Narrative, and the Origins of Human Communication. Musicae Scientiae,
Special Issue, 1999–2000 (pp. 29–57). Liège, Belgium: European Society for the Cognitive
Sciences of Music.
Mazokopaki, K., & Trevarthen, C. (2007). “Infants’ rhythms: Moving in the absence and
presence of music”. In S. Malloch & C. Trevarthen (Eds.), Communicative Musicality:
Narratives of Expressive Gesture and Being Human. Oxford: Oxford University Press (in
preparation).
Meltzoff, A. N., & Moore, M. K. (1998). “Infant intersubjectivity: Broadening the dialogue to
include imitation, identity and intention.” In S. Bråten (Ed.), Intersubjective Communication
and Emotion in Early Ontogeny (pp. 47–62). Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
Nagy, E., & Molnár, P. (2004). “Homo imitans or Homo provocans? Human imprinting model
of neonatal imitation.” Infant Behaviour and Development, 27 (1), 54–63.
Panksepp, J., & Bernatzky, G. (2002). “Emotional sounds and the brain: The neuro-affective
foundations of musical appreciation.” Behavioural Processes, 60, 133–155.
JB[v.20020404] Prn:25/01/2007; 12:46 F: AICR6801.tex / p.13 (786-912)
Prologue
Papousek, H., & Papousek, M. (1987). “Intuitive parenting: a dialectic counterpart to the infant’s
integrative competence.” In H. R. Schaffer (Ed.), Handbook of Infant Development (pp. 67–
85). London: Academic Press.
Rall, J., & Harris, P. (2000). “In Cinderella’s slippers. Story comprehension from the protagonist’s
point of view.” Development Psychology, 36, 202–208.
Reddy, V. (2003). “On being the object of attention: Implications for self-other consciousness.”
Trends in Cognitive Sciences, 7 (9), 397–402.
Rogoff, B. (2003). The Cultural Nature of Human Development. Oxford: Oxford University Press.
Rizzolatti, G., Camarda, R., Fogassi, M., Gentilucci, M., Luppino, G., & Matelli, M. (1988).
“Functional organization of interior area 6 in the macaque monkey”. Experimental Brain
Research, 71, 491–507.
Rizzolatti, G., & Arbib, M. (1998). “Language within our grasp.” Trends in Neurosciences, 21 (5),
188–193.
Rizzolatti, G., Craighero, L., & Fadiga, L. (2002). “The mirror system in humans”. In M.
Stamenov & V. Gallese (Eds.), Mirror Neurons and the Evolution of Brain and Language
(pp. 37–59). Amsterdam/Philadelphia: John Benjamins.
Rommetveit, R. (1998). “Intersubjective attunement and linguistically mediated meaning
in discourse.” In S. Bråten (Ed.), Intersubjective Communication and Emotion in Early
Ontogeny (pp. 354–371). Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
Selby, J. M., & Bradley, B. S. (2003). “Infants in groups: A paradigm for study of early social
experience.” Human Development, 46, 197–221.
Stamenov, M., & Gallese, V. (Eds.). (2002). Mirror Neurons and the Evolution of Brain and
Language. Amsterdam/Philadelphia: John Benjamins.
Stern, D. N. (1985). The Interpersonal World of the Infant. New York: Basic Books.
Stern, D. N. (2000). “Introduction to the paperback edition.” In D. N. Stern (Ed.), The
Interpersonal World of the Infant (pp. xi–xxxix). New York: Basic Books. (Also: London:
Keaton 2003).
Stern, D. N. (2004). The Present Moment in Psychotherapy and Everyday Life. New York: Norton.
Trevarthen, C. (1974). “Conversation with a two-month-old.” New Scientist, 2, 230–235.
Trevarthen, C. (1979). “Communication and cooperation in early infancy: A description of
primary intersubjectivity.” In M. Bullowa (Ed.), Before Speech (pp. 227–270). Cambridge:
Cambridge University Press.
Trevarthen, C. (1980). “The Foundations of Intersubjectivity.” In D. Olson (Ed.), The Social
Foundation of Language and Thought (pp. 316–242). New York: Norton and Co.
Trevarthen, C. (1986). “Development of intersubjective motor control in infants.” In M. G. Wade
& H. T. A. Whiting (Eds.), Motor Development. Dordrecht: Martinus Nijhoff.
Trevarthen, C. (1988). “Infants trying to talk: How the child invites communication from the
human world.” In R. Söderbergh (Ed.), Children’s Creative Communication (pp. 9–31).
Lund: Lund University Press.
Trevarthen, C. (1989). “Origins and directions for the concept of infant intersubjectivity.” SRCD
Newsletter, Autumn, 1–4.
Trevarthen, C. (1990a). “Signs before speech.” In T. A. Sebeok & J. Umiker-Sebeok (Eds.), The
Semiotic Web (pp. 689–755). Berlin/New York: Mouton de Gruyter.
Trevarthen, C. (1990b). “Growth and education in the hemispheres.” In C. Trevarthen (Ed.),
Brain Circuits and Functions of the Mind: Essays in Honours of Roger Sperry (pp. 334–357).
New York: Cambridge University Press.
Trevarthen, C. (1992a). “Emotions of human infants and mothers and development of brain.”
Behavioral and Brain Sciences, 15 (3), 524–525.
JB[v.20020404] Prn:25/01/2007; 12:46 F: AICR6801.tex / p.14 (912-957)
Trevarthen, C. (1992b). “An infant’s motives for speaking and thinking in the culture.” In
A. H. Wold (Ed.), The Dialogical Alternative (pp. 99–138). Oslo: Scandinavian University
Press/Oxford University Press (distr.).
Trevarthen, C. (1993). “The self born in intersubjectivity: An infant communicating.” In U.
Neisser (Ed.), The Perceived Self (pp. 121–173). New York: Cambridge University Press.
Trevarthen, C. (1998). “The concept and foundations of infant intersubjectivity.” In S.
Bråten (Ed.), Intersubjective Communication and Emotion in Early Ontogeny (pp. 15–46).
Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
Trevarthen, C. (2002). “Origins of musical identity: Evidence from infancy for musical social
awareness.” In R. A. R. Mac Donald, D. J. Hargreaves, & D. Meill (Eds.), Musical Identities
(pp. 21–38). Oxford: Oxford University Press.
Trevarthen, C., & Hubley, P. (1978). “Secondary intersubjectivity: Confidence, confiding, and
acts of meaning in the first year.” In J. Lock (Ed.), Action, Gesture, and Symbol (pp. 183–229).
London: Academic Press.
Trevarthen, C., Aitken, K. J., Papoudi, D., & Robarts, J. Z. (1998). Children with Autism (2nd
ed.). London: Jessica Kingsley.
Trevarthen, C., & Schögler, B. (2004). “On musicality: Learning it’s meaning from infants’ voices
and jazz.” Draft for the Theory Forum Symposium on (Pre)verbal Intersubjectivity in Light
of New Findings. The Norwegian Academy of Science, Oslo, October 3–5.
JB[v.20020404] Prn:25/01/2007; 12:52 F: AICR6802.tex / p.1 (49-114)
chapter
Daniel N. Stern
University of Geneva / Cornell University Medical School
Introduction
There must exist mechanisms for phenomena such as sympathy, empathy, iden-
tification, imitation, internalization, “reading” other’s intentions, psychological
intimacy, etc. – intersubjectivity, in general. In this volume, we will learn of re-
cent neuroscientific findings that suggest mechanisms for these phenomena. We
are also offered developmental accounts of the capacity for these various forms of
intersubjectivity. I will briefly review these two, by way of introducing them, and as
a necessary background for viewing the change process in psychotherapy as seen
in the light of what we now know about other-centred participation.
There are a host of related phenomena that can be observed or felt when
human beings interact: resonance, empathy, identification, imitation, internal-
ization, “reading” other’s intentions, affect attunement, social referencing, and
other-centred participation, etc. These can, perhaps, be pulled together as various
forms of sympathy and of intersubjectivity.
Without these forms of sympathy and intersubjectivity it is impossible to
imagine a number of phenomena, such as: basic social skills; harmonious affective
interactions; language acquisition; the development of moral emotions and moral-
ity; children’s play that involves jokes, tricks, fooling around, and lying; highly
coordinated spontaneous group behaviour; the possibility of psychotherapy; the
psychic intimacy involved in friendship; and in falling in love. And that is only a
very partial list. Life would be barren, indeed.
The capacity for sympathy and intersubjectivity also seems to be required for
mental health in general. It is suggested that several forms of psychopathology
such as sociopathologies, some personality disturbances, forms of schizophrenia,
and autism, come about, in part, through deficits in these capacities.
JB[v.20020404] Prn:25/01/2007; 12:52 F: AICR6802.tex / p.2 (114-165)
Daniel N. Stern
The symposium giving rise to this volume has been devoted to exploring the
mechanisms that underlie these capacities. To set the stage for this exploration,
I will give a brief overview of the situation from a philosophical, neuroscientific,
developmental and clinical viewpoint.1
On philosophy of intersubjectivity
The philosophers have recognized the profound importance of and necessity for
sympathy and intersubjectivity in humans for a very long time. Until relatively re-
cently, in the modern scientifically oriented west, we have isolated the mind from
the body, from nature, and most importantly for our purposes here, from other
minds. It was thought that each mind has to be constructed privately and per-
haps quite idiosyncratically, from within. We are now experiencing a revolution.
The new view assumes that the mind is always embodied in and made possible by
the sensori-motor activity of the body. That it is interwoven with and co-created
by the environment that immediately surrounds it, which includes the intentions,
desires, feelings, actions, sounds of other minds. And that it is constituted and
maintained by way of its interactions with other minds. Without these constant
interactions there would be no recognizable mind. This leads to the view that the
mind is, by nature, “intersubjectively open, since it is partially constituted through
its interaction with other minds (see Husserl 1960, for an earlier philosophical po-
sition; Zahavi 1996, 2001, for a more recent one). What this means is that human
beings possess a mental primitive described as, the passive (not voluntarily initi-
ated), pre-reflected experience of the other as an embodied being like oneself...”
(Thompson 2001: 12). Intersubjectivity is not simply a capacity, it is a condition of
humanness from the phenomenological point of view.
Neuroscience findings
mation received when watching another act gets mapped on to the equivalent
motor representation in our own brain by the activity of these mirror neurons.
It permits us to directly participate in another’s actions, without having to imi-
tate them. We experience the other as if we were executing the same action, or
feeling the same emotion. This “participation” in another’s mental life creates a
sense of feeling/sharing with/understanding them, and in particular their inten-
tions and feelings. I am purposely using the term feelings instead of affects so as to
include sentiments, sensory sensations and motor sensations, along with classical
Darwinian affects.
Clearly, the mirror neuron system takes us further in understanding (at the
neural level) resonance, empathy, sympathy, identification, other-centred partici-
pation and intersubjectivity. This story is not yet over. At this point, the evidence
for such a resonance system seems to apply to hand, mouth, face and foot actions,
as well as for vocal sounds.
There is another feature of this system. It is particularly sensitive to goal-
directed actions, i.e. movements with a readily inferable intention. Even more, the
perception of an attributable intention seems to have its own brain localization –
a sort of intention detecting centre (Blakemore & Decety 2001). For example, the
intention-detector brain centre will get activated if the action, in its context, seems
to have an intention. If the exact same movement is seen but in another context
where no intention can be attributed, the brain centre will not activate.
The longstanding idea of a human tendency of mind to perceive and interpret
the human world in terms of intentions is strengthened by such findings. And the
reading of another’s intentions is cardinal to intersubjectivity.
There is another finding that may serve as a mechanism for partially under-
standing sympathy and intersubjectivity. To resonate with someone, the two of
you may have to be in synch. Either you could move in synchrony, as one may
see lovers do as they sit across a table and simultaneously approach and withdraw
their faces from one another, and start to move their hands together at the same
instant.
The discovery of adaptive oscillators may provide a clue. These oscillators act
like clocks within our body. They can be reset, rapidly, over and over, and their
rate of firing can be adjusted to match the rate of an incoming stimulation. These
inner clocks use the real time properties of incoming signals (e.g. from someone
handing you a dish) to “set” your adaptive oscillators, so that they immediately
bring their own rate of neural firing into synch with the periodicity of the incom-
ing signal (Torras 1985; Port & van Gelder 1995). The result is that the outreaching
arm of the person drying the dishes will be perfectly coordinated in time with the
outreaching hand of the person handing over the dish. David Lee has devised el-
egant models, tau theory, to describe how this kind of dyadic coordination and
synchrony could occur (Lee 1998).
JB[v.20020404] Prn:25/01/2007; 12:52 F: AICR6802.tex / p.4 (218-266)
Daniel N. Stern
The need for some such mechanism is evident when one thinks about the
extraordinary temporal coordination human beings and animals are capable of.
Think how easy it is for us to kick a moving soccer ball while we are running, or
catch a fly ball on the run. In interpersonal interactions the problems of temporal
coordination may be even more complex because we alter trajectories more rapidly
and unpredictably than moving balls do. Even so, when moving heads together for
a kiss, even a first time, sudden, passionate kiss, we rarely end up breaking our
front teeth. There is usually a soft landing.
The essential point is that when people move synchronously or in temporal
coordination, they are participating in an aspect of the other’s experience.
and colleagues concluded that infants take in something of the other in the act
of imitation, which solidifies the sense that the other is “like me”, and “I am like
them”. He further speculates that for an infant to learn about (make internal rep-
resentations of) inanimate objects she must manipulate or mouth them, but to
learn about (and represent) people she must imitate them. The infant’s mind uses
different channels for people.
My colleagues and I have taken a third route, focusing on how a mother can
let her infant know that she knows about their inner feeling state (Stern et al.
1984; Stern 1985). For instance, if an infant emitted an affective behaviour after
an event, how could the mother let the infant know that she grasped, not sim-
ply what the infant did, but what was the feeling the infant experienced that lay
behind what he did. The emphasis has shifted from the overt behaviour to the
subjective experience underlying it. I proposed “affect attunement,” a form of se-
lective and cross-modal imitation, as the path to sharing inner feeling states, in
contradistinction to faithful imitation as the path to sharing overt behaviour.
Jaffe et al. (2001) add another piece of suggestive evidence. They show how
preverbal infants (four and twelve months) and mothers precisely time the start-
ing, stopping, and pausing of their vocalizations to create a rhythmic coupling and
bidirectional coordination of their vocal dialogues. This implies that they have
control over not only their own, timing, but have captured that of the other as
well.
The issue of coordinated timing is obviously central for synchronicity and ac-
cess to another’s temporal experience. Watson and colleagues (1995) and Gergely
and Watson (1999) have found a most fascinating way the infant becomes sen-
sitive to the behaviour and timing of others. They propose that we, and infants,
have “innate contingency detection analysers”. Such modules measure the extent to
which someone’s behaviour is exactly synchronous with your own. They find that
before three months, infants are most interested in events that are perfectly con-
tingent. This would make babies most sensitive to themselves. Between four and
six months there is a shift. Infants become most interested in events that are highly
but imperfectly contingent with their own behaviour. That is exactly what an in-
teracting other person does. They now become most interested in the behavioural
timing of others, using themselves as the standard.
There is now a consensus forming that infants are born with minds that are es-
pecially attuned to other minds as manifest through their behaviour. This is based
in large part on the detection of correspondences in timing, intensity and form
that are inter-modally transposable. The result is that from birth on, one can speak
of a psychology of mutually sensitive minds.
JB[v.20020404] Prn:25/01/2007; 12:52 F: AICR6802.tex / p.6 (319-365)
Daniel N. Stern
Bråten (1998a, b) has pulled together the above developmental evidence in the
pre-symbolic infant by coining the term “altero-centred participation”. By this he
means that intersubjectivity is available in infancy by virtue of the innate ability to
enter into the other’s experience and participate in it. He suggests that the human
mind is constructed to encounter “virtual others”. His conclusions fit very well
with the presence of an underlying mechanisms of mirror neurons and adaptive
oscillators as well as with the thrust of the philosophers’ arguments.
After roughly seven to nine months, the scene changes somewhat. The infant
becomes capable of a more elaborate form of intersubjectivity, of what Trevarthen
and Hubley (1978) have called “secondary intersubjectivity”. (See also Stern 2000,
new introduction.) These forms of intersubjectivity, too, are being put in place well
before the infant is verbal or symbolic. The sharable mental states start to include
goal-directed intentions, focus of attention, affects and hedonic evaluations, and,
as before, the experience of action. Each is a partially separate domain of intersub-
jectivity. The participating in the other’s feelings is only one such domain. There
is far more work going on concerning the sharing of the focus of attention in or-
der to triangulate a referent and create the joint framing necessary for language to
emerge (Tomasello 2003).
The “reading” of intentions deserves a special mention because intention is
central to all perspectives on motivated human activity. Some psychological ele-
ment is needed to push, pull, activate or somehow put events in motion. Intentions
go under many guises and variations. In folk psychology, using the examples of
journalism and gossip, it is the motive, the “why?” that propels the tale. In psy-
choanalysis it is the wish or desire. In ethology it is the activated motivation. In
cybernetics it is the goal and its value. In narrative theories it can be the desire, or
belief, or goal, or motive, or “trouble”. But intentions, in one form or another, in
one state of completeness or another, are always there, acting as the engine driving
the action forward.
We see the human world in terms of intentions (Bruner 1990). And we act
in terms of our own. You cannot function with other humans without reading
or inferring their motives or intentions. This reading or attributing intentions
is our primary guide to responding and initiating action. Inferring intentions in
human behaviour appears to be universal. It is a mental primitive. It is how we
parse and interpret our human surround. If one is unable to infer the intentions
of others, or profoundly uninterested in so doing, they will act outside of the hu-
man pale. Autistic people have been assumed to be in this position. So have some
schizophrenic patients (see Parnas, Bovet, & Zahavi 2002).
The perceiving/inferring intentions in human actions begin early in life. Melt-
zoff and colleagues have described several situations in which pre-verbal infants
JB[v.20020404] Prn:25/01/2007; 12:52 F: AICR6802.tex / p.7 (365-418)
grasp the intention of someone acting, even when they have never seen the in-
tention fully enacted, i.e. never reaching its intended goal. In such a situation,
grasping the intention requires an inference.
In one experiment, the pre-verbal infant watches an experimenter pick up an
object and “try” to put it into a container. But, the experimenter drops the object
en route so it never gets to the intended goal. Later, when the infant is brought back
to the scene and given the same material, he picks up the object and directly puts
it into the container. In other words, he enacts the action that he assumes was in-
tended, not the one he saw. The infant has chosen to privilege the unseen, assumed
intention over the seen, actual action (Meltzoff 1995). Other such experiments
make the same point (Meltzoff & Moore 1999).
Gergely et al. (1995) and Gergely and Csibra (1997) have performed a related
experiment using animated televised cartoons. Here too, the infants when watch-
ing the animation, interpret the scene in terms of the intentions they infer rather
than the actions they see. (The fact that the objects are animated, i.e. act like people
would, is certainly crucial.) Rochat and colleagues have shown the same primacy
of inferred intention over seen action in infants even younger, at nine months
(Rochat, Morgan, & Carpenter 1997). In any event, the reading of intentions (at
whatever developmental level) is possible and necessary from very early in life.
At twelve months “social referencing” is seen (Emde & Sorce 1983). A com-
mon example is when an infant just learning to walk falls and is surprised but not
really hurt. She will look to her mother’s face to “know” what to feel. If the mother
expresses fear and concern, the infant will cry. If she smiles, the baby will probably
laugh. In other words, in situations of uncertainty or ambivalence, the affect state
shown in others is pertinent to how the baby will feel.
After eighteen months, when the child becomes verbal, new forms of inter-
subjectivity start to be quickly added (Astington 1993). As soon as the infant can,
herself, do it, feel it, think it, she can probably participate in its being done, felt or
thought by others. The breadth of the child’s intersubjectivity only awaits her own
development. (There is an interesting unanswered question here. Could an infant
participate in another’s experience even before she could do it herself? This is a
legitimate question because, as a rule in development, receptive capacities appear
before productive ones.)
During childhood, cognitive psychology assumes that children acquire a more
general “Theory of Mind”, i.e. they develop a more formal capacity to represent
mental states in others. There are several versions of Theory of Mind in children
that are currently debated (e.g., Leslie 1987; Harris 1989; Hobson 2002; Hobson
& Lee 1999; Fodor 1992; Goldman 1992; Baron-Cohen et al. 1993; Baron-Cohen
1995; Gopnik & Meltzoff 1997). A major point of contention is to what extent the
ability to represent other minds is a formal cognitive process, or must it rely on res-
onance or simulation that permits some kind of direct feeling access to the others’
JB[v.20020404] Prn:25/01/2007; 12:52 F: AICR6802.tex / p.8 (418-467)
Daniel N. Stern
experience. Certainly, each could reinforce the other as development proceeds. But
I can not imagine any fundamental base for intersubjectivity without resonance,
by whatever mechanism. In the last analysis, it is about feeling, not cognition.
There are two other points worth mentioning. Two-way intersubjectivity (“I
know (feel), that you know (feel), that I know (feel)”) requires some kind of re-
cursive participation in, or representation of the other’s mind. Theory of Mind
may be helpful in such considerations, at least after infancy. For instance, one-way
intersubjectivity (“I know (feel) that you...”) may not require a theory of mind.
However, the intersubjective reiteration necessary for two-way intersubjectivity
may be greatly enhanced by a theory of mind when it develops later. (The sharp
distinction I have drawn between one-way and two-way intersubjectivity is too
sharp, especially in practice. In the majority of situations it is more fruitful to think
in terms of degrees of symmetry and asymmetry, where these represent the poles of
a spectrum. There is also the question of, can you participate in the non-conscious
experience of another? Many clinical notions would have to answer yes.)
I believe that many Theory of Mind theorists set too strict criteria of when
a true Theory of Mind can be assumed, often using the ability to represent false
beliefs in others as the sole and ultimate criterion (around five years). Yet, Judy
Dunn’s (1999) and Vasu Reddy’s (1991, 2002) work, on younger children’s joking,
teasing, tricking and being mean to each other would suggest that even earlier
forms of Theory of Mind are frequently seen in natural and not necessarily verbal
settings.
In brief, the developmental evidence suggests that beginning at birth the in-
fant enters into an intersubjective matrix. This is assured because basic forms
of intersubjectivity are manifest right away. As new capacities are developed and
new experiences come available they will be swept into the intersubjective matrix,
which has its own ontogenesis. The breadth and complexity of this matrix ex-
pands rapidly, even during the first year of life when the infant is still pre-symbolic
and pre-verbal. Then, as the infant reaches the second year and is capable of new
experiences, such as, for example, the “moral” emotions of shame, guilt and em-
barrassment, these will get drawn into the intersubjective matrix, as something he
can now experience within himself and in others. Intersubjective richness expands
again with the advent of more developed cognitive capacities during childhood.
And again, at each phase of our life course development the intersubjective matrix
grows deeper and richer.
Some clinical observations point in the same direction as the above mentioned
work. Autistic people continue to amaze. What strikes one most about autism,
JB[v.20020404] Prn:25/01/2007; 12:52 F: AICR6802.tex / p.9 (467-520)
In summary
Daniel N. Stern
mind, and how we view their development. It also provides pertinent glimpses
into mental health.
Notes
. Portions of this overview have been taken from The Present Moment in Psychotherapy and
Everyday Life. D. N. Stern, 2004.
. The members of the Boston CPSG are Nadia Bruschweiler-Stern, Karlen Lyons-Ruth, Alec
Morgan, Jeremy Nahum, Lou Sander, and myself.
References
Astington, J. W. (1993). The Child’s Discovery of the Mind. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University
Press.
Baron-Cohen, S. (1995). Mindblindness: An Essay on Autism and Theory of Mind. Cambridge,
MA: MIT Press.
Blakemore, S.-J., & Decety, J. (2001). “From the perception of action to the understanding of
intention.” Neuroscience, Nature Review, 2, 561–576.
Boston Change Process Study Group (2002). “Explicating the implicit: The interactive
microprocess in the analytic situation. Report Number 3.” International Journal of
Psychoanalysis.
Boston Change Process Study Group (2003). “The “something more than interpretation”:
Sloppiness and co-construction in the psychoanalytic encounter.” Report Number 4 (in
preparation).
Bråten, S. (Ed.). (1998a). Intersubjective Communication and Emotion in Early Ontogeny.
Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
Bråten, S. (1998b). “Infant learning by alter-centric participation: The reverse of egocentric
observation in autism.” In S. Bråten (Ed.), Intersubjective Communication and Emotion in
Early Ontogeny (pp. 105–124). Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
Bruner, J. (1990). Acts of Meaning. New York: Basic Books Inc.
Damasio, A. (1999). The Feeling of What Happens: Body and Emotion in the Making of
Consciousness. San Diego, CA: Harcourt, Inc.
Dunn, J. (1999). “Making sense of the social world: Mind reading, emotion and relationships.”
In P. D. Zelazo, J. W. Astington, & D. R. Olson (Eds.), Developing Theories of Intention.
Mahwah, NJ: Lawrence Erlbaum Associates.
Emde, R. N., & Sorce, J. E. (1983). “The rewards of infancy: Emotional availability and maternal
referencing.” In J. D. Call, F. Galenson, & Tyson (Eds.), Frontiers of Infant Psychiatry, Vol. 2.
New York: Basic Books.
Fodor, J. (1992). “A theory of the child’s theory of mind.” Cognition, 44, 283–296.
Gallese, V., Fadiga, L., Fogassi, L., & Rizzolatti, G. (1996). “Action recognition in the premotor
cortex.” Brain, 119, 593–609.
Gallese, V., & Goldman, A. (1998). “Mirror neurons and the simulation theory of mind reading.”
Trends Cognitive Science, 2, 493–501.
JB[v.20020404] Prn:25/01/2007; 12:52 F: AICR6802.tex / p.11 (609-727)
Gallese, V. (2001). “The ‘Shared Manifold’ Hypothesis. From Mirror neurons to empathy.”
Journal of Consciousness Studies, 5–7, 33–50.
Gergely, G., Nadsasdy, Z., Csibra, G., & Biro, S. (1995). “Taking the intentional stance at 12
months of age.” Cognition, 56, 165–193.
Gergely, G., & Csibra, C. (1997). “Teleological reasoning in infancy: The infant’s naive theory of
rational action. A reply to Premack and Premack.” Cognition, 63, 227–233.
Gergely, G., & Watson, J. S. (1999). “Early social-emotional development: Contingency
perception and the social biofeedback model.” In P. Rochat (Ed.), Early Social Cognition
(pp. 101–136). Hillsdale, NJ: Erlbaum.
Goldman, A. (1992). “In defence of the simulation theory.” Mind and Language, 7, 104–119.
Gopnik, A., & Meltzoff, A. N. (1998). Words, Thoughts and Theories. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.
Harris, P. (1989). Children and Emotion. Oxford: Blackwell Publishers.
Hobson, R. P., & Lee, A. (1999). “Imitation and identification in autism.” Journal of Child
Psychology and Psychiatry, 40, 649–659.
Hobson, R. P. (2002). The Cradle of Thought. London: Pan Macmillan.
Husserl, E. (1960). Cartesian Meditations (transl. Dorian Cairns). The Hague: Martinus Nijhoff.
Kugiumutzakis, G. (1998). “Neonatal imitation in the intersubjective companion space.” In S.
Bråten (Ed.), Intersubjective Communication in Early Ontogeny (pp. 63–88). Cambridge:
Cambridge University Press.
Jaffe, J., Beebe, B., Feldsteln, S., Crown, S., & Jasnow, M. (2001). “Rhythms of dialogue in early
infancy.” Monographs of the Society for Research in Child Development, 66 (2), Serial No.
264.
Kugiumutzakis, G. (1999). “Genesis and development of early human mimesis to facial and
vocal models.” In J. Nadel & C. Butterworth (Eds.), Imitation in Infancy (pp. 36–59).
Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
Lee, D. N. (1998). “Guiding movements by coupling taus.” Ecological Psychology, 10 (3–4), 221–
250.
Leslie, A. M. (1987). “Pretence and representation: The origins of “theory of mind.””
Psychological Review, 94, 412–426.
Maratos, O. (1973). The origin and development of imitation in the first six months of life.
Unpublished doctoral dissertation, University of Geneva.
Meltzoff, A. N. (1981). “Imitation, Intermodal Coordination and Representation in Early
Infancy.” In G. Butterworth (Ed.), Infancy and Epistemology (pp. 85–114). Brighton:
Harvester Press.
Meltzoff, A. N. (1995). “Understanding the intentions of others: Re-enactment of intended acts
by eighteen month-old children.” Developmental Psychology, 3, 838–850.
Meltzoff, A. N., & Moore, M. K. (1977). “Imitation of facial and manual gestures by human
neonates.” Science, 198, 75–78.
Meltzoff, A. N., & Gopnik, A. (1993). “The role of imitation in understanding persons and
developing a theory of mind.” In S. Baron-Cohen, H. Tager-Flusberg, & D. J. Cohen (Eds.),
Understanding Other Minds: Perspectives from Autism (pp. 335–366). New York: Oxford
University Press.
Meltzoff, A. N., & Moore, M. K. (1999). “Persons and representations: Why infant imitation
is important for theories of human development.” In J. Nadel & G. Butterworth (Eds.),
Imitation in Infancy (pp. 9–35). Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
Parnas, J., Bovet, P., & Zahavi, D. (2002). “Schizophrenic autism: Clinical phenomenology and
pathogenic implications.” World Psychiatry, 1 (3), 131–136.
JB[v.20020404] Prn:25/01/2007; 12:52 F: AICR6802.tex / p.12 (727-842)
Daniel N. Stern
Port, R., & van Gelder, T. (Eds.). (1995). Mind as Motion: Explorations in the Dynamics of
Cognition. Cambridge, MA: MIT press.
Reddy, V. (1991). “Playing with other’s expectations: Teasing and mucking about in the first
year.” In A. Whiten (Ed.), Natural Theories of Mind (pp. 143–158). Oxford: Blackwell.
Reddy, V. (2002). “Sharing humor and laughter in autism and Down’s Syndrome.” British
Journal of Psychology (in press).
Rizzolatti, G., & Arbib, M. A. (1998). “Language within our grasp.” Trends in Neuroscience, 21,
188–194.
Rizzolatti, G., Fogassi, L., & Gallese, V. (2001). “Neurophysiological mechanisms underlying the
understanding and imitation of action.” Neuroscience Nature Reviews, 2 (9), 661–670.
Rizzolatti, G., Fadiga, L., Fogassi, L., & Gallese, V. (1996). “Premotor cortex and the recognition
of motor actions.” Cognitive Brain Research, 3, 131–141.
Rochat, P., Morgan, R., & Carpenter, M. (1997). “Young infants’ sensitivity to movement
information specifying social causality.” Cognitive Development, 12, 441–465.
Stern, D. N. (1985). The Interpersonal World of the Infant: A View from Psychoanalysis and
Developmental Psychology. New York: Basic Books.
Stern, D. N. (2000). “New introduction.” The Interpersonal World of the Infant: A View from
Psychoanalysis and Developmental Psychology. New York: Basic Books.
Stern, D. N. (2004). The Present Moment in Psychotherapy and Everyday Life. New York: W. W.
Norton.
Stern, D. N., & Gibbon, J. (1978). “Temporal expectancies of social behavior in mother-
infant play.” In E. B. Thoman (Ed.), Origins of Infant’s Social Responsiveness. Hillsdale, NJ:
Erlbaum.
Stern, D. N., Hofer, L., Haft, W., & Dore, J. (1984). “Affect attunement: The sharing of feeling
states between mother and infant by means of intermodal fluency.” In T. Field & N. Fox
(Eds.), Social Perception in Infancy. Norwood, NJ: Ablex.
Stern, D. N., Sander, L. W., Nahum, J. P., Harrison, A. M., Lyons-Ruth, K., Morgan, A.
C., Bruschweiler-Stern, N., & Tronick, E. Z. (1998). “Non-interpretive mechanisms in
psychoanalytic therapy. The “something more” than interpretation.” (The Boston Change
Process Study Group, Report No. 1.) International Journal of Psychoanalysis, 79, 903–921.
Thompson, E. (2001). “Empathy and consciousness.” Journal of Consciousness Studies, 8 (5–7),
1–32.
Tomasello, M. (2003). Constructing a Language: An Usage-based Theory of Language Acquisition.
Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.
Torras, C. (1985). Temporal-Pattern Learning in Neural Models. Amsterdam: Springer Verlag.
Trevarthen, C. (1979). “Communication and cooperation in early infancy: A description
of primary intersubjectivity.” In M. M. Bullowa (Ed.), Before Speech: The Beginning of
Interpersonal Communication (pp. 321–347). New York: Cambridge University Press.
Trevarthen, C. (1980). “The foundation of intersubjectivity: Development of interpersonal and
cooperative understanding in infants.” In D. Olson (Ed.), The Social Foundation of Language
and Thought (pp. 316–242). New York: Norton.
Trevarthen, C. (1988). “Universal cooperative motives: How infants begin to know the language
and skills of the culture of their parents.” In C. Jahoda & I. M. Lewis (Eds.), Acquiring
Culture (pp. 37–90). Beckenham, Kent: Croom Helm.
Trevarthen, C. (1993). “The self born in intersubjectivity: An infant communicating.” In U.
Neisser (Ed.), The Perceived Self (pp. 121–173). New York: Cambridge University Press.
JB[v.20020404] Prn:25/01/2007; 12:52 F: AICR6802.tex / p.13 (842-887)
Trevarthen, C. (1998). “The nature of motives for human consciousness.” Psychology: The
Journal of the Hellenic Psychological Society, 4 (3), 187–221. (Special issue: The place of
psychology in contemporary sciences, Part 2. T. Velli (Ed.).)
Trevarthen, C. (1999/2000). “Musicality and the intrinsic motive pulse: Evidence from human
psychobiology and infant communication.” Musicae Scientiae: Special Issue, Rhythm,
Musical Narrative, and Origin of Human Communication, 155–211.
Trevarthen, C. (2001). Intrinsic motives for companionship in understanding: Their origin,
development, and significance for infant mental health. Infant Mental Health Journal, 22
(12), 95–131.
Trevarthen, C., & Hubley, P. (1978). “Secondary intersubjectivity: confidence, confides and acts
of meaning in the first year.” In A. Lock (Ed.), Action, Gesture and Symbol (pp. 183–229).
New York: Academic Press.
Tronick, E. Z., BruschweiIer-Stern, N., Harrison, A. M., Lyons-Ruth, K., Morgan, A. C., Nahum,
J. P., Sander, L. W., & Stern, D. N. (1998). “Dyadically expanded states of consciousness and
the process of therapeutic change.” Infant Mental Health Journal, 19, 290–299.
Watson, J. S. (1994). “Detection of self: The perfect algorithm.” In S. Parker, R. Mitchell, & M.
Boccia (Eds.), Self-Awareness in Animals and Humans Developmental Perspectives (pp. 131–
149). Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
Zahavi, D. (1996). “Husserl’s intersubjective transformation of transcendental philosophy.”
Journal of the British Society for Phenomenology, 27, 228–245.
Zahavi, D. (2001). “Beyond empathy. Phenomenological approaches to intersubjectivity.”
Journal of Consciousness studies, 8, 151–167.
JB[v.20020404] Prn:7/03/2007; 16:54 F: AICR6803.tex / p.1 (49-112)
chapter
Frans B. M. de Waal
Yerkes National Primate Research Center, Emory University
Evolution rarely throws out anything. Instead, structures are transformed, mod-
ified, co-opted for other functions, or “tweaked” in another direction. Thus, the
frontal fins of fish became the front limbs of land animals, which over time turned
into hoofs, paws, wings, and hands. They became flippers in mammals that re-
turned to the water. Occasionally, a structure loses all function and becomes super-
fluous, but this is a gradual process, often ending in rudimentary traits rather than
disappearance. Thus, we find tiny vestiges of leg bones under the skin of whales
and remnants of a pelvis in snakes.
This is why to the biologist, a Russian doll is such a satisfying plaything, es-
pecially if it has a historical dimension. I own a doll that shows Russian President
Vladimir Putin on the outside, within whom we discover, in this order, Yeltsin,
Gorbachev, Brezhnev, Kruschev, Stalin, and Lenin. Finding a little Lenin and Stalin
within Putin will hardly surprise most political analysts. The same is true for
biological traits: the old always remains present in the new.
This is relevant to the debate about the origins of empathy and imitation since
psychologists tend to look at the world through different eyes than the biologist.
Psychologists sometimes put our most advanced traits on a pedestal, ignoring or
even denying simpler antecedents. They believe in saltatory change, at least in
relation to our own species. This leads to unlikely origin stories, postulating dis-
continuities with respect to language, which is said to result from a brand new
“module” in the human brain (e.g. Pinker 1995), or with respect to human cogni-
tion, which is viewed as having cultural origins (e.g. Tomasello 1999). True, human
capacities reach dizzying heights, such as when I understand that you understand
that I understand, etcetera. But we are not born with what phenomenologists call
“reiterated empathy.” Both developmentally and evolutionarily, advanced forms of
empathy are preceded by and grow out of more elementary ones. In fact, instead
of language and culture appearing with a Big Bang in our species and then trans-
JB[v.20020404] Prn:7/03/2007; 16:54 F: AICR6803.tex / p.2 (112-160)
Frans B. M. de Waal
forming the way we relate to each other, Greenspan and Shanker (2004) propose
that it is from early emotional connections and nonverbal “proto conversations”
(cf. Trevarthen this volume) between mother and child that language and culture
sprang. Instead of empathy being an endpoint, it may have been the starting point.
Biologists prefer bottom-up over top-down accounts, even though there is def-
initely room for the latter. Once higher order processes have come into existence,
they begin to modify processes at the base. The central nervous system is a good
example of top-down processing, such as the control the prefrontal cortex exerts
over memory. The prefrontal cortex is not the seat of memory, but can “order”
memory retrieval (Tomita et al. 1999). In the same way, culture and language fil-
ter and shape expressions of empathy. The distinction between “origin of ” and
“shaping” is a fundamental one, though, and I will argue here that empathy is the
original, pre-linguistic form of inter-individual linkage that only secondarily has
come under the influence of language and culture. The same argument applies to
imitation, which I will discuss at the end of this essay.
Bottom-up accounts are the opposite of Big Bang theories. They assume conti-
nuity between past and present, child and adult, human and animal, even between
humans and the most primitive mammals. We may assume that empathy evolved
in the context of the parental care obligatory in mammals (Eibl-Eibesfeldt 1971;
MacLean 1985). Signalling their state through smiling and crying, human infants
urge their caregiver to pay attention and come into action (Acebo & Thoman 1995;
Bowlby 1958). This also applies to other primates. The survival value of these in-
teractions is evident from the case of a female chimpanzee, who lost a succession
of infants despite intense positive interest because she was deaf and did not correct
positional problems (such as sitting on the infant, or holding it upside-down) in
response to its distress calls (de Waal 1982).
In mammals, parental care is tied to lactation, which only one gender is ca-
pable of. During the 180 million years of mammalian evolution, females who
responded to their offspring’s needs out-reproduced those who were cold and dis-
tant. Having descended from a long line of mothers who nursed, fed, cleaned, car-
ried, comforted, and defended their young, we should not be surprised, therefore,
by gender differences in human empathy. They appear well before socialization:
the first sign of empathy – one baby crying when it hears another baby cry – is
already more typical of girl babies than boy babies (Hoffman 1977). In an obser-
vational study (based on maternal reports) of children in their second year of life,
girls witnessing distress in others showed more concern than boys (Zahn-Waxler
et al. 1992). According to the literature on adult gender differences, women report
stronger empathic reactions than men (Eisenberg 2000). In line with the above
parental care hypothesis, Taylor (2002) attributes such differences to the “tending
instinct” of women. The flip-side of this gender picture is provided by empathy
JB[v.20020404] Prn:7/03/2007; 16:54 F: AICR6803.tex / p.3 (160-221)
disorders, such as autism, which are four times more common in the human male
than female (Baron-Cohen 2003).
For a human characteristic, such as empathy, that is so pervasive, develops so
early in life (e.g. Hoffman 1975; Zahn-Waxler & Radke-Yarrow 1990), shows such
important neural and physiological correlates (e.g. Adolphs et al. 1994; Rimm-
Kaufman & Kagan 1996; Decety & Chaminade 2003) as well as a genetic substrate
(Plomin et al. 1993), it would be strange indeed if no evolutionary continuity
existed with other mammals. The possibility of empathy and sympathy in other
animals has been largely ignored, however. This is partly due to an excessive fear
of anthropomorphism, which has stifled research into animal emotions (Panksepp
1998; de Waal 1999), and partly to the one-sided portrayal of the natural world as
a place of combat rather than social connectedness.
After a distinctly Huxleyan period of “nature red in tooth and claw” (e.g.
Huxley 1894; Dawkins 1976), evolutionary biologists are returning to Charles
Darwin, who – inspired by the Scottish Enlightenment – regarded sympathy and
even morality as inborn in both humans and other animals. In The Descent of
Man, Darwin (1871: 77) noted that “many animals certainly sympathize with
each other’s distress or danger.” Adopting the same perspective, de Waal (1996)
and Flack and de Waal (2000) have argued that human morality is constructed
from building blocks that we share with other social animals, with empathy being
foremost among them.
Within a bottom-up framework the focus is not so much on the highest levels
of empathy and imitation, but rather on their simplest forms, and how these forms
combine with increased cognition to produce more complex ones. Is it possible to
trace the evolution of empathy and imitation across the phylogenetic tree? Can we
follow these capacities from when they were mere frontal fins, so to speak, to when
they became as versatile as the human hand? How and why did this transformation
take place? The evolution of empathy and imitation runs from shared emotions
and intentions to a gradual “unblurring” of the lines between individuals. The own
experience is increasingly set apart from the vicarious one, even though both reside
within the same brain and body. This process culminates in a cognitive appraisal
of the other’s behaviour and situation: we adopt the other’s perspective.
As in a Russian doll, however, the outer layers never separate from the inner
core. Instead of evolution having replaced simpler forms by advanced ones, the
latter are merely elaborations on the former and remain dependent on them.
JB[v.20020404] Prn:7/03/2007; 16:54 F: AICR6803.tex / p.4 (221-271)
Frans B. M. de Waal
Animal empathy
What is empathy?
Two mechanisms related to empathy are sympathy and personal distress, which
in their social consequences are each other’s opposites. Sympathy is defined as “an
affective response that consists of feelings of sorrow or concern for a distressed or
needy other (rather than the same emotion as the other person). Sympathy is be-
lieved to involve an other-oriented, altruistic motivation” (Eisenberg 2000: 677).
Personal distress, on the other hand, makes the affected party selfishly seek to
alleviate its own distress, which is similar to what it has perceived in the object.
Personal distress is therefore not concerned with the situation of the empathy-
inducing other (Batson 1991). A striking primate example was offered by de Waal
(1996: 46): the screams of a severely punished or rejected infant rhesus monkey
will often cause other infants to approach, embrace, mount or even pile on top
of the victim. Thus, the distress of one infant seems to spread to its peers, which
then seek contact to soothe their own arousal. Inasmuch as personal distress lacks
cognitive evaluation and behavioural complementarity, it does not reach beyond
the level of emotional contagion.
That most modern textbooks on animal cognition (e.g. Shettleworth 1998)
fail to index empathy or sympathy does not mean that these capacities are not
an essential part of animal lives; it only means that they are being overlooked by
a science traditionally focused on individual rather than inter-individual capac-
ities. Tool-use and numerical competence, for instance, are seen as hallmarks of
intelligence, whereas appropriately dealing with others is not. It is obvious, how-
ever, that survival often depends on how animals fare within their group, both in a
cooperative sense (e.g. concerted action, information transfer) and a competitive
sense (e.g. dominance strategies, deception). It is in the social domain, therefore,
that one expects the highest cognitive achievements. Selection must have favoured
mechanisms to evaluate the emotional states of others and to quickly respond to
them. Empathy is precisely such a mechanism.
In human behaviour, there exists a tight relation between empathy and sympa-
thy, and its expression in psychological altruism (e.g. Batson et al. 1987; Eisenberg
& Strayer 1987; Hoffman 1982; Hornblow 1980; Wispé 1986). It is reasonable to
assume that the altruistic and caring responses of other animals, especially mam-
mals, rest on similar mechanisms. When Zahn-Waxler visited homes to find out
how children respond to family-members instructed to feign sadness (sobbing),
pain (crying), or distress (choking), she discovered that children a little over one
year of age already comfort others. Since expressions of sympathy emerge at an
early age in virtually every member of our species, they are as natural as the
first step. An unplanned side-bar to this study, however, was that household pets
appeared as worried as the children by the “distress” of a family-member. They
hovered over them or put their heads in their laps (Zahn-Waxler et al. 1984).
Rooted in attachment and what Harlow named the “affectional system”
(Harlow & Harlow 1965), responses to the emotions of others are commonplace in
JB[v.20020404] Prn:7/03/2007; 16:54 F: AICR6803.tex / p.6 (313-356)
Frans B. M. de Waal
social animals. Thus, behavioural and physiological data suggest emotional conta-
gion in a variety of species (reviewed in Preston & de Waal 2002b; de Waal 2003).
Rats and pigeons display distress in response to the suffering of a conspecific, and
have been observed to terminate stress manipulations affecting others in a vari-
ety of laboratory procedures (Church 1959; Watanabe & Ono 1986). Monkeys are
prepared to starve themselves by not pressing a bar that delivers food if such action
is paired with shock to a conspecific (Masserman et al. 1964).
Although these early studies suggest that, by behaving in certain ways, ani-
mals try to alleviate or prevent distress in others, it remains unclear if spontaneous
responses to distressed conspecifics are explained by (a) distress signals of others
being aversive, (b) personal distress generated through emotional contagion, or
(c) true helping motivations. Work on nonhuman primates has furnished further
information. Some of this evidence is anecdotal, which – albeit a respectable start-
ing point for research – does not permit a choice between alternative hypotheses
(de Waal 1991), but systematic data on empathic reactions exists as well.
De Waal (1996, 1997) has suggested that apart from emotional connectedness apes
have an appreciation of the other’s situation and a degree of perspective-taking.
So, the main difference with monkeys is not in empathy per se, but in the cognitive
overlays, which allow apes to adopt the other’s viewpoint. One striking report in
JB[v.20020404] Prn:7/03/2007; 16:54 F: AICR6803.tex / p.7 (356-407)
this regard concerns a bonobo female empathizing with a bird at Twycross Zoo, in
England:
One day, Kuni captured a starling. Out of fear that she might molest the stunned
bird, which appeared undamaged, the keeper urged the ape to let it go. . . . Kuni
picked up the starling with one hand and climbed to the highest point of the
highest tree where she wrapped her legs around the trunk so that she had both
hands free to hold the bird. She then carefully unfolded its wings and spread them
wide open, one wing in each hand, before throwing the bird as hard she could
towards the barrier of the enclosure. Unfortunately, it fell short and landed onto
the bank of the moat where Kuni guarded it for a long time against a curious
juvenile. (de Waal 1997: 156)
What Kuni did would obviously have been inappropriate towards a member of her
own species. Having seen birds in flight many times, she seemed to have a notion
of what would be good for a bird, thus offering us an anthropoid version of the
empathic capacity so enduringly described by Adam Smith (1759: 10) as “chang-
ing places in fancy with the sufferer.” Perhaps the most striking example of this
capacity is a chimpanzee who, as in the original Theory-of Mind (ToM) experi-
ments of Premack and Woodruff (1978), seemed to understand the intentions of
another and provided specific help:
During one winter at the Arnhem Zoo, after cleaning the hall and before releas-
ing the chimps, the keepers hosed out all rubber tires in the enclosure and hung
them one by one on a horizontal log extending from the climbing frame. One day,
Krom was interested in a tire in which water had stayed behind. Unfortunately,
this particular tire was at the end of the row, with six or more heavy tires hanging
in front of it. Krom pulled and pulled at the one she wanted but couldn’t remove
it from the log. She pushed the tire backward, but there it hit the climbing frame
and couldn’t be removed either. Krom worked in vain on this problem for over
ten minutes, ignored by everyone, except Jakie, a seven-year-old Krom had taken
care of as a juvenile.
Immediately after Krom gave up and walked away, Jakie approached the scene.
Without hesitation he pushed the tires one by one off the log, beginning with the
front one, followed by the second in the row, and so on, as any sensible chimp
would. When he reached the last tire, he carefully removed it so that no water was
lost, carrying it straight to his aunt, placing it upright in front of her. Krom ac-
cepted his present without any special acknowledgment, and was already scooping
up water with her hand when Jakie left. (adapted from de Waal 1996)
That Jakie assisted his aunt is not so unusual. What is special is that he correctly
guessed what Krom was after. He grasped his aunt’s goals. Such so-called “targeted
helping” is typical of apes, but rare or absent in most other animals. It is defined
as altruistic behaviour tailored to the specific needs of the other even in novel
JB[v.20020404] Prn:7/03/2007; 16:54 F: AICR6803.tex / p.8 (407-487)
Frans B. M. de Waal
situations, such as the highly publicized case of Binti-Jua, a female gorilla who
rescued a human child at the Brookfield Zoo, in Chicago (de Waal 1996, 1999).
It is important to stress the incredible strength of the ape’s helping response,
which makes these animals take great risks on behalf of others. Whereas in a recent
debate about the origins of morality, Kagan (2000) took it as self-evident that a
chimpanzee would never jump into a cold lake to save another, it may help to
quote Goodall (1990: 213) on this issue:
In some zoos, chimpanzees are kept on man-made islands, surrounded by water-
filed moats . . . Chimpanzees cannot swim and, unless they are rescued, will drown
if they fall into deep water. Despite this, individuals have sometimes made heroic
efforts to save companions from drowning – and were sometimes successful. One
adult male lost his life as he tried to rescue a small infant whose incompetent
mother had allowed it to fall into the water. (Goodall 1990: 213)
The only other animals with a similar array of helping tendencies are dolphins and
elephants. This evidence, too, is largely descriptive (dolphins: Caldwell & Caldwell
1966; Connor & Norris 1982; elephants: Moss 1988; Payne 1998), yet here again
it is hard to accept as coincidental that scientists who have watched these animals
for any length of time have numerous such stories, whereas scientists who have
watched other animals have few, if any.
Consolation behaviour
A difference between monkey and ape empathy is also evident in systematic stud-
ies of a behaviour known as “consolation,” first documented by de Waal and van
Roosmalen (1979). Consolation is defined as friendly, reassuring contact directed
by an uninvolved bystander at one of the combatants in a previous aggressive in-
cident. For example, a third-party goes over to the loser of a fight and gently puts
an arm around his or her shoulders (Figure 1). The advantages of consolation for
the actor are unclear. The actor could probably walk away from the scene without
any negative consequences.
Chimpanzee consolation is well-quantified. De Waal and van Roosmalen
(1979) based their conclusions on an analysis of hundreds of post-conflict ob-
servations, and a replication by de Waal and Aureli (1996) included an even larger
sample in which the authors sought to test two relatively simple predictions. If
third-party contacts indeed serve to alleviate the distress of conflict participants,
these contacts should be directed more at recipients of aggression than at aggres-
sors, and more at recipients of intense than of mild aggression. Comparing third-
party contact rates with baseline levels, we found support for both predictions
(Figure 2).
JB[v.20020404] Prn:7/03/2007; 16:54 F: AICR6803.tex / p.9 (487-504)
Consolation has thus far been demonstrated in great apes only. When de Waal
and Aureli (1996) set out to apply exactly the same observation protocols as used
on chimpanzees to detect consolation in macaques, they failed to find any. De-
spite numerous attempts to demonstrate it, consolation has thus far not been
found in monkeys (Watts et al. 2000). One recent monkey study even failed to find
alleviation of another’s distress in the one relationship category in which one defi-
nitely would expect it: between mother and offspring (Schino et al. 2004). Mother
macaques do not provide spontaneous reassurance to distraught offspring. This
came as a surprise, because reconciliation studies, which employ essentially the
same research methodology, have demonstrated reconciliation in species after
species. Why, then, is consolation restricted just to humans and apes?
Targeted helping and consolation may require a distinction between self and
other that allows the other’s situation to be distinguished from one’s own while
maintaining the emotional link that motivates behaviour. Possibly, one cannot
JB[v.20020404] Prn:7/03/2007; 16:54 F: AICR6803.tex / p.10 (504-529)
Frans B. M. de Waal
Figure 2. Graph showing the rate with which third parties contact victims of aggression in
chimpanzees, comparing recipients of serious and mild aggression. Especially in the first
two minutes following an incident, recipients of serious aggression receive more contacts
than baseline. After de Waal and Aureli (1996).
The literature includes accounts of empathy as a cognitive affair, even to the point
that apes, let alone other animals, probably lack it (Povinelli 1998; Hauser 2000).
This view equates empathy with mental state attribution and ToM. The opposite
position has recently been defended, however, in relation to autistic children. Con-
tra earlier assumptions that autism reflects a ToM deficit (Baron-Cohen 2000),
autism is noticeable well before the age of 4 years at which ToM typically emerges.
Williams et al. (2001) argue that the main deficit of autism concerns the socio-
affective level, which in turn negatively impacts sophisticated down-stream forms
of inter-personal perception, such as ToM. So, ToM is seen as a derived trait, and
the authors urge more attention for its antecedents (see also Baron-Cohen 2003,
2004).
Preston and de Waal (2002a) propose that at the core of the empathic capac-
ity is a relatively simple mechanism that provides an observer (the “subject”) with
access to the subjective state of another (the “object”) through the subject’s own
neural and bodily representations. When the subject attends to the object’s state,
the subject’s neural representations of similar states are automatically activated.
The closer and more similar subject and object, the more perceiving the object
will activate matching peripheral motor and autonomic responses in the subject
(e.g. changes in heart rate, skin conductance, facial expression, body posture). This
activation allows the subject to get “under the skin” of the object, sharing its feel-
ings and needs, which in turn fosters sympathy, compassion, and helping. Preston
and de Waal’s (2002a) Perception-Action Mechanism (PAM) fits Damasio’s (1994)
somatic marker hypothesis of emotions as well as recent evidence for a link at the
cellular level between perception and action (e.g. “mirror neurons,” di Pellegrino
et al. 1992; Fadiga & Craighero this volume; Ferrari & Gallese this volume).
The idea that perception and action share common representations is any-
thing but new: it goes as far back as the first treatise on Einfühlung, the German
concept translated into English as “empathy” (Wispé 1991). When Lipps (1903)
spoke of Einfühlung, which literally means “feeling into,” he speculated about in-
nere Nachahmung (inner mimicry) of another’s feelings along the same lines as
proposed by the PAM. Accordingly, empathy is a routine involuntary process, as
demonstrated by electromyographic studies of invisible muscle contractions in
people’s faces in response to pictures of human facial expressions. These reac-
tions are fully automated, occurring even when we are unaware of what we saw
(Dimberg et al. 2000). Accounts of empathy as a higher cognitive process neglect
such gut-level reactions, which are far too rapid to be under conscious control.
Perception-action mechanisms are well-known for motor perception (Prinz &
Hommel 2002), causing researchers to assume similar processes to underlie emo-
tion perception (Gallese 2001; Wolpert et al. 2001). Data suggest that observing
JB[v.20020404] Prn:7/03/2007; 16:54 F: AICR6803.tex / p.12 (573-619)
Frans B. M. de Waal
Figure 3. The Russian doll model of intersubjectivity. Empathy covers all processes lead-
ing to related emotional states in subject and object, with at its core the perception-action
mechanism (PAM) of Preston and de Waal (2002a), such as the tendency to match the
other’s emotional state. Higher levels of empathy build upon this hard-wired socio-affective
basis, such as cognitive empathy (i.e. assessment of the reasons for the other’s emotions – a
requirement for targeted helping) and adoption of the other’s perspective. On the copying
side (left), the emphasis is on matching the other’s behavior through mimicry, sharing the
other’s goals and intentions, and assessment of the other’s methods to reach a particular
goal, as in full-blown imitation. It is assumed that the outer layers of the Russian doll can-
not exist without its inner ones, and that its core processes underlie all manifestations of
intersubjectivity.
Figure 4. Cognitive empathy (i.e. emotional empathy combined with appraisal of the
other’s situation) allows for aid tailored to the other’s needs. In this case a mother chim-
panzee reaches out to help her son out of tree after he screamed and begged (see hand
gesture). Photograph by the author.
at a loss about what moves others. At the core of the Russian doll we find PAM-
induced emotional contagion around which cognitive empathy and attribution
are constructed. Cognitive empathy implies appraisal of another’s predicament or
situation (cf. de Waal 1996). The subject not only responds to the signals emitted
by the object, but seeks to understand the reasons for these signals, looking for
clues in the other’s behaviour and situation. Cognitive empathy makes it possible
to furnish targeted helping that takes the specific needs of the other into account
(Figure 4). These responses go well beyond emotional contagion, yet they would
be hard to explain without the motivation activated by the emotional component.
Without this core component we would be as disconnected as Mr. Spock in Star
Trek, constantly wondering why others feel what they say they feel.
JB[v.20020404] Prn:7/03/2007; 16:54 F: AICR6803.tex / p.14 (647-684)
Frans B. M. de Waal
Whereas monkeys (and many other social mammals) clearly seem to possess
emotional contagion and some forms of targeted helping, the latter phenomenon
is not nearly as robust as in the great apes. For example, at Jigokudani monkey
park, in Japan, first-time mother macaques are kept out of the hot water springs by
park wardens because of the experience that these females will accidentally drown
their infants. They fail to pay attention to them when submerging themselves in the
ponds (de Waal 1996). This is something monkey mothers apparently learn with
time, showing that they do not automatically take their offspring’s perspective. De
Waal (1996) ascribed their behavioural change to “learned adjustment,” setting
it apart from cognitive empathy, which is more typical of apes and humans. Ape
mothers respond immediately and usually appropriately to the specific needs of
their offspring. They are, for example, very careful to keep them away from water,
rushing over to pull them away as soon as they get too close.
In conclusion, empathy is not an all-or-nothing phenomenon: it covers a wide
range of emotional linkage patterns, from the very simple and automatic to the
very sophisticated. It seems logical to first try to understand the basic forms, which
are widespread indeed, before addressing the variations that cognitive evolution
has constructed on top of this foundation.
The same PAM underlying emotional state-matching and empathy likely provides
the basis for motor mimicry and imitation (Figure 3). We know from mirror-
neuron studies that monkeys not only make the actions of others their own (i.e.
mirror neurons respond similarly during a performed action, such as grasping,
and a perceived one in others), but do the same for chains of actions and their
predicted outcomes. In other words, the intentions of others, instead of being
cognitively understood, seem to be automatically encoded from observed motor
sequences (Fogassi et al. 2005; Fadiga & Craighero this volume). When reading
one another, monkeys thus adopt an “intentional stance” (cf. Dennett 1987).
This predisposition to be in tune with others and their intentions has high sur-
vival value for group-living animals, which need to synchronize activities. Imagine
a group in which every individual would eat and sleep and play at different times:
group coordination would become impossible. Primates sleep when others sleep,
play when others play, and forage or hunt when others forage or hunt. Known as
“social facilitation,” experiments show that satiated primates begin eating again
when they see others eat (Addessi & Visalberghi 2001; Ferrari et al. 2005), scratch
themselves when they see others scratch themselves (Nakayama 2004), and yawn
in response to a video of a yawning conspecific (Anderson et al. 2004). Novel be-
haviour is copied, too, at least by apes. Examples are the imitation of a specific
JB[v.20020404] Prn:7/03/2007; 16:54 F: AICR6803.tex / p.15 (684-758)
limping walk by juvenile group mates of an injured adult male (de Waal 1982)
and successful “Do as I Do” experiments involving human models (Custance et al.
1995; Myowa-Yamakoshi & Matsuzawa 1999).
De Waal (1998) proposed “identification” with others as the basis of imitation.
Similar to Preston and de Waal’s (2002a) characterization of PAM, identification
entails bodily mapping the self onto the other (or the other onto the self), re-
sulting in feeling one with another. One thus becomes vicariously one with the
other. Bodily similarity – such as with members of the own gender and species –
likely enhances shared representation, hence identification. It is hardly surpris-
ing, therefore, that after the initial scepticism about imitation in primates, based
on their failure to copy complex human actions (e.g. Tomasello et al. 1993), the
first convincing evidence came from a study using conspecific models (Voekl &
Huber 2000). It is also not surprising that when young chimpanzees learn to use
a wand to fish for ants, daughters copy their mothers more precisely than sons
(Lonsdorf et al. 2004). Identification with others seems so central that de Waal
(2001) proposed that the cultural transmission of habits and skills is based on
conformism with those to whom one feels close. Instead of cultural transmission
being driven by reward-based learning, as assumed by learning psychologists (e.g.
Galef 1990), it seems motivated by a desire to be and act like others (see also
Matsuzawa et al. 2001). Rewards help, but are not critical: the driving force of
observational learning rather seems socio-emotional. There are many examples of
socially learned habits that provide no extrinsic rewards during most of the learn-
ing period, and sometimes no such rewards ever (reviewed in de Waal 2001). This
theory of Bonding- and Identification-Based Observational Learning (BIOL) is
currently being tested by my research team with encouraging initial results.
The cooperative nature of primates implies that they read the emotions and
intentions of others, coordinate with them, and spontaneously help each other
achieve shared goals. Thus, chimpanzees regularly recruit each other’s support
when chasing off an opponent (de Waal & van Hooff 1981), hold up a pole as
“ladder” for another to reach out-of-reach goals (Menzel 1972; de Waal 1982),
or jointly transport heavy objects (Figure 5).1 Wild chimpanzee males could not
possibly hunt together without the same ability to read each other, which prob-
ably also applies to other highly coordinated hunters, such as killer whales and
wolves. This is not to say that animals help each other all the time. Even if they
automatically read emotions and intentions, this information is not necessarily
translated into action. Moreover, if action does result, it does not always bene-
fit the other. Animals can use the same understanding of others to out-compete or
deceive them. They may see another individual heading for food, and make sure to
get there first. However, we should not confuse their understanding of others with
the specific application of this information, which varies with social relationships
and circumstances.
JB[v.20020404] Prn:7/03/2007; 16:54 F: AICR6803.tex / p.16 (758-776)
Frans B. M. de Waal
Figure 5ab. Cooperation and coordination come naturally to primates. It involves an ap-
praisal of the other’s behaviour and intentions, such as here by a young chimpanzee who
has joined an unrelated adult to “help” her move a heavy drum from one location to
another. Afterwards, the two sat together on the drum. Photographs by the author.
Even if the literature on empathy and imitation often emphasizes the cogni-
tive side of these abilities – especially in the case of humans – Hoffman (1981: 79)
rightly noted that “humans must be equipped biologically to function effectively
in many social situations without undue reliance on cognitive processes.” It could
not be otherwise. If each time we saw someone perform an activity or express an
emotion we would need to mentally imagine their situation and objectives so as
to grasp the meaning of their behaviour, we would be far too slow to respond and
perhaps, after a while, far too tired, too. Luckily, we grasp the meaning of the be-
haviour of others based on bodily representations that come to us without any
conscious effort. We are hard-wired to connect to those around us, and so are
many other animals.
Note
. The Living Links website features footage of Crawford’s (1937) classical experiment on ape
cooperation, which shows a high degree of coordination as well as the willingness of an unmoti-
vated partner to help a motivated one achieve its goals: http://www.emory.edu/LIVING_LINKS/
crawfordvideo.html
JB[v.20020404] Prn:7/03/2007; 16:54 F: AICR6803.tex / p.17 (776-876)
References
Acebo, C., & Thoman, E. B. (1995). “Role of infant crying in the early mother-infant dialogue.”
Physiology & Behavior, 57, 541–547.
Addessi, E., & Visalberghi, E. (2001). “Social facilitation of eating novel food in tufted capuchin
monkeys (Cebus apella): Input provided by group members and responses affected in the
observer.” Animal Cognition, 4 297–303.
Adolphs, R., Cahill, L., Schul, R., & Babinsky, R. (1997). “Impaired declarative memory for
emotional material following bilateral amygdala damage in humans.” Learning & Memory,
4, 291–300.
Adolphs, R., Damasio, H., Tranel, D., Cooper, G., & Damasio, A. R. (2000). “A role for
somatosensory cortices in the visual recognition of emotion as revealed by three-
dimensional lesion mapping.” Journal of Neuroscience, 20, 2683–2690.
Adolphs, R., Tranel, D., Damasio, H., & Damasio, A. R. (1994). “Impaired recognition of
emotion in facial expressions following bilateral damage to the human amygdala.” Nature,
372, 669–672.
Anderson, J. R., & Gallup, G. G. (1999). “Self-recognition in nonhuman primates: Past and
future challenges.” In M. Haug & R. E. Whalen (Eds.), Animal Models of Human Emotion
and Cognition (pp. 175–194). American Psychological Association (APA).
Anderson, J. R., Myowa-Yamakoshi, M., & Matsuzawa, T. (2004). “Contagious yawning in
chimpanzees.” Proc. R. Soc. Lond. B (Suppl.), 271, S468–S470.
Baron-Cohen, S. (2000). “Theory of mind and autism: A fifteen year review.” In S. Baron-Cohen,
H. Tager-Flusberg, & D. J. Cohen (Eds.), Understanding Other Minds (pp. 2–20). Oxford:
Oxford University Press.
Baron-Cohen, S. (2003). The Essential Difference. New York: Basic Books.
Baron-Cohen, S. (2004). “Sex differences in social development: Lessons from autism.” In L. A.
Leavitt & D. M. B. Hall (Eds.), Social and Moral Development: Emerging Evidence on the
Toddler Years (pp. 125–141). Johnson & Johnson Pediatric Institute.
Batson, C. D. (1991). The Altruism Question: Toward a Social-Psychological Answer. Hillsdale,
NJ: Erlbaum.
Batson, C. D., Fultz, J., & Schoenrade, P. A. (1987). “Distress and empathy: Two qualitatively
distinct vicarious emotions with different motivational consequences.” Journal of
Personality, 55, 19–39.
Bischof-Köhler, D. (1988). “Über den Zusammenhang von Empathie und der Fähigkeit sich im
Spiegel zu erkennen.” Schweizerische Zeitschrift für Psychologie, 47, 147–159.
Bowlby, J. (1958). “The nature of the child’s tie to his mother.” International Journal of Psycho-
Analysis, 39, 0–373.
Caldwell, M. C., & Caldwell, D. K. (1966). “Epimeletic (care-giving) behavior in Cetacea.” In
K. S. Norris (Ed.), Whales, Dolphins, and Porpoises (pp. 755–789). Berkeley, CA: University
of California Press.
Carr, L., Iacoboni, M., Dubeau, M. C., Mazziotta, J. C., & Lenzi, G. L. (2003). “Neural
mechanisms of empathy in humans: A relay from neural systems for imitation to limbic
areas.” Proceedings from the National Academy of Sciences, 100, 5497–5502.
Church, R. M. (1959). “Emotional reactions of rats to the pain of others.” Journal of Comparative
& Physiological Psychology, 52, 132–134.
Connor, R. C., & Norris, K. S. (1982). “Are dolphins reciprocal altruists?” American Naturalist,
119, 358–372.
JB[v.20020404] Prn:7/03/2007; 16:54 F: AICR6803.tex / p.18 (876-994)
Frans B. M. de Waal
Eisenberg, N., & Strayer, J. (1987). Empathy and its Development. New York: Cambridge
University Press.
Ekman, P. (1982). Emotion in the Human Face (2nd ed.). Cambridge: Cambridge University
Press.
Ferrari, P. F., Maiolinia, C., Addessi, E., Fogassi, L., & Visalbergh I. E. (2005). “The observation
and hearing of eating actions activates motor programs related to eating in macaque
monkeys.” Behavioural Brain Research, 161, 95–101.
Flack, J. C., & de Waal, F. B. M. (2000). “ ‘Any animal whatever:’ Darwinian building blocks of
morality in monkeys and apes.” Journal of Consciousness Studies, 7, 1–29.
Fogassi, L., Ferrari, P. F., Gesierich, B., Rozzi, S., Chersi F., & Rizzolatti, G. (2005). “Parietal lobe:
From action organization to intention understanding.” Science, 308, 662–667.
Galef, B. G. (1990). “The question of animal culture.” Human Nature, 3, 157–178.
Gallese, V. (2001). “The ‘shared manifold’ hypothesis: From mirror neurons to empathy.” In
E. Thompson (Ed.), Between ourselves: Second-person issues in the study of consciousness
(pp. 33–50). Thorverton, UK: Imprint Academic.
Gallup, G. G. (1982). “Self-awareness and the emergence of mind in primates.” American Journal
of Primatology, 2, 237–248.
Goodall, J. (1990). Through a Window: My Thirty Years with the Chimpanzees of Gombe. Boston:
Houghton Mifflin.
Greenspan, S. I., & Shanker, S. G. (2004). The First Idea. Cambridge, MA: Da Capo Press.
Harlow, H. F., & Harlow, M. K. (1965). “The affectional systems.” In A. M. Schrier, H. F. Harlow,
& F. Stollnitz (Eds.), Behavior of Nonhuman Primates (pp. 287–334). New York: Academic
Press.
Hatfield, E., Cacioppo, J. T., & Rapson, R. L. (1993). “Emotional contagion. Current directions.”
Psychological Science, 2, 96–99.
Hauser, M. D. (2000). Wild Minds: What Animals Really Think. New York: Holt.
Hoffman, M. L. (1975). “Developmental synthesis of affect and cognition and its implications
for altruistic motivation.” Developmental Psychology, 11, 607–622.
Hoffman, M. L. (1977). “Sex differences in empathy and related behaviors.” Psychol. Bull., 84,
712–722.
Hoffman, M. L. (1981). “Perspectives on the difference between understanding people and
understanding things: The role of affect.” In J. H. Flavell & L. Ross (Eds.), Social Cognitive
Development (pp. 67–81). Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
Hoffman, M. L. (1982). “Affect and moral development.” New Directions for Child Development,
16, 83–103.
Hornblow, A. R. (1980). “The study of empathy.” New Zealand Psychologist, 9, 19–28.
Huxley, T. H. (1989 [1894]). Evolution and Ethics. Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press.
Kagan, J. (2000). “Human morality is distinctive.” Journal of Consciousness Studies, 7, 46–48.
Ladygina-Kohts, N. N. (2001 [1935]). Infant Chimpanzee and Human Child: A Classic 1935
Comparative Study of Ape Emotions and Intelligence. F. B. M. de Waal (Ed.). New York:
Oxford University Press.
Levenson, R. W., & Reuf, A. M. (1992). “Empathy: A physiological substrate.” Journal of
Personality and Social Psychology, 63, 234–246.
Lipps, T. (1903). “Einfühlung, innere Nachahmung und Organempfindung.” Archiv für die
gesamte Psychologie, 1, 465–519.
Lonsdorf, E. V., Eberly, L. E., & Pusey, A. E. (2004). “Sex differences in learning in chimpanzees.”
Nature, 428, 715–716.
JB[v.20020404] Prn:7/03/2007; 16:54 F: AICR6803.tex / p.20 (1110-1213)
Frans B. M. de Waal
MacLean, P. D. (1985). “Brain evolution relating to family, play, and the separation call.” Archives
of General Psychiatry, 42, 405–417.
Masserman, J., Wechkin, M. S., & Terris, W. (1964). “Altruistic behavior in rhesus monkeys.”
Am. J. Psychiatry, 121, 584–585.
Matsuzawa, T., Biro, D., Humle, T., Inoue-Nakamura, N., Tonooka, R., & Yamakoshi, G. (2001).
“Emergence of a culture in wild chimpanzees: Education by master-apprenticeship.” In T.
Matsuzawa (Ed.), Primate Origins of Human Cognition and Behavior (pp. 557–574). Tokyo:
Springer Verlag.
Menzel, E. (1972). “Spontaneous invention of ladders in a group of young chimpanzees.” Folia
primatologica, 17, 87–106.
Moss, C. (1988). Elephant Memories: Thirteen Years in the Life of an Elephant Family. New York:
Fawcett Columbine.
Myowa-Yamakoshi, G., & Matsuzawa, T. (1999). “Factors influencing imitation of manipulatory
actions in chimpanzees.” Journal of Comparative Psychology, 113, 128–136.
Nakayama, K. (2004). “Observing conspecifics scratching induces a contagion of scratching in
japanese monkeys (Macaca fuscata).” Journal of Comparative Psychology, 118, 20–24.
O’Connell, S. M. (1995). “Empathy in chimpanzees: Evidence for theory of mind?” Primates, 36,
397–410.
Panksepp, J. (1998). Affective Neuroscience: The Foundations of Human and Animal Emotions.
Oxford: Oxford University Press.
Payne, K. (1998). Silent Thunder. New York: Simon & Schuster.
Pinker, S. (1994). The Language Instinct. New York: Morrow.
Plomin, R. et al. (1993). “Genetic change and continuities from fourteen to twenty months: The
MacArthur longitudinal twin study.” Child Development, 64, 1354–1376.
Povinelli, D. J. (1998). “Can animals empathize? Maybe not.” Scientific American http://
geowords.com/lostlinks/b36/7.htm
Premack, D., & Woodruff, G. (1978). “Does the chimpanzee have a theory of mind?” Behavioral
and Brain Sciences, 1, 515–526.
Preston, S. D., & de Waal, F. B. M. (2002a). “Empathy: Its ultimate and proximate bases.”
Behavioral & Brain Sciences, 25, 1–72.
Preston, S. D., & de Waal, F. B. M. (2002b). “The communication of emotions and the possibility
of empathy in animals.” In S. G. Post, L. G. Underwood, J. P. Schloss, & W. B. Hurlbut (Eds.),
Altruistic Love: Science, Philosophy, and Religion in Dialogue (pp. 284–308). Oxford: Oxford
University Press.
Prinz, W., & Hommel, B. (2002). Common Mechanisms in Perception and Action. Oxford: Oxford
University Press.
Reiss, D., & Marino, L. (2001). “Mirror self-recognition in the bottlenose dolphin: A case of
cognitive convergence.” Proceedings of the National Academy of Science, 98, 5937–5942.
Rimm-Kaufman, S. E., & Kagan, J. (1996). “The psychological significance of changes in skin
temperature.” Motivation and Emotion, 20, 63–78.
Schino, G., Geminiani, S., Rosati, L., & Aureli, F. (2004). “Behavioral and emotional response
of Japanese macaque (Macaca fuscata) mothers after their offspring receive an aggression.”
Journal of Comparative Psychology, 118, 340–346.
Shettleworth, S. J. (1998). Cognition, Evolution, and Behavior. New York: Oxford University
Press.
Singer, T., Seymour, B., O’Doherty, J., Kaube, H., Dolan, R. J., & Frith, C. D. (2004). “Empathy
for pain involves the affective but not sensory components of pain.” Science, 303, 1157–
1162.
JB[v.20020404] Prn:7/03/2007; 16:54 F: AICR6803.tex / p.21 (1213-1304)
Smith, A. (1937 [1759]). A Theory of Moral Sentiments. New York: Modern Library.
Taylor, S. E. (2002). The Tending Instinct. New York: Holt.
Tomasello, M. (1999). The Cultural Origins of Human Cognition. Cambridge, MA: Harvard
University Press.
Tomasello, M., Kruger, A. C., & Rander, H. H. (1993). “Cultural learning.” Behavioral & Brain
Sciences, 16, 495–552.
Tomita, H., Ohbayashi, M., Nakahara, K., Hasegawa, I., & Miyashita, Y. (1999). “Top-down
signal from prefrontal cortex in executive control of memory retrieval.” Nature, 401, 699–
703.
van Hooff, J. A. R. A. M. (1967). “The facial displays of the Catarrhine monkeys and apes.” In D.
Morris (Ed.), Primate Ethology (pp. 7–68). Chicago: Aldine.
Voelkl, B., & Huber, L. (2000). “True imitation in marmosets.” Animal Behaviour, 60, 195–202.
Watanabe, S., & Ono, K. (1986). “An experimental analysis of “empathic” response: Effects of
pain reactions of pigeon upon other pigeon’s operant behavior.” Behavioural Processes, 13,
269–277.
Watts, D. P., Colmenares, F., & Arnold, K. (2000). “Redirection, consolation, and male policing:
How targets of aggression interact with bystanders.” In F. Aureli & F. B. M. de Waal (Eds.),
Natural Conflict Resolution (pp. 281–301). Berkeley, CA: University of California Press.
Wicker, B., Keysers, C., Plailly, J., Royet„ J. P., Gallese, V., & Rizzolatti, G. (2003). “Disgusted in
my insula: The common neural basis of seeing and feeling disgust leads to a propositional
representation of the inferred state of disgust.” Neuron, 40, 655–664.
Williams, J. H. G., Whiten, A., Suddendorf, T., & Perrett, D. I. (2001). “Imitation, mirror
neurons and autism.” Neuroscience and Biobehavioral Reviews, 25, 287–295.
Wispé, L. (1986). “The distinction between sympathy and empathy: To call forth a concept, a
word is needed.” Journal of Personality & Social Psychology, 50, 314–321.
Wispé, L. (1991). The Psychology of Sympathy. New York: Plenum.
Wolpert, D. M., Ghahramani, Z., & Flanagan, J. R. (2001). “Perspectives and problems in motor
learning.” Trends in Cognitive Sciences, 5 487–494.
Yerkes, R. M. (1925). Almost Human. New York: Century.
Zahn-Waxler, C., & Radke-Yarrow, M. (1990). “The origins of empathic concern.” Motivation
and Emotion, 14, 107–130.
Zahn-Waxler, C., Hollenbeck, B., & Radke-Yarrow, M. (1984). “The origins of empathy and
altruism.” In M. W. Fox & L. D. Mickley (Eds.), Advances in Animal Welfare Science (pp. 21–
39). Washington, DC: Humane Society of the United States.
Zahn-Waxler, C., Radke-Yarrow, M., Wagner, E., & Chapman, M. (1992). “Development of
concern for others.” Developmental Psychology, 28, 126–136.
JB[v.20020404] Prn:26/10/2006; 15:58 F: AICR68P2.tex / p.1 (48-76)
chapter
Introduction
About ten years ago Rizzolatti and colleagues discovered a class of premotor visuo-
motor neurons, named mirror neurons, that discharge not only when the monkey
executes goal-related hand actions like grasping objects, but also when observing
other individuals (monkeys or humans) executing similar actions (di Pellegrino
et al. 1992; Gallese et al. 1996; Rizzolatti et al. 1996). Neurons with similar prop-
erties were later discovered in a sector of the posterior parietal cortex reciprocally
connected with area F5 (PF mirror neurons, see Rizzolatti et al. 2001; Gallese et al.
2002).
The most interesting property of mirror neurons consists in the fact that in
most of them there is a good congruence between the seen and the executed ac-
tions effective in activating them. Because of this congruence, it was hypothesized
that mirror neurons, by matching action observation with action execution, al-
low understanding of actions made by others. This latter capacity is not simply
limited to recognition of motor patterns, but it extends also to the goal of the ob-
served action. Every time we observe an action made by another individual, we are
able to understand its goal because the observed action is matched on our internal
representation of it, which, in turn, is endowed with the knowledge of the goal.
Further studies carried out in our lab corroborated and extended our original
hypothesis. We showed that F5 mirror neurons are also activated when the final
critical part of the observed action, that is, the hand-object interaction, is hidden
(Umiltà et al. 2001). In a second study we showed that a particular class of F5
JB[v.20020404] Prn:25/01/2007; 14:25 F: AICR6804.tex / p.3 (178-260)
mirror neurons, “audio-visual mirror neurons”, can be driven not only by action
execution and observation, but also by the sound produced by the same action
(Kohler et al. 2002). These neurons instantiate semblant informational content
at quite an “abstract” level. If the various modes of presentation of events as in-
trinsically different as sounds, images, or voluntary body actions, nevertheless are
bound together within the same neural substrate, what we have is a mechanism in-
stantiating a form of conceptualization. This perspective can be extended to other
parts of the sensory-motor system (see Gallese & Lakoff 2005).
In a recent study (Ferrari et al. 2005a) it has been shown that mirror neurons
can generalize the goal of an action to actions that are not in the monkey motor
repertoire such as those made with a tool. What is interesting here is that what is
coded, at a very abstract level, is the goal of an action even though the monkey is
not able to reproduce it. The fact that the visual descriptions of actions outside the
motor repertoire can map onto one’s own motor system supports the idea that the
sensory description of observed social stimuli is strongly related (embodied), and
somehow interpreted, to the observer’s own body sensory-motor knowledge.
So far, the capability of monkey mirror neurons to connect the observed in-
dividual with the observer seems to configure a mechanism that can be useful in
understanding actions but with no necessity to directly interact with another indi-
vidual. It is as if we were watching a TV movie in which we observe and interpret
the events that unfold in a story. However, the mirror neuron story becomes more
complex in the light of the recent findings of a new category of mirror neurons
that are related to the execution/observation matching system for mouth actions
(Ferrari et al. 2003). Most mouth mirror neurons, as they have been named, re-
spond to observation of ingestive actions such as biting, tearing with the teeth,
sucking, licking, etc. An example of an “ingestive” mouth mirror neuron is shown
in Figure 1, A. They show the same specificity of hand mirror neurons. They do
not respond to simple object presentation or to mouth mimed actions.
An interesting finding is that a small percentage of mouth-related mirror
neurons discharge during the observation of intransitive, communicative facial
actions performed by the experimenter in front of the monkey (“communicative
mouth mirror neurons”), such as lips-smacking, lips protrusion or tongue pro-
trusion. Figure 1, B and C shows two examples of “communicative” mouth mirror
neurons. The motor response of mouth communicative mirror neurons is more
complex. In those neurons in which it was possible to test the motor response
during monkey execution of communicative actions, there was a clear activation
(Figure 1, C). However, most neurons responded also when the monkey executed
ingestive actions. It has been hypothesized that the presence of mouth mirror
neurons is indicative of a system originated for understanding transitive mouth ac-
JB[v.20020404] Prn:25/01/2007; 14:25 F: AICR6804.tex / p.4 (260-260)
Figure 1. Examples of mouth mirror neurons. In each panel the rasters and the histograms
represent the neuron response during a single experimental condition. The histogram rep-
resents the average of ten trials. Rasters and histograms are aligned with the moment in
which the mouth or the hand of the experimenter (observation conditions) or of the
monkey (motor conditions) touched the food or when the food is abruptly presented
(presentation conditions). During observation of communicative actions the rasters and
histograms alignment was made with the moment in which the action was fully expressed.
Ordinates: spikes/sec; abscissae: time; bin width: 20 ms. A. Ingestive mouth mirror neuron.
JB[v.20020404] Prn:25/01/2007; 14:25 F: AICR6804.tex / p.5 (260-301)
Figure 1. Top. The experimenter approaches with his mouth the food held on a support,
grasps it with the teeth and holds it. Middle. The experimenter grasps with the hand a piece
of food placed on a support and holds it. Bottom. The experimenter moves a piece of food
to the monkey’s mouth; the monkey grasps and holds it with its teeth. B. Communicative
mouth mirror neuron. Top. The experimenter makes a lip-smacking action looking at the
monkey. Middle. The experimenter protrudes his lips looking at the monkey. Bottom. The
experimenter moves a piece of food toward the monkey’s mouth; the monkey protrudes its
lips and takes the food. C. Communicative mouth mirror neuron. Left. The experimenter
protrudes his lips looking at the monkey. Right. During the experimenter lips protrusion
the monkey responds almost simultaneously to the experimenter gesture by making a lip-
smacking action. Modified from Ferrari et al. (2003).
JB[v.20020404] Prn:25/01/2007; 14:25 F: AICR6804.tex / p.6 (301-358)
When writing about neural correlates of intersubjectivity, Stern in his recent book
pointed out an interesting issue: “To resonate with someone, you may have to be
unconscious in synch with that person. You could move in synchrony, as lovers
may do when they sit across a coffee table and trace a dance as they simultaneously
approach and withdraw their faces from one another or move their hands together
at the same instant” (Stern 2004: 80).
What do mirror neurons tell us about synchrony and resonance? Is it pos-
sible to formulate and test hypotheses in the examination of these phenomena?
Rizzolatti et al. (1999) used a metaphor to better elucidate how we understand the
actions of others through the mirror mechanism. We understand other’s actions
through a mechanism of resonance, in which the motor system of the observer
“resonates” (i.e. mirror neurons activation) whenever an appropriate visual and/or
acoustic input is presented, although it does not necessarily imply the production
of an overt movement. Rizzolatti and coworkers (1999, 2002) proposed that the
internal motor representation of the observed action can be used for response fa-
cilitation, i.e., for triggering the repetition of an observed action that is already
in the observer’s motor repertoire. Response facilitation is achieved by means of a
resonance mechanism (Rizzolatti et al. 1999) in which the motor system of the ob-
server (or the listener) is activated specifically when an appropriate visual (and/or
acoustic) stimulus is presented.
JB[v.20020404] Prn:25/01/2007; 14:25 F: AICR6804.tex / p.7 (358-462)
Figure 2. Mean number of instantaneous eating sample points scored during baseline and
test period in ten pig-tailed macaques (Macaca nemestrina). Each individual contributed
with the averaged value of its three sessions. During the baseline period the demonstra-
tor was visible to the observer (only in experiment 1) but could not eat any food. During
the test period the stimulus (the sound or the vision of a monkey eating food) was in-
troduced (Top) Experiment 1 (monkey heard and observed another individual eating),
(Middle) Experiment 2 (monkey heard another individual eating), and (Bottom) Exper-
iment 3 (monkey heard ripping paper sound). Asterisks indicate significant differences
between test and baseline period scan samples (p < 0.05, Wilcoxon test). From Ferrari et al.
(2005b).
JB[v.20020404] Prn:25/01/2007; 14:25 F: AICR6804.tex / p.9 (462-462)
similar phenomenon in infant macaques for a few days after birth (Ferrari et al.
2006). Using a methodology similar to that adopted by Meltzoff and Moore (1977)
we tested the behavioural response specificity of the infant macaques to human
and facial and hand gestures. The facial and hand gestures used as stimuli were:
mouth opening, lips protrusion, tongue protrusion and hand opening. The infant
macaques were tested at the age of 1, 3, 7 and 14 days. At the age of 1 week, infant
macaques imitated tongue protrusion, lipsmacks and mouth openings when they
saw them performed by a human experimenter (see Figure 3). These findings sug-
gest that macaques may possess such imitative capacity very soon after birth (i.e.
in the first week of life), which, however, tends to disappear very early. Although
data on nonhuman primates are very scarce, it is clear that human early imita-
tion is not a unique feature of the human being but has evolved probably from
other related non-human primates. The fact that the type of gestures imitated are
usually related to affiliate meanings seems to suggest that in primates the need to
establish a deep relation (not just in term of attachment but also in term of dif-
ferent forms of intersubjectivity) between two individuals, typically the mother
and the infant, could have been a crucial evolutionary force. Furthermore, what
the data on early imitation seems to suggest is that in some species of primates
the newborn is capable of tuning his/her behaviour with that observed by another
individual. The sensory-motor system is already set to be coordinated with some-
one else’s experience in a participatory sense. This ‘alter-centred participation’ is
one of the tenet of the “primary intersubjectivity” model (Bråten 1998). Accord-
ing to this model, in fact, infants have a whole set of capacities to attune their
Figure 3. Neonatal imitation of tongue protrusion in a one week old macaque. The two
pictures are taken from a videotape. In the left picture is depicted the gesture made by the
model that is holding in his hand the infant monkey. The picture on the right has been
taken about two seconds after the end of the model’s gesture. The gesture made by the
model was repeated 7–8 times in a period of 20 seconds. As the monkey protruded its
tongue, no other movements (either with the hand or the mouth) were recorded.
JB[v.20020404] Prn:25/01/2007; 14:25 F: AICR6804.tex / p.10 (462-518)
minds with those of others. The result of this attunement is that of sharing the
first- and the third-person experience. This (probably) innate capacity to enter
and participate in other’s experience could be served by a neural mechanism such
as that of the mirror neurons. One aspect that neuroscience should explore more
in depth is whether the mirror neurons matching system is confined to functions
such as action understanding or whether the system can be further exploited in
the alter-centred participation.
Before becoming verbal and symbolic, the infant acquires more complex forms
of intersubjectivity. One of these is of utmost importance in the development of
the capacity of interacting and sharing experiences with others: understanding
intentions.
We will show here that the organization of the motor system may provide a
substrate for perceiving/inferring intentions. We will see that for the development
of a motor system fully adapted to interact with the physical and inanimate world,
it is necessary to intrinsically have a concept of intention for guiding the body in
space towards a goal.
Emotions constitute one of the earliest ways available to the individual to acquire
knowledge about its situation, thus enabling to reorganize this knowledge on the
basis of the outcome of the relations entertained with others. The coordinated ac-
tivity of sensory-motor and affective neural systems results in the simplification
and automatization of the behavioural responses that living organisms are sup-
posed to produce in order to survive. The integrity of the sensory-motor system
indeed appears to be critical for the recognition of emotions displayed by others
(see Adolphs 2003; Adolphs et al. 2000), because the sensory-motor system ap-
pears to support the reconstruction of what it would feel like to be in a particular
emotion, by means of simulation of the related body state. The implication of this
process for empathy should be obvious.
A recently published functional Magnetic Resonance Imaging (fMRI) study
showed that experiencing disgust and witnessing the same emotion expressed by
the facial mimicry of someone else, both activate the same neural structure –
the anterior insula – at the same overlapping location (Wicker et al. 2003). This
suggests, at least for the emotion of disgust, that the first- and third-person ex-
periences of a given emotion are underpinned by the activity of a shared neural
substrate. Thus, it is the activation of a neural mechanism shared by the observer
and the observed to enable direct experiential understanding.
Similar to emotions, also the tactile dimension can be intimately related to the
interpersonal dimension. New empirical evidence suggests that the first-person
experience of being touched on one’s body activates the same neural networks ac-
JB[v.20020404] Prn:25/01/2007; 14:25 F: AICR6804.tex / p.13 (606-661)
tivated by observing the body of someone else being touched (Keysers et al. 2004).
Within SII-PV, a multimodal cortical region, there is a localized neural network
similarly activated by the self-experienced sensation of being touched, and the
perception of an external tactile relation.
The double pattern of activation of the same brain region suggests that our
capacity to experience and directly understand the emotional and tactile experi-
ence of others could be mediated by embodied simulation, that is, by the externally
triggered activation of some of the same neural networks underpinning our own
emotion and tactile sensations (see Gallese 2005).
Conclusion
In the present chapter we propose that mirror neurons and mirror-related mecha-
nisms here described may represent the neurobiological grounding for the expres-
sion of some forms of primary and secondary intersubjectivity. These mechanisms
allow individuals to participate in another’s action, feeling or emotion through a
preferential access of the visual information about the outside social world to our
sensorimotor experience. The mirror neuron systems and the other non-motor
mirroring neural clusters in our brain represent one particular sub-personal in-
stantiation of embodied simulation. With this mechanism we do not just “see” an
action, an emotion, or a sensation. Side by side with the sensory description of the
observed social stimuli, internal representations of the body states associated with
these actions, emotions, and sensations are evoked in the observer, ‘as if ’ he/she
would be doing a similar action or experiencing a similar emotion or sensation.
According to this perspective, social cognition is not only explicitly reason-
ing about the contents of someone else’s mind. Our brains, and those of other
primates, appear to have developed a basic functional mechanism, embodied sim-
ulation, which gives us an experiential insight of other minds.
We also elucidated the possible link between the organization of the motor
system and its capacity to generate internal representations of what the agent is
going to do. In fact, the motor neurons in the parietal cortex seem to be orga-
nized in chains that code different motor acts which are dependent to each other
as they participate to the global overarching goal of an action. By means of em-
bodied simulation, the activation of these chains during the observation of motor
acts of others determines the activation in the observer’s brain of the final goal
of the action. Thus, mirror neurons appear to be a suitable mechanism not only
for action understanding but also for the detection of the intentions promoting
the behaviour of others. In other terms, as previously hypothesized (Gallese &
Goldman 1998), it could be at the basis of basic forms of mind reading.
JB[v.20020404] Prn:25/01/2007; 14:25 F: AICR6804.tex / p.14 (661-730)
Acknowledgements
References
Adolphs, R. (2003). “Cognitive neuroscience of human social behaviour.” Nature Rev. Neurosci.,
4, 165–178.
Adolphs, R., Damasio, H., Tranel, D., Cooper, G., & Damasio, A. R. (2000). “A role for
somatosensory cortices in the visual recognition of emotion as revealed by three-
dimensional lesion mapping.” J. Neurosci., 20, 2683–2690.
Bråten S. (1998). Intersubjective Communication and Emotion in Early Ontogeny. Cambridge:
Cambridge University Press.
Buccino, G., Binkofski, F., Fink, G. R., Fadiga, L., Fogassi, L., Gallese, V., Seitz, R. J., Zilles, K.,
Rizzolatti, G., & Freund, H. J. (2001). “Action observation activates premotor and parietal
areas in a somatotopic manner: An fMRI study.” Eur. J. Neurosci., 13, 400–404.
Buccino, G., Lui, F., Vanessa, N., Patteri, I., Lagravinese, G., Benuzzi, F., Porro, C. A., &
Rizzolatti, G. (2004). “Neural circuits involved in the recognition of actions performed by
nonconspecifics: An FMRI study.” J. Cogn. Neurosci., 16, 114–126.
Cisek, P., & Kalaska, J. (2004). “Neural correlates of mental rehearsal in dorsal premotor cortex.”
Nature, 431, 993–996.
Coussi-Korbel, S., & Fragaszy, D. (1995). “On the relation between social dynamics and social
learning.” Animal Behav., 50, 1441–1453.
Di Pellegrino, G., Fadiga, L., Fogassi, L., Gallese, V., & Rizzolatti, G. (1992). “Understanding
motor events: A neurophysiological study.” Exp. Brain Res., 91, 176–180.
Ferrari, P. F., Gallese, V., Rizzolatti, G., & Fogassi, L. (2003). “Mirror neurons responding to
the observation of ingestive and communicative mouth actions in the monkey ventral
premotor cortex.” European J. Neurosci., 17, 1703–1714.
Ferrari, P. F., Rozzi, S., & Fogassi, L. (2005a). “Mirror neurons responding to observation of
actions made with tools in monkey ventral premotor cortex.” J. Cogn. Neurosci., 17, 212–
226.
JB[v.20020404] Prn:25/01/2007; 14:25 F: AICR6804.tex / p.15 (730-839)
Ferrari, P. F., Maiolini, C., Addessi, E., Fogassi, L., & Visalberghi, E. (2005b). “Social facilitation
of eating behavior by action observation and action hearing in macaque monkeys.” Behav.
Brain Res.
Ferrari, P. F., Vislberghi, E., Paukner, A., Fogassi, L., Ruggiero, A., Suomi, S. J. (2006). “Neonatal
imitation in Rhesus Macaques.” PloS Biology, 4, e302.
Fogassi, L., Ferrari, P. F., Chersi, F., Gesierich, B., Rozzi, S., & Rizzolatti, G. (2005). “Parietal lobe:
From action organization to intention understanding.” Science, 308 (29 April), 662–667.
Fogassi, L., & Ferrari, P. F. (2004). “Mirror neurons, gesture and evolution of language.”
Interaction studies, 5, 343–361.
Fogassi, L., Ferrari, P. F., Rozzi, S., Gesierich, B., Chersi, F., Monfardini, E., Maiolini, C., &
Rizzolatti, G. (2004). “Parietal cortex motor neurons code the final goal of complex actions
in the monkey.” Soc. Neurosci. Abs., 211, 10.
Gallese, V. (2005). “Embodied simulation: From neurons to phenomenal experience.”
Phenomenology and the Cognitive Sciences, 4, 23–48.
Gallese, V., & Lakoff, G. (2005). “The brain’s concepts: The role of the sensory-motor system in
reason and language.” Cognitive Neuropsychology, 22, 455–479.
Gallese, V., Fadiga, L., Fogassi, L., & Rizzolatti, G. (1996). “Action recognition in the premotor
cortex.” Brain, 119, 593–609.
Gallese, V., & Goldman, A. (1998). “Mirror neurons and the simulation theory of mind-
reading.” TICS, 12, 493–501.
Gallese, V., Fogassi, L., Fadiga, L., & Rizzolatti, G. (2002). “Action representation and the inferior
parietal lobule.” In W. Prinz & B. Hommel (Eds.), Common Mechanisms in Perception and
Action: Attention and Performance, Vol. XIX (pp. 334–355). Oxford: Oxford University
Press.
Gallese, V., Keysers, C., & Rizzolatti, G. (2004). “A unifying view of the basis of social cognition.”
TICS, 8, 396–403.
Iacoboni, M., Molnar-Szakacs, I., Gallese, V., Buccino, G., Mazziotta, J., & Rizzolatti, G. (2005).
“Grasping intentions of others with one’s own mirror neuron system.” PloS Biology, 3, e79.
Iacoboni, M., Woods, R. P., Brass, M., Bekkering, H., Mazziotta, J. C., & Rizzolatti, G. (1999).
“Cortical mechanisms of human imitation.” Science, 286, 2526–2528.
Keysers, C., Wickers, B., Gazzola, V., Anton, J-L., Fogassi, L., & Gallese, V. (2004). “A touching
sight: SII/PV activation during the observation and experience of touch.” Neuron, 42, 1–20.
Kohler, E., Keysers, C., Umiltà, M. A., Fogassi, L., Gallese, V., & Rizzolatti, G. (2002). “Hearing
sounds, understanding actions: Action representation in mirror neurons.” Science, 297,
846–248.
Kuigiumutzakis, G. (1998). “Neonatal imitation in the intersubjective companion space.” In S.
Bråten (Ed.), Intersubjective Communication and Emotion in Early Ontogeny (pp. 63–88).
Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
Kuigiumutzakis, G. (1999). “Genesis and development of early human mimesis to facial and
vocal models.” In J. Nadel & G. Butterworth (Eds.), Imitation in Infancy (pp. 36–59).
Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
Meltzoff, A. N., & Moore, M. K. (1977). “Imitation of facial and manual gestures by human
neonates.” Science, 198, 74–78.
Meltzoff, A. N. (1990). “Foundations for developing a concept of self: The role of imitation in
relating self to other and the value of social mirroring, social modelling, and self practice in
infancy.” In D. Cicchetti & M. Beeghly (Eds.), The Self in Transition: Infancy to Childhood
(pp. 139–164). Chicago: University of Chicago Press.
JB[v.20020404] Prn:25/01/2007; 14:25 F: AICR6804.tex / p.16 (839-948)
Meltzoff, A. N., & Gopnik, A. (1993). “The role of imitation in understanding persons and a
theory of mind.” In S. Baron-Cohen, H. Flusberg, & D. Cohen (Eds.), Understanding Other
Minds (pp. 335–366). Oxford: Oxford University Press.
Meltzoff, A. N. (2002). “Elements of a development theory of imitation.” In A. N. Meltzoff &
W. Prinz (Eds.), The imitative mind. Development, evolution, and brain bases (pp. 19–41).
Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
Myowa, M. (1996). “Imitation of facial gestures by an infant chimpanzee.” Primates, 37, 207–
213.
Myowa-Yamakoshi, M., Tomonaga, M., Tanaka, M., & Matsuzawa, T. (2004). “Imitation in
neonatal chimpanzees (Pan troglodytes).” Dev Sci., 7, 437–442.
Rizzolatti, G., Fadiga, L., Gallese, V., & Fogassi, L. (1996). “Premotor cortex and the recognition
of motor actions.” Cog. Brain Res., 3, 131–141.
Rizzolatti, G., Fadiga, L., Fogassi, L., & Gallese, V. (1999). “Resonance behaviors and mirror
neurons.” Arch. Ital. Biol., 137, 85–100.
Rizzolatti, G., Fogassi, L., & Gallese, V. (2001). “Neurophysiological mechanisms underlying the
understanding and imitation of action.” Nature Rev. Neurosci., 2, 661–670.
Rizzolatti, G., Fadiga, L., Fogassi, L., & Gallese, V. (2002). “From mirror neurons to imitation:
Facts and speculations.” In A. N. Meltzoff & W. Prinz (Eds.), The Imitative Mind.
Development, Evolution, and Brain Bases (pp. 247–265). Cambridge: Cambridge University
Press.
Rizzolatti, G., & Craighero, L. (2004). “The mirror neuron system.” Ann. Rev. Neurosci., 27,
169–192.
Rizzolatti, G, Ferrari, P. F., Rozzi, S., & Fogassi, L. (2006). “The inferior parietal lobule: Where
action becomes perception.” Novartis Foundation Symposium.
Stern, D. N. (1985). The Interpersonal World of the Infant: A View from Psychoanalysis and
Development Psychology. New York: Basic Books.
Stern, D. N. (2004). The Present Moment in Psychotherapy and Everyday Life. New York: Norton.
Trevarthen, C. (1974). “Conversation with a two-month-old.” New Scientist, 2, 230–235.
Trevarthen, C. (1979). “Communication and cooperation in early infancy: A description
of primary intersubjectivity.” In M. M. Bullowa (Ed.), Before Speech: The Beginning of
Interpersonal Communication (pp. 231–347). New York: Cambridge University Press.
Trevarthen, C. (1980). “The foundation of intersubjectivity: Development of interpersonal and
cooperative understanding in infants.” In D. Olson (Ed.), The Social Foundation of Language
and Thought (pp. 316–342). New York: Norton.
Umiltà, M. A., Kohler, E., Gallese, V., Fogassi, L., Fadiga, L., Keysers, C., & Rizzolatti, G. (2001).
“I know what you are doing. A neurophysiological study.” Neuron, 31, 155–165.
Watkins, K. E., Strafella, A. P., & Paus, T. (2003). “Seeing and hearing speech excites the motor
system involved in speech production.” Neuropsychologia, 41, 989–994.
Wicker, B., Keysers, C., Plailly, J., Royet, J.-P., Gallese, V., & Rizzolatti, G. (2003). “Both of us
disgusted in my insula: The common neural basis of seeing and feeling disgust.” Neuron,
40, 655–664.
JB[v.20020404] Prn:7/03/2007; 16:56 F: AICR6805.tex / p.1 (49-140)
chapter
Riitta Hari
Helsinki University of Technology
As social creatures, we human beings crave for interaction with each other, and our
most important “stimuli” are the other humans. Consequently, it would be rea-
sonable to study functions of the human brain during natural social interaction.
From the experimental neuroscientist’s point of view, such attempts are, however,
highly complex as the stimuli are multifaceted, context-dependent, and vary dy-
namically during the interaction, depending also on the subject’s own reactions.
For that reason, reliable interpretation of the results of such experiments would be
extremely challenging.
It is therefore understandable that the progress of human brain research has
rather relied on “bottom-up” approaches, starting from detailed descriptions of
sensory functions. The bottom-up doctrine derives, among others, from the bril-
liant work of the Nobel laureates David Hubel and Torsten Wiesel, who in 1960’s
identified in the cat and monkey visual cortex classes of neurons with increasing
complexity. Similar approaches have been invaluable in increasing our knowledge
about various aspects of brain function. However, the pitfall is that the method-
ologically limited practices of research may bias the scientists to think that the
percepts and higher cognitive functions are realized only in a bottom-up way,
starting from the simple low-level analysis and progressing towards more demand-
ing neuronal computations that finally give rise to conscious percepts.
In strong conceptual contrast to the bottom-up approach is the “top-down”
thinking that assumes that the organism’s experience about the world – collected
during evolution, ontogenesis, and cultural interaction – leads to strong expecta-
tions, hypotheses, and predictions of the forthcoming events. Thus the external
JB[v.20020404] Prn:7/03/2007; 16:56 F: AICR6805.tex / p.2 (140-214)
Riitta Hari
stimuli would rather serve as a testing material for the available hypotheses, in
addition to being triggers for percepts and thoughts.
Within the top-down framework, some aspects of social cognition and inter-
action become more understandable. For example, humans are surprisingly fast in
categorizing complex stimuli: The emotional expression of a face is, at the brain
level, recognized within 100 ms (Pourtois et al. 2004). Also, pictures of distorted
finger postures elicit additional activation in the extrastriatal visual cortex already
from 250 ms onwards (Avikainen et al. 2003). Such categorization processes are
highly automatized because of the extensive practice in everyday life – much more
so than the perception of checkerboard patterns or monotonous sound sequences
that are commonly used as stimuli in brain research in the hope of simplifying
the experimental setups. It should be noted that it is not always self-evident how,
and to which direction, an experimental setup should be modified to make it as
simple as possible. For example, some logical puzzles are more easily solved in a
social than in an abstract context, encouraging the real-life approaches for studies
of brain basis of higher cognitive functions.
One recent research line, relevant for brain basis of social interaction, ad-
dresses non-verbal communication via “mirror neurons” that were discovered in
the monkey frontal lobe a decade ago (for reviews, see Rizzolatti et al. 2001; Rizzo-
latti & Craighero 2004). These mirror neurons (Fadiga & Craighero 2005), have
been proposed to serve as the basis for shared motor representations between
the producer and receiver of a motor-act based message. The mirror neurons
are, in a strict sense, motor neurons: they are activated both when the subject
makes a movement herself and sees another person making a similar movement.
The human mirror-neuron system (Nishitani & Hari 2000), comprising several
interconnected brain areas, provides one possible mechanism for shared motor
representations, and it is closely interconnected to other brain areas that likely
form corresponding sensory mirroring systems.
In this chapter the mirroring systems will be discussed in a rather broad
context, starting from a brief summary of our magnetoencephalographic (MEG)
mirror-neuron system studies, and then progressing to considerations of human–
human interactions from a neuroscientist’s point of view. The MEG recordings,
carried out with state-of-the art whole-scalp neuromagnetometers (see Figure 1),
allow non-invasive tracking of brain functions at time scales from 1 ms to several
hundreds of ms – all relevant for brain processes underlying percepts, movements,
and speech (Hämäläinen et al. 1993; Hari et al. 2000; Hari 2004). The excellent
temporal accuracy of MEG, combined with the superb spatial resolution of func-
tional magnetic resonance imaging (fMRI), provides a state-of-the-art approach
to image the brain basis of social cognition and dynamic interaction.
JB[v.20020404] Prn:7/03/2007; 16:56 F: AICR6805.tex / p.3 (214-214)
Our earliest mirror-neuron system study used the level of the 20-Hz motor-cortex
oscillations as a tool to monitor the functional state of the primary motor cortex
JB[v.20020404] Prn:7/03/2007; 16:56 F: AICR6805.tex / p.4 (214-266)
Riitta Hari
when the subject either performed finger manipulations herself or just observed
similar movements (Hari et al. 1998). The aim was to see whether the primary
motor cortex, normally controlling skilled voluntary movements, would be acti-
vated during observation of action. When the subject was herself manipulating a
small object, the primary motor cortex was clearly activated, as was evident from
a suppression of the 20-Hz oscillations. Interestingly, activation – although to a
smaller extent – was also seen when the subject just viewed another person’s ma-
nipulation movements without moving herself. Surface electromyogram indicated
that the subject did not herself contract muscles while viewing the other person’s
movements.
These findings on the modulation of cortical rhythms indicate that the human
primary motor cortex is activated when the subject just views another person’s ac-
tions. A later study showed 15–20% stronger suppression for motor acts presented
live than those seen on a video (Järveläinen et al. 2001), suggesting differentiation
of natural and artificial movements at the level of the primary motor cortex.
To be able to monitor a wider cortical network, the next MEG study applied
brain activity time-locked to hand movements (Nishitani & Hari 2000): The sub-
ject either stretched his right arm and hand towards a manipulandum, ending the
movement with a pinch of the tip, or he just observed, or both observed and im-
itated on-line similar movements made by the experimenter. The first activation,
occurring in the posterior visual areas about 400 ms before the subject pinched the
top of the manipulandum, was followed by activation in Broca’s region, then in the
left motor cortex (contralateral to the moving arm), and finally in the right motor
cortex. Importantly, Broca’s region and the primary motor cortex were activated
both during action execution and observation, thereby fulfilling the requirements
for containing motor mirror neurons. Broca’s region, the core area of the hu-
man mirror system (and the human homologue of the monkey mirror-neuron
area F5) seems to support many functions related to both verbal and non-verbal
communication (Nishitani et al. 2005).
In monkeys, the mirror neurons of the F5 region are also activated by oro-
facial gestures. The same seems to be true for humans because still pictures of
lip forms activated the human mirror-neuron system with a clear dynamic pro-
gression of the signals from posterior to anterior brain areas (Nishitani & Hari
2002): During both viewing and imitation conditions, the activation spread, in
both hemispheres, from occipital cortex to the superior temporal region (STS),
the inferior parietal lobule, the inferior frontal lobe (Broca’s region), and finally to
the primary motor cortex. The whole activation sequence took only 250 ms. Sur-
face electromyogram from mouth muscles ruled out muscular activity during the
observation condition.
JB[v.20020404] Prn:7/03/2007; 16:56 F: AICR6805.tex / p.5 (266-308)
Riitta Hari
hemisphere (Nishitani et al. 2004). This finding suggests a disorder either in the
frontal or parietofrontal part of the mirror-neuron system and may be related to
deficient action–perception matching in subjects with Asperger.
Figure 2. Top: Examples of the video clips presented during observation of goal-directed
and non-goal-directed tool use: The subject observed the experimenter either to place small
objects with chopsticks from one plate to another or to execute similar movements without
touching or moving the objects. Bottom: Activation levels in the right primary motor cortex
of 9 subjects, quantified on the basis of the local 20-Hz oscillatory activity. The normalized
levels of activation are indicated, value 0 corresponding to full activation/excitation during
subject’s own movements and value 100 referring to inhibition during rest. Adapted from
Järveläinen et al. (2004).
JB[v.20020404] Prn:7/03/2007; 16:56 F: AICR6805.tex / p.8 (384-427)
Riitta Hari
With the rapid progress of brain imaging methods, many aspects of the human
brain structure, connections, and function can be made public, i.e., visible to other
persons. In contrast, the mind largely remains private; the best we can do at present
is to search for neuronal correlates of different mental phenomena.
However, the discovery of mirror neurons has reawakened old views about
human motor actions as informants about the mind. Phenomenological philoso-
phers consider the body as the expression and display site of the mind. Folk psy-
chology and arts also contain frequent, and often humorous references to similar
phenomena (e.g. “Einen Mann von Geist erkennt mann auch von hinten” (Schopen-
hauer)). It is true that we unconsciously interpret many personal characteristics
of other persons on the basis of their gaze, posture, gait, gestures, and facial ex-
pressions, even in the absence of any verbal interaction. Interpretations of bodily
actions as indicators of the mind often go beyond species, so that we may think that
a monkey or a cat is nervous or depressed. Some degree of cross-species reading of
motor intentions is beneficial for both parties in predator–prey interactions.
A part of our intentions obviously become public in our motor actions. To
understand the mind, it is therefore necessary, besides reading signals from the
JB[v.20020404] Prn:7/03/2007; 16:56 F: AICR6805.tex / p.9 (427-479)
brain, to observe the subject’s motor behaviour and expressions while she inter-
acts with her environment – an environment which includes, as most important
constituents, other people.
Common to all successful communication is that the sender and receiver of a mes-
sage stay tuned. In crickets, for example, acoustic communication is temperature-
coupled so that alterations in temperature induce parallel changes in production of
the calling song (by males) and in the preference for the song (by females) (Pires &
Hoy 1992). The required “parity” of the receptive and productive modes between
different individuals of a species inevitably leads into a tight action–perception
link within each individual: one subject’s output is the other’s input and vice versa.
One good example is the motor theory of speech (Liberman & Whalen 2000), as-
suming that the listener tries to match her/his own motor representations to the
motor articulation patterns of the speaker.
Although the mirror neurons could well serve as links between the sender
and receiver of a motor-act based messages, they are not sufficient to support the
multitude of human–human interactions that require shared motor and sensory
representations. For example, observation of hand actions results in modification
of activations of both the primary and secondary somatosensory cortices SI and
SII (Avikainen et al. 2002), and seeing someone to be touched activates the SII
cortex (Keysers et al. 2004). Moreover, speech listening modulates the excitability
of tongue muscles (Fadiga et al. 2002), and viewing of orofacial gestures of speech
results in a somatotopic modulation of the SI cortex of left hemisphere (Möttönen
et al. 2005). Some of the sensory activations associated with action observation
might be related to “forward models” that, via efference copies, inform the sen-
sory areas about the forthcoming sensory input which then would be compared
with the predictions.
The pioneering findings of the motor mirror neurons are already followed by
discoveries of a number of other mirroring systems that support our shared rep-
resentations for actions, intentions, feelings, and emotions, including pain (e.g.
Singer et al. 2004; Saarela et al. 2006). In addition to the motor representations
important for imitation, our brains most likely house similar highly automatized
systems for motor counter-acting and co-operation. Social interaction also re-
quires insight into the beliefs, desires, and thoughts of the other persons, and the
links of brain’s “theory-of-mind” circuits (Frith & Frith 1999) with the motor and
sensory mirroring systems still remain to be resolved.
JB[v.20020404] Prn:7/03/2007; 16:56 F: AICR6805.tex / p.10 (479-562)
Riitta Hari
Acknowledgments
This study was supported by the Academy of Finland and the Sigrid Jusélius Foun-
dation. I thank Drs. Marieke Longcamp, Nobuyki Nishitani, Martin Schürmann,
and Amanda C. de C. Williams for comments on the manuscript.
References
Avikainen, S., Forss, N., & Hari, R. (2002). “Modulated activation of the human SI and SII
cortices during observation of hand actions.” Neuroimage, 15, 640–646.
Avikainen, S., Liuhanen, S., Schurmann, M., & Hari, R. (2003). “Enhanced extrastriate
activation during observation of distorted finger postures.” Journal of Cognitive
Neuroscience, 15, 658–663.
Fadiga, L., & Craighero, L. (2007). “Cues to the origin of language: From electro-
physiological data on mirror neurons and motor represenatations.” This volume: Chapter
6.
Fadiga, L., Craighero, L., Buccino, G., & Rizzolatti, G. (2002). “Speech listening specifically
modulates the excitability of tongue muscles: A TMS study.” European Journal of
Neuroscience, 15, 399–402.
Flanagan, J. R., & Johansson, R. S. (2003). “Action plans used in action observation.” Nature,
424, 769–771.
Frith, C., & Frith, U. (1999). “Interacting minds – A biological basis.” Science, 286, 1692–1695.
Hämäläinen, M., Hari, R., Ilmoniemi, R., Knuutila, J., & Lounasmaa, O. V. (1993). “Magneto-
encephalography – Theory, instrumentation, and applications to noninvasive studies of the
working human brain.” Reviews of Modern Physics, 65, 413–497.
Hari, R. (2004). “Magnetoencephalography in clinical neurophysiological assesment of human
cortical functions.” In E. Niedermeyer & F. Lopes da Silva (Eds.), Electroencephalography:
Basic Principles, Clinical Applications, and Related Fields (pp. 1165–1197). Lippincott,
Williams & Wilkins.
Hari, R., Forss, N., Avikainen, S., Kirveskari, E., Salenius, S., & Rizzolatti, G. (1998). “Activation
of human primary motor cortex during action observation: A neuromagnetic study.”
Proceedings of the National Academy of Sciences USA, 95, 15061–15065.
Hari, R., Levänen, S., & Raij, T. (2000). “Timing of human cortical activation sequences during
cognition: Role of MEG.” Trends in Cognitive Sciences, 4, 455–462.
Järveläinen, J., Schürmann, M., Avikainen, S., & Hari, R. (2001). “Stronger reactivity of the
human primary motor cortex during observation of live rather than video motor acts.”
Neuroreport, 12, 3493–3495.
Järveläinen, J., Schürmann, M., & Hari, R. (2004). “Activation of the human primary motor
cortex during observation of tool use.” Neuroimage, 23, 187–192.
Keysers, C., & Perrett, D. I. (2004). “Demystifying social cognition: A Hebbian perspective.”
Trends in Cognitive Sciences, 8, 501–507.
Keysers, C., Wicker, B., Gazzola, V., Anton, J. L., Fogassi, L., & Gallese, V. (2004). “A touching
sight: SII/PV activation during the observation and experience of touch.” Neuron, 42, 335–
346.
JB[v.20020404] Prn:7/03/2007; 16:56 F: AICR6805.tex / p.11 (562-638)
Kohler, E., Keysers, C., Umilta, M. A., Fogassi, L., Gallese, V., & Rizzolatti, G. (2002). “Hearing
sounds, understanding actions: Action representation in mirror neurons.” Science, 297,
846–848.
Kohonen, T., & Hari, R. (1999). “Where the abstract feature maps of the brain might come
from.” Trends in Neurosciences, 22, 135–139.
Liberman, A. M., & Whalen, D. H. (2000). “On the relation of speech to language.” Trends in
Cognitive Sciences, 4, 187–196.
Llinas, R. (2001). I of the Vortex. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.
Möttönen, R., Järveläinen, J., Sams, M., & Hari, R. (2005). “Viewing speech modulates activity
in the left SI mouth cortex.” Neuroimage, 24, 731–737.
Nishitani, N., Avikainen, S., & Hari, R. (2004). “Abnormal imitation-related cortical activation
sequences in Asperger’s syndrome.” Annals of Neurology, 55, 558–562.
Nishitani, N., & Hari, R. (2000). “Temporal dynamics of cortical representation for action.”
Proceedings of the National Academy of Sciences USA, 97, 913–918.
Nishitani, N., & Hari, R. (2002). “Viewing lip forms: Cortical dynamics.” Neuron, 36, 1211–1220.
Nishitani, N., Schurmann, M., Amunts, K., & Hari, R. (2005). “Broca’s region: From action to
language.” Physiology (Bethesda), 20, 60–69.
Pires, A., & Hoy, R. R. (1992). “Temperature coupling in cricket acoustic communication.
II. Localization of temperature effects on song production and recognition networks in
Gryllus firmus.” Journal of Comparative Physiology [A], 171, 79–92.
Pourtois, G., Grandjean, D., Sander, D., & Vuilleumier, P. (2004). “Electrophysiological
correlates of rapid spatial orienting towards fearful faces.” Cerebral Cortex, 14, 619–633.
Rizzolatti, G., & Craighero, L. (2004). “The mirror-neuron system.” Annual Review of
Neuroscience, 27, 169–192.
Rizzolatti, G., Fogassi, L., & Gallese, V. (2001). “Neurophysiological mechanisms underlying the
understanding and imitation of action.” Nature Reviews Neuroscience, 2, 661–670.
Saarela, M., Hlushchuk, Y., de C. Williams, A. C., Schürmann, M., Kalso, E., & Hari, R. (2007).
“The compassionate brain: Humans detect intensity of pain from another’s face.” Cerebral
Cortex, 17, 230–237.
Schürmann, M., Hesse, M. D., Stephan, K. E., Saarela, M., Zilles, K., Hari, R., & Fink, G. R.
(2005). “Yearning to yawn: The neural basis of contagious yawning.” Neuroimage, 24, 1260–
1264.
Singer, T., Seymour, B., O’Doherty, J., Kaube, H., Dolan, R. J., & Frith, C. D. (2004). “Empathy
for pain involves the affective but not sensory components of pain.” Science, 303, 1157–
1162.
JB[v.20020404] Prn:25/01/2007; 15:33 F: AICR6806.tex / p.1 (48-127)
chapter
Introduction
There are two main views on the origin of human language. The first is that it
derives from animal’s call, the other from gestures. In the present article we argue
that the second view is much more plausible. We discuss first a neurophysiological
mechanism, the mirror neuron system, which solves the problem of direct com-
prehension of action meaning. We discuss then how this system can be also at the
basis of speech perception.
The faculty of language is a cognitive ability that only humans possess. How
then, did language appear? This is a completely open question. Yet, the discovery
of a new class of neurons in the monkey, the so-called mirror neurons, indicates
a mechanism that may give some clues on the origin of speech and its continuity
with non-human primate behaviour. This mechanism, in fact, is of great evolu-
tionary importance since it is supposed to be at the basis of the way in which pri-
mates understand actions made by their conspecifics. Moreover, evidence coming
from different experimental approaches has demonstrated that a mirror-neuron
system is present also in humans. The most intriguing finding deriving from brain
imaging studies is that one of the regions mainly involved in this system is the left
inferior frontal cortex in correspondence of the Broca’s region which is classically
considered a language-related brain region. In the present article we will briefly
describe the basic properties of mirror neurons in non-human primates and man
and we will present some experimental data indicating that the mirror neuron
system in humans could be at the basis of speech perception.
JB[v.20020404] Prn:25/01/2007; 15:33 F: AICR6806.tex / p.2 (127-165)
Mirror neurons are a set of neurons originally discovered in the ventral premotor
cortex of the macaque monkey. Their defining property is that they became ac-
tive both when the monkey does a particular action (like grasping an object) and
when it observes another individual making a similar action (see Rizzolatti et al.
2001). In order to be triggered by visual stimuli, mirror neurons require an inter-
action between a biological effector (hand or mouth) and an object. The sights of
an object alone, of an agent mimicking an action, or of an individual making in-
transitive (non-object directed) gestures are all ineffective. The object significance
for the monkey has no obvious influence on mirror neuron response. Grasping a
piece of food or a geometric solid produces responses of the same intensity. Mirror
neurons show a large degree of generalization. Largely different visual stimuli, but
representing the same action, are equally effective. For example, the same grasping
mirror neuron that responds to a human hand grasping an object, responds also
when the grasping hand is that of a monkey. Similarly, the response is, typically,
not affected if the action is done near or far from the monkey, in spite of the fact
that the size of the observed hand is obviously different in the two conditions. It
is also of little importance for neuron activation if the observed action is eventu-
ally rewarded. The discharge is of the same intensity if the experimenter grasps the
food and gives it to the recorded monkey or to another monkey, introduced in the
experimental room.
An important functional aspect of mirror neurons is the relation between
their visual and motor properties. Virtually, all mirror neurons show congruence
between the visual actions they respond to and the motor responses they code.
According to the type of congruence they exhibit, mirror neurons have been sub-
divided into “strictly congruent” and “broadly congruent” neurons (Gallese et al.
1996). Mirror neurons in which the effective observed and effective executed ac-
tions correspond in terms of goal (e.g. grasping) and means for reaching the goal
(e.g. precision grip) have been classed as “strictly congruent”. They represent about
one third of F5 mirror neurons. Mirror neurons that, in order to be triggered, do
not require the observation of exactly the same action that they code motorically,
have been classed as “broadly congruent”. They represent about two-third of F5
mirror neurons.
There are no studies in which single neurons were recorded from the putative
mirror-neuron areas in humans. Thus, a direct evidence of the existence of mirror
neurons in humans is lacking. There is, however, a rich amount of data proving,
JB[v.20020404] Prn:25/01/2007; 15:33 F: AICR6806.tex / p.3 (165-201)
indirectly, that a mirror-neuron system does exist also in humans. Evidence in this
sense comes from neurophysiological and brain-imaging experiments (Gastaut
& Bert 1954; Cochin et al. 1998, 1999; Altschuler et al. 1997, 2000; Hari et al.
1998; Salmelin & Hari 1994; Hari & Salmelin 1997). More direct evidence that
the motor system in humans has mirror properties was provided by transcranial
magnetic stimulation (TMS) studies. Fadiga et al. (1995) recorded motor evoked
potentials (MEPs), elicited by stimulation of the left motor cortex, from the right
hand and arm muscles in volunteers required to observe an experimenter grasping
objects (transitive hand actions) or performing meaningless arm gestures (intran-
sitive arm movements). Detection of the dimming of a small spot of light and
presentation of 3-D objects were used as control conditions. The results showed
that the observation of both transitive and intransitive actions determined an in-
crease of the recorded MEPs with respect to the control conditions. The increase
concerned selectively those muscles that the participants use for producing the
observed movements.
The MEPs facilitation during movement observation may result from a fa-
cilitation of the primary motor cortex due to mirror activity of the premotor
areas, to a direct facilitatory input to the spinal cord originating from the same
areas, or from both. Support for the cortical hypothesis (see also below, brain
imaging experiments) came from a study by Strafella and Paus (2000). By using
a double-pulse TMS technique, they demonstrated that the duration of intracorti-
cal recurrent inhibition, occurring during action observation, closely corresponds
to that occurring during action execution.
A large number of brain imaging studies showed that the observation of ac-
tions done by others activates in humans a complex network formed by occipital,
temporal and parietal visual areas, and two cortical regions whose function is fun-
damentally or predominantly motor (Rizzolatti et al. 1996; Grafton et al. 1996;
Grèzes et al. 1998, 2001, 2003; Iacoboni et al. 1999, 2001; Nishitani & Hari 2000,
2002; Buccino et al. 2001; Perani et al. 2001; Decety et al. 2002, Koski et al. 2002,
2003; Manthey et al. 2003). These two last regions are the rostral part of the in-
ferior parietal lobule and the lower part of the precentral gyrus plus the posterior
part of the inferior frontal gyrus (IFG). These regions form the core of the human
mirror-neuron system. Hand grasping movements (Grafton et al. 1996; Rizzolatti
et al. 1996) as well as more complex hand/arm movements were used as visual
stimuli (Decety et al. 1997; Grèzes et al. 1998). The results of the first experiments
showed that during the observation of hand grasping there was an activation of
the left inferior frontal cortex, in correspondence of the Broca’s region. In addi-
tion activations were found in the left superior temporal sulcus (STS), the rostral
part of the left inferior parietal lobule (area 40), the left opercular parietal region
and the rostral part of the supplementary motor area (SMA-proper) (Grafton et al.
1996; Rizzolatti et al. 1996). The first three regions most likely correspond to the
JB[v.20020404] Prn:25/01/2007; 15:33 F: AICR6806.tex / p.4 (201-254)
monkey cortical areas where there are neurons that discharge when the monkey
observes biological actions, namely: area F5 (Gallese et al. 1996), the STS region
(Perrett et al. 1989; Carey et al. 1997) and the rostral part of the inferior parietal
lobule (Fogassi et al. 1998).
In studies carried out by the Lyon group (Decety et al. 1997; Grèzes et al. 1998)
the involvement of Broca’s area during observation of hand/arm actions was fur-
ther confirmed. The authors instructed subjects to observe meaningful (with a
goal) and meaningless movements. The main results of the condition in which
subjects observed meaningless arm movements were these: an activation of the
parietal lobe bilaterally, in the left precentral gyrus and the cerebellum on the
right side (Grèzes et al. 1998). On the contrary, the observation of meaningful
hand actions, in addition to the already mentioned frontal and parietal areas, ac-
tivates the left inferior frontal gyrus (Broca’s region). Note that the activation of
Broca’s region during observation of action, suggests for this area the putative role
of human homologue of area F5. In this direction point also some comparative
cytoarchitectonical data (see Petrides & Pandya 1997) which entail a morpho-
logical parallel between monkey premotor area F5 (a disgranular frontal cortex)
with Broca’s area (BA44 and the most posterior part of 45), and fMRI data from
Binkofsky et al. (1999) demonstrating that Broca’s region become active also dur-
ing manipulation of complex objects. In an fMRI study (Buccino et al. 2001), it was
assessed whether the observation of actions made with different effectors would
activate specific parts of the premotor cortex in accord with the somatotopic or-
ganization of the region. While being scanned, normal participants were asked
to carefully observe different videotaped object- and non-object-related actions,
performed by another individual with different effectors (mouth, arm/hand and
foot). Results showed that observation of both object- and non-object-related ac-
tions determined a somatotopically organized activation of premotor cortex. The
somatotopic pattern was similar to that of the classical motor cortex homuncu-
lus. In addition, during the observation of object-related actions, an activation,
also somatotopically organized, was found in the posterior parietal lobe. Thus,
when individuals observe an action, an internal replica of that action is automat-
ically generated in their premotor cortex. In the case of object-related actions, a
further object-related analysis is performed in the parietal lobe, as if the subjects
were indeed using those objects. These results bring the previous concept of an
action observation/execution matching system (mirror system) into a broader per-
spective: this system is not restricted to the ventral premotor cortex, but involves
several somatotopically organized motor circuits.
It is important to note that the observation of transitive actions activated both
the parietal and the frontal node of the mirror-neuron system, while the intran-
sitive actions the frontal node only. This observation is in accord with the lack
of inferior parietal lobule activation found in other studies in which intransitive
JB[v.20020404] Prn:25/01/2007; 15:33 F: AICR6806.tex / p.5 (254-302)
actions were used (e.g. finger movements, Iacoboni et al. 1999, 2001; Koski et al.
2002, 2003). Considering that the premotor areas receive visual information from
the inferior parietal lobule, it is hard to believe that inferior parietal lobule was not
activated during the observation of intransitive actions. It is more likely, there-
fore, that when an object is present, the inferior parietal activation is stronger than
when the object is lacking, and the activation, in the latter case, does not reach
statistical significance.
Mirror neurons represent the neural basis of a mechanism that creates a direct
link between the sender of a message and its receiver. By transforming an action
done by an individual into a representation of the same action in the motor cortex
of the observer, this mechanism creates a direct, non-arbitrary link between two
communicating individuals. Actions done by other individuals become messages
that are understood by an observer without any cognitive mediation.
Others’ actions, however, do not generate only visually perceivable signals.
Action-generated sounds and noises are also very common in nature. One could
expect, therefore, that also this sensory information, related to a particular ac-
tion, could determine a motor activation specific for that same action. A recent
neurophysiological experiment addressed this point. Kohler and colleagues (2002)
investigated whether there are neurons in area F5 that discharge when the monkey
makes a specific hand action and also when it hears the corresponding action-
related sounds. The experimental hypothesis started from the remark that a large
number of object-related actions (e.g. breaking a peanut) can be recognized by
a particular sound. The authors found that 13% of the investigated neurons dis-
charge both when the monkey performed a hand action and when it heard the
action-related sound. Moreover, most of these neurons discharge also when the
monkey observed the same action demonstrating that these ‘audio-visual mirror
neurons’ represent actions independently of whether they are performed, heard or
seen.
The presence of an audio-motor resonance in a region that, in humans, is clas-
sically considered a speech-related area, evokes the Liberman’s hypothesis on the
mechanism at the basis of speech perception (motor theory of speech perception,
Liberman et al. 1967; Liberman & Mattingly 1985; Liberman & Whalen 2000).
The motor theory of speech perception maintains that the ultimate constituents
of speech are not sounds, but articulatory gestures that have evolved exclusively
at the service of language. A cognitive translation into phonology is not necessary
because the articulatory gestures are phonologic in nature. Furthermore, speech
perception and speech production processes use a common repertoire of motor
JB[v.20020404] Prn:25/01/2007; 15:33 F: AICR6806.tex / p.6 (302-376)
primitives that, during speech production, are at the basis of articulatory gesture
generation, while during speech perception, are activated in the listener as the re-
sult of an acoustically evoked motor “resonance”. Thus, sounds conveying verbal
communication are the vehicle of motor representations (articulatory gestures)
shared by both the speaker and the listener, on which speech perception could
be based upon. In other terms, the listener understands the speaker when his/her
articulatory gestures representations are activated by verbal sounds.
Fadiga et al. (2002), in a TMS experiment based on the paradigm used in 1995
(Fadiga et al. 1995), tested for the presence in humans of a system that motor-
ically “resonates” when the individuals listen to verbal stimuli. Normal subjects
were requested to attend to an acoustically presented randomized sequence of di-
syllabic words, disyllabic pseudo-words and bitonal sounds of equivalent intensity
and duration. Words and pseudo-words were selected according to a consonant-
vowel-consonant-consonant-vowel (cvccv) scheme. The embedded consonants in
the middle of words and of pseudo-words were either a double ‘f ’ (labio-dental
fricative consonant that, when pronounced, requires slight tongue tip mobiliza-
tion) or a double ‘r’ (lingua-palatal fricative consonant that, when pronounced,
requires strong tongue tip mobilization). Bitonal sounds, lasting about the same
time as verbal stimuli and replicating their intonation pattern, were used as a con-
trol. The excitability of motor cortex in correspondence of tongue movements
representation was assessed by using single pulse TMS and by recording MEPs
from the anterior tongue muscles. The TMS stimuli were applied synchronously
with the double consonant of presented verbal stimuli (words and pseudo-words)
and in the middle of the bitonal sounds. Results (see Figure 1) showed that during
speech listening there is an increase of motor evoked potentials recorded from the
listeners’ tongue muscles when the listened word strongly involves tongue move-
ments, indicating that when an individual listens to verbal stimuli his/her speech
related motor centres are specifically activated. Moreover, word-related facilitation
was significantly larger than in the case of pseudo-words related to.
These results indicate that the passive listening to words that would involve
tongue mobilization (when pronounced) induces an automatic facilitation of the
listener’s motor cortex. Furthermore, the effect is stronger in the case of words
than in the case of pseudo-words suggesting a possible unspecific facilitation of
the motor speech centre due to recognition that the presented material belongs to
an extant word.
The presence of “audio-visual” mirror neurons in the monkey and the pres-
ence of “speech-related acoustic motor resonance” in humans, indicate that inde-
pendently from the sensory nature of the perceived stimulus, the mirror-resonant
system retrieves from action vocabulary (stored in the frontal cortex) the stimulus-
related motor representations.
JB[v.20020404] Prn:25/01/2007; 15:33 F: AICR6806.tex / p.7 (376-391)
Figure 1. Average value (+ SEM) of intrasubject normalized MEPs total areas for each
condition. Data from all subjects; ‘rr’ and ‘ff ’ refer to verbal stimuli containing a dou-
ble lingua-palatal fricative consonant ‘r’, and containing a double labio-dental fricative
consonant ‘f ’, respectively.
Conclusions
Mirror neurons represent the neural basis of a mechanism that creates a direct link
between the sender of a message and its receiver. This mechanism, by transform-
ing an action done by an individual into a representation of the same action in
the motor cortex of the observer, creates, a direct, non-arbitrary link between two
communicating individuals. Actions done by other individuals become messages
that are understood by an observer without any cognitive mediation. On the basis
of this property, Rizzolatti and Arbib (1998) propose that the mirror-neuron sys-
tem represents the neurophysiological mechanism from which language evolved.
Their theoretical proposal is consistent with theories that postulate that speech
evolved mostly from gestural communication and that sound was a late commu-
nicative acquisition developed on the top of it, with no link with ancient calls (see
Armstrong et al. 1995; Corballis 2002). The novelty of the theory proposed by
Rizzolatti and Arbib consists in their indication of a neurophysiological mecha-
nism that creates a common (parity requirement), non-arbitrary, semantic link
between communicating individuals.
JB[v.20020404] Prn:25/01/2007; 15:33 F: AICR6806.tex / p.8 (391-447)
Acknowledgements
This work has been supported by EU (ROBOT-CUB and CONTACT) and MIUR
grants.
References
Altschuler, E. L., Vankov, A., Hubbard, E. M., Roberts, E., Ramachandran, V. S., & Pineda, J. A.
(2000). “Mu wave blocking by observation of movement and its possible use as a tool to
study theory of other minds.” Society of Neuroscience Abstract, 68, 1.
Altschuler, E. L., Vankov, A., Wang, V., Ramachandran, V. S., & Pineda, J. A. (1997). “Person see,
person do: Human cortical electrophysiological correlates of monkey see monkey do cell.”
Society of Neuroscience Abstract, 719, 17.
Arbib, M. A. (2002). “Beyond the mirror system: Imitation and evolution of language.” In
C. Nehaniv & K. Dautenhan (Eds.), imitation in animals and artifacts (pp. 229–280).
Cambridge, MA: The MIT Press.
Armstrong, A. C., Stokoe, W. C., & Wilcox, S. E. (1995). Gesture and the Nature of Language.
Cambridge, UK: Cambridge University Press.
Binkofski, F., Buccino, G., Posse, S., Seitz, R. J., Rizzolatti, G., & Freund, H. (1999). “A fronto-
parietal circuit for object manipulation in man: Evidence from an fMRI-study.” European
Journal of Neuroscience, 11, 3276–3286.
JB[v.20020404] Prn:25/01/2007; 15:33 F: AICR6806.tex / p.9 (447-554)
Buccino, G., Binkofski, F., Fink, G. R., Fadiga, L., Fogassi, L. et al. (2001). “Action observation
activates premotor and parietal areas in a somatotopic manner: An fMRI study.” European
Journal of Neuroscience, 13, 400–404.
Carey, D. P., Perrett, D. I., & Oram, M. W. (1997). “Recognizing, understanding and reproducing
actions.” In M. Jeannerod & J. Grafman (Eds.), Handbook of neuropsychology, Vol. 11: Action
and Cognition (pp. 111–130). Amsterdam: Elsevier.
Cochin, S., Barthelemy, C., Lejeune, B., Roux, S., & Martineau, J. (1998). “Perception of motion
and qEEG activity in human adults.” Electroencephalography and Clinical Neurophysiology,
107, 287–295.
Cochin, S., Barthelemy, C., Roux, S., & Martineau, J. (1999). “Observation and execution
of movement: Similarities demonstrated by quantified electroencephalograpy.” European
Journal of Neuroscience, 11, 1839–1842.
Decety, J., Chaminade, T., Grezes, J., & Meltzoff, A. N. (2002). “A PET exploration of the neural
mechanisms involved in reciprocal imitation.” Neuroimage, 15, 265–272.
Decety, J., Grezes, J., Costes, N., Perani, D., Jeannerod, M., Procyk, E., Grassi, F., & Fazio,
F. (1997). “Brain activity during observation of actions: Influence of action content and
subject’s strategy.” Brain, 120, 1763–1777.
Fadiga, L., Craighero, L., Buccino G., & Rizzolatti, G. (2002). “Speech listening specifically
modulates the excitability of tongue muscles: A TMS study.” European Journal of
Neuroscience, 15, 399–402.
Fadiga, L., Fogassi, L., Pavesi, G., & Rizzolatti, G. (1995). “Motor facilitation during action
observation: A magnetic stimulation study.” Journal of Neurophysiology, 73, 2608–2611.
Fogassi, L., Gallese, V., Fadiga, L., & Rizzolatti, G. (1998). “Neurons responding to the sight of
goal directed hand/arm actions in the parietal area PF (7b) of the macaque monkey.” Society
of Neuroscience Abstract, 24, 257.5.
Gallese, V., Fadiga, L., Fogassi, L., & Rizzolatti, G. (1996). “Action recognition in the premotor
cortex.” Brain, 119, 593–609.
Gastaut, H. J., & Bert, J. (1954). “EEG changes during cinematographic presentation.”
Electroencephalography and Clinical Neurophysiology, 6, 433–444.
Gentilucci, M., Benuzzi, F., Gangitano, M., & Grimaldi, S. (2001). “Grasp with hand and mouth:
A kinematic study on healthy subjects.” Journal of Neurophysiology, 86, 1685–1699.
Grafton, S. T., Arbib, M. A., Fadiga, L., & Rizzolatti, G. (1996). “Localization of grasp
representations in humans by PET: 2. Observation compared with imagination.”
Experimental Brain Research, 112, 103–111.
Grèzes, J., Armony, J. L., Rowe, J., & Passingham, R. E. (2003). “Activations related to “mirror”
and “canonical” neurones in the human brain: An fMRI study.” Neuroimage, 18, 928–937.
Grèzes, J., Costes, N., Decety, J. (1998). “Top-down effect of strategy on the perception of human
biological motion: A PET investigation.” Cognitive Neuropsychology, 15, 553–582.
Grèzes, J., Decety, J. (2001). “Functional anatomy of execution, mental simulation, observation,
and verb generation of actions: A meta-analysis.” Human Brain Mapping, 12, 1–19.
Hari, R., Forss, N., Avikainen, S., Kirveskari, S., Salenius, S., & Rizzolatti, G. (1998). “Activation
of human primary motor cortex during action observation: A neuromagnetic study.”
Proceedings of the National Academy of Science USA, 95, 15061–15065.
Hari, R., & Salmelin, R. (1997). “Human cortical oscillations: A neuromagnetic view through
the skull.” Trends in Neuroscience, 20, 44–49.
Iacoboni, M., Koski, L. M., Brass, M., Bekkering, H., Woods, R. P. et al. (2001). “Reafferent
copies of imitated actions in the right superior temporal cortex.” Proceedings of the National
Academy of Science USA, 98, 13995–13999.
JB[v.20020404] Prn:25/01/2007; 15:33 F: AICR6806.tex / p.10 (554-662)
Iacoboni, M., Woods, R. P., Brass, M., Bekkering, H., Mazziotta, J. C., & Rizzolatti, G. (1999).
“Cortical mechanisms of human imitation.” Science, 286, 2526–2538.
Jürgens, U. (2002). “Neural pathways underlying vocal control.” Neuroscience Biobehavioral
Review, 26, 235–258.
Kohler, E., Keysers, C., Umiltà, M. A., Fogassi, L., Gallese, V., & Rizzolatti, G. (2002). “Hearing
sounds, understanding actions: Action representation in mirror neurons.” Science, 297,
846–848.
Koski, L., Iacoboni, M., Dubeau, M. C., Woods, R. P., Mazziotta, J. C. (2003). “Modulation
of cortical activity during different imitative behaviors).” Journal of Neurophysiology, 89,
460–471.
Koski, L., Wohlschlager, A., Bekkering, H., Woods, R. P., & Dubeau, M. C. (2002). “Modulation
of motor and premotor activity during imitation of target-directed actions.” Cerebral
Cortex, 12, 847–855.
Liberman, A. M., Cooper, F. S., Shankweiler, D. P., & Studdert-Kennedy, M. (1967). “Perception
of the speech code.” Psychol. Rev., 74, 431–461.
Liberman, A. M., & Mattingly, I. G. (1985). “The motor theory of speech perception revised.”
Cognition, 21, 1–36.
Liberman, A. M., & Whalen, D. H. (2000). “On the relation of speech to language.” Trends in
Cognitive Sciences, 4 (5), 187–196.
Maeda, F., Kleiner-Fisman, G., & Pascual-Leone, A. (2002). “Motor facilitation while observing
hand actions: Specificity of the effect and role of observer’s orientation.” Journal of
Neurophysiology, 87, 1329–1325.
Manthey, S., Schubotz, R. I., & von Cramon, D. Y. (2003). “Premotor cortex in observing
erroneous action: An fMRI study.” Cognitive Brain Research, 15, 296–307.
Nishitani, N., & Hari, R. (2002). “Viewing lip forms: Cortical dynamics.” Neuron, 36, 1211–1220.
Paget, R. (1930). Human Speech. London: Kegan Paul, Trench and Co.
Perani, D., Fazio, F., Borghese, N. A., Tettamanti, M., Ferrari, S. et al. (2001). “Different brain
correlates for watching real and virtual hand actions.” Neuroimage, 14, 749–758.
Perrett, D. I., Harries, M. H., Bevan, R., Thomas, S., Benson, P. J. et al. (1989). “Frameworks
of analysis for the neural representation of animate objects and actions.” Journal of
Experimental Biology, 146, 87–113.
Petrides, M., & Pandya, D. N. (1997). “Comparative architectonic analysis of the human and the
macaque frontal cortex.” In F. Boller & J. Grafman (Eds.), Handbook of Neuropsychology,
Vol. IX (pp. 17–58). New York: Elsevier.
Rizzolatti, G., & Arbib, M. A. (1998). “Language within our grasp.” Trends in Neuroscience, 21,
188–194.
Rizzolatti, G., & Craighero, L. (2004). “The mirror neuron system.” Annual Review Neuroscience,
27, 169–192.
Rizzolatti, G., Fadiga, L., Matelli, M., Bettinardi, V., Paulesu, E. et al. (1996). “Localization of
grasp representation in humans by PET: 1. Observation versus execution.” Experimental
Brain Research, 111, 246–252.
Rizzolatti, G., Fogassi, L., & Gallese, V. (2001). “Neurophysiological mechanisms underlying the
understanding and imitation of action.” Nature Reviews Neuroscience, 2, 661–670.
Salmelin, R., & Hari, R. (1994). “Spatiotemporal characteristics of sensorimotor neuromagnetic
rhythms related to thumb movement.” Neuroscience, 60, 537–550.
Strafella, A. P., & Paus, T. (2000). “Modulation of cortical excitability during action observation:
A transcranial magnetic stimulation study.” NeuroReport, 11, 2289–2292.
Vygotsky, L. S. (1934). Thought and Language. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.
JB[v.20020404] Prn:7/03/2007; 16:59 F: AICR6807.tex / p.1 (48-141)
chapter
Stein Bråten
University of Oslo
Norwegian boy: Having been spoon-fed by his sister, the infant boy (11 3/4
month), when allowed to take the spoon with food in his
own hand, reciprocates his sister’s spoon-feeding, and as he
reaches out the spoon with food towards his sister’s mouth
he opens his own mouth (Bråten 1996b, 1998c) (cf. Fig. 2
(bottom left).
Yanomami-girl: Infant girl (probably about same age as the above boy) in
an Amazonas tribe, when offering a morsel to her big sister
opens her mouth as she extend the morsel towards her sister’s
mouth, and tightens her lips as her sister’s mouth closes on
the food (photo recordings by Eibl-Eibesfeldt 1979) (cf. Fig. 2
(right)).
Sports spectator: When standing in the spectator box at the summer Olympics
2000 in Sidney, watching her horse in the competition ridden
by an Englishman, the Norwegian princess, Märtha Louise,
jumps high in the air as her horse and rider begin the jump to
cross the last high obstacle (Norwegian Broadcast television
NRK1 2000).
Sartre as listener: In the conversations between Jean Paul Sartre and Simone de
Beauvoir, reported in Adieux, these passages occur in which
Sartre completes her utterance (one of several instances):
Beauvoir: “[I] say it’s odd, this contrast between your stiffness and a wel-
coming attitude, a kindness, a warmth a soon as . . . .”
Sartre: “As soon as anyone turns to me to ask for something, it vanishes”
(Beauvoir 1986: 289).
In spite of differing with respect to whether infants or adults are involved, what
all the above episodes have in common is the overt manifestations, entailing pre-
enacting or co-enacting movements, anticipant or concurrent mirroring or simu-
lation of what the perceived patient or performer or partner is about to do or say,
as if being a co-author of the newborn’s attempt to imitate, or of the other’s in-
take of the afforded food, or of the crossing of the obstacle, or of the conversation
partner’s statement.
Adam Smith (1759) had noticed how spectators watching a French line dancer
would sometimes wriggle and other ways move their own bodies as if helping the
dancer to keep the balance as he walked on the slack line. He saw this as a mani-
festation of what he termed ‘sympathy’ (which is not a bad term when considering
the Greek roots of ‘sym’ for joint and ‘pathos’ for feelings or suffering). More than
a hundred years later, Darwin (1872), in his work on expression of emotions in
animal and in man, mentions that he has heard of sport event spectators of high
jumping who move their own legs when watching the high jumper take off, but he
JB[v.20020404] Prn:7/03/2007; 16:59 F: AICR6807.tex / p.3 (166-229)
doubted that girls would do such a thing. Darwin was of course wrong as attested
by the television glimpses showing how the Norwegian princess in the spectator
box at the summer Olympics 2000 in Sidney, jumps high in the air as her horse,
ridden by an Englishman, is about to cross the last high obstacle.
So, what she was doing when watching what the horse and rider were trying
to do, and what some of the lecture audience were doing when watching what the
newborn girl was trying to do, or what the feeder often unwittingly does when the
patient prepares to mouth grasp the afforded food, is to show by such pre-enacting
or co-enacting muscle activation and semblant part movements or co-movements
(termed Mitbewegungen by Eibl-Eibelsfeldt 1997: 486) that they take a virtual part
in what the other is trying to do, as if sharing the bodily centre of the other’s
muscular activity. This is other-centred participation entailing altercentricity – the
very reverse of egocentricity.
As the very reverse of perception of other subjects from an ego-centric per-
spective, the above are all instances of ‘altercentric participation’ which entails the
empathic capacity to identify with the other in a virtual participant manner that
evokes co-enactment or shared experience as if being in the other’s bodily centre:
Altercentric participation: Ego’s virtual participation in Alter’s act as if Ego were a
co-author of the act or being hand-guided from Alter’s stance. This is sometimes
unwittingly manifested overtly, for example, when lifting one’s leg when watching
a high jumper, or when opening one’s own mouth when putting a morsel into
another’s mouth . . . (Bråten 2000: 297–298)
A more general definition is given by Stern in the glossary of his book on The
Present Moment in Psychotherapy and Everyday Life. In the glossary he gives this
definition:
Altero-centered participation (Bråten 1998b) is the innate capacity to experience,
usually out of awareness, what another is experiencing [. . . ] as if your center
of orientation and perspective were centered in the other. [. . . ] It is the ba-
sic intersubjective capacity that makes imitation, empathy, sympathy, emotional
contagion, and identification possible. (Stern 2004: 241–242)
Whether manifested in the modus of pre-enactment, of co-enactment, or of re-
enactment, as in learning by imitation, this intersubjective capacity for participant
perception entails that the perceiver resonates with what the other is doing or expe-
riencing as if the perceiving Ego’s frame of reference were centred in Alter. That is
why I found the term ‘alter-centric’ appropriate when identifying such occurrences
in line with this virtual other postulate:
(P) The infant’s body-centred (ego-centric) embodied perspective is accompa-
nied by a virtual companion perspective, a virtual Alter, allowing for alter-
centric participation in actual others in the mode of felt immediacy (Bråten
1988, 2000).
JB[v.20020404] Prn:7/03/2007; 16:59 F: AICR6807.tex / p.4 (229-264)
Newborn imitation
Figure 1. A newborn girl (20 minutes old) exposed to and imitating a mouth opening
gesture, occurring in Crete 1983 and as recorded and recounted by Kugiumutzakis (1998).
When lecture audiences are shown this video, some in the audience will open their own
mouth slightly in advance of the recorded newborn’s attempt to imitate (Bråten 2003).
JB[v.20020404] Prn:7/03/2007; 16:59 F: AICR6807.tex / p.5 (264-328)
When Meltzoff and Moore (1977, 1983) published their reports on neona-
tal imitation this came as a chock to many of those who had been socialized in
the traditional Piagetian and object-relations theories to view infants as asocial or
egocentric. What is reported in their now classical Science paper is how each of the
newborns (between 12 and 22 days old), when exposed to the lightened face of
Andrew Meltzoff exhibiting tongue protrusion, or lip protrusion, or wide mouth
opening, took after his gesture in a manner that could not be explained away as a
reflex act or a coincidence.
What Kugiumutzakis did a few years later at Crete was to invite such and other
imitations, such as eyebrow moves and sounds, from much younger ones – some
between 20 and 45 minutes old. That was in 1983 (the same year which Meltzoff
and Moore reported gestural imitation in one-hour-olds). He even tried to in-
vite imitation of the sounds /a/, /m/, and /ang/. Only the former non-front vowel
/a/ was attempted imitated by such young newborns, while at two months they
managed better (Kugiumutzakis 1998: 74). A closer study of the video recordings
of those episodes will rule out reflex actions. They reveal the newborns’ intense
scrutiny of his whole face, not just of the mouth or eyebrow used in the movement,
and the time they need and the effort it takes to come up with a semblant gesture.
Take for example the girl, twenty minutes old, gazing intensely at his face as he
does a wide mouth-opening and then, after a while, coming up with a semblant
mouth movement with an obvious effort (Fig. 1).
In one way, the newborn may be seen intuitively to try to reach for the centre
of the other’s mind; in another way by a deliberate effort to come up with a gestu-
ral match (cf. Kugiumutzakis 1998: 80–81). Meltzoff and Moore (1998: 58) suggest
that infants have a self-oriented code for interpreting that the other is ‘Like Me’. I
have rather suggested that they are engaged in other-oriented perception resonat-
ing with the feeling of ‘Like You and Liking You’ – as if in the double sense to show
that ‘I am like you’ and ‘I like you’, so ‘Please, take care of me!’. In phylogenetic
terms of survival: they are making a case for being picked up because of their be-
ing like (and liking) the potential caretaker. Being unable to physically cling, as
pointed out by Bowlby (1984), they have to speedily connect by ‘mental clinging’.
This is suggested by the fact that it is easer to elicit neonatal imitation in the first
hour after birth, when survival would have been at stake in the wilderness, than
later on.
Regard the mouth of the infant feeders in Figure 2. Three impressive features are
revealed here:
JB[v.20020404] Prn:7/03/2007; 16:59 F: AICR6807.tex / p.6 (328-345)
lips as her big sister’s mouth closes on the morsel. Eibl-Eibesfeldt (1997) wonders
if this is “playful imitation”. I would rather say that what you see revealed here,
like what you yourself may unwittingly exhibit when feeding a child or a patient,
is taking a virtual part in the patient’s intake of the food, as if participating in the
other’s eating from the other’s stance, or virtually helping the other to grasp by
mouth the food offered.
stance – the very reverse of what is seen from an outside, egocentric stance in
such face-to-face situations. In order for infants to be able reciprocate the spoon-
feeding they must have been able to virtually partake in their caregivers’ previous
spoon-feeding activity as if they were co-authors of the feeding, even though their
caregivers have been the actual authors.
Such other-centred participation enables the infant learners (i) to transcend a self-
centred stance and engage from the performer’s stance (ii) as a virtual co-author of
the performance (iii) leaving an e-motional or participatory memory inviting (iv)
imitative re-enactment. The mirror neuron system affords a likely partial support
of such other-centred participation. Moreover, when the perceiver is face-to-face
with the performer and then prepares for circular re-enactment of what has been
perceived in an altercentric modus, a mirror reversal is entailed when the per-
ceiver transform from an other-centred frame of reference to the body-centred
(egocentric) frame of reference required for execution of the re-enactment.
Consider the simple imitation example of raising arms in the face-to-face situation
depicted in Figure 3 (left), and which actually is not so simple at all, at least not for
some subjects with autism who understand the adult model’s request ‘Do as I do!’
and try to comply (cf. Ohta 1987; Whiten & Brown 1998). What some of these
subjects with autism will do is to notice the inside of the model’s raised hands,
relate this to the inside of own hands, and then raise the hands with palms inward,
while ordinary children have no problems with doing what the model does, raising
their arms with palms outwards, as illustrated by the drawing. It appears to be
simple. In a face-to-face situation, however, this actually entails a mirror reversal
of what the child sees done by the model (palms inwards towards the child) to
what the child does when re-enacting (palm outwards from the child). It is a case
of transformation from the child’s other-centred perception of the adult’s model
act, as if the child were a co-author of that act from the adult’s bodily centre, to
the child’s executed re-enactment within the child’s own body-centred frame of
reference co-ordinates.
Both these face-to-face cases entail a transformation from the child’s other-
centred perception of the adult’s model act, as if the child were a co-author of that
act from the adult’s bodily centre, to the child’s executed re-enactment within the
child’s own body-centred frame of reference co-ordinates. Hence, there is a mirror
reversal from the altercentric frame evoked in the perception to the body-centred
JB[v.20020404] Prn:7/03/2007; 16:59 F: AICR6807.tex / p.9 (440-482)
cumbersome to simulate the arm raising movements with our simplistic models
(implemented in Java 1.02), and we turned instead to a simple hand sign, devoid
of moves, to which two alternative competing networks were exposed. So-called
“Ego-nets” were “trained” to reproduce the image without reversal, while “Alter-
nets” were “trained” for mirror reversal. Given the same frequency of “training”
sweeps (400 presentation of the input pattern) I was surprised to see that the Ego-
net and the Alter-net did not differ much in terms of error of time. From this I
reached the preliminary expectation that “an evolved system sensitized to alter-
centric (mirror) perception may be as speedy in operation as a system operating
from an egocentric perspective, incapable of reversal” (Bråten 2000: 295).1
Clearly, such a sensitized system, allowing for imitative learning to listen and to
cope from a distance and in face-to-face situations, would have afforded a critical
advantage to hominin infants deprived of the instructive and protective advantage
enjoyed by other back-riding primate offspring. This was one my points in a talk at
the conference on mirror neurons and the evolution of brain and language, which
Vittorio Gallese and Maxim Stamenov organized in Delmenhorst July 5–8 2000.
Here, a computational model by Aude Billard and Michal Arbib was presented
which offers an illustration of the frame of reference transformation entailed in an
imitation of arm-raising in face-to-face situations of the kind portrayed in Figure 3
(left). Proposing that the mirror neurons system afford neural mechanisms crucial
to learning by imitation, they focus on the capacity for representation underlying
imitation and investigate the neural mechanisms that may be involved, for exam-
ple, when the imitator is re-enacting the arm-raising done by the demonstrator in
a face-to-face situation. In one of the module concerned with input of visual data,
a frame of reference transformation is carried out: from the ‘eccentric’ frame in
terms of which the demonstrator’s arm raising is viewed to the ‘egocentric’ frame
of reference required for the imitator’s subsequent own execution (cf. Billard &
Arbib 2002: 346 (Fig. 1)).
An interesting feature of the Billard-Arbib model is the way in which they explic-
itly include a cerebellum module in addition to primary, premotor and temporal
JB[v.20020404] Prn:7/03/2007; 16:59 F: AICR6807.tex / p.11 (524-565)
cortex modules and such that the learning of new combination of movements
is modelled to be done in the premotor cortex and in the cerebellum modules,
pertaining specifically to the temporal move sequences. Thus, neurons in the
premotor cortex respond to both visual recognition of movements and to the
corresponding motor modulation commands produced by the cerebellum. This
pertains to a question about cerebellum raised in a seminar talk of mine in Parma
(June 2000) concerning the potential role of the cerebellum in a bodily frame of
reference transformation.
It is well documented that spinocerebellum subserves adjustment of own
body-centred movements (Ghez 1991). The spinocerebellum is evoked to subserve
adjustment of ongoing movements, probably making use of body mapping in two
different areas, the anterior lobe and the posterior lobe, of the spinocerebellum
cortex. Two different somatosensory maps of the body appear to be involved, in-
verted relative to one another: One in the anterior lobe with feet forward and face
extended backwards, while the other with a forward and possibly divided map-
ping of the head and limbs (Brodal 1995: 399; Ghez 1991: 634 with reference to the
findings of Adrian 1943; and of Snider & Stowell 1944). If these findings are still
accepted to apply also the human cerebellum, then we may ask: May cerebellum
play a part role, in conjunction inter alia with the adapted mirror neuron systems,
in subserving the kind of mirror reversal that is entailed in face-to-face imitative
situations? And furthermore, in which evolutionary conditions may such a mir-
ror neurons systems adaptation have played a particular critical role? To the latter
question I shall now turn.
Bråten (2000: 282–285). Here follows just some brief observations that pertains
to the above question.
Gaze-following from the back while virtual absence of prolonged eye-contact. The
above pertains to the preference of from behind positions, for example in groom-
ing, and the rare occurrences of face-to-face contact. Pertinent in this respect is
the virtual absence of prolonged eye-contact (as also stressed by Bruner (1996: 163
with reference to Savage-Rumbaugh et al. 1993).
When clinging to the mother’s back, offspring of great apes learn to ori-
ent themselves in the world in which they operate from the carrying mother’s
stance. Moving with her movements, they may even be afforded the opportu-
nity to learn by copying her movements (perhaps in the way that Byrne 1998
terms “program-level imitation”) without having to transcend own (egocentric)
body-centred perspective. In my periodic studies of captive chimpanzee-offspring
relations, I observe how the infants, when old enough to cling to the mother’s
back, not only bodily move with the mother’s movements but often adjust their
head to her movement direction, appearing to be gazing in the same direction as
she does. When a mother holds the infant in front of her for grooming (which
adults more often do from behind one another), a sort of face-to-face situation
is established, but not for the kind of reciprocal interplay entailing mutual gazing
and gesticulation which we observe in human infant-adult pairs.
That must have been prepared for in human evolution. Thus, based inter alia on
my comparative studies of infant-adult relations in humans and chimpanzees, I
have offered this Hominin Infant Decentration Hypothesis about how a decentred
JB[v.20020404] Prn:7/03/2007; 16:59 F: AICR6807.tex / p.13 (626-670)
mirror neurons system subserving learning to cope and take care by (m)other-
centred participation would have made a critical difference for hominin infants
who had lost the protective and instructive advantage of riding on their mothers’
back, as enjoyed by ape offspring. An evolved decentred capacity for learning by al-
tercentric perception to cope and take care would have overcome and compensated
for the loss of the instructive and protective advantage enjoyed by back-clinging
offsprings of other primates (Bråten 2002: 289–290, 2004: 508–509). In the vol-
ume on Mirror Neurons and the Evolution of Brain and Language (ed. by Stamenov
& Gallese 2002), and in a Behavioral and Brain Science commentary, I have pro-
posed that the efficient speech perception that may be observed in early human
ontogeny may be subserved by a phylogenetically afforded and adapted resonant
mirror system, decentred in phylogeny to subserve (m)other-centred participation
by hominin infants.
This is acknowledged by Falk (2004) in her response to commentators on her
target article on “Prelinguistic evolution in early hominins”:
i.e. without having to transcend own (egocentric) stance. In fact, modern chim-
panzee offspring appears only to be able share the mother’s perception when riding
on her back and looking in the same direction (which they tend to do), and pos-
sibly, as they grow older, to transcend own egocentric perspective in an allocentric
direction, which would be required for rudimentary imitative learning when not
facing the same direction as the model. Tomasello, who earlier has declared the
chimpanzee as incapable of imitative learning, acknowledges that enculturated
chimpanzees appear to more advanced in this respect, and later modifies his posi-
tion also with respect to non-cultivated chimpanzees. There is still a leap, however,
to the kind of frame of reference reversal that human infant learners are capa-
ble of when learning by imitation from face-to-face situations, while back-riding
chimpanzee infants are afforded instruction and protection without having to
transcend their body-centred perspective.
In any case, before the invention of baby slings or other baby-carrying facilities
(attributed by Leakey 1995: 94 to early Homo erectus), hominin species may have
been faced with extinction when turning bipedal, I have submitted, if their young
offspring were unable to listen and learn to cope and take care by (m)other-centred
mirroring and participation (Bråten 2000: 275).
JB[v.20020404] Prn:7/03/2007; 16:59 F: AICR6807.tex / p.14 (670-722)
Such a capacity is at play, as we have seen, even in early human ontogeny, facilitat-
ing the ontogenetic path to speech in the culture into which the child is born. This
path comprises inter alia these steps: Mutually attuned protoconversation in the
first months of life, and speech perception by the efficient infant learner entailing
that already by six months the infant may disregard sound distinctions that make
no sense in the ambient language (Kuhl 1998).
Patricia Kuhl points out that as they listen to speech they appear to include
more than the auditory characteristics; “the infants store ‘polymodal’ aspects of
speech – the auditory and visual speech they experience, and the motor pat-
terns they themselves produce” (Kuhl 1998: 300). She suggests that infants acquire
a life-long native-language accent inter alia by virtue of an innate link between
perception and action, extending the influence of linguistic experience beyond
perception to the motor patterns acquired in speech (cf. also Conboy & Kuhl this
volume).
If that is the case, then this may perhaps invite a specification in terms of
learning by altercentric perception of ambient speakers and virtual participation
in their speech production. Once established, Kuhl points out, the perceptual and
perceptual-motor system underlying speech is difficult to alter. This would some-
how entail that the learner, perhaps even the pre-verbal learner, be capable of
altercentric perception of and participation in the sound-producing movements
of the ambient speech performers. This kind of learning can hardly be accounted
for in terms of perspective-taking in a social-cognitive sense, but rather in an e-
motive and participatory sense of more primitive subjective experience evoking
temporal feeling flow patterns that are shared by the speaker and the learner.
Subserving verbal learning by (m)other-centred participation, this altercentric
capacity is supportive of verbal conversation to come with its reciprocal and par-
ticipant characteristics. Not only may the speaker co-process his own production
from the listener’s stance. The listener may co-articulate the speaker’s production
as if she or he were a coauthor. Such virtual co-articulation from the other’s stance
is manifested when a listener completes the speaker’s aborted sentence or answers
a half-spoken question. It is supported by the capacity for other-centred mirroring
and resonance that we see at play in protoconversation and response to motherese
(Bråten 1988, 2002, 2003; Trevarthen 1998; Stern 2000, 2004a).
Listening to fairytales. For example, in an Oxford study, Rall and Harris (2000)
find that when 3- and 4-year-olds are asked to retell fairytales, say about Cin-
derella, they manage best when the verbs in the stories listened to are consistent
with the stance of the protagonist with whom they identify, inviting their alter-
centric participation in ‘Cinderella’s slippers’, as it were. The children have trouble
when the verbs in the stories told are used from the reverse perspective, at odds
with their perspective-taking:
[it] would be plausible to conclude that listeners engage in what we might call
‘altercentric participation’ (Bråten 1998). This would allow us to make sense of
the fact that listeners not only encode movements and location in relation to the
protagonist, they also anticipate the emotional implications of impending events.
(Rall & Harris 2000: 207)
Now, above is an indication of how the listener may take the stance of the main
character in a story listened to. We may, of course, also observe the manifesta-
tions of such virtual participation during verbal conversation between speech-
competent partners. In verbal conversation partners, such simulation of mind
(Bråten 1973, 1974) by virtue of altercentric perspective-taking enables them
to complete one another’s utterances and to reply to one another’s half-spoken
questions. Conversation partners manifest their virtual other-centred participa-
tion inter alia by sentence completion as an overt manifestation of such virtual
participation in the other’s production.
When the listener completes the speaker’s statement. In conversations taped dur-
ing the fall and summer 1974 between Sartre (JPS) and de Beauvoir (SdB) there
sometimes occur passages in which one of them completes the unfinished utter-
ance made by the other. An example quotation was given in the beginning of this
chapter. Below is another quote from Simone de Beauvoir (1984) Adieux (Quota-
JB[v.20020404] Prn:7/03/2007; 16:59 F: AICR6807.tex / p.16 (765-823)
tions within [ ] in italics is taken from the French edition La cérémonie des adieux
(1981)). At some point in their conversations de Beauvoir asks Sartre about the
book he wrote about Genet, a writer friend of Sartre and of Cocteau, and she asks
Sartre about how Genet took the book Sartre had written about him, and Sartre
replies (on p. 273 in the English edition):
JPS: In a very odd fashion [. . . ] When I had finished I gave him the manuscript.
He read it, and one night he got up and went over to fireplace with the in-
tention of burning it [. . . ] It disgusted him because he felt that was as I had
described him, and although he was not disgusted with himself, yet . . . [Ca
le dégoûtait parce qu’il se sentait bien tel que je l’avais décrit et il n’était pas
dégoûté de lui, mais . . . ]
SdB: Yet he was disgusted that a book should be written about him [ . . . ] [Mais il
était dégoûté qu’on écrive un livre sur lui [ . . . ] (p. 389)]
Gallese and Goldman (1998) finds the discovery of mirror neurons to support the
simulation version, and not the theory version, of theory of mind assumptions.
Their conjecture is that the mirror neurons found in the macaque monkey brain
do not constitute a full-scale realization, but only a primitive version, or possibly
a precursor in phylogeny, of the simulation heuristic that might underlie mind-
reading as simulation of mind. The kind of matching occurring in mirror neurons
experiments between states or process in the observer and the observed, implies
processes of simulation (ST), not theory deductions (TT).
A further link between mirror neuron activity and simulation can be inferred from
the fact that, as the TMS experiment by Fadiga et al. [1995] demonstrates, the
human equivalent matching system facilitates in the observer that same muscle
groups as those utilized by the target [ . . . ] if ST were correct, and a mind-reader
represents an actor’s behavior by recreating in himself the plans or movement
intentions of the actor, then it is reasonable to predict that the same muscular ac-
tivation [when not entirely inhibited] will occur in the mind-reader. As matching
muscular activation is actually observed in the observer, this lends support to ST
[simulation of mind] as opposed to TT. (Gallese & Goldman 1998: 498)
But then, there is the question of whether such simulation is carried out in terms
of a body-centred (ego-centric) map, which would be the case for the macaque in
the observer’s position, or in terms of an other-centred map which would pertain
to ordinary human observers in face-to-face situations.
minds entails identification with the mental state of the other by virtue of “our
capacity for recentering our egocentric maps.” This is his conclusion:
[a]scent routines, coupled with our capacity for recentering our egocentric maps,
enable us directly, rather than by inference from our own case, to identify the
mental state of others. (Gordon 1995: 63)
In this chapter we have seen how perception of others’ acts invites participa-
tory perception as if being a virtual co-author of the perceived act, entailing
anticipatory or concurrent simulation and virtual co-enactment, or subsequent
imitative re-enactment. I have offered some illustrations of other-centred partic-
ipation in another’s performed or attempted act, manifested by the perceiver’s
co-movements. In the prologue (with Trevarthen, this volume) various layers of
intersubjectivity were distinguished. The illustrated occurrences may now be qual-
ified according to the proper layer of intersubjectivity at which they occur, and
according to their temporal relation to the perceived or anticipated (attempted)
performance by which they are evoked.
One of these episodes, comparable to the way in which spectators may engage in
the efforts of a performer at the sports arena, is the way in which some in the lec-
ture audience unwittingly opened their own mouth when watching on the screen
one of the newborns preparing itself for imitating Kugiumutzakis’ wide mouth
opening apparently to try to come to virtual aid of the newborn’s effort. Unlike
the detached mode of perception by an unmotivated observer, evoking no muscle
activation, the motivated viewers and participants in the above episodes exhibit
accompanying movements, with inhibition lifted by their engagement in the suc-
cessful outcome of the performance. Identifying with the performer, they may be
seen to be unwittingly pre- or co-enacting parts of the performance. At this layer of
JB[v.20020404] Prn:7/03/2007; 16:59 F: AICR6807.tex / p.19 (915-971)
The same applies to the caregiver or reciprocating infant who opens own mouth
slightly in advance or concurrently with the food or spoon with food being fed
into the patient’s mouth. For example, when spoon-feeding, also adult caregivers
often unwittingly open their own mouth as the mouth of the infant or patient
begins to open to take in the afforded food, reflecting how they identify with the
patient’s performance, virtually participating in the patient’s preparation to eat or
coming to “virtual” aid of the patient’s effort to eat. As we have seen, not only
adult caregivers do this. I have offered episodic illustrations of infants, between 11
and 12 months, who when allowed to take the spoon full of food in own hand, re-
ciprocate the caregiver’s spoon-feeding and sometimes open their mouth as they
clumsily offer the spoonful to the caregiver’s opening mouth. Such accompany-
ing mouth movements deserve the German label ‘Mitbewegungen’ (co-movement;
moving with) used, for example, to describe a recorded Yanomamo-infant who
opens the mouth when offering a morsel to the big sister’s mouth, and tightens
own lips as her mouth closes on the offered morsel (Eibl-Eibesfeldt 1997: 486).
This is not imitation, but an anticipatory and concurrent manifestation of vir-
tual participation in the other’s intake of the afforded food. The feeder’s mouth
movements attest to anticipatory simulation of the other’s food intake.
On the other hand, imitative learning by other-centred participation entails
circular re-enactment of the preceding model action of feeding. When the in-
fant reciprocates spoon-feeding from e-motional memory of having been a virtual
co-author of spoon-feeding, this attests to imitative learning by other-centred par-
ticipation in the caregiver’s previous spoon-feeding, for example as illustrated in
Figure 3 (right).
Another example that may properly be allocated to the object-oriented layer
of secondary intersubjectivity is provided by the toddlers in Meltzoff ’s behavioural
re-enactment experiment (cf. Meltzoff & Brooks this volume (9)). When exposed
JB[v.20020404] Prn:7/03/2007; 16:59 F: AICR6807.tex / p.20 (971-1026)
What the toddlers prove themselves capable of doing, successfully realizing and
completing an act that the experimenter failed to bring to a successful conclusion,
may be compared to the way in which listeners sometimes complete a half-spoken
utterance. When you more or less unwittingly complete covertly or overtly what
you experience that the other is about to say, you do so by virtue of altercentric
participation in the other’s speech act. Even though the other is the initial author
of the incomplete sentence, your virtual co-author participation in what is about
to be said enables you to overtly join in the co-authorship. The listener may be seen
to be virtually co-authoring the speaker’s talking as soon as the listener realizes the
end-point towards which the utterance is headed. This is illustrated by the snap-
shots from the conversations between Jean Paul Sartre and Simone de Beauvoir,
reported in Adieux, and quoted above and in the beginning of this chapter. Here,
Sartre manifests by his completion of her statements, his other-centred participa-
tion in what she is about to utter. Even though the other is the initial author of the
incomplete sentence he is listening to, his virtual co-author participation in what
has already been said enables him to overtly join in the co-authorship.
Note
presented to the ‘perceiving’ net, inviting mirror reversal, corresponding to how it is re-enacted
from an egocentric stance). While in one experimental run (with 400 training sweeps, using the
tlearn network developed at Oxford (cf. Plunkett & Elman 1997)) the Ego-net was trained to
reproduce the image of the input pattern without any reversal, while the Alter-net was trained
to reproduce the reverse image. The result was that the two competing networks did not differ
much in terms of time or numbers of errors. Relative time and errors increased, however, given
the same number of training sweeps, when the Alter-net was trained to respond both in terms
of ego-input and a mirror reversal.
References
Adrian, E. P. (1943). “Afferent areas in the cerebellum connected with the limbs.” Brain, 66,
289–315.
Beauvoir, S. de (1986). Adieux. A Farewell to Sartre (transl. by Patrick O. Brian). Hamondsworth:
Penguin Books. (In French: Le Céremonie des adieux Édition Gallimard 1981.)
Billard, A., & Arbib, M. (2002). “Mirror neurons and the neural basis for learning by imitation:
Computational modeling.” In M. Stamenov & V. Gallese (Eds.), Mirror Neurons and the
Evolution of Brain and Language (pp. 343–352). Amsterdam/Philadelphia: John Benjamins.
Bowlby, J. (1984). Attachment and Loss. Reading: Pelican Books.
Bråten, S. (1973). Tegnbehandling og meningsutveksling (On sign processing and simulation of
mind during conversation). Oslo: Universitetsforlaget / Scandinavian University Books.
Bråten, S. (1974). “Coding simulation circuits during symbolic interaction.” In Proceedings
of the 7th International Congress on Cybernetics 1973 (pp. 327–336). Namur: Assocation
Internationale de Cybernetique.
Bråten, S. (1988). “Dialogic Mind: The Infant and Adult in Protoconversation.” In M. Carvallo
(Ed.), Nature, Cognition and System, I (pp. 187–205). Dordrecht: Kluwer Academic
Publishers.
Bråten, S. (1998a). Kommunikasjon og samspill – fra fødsel til alderdom (Communication and
Interplay from Birth to Old Age). Oslo: Tano-Aschehoug. (Danish edition: Dafolo Forlag
1999.)
Bråten, S. (1998b). “Infant learning by altercentric participation: The reverse of egocentric
observation in autism.” In S. Bråten (Ed.), Intersubjective Communication and Emotion in
Early Ontogeny (pp. 105–124). Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
Bråten, S. (2002). “Altercentric perception by infants and adults in dialogue.” In M. Stamenov
& V. Gallese (Eds.), Mirror Neurons and the Evolution of Brain and Language (pp. 273–294).
Amsterdam/Philadelphia: John Benjamins.
Bråten, S. (2003a). “In Gegensatz zu Piagets Theorie: Spracherwerb und Sprachentwicklung
von einem alterzentrischen Standpunkt.” In N. Psarros, P. Stekeler-Weithofer, & G.
Voruba (Eds.), Die Entwicklung sozialer Wirklichkeit (pp. 61–88). Weilerswisst: Velbrück
Wissenschaft.
Bråten, S. (2003b). “Participant perception of others’ acts: Virtual otherness in infants and
adults.” Culture & Psychology, 9 (3), 261–276.
Bråten, S. (2004). “The hominin infant decentration hypothesis: Mirror neurons system adapted
to subserve mother-centred participation.” Commentary Behavioral and Brain Sciences, 27
(4), 508–509.
JB[v.20020404] Prn:7/03/2007; 16:59 F: AICR6807.tex / p.22 (1118-1240)
Bråten, S., & Trevarthen, C. (1994/2000). “Beginnings of cultural learning.” Talk at the ZiF
symposium on The Formative process of society, Bielefeld 17–19 Nov. 1994. In S. Bråten
(Ed.), Modellmakt og altersentriske spedbarn. Essays on Dialogue in Infant & Adult (pp. 213–
218). Bergen: Sigma 2000.
Bråten, S., &. Gallese, V. (2004). “On mirror neurons systems implications for social cognition
and intersubjectivity” (Interview by the journal editors L. T. Westlye & T. Weinholdt).
Impuls, 58 (3), 97–107.
Brodal, P. (1995). Sentralnervesystemet. Bygning og funksjon. Oslo: Tano Aschehoug.
Bruner, J. (1996). The Culture of Education. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.
Byrne, R. W. (1998). “Imitation: The contribution of priming and program-level copying.” In S.
Bråten (Ed.), Intersubjective Communication and Emotion in Early Ontogeny (pp. 228–244).
Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
Davies, M., & Stone, T. (Eds.). (1995). Mental Simulation. Oxford: Blackwell.
Darwin, C. (1872/1955). The Expression of the Emotions in Man and Animals. New York:
Philosophical Library.
Di Pellegrino, G., Fadiga, L., Fogassi, L., Gallese, V., &. Rizzolatti, G. (1992). “Understanding
motor events: A neurophysiological study.” Experimental Brain Research, 91, 176–180.
Dunn, J. (1998). “Sibling, Emotion and the Development of Understanding.” In S. Bråten (Ed.),
Intersubjective Communication and Emotion in Early Ontogeny (pp. 158–168). Cambridge:
Cambridge University Press.
Eibl-Eibesfeldt, I. (1979). “Human ethology: Concepts and implications for the sciences of man.”
Behavioral and Brain Sciences, 2, 1–57.
Eibl-Eibesfeldt, I. (1997). Die Biologie des menschlichen Verhaltens. Weyarn: Seehamer Verlag.
Falk, D. (2004). “Prelinguistic evolution in early hominins: Whence motherese?” Behavioral and
Brain Sciences, 27 (4), 491–503. (Cf. also Author’s response in the same issue: 527–534.)
Falk, D. (2004). “The “putting the baby down” hypothesis.” Author’s response to commentaries.
Behavioral and Brain Sciences, 27 (4), 527–534.
Fogel, A. (2004). “Remembering infancy: Accessing our earliest experiences.” In G. Bremner &
A. Slater (Eds.), Theories of Infant Development (pp. 204–230). Cambridge: Blackwell.
Gallese, V., & Goldman, A. (1998). “Mirror neurons and the simulation theory of mind-
reading.” Trends in Cognitive Science, 2 (12), 293–450.
Ghez, C. (1991). “The Cerebellum.” In E. R. Kandel et al. (Eds.), Principles of Neural Science (3rd
ed.) (pp. 626–646). New York/Amsterdam: Elsevier.
Gordon, R. M. (1995). “Simulation without introspection or inference from me to you.” In
M. Davies & T. Stone (Eds.), Mental Simulation (pp. 53–67). Oxford: Blackwell.
Harris, P. L. (1998). “Fictional absorption: Emotional response to make-believe.” In S. Bråten
(Ed.), Intersubjective Communication and Emotion in Early Ontogeny (pp. 336–353).
Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
Kugiumutzakis, G. (1998)). “Neonatal imitation in the intersubjective companion space.” In S.
Bråten (Ed.), Intersubjective Communication and Emotion in Early Ontogeny (pp. 63–88).
Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
Kuhl, P. (1998). “Language, culture and intersubjectivity.” In S. Bråten (Ed.), Intersubjective
Communication and Emotion in Early Ontogeny (pp. 297–315). Cambridge: Cambridge
University Press.
Leakey, R. (1995). The Origin of Humankind. London. Phoenix.
Liberman, A. M. (1957). “Some results of research on speech perception.” J. of Acoustic Soc. Am.,
29, 117–123.
JB[v.20020404] Prn:7/03/2007; 16:59 F: AICR6807.tex / p.23 (1240-1354)
Meltzoff, A. N., & Moore, M. K. (1977). “Imitation of facial and manual gestures by human
neonates.” Science, 198, 75–78.
Meltzoff, A. N., & Moore, M. (1983). “Newborn infants imitate facial gestures.” Child
Development, 54, 702–709.
Meltzoff, A. N., & Moore, M. K. (1998). “Infant intersubjectivity: Broading the dialogue to
include imitation, identity and intention.” In S. Bråten (Ed.), Intersubjective Communication
and Emotion in Early Ontogeny (pp. 47–62). Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
NRK1 (Norwegian Broacasting Corporation) (2000). Report from the Summer Olympic Games,
Sidney.
Ohta, M. (1987). “Cognitive disorder of infantile autism.” J. of Autism and Developmental
Disorders, 17, 45–62.
Piaget, J. (1926/1959). The Language and Thought of the Child. London: Routledge.
Plunkett, K., & Elman, J. E. (1997). Exercises in Rethinking Innateness. Cambridge, MA: MIT
Press.
Rall, J., &. Harris, P. L. (2000). “In Cinderella’s slippers? Story comprehension from the
protagonist’s point of view.” Developmental Psychology, 36, 202–208.
Rizzolatti, G., & Arbib, M. (1998). “Language within our grasp.” Trends in Neurosciences, 21 (5),
188–193.
Rommetveit, R. (1972). Språk, tanke og kommunikasjon. Oslo: Universitetsforlaget.
Rommetveit, R. (1974). On Message Structure. New York: Wiley.
Rommetveit, R. (1998). “Intersubjective attunement and linguistically mediated meaning
in discourse.” In S. Bråten (Ed.), Intersubjective Communication and Emotion in Early
Ontogeny (pp. 154–371). Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
Rossnes, R. (2004). “I think I understand what you mean: Negotiating intersubjective
understanding.” In A. Carlen, R. Klev, & G. von Krogh (Eds.), Living Knowledge (pp. 99–
113). New York: Palgrave Macmillan.
Savage-Rambaugh, E. S., Sue, E., Murphy, J., Seveik, R. A., Brakke, K. B., Williams, S. L., &
Rambaugh, D. M. (1993). “Language comprehension in ape and child.” Monographs of the
Society for Research in Child Development, 58 (3–4), Serial No. 233.
Smith, A. (1790/1976). The Theory of Moral Sentiments (6 ed., published 1976). Oxford:
Clarendon Press.
Snider, R. S., & Stowell, A. (1944). “Receiving areas of the tactile, auditory, and visual system in
the cerebellum.” J. Neurophysiology, 7, 331–357.
Stamenov, M., & V. Gallese, V. (Eds.). (2002). Mirror Neurons and the Evolution of Brain and
Language. Amsterdam/Philadelphia: John Benjamins.
Stern, D. N. (2000). “Introduction to the paperback edition.” In D. N. Stern (Ed.), The
Interpersonal World of the Infant (pp. xi–xxxix). New York: Basic Books. (Also London:
Karnac 2003.)
Stern, D. N. (2004). The Present Moment in Psychotherapy and Everyday Life. New York: Norton.
Tomasello, M., Kruger, A. C., & Ratner, H. H. (1993). “Cultural learning.” Behavioral and Brain
Sciences, 16, 495–525.
Trevarthen, C. (1979). “Communication and cooperation in early infancy: A description of
primary intersubjectivity.” In M. M. Bullowa (Ed.), Before Speech (pp. 321–347). New York:
Cambridge University Press.
Trevarthen, C. (1986). “Development of intersubjective motor control in infants.” In M. G.
Wade & H. T. A. Whiting (Eds.), Motor Development in Children (pp. 209–261). Dordrecht:
Martinus Nijhoff.
JB[v.20020404] Prn:7/03/2007; 16:59 F: AICR6807.tex / p.24 (1354-1414)
Appendix
On the difference between imitation and anticipatory embodied simulation
As we saw in the openings episodes, when committed to a positive outcome by the performer,
the spectator may come to manifest semblant movements in advance of or concurrent with the
performer’s movements, much like a feeder does who opens her mouth slightly in advance of
her patient’s opening the mouth to receive her food. This is strictly speaking not imitation which
more or less entails copying a preceding act, and differs in terms of time with what a spectator
may reveal by virtue of his empathic identification in sympathy with a performer’s effort through
anticipatory or concurrent simulation of what the other is about to do or utter.
Return again to Figure 2. When the feeding children mirror by their mouth movements
the recipient’s mouth movements what we see manifested here, just like what feeding adult un-
wittingly do, is other-centred participation in an unwitting mode of anticipatory or concurrent
simulation. Again, this is not imitation. In terms of time and execution one may distinguish be-
tween imitation and simulation – while imitation entails an executed re-enactment of the whole
model act after the fact of the model’s enactment of that act, simulation entails an internal vir-
tual enactment which may, but need not be, accompanied by overt manifestations of any kind.
While a model act, occurring at t, is followed by an imitative act at t + 1, by virtue of altercentric
participation at t, simulation may be concurrent at t or even anticipatory, at t – 1. For example,
the Yanomami-girl (probably about 12 months of age) (Fig. 2), opens her mouth as she extends
the morsel towards her sister’s mouth, and tightens her lips as her sister’s mouth closes on the
food (shown by photo recordings by Eibl-Eibesfeldt 1979: 15, 1997: 486 (Fig. 4.88)). This is a
manifestation of other-centred anticipation of what the other is about to do. The baby antici-
pates by her mouth movements what the other is going to do when taking in the food. Imitative
learning by other-centred participation, on the other hand, entails circular re-enactment of the
pre-ceding model action following from the learner virtual participation in the feeding to which
the learner has been subjected to.
Let E.p denote the executed manual act of feeding and E.q the executed mouth act of taking
in the food, while *A.*p’ and *A.*q’ mark altercentric participation in respectively alter’s feeding
and food-intake, involving the virtual-Alter mechanism *A. Then we may specify:
JB[v.20020404] Prn:7/03/2007; 16:59 F: AICR6807.tex / p.25 (1414-1475)
Caregiver (E.p; *A.*q’) → Infant learner (E.q; *A.*p’) → Re-enacting infant (E.p’)
Thus, the caregiver execution of feeding (while participating in the baby’s food-intake) evokes
in the infant concurrent intake of food and virtual participation in the caregiver’s feeding, which
in turn invites and enables the baby – when allowed to take the spoon in own hand – to feed
the caregiver in a semblant manner. This is learning by imitation, while the feeder’s antici-
patory mouth movements revealing virtual other participation in the patient’s food intake is
anticipatory or concurrent embodied simulation (cf. Bråten 2002: 290–291).
JB[v.20020404] Prn:21/03/2007; 16:01 F: AICR6808.tex / p.1 (49-118)
chapter
Introduction
Although neuroimaging studies over the past two decades have shed light on the
neural basis of speech and language function, the genetic basis of this unique
human ability has remained elusive. Recently, a gene involved in the neurode-
velopmental process that culminates in speech and language was identified (Lai
et al. 2001). This discovery was made possible mainly through the study of the
three-generational KE family, half of whose 30 members suffer from a severe ver-
bal and orofacial dyspraxia. Here, we review the neuropsychological as well as the
structural and functional magnetic resonance imaging (MRI) findings in the KE
family (see also Vargha-Khadem et al. 2005). We will consider the putative role of
the FOXP2 gene on brain structure and function, and, ultimately, on speech and
language development.
The disorder in the affected KE members was first reported by geneticists at
the University College London Institute of Child Health (Hurst et al. 1990) who
described serious communication difficulties in several members of the family.
The disorder was characterized as a severe form of developmental verbal dyspraxia.
In 1992, Marcus Pembrey described the regular Mendelian transmission of the
disorder with autosomal mode of inheritance. The pedigree of the KE family is
shown in Figure 1a.
JB[v.20020404] Prn:21/03/2007; 16:01 F: AICR6808.tex / p.2 (118-173)
Figure 1a. From Vargha-Khadem, F. et al., PNAS 1998. Pedigree of KE family. Roman
numerals indicate the generation, and Arabic numerals, the member’s pedigree number
within a generation. Affected members, filled shapes; unaffected members, open shapes;
females, circles; males, squares; /, deceased; ^, twins.
It was initially claimed that the affected family members had a selective impair-
ment in applying the morphosyntactic rules of grammar. The deficit was charac-
terized as “feature blindness” (Gopnik 1990), for example, an inability to apply
the “ed” rule and inflect regular verbs to indicate past tense. This claim was largely
negated, however, when on a test of past tense production the affected members
were found to commit a high number of errors across both regular and irregular
verb categories (Vargha-Khadem et al. 1995). Furthermore, the affected mem-
bers showed many over-regularization errors, suggesting that they had acquired
knowledge of the ‘ed’ rule for inflecting verbs but they were applying the rule in-
appropriately just as younger children do when their language skills are developing
(Vargha-Khadem et al. 1995).
Throughout the investigations of the affected KE members, a primary goal
was to establish the core phenotype of the disorder through quantitative tests
that revealed affected versus unaffected status. As a group, the affected mem-
JB[v.20020404] Prn:21/03/2007; 16:01 F: AICR6808.tex / p.3 (173-183)
Figure 1b. Adapted from Vargha-Khadem, F. et al., PNAS 1998. (a) Word and nonword
repetition. Bars indicate mean percent correct for the groups of affected and unaffected
family members (n = 13 and 10, respectively). Dark bars, affected group; light bars, un-
affected group; small squares, scores of individual family members. Note the absence of
overlap between the scores of the two groups on both tests. (b) Simultaneous and sequen-
tial orofacial movements to command. Bars indicate mean percent correct for the group of
affected family members and the normal control group (n = 11 and 52, respectively). Dark
bar, affected group; light bar, control group; small squares, scores of individuals (for clar-
ity, the same score obtained by two or more control subjects is marked by a single square).
Again note the absence of overlap between the scores of the two, groups, except for one
statistical outlier in the control group.
bers were impaired relative to the unaffected members on virtually every measure
of expressive and receptive language, grammar, and even nonverbal intelligence
(Vargha-Khadem et al. 1995). However, among the 30 neuropsychological tests
administered, two showed no overlap between the scores of the affected and the
unaffected individuals, thus clearly identifying the status of each family member.
The first was the ‘Word and Non-word’ Repetition Test, providing a measure of
phonological short term memory (Gathercole & Baddeley 1990), while the second
was a test of orofacial movement imitation that did not require the production of
speech sounds (Alcock et al. 2000). Scores obtained from these two tests clearly
distinguished the performance of the affected from the unaffected members thus
establishing the core phenotype of the disorder (Figure 1b).
JB[v.20020404] Prn:21/03/2007; 16:01 F: AICR6808.tex / p.4 (183-222)
When the Word and Non-word Repetition results were further examined, it
was found that complex words and non-words (both types consisting of con-
sonant vowel combinations) considerably taxed the articulation capacity of the
affected members. Furthermore, their difficulties with articulation became more
pronounced as the number of syllables in words and nonwords increased (Watkins
et al. 2002a). Similarly, the affected members’ difficulties became especially promi-
nent during the execution of sequential movements on the orofacial imitation test
(Alcock et al. 2000).
In summary, the core phenotype in the affected members is a verbal and an
orofacial dyspraxia evident during execution of movement sequences. There are
associated deficits, however, but it remains to be determined whether these are a
direct result of the core deficits or independent deficits.
The two patterns just described thus appear to reflect the fact that:
i. developmental plasticity in the affected members leads to greater fluency than
in the aphasic patients;
ii. this plasticity does not confer any advantage in word repetition, on which, in-
stead, the stroke patients perform better, presumably because of prior knowl-
edge;
iii. neither developmental plasticity nor prior knowledge yields an advantage in
repetition of non-words, where both groups are impaired about equally.
Having identified the phenotype, the brain implications of this disorder were next
investigated. Here the critical question was which regions of the brain, and in par-
ticular which regions likely to be part of the circuitry that produces coherent and
intelligible speech, did not develop properly. In addressing this question, the is-
sues of age at injury and laterality of function must be first considered in relation
to two hypotheses about the phenotype in the affected KE members. In adult-
hood, injury to the left hemisphere alone is sufficient to produce a chronic and
severe aphasia. In contrast, in childhood, chronic aphasia results only if there is
bilateral pathology of the perisylvian regions, with unilateral pathology leading
to only subtle language deficits at most (Bates et al. 2001). Since it is unusual to
sustain bilateral lesions to the speech and language areas of the cerebral hemi-
spheres during development, cases of congenital aphasia are extremely rare (but
see, Vargha-Khadem et al. 1985). Given that the chronic speech and language
disorder in the affected KE members is neurodevelopmental, the first hypothesis
was that the brain pathology would be bilateral. The second hypothesis was that
the brain regions affected would include one or more components of the motor
system, because one of the core deficits is an orofacial dyspraxia. Thus, the two
hypotheses called for bilaterality and involvement of the motor system.
ten affected and seven unaffected family members, as well as from 17 age- and
sex-matched normal controls. Findings included comparisons of affected with un-
affected members, and affected with controls. The results were mostly consistent
across both sets of comparisons. The most important finding was that the cau-
date nucleus had decreased grey matter density bilaterally. In terms of increased
grey matter, three sites of abnormality were indicated – the putamen bilaterally,
left frontal operculum and the left anterior insula. A newly-designed voxel-based
morphometry analysis aimed at detecting abnormalities that affect homotopic re-
gions of the left and right cerebral hemispheres was used to identify loci of bilateral
abnormalities in the affected members (Salmond et al. 2000). When this tech-
nique was applied to the above MR data sets, the previous bilateral findings were
replicated (Belton et al. 2003), with less gray matter density in the inferior frontal
gyrus, precentral gyrus, temporal pole, caudate nucleus and cerebellum. More gray
matter was found in the posterior superior temporal gyrus, angular gyrus, and
the putamen.
Volumetric analyses
On the basis of these findings, volumetric analyses of the caudate nucleus were
carried out (Watkins et al. 2002b). The results, corrected for intracranial volume,
indicated significant reduction in the affected compared to unaffected KE family
members. However, there was overlap between the datasets of the two groups in
terms of individual caudate volumes, suggesting that this measure is not as ac-
curate as the behavioural phenotype in differentiating affected from unaffected
status. Overall, there was about 25% reduction of volume in the caudate nucleus
bilaterally in the affected group.
In the affected members of the KE family, numerous cortical and subcortical re-
gions involved in speech and language showed subtle structural abnormalities on
morphometric analyses. To investigate whether these abnormalities impacted on
the functioning of those brain regions, especially during speech and language tasks,
a functional magnetic resonance imaging (fMRI) study was carried out (Liégeois
et al. 2003) addressing the following questions:
1. Is brain activation during language tasks typical or atypical in the affected
members?
2. If brain activation is atypical, are the functional abnormalities located in re-
gions that are also morphologically abnormal?
3. Are the regions activated by language distributed abnormally?
JB[v.20020404] Prn:21/03/2007; 16:01 F: AICR6808.tex / p.7 (328-373)
Two experiments were conducted. The first examined brain activation during a
silent word retrieval task where single verbs were generated in response to nouns
presented (i.e. covert verb generation). In the second experiment, two overt tasks
were used where this time responses were spoken, namely, overt verb generation
and word repetition.
The four groups studied consisted of a group of affected members and their
matched controls, and a group of unaffected members and their matched con-
trols (n = 5 in each group). Verb generation requires word comprehension, as
well as semantic search and word retrieval. When contrasted to a rest period that
does not involve language (e.g., listening to bursts of noise), normal participants
typically show left hemisphere activation, including Broca’s and Wernicke’s areas.
Average maps of activation indicated that the unaffected group and the control
groups showed this typical pattern of activation. In contrast, the activation map
in the affected group was atypical and diffuse, and distributed posteriorly and
bilaterally relative to that of the other groups. Interestingly, no activation was
detected in Broca’s area or its homologue in the right hemisphere. In order to
localize regions of functional abnormality, an interaction analysis was conducted.
This analysis enabled the comparison of activation in the unaffected and affected
groups, while controlling for factors such as sex, age and handedness. Some re-
gions were significantly less (underactive) while others were significantly more
(overactive) active in the affected group than in the other groups. Significant un-
deractivation was detected in several regions of the left hemisphere implicated in
language and motor functions, namely, the posterior part of Broca’s area (pars
opercularis), the primary motor cortex, and the supramarginal gyrus. In addi-
tion, underactivation was detected in the right putamen/globus pallidus, and right
inferior frontal gyrus (Brodmann’s area 45). There were numerous areas of overac-
tivation located in the occipital, parietal and temporal regions. These are difficult
to interpret since they may reflect compensatory strategies to perform the task, or
indicate functional reorganization to those regions that are not usually involved in
subserving language.
Results from the covert verb generation task revealed areas of functional abnor-
mality during a task that requires motor planning and programming as well as
semantic search and retrieval, but not articulation per se. In view of the pheno-
type of verbal and orofacial dyspraxia, it was important to determine whether
functional abnormalities were also observed during tasks requiring the execution
JB[v.20020404] Prn:21/03/2007; 16:01 F: AICR6808.tex / p.8 (373-441)
References
Alcock, K. J., Passingham, R. E., Watkins, K. E., & Vargha-Khadem, F. (2000). “Oral dyspraxia in
inherited speech and language impairment and acquired dysphasia.” Brain Lang, 75, 17–33.
Bates, E., Reilly, J.,Wulfeck, B. et al. (2001). “Differential effects of unilateral lesions on language
production in children and adults.” Brain Lang, 79, 223–265.
Belton, E., Salmond, C. H., Watkins, K. E., Vargha-Khadem, F., & Gadian, D. G. (2003).
“Bilateral brain abnormalities associated with dominantly inherited verbal and orofacial
dyspraxia.” Hum. Brain Mapping, 18, 194–200.
Gathercole, S. E., & Baddeley, A. D. (1990). “Phonological memory deficits in language
disordered children: Is there a causal connection?” Journal of Memory and Language, 29,
336–360.
Gopnik, M. (1990). “Feature-blind grammar and dysphagia.” Nature, 344, 715.
Hillis, A. E., Barker, P. B., Wityk, R. J. et al. (2004a). “Variability in subcortical aphasia is due to
variable sites of cortical hypoperfusion.” Brain Lang, 89, 524–530.
Hillis, A. E., Work, M., Barker, P. B., Jacobs, M. A., Brees, E. L., & Maurer, K. (2004b).
“Reexamining the brain regions crucial for orchestrating speech articulation.” Brain, 127,
1479–1487.
Hurst, J. A., Baraitser, M., Auger, E., Graham, F., & Norell, S. (1990). “An extended family with
a dominantly inherited speech disorder.” Dev Med Child Neurol, 32 (4), 352–355.
JB[v.20020404] Prn:21/03/2007; 16:01 F: AICR6808.tex / p.10 (491-578)
Lai, C. S., Fisher, S. E., Hurst, J. A., Vargha-Khadem, F., & Monaco, A. P. (2001). “A forkhead-
domain gene is mutated in a severe speech and language disorder.” Nature, 413, 519–523.
Liegeois, F., Baldeweg, T., Connelly, A., Gadian, D. G., Mishkin, M., & Vargha-Khadem,
F. (2003). “Language fMRI abnormalities associated with FOXP2 gene mutation.”
NatNeurosci, 6 (11), 1230–1237.
Liegeois, F., & Connelly, A., Cross, J. H. et al. (2004). “Language reorganization in children with
early-onset lesions of the left hemisphere: An fMRI study.” Brain, 127, 1229–1236.
Nadeau, S. E., & Crosson, B. (1997). “Subcortical aphasia.” Brain Lang, 58, 355–402.
Pembrey, M. E. (1992). “Genetics and language disorders.” In P. Fletcher & D. Hall (Eds.), Specific
Speech and Language Disorders in Children: Correlates, Characteristics, and Outcomes (pp.
51–62). London: Whurr.
Pickett, E. R., Kuniholm, E., Protopapas, A., Friedman, J., & Lieberman, P. (1998). “Selective
speech motor, syntax and cognitive deficits associatedwith bilateral damage to the putamen
and the head of the caudate nucleus: A case study.” Neuropsychologia, 36, 173–188.
Rizzolatti, G., & Arbib, M. A. (1998). “Language within our grasp.” Trends Neurosci., 21, 188–
194.
Salmond, C. H., Ashburner, J., Vargha-Khadem, F., Gadian, D. G., & Friston, K. J.
(2000). “Detecting bilateral abnormalities with voxel-based morphometry.” Human Brain
Mapping, 11, 223–232.
Tallal, P., Jernigan, T. L., & Trauner, D. (1994). “Developmental bilateral damage to the head
of the caudate nuclei: Implications for Speech-Language pathology.” Journal of Medical
Speech-Language Pathology, 2, 23–28.
Vargha-Khadem, F., Watters, G. V., & O’Gorman, A. M. (1985). “Development of speech and
language following bilateral frontal lesions.” Brain Lang, 25, 167–183.
Vargha-Khadem, F., Watkins, K. E., Alcock, K. J., Fletcher, P., & Passingham, R. E. (1995). “Praxic
and non-verbal cognitive deficits in a large family with a genetically transmitted speech and
language Disorder.” Proceedings of the National Academy of Science, 92, 930–933.
Vargha-Khadem, F., Watkins, K. E., Price, C. E., Ashburner, J., Alcock, K. J., Connelly, A. et al.
(1998). “Neural basis of an inherited speech and language disorder.” Proceedings of the
National Academy of Science, 95, 12695–12700.
Vargha-Khadem, F., Gadian, D. G., Copp, A., & Mishkin, M. (2005). “FOXP2 and the
neuroanatomy of speech and language.” Nature Reviews Neuroscience, 6, 131–138.
Watkins, K. E., Dronkers, N. F., & Vargha-Khadem, F. (2002a). “Behavioural analysis of an
inherited speech and language disorder: Comparison with acquired aphasia.” Brain, 125,
452–464.
Watkins, K. E., Vargha-Khadem, F., Ashburner, J. et al. (2000b). “MRI analysis of an inherited
speech and language disorder: Structural brain abnormalities.” Brain, 125, 465–478.
JB[v.20020404] Prn:27/10/2006; 11:04 F: AICR68P3.tex / p.1 (48-76)
chapter
The intellectual ferment derives in large measure from the fact that, within our
lifetimes, we have witnessed the overturning of one of the most pervasive myths
in social science – the myth of the asocial infant. On classical views of human de-
velopment, the newborn is cut off from others. Freud and his followers proposed
a distinction between a physical and psychological birth. When the baby is born
there is a physical birth but not yet an interpersonal birth (Freud 1911; Mahler,
Pine, & Bergman 1975). The baby is like an unhatched chick, incapable of inter-
acting as a social being because a ‘barrier’ leaves the newborn cut off from external
reality. Freud struggles to find a metaphor for the newborn-parent relationship
and ended up likening the child’s situation to the isolation found inside a shell: “A
neat example of a psychical system shut off from the stimuli of the external world...
is afforded by a bird’s egg with its food supply enclosed in its shell; for it, the care
provided by its mother is limited to the provision of warmth” (Freud 1911: 220).
Piaget’s (1952, 1954) newborn is similar, but he uses a philosophical rather
than biological metaphor. He believed that the baby is ‘radically egocentric’ or
even ‘solipsistic.’ The neonate has only a few reflexes at her disposal (e.g., sucking,
grasping), and people are registered only to the extent that they can be assimi-
lated to these action schemes. The child breaks free of the inborn solipsism by 18
months. It is a very long and hard journey from solipsism to establishing intersub-
jective understanding of others’ minds and emotions: “During the earliest stages
the child perceives things like a solipsist... This primitive relation between subject
and object is a relation of undifferentiation... when no distinction is made between
the self and the non-self ” (Piaget 1954: 352–355).
Skinner (1953) claimed that the newborn had even less to work with. One
cannot quote from Skinner about how children come to feel a sense of intersubjec-
tivity with others, because, in a sense, he does not think they ever do. Even adults
are described as reacting to behaviours and not to participating in the hearts and
minds of their interactive partners. Human beings have exquisite contingency de-
tectors, and that is all there is. To use Skinner’s phrase, intersubjectivity is largely
a ‘matter of consequences’ (Skinner 1983), by which he means that people are im-
portant only as shapers of the child’s behaviour. In theory, a Skinner box would do
just as well as a mother’s embrace if the contingencies were programmed correctly.
Against all three of these views are precursors to the modern-day findings of an
innate intersubjectivity. Philosophers such as Husserl (1950/1960) and Merleau-
Ponty (1945/1962) and psychologists such as Baldwin (1906) and Mead (1934)
refused to portray the human from an ‘isolationist’ perspective and saw a deep
connection between self and other. Modern-day findings support and elaborate
the ideas of these pioneers (see Gallagher & Meltzoff 1996 for an analysis of
JB[v.20020404] Prn:7/03/2007; 17:04 F: AICR6809.tex / p.3 (160-211)
In this chapter we wish to discuss three phenomena that illuminate the nature of
preverbal intersubjectivity: (a) action imitation, (b) joint visual attention, and (c)
sensitivity to intentionality. These phenomena make manifest the intrinsic bonds
infants have with social others. Bråten (2004) calls it ‘participant perception’ and
Hobson (Hobson & Lee 1999; Hobson & Meyer 2005) discusses ‘identification’ –
but, regardless of the label, the convergent point is that infants respond to the
actions of people in special ways revealing a desire for sharing in their experiences.
We discuss three kinds of social sharing that are interconnected developmentally
and philosophically.
First we discuss imitation, which shows a sharing of actions. This action shar-
ing is literally present at birth and tells us much about the intersubjectivity that
infants bring to their first encounters with embodied others. Second, we discuss
joint visual attention. A momentous development in the first year is the onset of
gaze following. Infants begin to turn to look at another’s target of attention. They
seem to want to share the viewpoint of others, to have the same perceptual experi-
ence of others, with important implications for emotions and language. Third, we
discuss experiments showing that in the second year of life infants have a grow-
ing sense of intentionality. They respond to the unfulfilled goals and intentions
of others – what people mean to do, not simply what they actually do. People are
intentional agents and as such are not always to be taken literally.
A principal purpose of this chapter is to show that Seattle’s laboratory research,
which is sometimes misinterpreted as exclusively cognitive in nature, actually pro-
vides three windows onto the nature and development of infant intersubjectivity.
By coupling experimental work and theorizing we can get a fuller picture not only
of infants’ initial state but also of the mechanisms of change in socio-emotional
development (Meltzoff 2007; Repacholi & Meltzoff in press).
Being caught up in others’ movements, imitating what you see, is an essential as-
pect of human intersubjectivity. Although other primates learn from observation,
they are more proficient at adopting the outcomes/results than in duplicating the
JB[v.20020404] Prn:7/03/2007; 17:04 F: AICR6809.tex / p.4 (211-254)
means and mannerisms we use to achieve these results (Meltzoff 1996; Povinelli
2000; Tomasello & Call 1997; Williamson & Markman 2006; Whiten 2002). Ac-
tion imitation is also impaired in children with autism (e.g., Dawson, Meltzoff,
Osterling, & Rinaldi 1998; Hobson & Lee 1999; Hobson & Meyer 2005; Meyer &
Hobson 2005; Rogers 1999; Toth, Munson, Meltzoff, & Dawson 2006; Whiten &
Brown 1998).
The imitation of simple body actions is sometimes dismissed as ‘mere
mimicry,’ and this language has caused generations of psychologists to miss its
essence and importance. Such action imitation is important for building social
rapport and the maintenance of caring communication. It is well-known that
body mirroring occurs between patient and therapist in successful psychother-
apy sessions (Beebe, Rustin, Sorter, & Knoblauch 2003). Similarly, many of the
customs, rituals, greetings, and everyday emotional exchanges revolve around acts
of reciprocal imitation. The duplication of the action patterns, mannerisms, and
gestures others use is part of the fabric of human communication. It runs in
the background and fosters emotional cohesion in everyday interactions, often-
times outside of explicit awareness (Bargh & Chartrand 1999; Chartrand & Bargh
1999; for related brain imagining work, see Decety, Chaminade, Grèzes, & Meltzoff
2002).
Meltzoff and Moore (1983, 1989) reported that newborns imitate facial acts. The
mean age of these infants was 36 hours old. The youngest child was 42 minutes old
at the time of test. Newborn facial imitation suggests an innate mapping between
observation and execution in the human case. Moreover, the studies provide in-
formation about the nature of the machinery infants use to connect observation
and execution.
It is important to realize that this is genuine imitation and not simply a diffuse
arousal response, which would have far fewer implications for intersubjectivity
and neuroscience. Meltzoff and Moore (1977) demonstrated that 12- to 21-day-
olds didn’t confuse either actions or body parts. They differentially responded to
tongue protrusion with tongue protrusion and not lip protrusion, showing that
the specific body part can be identified. They also differentially responded to lip
protrusion versus lip opening, showing that differential action patterns can be im-
itated with the same body part. This was extended by research showing that infants
differentially imitate two different kinds of movements with the tongue (Meltzoff
& Moore 1994, 1997). In all, there are 30 studies of early imitation from more
than a dozen independent laboratories across a range of gestures (see Meltzoff &
Moore 1997 for a systematic review). To be sure, there is development in imitation,
for example the neonate is less self-conscious about imitating than the toddler
JB[v.20020404] Prn:7/03/2007; 17:04 F: AICR6809.tex / p.5 (254-306)
(Meltzoff & Moore 1997), but the evidence clearly shows that human infants are
born imitating.
The nature of the imitative response is informative for theories. First, many
labs have reported that infants do not imitate the social other immediately
(Heimann 1998, 2002; Kugiumutzakis 1998; Meltzoff & Moore 1994, 1997). The
infant’s first response to seeing a facial gesture is activation of the corresponding
body part. For example, when infants see tongue protrusion, there is a quieting
of other body parts and an activation of the tongue. They do not necessarily pro-
trude the tongue at first, but may elevate it or move it slightly in the oral cavity.
The important point is that the tongue, rather than the lips or fingers, is energized
before the movement is isolated. Meltzoff and Moore (1997) call this ‘organ iden-
tification.’ Neurophysiological data show that visual displays of parts of the face
and hands activate specific brain sites in monkeys (Desimone 1991; Gross 1992;
Gross & Sergent 1992; Jellema, Baker, Oram, & Perrett 2002; Perrett, Hietanen,
Oram, & Benson 1992) and related work is emerging in human studies (Buccino
et al. 2001). Specific body parts could be neurally represented at birth and serve
as a foundation for infant imitation. An embryonic body scheme is drawn on in
imitation (Gallagher & Meltzoff 1996).
AIM hypothesis. Meltzoff and Moore proposed that early facial imitation is based
on active intermodal mapping (AIM) (Meltzoff & Moore 1977, 1997). This is not a
complex mechanism that requires cognitive machinations by the infant. The prin-
cipal claim is that imitation is a matching-to-target process. The active nature of
the matching process is captured by the proprioceptive feedback loop. The loop
allows infants’ motor performance to be compared against the seen target and
serves as a basis for infants’ correcting the response and homing in on the tar-
get act. AIM proposes that such comparison is possible because the observation
and execution of human acts are coded within a common framework. We call it
a ‘supramodal’ act space, because it is not restricted to modality-specific infor-
mation (visual, tactile, motor, etc.). Metaphorically, we can say that exteroception
(perception of others) and proprioception (perception of self) speak the same lan-
guage; there is no need for associating the two through prolonged learning because
they are bound together at birth. A more detailed analysis of the metric of equiva-
lence between acts of self and other is provided elsewhere (Meltzoff 2006; Meltzoff
& Moore 1997).
This hypothesis of a supramodal framework for coding of acts that emerged
from developmental psychology nearly 30 years ago fits well with modern pro-
posals from cognitive science (Prinz 2002, 2005) and neuroscience (Decety 2002;
Iacoboni et al. 1999; Rizzolatti, Fogassi, & Gallese 2001). Some effort is being made
to analyze the commonalities and differences in the models proposed from these
different fields (Gallese 2003; Meltzoff & Decety 2003; Rizzolatti et al. 2002). But
JB[v.20020404] Prn:7/03/2007; 17:04 F: AICR6809.tex / p.6 (306-351)
even at this time, we can say that they all converge on the idea of a close cou-
pling between perception and action that undergirds intersubjective engagement
with others. The unique contribution from developmental science is that newborn
imitation demonstrates that self-other connectedness is functional at birth in the
human case. Imitation is a marker of innate intersubjectivity in action.
The blissful state of dyadic interaction does not last for long. Soon there are in-
terlopers as the infant becomes aware that third parties are vying for mother’s
affection. For example, infants begin to pay attention to the fact that mothers do
not always look at them, but also cast their gaze to external objects, siblings, and
spouses in the environment. One measure of this dawning realization is infants’
gaze following, that is, their tendency to follow mother’s gaze to an external target
in order to see what she is looking at. This is not the duplication of exact bodily
movement, but rather a taking into account that her behaviour is directed toward
an external target.
Gaze following is the leading edge of what some refer to as ‘secondary in-
tersubjectivity’ (Bråten 1998b, 2003; Trevarthen & Hubley 1978) and others call
‘triadic’ communication (Bakeman & Adamson 1984; Hobson, Patrick, Crandell,
García-Pérez, & Lee 2004). Through gaze following there is the creation of a pre-
verbal referential triangle – mother-baby-object – in which the mother’s visual
glances refer infants to selected external targets. Among adults, detecting the di-
rection of another’s gaze is a crucial component of social interactions (Argyle &
Cook 1976; Kleinke 1986; Langton, Watt, & Bruce 2000).
The onset of gaze following has profound implications both for language and
emotions. It is relevant for understanding the meaning of an emotional display,
because a person’s emotion is often engendered by what he or she sees in the exter-
nal world (e.g., that object is appealing or disgusting). By following your partner’s
gaze you can grasp the cause of her emotional display (Moses, Baldwin, Rosicky,
& Tidball 2001; Repacholi 1998; Repacholi & Meltzoff in press). Language acquisi-
tion is also facilitated by understanding another’s line of regard. In the prototypical
case, a verbal label refers to the object being looked at, and not the other objects
in the room. Individual infants who follow mother’s gaze may be given a boost in
language learning (Baldwin 1995; Brooks & Meltzoff 2005; Morales, Mundy, & Ro-
jas 1998; Mundy, Fox, & Card 2003; Carpenter, Nagell, & Tomasello 1998). Beyond
all this, some, like Ginger Rogers, would argue that gaze following is an intersub-
JB[v.20020404] Prn:7/03/2007; 17:04 F: AICR6809.tex / p.7 (351-413)
jective act that allows us to take the perspective of another: “When two people love
each other, they don’t look at each other, they look in the same direction.”
It is well established that young typically developing infants turn in the di-
rection that an adult has turned, but there is a debate about the underlying
mechanism and developmental time course (Butterworth 2001; Moore & Dunham
1995). One conservative proposal suggests that following where another looks has
nothing to do with intersubjective sharing. On this view, the behaviour is based on
infants’ visually tracking the adult’s head movements because the head produces
salient/large displacements in the visual field. Inasmuch as infants visually follow
head movements, they are automatically ‘dragged’ to the correct half of space.
Once in the correct hemi-field they latch onto whatever attractive object is there,
usually the same one at which the adult is looking. On this account, infants are
not responding intersubjectively and are simply processing physical movements in
space caused by the head, regardless of what the eyes, are doing. They would be
just as likely to follow the movements of an inanimate object.
Figure 1a. An infant and adult make eye contact, the adult turns to look at the target, and
the infant follows and looks at the correct target.
Figure 1b. The looking score is a total of correct looks, incorrect looks and ‘non-looks.’
Thus, when an infant looks at correct targets, she receives a higher total score; however, if
she looks at incorrect targets, she lowers her total score. Infants look at the correct target
more often in the open-eyes than the closed-eyes condition. Adapted from Brooks and
Meltzoff (2002).
fants’ average duration of correct looks. This revealed that infants inspected the
target for a longer duration when the adult turned to it with open versus closed
eyes. Second, analysis of infant vocalizations showed that they vocalized more
toward the correct target in the open-eyes as opposed to closed-eyes condition.
Third, significantly more infants pointed to the targets in the open-eyes condition
than in the closed-eyes condition (Figure 2). This latter behaviour is particu-
larly striking because it is ostensive – the results show that infants are taking into
account the perceptual status of the audience. Infants point when the social part-
ner can see the objects but refrain when the partner cannot (eyes closed), which
Brooks and Meltzoff (2002) interpreted as ‘proto-declarative’ pointing (see also:
Bates, Benigni, Bretherton, Camaioni, & Volterra 1979; Camaioni, Perucchini, Bel-
lagamba, & Colonnesi 2004; Franco & Butterworth 1996; Liszkowski, Carpenter,
Henning, Striano, & Tomasello 2005).
We return now to the rationale for conducting this study. The non-social in-
terpretation of gaze following is that a visible movement simply drags infants’
JB[v.20020404] Prn:7/03/2007; 17:04 F: AICR6809.tex / p.9 (469-492)
Figure 2. (a) A 12-month-old boy points at the target. (b) Infants selectively point to the
target when the adult has her eyes open rather than closed. This suggests that points are
used to share with others in a ‘proto-declarative’ manner and not produced solipsistically.
eyes are the critical organ. This is an important step in secondary intersubjectivity
because the infant is coming to regard eyes as special.
The foregoing research indicates that at least one kind of occluder to vision, eye
closure, is understood quite early. One hypothesis is that this is because infants
themselves have ample prior intrasubjective experience with the perceptual effects
of eye closure. When they do so, the world goes black. They may be able to use
this experience to imbue the eye closures of others with meaning. If true, the
non-biological occluders should become more meaningful as a block to others’
perception if infants are themselves given opportunities to learn that they block
their own vision.
Meltzoff and Brooks (2004) gave 12-month-olds experience that blindfolds lead
to psychological effects – that the infants themselves cannot see through a blind-
fold. Infants were randomly assigned to a baseline condition or two treatment
groups, one of which involved blindfolds and the other involved the same black
cloth but with a ‘peeking window’ cut out of the middle. The infants experienced
that the blindfold blocked their view. Their perception of the world was blocked
when the blindfold was held in front of their eyes, and was restored again when the
blindfold was removed. This intrasubjective experience had nothing to do with the
experimenter’s viewpoint; it was a first-person experience. In the critical test, the
adult put the blindfold over her own eyes. This was the first time the infants were
presented with the blindfolded adult.
The results showed that infants now appreciated the consequences of blind-
folds for the other. They did not turn when the adult wore the blindfold. In the
control groups (baseline and cloth with peeking window) the infants were allowed
to familiarize themselves with the cloth, but without the perceptual experience of
a loss of vision. These two experiences had no effect on how they treated the other.
As we expected, the control-group infants still mistakenly followed the blindfolded
adult’s ‘gaze.’
This is the first study showing that infants use first-person experience about
a mental state such as “seeing” to grasp the experience of others. We believe that
first-person experience with blindfolds changes infants’ appreciation of the other’s
situation. These effects provide a nice demonstration of a ‘like me’/‘like you’ in-
terpersonal mechanism at work. This mechanism and its philosophical and de-
velopmental implications are elaborated in more detail elsewhere (Meltzoff 2006,
2007).
JB[v.20020404] Prn:7/03/2007; 17:04 F: AICR6809.tex / p.12 (603-645)
On theoretical grounds, there is good reason for thinking that secondary intersub-
jectivity embodied in gaze following may be an important component of language
acquisition. Infants who understand adult gaze as an ostensive act are in a better
position to use everyday interactions with adults to learn words as labels for ex-
ternal objects (e.g., Baldwin & Moses 2001; Bruner 1983; Meltzoff & Brooks 2006;
Tomasello 2003). Not all language refers to tangible entities that can be looked at
(Gopnik 1982, 1988; Gopnik & Meltzoff 1986). Nonetheless one basic format in
the “initial word learning game” (Bruner 1983) is for parents to point out salient
objects through gaze and then to label them. Infants who are advanced on gaze
following in particular (and perhaps in understanding referential intent in gen-
eral), may have a leg up on learning language (Tomasello, Carpenter, Call, Behne,
& Moll 2005). In order to pursue this idea within our own data set we conducted a
longitudinal follow-up of the children who came into the lab at 10–11 months of
age – the infants we caught right at the onset of gaze following.
In mature adult social cognition, I not only share behavioural actions and line of
regard with others, but I also share in their goals and unspoken intentions. Inten-
tions are particularly interesting for developmentalists. A first question is whether
infants have any inkling of the distinction between the actions someone performs
and their intention in performing these actions. Wittgenstein (1953) clarifies this
distinction with this pithy insight: ‘What is left over if I subtract the fact that my
arm goes up from the fact that I raise my arm?’ Answer: ‘Intention.’
Is there any evidence that infants have a feel for human action that penetrates
below the surface behaviour to the intentions that lay behind them? To address
these questions, it is not enough to explore whether young children act intention-
ally themselves; we need to investigate whether they appreciate the intentions and
goals of others.
Seeing goals in others’ actions. The ‘behavioural re-enactment procedure’ was cre-
ated to investigate infants’ reactions to the goals and intentions of others (Meltzoff
1995). The procedure capitalizes on children’s natural tendency to re-enact or im-
itate, but uses it in a more abstract way to investigate whether infants can read
below the literal surface behaviour to something like the goal or intention of the
actor. The procedure involves showing infants an unsuccessful act. For example,
the adult accidentally under- or overshoots his target, or he tries to pull apart a
dumbbell-shaped toy but his hand slips off the ends and he is unsuccessful. Thus
the goal-state is not achieved. Adults immediately sense the actor’s intentions al-
though he never fulfills them. The question is whether children see beyond the
literal body movements to the goal or intention of the act. In a sense, the ‘cor-
rect answer’ is to not copy the literal movement, but the intended act that remains
unfulfilled and invisible.
Meltzoff (1995) showed 18-month-old infants an unsuccessful act. The study
compared infants’ tendency to perform the target act in several situations: (a) af-
ter they saw the full-target act demonstrated, (b) after they saw the unsuccessful
attempt to perform the act, and (c) after it was neither shown nor attempted.
The results showed that 18-month-olds can infer the unseen goals implied by
unsuccessful attempts. Infants who saw the unsuccessful attempt and infants who
saw the full-target act both produced target acts at a significantly higher rate than
controls. Infants seemed to ‘see through’ the surface behaviour to the underlying
JB[v.20020404] Prn:7/03/2007; 17:04 F: AICR6809.tex / p.14 (684-729)
goals or intentions of the actor. Evidently, toddlers can understand our goals even
if we fail to fulfill them.
Seeking social help. In further work, 18-month-olds were shown similar displays,
but were handed a trick toy that prevented them from performing the interven-
tion (Meltzoff 2006). For example, the dumbbell-shaped object was surreptitiously
glued shut. If infants attempted to pull it apart, their hands slipped off the ends,
duplicating the adult’s behaviour. The question was whether this satisfied infants.
It did not. They varied the way they yanked on the dumbbell, systematically chang-
ing their strategies to find one that worked. They also appealed to their mothers
and the adult for help. About 90% of the infants looked up at an adult within 2-
sec after failing to pull apart the trick toy and many vocalized while staring at the
adult’s face. Why were they appealing for help from the social other? They had
matched the adult’s surface behaviour, but evidently they were striving toward
something else – the adult’s intended goals. This fits with Meltzoff ’s (1995) hy-
pothesis that infants had grasped the goal of the act, clearly differentiating it from
the literal surface behaviour that was observed.
The goals of people; the motions of machines. In the adult framework, only cer-
tain types of entities are ascribed to intention and purposiveness. Chairs and
boulders rock and roll, but their motions are not seen as intentional. Most pro-
totypically, human acts are the types of movement patterns that are seen as caused
by intentions. What do infants think?
To begin to examine this, Meltzoff (1995) tested how 18-month-olds re-
sponded to a mechanical device that mimicked the same movements as the actor in
the failed-attempt condition. An inanimate device was constructed that had poles
for arms and mechanical pincers for hands. It did not look human but it could
move very similarly to the human (Fig. 3, bottom panel). For the test, the pincers
‘grasped’ the dumbbell at the two ends just as the human hands did. One me-
chanical arm was then moved outwards, just as in the human case, and its pincer
Figure 3. Human demonstrator (top panel) and inanimate device mimicking these move-
ments (bottom panel) (from Meltzoff 1995).
JB[v.20020404] Prn:7/03/2007; 17:04 F: AICR6809.tex / p.15 (729-783)
slipped off the end of the dumbbell just as the human hand did. The movement
patterns of machine and man were closely matched from a purely spatiotemporal
description of movements in space.
The results showed that infants did not attribute a goal or intention to the
movements of the inanimate device. Although they were not frightened by the
device and looked at it as long as at the human display, they simply did not see
the sequence of actions as implying a goal. Infants were no more (or less) likely to
pull apart the toy after seeing the failed attempt of the inanimate device than in
baseline conditions when they saw nothing.
We think 18-month-olds cast the person’s actions within an intersubjective
framework that differentiates between the visible behaviour and a deeper level of
felt experience involving human goals and intentions. When they watch a person’s
hands slip off the ends of the dumbbell they immediately see what the adult was
‘trying’ to do. When they see the inanimate device slip off the end of the dumbbell,
they see it as mere mechanical slippage with no implications for purposiveness.1
The appreciation of others’ goals and intentions is intersubjectivity in action.
Third, experiments with human infants belie the premise of infantile solipsism.
We have accumulated massive evidence not only for preverbal intersubjectivity,
but for innate intersubjectivity.
Mirror neurons
The philosopher’s queries about man’s original nature are not definitively an-
swered by tests of adults (whether monkey or man). These need to be supple-
JB[v.20020404] Prn:7/03/2007; 17:04 F: AICR6809.tex / p.17 (839-897)
That young infants can interpret the acts of self and other within the same frame-
work provides them with enormous leverage and an engine for interpersonal
development. For example, the infant knows that when she wants something she
reaches out and grasps it. The infant experiences her own internal desires and the
concomitant bodily movements (hand extension, finger movements, etc.). The ex-
perience of grasping to satisfy desires gives infants leverage for ‘feeling with’ the
other who grasps for things. When the child sees another person reaching for
an object, she sees the person extending his hand in the same way. These move-
ments are imbued with experiential meaning, in part because of the child’s own
experience with these acts.
A similar argument applies to the goal-directed ‘striving’ and ‘try and try
again’ behaviour in Meltzoff ’s (1995) studies using the behavioural re-enactment
procedure. Infants have subjective desires and act intentionally. They have experi-
JB[v.20020404] Prn:7/03/2007; 17:04 F: AICR6809.tex / p.18 (897-938)
enced their own thwarted desires, failed plans, and unfulfilled intentions. Indeed
in the second half-year of life they are obsessed with the success and failure of
their plans: They mark such self-failures with verbal labels such as “uh-oh,” “no,”
or as recorded in a British child, “oh bugger” (Gopnik & Meltzoff 1986). More
strikingly, they actually play with failed efforts by repeating the solution (and the
failure) numerous times until the solution comes under voluntary control (Gopnik
& Meltzoff 1997; Gopnik, Meltzoff, & Kuhl 1999; Moore & Meltzoff 2004). During
such episodes of testing why they failed, infants often vary their strategies and ‘try
and try again.’ This intrasubjective exploration deepens their intersubjective grasp
about the motivation and meaning of others’ behaviour. Specifically, when an in-
fant sees another act in this same way, the infant’s self-experience could suggest
that there is a purpose, desire, or intention beyond the surface behaviour. Thus in-
fants would see the adult’s failed attempts, and the behavioural envelope in which
they occur, as a pattern of ‘strivings’ rather than ends in themselves.
Gaze following admits to a similar theoretical analysis. The understanding of
another’s looking behaviour could benefit from intrasubjective experiences – in
this case, experience of oneself as a perceiver. Infants in the first year of life can
imitate head movements and eye blinking (Meltzoff 1988; Meltzoff & Moore 1989;
Piaget 1962). As unlikely as it seems at first, these data indicate that infants can
map between the head movements and eyelid closures they see others perform
and their own head movements and their own eye closures. The infant’s experi-
ence is that eye closure cuts off the infant’s own perceptual access. This experience
may provide a basis for imbuing the eye-closures of others with felt experiential
content.
This theorizing can also can help us make sense of the finding that young in-
fants have more advanced understanding of eye-closure than blindfolds (Brooks &
Meltzoff 2002). Certainly, 1-year-olds are well versed with voluntary looking away
and eye closing to cut off unwanted stimuli. This bodily act is well mastered. Its
meaning when used by others may therefore be in advance of the understanding of
inanimate occluders. Our intervention experiment training infants with blindfolds
gave them the experiential basis for appreciating the situation of another person
who wore a blindfold.
A stumbling block for classical theories was that the self-other equivalence was
postulated to be late developing – emerging from language or complex cognitive
analyses. The last quarter century of research stands this proposition on its head.
It indicates that young infants register the acts of others and their own acts in
commensurate terms. The recognition of self-other equivalences is the starting point
for social cognition – a precondition for infant development, not the outcome of it.
JB[v.20020404] Prn:7/03/2007; 17:04 F: AICR6809.tex / p.19 (938-986)
Given this facile self-other mapping, early social encounters are more inter-
pretable to infants than supposed by Freud, Skinner, and Piaget. Infants have
a storehouse of experience from which to draw: They can use the experienced
subjectivity of self as a scaffold for the subjectivity of others. The child’s inter-
subjectivity is thus not restricted to decoding minds in isolation or abstraction
through ‘cool cognition,’ but involves felt immediacy through bodily actions as
well.
The neural circuits underlying this preverbal human intersubjectivity are still
being sought. Some of the most interesting advances in next decade may come
from developmental social neuroscience. The task will be to consider intersubjec-
tivity, imitation, mirror neurons, empathy, and much more, collaboratively from
both a developmental and neuroscience perspective. Our joint purpose will be to
crack one of the most urgent and ancient cries for human meaning: Am I alone?
Do others feel what I’m feeling? This also is the baby’s quest.
Acknowledgments
This work was supported by a grant from NIH (HD-22514), NSF (SBE-0354453),
and a gift to the University of Washington from the Tamaki Foundation. We thank
Stein Bråten for his gracious hospitality at the Norwegian Academy of Science and
Letters Theory Forum that spawned this chapter; and also for being such a good
‘virtual other’ – gently planting a voice within our brains that continues to remind
us about the importance of intersubjectivity.
Note
. It is possible that displays can be constructed that fool infants, as they do adults. Can a com-
puter be considered intentional? Or is it just an inert hunk of plastic and silicon? We do not know
the necessary and sufficient conditions for infants ascribing purposiveness to entities. There is
research, however, indicating that in certain circumstances infants see purposiveness in the ac-
tions of pretend humans (stuffed animals and puppets, Johnson 2000) and dynamic displays
that may be ambiguous as to animacy (e.g., researchers have used 2-D spots that leap and move
spontaneously on a TV screen, Csibra 2003 and Gergely 2002). This does not run against the
thesis suggested here, but underscores the need for research on boundary conditions. The inan-
imate 3-D object used by Meltzoff (1995) gives a lower boundary (infants fail) and real people
with whom the infant has an intersubjective relation give an upper boundary (infants succeed).
There is a lot of room in between for more empirical research.
JB[v.20020404] Prn:7/03/2007; 17:04 F: AICR6809.tex / p.20 (986-1098)
References
Argyle, M., & Cook, M. (1976). Gaze and Mutual Gaze. Cambridge, UK: Cambridge University
Press.
Bakeman, R., & Adamson, L. B. (1984). “Coordinating attention to people and objects in
mother-infant and peer-infant interaction.” Child Development, 55, 1278–1289.
Baldwin, D. A. (1995). “Understanding the link between joint attention and language.” In C.
Moore & P. J. Dunham (Eds.), Joint Attention: Its Origins and Role in Development (pp. 131–
158). Hillsdale, NJ: Erlbaum.
Baldwin, D. A., & Moses, L. J. (2001). “Links between social understanding and early word
learning: Challenges to current accounts.” Social Development, 10, 309–329.
Baldwin, J. M. (1906). Mental Development in the Child and the Race: Methods and Processes (3rd
ed.). New York: Macmillan.
Bargh, J. A., & Chartrand, T. L. (1999). “The unbearable automaticity of being.” American
Psychologist, 54, 462–479.
Bates, E., Benigni, L., Bretherton, I., Camaioni, L., & Volterra, V. (1979). The Emergence of
Symbols: Cognition and Communication in Infancy. New York: Academic Press.
Beebe, B., Rustin, J., Sorter, D., & Knoblauch, S. (2003). “An expanded view of intersubjectivity
in infancy and its application to psychoanalysis.” Psychoanalytic Dialogues, 13, 805–841.
Beebe, B., Sorter, D., Rustin, J., & Knoblauch, S. (2003). “A comparison of Meltzoff, Trevarthen,
and Stern.” Psychoanalytic Dialogues, 13, 777–804.
Bråten, S. (1998a). “Infant learning by altercentric participation: The reverse of egocentric
observation in autism.” In S. Bråten (Ed.), Intersubjective Communication and Emotion in
Early Ontogeny (pp. 105–124). Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
Bråten, S. (1998b). “Intersubjective communion and understanding: Development and
perturbation.” In S. Bråten (Ed.), Intersubjective communication and emotion in early
ontogeny (pp. 372–382). Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
Bråten, S. (2003). “Participant perception of others’ acts: Virtual otherness in infants and adults.”
Culture & Psychology, 9, 261–276.
Bråten, S. (2004). “On the foundations of (pre)verbal intersubjectivity: Introduction to a
symposium in the Norwegian Academy of Science and Letters.” Impuls, 3, 91–95.
Brooks, R., & Meltzoff, A. N. (2002). “The importance of eyes: How infants interpret adult
looking behavior.” Developmental Psychology, 38, 958–966.
Brooks, R., & Meltzoff, A. N. (2005). “The development of gaze following and its relation to
language.” Developmental Science, 8, 535–543.
Bruner, J. (1983). Child’s Talk: Learning to Use Language. New York: Norton.
Buccino, G., Binkofski, F., Fink, G. R., Fadiga, L., Fogassi, L., Gallese, V., Seitz, R. J., Zilles, K.,
Rizzolatti, G., & Freund, H.-J. (2001). “Action observation activates premotor and parietal
areas in a somatotopic manner: An fMRI study.” European Journal of Neuroscience, 13, 400–
404.
Butterworth, G. (2001). “Joint visual attention in infancy.” In G. Bremner & A. Fogel (Eds.),
Blackwell Handbook of Infant Development (pp. 213–240). Oxford: Blackwell.
Camaioni, L., Perucchini, P., Bellagamba, F., & Colonnesi, C. (2004). “The role of declarative
pointing in developing a theory of mind.” Infancy, 5, 291–308.
Carpenter, M., Nagell, K., & Tomasello, M. (1998). “Social cognition, joint attention, and
communicative competence from 9 to 15 months of age.” Monographs of the Society for
Research in Child Development, 63 (4), Serial No. 255.
JB[v.20020404] Prn:7/03/2007; 17:04 F: AICR6809.tex / p.21 (1098-1228)
Chartrand, T. L., & Bargh, J. A. (1999). “The chameleon effect: The perception-behavior link
and social interaction.” Journal of Personality and Social Psychology, 76, 893–910.
Csibra, G. (2003). “Teleological and referential understanding of action in infancy.” Philosophical
Transactions of the Royal Society of London. Series B, Biological Sciences, 358, 447–458.
Dawson, G., Meltzoff, A. N., Osterling, J., & Rinaldi, J. (1998). “Neuropsychological correlates
of early symptoms of autism.” Child Development, 69, 1276–1285.
Decety, J. (2002). “Is there such a thing as functional equivalence between imagined, observed,
and executed action?” In A. N. Meltzoff & W. Prinz (Eds.), The Imitative Mind:
Development, Evolution, and Brain Bases (pp. 291–310). Cambridge: Cambridge University
Press.
Decety, J., Chaminade, T., Grèzes, J., & Meltzoff, A. N. (2002). “A PET exploration of the neural
mechanisms involved in reciprocal imitation.” NeuroImage, 15, 265–272.
Desimone, R. (1991). “Face-selective cells in the temporal cortex of monkeys.” Journal of
Cognitive Neuroscience, 3, 1–8.
Fenson, L., Dale, P. S., Reznick, J. S., Bates, E., Thal, D. J., & Pethick, S. J. (1994). “Variability
in early communicative development.” Monographs of the Society for Research in Child
Development, 59 (5), Serial No. 242.
Franco, F., & Butterworth, G. (1996). “Pointing and social awareness: Declaring and requesting
in the second year.” Journal of Child Language, 23, 307–336.
Freud, S. (1911). “Formulations on the two principles of mental functioning.” In J. Strachey
(Ed.), The Standard Edition of the Complete Psychological Works of Sigmund Freud (Vol. 12)
(pp. 215–226). London: Hogarth Press.
Frith, C. D., & Wolpert, D. M. (2003). “Introduction.” Philosophical Transactions of the Royal
Society of London. Series B, Biological Sciences, 358, 431–434.
Gallagher, S. (2001). “The practice of mind: Theory, simulation or primary interaction?” Journal
of Consciousness Studies, 8, 83–108.
Gallagher, S. (2004). “Understanding interpersonal problems in autism: Interaction theory as
an alternative to theory of mind.” Philosophy, Psychiatry, & Psychology, 11, 199–217.
Gallagher, S., & Meltzoff, A. N. (1996). “The earliest sense of self and others: Merleau-Ponty and
recent developmental studies.” Philosophical Psychology, 9, 211–233.
Gallese, V. (2003). “The manifold nature of interpersonal relations: The quest for a common
mechanism.” Philosophical Transactions of the Royal Society of London. Series B, Biological
Sciences, 358, 517–528.
Gallese, V. (2005). “Being like me: Self-other identity, mirror neurons, and empathy.” In S.
Hurley & N. Chater (Eds.), Perspectives on Imitation: From Neuroscience to Social Science
(Vol. 1: Mechanisms of imitation and imitation in animals) (pp. 101–118). Cambridge,
MA: MIT Press.
Gergely, G. (2002). “The development of understanding self and agency.” In U. Goswami (Ed.),
Handbook of Childhood Cognitive Development (pp. 26–46). Oxford: Blackwell Publishers.
Goldman, A. I. (2005). “Imitation, mind reading, and simulation.” In S. Hurley & N. Chater
(Eds.), Perspectives on Imitation: From Neuroscience to Social Science (Vol. 2: Imitation,
human development, and culture) (pp. 79–93). Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.
Gopnik, A. (1982). “Words and plans: Early language and the development of intelligent action.”
Journal of Child Language, 9, 303–318.
Gopnik, A. (1988). “Three types of early word: The emergence of social words, names
and cognitive-relational words in the one-word stage and their relation to cognitive
development.” First Language, 8, 49–70.
JB[v.20020404] Prn:7/03/2007; 17:04 F: AICR6809.tex / p.22 (1228-1349)
Gopnik, A., & Meltzoff, A. N. (1986). “Relations between semantic and cognitive development
in the one-word stage: The specificity hypothesis.” Child Development, 57, 1040–1053.
Gopnik, A., & Meltzoff, A. N. (1997). Words, thoughts, and theories. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.
Gopnik, A., Meltzoff, A. N., & Kuhl, P. K. (1999). The Scientist in the Crib: Minds, Brains, and
How Children Learn. New York: Morrow.
Gordon, R. M. (2005). “Intentional agents like myself.” In S. Hurley & N. Chater (Eds.),
Perspectives on Imitation: From Neuroscience to Social Science (Vol. 2: Imitation, human
development, and culture) (pp. 95–106). Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.
Gross, C. G. (1992). “Representation of visual stimuli in inferior temporal cortex.” In V. Bruce,
A. Cowey, A. W. Ellis, & D. I. Perrett (Eds.), Processing the Facial Image (pp. 3–10). New
York: Oxford University Press.
Gross, C. G., & Sergent, J. (1992). “Face recognition.” Current Opinion in Neurobiology, 2, 156–
161.
Heimann, M. (1998). “Imitation in neonates, in older infants and in children with autism:
Feedback to theory.” In S. Bråten (Ed.), Intersubjective Communication and Emotion in Early
Ontogeny (pp. 89–104). Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
Heimann, M. (2002). “Notes on individual differences and the assumed elusiveness of neonatal
imitation.” In A. N. Meltzoff & W. Prinz (Eds.), The Imitative Mind: Development, Evolution,
and Brain Bases (pp. 74–84). Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
Heimann, M., Strid, K., Smith, L., Tjus, T., Ulvund, S., & Meltzoff, A. N. (2006). “Exploring
the relation between memory, gestural communication, and the emergence of language in
infancy: A longitudinal study.” Infant and Child Development, 15, 233–249.
Hobson, R. P. (2002). The Cradle of Thought: Exploring the Origins of Thinking. London:
Macmillan.
Hobson, R. P., & Lee, A. (1999). “Imitation and identification in autism.” Journal of Child
Psychology and Psychiatry, 40, 649–659.
Hobson, R. P., & Meyer, J. A. (2005). “Foundations for self and other: A study in autism.”
Developmental Science, 8, 481–491.
Hobson, R. P., Patrick, M. P. H., Crandell, L. E., García Pérez, R. M., & Lee, A. (2004). “Maternal
sensitivity and infant triadic communication.” Journal of Child Psychology and Psychiatry,
45, 470–480.
Hurley, S., & Chater, N. (Eds.). (2005). Perspectives on Imitation: From Neuroscience to Social
Science. (Vol. 1 and 2). Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.
Husserl, E. (1950/1960). Cartesian Meditations: An Introduction to Phenomenology (D. Cairns,
Trans.). The Hague: Martinus Nijhoff.
Iacoboni, M., Woods, R. P., Brass, M., Bekkering, H., Mazziotta, J. C., & Rizzolatti, G. (1999).
“Cortical mechanisms of human imitation.” Science, 286, 2526–2528.
Jackson, P. L., Brunet, E., Meltzoff, A. N., & Decety, J. (2006). “Empathy examined through
the neural mechanisms involved in imagining how I feel versus how you feel pain.”
Neuropsychologia, 44, 752–761.
Jackson, P. L., Meltzoff, A. N., & Decety, J. (2006). “Neural circuits involved in imitation and
perspective-taking.” NeuroImage, 31, 429–439.
Jellema, T., Baker, C. I., Oram, M. W., & Perrett, D. I. (2002). “Cell populations in the banks
of the superior temporal sulcus of the macaque and imitation.” In A. N. Meltzoff & W.
Prinz (Eds.), The Imitative Mind: Development, Evolution, and Brain Bases (pp. 267–290).
Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
Johnson, S. C. (2000). “The recognition of mentalistic agents in infancy.” Trends in Cognitive
Sciences, 4, 22–28.
JB[v.20020404] Prn:7/03/2007; 17:04 F: AICR6809.tex / p.23 (1349-1458)
Kleinke, C. L. (1986). “Gaze and eye contact: A research review.” Psychological Bulletin, 100,
78–100.
Kugiumutzakis, G. (1998). “Neonatal imitation in the intersubjective companion space.” In S.
Bråten (Ed.), Intersubjective Communication and Emotion in Early Ontogeny (pp. 63–88).
Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
Langton, S. R. H., Watt, R. J., & Bruce, V. (2000). “Do the eyes have it? Cues to the direction of
social attention.” Trends in Cognitive Sciences, 4, 50–59.
Liszkowski, U., Carpenter, M., Henning, A., Striano, T., & Tomasello, M. (2004). “Twelve-
month-olds point to share attention and interest.” Developmental Science, 7, 297–307.
Mahler, M. S., Pine, F., & Bergman, A. (1975). The Psychological Birth of the Human Infant. New
York: Basic Books.
Mead, G. H. (1934). Mind, Self, and Society from the Standpoint of a Social Behaviorist. Chicago:
University of Chicago Press.
Meltzoff, A. N. (1988). “The human infant as Homo imitans.” In T. R. Zentall & B. G. Galef
(Eds.), Social learning: Psychological and biological perspectives (pp. 319–341). Hillsdale, NJ:
Erlbaum.
Meltzoff, A. N. (1995). “Understanding the intentions of others: Re-enactment of intended acts
by 18-month-old children.” Developmental Psychology, 31, 838–850.
Meltzoff, A. N. (1996). “The human infant as imitative generalist: A 20-year progress report
on infant imitation with implications for comparative psychology.” In C. M. Heyes & B.
G. Galef (Eds.), Social Learning in Animals: The Roots of Culture (pp. 347–370). New York:
Academic Press.
Meltzoff, A. N. (2006). “The ‘like me’ framework for recognizing and becoming an intentional
agent.” Acta Psychologica, doi:10.1016/j.actpsy.2006.09.005.
Meltzoff, A. N. (2007). “‘Like Me’: A foundation for social cognition.” Developmental Science,
10, 126–134.
Meltzoff, A. N., & Brooks, R. (2004). “Development changes in social cognition with an eye
toward gaze following.” Symposium conducted at the Biennial meeting of the International
Conference on Infant Studies, Chicago, Illinois.
Meltzoff, A. N., & Brooks, R. (2006). “Eyes wide shut: The importance of eyes in infant gaze
following and understanding other minds.” In R. Flom, K. Lee, & D. Muir (Eds.), Gaze
Following: Its Development and Significance (pp. 217–241). Mahwah, NJ: Erlbaum.
Meltzoff, A. N., & Decety, J. (2003). “What imitation tells us about social cognition:
A rapprochement between developmental psychology and cognitive neuroscience.”
Philosophical Transactions of the Royal Society of London. Series B, Biological Sciences, 358
491–500.
Meltzoff, A. N., & Moore, M. K. (1977). “Imitation of facial and manual gestures by human
neonates.” Science, 198, 75–78.
Meltzoff, A. N., & Moore, M. K. (1983). “Newborn infants imitate adult facial gestures.” Child
Development, 54, 702–709.
Meltzoff, A. N., & Moore, M. K. (1989). “Imitation in newborn infants: Exploring the range of
gestures imitated and the underlying mechanisms.” Developmental Psychology, 25, 954–962.
Meltzoff, A. N., & Moore, M. K. (1994). “Imitation, memory, and the representation of persons.”
Infant Behavior & Development, 17, 83–99.
Meltzoff, A. N., & Moore, M. K. (1997). “Explaining facial imitation: A theoretical model.” Early
Development and Parenting, 6, 179–192.
Meltzoff, A. N., & Prinz, W. (Eds.). (2002). The Imitative Mind: Development, Evolution and
Brain Bases. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
JB[v.20020404] Prn:7/03/2007; 17:04 F: AICR6809.tex / p.24 (1458-1570)
Rizzolatti, G., Fadiga, L., Fogassi, L., & Gallese, V. (2002). “From mirror neurons to imitation:
Facts, and speculations.” In A. N. Meltzoff & W. Prinz (Eds.), The Imitative Mind:
Development, Evolution, and Brain Bases (pp. 247–266). Cambridge: Cambridge University
Press.
Rizzolatti, G., Fadiga, L., Gallese, V., & Fogassi, L. (1996). “Premotor cortex and the recognition
of motor actions.” Cognitive Brain Research, 3, 131–141.
Rizzolatti, G., Fogassi, L., & Gallese, V. (2001). “Neurophysiological mechanisms underlying the
understanding and imitation of action.” Nature Reviews Neuroscience, 2, 661–670.
Rochat, P., & Striano, T. (1999). “Social-cognitive development in the first year.” In P. Rochat
(Ed.), Early Social Cognition: Understanding Others in the First Months of Life (pp. 3–34).
Mahwah, NJ: Erlbaum.
Rogers, S. J. (1999). “An examination of the imitation deficit in autism.” In J. Nadel & G.
Butterworth (Eds.), Imitation in Infancy (pp. 254–283). Cambridge: Cambridge University
Press.
Rommetveit, R. (1998). “Intersubjective attunement and linguistically mediated meaning
in discourse.” In S. Bråten (Ed.), Intersubjective Communication and Emotion in Early
Ontogeny (pp. 354–371). Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
Skinner, B. F. (1953). Science and Human Behavior. New York: The Macmillan Company.
Skinner, B. F. (1983). A Matter of Consequences. New York: Alfred A. Knopf.
Smith, A. (1759/1976). The Theory of Moral Sentiments. Reprints of Economic Classics. New
York: Oxford University Press.
Stern, D. N. (1985). The Interpersonal World of the Infant: A View from Psychoanalysis and
Developmental Psychology. New York: Basic Books.
Tomasello, M. (1999). The Cultural Origins of Human Cognition. Cambridge, MA: Harvard
University Press.
Tomasello, M. (2003). Constructing a Language: A Usage-based Theory of Language Acquisition.
Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.
Tomasello, M., & Call, J. (1997). Primate cognition. New York: Oxford University Press.
Tomasello, M., Carpenter, M., Call, J., Behne, T., & Moll, H. (2005). “Understanding and sharing
intentions: The origins of cultural cognition.” Behavioral and Brain Sciences, 28, 675–691.
Toth, K., Munson, J., Meltzoff, A. N., & Dawson, G. (2006). “Early predictors of communication
development in young children with autism spectrum disorder: Joint attention, imitation,
and toy play.” Journal of Autism and Developmental Disorders, doi:10.1007/s10803-
006.0137-7.
Trevarthen, C. (1979). “Communication and cooperation in early infancy: A description
of primary intersubjectivity.” In M. Bullowa (Ed.), Before Speech: The Beginning of
Interpersonal Communication (pp. 321–347). New York: Cambridge University Press.
Trevarthen, C., & Hubley, P. (1978). “Secondary intersubjectivity: Confidence, confiding and
acts of meaning in the first year.” In A. Lock (Ed.), Action, Gesture, and Symbol: The
Emergence of Language (pp. 183–229). London: Academic Press.
Whiten, A. (2002). “The imitator’s representation of the imitated: Ape and child.” In A. N.
Meltzoff & W. Prinz (Eds.), The Imitative Mind: Development, Evolution, and Brain Bases
(pp. 98–121). Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
Whiten, A., & Brown, J. D. (1998). “Imitation and the reading of other minds: Perspectives
from the study of autism, normal children and non-human primates.” In S. Bråten (Ed.),
Intersubjective Communication and Emotion in Early Ontogeny (pp. 260–280). Cambridge:
Cambridge University Press.
JB[v.20020404] Prn:7/03/2007; 17:04 F: AICR6809.tex / p.26 (1689-1696)
chapter
Throughout the first year of life, infants experience dramatic changes in speech
sound perception that reflect a move from universal to specific ways of listening
appropriate for their language community. In this chapter, we explore the role of
social experience in this important transition in language development. Focusing
on the phonetic aspects of language acquisition, we ask: what aspects of language
experience serve as agents of change in helping infants to become perceptually
attuned to other speakers of the language? We begin with a brief summary of
the literature on the development of speech perception, which illustrates the im-
portance of language experience during infancy for establishing native-like speech
perception abilities (more extensive reviews of infant speech perception research
are available from Goodman & Nusbaum 1994; Kuhl 2004; Jusczyk 1997; Werker
& Tees 2005). Next, we review studies in which we have applied the “Conditioned
Head Turn” technique to investigate the role of language experience in influenc-
ing developmental patterns of speech perception. We then review the results of
a recent study that suggest that when a new language is introduced towards the
end of the first year, infants participate through social interaction in the process
of phonetic learning, rather than learning solely through passive listening. Thus,
the language experience required for effective phonetic learning has a highly social
nature.
We suggest that particular social cues play an important role in heightening in-
fants’ attention to relevant language stimuli in such early second language learning
situations, and may also be essential for first language phonetic learning. Based on
studies of social-cognitive development during the first year and its relationship
to early language acquisition, we suggest that the process of attunement to social
information and a sharing of perception throughout the first year direct infants’ at-
JB[v.20020404] Prn:7/03/2007; 17:06 F: AICR6810.tex / p.2 (108-158)
Three decades of research on infant speech perception have shown that shifts in
speech sound perception occurring over the course of the first year are driven by
experience with ambient language. Following a landmark study in which categor-
ical perception of speech sounds was discovered in 1-month-old infants (Eimas
et al. 1971), researchers began to explore how perception of particular speech
contrasts varied as a function of the language spoken to the infant (e.g., Aslin
et al. 1981; Eilers, Gavin & Oller 1982; Eilers, Gavin Wilson 1979; Lasky et al.
1975; Streeter 1976; Trehub 1976; Werker et al. 1981). The work of Werker and
Tees (1984a) indicated a developmental progression from similar discrimination
of native and nonnative contrasts at 6–8 months, to lack of discrimination of
the same nonnative contrast at 10–12 months. Further research replicated these
results, leading to a now widely cited developmental pattern of speech percep-
tion: infants’ ability to discriminate a variety of speech sounds occurring across
the world’s languages is initially unconstrained by the language of their commu-
nity; this subsequently gives way to language-specific patterns of discrimination as
early as 6 months of age for vowels (Kuhl et al. 1992) and by 10–12 months for
consonants (Best, McRoberts, & Sithole 1988; Best et al. 1995; Bosch & Sebastián-
Gallés 2003; Burns, Werker, & McVie 2003; Conboy et al. 2005; Kuhl et al. 2001;
Kuhl, Tsao, & Liu 2003; Pegg & Werker 1997; Werker & Lalonde 1988). Recent
studies using event-related potentials (ERPs) to measure brain activity have pro-
vided additional evidence for changes in speech perception over the first year of life
(Cheour et al. 1998; Kuhl et al. 2007; Rivera-Gaxiola, Silva-Pereyra, & Kuhl 2005a).
Several studies have shown that this well-documented reduction in the per-
ception of nonnative phonemes does not reflect a loss of sensory ability due to
mere lack of exposure to the sounds of nonnative languages (see Werker 1994).
First, adults retain the ability to discriminate some nonnative phoneme contrasts
under certain testing procedures (Carney, Widin, & Viemeister 1977; Werker &
Logan 1985; Werker & Tees 1984b), and can learn to discriminate many other
nonnative phonemes given training (e.g., Jamieson & Morosan 1986, 1989; Logan,
Lively, & Pisoni 1991; McClaskey, Pisoni, & Carrell 1983; McClelland, Fiez, &
McCandliss 2002; Morosan & Jamieson 1989; Pisoni et al. 1982, 1994; Tees &
Werker 1984; Zhang et al. 2005). Second, reduction in the perception of nonnative
phonemes is not uniform, but rather appears to be modulated by acoustic salience
(Burnham 1986), by the relationship of the nonnative phonemes to phonemic cat-
egories in the adult’s native language (e.g., Best 1994; Best & McRoberts 2003;
JB[v.20020404] Prn:7/03/2007; 17:06 F: AICR6810.tex / p.3 (158-212)
Best, McRoberts, & Goodell 2001; Best, McRoberts, & Sithole 1988; Best et al.
1995; Guion et al. 2000; Strange et al. 1998), or by acoustic factors and/or phonetic
familiarity (Polka 1991, 1992; Polka, Colantonio, & Sundara 2001).
While most previous studies have focused on the decline of nonnative speech
perception, we have proposed that native language perception improves over the
first year of life, and furthermore, that changes in nonnative speech perception
are linked to such sharpening of perception for the native language (Kuhl 2000).
Our lab has conducted a series of behavioural studies that indicate that improve-
ment in native language phonetic perception throughout infancy accompanies a
reduction in nonnative perception (Kuhl et al. 2005). For these behavioural stud-
ies, we have used the “Conditioned Head Turn Procedure” (HT), a widely used
method for testing infant speech perception (Eilers et al. 1979; Kuhl 1979, 1985;
Polka, Jusczyk, & Rvachew 1995; Werker et al. 1981). In our version of the HT task,
infants sit on their parent’s lap while an assistant, seated to the right, manipulates
silent toys to attract the infant’s attention. Infants are trained to turn away from the
assistant and toward a loudspeaker on their left when they detect a change from
the repeating background sound to the target sound. An experimenter observes
the infant on a video monitor in a control room during testing and judges the
head turn responses. Correct head turn responses are reinforced with presentation
of a mechanical toy (e.g., bear tapping on a drum) next to the loudspeaker. The HT
procedure consists of a conditioning phase followed by a test phase (Figure 1). In
the conditioning phase, all trials are change trials, allowing the infant to learn the
association between the target sound and visual reinforcement. During condition-
ing, the target sound is initially presented with an intensity cue to draw the infant’s
attention to the stimulus change. Following two consecutive correct head-turn re-
sponses to the target sound in anticipation of the reinforcer, no-intensity cue trials
are administered until three consecutive correct head-turn responses have been
achieved. In the test phase, change (sound change) and control (no sound change)
trials occur with equal probability (50%). For change trials, head-turns are scored
as “hits” and failure to turn as “misses”; for control trials, head-turns are scored as
“false alarms” and failure to turn as “correct rejections.” Several measures are taken
to control bias: (a) all contingencies and trial selection are under computer con-
trol; (b) the parent and assistant wear headphones and listen to music that masks
the speech sounds and prevents them from influencing the infants’ responses; and
(c) the experimenter’s headphones, which allow monitoring of the experimental
room, and are deactivated during trials so that the experimenter cannot hear the
stimuli during the trial. In addition, the results are analyzed using signal detection
measures that take both hit and false alarm rates into account.
Using the HT technique, along with a parent-report inventory of language
development – the MacArthur-Bates Communicative Development Inventory, or
CDI (Fenson et al. 1993) – we have shown that individual variation across in-
fants in the attainment of native-like speech perception is linked to advances in
other aspects of language development. As early as 6 months of age infants display
language-specific ways of perceiving vowel contrasts (Kuhl et al. 1992). Infants
who are better at vowel discrimination at 6 months have better language skills
throughout the 14 to 30 month period (Tsao, Liu, & Kuhl 2004). For consonants,
the shift to language-specific processing takes several months longer (Conboy et al.
2005; Kuhl et al. 2001, 2005). Infants who are more language-specific listeners for
consonants at 7-months also tend to have faster growth in language development
from 14 to 30 months (Kuhl et al. 2005, 2007). In this research, better performance
on native language phoneme discrimination was positively correlated with later
CDI scores, whereas better performance on nonnative phoneme discrimination
was negatively correlated with later CDI scores. Infants who have higher native-
language speech discrimination scores relative to their nonnative discrimination
scores also have higher concurrent CDI vocabulary scores (Conboy et al. 2005).
Studies using event-related potentials have likewise shown that the attainment of
native-like speech perception is linked to subsequent language skills (Kuhl et al.
2007; Rivera-Gaxiola et al. 2005b).
These results indicate that the shift to a language-specific way of listening
may be considered a developmental milestone that is continuous with subsequent
learning in that language. Infants who more quickly learn to tune out phonetic
contrasts that are not meaningful for their native language are also more proficient
at detecting contrasts that are phonemic in their language. Infants who reach the
milestone of native-like speech perception sooner have an advantage in other as-
pects of language acquisition. Experience with the native language, and the uptake
of information from such experience, appears to influence language acquisition
on several levels, beginning with the phonetic level. Although these correlational
JB[v.20020404] Prn:7/03/2007; 17:06 F: AICR6810.tex / p.5 (253-323)
results do not necessarily establish that phonetic learning drives other aspects of
language acquisition, they suggest, at a minimum, that there is continuity across
domains and that learning from experience may be essential for each (see also
Jusczyk 1997; Werker & Curtin 2005).
We have suggested elsewhere (Kuhl et al. 2005, 2007) that both the decline
in the perception of nonnative phonemes during the first year, and constraints
on learning at later ages, arise from native-language learning that begins during
the first year of life. On this view, native-language learning produces dedicated
neural networks that code the patterns of native-language speech, resulting in
a “warping” of perceptual representations of the acoustic properties of speech
sounds (Kuhl 2000; Kuhl 2004; Kuhl et al. 2005). The result of such neural com-
mitment is resistance to learning phonetic features that are in opposition to those
of the native language. Although early proposals regarding “critical periods” for
language acquisition (e.g., Lenneberg 1967) asserted that a second language could
be acquired without a foreign accent anytime until puberty, more recent research
suggests that optimal learning of a second language’s phonology occurs much ear-
lier than puberty. For example, Flege and colleagues have shown that learning a
second language after approximately 5 years of age leads to more difficulty per-
ceiving particular speech sounds in that language when compared to acquisition
that takes place before that age (Flege, Bohn, & Jang 1997; Flege & Eefting 1987;
Flege & MacKay 2004; Flege, MacKay, & Meador 1999). For vowels, acquisition as
early as 3–4 years of age may still not result in native-like perception (Bosch, Costa,
& Sebastián-Gallés 2000; Pallier, Bosch, & Sebastián-Gallés 1997). Adults may be
trained to perceive nonnative phonemic contrasts, but this does not always result
in native-like speech perception (Polka 1991). In the rest of this chapter we ex-
plore some of the factors that might be important for phonetic learning in infancy
to be successful. We start with the assumption that brain plasticity remains open
for second language acquisition throughout infancy, but also suggest that certain
environmental conditions are important for learning to ensue.
Kuhl and colleagues (Kuhl, Tsao, & Liu 2003) applied the HT technique to ad-
dress the question of how infants who are well within the “critical” or “sensitive”
period for second language acquisition learn to perceive speech sound contrasts
from a nonnative language. In Experiment 1, two groups of 10–11-month-old in-
fants growing up in Seattle in monolingual English-speaking homes were tested on
a phonetic discrimination HT task using the Mandarin alveolar-palatal /./ vs. /t.h /
fricative/affricate contrast, two sounds that are not English phonemes. Although
English uses a fricative/affricate phonemic contrast (“sh” vs. “ch”), it does so at
JB[v.20020404] Prn:7/03/2007; 17:06 F: AICR6810.tex / p.6 (323-383)
a different place of articulation (palato-alveolar). All of the infants came into the
laboratory for play sessions for approximately one month prior to testing, a total of
twelve 25-minute sessions. The first group (Mandarin live-exposure) heard Man-
darin from live native speakers who interacted with the infants in a naturalistic
way, while showing them toys and books. The second group of infants (English-
only control group) came into the laboratory exactly the same number of sessions
but heard only English, from live speakers who interacted with the infants in a nat-
uralistic way and showed them the same toys and books. Remarkably, the infants
who received live exposure to Mandarin showed phonetic learning as assessed us-
ing the HT task, even though their total amount of exposure was only 5 hours
over a month’s time. Their results were compared to the results of a separate study
in which the same phonetic contrast was tested in infants of the same age from
either monolingual Mandarin-speaking homes in Taiwan or monolingual English-
speaking homes in Seattle (Kuhl et al. 2001, Figure 2). The infants who received live
exposure to Mandarin showed a statistically identical level of performance on the
Mandarin contrast as the infants growing up in Taiwan. This result could not be
explained simply by familiarity with going to the laboratory and interacting, since
the infants who received live English exposure during play sessions with adults did
not show better performance on the Mandarin phonetic contrast than those who
had never been to the laboratory prior to testing.
These results suggested that even a relatively small amount of naturalistic ex-
posure to a new language could result in significant learning at this age. Towards
the end of the first year of life, infants are well-equipped for learning to map the
phonetic patterns of a new language when it is introduced in a naturalistic way,
through social interaction with speakers of that language. Although their speech
perception has already begun to show native-like processing at this age, as re-
viewed above, their systems seem to remain sufficiently plastic for the learning
of a new language. But the results left open the question of whether live exposure
through social interaction was necessary for such learning to ensue. Numerous
studies of younger infants had shown that infants could learn from audio-only
exposure to a small number of artificial language stimuli presented in a disem-
bodied voice, based on the statistical properties of the input (e.g., Aslin, Saffran,
& Newport 1998; Goodsitt, Morgan, & Kuhl 1993; Maye et al. 2002; Saffran 2003;
Saffran, Aslin, & Newport 1996; Saffran et al. 1999). Perhaps infants could learn
to perceive the Mandarin phonetic contrast just as well if they were exposed to
speakers of the language via audiotapes. Alternatively, perhaps they would learn in
audio-only conditions, but would learn better if they had both audio and visual
information, presented in a television format. Previous studies had shown that
audiovisual information is also important for early phonetic learning in infancy
(Kuhl & Meltzoff 1982, 1996). Experiment 2 was designed to test these possibilities.
JB[v.20020404] Prn:7/03/2007; 17:06 F: AICR6810.tex / p.7 (383-399)
In Experiment 2, two groups of infants were brought to the lab for twelve 25-
minute sessions. The first group (Mandarin audiovisual-exposure) watched DVDs
of the same Mandarin speakers who were used in Experiment 1, showing the same
toys and books, but there was no live interaction. The second group (Mandarin
audio-exposure) listened to the audio channel of the same DVDs, but received no
visual input from speakers of the language. Both groups heard the same amount
of Mandarin as the live-exposure group from Experiment 1, delivered in the same
naturalistic infant-directed speech by the same speakers. These two groups of in-
fants were then tested on the same Mandarin fricative/affricate contrast used in
Experiment 1.
The results of the testing were surprising. The Mandarin-audio-only and
Mandarin-audiovisual groups both performed similarly to the English-only con-
trol group from Experiment 1; all three groups performed similarly to a separate
group of monolingual-English infants who were tested at the same age but had
never been to the laboratory before (Figure 2). These results show that something
special happened during the live Mandarin exposure sessions. Passive listening to
JB[v.20020404] Prn:7/03/2007; 17:06 F: AICR6810.tex / p.8 (399-444)
Mandarin from a television did not induce learning, even when visual as well as
audio cues were available. All three learning conditions were similar in the sense
that language input was provided using a natural voice, and the infants were not re-
quired to do anything except sit and listen. Yet phonetic learning was not triggered
simply by auditory, or even audio-visual, exposure to Mandarin, in contrast to the
previous studies that found that 6–8-month-old infants could learn statistically
from small amounts of audio-only exposure to language stimuli.
As discussed previously by Kuhl and colleagues (2003), naturalistic exposure
to multiple speakers presents infants with a much more complex learning situ-
ation than controlled exposure to isolated instances of speech stimuli during an
experiment. Learning occurs in both instances. However, learning in the natu-
ral exposure experiments requires much more from infants; they must extract
phonetic information for the target contrast over a much broader and more vari-
able range of exemplars. For example, infants in the exposure experiments heard
between 26,000 and 42,000 (mean = 33,000) syllables over the course of the exper-
iment, spoken by 4 different people with different voices and styles of speaking. In
the statistical learning task conducted by Maye et al. (2002), infants heard tokens
of 10 computer-synthesized syllables. The infants exposed to Mandarin in the live
condition were shown books and toys that they could track visually. The pairing
of auditory and visual information in meaningful interactive contexts may have
engaged infants in the live-exposure group in a way that did not occur for the in-
fants in the group that simply watched and listened to the same material over a
television screen, or the infants who only heard the speakers’ voices but did not
have visual cues.
In complex naturalistic situations, social interaction could be a useful mech-
anism for heightening infants’ attention to relevant linguistic cues in the input.
Previous studies have suggested that attention affects speech processing in infants
(see Jusczyk 1997). The attainment of native-like speech perception between 9 and
11 months (as reflected in decreased sensitivity to nonnative contrasts to which in-
fants have had no exposure) has been linked to performance on problem-solving
tasks that require attentional control (Conboy, Sommerville, & Kuhl 2006; Lalonde
& Werker 1995). This suggests an underlying role for attention in both sets of skills.
Perhaps infants’ attention to audiovisual speaker cues, shown in previous studies
to be important for phonetic learning (Kuhl & Meltzoff 1982, 1996), was enhanced
during the live interactions but not during passive viewing of the DVDs. Indeed,
attention rating scores on a 4-point scale indicated that infants in the live con-
dition were more attentive to the speakers and their materials than those in the
audio-visual group, and the latter group was more attentive than infants in the
audio-only condition. Kuhl and colleagues have argued that attention and moti-
vation are key elements for communicative learning in humans and other species,
and are enhanced by social contact (Doupe & Kuhl 1999; Kuhl et al. 2003, 2007).
JB[v.20020404] Prn:7/03/2007; 17:06 F: AICR6810.tex / p.9 (444-502)
other’s states with remarkably high levels of coordination (Bateson 1979; Beebe et
al. 1988; Crown et al. 2002; Jaffe, Stern, & Peery 1973; Jaffe et al. 2001; Murray &
Trevarthen 1986; Stern 1977; Stern et al. 1975; Trevarthen 1979, 1998). The sponta-
neous, rhythmic “protoconversations” that take place during the first few months
of life, marked by mutual eye gaze, smiling, and vocalizations (Bateson 1979; Stern
2002), appear to reflect the infant’s desire for communication with other hu-
mans, and thus prepare infants for the acquisition of language (Trevarthen 1998).
Moreover, they are meaningful in the sense that they are embedded in a cultural
collectivity, a community of meaning provided by the adult (Rommetveit 1998).
Thus, even during the earliest stages of infancy, a primary intersubjectivity entail-
ing some sense of a “virtual other” is present, and appears to form a foundation
for learning via participation with other humans (Bråten 1998b).
Such reciprocal attunement with other humans may underlie the infant’s ear-
liest successes at learning to perceive speech in culturally specific ways. As early
as 6 months, the perception of vowels reflects the influence of the language en-
vironment (Kuhl et al. 1992). In a previous chapter, Kuhl (1998) suggested that
an ability to share perception with other speakers of their language allows such
early language-specific learning to take place. In that chapter, it was argued that a
sharing of perception allows infants to “mentally align themselves with adults of
the culture” (p. 297). In other words, infants learn mental maps, or filters, through
which to perceive language, which resemble the mental maps of other members
of the language community. Exposure to the sounds used by the community’s
language and distributional properties of those sounds in the ambient language
provide additional cues that allow infants to form such culturally specific percep-
tual filters or “native language perceptual magnets” (Kuhl 1993, 2000). Thus when
the infant experiences multiple exemplars of a phonetic prototype (the most rep-
resentative instance of a phonetic category), his/her perception of other speech
sounds in nearby acoustic space is influenced by that prototype. The prototype
functions as a “perceptual magnet,” perceptually pulling the other sounds towards
it so that all of the sounds are perceived as members of the same category by speak-
ers of that language. The infant becomes a member of the language community by
sharing in this language-specific perceptual warping.
At the time of that writing, little was known about the nature of the language
experience needed for such learning to occur. It had been established that infants
as young as 6–8 months of age could learn certain properties of a language from
passive exposure to the statistical properties present in disembodied speech di-
rected at them during structured experiments (e.g., Aslin et al. 1998; Goodsitt et
al. 1993; Maye et al. 2002; Saffran et al. 1996, 1997). It had also been established
that a yoking of visual information (mouth shape) to the auditory information
in speech was important for perception (Kuhl & Meltzoff 1982, 1996). The more
recent finding that 9–10-month-olds do not learn phonetically from passive expo-
JB[v.20020404] Prn:7/03/2007; 17:06 F: AICR6810.tex / p.11 (551-612)
Shifts in social cognition occurring in the second half of the first year have been
linked to important transitions in language development. Most notably, the in-
fant’s increasing ability to understand another person’s reference to an object of
joint attention is crucial for the acquisition of a meaningful, referential lexicon
(Akhtar & Tomasello 1998; Bakeman & Adamson 1984; Baldwin 1995; Baldwin
& Markman 1989; Brooks & Meltzoff 2002; Bruner 1983; Carpenter, Nagell,
& Tomasello 1998; Gogate, Walker-Andrews & Bahrick 2001; Tomasello 1999;
Tomasello & Farrar 1986; Tomasello & Todd 1983). Several key developments
coincide with this ability to understand reference. By 9 months infants begin to
engage in triadic “person-person-object games” – they systematically combine
purposes directed to objects with those that invoke interest from another human,
reflecting a “secondary intersubjectivity” (Trevarthen & Hubley 1978; Trevarthen
1998). Bråten (1998a) has demonstrated that towards the end of the first year,
infants display an “altercentric” participatory perception of others, as seen in be-
haviours that require a reversal of the perspective of the other during face-to-face
interactions. Tomasello and colleagues have further argued that shared perception
of communicative intentions, which emerges at around 9 months of age, is crucial
for the acquisition of language (Akhtar & Tomasello 1998; Tomasello 1999). The
ability to attend to objects of another person’s reference appears to be linked to
the infant’s ability to understand others as intentional agents (Tomasello 1999).
Around the same time that infants begin to display such abilities, they also begin
to display comprehension of the meanings of words (Fenson et al. 1994).
We suggest that attunement to the communicative intentions of other humans
enhances attention to linguistic units at several levels. Attention to the meaning of
a communicative act enhances the uptake of units of language present in that act.
For example, 9–10-month-old infants can follow the line of regard of others. When
JB[v.20020404] Prn:7/03/2007; 17:06 F: AICR6810.tex / p.12 (612-649)
faced with a language learning situation, specific meaningful social cues provided
by adults, such as eye gaze and pointing to an object of reference, may help infants
segment words from ongoing speech, thus facilitating phonetic learning from the
sounds contained in those words (Kuhl et al. 2003). This does not necessarily mean
that infants this age are able to integrate all of the relevant information present in
the signal at once. Indeed, recent studies have suggested that even at 14 months
infants are unable to use fine phonetic detail when processing words with mean-
ing (Mills et al. 2004; Stager & Werker 1997; Werker, Fennell, Corcoran, & Stager
2002), although infants this age can perceive such phonetic information in words
(Swingley & Aslin 2002). Early language acquisition is most likely a piecemeal pro-
cess in which multiple pieces of information are gradually integrated (Hollich,
Hirsh-Pasek, & Golinkoff 2000). When faced with a new language learning situa-
tion, infants this age may tune into the meaningfulness of interactions with their
interlocutors first, and this in turn may facilitate their learning of other aspects
of the language. Situations in which meaning is mediated by the adult, via be-
haviours that are contingent on the infants’ behaviours, are thus more likely to
induce learning than situations not mediated in this way. Infants’ understanding
of the contingencies between their actions and those of adults may influence their
attention to linguistic units at all levels. Infants’ behaviours, such as levels of gen-
eral attention and arousal, may in turn enhance the quality of the input they receive
from adults.
The role of shared perception for phonetic learning may increase throughout
development, as infants become increasingly aware of the communicative inten-
tions of others and more in tune with the meaning of such communication. As
such, older infants may be more attuned to information presented in situations
in which their interlocutors’ responses are contingent upon their actions. Further
research is needed to determine whether audiovisual information presented in a
static, non-contingent format such as the DVD condition in the study reported
by Kuhl et al. 2003) is more useful to infants at particular developmental stages,
and whether a television format in which such contingencies are present would
be equally effective for phonetic learning. In a study of 14- and 24-month-old in-
fants, Meltzoff found that infants of both ages could imitate adult actions with
objects presented over a television screen, even after a 24-hour delay (Meltzoff
1988). In that study the video presentations were timed so that they coincided
with optimal levels of infant visual attention. Language exposure presented in a
similar format, while not completely interactive, could nevertheless provide some
level of responsivity to infants’ attentional levels.
The phonetic learning that occurs in live, natural interactions with speak-
ers of a language may also be more robust and durable than that which occurs
through static, non-contingent exposure to speech. For example, infants in the live
Mandarin exposure experiment were tested between 2 and 12 days after the final
JB[v.20020404] Prn:7/03/2007; 17:06 F: AICR6810.tex / p.13 (649-697)
exposure session. A median split based on the number of days between infants’ last
exposure session and the HT learning assessment session indicated that learning
was not short-lived. Infants tested immediately after the last exposure performed
similarly to those who were tested more than a week later. Learning in live inter-
actions and controlled experiments may be fruitfully compared with regard to the
durability and robustness of learning; our working hypothesis is that infants need
exposure to multiple instances spoken by different talkers in natural settings to
show phonetic learning that is robust and durable. Even the 5-hour exposure that
infants experience in our experiments is not expected to be as robust as the learn-
ing shown by infants who have been raised listening to a particular language for
11 months.
Further research is also needed to determine whether there are individual
differences in the ability to shift to culturally/linguistically appropriate ways of
listening to a language. As discussed previously, studies from our lab have shown
that individual variation in the attainment of native-language perception is linked
to other advances (Conboy et al. 2005; Kuhl et al. 2005; Rivera-Gaxiola et al. 2005b;
Tsao et al. 2004). Individual variation in the learning of a new language may also
be predicted by first language abilities, and by advances in other areas of cognition.
For example, infants who display more joint attention behaviours during language
learning situations may learn more than those who hear the same phonetic in-
formation but engage in fewer joint attention behaviours. Infants who display
a greater number of contingent responses to the adults’ actions and speech may
show a greater amount of learning than other infants. Furthermore, infants who
are more advanced on problem-solving tasks that require high levels of attentional
control may be better able to learn from second language exposure than infants
who are less advanced on such tasks.
We are currently exploring these ideas through a study in which infants from
English-speaking homes are being exposed to Spanish at 9–10 months of age. In-
fants are brought to the lab for a total of twelve 25-minute sessions in which they
hear Spanish from native speakers who interact with them naturally while show-
ing them toys and picture books. In this research, we are also analyzing the social
behaviours that occur in these second-language learning situations. Of interest to
us is whether aspects of the interactions are predictive of the amounts of phonetic
learning that occur. We are assessing the robustness and durability of learning by
comparing performance on the HT task between infants who receive this short-
term exposure to Spanish and those who have had naturalistic exposure to Spanish
for longer periods of time, both in monolingual and bilingual learning situations.
JB[v.20020404] Prn:7/03/2007; 17:06 F: AICR6810.tex / p.14 (697-753)
We are also exploring whether infants are able to learn other aspects of language
from these interactions. If they are attending to their language input at the word
level, then this should also be reflected in the way they process words. Previous
research using event-related brain potentials (ERPs) has established that infants
as young as 9–11 months of age process words they have been familiarized with
differently from unfamiliar words (Addy & Mills 2005; Mills, Coffey-Corina, &
Neville 1994; Thierry, Vihman, & Roberts 2003). If infants attend to language at
this level in second-language learning situations, then the ERPs to words they have
heard during these sessions should be processed differently from words they have
never heard. As with phonetic learning, such lexically based learning may be pre-
dicted by the social behaviours displayed by infants and their adult communicative
partners during second-language learning interactions.
We are also examining whether individual differences in the overall quality
of dyadic behaviours during language exposure sessions are linked to later cogni-
tive and language outcomes. Previous research has shown that infants who receive
high levels of “mediated learning experiences” from their mothers show better per-
formance on tests of language and cognitive development at 2, 3, 4, and 5 years
of age (Klein & Alony 1992; Klein, Weider, & Greenspan 1987). In this research,
interactions were said to be “mediated” by the adult when they contained the fol-
lowing elements: (1) intentionality (an act directed toward affecting the infant’s
perception or behaviour) and reciprocity (an observable response from the infant
that s/he saw/heard the intentional behaviour); (2) mediation of meaning (expres-
sions of excitement, appreciation, or affect in relation to objects, concepts, etc.);
(3) transcendence (attempts to expand the infant’s cognitive awareness); (4) me-
diation of feelings of competence (expressions of satisfaction with the infant’s
behaviour); and (5) regulation of behaviour (matching tasks to the infant’s capac-
ities, interests, etc.). Such experiences may be defined differently across cultures,
but are believed to be found universally. Other research has shown that adult re-
sponsivity to infants predicts cognitive and language outcomes (e.g., Baumwell et
al. 1997; Beckwith et al. 1976; Beckwith & Cohen 1989; Bloom 1993; Bornstein
1989; Bornstein et al. 1990; Bornstein & Tamis-LeMonda 1989, 1997; Bornstein,
Tamis-LeMonda, & Haynes 1999; Carew & Clarke-Stewart 1980; Clarke-Stewart
1973; Landry et al. 1997, 2001; Nicely, Tamis-LeMonda & Bornstein 1999; Tamis-
LeMonda & Bornstein 2002; Tamis-LeMonda et al. 1996, 2001). Based on this
previous work and the results of our studies reviewed in this chapter, we pre-
dict that both the quality of infant-tutor interactions during language exposure,
as measured by the amount of mediation provided by the adult and the respon-
sivity of the adult to the infant’s behaviours, will influence infant second language
learning. On the infant’s part, joint attention and engagement behaviours should
enhance learning.
JB[v.20020404] Prn:7/03/2007; 17:06 F: AICR6810.tex / p.15 (753-800)
We have suggested that social interactions between infants and adults provide a
cultural context that moves infants into specific ways of listening to language and
facilitates subsequent language learning from members of the cultural linguistic
group. A key component of these interactions may be the degree to which infants
and adults engage in contingent behaviours that enhance infants’ attention to rel-
evant linguistic information. Thus, infants’ cognitive abilities, their understanding
of social cues, and adult behaviours coincide to provide effective environments for
phonetic learning. We have presented data that suggest how these factors might
influence second language phonetic learning in infancy, and have generated hy-
potheses we are now investigating. We have also suggested that similar processes
play an important role in first language phonetic learning. Additional research is
needed to examine what kinds of phonetic information can be learned across first
and early second language situations, and under what conditions. More work is
also needed to assess the extent to which short-term exposure to language under
conditions that simulate natural language interactions can result in robust, durable
learning such as that found in primary language acquisition.
We also wish to emphasize that there are likely to be differences across cultural
groups in the ways in which phonetic learning occurs. Face-to-face interactions
between infants and adults are not uniformly common across all cultures (e.g.,
Bornstein et al. 1990a, b, c; Heath 1983; Martini & Kirkpatrick 1981; Rogoff 2003;
Schieffelin 1991); thus, they may not be as important for the development of
shared perception as has been suggested by developmental research in middle-class
Western cultures. The degree to which talk is valued compared to nonverbal forms
of communication varies across cultures. Distal forms of communication involv-
ing sound, rather than more proximal nonverbal communication involving touch,
may be emphasized to a greater extent in cultures in which infants are physically
separated from other people compared to those in which infants are always kept
close (see Rogoff 2003). It is well known that across many cultures the speech di-
rected towards infants (often referred to as “motherese”) contains properties that
attract and hold infant attention (Fernald 1984; Fernald & Kuhl 1989), and speech
units that are exaggerated (Kuhl et al. 1997). Our work has recently shown that
the degree of mothers’ speech clarity in these infant-directed episodes strongly
correlates with infants’ speech discrimination in the HT task (Liu, Kuhl, & Tsao
2003), suggesting that the exaggerated language directed towards infants in social
settings attracts infants’ attention and assists learning. Whether this process is con-
sistent or different across cultures remains to be explored. In some cultures infants
are not regarded as conversational partners, and little speech is directed at them
(Heath 1983; Ochs & Schieffelin 1984; Schieffelin 1991; Ward 1971). However,
the infants are surrounded by the speech of others, and their actions or interests
JB[v.20020404] Prn:7/03/2007; 17:06 F: AICR6810.tex / p.16 (800-867)
References
Addy, D., & Mills, D. (2005, April). “Brain activity to familiar, unfamiliar, and backward words
in infants 3 to 10 months of age.” Poster presented at the Biennial Meeting of the Society for
Research in Child Development, Atlanta, GA.
Adret, P. (1993). “Operant conditioning, song learning and imprinting to taped song in the
zebra finch.” Animal Behaviour, 46, 149–159.
Akhtar, N., & Tomasello, M. (1998). “Intersubjectivity in early language learning and use.” In S.
Bråten (Ed.), Intersubjective Communication and Emotion in Early Ontogeny (pp. 316–335).
Cambridge, UK: Cambridge University Press.
Aslin, R. N., Pisoni, D. B., Hennessy, B. L., & Percy, A. J. (1981). “Discrimination of voice onset
time by human infants: New findings and implications for the effects of early experience.”
Child Development, 52 (4), 1135–1145.
Aslin, R. N., Saffran, J. R., & Newport, E. L. (1998). “Computation of conditional probability
statistics by 8-month-old infants.” Psychological Science, 9 (4), 321–324.
Bakeman, R., & Adamson, L. B. (1984). “Coordinating attention to people and objects in
mother-infant and peer-infant interaction.” Child Development, 55, 1278–1289.
Baldwin, D. (1995). “Understanding the link between joint attention and language.” In C. Moore
& P. J. Dunham (Eds.), Joint Attention: Its Origins and Role in Development (pp. 131–158).
Hillsdale, NJ: Erlbaum.
Baldwin, D. A., & Markman, E. M. (1989). “Establishing word-object relations: A first step.”
Child Development, 60, 381–398.
Baptista, L. F., & Petrinovich, L. (1986). “Song development in the white-crowned sparrow:
Social factors and sex differences.” Animal Behaviour, 34 (5), 1359–1371.
Bates, E. (1976). Language and Context: The Acquisition of Pragmatics. New York : Academic
Press.
JB[v.20020404] Prn:7/03/2007; 17:06 F: AICR6810.tex / p.17 (867-965)
Hart, B., & Risley, T. (1995). Meaningful Differences in the Everyday Experiences of Young
American Children. Baltimore, MD: Brookes.
Hart, B., & Risley, T. R. (1999). The Social World of Children Learning to Talk. Baltimore, MD:
Brookes.
Heath, S. B. (1983). Ways with Words: Language, Life and Work in Communities and Classrooms.
Cambridge, UK: Cambridge University Press.
Hollich, G., Hirsh-Pasek, K., & Golinkoff, R. (2000). “Breaking the language barrier: An
emergentist coalition model for the origins of word learning.” Monographs of the Society
for Research in Child Development, 65 (3), Serial No. 262.
Immelmann, K. (1969). “On the effect of early experience upon sexual object fixation in
estrildine finches.” Zeitschrift fur Tierpsychologie, 26 (6), 677–691.
Jaffe, J., Beebe, B., Feldstein, S., Crown, C. L., & Jasnow, M. C. (2001). “Rhythms of dialogue in
infancy.” Monograhs of the Society for Research in Child Development, 66 (2), Serial No. 265.
Jaffe, J., Stern, D. N., & Peery, J. C. (1973). “ “Conversational” coupling of gaze behavior in
prelinguistic human development.” Journal of Psycholinguistic Research, 2 (4), 321– 329.
Jamieson, D. G., & Morosan, D. E. (1986). “Training nonnative speech contrasts in adults:
Acquisition of the English /θ/-/ð/ contrast by francophones.” Perception & Psychophysics,
40, 205–215.
Jamieson, D. G., & Morosan, D. E. (1989). “Training new, nonnative speech contrasts: A
comparison of the prototype and perceptual fading techniques.” Canadian Journal of
Psychology, 43 (1), 88–96.
Jusczyk, P. W. (1997). The Discovery of Spoken Language. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.
Klein, P. S., & Alony, S. (1993). “Immediate and sustained effects of maternal mediating
behaviors on young children.” Journal of Early Intervention, 17, 177–193.
Klein, P. S., Weider, S., & Greenspan, S. L. (1987). “A theoretical overview and empirical study
of mediated learning experience: Prediction of preschool performance from mother-infant
interaction patterns.” Infant Mental Health Journal, 8, 110–129.
Kuhl, P. K. (1979). “Speech perception in early infancy: Perceptual constancy for spectrally
dissimilar vowel categories.” Journal of the Acoustical Society of America, 66, 1668–1679.
Kuhl, P. K. (1985). “Methods in the study of infant speech perception.” In G. Gottlieb & N.
Krasnegor (Eds.), Measurement of Audition and Vision in the First Year of Postnatal Life: A
Methodological Overview (pp. 223–251). Norwood, NJ: Ablex.
Kuhl, P. K. (1993). “Early linguistic experience and phonetic perception: Implications for
theories of developmental speech perception.” Journal of Phonetics, 21, 125–139.
Kuhl, P. K. (1998). “Language, culture and intersubjectivity: The creation of shared perception.”
In S. Bråten (Ed.), Intersubjective Communication and Emotion in Early Ontogeny (pp. 297–
315). Cambridge, UK: Cambridge University Press.
Kuhl, P. K. (2000). “A new view of language acquisition.” Proceedings of the National Academy of
Sciences, 97, 11850–11857.
Kuhl, P. K. (2004). “Early language acquisition: Cracking the speech code.” Nature Reviews
Neuroscience, 5, 831–843.
Kuhl, P. K., Conboy, B. T., Coffey-Corina, S., Padden, D., Rivera-Gaxiola, M., & Nelson, T. (2007,
in press). “Developmental phonetic perception: Native Language Magnet Theory-expanded
(NLM-e).” Philosophical Transactions of the Royal Society B. (in press).
Kuhl, P. K., Conboy, B., Padden, D., Nelson, T., & Pruitt, J. (2005). “Early speech perception and
later language development: Implications for the ‘critical period’.” Language Learning and
Development, 1, 237–264.
JB[v.20020404] Prn:7/03/2007; 17:06 F: AICR6810.tex / p.21 (1288-1395)
Kuhl, P. K., & Meltzoff, A. N. (1982). “The bimodal perception of speech in infancy.” Science,
218, 1138–1141.
Kuhl, P. K., & Meltzoff, A. N. (1996). “Infant vocalizations in response to speech: Vocal imitation
and developmental change.” Journal of the Acoustical Society of America, 100 (4, Pt 1), 2425–
2438.
Kuhl, P. K., Tsao, F.-M., & Liu, H.-M. (2003). “Foreign-language experience in infancy: Effects
of short-term exposure and social interaction on phonetic learning.” Proceedings of the
National Academy of Sciences, 100, 9096–9101.
Kuhl, P. K., Tsao, F.-M., Liu, H.-M., Zhang, Y., & de Boer, B. (2001). “Language/Culture/
Mind/Brain: Progress at the margins between disciplines.” In A. Damasio, A. Harrington,
J. Kagan, B. Mcewen, H. Moss, & R. Shaikh (Eds.), Unity of Knowledge: The Convergence
of Natural and Human Science (Vol. 935) (pp. 136–174). New York: New York Academy of
Sciences.
Kuhl, P. K., Williams, K. A., Lacerda, F., Stevens, K. N., & Lindblom, B. (1992). “Linguistic
experience alters phonetic perception in infants by 6 months of age.” Science, 255, 606–608.
Lalonde, C. E., & Werker, J. F. (1995). “Cognitive influences on cross-language speech perception
in infancy.” Infant Behavior & Development, 18, 459–475.
Landry, S. H., Smith, K. E., Miller-Loncar, C. L., & Swank, P. R. (1997). “Predicting cognitive-
language and social growth curves from early maternal behaviors in children at varying
degrees of biological risk.” Developmental Psychology, 33 (6), 1040–1053.
Landry, S. H., Smith, K. E., Swank, P. R., Assel, M. A., & Vellet, S. (2001). “Does early responsive
parenting have a special importance for children’s development or is consistency across
early childhood necessary?” Developmental Psychology, 37 (3), 387–403.
Lasky, R. E., Syrdal-Lasky, A., & Klein, R. E. (1975). “VOT discrimination by four to six month
old infants from Spanish environments.” Journal of Experimental Child Psychology, 20, 215–
225.
Lenneberg, E. H. (1967). The Biological Foundations of Language. New York: Wiley.
Liu, H.-M., Kuhl, P. K., & Tsao, F.-M. (2003). “An association between mothers’ speech clarity
and infants’ speech discrimination skills.” Developmental Science, 6, F1–F10.
Logan, J. S., Lively, S. E., & Pisoni, D.B . (1991). “Training Japanese listeners to identify /r/ and
/l/: A first report.” Journal of the Acoustical Society of America, 89 (2), 874–886.
Martini, M., & Kirkpatrick, J. (1981). “Early interactions in the Marquesas Islands.” In T. M.
Fields, A. M. Sostek, P. Vietze, & P. H. Leiderman (Eds.), Culture and Early Interactions
(pp. 189–213). Hillsdale, NJ: Erlbaum.
Maye, J., Werker, J. F., & Gerken, L. (2002). “Infant sensitivity to distributional information can
affect phonetic discrimination.” Cognition, 82, B101–B111.
McClasky, C. L., Pisoni, D. B., & Carrell, T. D. (1983). “Transfer of training of a new linguistic
contrast in voicing.” Perception and Psychophysics, 34, 323–330.
McClelland, J. L, Fiez, J. A., & McCandliss, B. D. (2002). “Teaching the /r/–/l/ discrimination to
Japanese adults: Behavioral and neural aspects.” Physiology & Behavior, 77 (4–5), 657–662.
Meltzoff, A. N. (1988). “Imitation of televised models by infants.” Child Development, 59 (5),
1221–1229.
Mills, D. L., Coffey-Corina, S., & Neville, H. J. (1994). “Variability in cerebral organization
during primary language acquisition.” In G. Dawson & K. W. Fischer (Eds.), Human
Behavior and the Developing Brain (pp. 427–455). New York: Guilford Press.
JB[v.20020404] Prn:7/03/2007; 17:06 F: AICR6810.tex / p.22 (1395-1497)
Mills, D. L., Prat, C., Zangl, R., Stager, C. L., Neville, H. J., & Werker, J. F. (2004). “Language
experience and the organization of brain activity to phonetically similar words: ERP
evidence from 14- and 20-month-olds.” Journal of Cognitive Neuroscience, 16 (8), 1452–
1464.
Morosan, D. E., & Jamieson, D. G. (1989). “Evaluation of a technique for training new speech
contrasts: Generalization across voices, but not word-position or task.” Journal of Speech &
Hearing Research, 32 (3), 501–511.
Murray, L., & Trevarthen, C. (1986). “The infant’s role in mother-infant communications.”
Journal of Child Language, 13 (1), 15–29.
Nicely, P., Tamis-LeMonda, C. S., & Bornstein, M. H. (1999). “Mothers’ attuned responses
to infant affect expressivity promote earlier achievement of language milestones.” Infant
Behavior & Development, 22 (4), 557–568.
Ochs, E., & Schieffelin, B. B. (1984). “Language acquisition and socialization: Three
developmental stories and their implications.” In R. Schweder & R. LeVine (Eds.), Culture
and its Acquisition. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.
Pegg, J. E., & Werker, J. F. (1997). “Adult and infant perception of two English phones.” Journal
of the Acoustical Society of America, 102, 3742–3753.
Pallier, C., Bosch, L., & Sebastián-Gallés, N. (1997). “A limit on behavioral plasticity in speech
perception.” Cognition, 64, B9–B17.
Pisoni, D., Aslin, R., Perey, A., & Hennessy, B. (1982). “Some effects of laboratory training
on identification and discrimination of voicing contrasts in stop consonants.” Journal of
Experiemntal Psychology: Human Perception and Performance, 8, 297–314.
Pisoni, D. B., Lively, S. E., & Logan, J. S. (1994). “Perceptual learning of nonnative speech
contrasts.” In J. C. Goodman & H. C. Nusbaum (Eds.), The Development of Speech
Perception: The Transition from Speech Sounds to Spoken Words (pp. 121–166). Cambridge,
MA: MIT Press.
Polka, L. (1991). “Cross-language speech perception in adults: Phonemic, phonetic, and acoustic
contributions.” Journal of the Acoustical Society of America, 89 (6), 2961–2977.
Polka, L. (1992). “Characterizing the influence of native language experience on adult speech
perception.” Perception & Psychophysics, 52, 37–52.
Polka, L., Colantonio, C., & Sundara, M. (2001). “A cross-language comparison of /d/–/ð/
perception: Evidence for a new developmental pattern.” Journal of the Acoustical Society
of America, 109, 2190–2201.
Polka, L. J., & Rvachew, S. (1995). “Methods for studying speech perception in infants and
children.” In W. Strange (Ed.), Speech Perception and Linguistic Experience: Theoretical and
Methodological Issues in Cross-language Speech Research. Timonium, MD: York Press.
Rivera-Gaxiola, M., Klarman, L., Garcia-Sierra, A., & Kuhl, P. K. (2005b). “Neural patterns to
speech and vocabulary growth in American infants.” NeuroReport, 16, 495–498.
Rivera-Gaxiola, M., Silva-Pereyra, J., & Kuhl, P. K. (2005a). “Brain potentials to native-
and nonnative speech contrasts in seven and eleven-month-old American infants.”
Developmental Science, 8, 162–172.
Rogoff, B. (2003). The Cultural Nature of Human Development. London: Oxford University
Press.
Rogoff, B., Mistry, J., Goncu, A., Mosier, C., Chavajay, P., & Heath, S. B. (1993). “Guided
participation in cultural activity by toddlers and caregivers.” Monographs of the Society for
Research in Child Development, 58 (8), Serial No. 179.
JB[v.20020404] Prn:7/03/2007; 17:06 F: AICR6810.tex / p.23 (1497-1609)
Werker, J. F., & Tees, R. C. (2005). “Speech perception as a window for understanding plasticity
and commitment in language systems in the brain.” Developmental Psychobiology, 46 (3),
233–251.
Whaley, S. E., Sigman, M., Beckwith, L., Cohen, S. E., & Espinosa, M. P. (2002). “Infant-caregiver
interaction in Kenya and the United States: The Importance of multiple caregivers and
adequate comparison samples.” Journal of Cross-Cultural Psychology, 33 (3), 236–247.
Zhang, Y., Kuhl, P. K., Imada, T., Kotani, M., & Tohkura, Y. (2005). “Effects of language
experience: Neural commitment to language-specific auditory patterns.” NeuroImage, 26,
703–720.
Zukow, P. G. (Ed.) (1989). Sibling Interaction Across Cultures: Theoretical and Methodological
Issues. New York: Springer-Verlag Publishing.
JB[v.20020404] Prn:13/02/2007; 14:23 F: AICR6811.tex / p.1 (48-106)
chapter
Ivar Frönes
University of Oslo
The social sciences have always been faced with the challenge of understanding
and describing the relation between individual and society, between structure and
subject. Central to this relation is socialization: how a human being comes to be
a member of a formative culture and society and in that process develops as a
unique individual and an (inter)acting subject. Occuring in the intersection of
innate capacities and environment, socialization constitutes the meeting point of
the individual subject and the structures of a culture.
Theories of socialization postulate how human beings are formed or shaped,
affording not only theories of socialization as such, but also models and images of
essential characteristics of human beings. Theories present children both as aso-
cial and prosocial, as shaped by the nurturance of the family or by the influence
of peers, as influenced by inherited genes or as dominated by the environment.
Some theories picture man as an acting and reflective subject, others as a cul-
tural puppet governed by normative strings. To analyze theories of socialization
is to grapple with all these aspects and varieties of theories. While sociology and
anthropology are mainly concerned with the socialized human being, a variety
of psychological theories focus on the process of individual development. Even if
socialization is a key concept in the social sciences, analysis of the process of so-
cialization – the factual interaction between social and biological aspects, between
the micro and macro in the various phases of the process – is in fact surpris-
ingly absent. The myriad analyses of families and cultural mores, economic and
cultural resources, family dynamics and cognitive development, subgroups and
clinical protocols do not sum up to theories of socialization. They do, however,
JB[v.20020404] Prn:13/02/2007; 14:23 F: AICR6811.tex / p.2 (106-156)
Despite being a core concept of sociology, socialization is only rarely a topic for
empirical studies in the field. Children and youth have been analyzed empirically
as subcultures, as a child culture, as part of the family, as peer groups or as spe-
cial groups, and only to a lesser degree in terms of socialization. This is not to
criticize the choice of empirical topics in sociology, but to voice a concern about
the consequences. The field has, only to a limited degree, subjected the formation
of the (inter) acting social subject to the kind of scrutiny that extensive empirical
analyses of the process of socialization would have garnered. As a result, aspects of
socialization theory have been left with rather loose propositions or assumptions,
or the topic of socialization has been left to psychology. The relation between sub-
ject and structure is in sociology primarily formulated in terms of “agency” and
“structure”, rather than as an understanding of the dynamics of socialization, even
if discourses on social action convey some key dimensions of socialization.
Positing that societal norms and values are internalized and mirrored by the
psychic mind, some in sociological theories entertain the concept of the over-
socialized human being. This theory is well illustrated by Levi-Strauss, who said
that it is not man who expresses himself by myths, but rather the myths that
express themselves by man, or actors are recruited for their positions (as in
Althusser’s “interpellation”) by the grand discursive formations that shape human
actions and world images. The Marxist concept of “false consciousness” implies
the same: cultural structures are internalized by virtue of the socialization process.
Functionalist thought offers a different perspective, but within the same paradigm.
The combination of Marxist and psychoanalytic thought affords a theoretical bind
about the way in which the external society is transformed into internal moti-
vation (see, e.g., Marcuse 1968) through unconscious psychological mechanisms.
General theories in sociology seek to grasp the interplay between subject and struc-
ture. Examples are Talcott Parsons’ general theory of social action, and Berger and
Luckmann’s dialectics between internalization and externalization. In both cases,
JB[v.20020404] Prn:13/02/2007; 14:23 F: AICR6811.tex / p.3 (156-210)
they end up with a theory that conceptualizes how society is internalized rather
than how acting subjects influence social structures.
Bourdieu (1984) slightly relaxed the grip of structures with his notion of
autonomous fields populated by beings both who are influenced by structural
conditions and are actors. In a somewhat different perspective, Giddens (1984)
conceptualized a dynamic relation between structure and subject in his theory of
“structuration.” Even if anchored in a structuralist understanding, structures are
also seen to be “in” the actors, enabling and constraining them. The structura-
tion theory seeks to encompass both the dynamics of structural patterns and the
constitution of the subject.
In classic sociology, the theory of socialization centres largely on the fam-
ily and as occurring primarily in infancy and early childhood. The notion of
primary socialization implies that the first years of life are qualitatively different
from other stages in life, designated as secondary socialization, and that the forma-
tion occurring during the first year in the family is radically different from later
formation.
Although human behaviour, according to structuralist and functionalist the-
ories, reflects institutionalized structures, economic actors represent the under-
socialized human being. Rather than an acting social being, economic man is an
analytic model; man as a utility-function in a social landscape of uncertainty. Were
not the actor’s internal preferences treated as individual relata, they would become
norms, and optimalization would be seen as attempts to satisfy norms. The opti-
mizing economic actor striving to realize his or her own interests, confronted with
societal frames and constraints, may be viewed in a Hobbesian logic as the fight
between human “nature” and self-interest and the constraining society.
Over-socialized and under-socialized man have a lot in common. They are
both theoretical constructs and models of understanding, rather than description
of human beings living as acting subjects in a society. Both models afford explana-
tory power pertaining to action, but not to socialization. The under-socialized
man is simply optimizing his interest, and in doing so creating the paradox that all
actions will be defined as optimizing, since the actors internal preferences are un-
available. The model of the over-socialized man largely entertains the view of so-
cialization as a series of given mechanisms of internalization explaining how man
has become a part of the relevant culture. In both cases, the empirical dynamics of
the process and differentiated mechanisms are lost.
embedded in the context, but actors develop vocabularies of strategies within the
given social frames, the definitions of which are influenced by the strategies of the
actors. This social context is also clearly expressed in ethnometodology, although
more emphasis is placed here on actions based less on reflection and more on pre-
sumptions. In both perspectives, however, subject and context are interwoven in a
complex whole.
In symbolic interactionism, interaction is emphasized and, to a varying de-
gree, intersubjectivity. Mead distinguishes between an active core process, an “I,”
and the socially constituted “Me.” In a reflective human being, an active “I” relates
in a reflective manner to the social “Me” and creates and recreate Me. According
to Mead, “significant others,” by being a central part of a child’s social practice, are
not only persons, but represent contexts and culture. Mead’s specifications of “I”
and “Me” imply that the acting “I” acknowledges its “self ” by objectifying itself as
“Me”, by seeing itself from the outside. This “outside” may be the other, as position
and person; that is, “decentration” in the sense of Piaget. Decentration may also
imply taking a position in which the actor is able to understand dialogues as those
of “the third”: I reflect on my relation to the other. Thus, Mead’s logic becomes
dialogical, the “I” reflects on the dialogue between the “I,” the social “Me,” and
the general/significant other by comprehending the dialogue from the position of
“the third.” Humans are anchored in their social dialogues, and reflections on dia-
logues take the form of inner dialogues. This does not mean that all human beings
have the same reflective capacity. Although based on a general dialogical capac-
ity, reflection is an acquired ability, linked in particular to the modern, socially
composite, environment (Frönes 1995).
Although language as symbolic structure has been the point of departure
for structuralist understanding, the theory of speech and communicative action
entails another perspective. Language becomes a tool for realizing an actor’s inten-
tions. The focal relationship is not the structure-subject, but the subject-subject.
When Habermas breaks with the structuralist approach of the “old” Frankfurter
school, he is not doing so by virtue of escaping systemic impact, but through
the concept of communicative action. Communicative action establishes a relation
between subjects, thus intersubjectivity. Although a communicative action is an-
chored in cultural symbols and language, it is equally a part of a communicative
contract with another party.
Habermas’ dialog presupposes acting subjects. In a semiotic perspective, the
addressee – the recipient constructed in the message – is underlined. The same re-
cipient may have a series of possible positions, as an addressee varying with genres
of communications or “language games.” A letter that never reaches anyone is yet
directed to someone, and the same possible recipient may be addressed as lover,
friend, or enemy, or as being in a formal position defining the genre of the commu-
nication. Between two subjects, a variety of genres of dialogues can be established.
JB[v.20020404] Prn:13/02/2007; 14:23 F: AICR6811.tex / p.5 (258-310)
In this view, both the development of dialogical capacity and the processes of
social interpretation are dialogically structured in one’s mental capacity. In a com-
municative perspective, it is reasonable to talk about dialogical programming for
communication. By virtue of an intersubjective disposition, the child interprets
communication and relationships, which suggest that the child is born with ca-
pacity to decentre from the outset, that is, reaching out beyond itself. The complex
modes of self-objectification that are gradually developed are congruent with the
child’s essential nature, not in conflict with it.
Not only is the child biologically equipped to engage and exist in streams of
dialogues, but he or she may interpret the world as streams of dialogues. This
is illustrated by the child’s capacity for other-centred participation and empathy
(Bråten 1998). The little child is not driven toward others by inner needs or eth-
nocentrism, but enters the social world by virtue of its dialogical capacity. Thus
collapses the image of the child-environment link in which the child sees the other
as itself and who only later learns to distinguish between self and others. The little
dialogical human being socializes itself by initiating communion from birth. This
offers a new perspective on language development, with the child’s virtual other
creating a child who wants to communicate. By virtue of empathy in felt immedi-
acy (see, e.g., Bråten 1998), the actual other is constituted as a subject, not as an
object grasped in egocentrism. This does not suggest that the child cannot behave
in a self-centred manner, but that the child’s altercentric capacity provides the ba-
sis for empathy and decentration. This involves a further quantum leap related
to the active and robust infant portrayed by infancy research only a few decades
ago, in that the infant is not only self-driven, communicative, and robust, but also
competent for communion by virtue of what Stern (2004) terms “the intersub-
jective matrix”. In the dialogical perspective, context is constituted not as social
“environment,” or as “society” and “social structure,” but as a set of intersubjective
structures. The subject exists in a series of shifting dialogues; the context includes
not only present dialogues, but also past and planned potential dialogues. The in-
tersubjective structure thereby creates and influence structures and meaning in the
context. The potential meaning of a given context is thereby enriched, given that
that meaning rests on several possible perspectives and the capacity of the inter-
preter. Contents emerge not only by virtue of the external world, but from the
perspectives applied.
Empathy in the mode of felt immediacy and the infant as an acting subject
entail that the child encounters language and symbols not as incapable of distin-
guishing itself from the environment, but as an acting subject who parses the world
in dialogical patterns. The altercentric infant who aids another child has a different
relation to the sign than the posited egocentric child. The perspective of intersub-
jective altercentricity suggests a direction for the child’s formation of meaning
and significance, in which the child is exposed to signifiers, or sign-expressions,
JB[v.20020404] Prn:13/02/2007; 14:23 F: AICR6811.tex / p.10 (510-553)
such as “habitus,” roles, and interpellations into discursive positions imply postu-
lating a social identity that mirrors social structures. In modern life, we meet social
identity as a strategic composition of symbols and consummation, which are influ-
enced by social and cultural positions. Social identity is not, however, understood
as a passive reflection of hegemonic structures
A dialogical perspective anchors identity in subject and context, implying that
the construction of identity is an act, as well as interaction. My striving to compose
various aspects of myself as a whole or to send signals about my social position in-
volves a series of acts. The acts are themselves embedded in existing and potential
dialogues. My social constructions are rooted in the social context, but may also
transcend it. To construe one’s social belongingness is also an act, even though
it may be presented as a natural whole – for example, in terms of one’s “roots.”
That the act is influenced by structural relations does not change its being an act
or an utterance. From a psychological perspective, the modern identity task is to
maintain the coherence of self, and to draw the boundaries between oneself and
the processes in which one is embedded. It is considered problematic when iden-
tity is fragmented, without clear boundaries between self and the environment.
In a dialogical perspective, this fragmented identity may be viewed as lacking an
understanding of how to construct a modern self. The “dissolved self ” may be
understood as lacking the capacity to handle the dialogic self in a reflective man-
ner, in contexts in which the individual is anchored in many and interconnected
dialogues. The “dissolved” self may refer to a clinical problem, but also to the
existential challenges to the dialogical self in a modern environment.
Social expressions/utterances are developed in a context and need to be un-
derstood as acts, not as expressions of stable inner characteristics, even if stable
inner traits exist. As any utterance is an act, there is no point in distinguishing acts
from meanings or attitudes. Replying to a question in a survey by stating that I
intend to do so and so is an act, not a “reflection” of an inner (otherwise hidden)
state. The fact that replies in a survey vary with the interviewers or contexts does
not mean that the respondents are liars or unstable, but that communication is an
act in a context. A child is not lying when, alone with an interviewer, he or she
states that the school is interesting and important, and later, when joined by two
schoolmates, says that school is boring. The child “meant” what was said on both
occasions, but as actions, these statements are anchored socially. The first is a part
of the child-adult dialogue; the second as part of child culture.
The process of socialization is facilitated by the capacity of intersubjectivity
and most likely by other structural properties that may be traced in proto-language
and the mechanisms of language acquisition. The cultural world exists as an ob-
jective reality, which is gradually acquired by the active child. The internalization
of culture is a process of active acquisition of meaning, the process is structured by
the intersubjective matrix of the child and by the “social facts,” in a Durkheimian
JB[v.20020404] Prn:13/02/2007; 14:23 F: AICR6811.tex / p.12 (609-650)
sense, of language and culture. Within this framework the dialogic child meets
culture and language as something that the child gradually creates. Internalization
begins by relating sign and content, and the cultural conventions between signifier
and signified are gradually constructed by “doing,” by experience. The constitu-
tion of linguistic understanding does not occur by virtue of the language being
internalized as a series of signs with appropriate formal content, but by virtue of
the language being acquired through social processes in which the child itself is
active. Even if this gradually makes the external structure internal, the individual
and social variations reflect the social nature of meaning acquisition.
The innate intersubjective matrix does not only change theoretical points of depar-
ture for sociological and psychological conceptions of socialization, it also alters
JB[v.20020404] Prn:13/02/2007; 14:23 F: AICR6811.tex / p.13 (650-706)
how we conceptualize the acquisition of language and culture, the parent-child re-
lation, and child-child relations. This invites viewing a number of phenomena in a
different light and offers new perspectives on the child’s possible egoism. The fact
that the child seeks to promote itself does not mean he or she lacks the capacity to
recognize others.
In a dialogical matrix, the child’s language acquisition emerges as a dialogical
process in which the language is being moved from idiosyncratic and local con-
notations to general cultural and denotational categories, somewhat in line with
Peirce’s pragmatic understanding of communication: language has strong idiosyn-
cratic, local, and situation-anchored dimensions. Culture is acquired by the active
subject who is concurrently constituted as a cultural individual in this process. The
individual is formed owing to the existence of the subject, and not the other way
around. The other is also as subject established by virtue of the infant’s dialogic
matrix. Thereby the self is established as a subject, not as an acknowledgment, but
in the mode of felt immediacy in the layer of primary intersubjectivity. Although
this does not entail establishing a prosocial individual, the posited asocial individ-
ual can no longer be upheld. Although we cannot know the types of conversations
the child will encounter throughout life, we can know what the child is capable of.
The research on innate intersubjectivity provides a perspective on the mech-
anisms of phylogenetic and ontogenetic development. It is also easy to place the
development of the intersubjective matrix in an evolutionary framework and to
relate it to the perspectives of Dennet (2004), for example.
The idea of the child as a blank slate, being moulded by culture, can be viewed
on par not only with behaviourism, but with the idea of human beings as nothing
more than cultural beings. But the Durkheimian idea of “social facts” can very well
be preserved in a model of children born with innate structures and capacities that
influence and structure their interaction with culture patterns, and even perhaps
influencing cultural patterns as such. Culture as such must be understood as social
facts, as objective social realities. The conceptualizations of Peirce or Saussure of
language are no less fruitful if the child has dynamic innate capacities that struc-
ture how language and culture are acquired. However, the interaction between the
child and objective cultural realities should be understood in a different manner
than if the social facts alone ruled.
children in the 1970s and later. The variations in culture, class, and regions also
underscore how our assumptions of nurturance vary, and that the modern idea
of “stimulation” is different from the old bourgeoisie model of upbringing or the
aristocratic belief in sending children away for “training,” modelled after appren-
ticeships. I would argue that the modern assumptions that the nurturing acts of
parents shape the personality and growth of the child are related to the ideological
foundation of modern family, the demanding educational society, and the pop-
ular versions of educational theories that provide a stream of advice on how to
effectively stimulate one’s children.
This assumption about the centrality of nurturance must be separated from
the general importance of parenting. There is no doubt that the position of parents
has been strengthened as we shifted from an industrial society to an education-
based, postindustrial society. Parents are the basic provider of children’s total
environment, they influence children’s Weltanschauung as well as their habits, and
not in the least, parents’ actions shape or influence children’s environment, from
schools and organizational participation to neighbourhoods and peers. Parents as
providers of social and cultural capital, of emotional and economical support, en-
tail a different model of the parent-child relation from that inherent in nurture
assumptions. Nurturing, in its present dominating form, focuses on the infant or
young child and converges with the idea of the infant child as an object being
shaped into a subject by its parents. If the parents are responsible for such basic
humanization of the child, the idea of parents moulding the child’s personality
and development naturally follows. If the child is regarded as an acting subject,
bringing the matrix of intersubjectivity into his or her dialogues with their en-
vironment, the socialization process takes the form of interaction, with the child
as the active participant. The significant others who influence this acting subject
(and how) will vary with contextual factors, and with age and life phases. The role
of nurturing is implicitly based on the idea of primary socialization, an influence
prior to peer influence, or secondary socialization. Primary socialization assumes
a central role for early nurturance as shaping the child.
Our modern understanding of genetics also supports this weakening role of
parents as shaping their children (as does the prospect of siblings who differ
significantly from one another). An active subject, with the capacity for active
intersubjectivity, seeking the company of peers has a long history; play between
children seems to be a basic part of socialization and cultural competence (Frönes
1995). This critical view of the nurture assumption is not a rejection of the im-
portance of parents and parenting, but of the idea that children are shaped by the
nurturing of parents.
JB[v.20020404] Prn:13/02/2007; 14:23 F: AICR6811.tex / p.15 (756-798)
The intersubjective matrix constitutes not only the acting subject, but also “the
other” as a subject. The problem of the social sciences in establishing the subject is
that it may easily render the other invisible, as in the model of optimizing actor and
the over-socialized man. In an intersubjectivity perspective, the other is necessarily
at the centre of the matrix. The understanding of myself as a subject is based on
the recognition of the other as a subject. This opens the discussion for a further
elaboration of the position of the other in the understanding of intersubjectivity
as developed through the processes of socialization.
For Buber (1936) and Levinas (1996), the other is not just an acting subject;
the other constitute myself as a subject. The other is a different subject, one who
differs from me, while at the same time being like me, being a unique subject like
myself. The image of the other develops through socialization, from the simple
subject who is one like myself but still another, to the other as beings like me but
at the same time different, and even a mystery, the known unknown. The idea
of being close to another rests on the other being different, the romantic idea of
becoming as one is based on being two. Theories of development acknowledge the
same by emphasizing that social decentration entails acknowledging that the other
is not identical to me. The more we know about others, the further, deeper, and
more different the other becomes, while at the same time becoming closer.
The intersubjective matrix implies placing the other at the centre. The other
is not gradually recognized, it is always there at the centre of my own subjectivity
and as the basic mechanism in self-objectivation. Elaboration of the other is the
development of own self. The other as a mystery is a recognition of the complex
and mysterious self. In this acknowledgment lies the understanding of the dialog-
ical mind. The intersubjective matrix is a Hegelian subject with the other as the
necessary route to the self.
Theoretical elaboration and comprehensive empirical research support the di-
alogical child, affording a matrix for understanding human beings as biological
and social creatures. This new paradigm for understanding the relation between
culture and subject also offers new premises for socialization theory and for socio-
logical understanding in general. The intersubjective matrix not only accounts for
how the embodied individual is embedded in the social, but also how the subject
plays a role in constituting the dialogues in which it is embedded.
Acknowledgment
Some portions of this chapter are based on my essay (in Norwegian) on towards
a dialogical understanding of self and socialization, in Dialog, selv og samfunn,
JB[v.20020404] Prn:13/02/2007; 14:23 F: AICR6811.tex / p.16 (798-910)
I. Frönes and T. Schou Wetlesen (Eds.), Oslo: Abstrakt forlag, 2004: 250–268). I
thank the editor of the present volume for inviting this inclusion in spite of my
being prevented from presenting it at the Theory Forum Symposium on October
3–5 2004.
References
Mead, G. H. (1934). Mind, Self, and Society: From the Standpoint of a Social Behaviourist.
Chicago: University of Chicago Press.
Peirce, C. S. (1994). Semiotik og pragmatisme, A. M. Dinesen & F. Stjernfelt (Eds.). København:
Gyldendal.
Piaget, J. (1997). The Language and Thought of the Child. London: Routledge & Kegan Paul.
Stern, D. N. (2004). The Present Moment in Psychotherapy and Everyday Life. New York: W.W.
Norton.
Trevarthen, C., & Hubley, P. (1978). “Secondary intersubjectivity: Confidence, confiding, and
acts of meaning in the first year.” In J. Lock (Ed.), Action, Gesture, and Symbol (pp. 183–229).
London: Academic Press.
Veer, R. van der, & Valsiner, J. (1991). Understanding Vygotsky: A Quest for Synthesis. Oxford:
Blackwell.
Vygotskij, L. S. (1962). Thought and Language. New York: Wiley.
Winnicott, D. W. (1986). Familien og den individuelle udvikling: det sande og det falske selv.
Frederiksberg: Det lille forlag.
JB[v.20020404] Prn:13/02/2007; 14:47 F: AICR6812.tex / p.1 (48-110)
chapter
History of Psychology clearly states that “René Descartes stands at the portal of the
temple of modern philosophy and psychology” (p. 109).
As a point of departure we have the discrete, separate and autonomous sub-
ject. A lonely thinking ego (or even an autistic desiring unconscious), able to
differentiate and distance itself from the physical (including its body) and social
environment. Mind is considered discrete from the body. It rests “inside” the body
and its contents are private, subjective and accessible only by it. The body and the
rest of the world belong to the “exterior – outside”, are objectively perceived and in
fact are nothing more than “objects”. The relationship of the subject with the world
is not direct, but mediated by various psychological and especially cognitive pro-
cesses, like representations, beliefs, “prebeliefs”, schemes, desires, or unconscious
wishes. The other does not naturally exist for the self as a person simply by perceiv-
ing its special qualities, but must be discovered or constructed through action, or
the ascription of a mind, or the transcending of the initial fusion of the baby with
the mother. The relationship of the self with the world and the other persons is not
something given that develops further, but something that must be accomplished
through development.
Imagination revisited
person. We can discern at least two, the second-person and first-person intersubjec-
tivity. By the second-person intersubjectivity we refer to the direct, non-mediated
interaction between two persons that is characterized by sharing, mutuality, com-
plementarity and coordination. This broad kind of category can be further divided
into subcategories depending of which of the above dimensions prevails, or on
focus of the interaction. Following Stern (1983) we can differentiate between in-
tersubjectivity based on complementarity between the two partners, and intersub-
jectivity based on sharing and tuning. Another division could be between the in-
tersubjective interactions where the focal point is between the two persons (like in
primary intersubjectivity), and those where the two persons are jointly focussed on
a third “object” (like in secondary intersubjectivity) (Bråten 1998; Hobson 2002;
Trevarthen 1998). As first-person we define that kind of intersubjectivity where
there is not a direct, un-mediated meeting between two persons. Communication
or interaction is mediated by various forms of “(meta)representations” (Bråten
1998: 1–2). The other can be the “object” in the first-person’s consciousness, ex-
perience, reflection, simulation of mind, or imagination. Although, actually never
really an “object”, but the unique kind of object that a person always is.
In the context that is sketched by these propositions, imagination can no
longer be dealt as an individual, private, locked in the head faculty. Instead we
wish to promote the idea of the fundamentally dialogical and intersubjective na-
ture and development of imagination. Before discussing the various aspects of this
proposition, we need to define what imagination does. Through imagination the
absent is made present. We conceive of imagination as mental imagery, the abil-
ity to produce, maintain and manipulate mental images (Thomas 1997, 1999a,
1999b). This ability is directly linked to perception, without which it would be
hard to imagine how it could be possible for images to be formed at all. Gibson
(1979) defined perception as the active picking up of meaning afforded in the en-
vironment. We emphasize precisely the active dimension of this process. It is in
virtue of the activity of the whole person that meaning is perceived, through one’s
corporeal action in the world. Our bodily postures, orientations and actions deter-
mine perception and shape the meaning that is laid in the environment. Perceiving
and meaning through the whole body, implies that experience and various other
processes narrowly considered as merely “cognitive”, involve the whole person.
We consider imagination as a quasi-perceptional function. Its major differ-
ence from perception is this: while imagining the person does not actively explore
the actual environment (Thomas 1999b). The subject produces certain predic-
tions and expectations about how something might be, while refraining from
searching the “real world” to perceive. The body partakes in this process in three
ways. First, the bodily exploratory activity contributes decisively, through past ex-
periences, in the formation of these predictions. Perceptual experiences provide
imagination with raw data. Second, the perceptual-motor system participates fun-
JB[v.20020404] Prn:13/02/2007; 14:47 F: AICR6812.tex / p.4 (230-272)
damentally in the generation of mental images (Hebb 1968; Laeng & Teodorescu
2002; Neisser 1976). It was found that when subjects engage in mental imagery
of something that had actually been perceived in the past, they produce sponta-
neously eye movements that follow exactly the same scanpaths that where traced
during the perception phase (Brandt & Stark 1997; Laeng & Teodorescu 2002).
In another experiment in which the subjects where provided with verbal descrip-
tions of physical scenes not experienced before, they also generated spontaneously
eye movements that followed the direction and orientation of the described scene
(Demarais & Cohen 1998). Third, the body through its specific constitution, orga-
nization, position, and orientation in the world determines the meaning of what
is perceived, what the percepts mean to us, and the subjective nature of the ex-
perience. A widely used term to denote the organizational role of the body in
perception is “body scheme”. The body scheme may be defined as a holistic so-
matic complex or frame that orients the person and determines the way in which
experience is meaningful for the particular organism (Hermans 2003; Lakoff &
Johnson 1999; Neisser 2003). Imagination, as pointed out by Hermans (2003), is
an experience that has an “image-schematic” form. We “move” and process mean-
ings in imagination, much in the same way we move and process meanings in the
real world.
While talking about perception is usually done in the first person, a closer look
at development alters fundamentally the scene. Infants are from the beginning in-
troduced in a “second-person” world, an interpersonal and social world. Their
perception is continually structured by their interactions with other persons. Not
surprisingly, their perceptual system is well attuned to pick up the meanings that
are transmitted by another person, like eloquently shown in the case of neonatal
imitation (Kugiumutzakis 1998), and also attuned to co-perceive. Joint atten-
tion develops rapidly during the first year of life (Reddy 2003, 2005). Trevarthen
(1998, 2001) and Trevarthen and Aitken (2001) have eloquently described the
impressive development of the interpersonal interactions from primary through
secondary intersubjectivity during this period. What is entailed by this develop-
mental sequence is that perception is embedded in an intersubjective context,
where meaning is co-perceived and co-constructed.
In this developmental context imagination is coloured accordingly in two
ways. First, regarding its contents, imagination is populated by the reliving of the
most prominent and important facts of the infant’s experience. These are the inter-
actions with the important others. Stern (1985) maintains that after approximately
the second month, infants can memorize the structure of various forms of interac-
tions with other persons. He names them Representations of Interactions that have
been Generalized (RIGs), which incorporate and generate certain expectations of
action, feeling and sensation, about how an interaction may proceed. In a nearly
similar way, Bråten (2000) refers to E-motional Memory, the mnemonic retention
JB[v.20020404] Prn:13/02/2007; 14:47 F: AICR6812.tex / p.5 (272-313)
communicate and negotiate verbally the content and the form of pretence (Doyle
& Connolly 1989; Dunn & Dale 1984; Giffin 1984; Howe, Petrakos, & Rinaldi 1998;
Howes & Tonyan 1999; Miller & Garvey 1984).
The sharing of imagination depends and rests on various factors. We shall
list four contributing factors. First, imagination is intentional, but intentional-
ity is not a characteristic of consciousness or the mind. It is an attribute of the
embodied subject. The intentionality of the infant involves his whole corporeal
orientation and action towards an object in the environment. It carries then cer-
tain affordances that can be immediately perceived by a second person. Second,
through the course of development, a shared corpus of meaning is created and
consolidated in the context of intersubjective relations, in the form of scripts, rep-
resentations, or working models (Bowlby 1969; Nelson 1996; Stern 1985). These
co-created meanings are readily available and shared between those partners that
formed them. Third, imagination is immersed in feelings, both in the sense that it
triggers and is triggered by them, but also in the sense that its intended objects are
always intended in a certain way, with a certain value, quality and meaning. This
quality of imagination can be objectively perceived during its communication or
enactment, through the emotional presentations and the vitality affects that pro-
vide important information about its subjective meaning and quality. Fourth, a
first-person’s imagination can be understood by another person in an intersubjec-
tive context, if he is attuned to the first and tries to live the feelings, the thoughts
and the actions that are evoked in him by the sharing of the personal experience
of the first person (Bromberg 2001). We do not here refer to simulation, but to
the co-creation of the first-person’s imagination by two persons. For example in
Papastathopoulos’ (2004) research about the characteristics of children’s imagi-
nary companions, while interviewing the children about the characteristics of their
companions, some of them delayed to answer directly to some of the questions
(e.g. the colour of the imaginary companion’s eyes). The interviewer felt that the
children where at that moment thinking for the first time about the quality of those
characteristics. So, in this case we had an instance of co-creation of the character-
istics of the imaginary companion, by the child and the interviewer, which led to a
better understanding of the phenomenon by both parties. We doubt whether lone
simulation can recreate the quality of another’s subjective experience of complex
imaginary phenomena.
In summary so far, imagination, as we conceive it, entails these characteristics:
i. It is a faculty of the embodied person, directly related with perception, and has
as its major function the meaningful understanding and re-understanding of
experience.
JB[v.20020404] Prn:13/02/2007; 14:47 F: AICR6812.tex / p.7 (362-412)
ii. Its basic contents and meaning forms are derived from the structure and orga-
nization of the person’s actions in the environment and the interactions with
other persons.
iii. The development of imagination takes place inside the context of intersubjec-
tive interactions.
iv. Imagination and its contents can be communicated and shared in an intersub-
jective context.
The above hypotheses can be vigorously illustrated in the special case of children’s
imaginary companions. This is a very common phenomenon of childhood. From
children’s and their parents’ reports we know that the 41–67% of preschool and
school aged children have at least one imaginary companion at some point in time
(Gallino 1991; Pearson, Rouse, Doswell, Ainsworth, Dawson, Simms, Edwards, &
Faulconbridge 2001; Singer & Singer 1981; Taylor & Carlson 1997). While there
are various conceptions of this phenomenon, some common characteristics may
be captured in the following definition (Papastathopoulos 2004): An imaginary
companion is an imaginary person that is created or adopted by the child. It is an
invisible person, except in the case where the child has personified a real object,
which he nevertheless treats as having autonomous psychological existence. The
imaginary companion has an unusual air of reality for the child, although he rec-
ognizes its imaginary nature. In order for an imaginary person to be identified as
an imaginary companion, it should have a life span of several weeks and partake
in the child’s everyday life.
We hypothesize that the creation of an imaginary companion is an expected
and direct outcome of the intersubjective nature of development and the dialog-
ical structure of imagination. Its creation is guided by the same innate motives
that guide and support the communication and interaction between persons. The
imaginary companion is a person and has the functional equivalence in imagina-
tion of a real person. It has psychological and physical attributes, and is a being
with which the child can form various interpersonal relations. The form and the
quality of the child’s real interactions influence the characteristics of his interac-
tions with the imaginary companion and vice versa (Papastathopoulos 2004). In
order to evaluate these issues, we interviewed children with and without imaginary
companions and studied their playful interactions.
JB[v.20020404] Prn:13/02/2007; 14:47 F: AICR6812.tex / p.8 (412-460)
Method
Subjects. A total of 16 preschool aged girls took part in the study. They were
divided in two groups depending on whether they had or not imaginary compan-
ions. The first group consisted of 8 girls identified as having at least one imaginary
companion in the present time of the study. The second group consisted of 8 girls
identified as not having in the past and in the present an imaginary companion.
The mean age of the two groups was 5.4 years and 5.3 years respectively.
Results
Characteristics of the imaginary companions. All the girls had imaginary com-
panions with human form. The majority of the girls (62,5%, N = 5) had 1 imag-
inary companion, and the rest 2 imaginary companions (37,5%, N = 3). From
a total of 11 imaginary companions, the 7 (63,3%) had a name, while the rest 4
(36,4%) were anonymous. The majority of imaginary companions were females
(81,8%), and only two were defined as males (18,2%). Most of them were older
that the child (54,5%), and the rest were of the same (27,3%) or of a smaller
age (18,2%). They had blue eyes (72,2%) and blonde hair (45,5%). Most of the
imaginary companions were characterized by the girls as “good” (82%). One was
characterized as “so and so” and another one as “bad”.
When asked what they do with their imaginary companions, all of the girls
spontaneously responded that they play. So, the sum of the imaginary companions
functioned as playmates. The majority of the imaginary companions (82%) also
functioned as conversational partners. Only few of the girls (37,5%) reported that
their imaginary companions accompanied them to their everyday routines.
All the girls, when asked whether their imaginary companion really existed,
answered readily that they did not really exist. It is interesting that 2 girls spon-
taneously commented that they only “think of them” and another girl that her
imaginary companion existed only “in fantasy”.
JB[v.20020404] Prn:13/02/2007; 14:47 F: AICR6812.tex / p.9 (460-536)
Table 1. Descriptive statistics and paired-samples t values for girls speech scores during the
dyadic play sessions
Play and social preferences. Almost all of the girls that had imaginary companions
(87,5%, N = 7) reported that they preferred to play pretend games. On the con-
trary, only half of the girls without imaginary companions (50%, N = 4) referred
to pretend games as their favourite. All the girls from both groups, when asked
whether they preferred more to play alone or to play jointly with other children,
answered that they preferred to play with other children.
Girl’s speech during the play sessions. During the dyad’s play, the girls of the two
groups did not differ significantly on the total amount of speech (Table 1). How-
ever, the girls with imaginary companions directed their utterances significantly
more often to their play partner, than the girls without imaginary companions
(t = 3.550, df = 7, p < 0.01). That means that they used their speech more often to
communicate.
The two groups did not differ significantly on the verbal enactment of pre-
tence (t = 1.608, df = 7, p > 0.05). When the direction of the verbal enactment was
considered, a significant difference emerged. Girls with imaginary companions di-
rected their verbal enactment of pretence significantly more to their play partner,
than the girls without imaginary companions (t = 3.330, df = 7, p < 0.02). Their
verbal pretend enactment was more cooperative and social.
Negotiation of pretend play, which includes all the utterances that refer to the
discussion and determination of the pretend scenario, the identity of the objects,
the roles and the action plans, differentiated significantly the two group of girls.
The girls with imaginary companion engaged twice as more, than the other girls,
in negotiations of pretence (t = 3.383, df = 7, p < 0.02). One especially negotiation
strategy is of great importance, ulterior conversation. Giffin (1984) defines this as
the intentional proposal, by a player, of transformations in an already established
and enacted pretend scenario, without interrupting the ongoing enactment. Girls
with imaginary companion engaged significantly more in ulterior conversation,
that the girls without imaginary companion (t = 2.477, df = 7, p < 0.05).
JB[v.20020404] Prn:13/02/2007; 14:47 F: AICR6812.tex / p.10 (536-578)
Discussion
The findings of this study confirmed the suggested hypotheses. Imaginary com-
panions where described by the girls as persons. They had some recognizable phys-
ical characteristics (human form, sex, age, eye and hair colour), one psychological
attribute (moral quality) and certain relational roles (the role of a playmate and a
conversational partner). The moral quality of the imaginary companion is a very
important attribute, since it has always an interpersonal reference. Being “good”
is essential for close interpersonal relationships and especially those that are char-
acterized by mutuality and complementarity. Those two features are essential and
necessary in order to form interactions and relations based on conversation and
playfulness. The most important feature of a person, according to Hobson (2002),
is that a person is a being with which you can relate. The fact that all the imagi-
nary companions functioned as playmates and interlocutors constitutes the most
decisive evidence of their allowing to be characterized as persons.
Girls of both groups preferred mostly to play with other children than alone.
This might be taken as an indication that there is no difference between them re-
garding their motivation for interpersonal interaction and engagement. But the
results from the analysis of the dyadic play sessions draw a different picture. The
girls with imaginary companion used their language significantly more interper-
sonally, and especially during the enactment of pretence. This shows that they have
stronger and more elaborate motives for communication and sharing with other
children. They engaged in twice as much negotiations of pretence as did the second
group’s girls. The negotiation of pretence aims at the organization and establish-
ment of a joint and shared body of knowledge, meanings, rules and procedures
for the collaborative maintenance and experience of an imaginary reality (Doyle
& Connolly 1989; Giffin 1984; Howe et al. 1998).
The use of certain negotiation strategies reveals the communicational expert-
ness of the children with imaginary companion. As it was presented, they engaged
in significantly more ulterior conversations. The use of such a strategy demands
great caution and competency since the child, without interrupting the ongoing
enactment of pretence, must introduce a new transformation or action plan, which
was not established before.
These results point to the existence of a dialogical circuit that is composed
from two interrelated sub-circuits (Papastathopoulos 2004). The first sub-circuit
is formed in real life by the interaction of the child with other persons. The second
sub-circuit is formed in fantasy by the child and his imaginary companion. During
the interactions with real others the child practices and exercises its communica-
tional and sharing abilities and its understanding of mind. Those achievements,
together with the structure of conduct of the interactions, form and organize
generalized representations or internal working models that contain expectancies
JB[v.20020404] Prn:13/02/2007; 14:47 F: AICR6812.tex / p.11 (578-621)
about the way that another person is expected to act in communication and also
about the forms that its development might take. The expectancies of these in-
ternal working models are transferred and applied in the context of the relation
between the child and the imaginary companion. Now, in this second circuit, the
child can practice, simulate, evaluate and re-define a wide variety of themes that
concern interpersonal relations. What the child achieves in the context of fan-
tasy feeds back and modifies the internal working models, which guide in more
advanced ways future interactions with real others.
The working and the effects of this dialogical circuit can be more obviously
traced in the previous reported finding, that girls with imaginary companions en-
gaged in more interpersonally oriented verbal enactment of pretence. We discern
here the strong effect of their relation with the imaginary companion. This con-
text contains at least two very important elements, pretence and interaction. The
children pretend that they interact (talk or play) with their imaginary companion,
since as it was presented all of them recognized its unreality. So, the children in the
context of imagination exercise and practice at the same time on interaction and
pretence. What is achieved in imagination is subsequently reflected in interactional
pretend play with real children.
We have tried to show that imagination is not a secluded “castle” in the head,
that function apart from reality and especially intersubjective reality. It was pro-
posed instead that imagination is dialogically and intersubjectively constituted and
functioning. In order to portray this, we have chosen to refer especially on the phe-
nomenon of the children’s imaginary companions, whose presence is a profound
paradox for the older, individualistic theories of imagination (Papastathopoulos
2004).
Starting from this special case of child fantasy, we can now point at how de-
cisively our lives are immersed in fantasy, during our real lives. The imaginary
companion phenomenon is just one case of the imaginary persons or creatures
that populate our lives. From the mythological chimera or sphinx till Mickey
Mouse and Santa-Claus and from the TV-personas till our dialogues with deceased
loved persons, we enter into imaginary conversations, evaluations, disputes and so
on, with non-existing beings for vast amounts of time in our daily lives. These
imaginary relations and dialogues play an important role in the way we evaluate
in reality, in the decisions we take and the actions we perform. If in the name
of an objective science we deleted them from our research field, human reality
would not just be impoverished, but it would end up to be just the “psychologist’s
imagination”.
JB[v.20020404] Prn:13/02/2007; 14:47 F: AICR6812.tex / p.12 (621-724)
A new prologue for imagination should start from pointing out that it springs
from the same soil as with engagements with the real world: that is intersubjectiv-
ity. It shares its functions, contents and aims.
Note
. For a review of the recent findings on infant development see: Akhtar and Tomasello
(1998); Bråten (1998); Butterworth (1992, 1995); Harrist and Waugh (2002); Hobson (2002);
Jaffe, Beebe, Feldstein, Crown, and Jasnow (2001); Kugiumutzakis (1998); Meltzoff and Moore
(1998); Reddy (1999, 2003); Stern (1985); Trevarthen (1977, 1998, 2001); Trevarthen and Aitken
(2001); Trevarthen and Hubley (1978); Trevarthen, Murray, and Hubley (1981); Tronick (1989).
References
Akhtar, N., & Tomasello, M. (1998). “Intersubjectivity in early language and use.” In S.
Bråten (Ed.), Intersubjective Communication and Emotion in Early Ontogeny (pp. 316–335).
Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
Baldwin, J. M. (1913). History of Psychology: A Sketch and an Interpretation. London: Watts.
Bowlby, J. (1969). Attachment and Loss (Vol. 1 – Attachment). New York: Basic Books.
Bråten, S. (1998). “Introduction.” In S. Bråten (Ed.), Intersubjective Communication and Emotion
in Early Ontogeny (pp. 1–12). Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
Bråten, S. (2000). Modellmakt og altersentriske spedbarn. Essays on Dialogue in Infant & Adult.
Bergen: Sigma.
Brandt, S. A., & Stark, L. W. (1997). “Spontaneous eye movements during visual imagery reflect
the content of the visual scene.” Journal of Cognitive Neuroscience, 9, 27–38.
Bromberg, P. M. (2001). “The gorilla did it. Some thoughts on dissociation, the real, and the
really real.” Psychoanalytic Dialogues, 11, 385–404.
Butterworth, G. (1992). “The development of human consciousness.” Paper presented at the
symposium on “Consciousness” at the Royal Society of Edinburgh, November 1992.
Butterworth, G. (1995). “An ecological perspective on the origins of the self.” In J. L. Bermudez,
A. Marcel, & N. Eilan (Eds.), The Body and the Self (pp. 87–105). Cambridge, MA: MIT
Press.
Demarais, A. M., & Cohen, B. H. (1998). “Evidence for image-scanning eye movements during
transitive inference.” Biological Psychology, 4, 229–247.
Doyle, A. B., & Connolly, J. (1989). “Negotiation and enactment in social pretend play: Relations
to social acceptance and social cognition.” Early Childhood Research Quarterly, 4, 289–302.
Dunn, J., & Dale, N. (1984). “I a daddy: 2-year-olds’ collaboration in joint pretend with sibling
and with mother.” In I. Bretherton (Ed.), Symbolic Play (pp. 131–158). New York: Academic
Press.
Freud, S. (1908). “Creative writers and day-dreaming.” Standard Edition, Vol. IX (pp. 141–153).
London: Hogarth Press, 1981.
Gallino, T. G. (1991). “Bambini “con o senza” compagno immaginario.” Eta evolutina, 39, 33–44.
Gibson, J. J. (1979). The Ecological Approach to Visual Perception. Boston, MA: Houghton
Mifflin.
JB[v.20020404] Prn:13/02/2007; 14:47 F: AICR6812.tex / p.13 (724-844)
Papastathopoulos, E. (2004). Plasmata tou aera: i fantastiki sintrofi se koritsia prosxolikis ilikias.
Department of Philosophy and Social Studies, University of Crete. Unpublished Doctoral
Dissertation.
Pearson, D., Rouse, H., Doswell, S., Ainsworth, C., Dawson, O., Simms, K., Edwards, L.,
& Faulconbridge, J. (2001). “Prevalence of imaginary companions in a normal child
population.” Child: Care, Health and Development, 27, 13–22.
Piaget, J. (1951). Play, Dreams and Imitation in Childhood. London: Routledge & Kegan Paul
Ltd.
Reddy, V. (1999). “Prelinguistic communication.” In M. Barrett (Ed.), The Development of
Language (pp. 25–50). Hove: Psychology Press.
Reddy, V. (2003). “On being the object of attention: implications for self–other consciousness.”
TRENDS in Cognitive Sciences, 7, 397–402.
Reddy, V. (2005). “Before the “third element”: Understanding attention to the self.” In N.
Elian, J. Roessler, & P. McCormack (Eds.), Joint Attention: Perspectives from Philosophy and
Psychology. Oxford, England: Oxford University Press.
Singer, J. L., & Singer, D. G. (1981). Television, Imagination, and Aggression: A Study of
Preschoolers. Hillsdale: Lawrence Erlbaum.
Stern, D. (1983). “The early development of schemas of self, other, and “self with other”.” In J.
D. Lichtenberg & S. Kaplan (Eds.), Reflections on Self Psychology (pp. 49–84). Hillsdale, NJ:
The Analytic Press.
Stern, D. (1985). The Interpersonal World of the Infant. New York: Basic Books.
Taylor, M., & Carlson, S. M. (1997). “The relation between individual differences in fantasy and
theory of mind.” Child Development, 68, 436–455.
Thomas, N. J. T. (1997). “Imagery and the coherence of imagination: A critique of White.” The
Journal of Philosophical Research, 22, 95–127.
Thomas, N. J. T. (1999a). “Imagination.” In C. Eliasmith (Ed.), Dictionary of Philosophy of Mind
[WWW document] URL; http://www.artsci.wustl.edu/philos/MindDict/imagination.htm
Thomas, N. J. T. (1999b). “Are theories of imagery theories of imagination? An active perception
approach to conscious mental content.” Cognitive Science, 23, 207–245.
Trevarthen. C. (1977). “Descriptive analyses of infant communicative behavior.” In H. R.
Schaffer (Ed.), Studies in Mother-infant Interaction (pp. 227–270). London: Academic Press.
Trevarthen, C. (1998). “The concept and foundations of infant intersubjectivity.” In S.
Bråten (Ed.), Intersubjective Communication and Emotion in Early Ontogeny (pp. 15–46).
Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
Trevarthen, C. (2001). “Intrinsic motives for companionship in understanding: Their origin,
development, and significance for infant mental health”. Infant Mental Health Journal, 22,
95–131.
Trevarthen, C., & Aitken, K. J. (2001). “Infant intersubjectivity: Research, theory, and clinical
applications.” Journal of Child Psychology & Psychiatry & Allied Disciples, 42, 3–48.
Trevarthen, C., & Hubley, P. (1978). “Secondary intersubjectivity: Confidence, confiding and
acts of meaning in the first year.” In A. Lock (Ed.), Action, Gesture and Symbol: The
Emergence of Language (pp. 183–229). London: Academic Press.
Trevarthen, C., Murray, L., & Hubley, P. (1981). “Psychology of infants.” In J. A. Davis &
J. Dobbing (Eds.), Scientific Foundations of Pediatrics (pp. 211–274). London: William
Heinemann Medical Books Ltd.
Tronick, E. Z. (1989). “Emotions and emotional communication in infants.” American
Psychologist, 44, 112–126.
JB[v.20020404] Prn:13/02/2007; 14:47 F: AICR6812.tex / p.15 (964-977)
Wellman, H. M., & Estes, D. (1986). “Early understanding of mental entities: A reexamination
of childhood realism.” Child Development, 57, 910–923.
Woolley, J. D. (1995). “Young children’s understanding of fictional versus epistimic mental
representation: Imagination and belief.” Child Development, 66, 1011–1021.
Woolley, J. D. (1997). “Thinking about fantasy: Are children fundamentally different thinkers
and believers from adults?” Child Development, 68, 991–1011.
JB[v.20020404] Prn:13/02/2007; 14:48 F: AICR68P4.tex / p.1 (48-75)
chapter
Karsten Hundeide
University of Oslo
Introduction
In this chapter I will try to explicate the conditions that facilitate empathic care
and identification with the child on the one hand and those that obstruct this care
on the other. In the first part I present empathic care as a component embedded
in the normal communication between caregiver and child. This implies that care
is not seen as a one-sided contribution from the caregiver to the child, but as a
dialogical product where both contribute. In the second part of the chapter, I in-
troduce the concept of a “zone of intimacy” into which a child can be included and
cared for through empathic identification and sensitive availability of the caregiver
to the child’s needs. But a child can also be expelled from the zone of intimacy
with subsequent blockage of empathic identification, affective withdrawal leading
to neglect and possibly abuse. Through this theoretical metaphor, and offering
examples, inter alia from Angola, I try to describe three ways into the zone of in-
timacy. Finally I relate this perspective on empathic care with the newly emerging
field of “ethics of closeness” and Levinas’ ideas of the “appeal of the face” (Bauman
1996; Vetlesen 1999).
The questions
Recent research within early communication has shown that human care is not a
one-way process in which the care-giver provides and the child receives care, inde-
pendently of the child’s initiative and responses. Rather it seems that sensitive care
is a communicative or dialectic process in which the care-giver’s actions toward the
child is dependent on the expressive appeal of the child’s utterances, and conversely,
the child’s responses are dependent on the care-giver’s actions and on how they
JB[v.20020404] Prn:7/03/2007; 17:07 F: AICR6813.tex / p.2 (113-169)
are received and apprehended (Bråten 1996, 1998; Papousek & Papousek 1991;
Sameroff & Fiese 1990; Stern 1995; Trevarthen 1995). In this way the child (in this
case) becomes a co-creator of the care it receives – or more correctly: the care that
arises and is created between them. Thus, care cannot be reduced to static recipes
for “what one should do when. . .”. Nor can care be attributed to some compe-
tence or ability for caring in one person or the other. Rather it is the outcome of a
dialogical process that emerges between them (Hundeide 2002).
In order for such a caring process to take place, empathic sensitivity, and ability
to apprehend and recognize the quality and meaning of each other’s expressive
initiatives and responses is necessary. What do the child’s initiatives and utterances
express? What are the feelings and intentions behind a caring action?
According to one of the leading researchers in the field, Colwyn Trevarthen, this
facility for interpreting the expression of others appears to be a fundamental ability
existing in all of us. He writes:
. . . human perceivers have a remarkable sensitivity to beings with animacy and
intentionality. . .they can readily detect parameters of motivation in other sub-
jects’ behaviour, such as “emotion” of an action, or its “effort” and “vitality” . . .
But the ability to detect and observe qualitative differences in actions of others,
and thereby to perceive their motives, is but a small part of the capacity for imita-
tive identification, emotional empathy and reciprocal communication that all human
possess. Most importantly, a communicating subject is trying to make an effective
complementary reply, to enter into, and jointly regulate, a dyad of expressive “con-
versational” exchange with the Other . . . This is what Bråten (1988) means by the
term “dialogic closure” . . . (Trevarthen 1995: 8)
This demonstrates that what I have called the primary cycle of care1 is a dia-
logic response of a fundamental and immediate character, which can be seen both
in the committed care-giver’s spontaneous caring responses to the infant’s utter-
ances and expressive appeals and in the infant’s reactions to this response. This
means that there already exists a potential that can be activated and triggered so that
already existing communicative patterns (as a disposition) rather than learning a set
of new caring actions and communicative skills. This further implies that interven-
tion becomes a question of facilitating and sensitizing something that is natural and
that emerges spontaneously. Something the infant invites under normal circumstances
through its expressive initiatives (Hundeide 2000, 2001).
As an example of this, I had the opportunity some time ago to observe a young
sensitive mother’s relationship with her first born over a period of time. I was
struck by her absolute accessibility at all times, and her participation in everything
the child did. When the child was eating, she participated by opening her own
mouth when the child did. When I played with the child and made it laugh, the
mother participated all along, laughing with the child. When the child tried to
attain one goal or other, such as putting something into a box, the mother was
attentive and participating, and she made small movements as if to help the child
to carry out the activity. She was sensitively accessible throughout, participating in
everything the child did. Or to express it in other words; she is empathically iden-
tified with the child. The care-giver empathises with the child and participates in
both its assumed experiences and in its activities as an alternative, supporting self.
This is described in more detail in Bråten’s concept of “altercentric participation”
(see Bråten 1998, 2003; Hoffman 2000; Stern 2004).
In the following sections of this paper, I will return to how this primary cycle
of care can be reactivated in cases when it is obstructed and demobilised.
But not all interaction between care-giver and child has this immediate, empathic
and participatory quality. There are accounts of children being abused where this
empathic caring mechanism, that I have called empathic identification with the
child, does not seem to function or has become obstructed (or blocked). For ex-
ample; when children are placed in traditional institutions (Ryan & Tomas 1976),
when there is extreme poverty and the struggle for survival, when there is brutali-
sation and demoralization due to wartime violence, when there is high stress and
family-conflict involving alcohol and drug abuse, or when the child triggers neg-
ative images in the caregiver; images that may be associated with the caregiver’s
own problematic childhood (Fraiberg, Adelson, & Shapiro 1975; Pelzer 1995). In
the following section we will take a closer look at some examples from my work
JB[v.20020404] Prn:7/03/2007; 17:07 F: AICR6813.tex / p.4 (211-262)
with children in extreme situations, also from my social work in Angola and relate
them to conditions that seem to block empathic identification with the child.
In my experience there are two conditions that are particularly conducive to ne-
glect and failure of care, i.e. negative, stigmatizing definitions of the child and dis-
tancing in the relationship between care-giver and child. These often occur together
as part of a general pattern of rejection of the child and withdrawal of empathic
identification and care (Scheper-Hughes 1992).
Negative definitions in the relationship between parents and children often
develop in situations where there is a high level of family stress and where chil-
dren become a burden, both economically and emotionally. This is visible both in
environments with extreme poverty in developing countries, but also in wealthy
Western societies, where children may be experienced as a hindrance to the free ca-
reer development of the parents. Under such circumstances, negative, stigmatizing
and objectifying definitions of children, with subsequent emotional withdrawal
and distancing in relation to the children, may easily develop.
The anthropologist Scheper-Hughes (1992) gives a compelling example of
this from her studies in the poorest quarters of Recife in Brazil. In the district
where she was working, infant mortality was exceptionally high, close to fifty per-
cent, she discovered that poor mothers under such high survival pressure and
high infant mortality sometimes withdrew emotionally from these infants as if to
protect themselves from the ensuing emotional shocks and mourning when they
understood that their chances of survival were minimal.
A weak and physically vulnerable child, was labelled and defined by their
mother as “a child who wants to die” and a child that looked “ghost-like”, they
were also described as “small angels”. Such children had little chance of survival be-
cause of the maternal emotional withdrawal and the ensuing neglect. The negative
definition of the child as “ghost-like” started a self-fulfilling process of emotional and
physical neglect that usually ended in death. In some cases, it was said, the infants
were helped by their mothers to die – “that was what they wanted”... When the
researcher tried to help some of these children through special assistance, she was
warned that this would be wasted efforts, because sooner or later these children
would die, that was their destiny and that was what they wanted (Scheper-Hughes
1992).
When infant mortality is so high that the mother unconsciously tries to pro-
tect herself by withdrawing her emotional attachment to the child it is like an
unconscious calculus of risk and emotional investment, and if the conclusion is
withdrawal, the whole caring mechanism is at risk and the chances that the nega-
tive assessment of the infant will be self-fulfilling, is considerably increased. Under
JB[v.20020404] Prn:7/03/2007; 17:07 F: AICR6813.tex / p.5 (262-322)
In this way a self-fulfilling process was initiated on the basis of the mothers’ nega-
tive diagnosis or apprehension of the child. According to the anthropologist, “there
was no expression of great joy nor of sorrow”; at the child’s funeral, “the infant was
seldom even the focus of the conversation at all ...” (Scheper-Hughes 1992: 418).
It is nonetheless misguiding to interpret this as a general deficiency of empa-
thy and caring ability in these impoverished mothers, because it was at the same
time evident that the same mothers were sensitive and caring towards the other
siblings that showed signs of vitality and robustness.2 Such a selective emotional
withdrawal can therefore be understood as a strategic reaction of self- protection
with the purpose of avoiding repeated experiences of loss and depression following
the death of weak and physically vulnerable children to whom they were attached.
Such reactions may be interpreted as adaptive strategies that emerge under difficult
life circumstances where survival, both physical and psychological, has become a
challenge (see also LeVine et al. 1988).
In connection with social work directed towards vulnerable children in ex-
treme situations I have witnessed similar examples of the stigmatisation of chil-
dren in relation to local superstition of possession and bewitchment. In the rural
districts of Angola there is a prevailing belief that if a child is divergent for one
reason or another – it may be anything from physical defects and impairment,
to psychological handicaps following traumatic experiences of war – this devia-
tion is explained as result of bewitchment of the child and possession by demons.
An evil spirit is thought to have entered the child and it is this spirit that creates
aberrations in appearance or behaviour (Hundeide & Egebjerg 2003). As a con-
sequence of this diagnosis/definition (that was very often performed by the local
witch doctor) these children are rejected by their families, both physically and psy-
chologically. In the worst cases they are expelled from their homes and left to beg
in the streets for survival.3
The most extreme example I have witnessed in this context is a group of im-
poverished orphans in North-Angola. They had been “diagnosed” (or defined) as
being possessed by demons after consultation with the local witch doctor. These
children were blamed for most of the local accidents and misfortunes, from deaths
of people to crop failure and drought. They became public scapegoats, thus pro-
viding an explanation for the adversity experienced by the local society. As a
consequence they were usually expelled from their homes, ending up in treatment
centres owned by the same witch doctor that had diagnosed them. Here they were
subject to different forms of torture or exorcisms in order to “drive out Satan”. For
JB[v.20020404] Prn:7/03/2007; 17:07 F: AICR6813.tex / p.6 (322-376)
example, they had chilli-pepper applied to their eyes, which then became swollen
and red, so that they acquired the look of monsters. They were also subjected to
painful cleansing rituals in which they were beaten and tormented. This went on
for several months. When we were given the opportunity to visit this “institution”
following one such treatment, the children were already totally subdued, subju-
gated and traumatised. Even after the treatment was over, the stigmas persisted
which again led to the unwillingness on the part of their parents to take the chil-
dren back. Therefore most of them ended up as workers on the farm of the witch
doctor who had originally “diagnosed” them.
An interesting point in this context is that the children were themselves con-
vinced of their own possession, and they told the most incredible stories about
what they could do at night, all corresponding to the local beliefs about posses-
sion. In other words, the children dramatised the expectations, the “diagnosis”
and the conceptions they were attributed. It became a part of their understanding
of themselves and their behaviour.4
More generally, one can say that we approach other people according to our
definitions of them. We continuously interpret and attribute characteristics to our
fellow human beings, and behave towards them accordingly – thus initiating a
process that can easily become a self-fulfilling process.5
Extreme physical abuse and torture usually involve objectifying and demonising
definitions of the victim. “Traitor” is one such definition that appears to legitimize
abuse and torture. Working with child and teenage soldiers in Angola, we learned
about extreme abuse in this category.6 These youngsters had been kidnapped as
children and re-socialised as guerrilla soldiers in the UNITA. The soldiers were
trained according to the principle of “the son of a snake is also a snake”, and this
implied that entire family and all relatives were killed if one of the family members
were accused of treason. They were also trained in different torture techniques to
be used on alleged traitors. In an area on the border of Namibia a group of teenage
soldiers participated in the execution of a group of people accused of treason. This
was perpetrated by having the victims themselves collect wood for a pyre on which
they were subsequently burned alive. These teenage soldiers were highly regarded
among the officers because they were “totally loyal, they carried out orders and
killed without hesitation”.
An interview with a young female soldier from the war in Sierra Leone gives a
certain impression of what they had been through:
JB[v.20020404] Prn:7/03/2007; 17:07 F: AICR6813.tex / p.7 (376-415)
These are of course extreme cases, but they contain some of the legitimising com-
ponents one finds with lesser abuse as well.
– An objectification, and often a demonising definition of the victim who is seen as
morally inferior, non-human, traitor and therefore deserves to be abused.7
– That they were following orders – and if they did not comply, they would be killed
themselves.8
– That this was in fact a noble and necessary action performed in the service of their
country.
– These legitimising arguments seem to absolve the perpetrators from a feeling of
responsibility, guilt and awareness for their inhuman actions.
For the child soldiers, these ideological legitimations became an important part
of their indoctrination and preparation for their role as “under-aged soldier”9
(Bracken & Petty 1998). “We killed traitors because we were fighting for our coun-
try” . . .10 Many of these youngsters sustained serious psychological problems when
they were subsequently to be integrated into civil society after having lived for years
in brutalizing war conditions with totally different values (Hundeide 2003b).
CULTURAL MODELS OF
CONCEPTION OF CHILD
ABUSE/NEGLECT GOOD CARE
Caregiver’s definition of the child
OUTSIDE THE
ZONE
INSIDE THE ZONE
Stigma – negative Seeing the child as a “person”
conception of with tender qualities and human needs
the child (p) Inclusion P
Figure 1. A model of human care in the zone of intimacy, with indicated ways into the
zone and modes of being excluded or kept outside the zone
In the worst cases these inmates of such institutions live in a dehumanised world
in which they are being seen and treated as objects; sometimes referred to as num-
bers with uniforms to emphasise that they are not unique persons, but outsiders,
more like objects. This is dehumanization and de-individualization that invites
empathic withdrawal, objectification and abuse. Certainly not all institutions are
like this.
JB[v.20020404] Prn:7/03/2007; 17:07 F: AICR6813.tex / p.11 (560-620)
I will deal with each of these ways drawing upon some case studies from our work
in Angola.
Inclusion into the zone through face-to-face and gaze contact (p) → P
Face-to-face contact is one of the ways into the zone of intimacy and empathic
identification with the child. Face-to-face contact will also provide eye contact
and the reciprocal exchange of facial expressions and speech. A strong and direct
emotional experience can create sensitivity and openness to the child’s attitude,
or the “victim’s” “appeal of the face” is brought to bear, as Levinas and the ethics
of closeness has described it (Vetlesen 1998). There is a body of literature on the
importance of the face and gaze in the establishment of emotional contact that I
am unable to discuss here (Ekman & Friesen 1975; Vanderberg 1999; Oppenheim
et al. 2003).
JB[v.20020404] Prn:7/03/2007; 17:07 F: AICR6813.tex / p.12 (620-668)
the zone of intimacy, (P → (p)). In the example with the father who could not ac-
cept his child, but who experienced an emotional breakthrough in contact, we see
the opposite. Through gaze and the experience of the infant’s expressive appeal,
the father gained a spontaneous emotional contact with the child, which in turn
initiated empathic identification with the child – “my child”. From being ignored
and overlooked, the child was included in the zone of intimacy and care, ((p) →
P). From being a non-person, the child has become a person for whom the fa-
ther feels protective, i.e. there has been a movement from (p) to P. Furthermore,
these two examples illustrate two important ways into the zone of intimacy, i.e. the
importance of positive definitions of the child, and the importance of expressive
exchange through face-to-face contact and gaze contact. Body contact is also an
important way into the zone of intimacy as we shall see in the next section.
Inclusion in the zone of intimacy through sensitive touch and bodily contact
In the ICDP’s work with orphans and neglected children in different parts of the
world, we have observed the importance of bodily contact and affectionate touch-
ing when treating children who have been subject to affective deprivation and
traumatisation. I will discuss two examples from Angola.
We observed a blind girl in an institution for children with multiple hand-
icaps. When she arrived at the institution she was so weak and undernourished
that she could hardly walk. After a period of time with supplementary feeding
and care her condition improved, and this was when we discovered that she was
almost blind. This made communication with her very difficult (the signals for
mutuality were ambiguous), and when we met her, she appeared to ignore human
contact while the physical care was seen to. Through sensitive physical communi-
cation it was possible to achieve contact with her again. We have video recordings
of the emerging interaction between the girl and one of our female “facilitators”,
who first approaches the girl by taking her hand, holding it and gently caressing
the hand with sensitive touch. We can see how this leads to a change in the girl’s
expression: she leans back, relaxes, smiles contentedly and appears to enjoy this
intimate contact. The facilitator gradually expands the physical contact by first
touching the girl’s lips and then her cheeks with affectionate stroking. Finally, she
puts her arms around the girl and holds her closely. The girl responds by putting
her hands around the supervisor’s neck and clinging to her as if a crucial need in
her is satisfied. While the supervisor holds her like this, she speaks into the girl’s
ear, repeating her name and guiding her hands towards her eyes, nose, mouth and
ears while repeating the girl’s name and the names of the body parts she is touch-
ing. In this way they come to understand one another and by speaking about the
same things, a space for inter-subjective sharing was created between them. All the
JB[v.20020404] Prn:7/03/2007; 17:07 F: AICR6813.tex / p.14 (705-757)
time the facilitator holds the girl tightly to herself, and there is a contented smile
on the girl’s lips. The ice has been broken and an intimate contact is in the process
of developing between them.
Through sensitive physical contact, touching and intimate dialogue it was pos-
sible to bring the girl into the zone of intimacy – or more aptly; they included each
other mutually in their own zones of intimacy.
Sensitive, affectionate touching that leads to close embracing is the prototype
of closeness and mutual love, whether in relation to an infant or a partner in an
adult love relationship. In a situation of sorrow, loss, neglect and despair, such
contact can often release repressed feelings and tears, which may relieve pressure
and provide a considerable sense of comfort and security. Nonetheless, this is a
powerful form of intervention and contact, and it must be applied with sensitivity
and respect for the other person’s limits – more as a spontaneous response to the
other’s expression and appeal. Because the danger of infringement is of course
great in such situations and in relation to persons with strong dependency needs.
Therefore, this method must be used with prudence and follow-up in order to
prevent new disappointments and new betrayals.
Another way into the zone is by first establishing contact by imitating the child’s
gestures and initiatives, and then gradually developing this into communication
and participation in the child’s activities. This is a way of responding by follow-
ing the child’s initiative. As long as a child produces expressive or goal oriented
initiatives and actions, it is always possible to start a simple communicative cycle
by imitating and complementing the child’s actions, following the child’s initiative
and thus initiate a cycle of turn-taking.
The most well known example in this regard comes from Hunt’s intervention
study in Iran. In addition to instructing the care-givers to express an affectionate
attitude towards the children, he particularly asked them to imitate the children’s
gestures and expressions so that a simple communicative cycle could begin. It was
this simple, pragmatic instruction that turned out to have a very strong positive
effect on the orphans subsequent development when they were compared with a
control group only receiving so-called responsive toys, in line with Piaget’s theory
on the important role of self initiated actions (Hunt 1982).
In our work in Angola, the ICDP-team has occasionally employed the same
technique, particularly in cases where there have been contact difficulties. In one
case, one of our facilitators was contacted by a father who was an alcoholic and
unable to take care of his two and a half year old daughter after his wife died. At
JB[v.20020404] Prn:7/03/2007; 17:07 F: AICR6813.tex / p.15 (757-808)
that time the girl functioned apparently normally for age and she was able to say a
few words. Due to her father’s condition she was placed in a very poor foster home
with a foster mother who was only interested in the financial benefits of keeping
the child, thus subjecting her to extreme neglect.
The child was placed in a small room where she spent the next two years with-
out any form of human contact. There was a little window high up on one wall, but
no toilet. The room was never cleaned, food was thrown in once a day, and the girl
lived in her own dirt for two years. When this state of affairs was discovered, one
of our facilitators intervened and got the child out of the prison. At this time, the
child could no longer walk properly, but crawled about on the floor making sounds
like an animal. She had rat bites all over her body. It was impossible to estab-
lish eye-contact with her or gain contact through face-to-face expressive exchange.
She did not respond to normal communicative expressive signals, and her face
was closed and devoid of expression. She avoided eye contact and she constantly
moved restlessly around in the room. The only thing that caught her attention was
when she was given food, at which she produced a specific sound – something like
“tchee-tchee”. While this went on it was possible to focus her attention on the food
for a short time.
When one of our facilitators started working with this girl she was more than
four years old. The facilitators was deeply committed to help this girl and in line
with the ICDP approach she started by looking for expressive signals, initiatives
and actions that she could relate to and imitate in order to start a communicative
cycle (Hundeide 1991). In the beginning, these signals were the same sounds that
she made in connection with feeding. After a period of time, she was able to distin-
guish more signals from the child, and began to use them systematically in relation
to food, washing, visits to the toilet and play. Little by little, a rudimentary commu-
nicative system based on imitative signs and sounds began to develop between them
that seemed to work well in their practical daily lives. The girl also began to show
signs of emotional attachment to the supervisor, showing joy when she visited her,
and distress when she left. Gradually, her facial expression also changed, becom-
ing more lively and expressive and it as also possible to obtain eye contact with
her. Slowly she began to reciprocate the facilitator’s expressive initiatives with sim-
ilar expressive utterances, such as smiles and bodily contact, for example tickling.
In time she was also able to focus her attention on one activity over a somewhat
longer period of time.
When I saw her at a later point in time it was possible to establish eye con-
tact and exchange mutual expressive utterances; smiles and sounds, in the same
way as one would communicate with an infant. She could walk, albeit a little un-
steadily, and she showed a particular trust in her brother, and liked to sit on his
lap. Evidently, there was a normalisation and humanisation process under way.
This process started through sensitive communicative contact with another per-
JB[v.20020404] Prn:7/03/2007; 17:07 F: AICR6813.tex / p.16 (808-855)
son, a facilitator, who managed to establish contact and communication with her
through imitation of her accessible gestures and expressive utterances. This is where
the development begins. At this level, one must begin where the child is, with the
utterances and expressive initiative that are accessible.
In this account I have placed the main emphasis on what I have called the primary
care cycle. This implies an assumption that caring has its roots in a pre-verbal
and pre-theoretical disposition that is apparent in the infant immediately after
birth. In more general terms, one can say with Trevarthen that there appears to be
a “dynamic “together-with-the-other-consciousness” that comes first and that is
sustained throughout our lives in our deepest moral core”. He further elaborates
this in the following quote:
The human consciousness seems to emerge from a completely non-rational, non-
verbal, concept-less and totally non-theoretical potential for participation and
communication with other persons that one can see first in infants.
(Trevarthen 1995: 8)
This is a radical claim that goes against the traditional view of how the human
consciousness (the mind) is formed as a result of linguistic socialisation. Accord-
ing to the new perspective, it is rather a primary inter-subjectivity, formed before
language, that constitutes the basis for how further socialisation evolves (Bråten
1998; Stern 1985; Trevarthen 1989).
Quite surprisingly, this radical viewpoint appears to accord with French
philosopher Levinas and his idea about the “first philosophy” in which ethical re-
sponsibility for the other through the direct “appeal of the face” itself comprises
the basis for our subjectivity. In Levinas’ words:
When the other looks at me, I am responsible for him without expecting reci-
procity on his part ... responsibility for the other is the crucial, primary and
fundamental structure in our subjectivity.
the ethics of closeness, He mentions the following convergences between the two
positions:
– The view on the primary moral relation as “the first philosophy”.
– The significance of the appeal of the face and expressive closeness as funda-
mental to the development of responsibility for fellow human beings.
– The dangers of remote relationships which deprive human beings of the direct
experience of the other’s face and thus the feeling of direct responsibility.
– The dangers inherent in the abstracted and “totalizing gaze” of the bureau-
crat – the glance from a distant and abstract position.
– The dangers of negative definitions that can legitimise dehumanisation and in-
fringement, freeing the perpetrator from the feeling of responsibility for fellow
human beings.
In line with this viewpoint, the care of others is not only something we do for
others, but something we do in order to recreate our own human subjectivity –
our deepest moral core.
Acknowledgement
I am indebted to Pedro and Irina Mendes for case stories and discussions about
the content of this paper.
Notes
. Not all caring has its basis in the primary care cycle, however. There are forms of caring
adapted to older children and adults that naturally require a more reflective approach, mirroring
society’s varying conventions and values. This secondary caring does not have the same immedi-
ate and spontaneous qualities as the primary caring cycle, rather it represents the more reflected
humanitarian values and principles of human rights that are a part of our culture (Berger &
Luckman 1967; Bråten 2003; Skoe 1998).
. Instead of interpreting such behaviour as indications of “deficient caring competence in the
mother”, the focus is in this paper changed from the mother’s capacities to the way she defines
her children – and this is to a large extent not only a personal competence, but a situational,
interactive and cultural affordance.
. In social sense these children serve as scapegoats being held responsible for any negative
occurrence within the family or in the local community, thus functioning as scapegoats for
uncontrollable misfortunes in the community – in a similar way as the female witches of the
Middle Ages who were burnt on pyres.
. This appears like a hidden contract between themselves and the healer about who they are,
what their symptoms and powers are, and how they can be healed (Hundeide 2003b, c).
JB[v.20020404] Prn:7/03/2007; 17:07 F: AICR6813.tex / p.18 (916-991)
. But the definitions that we employ in this process of reciprocal definitions are also part of a
cultural repertoire of personality typifications which we appropriate as we are socialized into a
community, and this may also include recipes for healing which may not always coincide with
Western conceptions of therapy, as the examples above indicate.
. “We” implies collaborators inside ICDP, particularly Pedro and Irina Mendes, Milu and
Santana.
. It is important to note that this type of legitimising and stigmatisation also occurs in viola-
tions of human rights and UN conventions in the pursuit of what are called “terrorists” like the
abuse of Iraqi prisoners in the Abu Ghraib Prison. One can also find comparable justifications
in violence prone racist gangs, such as new Nazis (Bjørgo 1997; Hundeide 2003a, b).
. These experiences were a part of the teenage soldiers’ training: in some cases they were in-
structed to kill prisoners – in some cases members of their own families – while the others were
watching. If they were unable to comply with the orders or showed signs of weakness in crying or
clutching, they were themselves shot in front of the other recruits. This is the terrorism that led
to blind obedience to “the sergeant”, who often exploited them with extreme cruelty (Bracken &
Petty 1998; Hundeide 2003b).
. “Under-aged soldiers” is now the politically correct term as child soldiers is starting to have
a stigmatising effect due to the violence associated with this term.
. When some of these child soldiers were interviewed individually about their future life as-
pirations, some of them said they would become teachers, and when we asked why, many of
them replied “In order to help my country!”. This seems to indicate that collective national
identifications were dominant even in their personal motivation and self-construction.
. The concept of “person” as opposed to a non-person, a thing, has been used in social science
to indicate the crucial importance of labelling, stigmatisation and negative definitions when vio-
lence, terror, torture, massacres and crimes against humanity are committed (see contributions
by Buber, by Bauman, by Bråten, by Christie, and by Smedslund). The concept of “person” is
not necessarily limited to human beings; a loved animal, a pet, a dog or a whale, can become the
object for person-attributions, which implies that they are perceived as having similar sensitiv-
ity to pain. suffering and humiliation and also similar needs for being secure, included, loved
and respected – as we ourselves have. . . They are, in other words, co-human beings. This makes
empathic identification possible.
. In a similar vein, Daniel Stern talks about the “the intersubjective matrix” which implies
that our mental life, our personal feelings and thoughts are “cocreated through dialogues with
other minds” (Stern 2003: 77).
. According to Bauman (1996), this was one of the things the Nazis tried to prevent. Face-to-
face contact with “the Jew next door” could be the basis of inclusion into the zone with sympathy
and empathic identification.
. In his recent book The Present Moment in Psychotherapy and Everyday Life Daniel Stern
(2004, cf. also this volume (2)) points out the significance of short moments of intense con-
tact “. . . in which both partners create and undergo a joint experience. . . This resonant ex-
perience enlarges the intersubjective field between them and opens up new possibilities for
exploration. . .” This is exactly what happened in the example described above about the father
and his Down Syndrome child. The intense moment of eye-to-eye contact became a turning
point in their relationship.
JB[v.20020404] Prn:7/03/2007; 17:07 F: AICR6813.tex / p.19 (991-1112)
References
chapter
Andrea Cabassi
Child Psychiatric Service, Parma
Introduction
On destiny
Rainer Maria Rilke (1929), in his paper “Briefe an einen jungen Dichter”, writes to
a young Kappus who wants to become poet and advises him of the way to pursue
such a path. Commenting on destiny, Rilke claims that destiny is inside and not
on our outside. If we look in the deepest parts of ourselves we shall find that we
are authors of our destiny.
Common sense entertains a different view of the relationship between man
and destiny. In common sense destiny is something on the outside. It is inescapable
and connected with the position and the movement of stars and planets; astrology
is the dark side of destiny.
JB[v.20020404] Prn:13/02/2007; 14:53 F: AICR6814.tex / p.2 (110-158)
These reflections about the “inside” or “outside” with regard to destiny are
very important for the development of our topic, especially when we speak about
destinies repeating themselves in families. In such cases it seems that the life des-
tiny of one member repeats itself without variation in another member of the
following generation and it seems impossible to make a break in this repetition.
We can see this very well in multiproblems families.
The “common sense” way of thinking about this tends to be totally determin-
istic: it sees only the outside and thinks this repetition is like a curse on the family,
perhaps a deserving curse, a curse against which it is not possible to do anything,
a curse that the family only has to suffer. According to common sense nothing can
break this.
This curse seems to develop itself in a homogeneous and empty time as it is
described by Walter Benjamin (1974) in his thesis about history: a quantitative
time in which everything comes back without change and differences, a time in
which destiny seems to come from outside, from a cursed position of stars and
planets that persecute families. It seems like an eternal present repeating itself,
continuously. In our time, many families show the same pathology across three
generations, at least. When we work with this kind of families we can ask for our-
selves what destiny entails and whether it is an inside or outside matter. Which are
the mechanisms presiding, often invisibly, over repetition? And we can make the
invisible visible? If we reflect on this and try to answer such questions, inevitably,
concepts about destiny cross concepts of transgenerational and intergenerational
transmission.
Destinies repeating themselves in multiproblems families can be accounted
for in terms of Bråten’s and Stern’s theories. They have the great merit to give cues
of lecture and indications for interruption of repetition in psychotherapy or in
counselling when there is a perturbing infant-parents relationship. Before turning
to this let me present a concept that I have recently elaborated with my colleague
and family therapist, Maria Teresa Zini (2004): that of ‘family disseminate archives’.
From the first days of life the infant enters into a relationship with the home, with
its typical atmosphere. Home, as Winnicott (1986) asserts, is where we start from.
Maria Teresa Zini and I define family disseminate archives in terms of this home
environment.
The word archive derives from the ancient Greek term arché. Arché has a dou-
ble meaning: the first is that of beginning, the second is that of command. For
ancient Greeks, archive is the place where things begin but also the place where
authority exerts its power. Archeion was the residence where the supreme magis-
JB[v.20020404] Prn:13/02/2007; 14:53 F: AICR6814.tex / p.3 (158-218)
trates, the arcontes, lived. They oversaw and interpreted documents. They had the
power to put them in order and to be their hermeneuts. Home is an archive and
arcontes are its inhabitants. In this archive we can find family documents, papers,
objects like ornaments, linen chests, family album of photos, and the characteristic
atmosphere of the home.
The term disseminate means that the archive can be disseminated everywhere:
any room, any corner, any object, all the furniture, the home smell too, can be
places containing documents or a family memory. The disseminate archives are
of family because they concern family, its history, its destiny, its memory across
generations.
Family disseminate archives are composed of these six elements, then: (i)
home atmosphere, (ii) infant-parents relationships, (iii) objects, (iv) family nar-
ratives, (v) name, and (vi) documents.
The first element may seem to be virtual but it is not. I refer to home atmo-
sphere. Home atmosphere is home smell, the smell of each room, the light or the
darkness in the corners of each room, the colours, the dust, the half-light plays,
the atmosphere created by parents like serenity, calmness or tension. Infant per-
ceives everything by virtue of amodal perception and the mode of felt immediacy.
But about this topic I will speak later on.
The second element is infant-parents relationship. It is not possible to divorce
the first element from the second one because the most important scene where
infant-parents relationship is played out is the home and this relationship is strictly
connected with atmosphere and vice versa.
The third element is made up by objects; at home every room is full of all
kinds of objects: ornaments, pictures, photos hanging on the wall, linen chests,
cupboards, antiques tables, toys. . . and each of them can transmit a family story
from one generation to another. Many of these objects can have an affective value
for parents when, above all, they are objects belonging to their own parents or
ancestors. Ancestors, often, have handed down some objects, now in the home.
Poets well know that furniture has a story and conveys a family story. For example,
in his poetry Rimbaud addresses the buffet who knows the family stories: “– O
buffet du vieux temps, tu sais bien des histoires,/ Et tu voudrais conter tes contes, et tu
bruis/ Quand s’ouvrent lentement tes grands portes noires” Rimbaud (2002: 74).
The fourth element is constituted by family narratives. In the first phase of
life the infant hears sounds and speech without understanding the meaning of
words. But the baby can perceive tunes, voices, rhythms, serenity or tension. When
beginning to understand words and with the appearance of speech, the infant gets
the first sense of family narratives, and which may prevail throughout the lifetime.
The fifth element is, in part, linked with parents and ancestors, across age,
and begins before the birth: the name. In our culture name can be the name of
an ancestor or the name of a grandparent. The name reflects and hides parents’
JB[v.20020404] Prn:13/02/2007; 14:53 F: AICR6814.tex / p.4 (218-263)
expectations and their desires. A relative can be important because he or she has
had a great affective value, or because he or she has made something of importance
for the family, and the narrative of this deed has been handed down from one
generation to another. The child may feel to be under obligation to repeat the same
deed, or may come to feel this task to be too heavy to escape. It is not always like
this, but it may become a burden when the expectations are shared by each family
member and when these expectations and desires are very powerful. In the case
in which the name of the child is the same as that of a dead brother, this archive
element is like it is written on the body of the child. Often this means that the
parents have not been able to do the work of mourning.
The sixth element, finally, are made up by documents: all kind of documents,
wills, papers containing fragments of family story, often family secrets. These doc-
uments can be contained in linen chests, drawers, chest of drawers, and cupboards.
When the child becomes older, if he or she has felt an atmosphere of secret, sensed
that there is something hidden in the parents’ narratives, the child may turn into a
detective in search of secrets to disclose.
Family disseminate archives in light of poetry and Bråten’s and Stern’s theories
In this paragraph I will consider, above all, the elements of family disseminate
archives linked with the pre-verbal world of the infant.
Let me first consider Stern’s (1985) cue concept of amodal perception. Infants’
perceptive channels, in the first month of life, do not have a particular special-
ization. This entails a great richness because the infant can translate stimuli from
one sense to another, across sense modalities. The infant can, as it were, see taste,
hear colours, translate atmosphere around him. He can feel the parents’ tension,
the parents’ serenity, and translate them into movements and actions. In this way
it is possible to consider amodal perception as a forerunner of metaphor, a pro-
tometaphor, and to see the infant as a poet. Besides, poets well know amodal
perception.
Baudelaire writes in “Correspondences” about the long echoes of the smell and
colours that have been sensed and linked: “Comme de longs échos qui de loin se
confondent/ Dans une ténebreuse et profonde unitè,/ Vaste comme la nuit et comme
la clarté, les parfums, les couleurs et le sons se répondent” (Baudelaire 1961: 11).
This unity, where each thing answers to another, where everything corre-
sponds with everything and can be translated from one sense to the other, is the
unity of amodal perception that permits one to translate colours into sounds, scent
into sounds and colours etc.
Rimbaud (2002: 114) says in “Voyelles”: “A noir, E blanc, I rouge, U vert, O bleu
. . .” In this poem there is correspondence between each vowel and each colour:
A for black, B for white, I for red etc. This is another manner of reactivating
JB[v.20020404] Prn:13/02/2007; 14:53 F: AICR6814.tex / p.5 (263-324)
supramodal perception. The poet is like an infant and the infant is like a poet
(while children with autism and psychotic children when older find it very difficult
to use metaphor).
Marcel Proust (1989) uses and talks about the sense of smell in his “Recherche”.
The reactivation of sense of smell and the taste of the famous “madeleine” brings
him to remember and reconnect his life story. We, apparently, have lost this link
between sense of smell and some fragments of our life. But this connection lies
in the deepest part of our memory, of ourselves and – on particular occasions –
re-emerges because amodal perception continues to work also in the quiet. And in
these moments we find again the time that we believed to have forgotten.
Amodal perception and the mode of felt immediacy permit an entry into this
first element of family disseminate archives. Bråten defines felt immediacy as
the mode of directly perceiving own or other’s body movements in a presentational
immediacy, as in proprioception and alteroception, differing from perception in re-
presentational mediacy by symbolic and conceptual distinctions.
(Bråten 2000: 299–300)
The mode of felt immediacy permits one not only to perceive own or other’s move-
ments in a presentational immediacy, but also to enter in a world of smell, colours,
sounds because it is a-representational, a-symbolic, and infant, in this phase, feels
without representations, without making use of symbolization, the changes of
atmosphere, of smells, of light, any little change of movement at home.
We have distinguished infant-parents relationship as another important el-
ement of family disseminate archives. It cannot be divorced from atmosphere
because it determines it and vice versa. Here, I shall refer to Stern’s pertinent dis-
tinctions of affect attunement (1985) and protonarrative envelopes (1995b), and
then take into consideration Bråten’s (1998, 2000) simulation model and cue
concepts of altercentric participation and e-motional memory.
By virtue of amodal perception and the mode of felt immediacy, the relation-
ship between mother and infant is like a dance, where they follow the “music”,
the tune. Infant can answer to a movement of mother with a babble or vice versa.
When there is music in these sounds and movements, when tunes are synchro-
nised, we have affect attunement. When there are problems the tune, the “right
music”, is broken.
Andrea Zanzotto, one of the most important Italian and European poets, de-
scribes the similarity relation of poet and infant in one of his essays (2001), and
in his poetry he has anticipated Lacan’s (2002) theories. In his poetry Zanzotto
works from (pre)speech, using babble, interjection, onomatopeia, and the mode of
nursery rhyme. He defines this as “motherhood speech”. Babble, right tunes, ono-
matopeia, and interjection make up the mode of communication between mother
and infant, the way of communicating in the world, a mode which, when we are
JB[v.20020404] Prn:13/02/2007; 14:53 F: AICR6814.tex / p.6 (324-380)
adult, we do not use but which lies in our memory. This motherhood speech is a
speech in which what is understood is the signifier and not the meaning. Signifier
is tune; it is the music that the infant, in the preverbal world, can understand by
virtue of amodal perception and the mode of felt immediacy. In affect attunement,
there is an exchange among signifiers. We may regard all the pre-verbal communi-
cation between infant and parent, all the music and the dance of affect attunement,
to be under the sign of signifier.
Besides, the growing of intensity of tune, the maximum of attunement, and
then its descent, is the “music” that accompanies the infant-parent relationship.
This “music” is the first plot that the infant learns to know. It is the forerunner of
a narrative world in which we will be plunged for all our lifetime. This first plot is
what Stern has termed protonarrative envelopes, and that which Andrea Zanzotto
has well understood when he considers the motherhood speech, the protodialogue
between mother and infant as an exchange of signifiers.
Such affect attunement in parent-infant interplay entails other-centred partic-
ipation and leaves or evokes in the participants e-motional memory of a wordless
kind, inviting re-enactment.
These are the conceptual terms by which Bråten distinguish such phenom-
ena, which I think are fundamental: He has introduced the term “altercentric” to
characterize “other-centered perception and mirroring of movements which he
has identified in human infants in face-to-face situations, for example when they
reciprocate the spoon-feeding to which they have been subjected, reflecting the
opposite of egocentric perception of caretaker’s feeding” (Bråten 2000b: 297). Here
are his definitions:
Altercentric participation means an “ego’s virtual participation in Alter’s act as
if ego were a co-author of the act or being hand guided from Alter’s stance. This
is sometimes unwittingly manifested overtly, for example, when watching a high
jumper, or when opening one’s own mouth when putting a morsel into another’s
mouth, and differs from perspective-taking mediated by conceptual representa-
tion of other” (Bråten 2000b: 297–298).
E-motional memory is a “composite term, combining the folk sense of being
“moved by” and the root sense “out of motion”, for the procedural memory of
having co-enacted – virtually or actually – the goal-directed movements of oth-
ers, evoking in the learner shared vitality affect contours and inviting circular
re-enactment in similar situations” (Bråten 2000b: 299).
Other-centred participation and e-motional memory play a very important
role with regard to the second element; infant-parent relationship. Infants, aged
10–11 months, can see the mother’s movements and virtually co-enact them from
the mother stance. This may come about by virtue of mirror neurons support. Riz-
zolatti, Gallese and other researchers (2001) of the Human Physiology Institute of
Parma have discovered this particular kind of cells in monkeys. These neurons fire
JB[v.20020404] Prn:13/02/2007; 14:53 F: AICR6814.tex / p.7 (380-440)
Altercentric participation can create virtuous and vicious circles (Bråten 2000a).
Vicious circles are, strictly, linked with intergenerational transmission. The in-
fant, through other-centred participation, co-enacts, virtually, movements with
his parent (mother or father or other caretaker). Through e-motional memory,
he re-enacts, actually, this movement in another moment. If he has enjoyed care-
giving and sweet movements, he will easily in the future act out such movements
with other children or other person as he grows older. But if he has suffered abuse,
or ill-treatment by his parents, it is possible he could, in a future phase of his life,
re-enact the same attitudes towards other persons. He could become abusive or
ill-treat others, repeating the same family story. As Stern points out in many of his
papers and books (1985, 1995a, b) intergenerational transmission does not hap-
pen in “the ether”; it happens through acts and an act is an answer to another act.
Nothing magical and no mystery. But we must ask why it is that in one family one
act brings about repetition of pathology and in another family this does not hap-
pen. Or why in the same family a son repeats the “deed” of a parent or ancestor
while another pursues a very different way.
When faced with perturbing intergenerational transmission we must always
take into consideration these three variables because they can bring about different
outcomes:
First, infant temperament which is the constitutional factor. Every infant has
a distinct temperament and modes of reacting to situations will vary accordingly.
The same situation can bring about very different behaviours.
Second, the time that the infant spends with the most pathological members of
family and what importance they have for him. Is he prisoner of this relationship?
Can he not escape from it?
Third, is there another available member of the family that can take care of the
infant if, for example, the mother has heavy psychiatric problems or ill-treats his
son? May the father or another caretaker of the family offer a good alternative to
the mother? If no such caretaker is available, the infant may come to be brought to
repeat dysfunctional patterns.
I shall now turn to some examples in which I have tried to use Bråten’s theories
to interrupt a repetition seeming like a destiny. We may well regard destiny as
neither inside nor outside. It is on the border because a relationship is entailed, act
answering to the acts as Stern says, entailing virtual and actual movements, leaving
or evoking e-motional memory.
JB[v.20020404] Prn:13/02/2007; 14:53 F: AICR6814.tex / p.9 (475-527)
First example. Livio, his father and his peers. Counselling. Counselling with par-
ents can sometimes be a mode where the aim is to interrupt an ongoing cycle or
chain. In such cases counselling entails affording new insights or information to
the couple and in their relationship with the infant.
Two parents come to me for a counselling. They have a son, Livio, 2 years of
age. They worry because Livio ill-treats, pushes and bites peers. Peers cry and he
does not understand why. Livio believes he is only playing with them. But peers
are afraid when they see Livio coming in the park and they want to escape. Livio,
often, then is left and remains alone.
The father remembers when he was a child that he played rough or violent
games of movements with his own father. Probably, through e-motional memory
he has repeated the same movements with his son. He, again, remembers that
when his son was very young he played only movements games with him. It is
likely that Livio has co-enacted virtually these movements (when he was aged 10-
11 months) and that he now re-enacts similar rough movements with his peers,
thinking that this is only a play.
This is a vicious circle where there is a repetition of behaviours along genera-
tions. Counselling consists in trying to offer an insight to the parents, in particular
the father in this case. The counsel is to make Livio engage in plays without vio-
lent or rough movements, to leave him to play gradually alone, to play with him
with very different kind of movements permitting the toddler to co-enact such
movements and actually re-enact them, also with his peers.
Six months after I saw the parents, the situation is, truly, better. This has been
possible because the parents acquired a novel pertinent insight, and because of the
toddler’s good temperament, and emerging personality structure.
In this case the variables that did the good work were not only infant temper-
ament, but also the ability of the parents, in particular the father, to modify and to
extend the range of their behaviours with the son. In this case the chain of repeti-
tion in intergenerational transmission has been interrupted and this interruption
leaves space for new behaviours. In other terms, it is as if Livio has learned new
music, new tunes and new signifiers together with his parents.
marriage she married an alcoholic who then died in a car accident with car. She
then remarried, and she ill-treated her daughter.
The relationship between the mother and Ivo is very difficult, repeating the
same kind of relationship that pertained between Ivo’s mother and her mother. It is
likely that from e-motional memory, she remembers her own mother movements
and, like what happened to her, she has begun to ill-treat Ivo in the first month
of infancy. The Ivo’s family disseminate archives are those of a family in which at-
mospheres were full of tension, where darkness is incumbent in the rooms, where
the father is afraid of his wife. Even if Ivo does not understand every meaning
of events and things surrounding him, he understand signifiers, broken tunes,
the non-synchronized music. Through the mode of felt immediacy, Ivo perceives
everything about this atmosphere, feeling the tensions. But also, through alter-
centric participation, he lives the mother’s movements from the mother’s stance.
Movements of ill-treatment in his mother provokes movements in Ivo who co-
enacts, virtually, mother’s movements. In a following phase of his life he re-enacts
these movements with peers and adults, as well; he is violent, he says bad words to
peers, to teachers, to everybody. It seems that he repeats his mother’s deeds from
e-motional memory: a vicious circle very hard to break because in this multiprob-
lems family there is no corrective experience for Ivo. The father is not an alternative
model, and he does not manage to interrupt the pathological relationship between
the mother and Ivo. The father suffers from the violent temper of his wife and for
him it is impossible to help his son, who cannot defend himself.
We have, here, an example of intergenerational transmission, passing from
grandmother to mother, and from mother to infant. A destiny seems to be perse-
cuting this family, but we have seen destiny repeating itself as acts provoking other
acts feed acts from one generation to the next. In this family there are no variables
helping the infant. One needs to say again here that destiny is neither outside nor
inside. Destiny is on the border; it is the relationship between the infant and par-
ents, and the relationship between parents with their own parents, maintained by
the acts, by movements across generations.
This family lives in an empty homogeneus time, as Walter Benjamin (1974)
says, where things repeat themselves. It is a quantitative time, not qualitative. Here
Ivo cannot activate defensive mechanisms before altercentric participation begins
to work (and, probably, the same thing happened to his mother with her mother).
If altercentric participation begins to work, as Bråten (2000a) specifies when writ-
ing about vicious circles, it is most likely that Ivo can repeat the mother’s move-
ments from the mother stance, re-enacting the same behaviours. In fact, this is
what has happened because of Ivo’s sensitive temperament, and because his father
was not an alternative model, and because the relationship Ivo had with his mother
was continuous and prolonged in time. All these things combined to prevent the
creation of defence mechanisms interrupting altercentric participation.
JB[v.20020404] Prn:13/02/2007; 14:53 F: AICR6814.tex / p.11 (586-657)
References
Rizzolatti, G. et al. (2001). “From mirror neurons to imitation. Facts and speculations.” In W.
Prinz & A. Meltzoff (Eds.), The Imitative Mind: Development, Evolution and Brain Bases.
Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
Stern, D. N. (1985). The interpersonal world of the infant. New York: Basic Book
Stern, D. N. (1995a). The Motherhood Constellation. New York: Basic Book.
Stern, D. N. (1995b). “Self/other differentiation in the domain of intimate socio-affective
interaction: Some considerations.” In P. Rochat (Ed.), The Self in Infancy: Theory and
Research (pp. 419–430). Amsterdam: Elsevier Science.
Winnicott, D. (1986). Home is Where We Start From. Harmondsworth: Penguin Book.
Zanzotto, A. (2001). “Infanzie, poesie, scuolette.” In Scritti sulla letteratura. Milano: Mondatori.
Zanzotto, A. (2002). Poesie (1938–1986). Milano: Mondatori.
JB[v.20020404] Prn:7/03/2007; 17:09 F: AICR6815.tex / p.1 (48-107)
chapter
Birgit Kirkebaek
VIKOM Centre, Copenhagen
Introduction
Cathrine Lervig and six children with severe functional impairments develop and
which significance this may have for the special pedagogy.
The project is about what is ahead and under the words and the language in the
human interaction. It is about the congenital musical, which includes the social
and the emotional in the relation. It is about that which is one cut deeper than
alteration of turns. It is about rediscovering the basic musical and takes a starting
point in the congenital rhythmic pulse, which all humans are endowed with and
the physical experiences, which all interaction arises from. All children with or
without disability have a vital and basic experience with the body, the sounds, the
sent, the movement, the touch and the symbiosis with the motherly organism.
The musical elements that we respond to and which are ahead of the word and
also behind the word are: speech, variation of voice, rhythm, dynamic (whispering,
yelling), pause, vocal pitch, articulation, temper, science of gestures, facial expres-
sions, repetitions and imitation. However, it is also about theme and falling in and
the archetypical sounds, which exist from the beginning: sighs, grasp, complaint,
breathing etc.
Follow-on hypotheses which are important for the issue, namely Establishment
of shared experience through musical improvisation have been advanced on the
basis Cathrine Lervig’s music theoretical insight and supported by a number of
theories (Trevarthen 2000; Björkvold 1992; Bråten 1998, 2000; Lorentzen 2001,
2003; Sollied & Kirkebæk 2001; Stern 2004, and others):
– Instead of looking at the child and the situation from outside, as a third part,
and in advance consider how we wish the child to react, we must be in the sit-
JB[v.20020404] Prn:7/03/2007; 17:09 F: AICR6815.tex / p.3 (158-217)
uation, share it with the child and hereby make it important through inclusion
of the rhythm of the body, the sound of the voice, the dance of movements.
– We must not only accept, but also entirely appreciate sounds, movements and
rituals, different from normally seen and heard, and use them as a starting
point in the communication.
In the video material scrutinized so far the reason mentioned above and follow-
on hypotheses lead to following preliminary postulates interesting for the (special)
pedagogy:
– That external structure such as schemes programs and symbols do not neces-
sarily lead to inner structure and shared meaning.
– That the individually used communication “tool”, the tool an adult is using to
create meaning, must be developed to a high level such as Cathrine Lervig’s
use of her voice.
– That musical elements such as tempo, pitch, variation of voice, dynamic,
pause, vocal pitch, articulation, drama, gestures, repetition and imitation must
be included in the teamwork.
– That it is important to understand that we do not only imitate the expressions
of each other, we complete them too, extend them – and return to the known.
Cathrine Lervig seeks through wordless singing and musical improvisation to es-
tablish a shared dialogic room of sounds, rhythm and movements based on the
expressions of each individual child. This is a kind of singing, inspired by Saamish
jojk and African Ngoma. Ngoma is a total-concept of perception, involving the ex-
pansion of the moment in rhythm, movement, singing etc (Bjørkvold 1992). The
purpose of the project is to find new special pedagogical understanding of the basic
factors involved, when trying to establish contact, co-action and communication
with disabled children. These children are in a vulnerable situation because of the
uncertainty, which their functional impairments cause, people around them, and
because of their difficulties in interacting in an understandable way.
Cathrine Lervig, musician, and Birgit Kirkebæk, researcher and Doctor of ped-
agogic, are responsible of the project. The project material is partly based on a
pre-study of video analysis of Cathrine’s interaction with seven young persons and
adults, who are congenital deafblind; partly on video recordings of Cathrine’s in-
teraction with three children with multiple disabilities from Rosenvængets School
and three pupils from Geelsgaard School’s department for deafblind children.
These six pupils each had ten one-to-one lessons of about half an hour with
Cathrine. There is app. 30 hours of video recordings to be used in the analysis.
Besides this we have app. 10 hours of recordings of the concerts Cathrine gave for
all pupils and staff when she visited the two schools.
JB[v.20020404] Prn:7/03/2007; 17:09 F: AICR6815.tex / p.4 (217-259)
One of the elements that parents noticed watching the video recordings of
Cathrine Lervig’s co-action with their children is that no sounds and no move-
ments are wrong. In Cathrine’s improvisation she seeks to start from the child’s
movement or sound and integrates this to give it space and meaning in the in-
teraction. Cathrine Lervig starts creating meaning in her musical improvisation
without knowing whether it will lead to a shared meaning. She seeks to create a
language here and now in the situation. She is going “from outside and in”, where
we as professional social pedagogues traditionally move the other way. We start
with the meaning instead of taking our starting point in creating the meaning.
The concept of aesthetics was invented in the mid-18th Century. At that time it
was used in general about sensory perception and took part in the discussion of the
relationship between sensory and logical realization. The philosopher Immanuel
Kant (1724–1804) considered aesthetics a philosophical discipline. The idea, that
it is the relation between the piece of artwork and the participant that pronounces
the aesthetic verdict, came from him. This must be seen in contrast to the belief
that there is an objective way to acknowledge the quality of a work of art. In the
19th and 20th century aesthetics were interpreted more narrowly, and from a more
philosophical point of view. Now the focus was directly aimed at the object of art,
rather than being at the relationship between the viewer and the work. In German
philosophy, art played a particular role. Art was said to be in a privileged relation
with truth, as something able to uncover falseness and superficiality – an example
of someone with this perception is Martin Heidegger (1889–1976). In the 20th
century interest has again gathered around a wider understanding of aesthetics
and the relation between work of art and the recipient of it. One is talking about
the aesthetic product and its influence on the subject, and the subject’s perception
and use of the art, seen in relation to the culture to which the individual belongs.
Aesthetic means to feel or to sense. In the 17th Century philosophers talked
about “the recognition of a new area of experience which does not wind up
with rationally controllable knowledge, but concerns our sensibility towards the
individual appearance of situation”.8 The French philosopher Michel Foucault de-
scribes the existence of aesthetics as “the individual’s form conscious formalization
of his life”, but also emphasizes that the Antique ideal of aesthetics of life has been
replaced by an individualized art of self-creation which separates the ideal from the
social.9 The German philosopher Heidegger speaks aesthetically about the work of
art as “the initiation of the truth”. Immediately these quotations tell something
about the hypotheses formulated now, as expressed by these questions:
– Which kind of esthetical consciousness is developed in people who – due to
their impairments – grow up under other conditions than “normally”?
– What happens when the esthetical dimension is separated from the social? –
When the surroundings do not see the esthetical dimension in expressions
different from normally seen?
– Can we as professionals change and extend our understanding of the esthetical
in spite of the theoretical and practical knowledge already acquired?
– Which kind of “setting” of life do we meet in congenital deafblind children
and children with multiple disabilities that we interact with?
JB[v.20020404] Prn:7/03/2007; 17:09 F: AICR6815.tex / p.7 (365-423)
– Heidegger is calling the work of art for “the initiation of the truth”. What type
of art are we creating when the meeting with the disabled children becomes a
success?
Per Lorentzen tells in his book about “different” persons he has met; there is the
man who can spin his belt around his arm in a very sophisticated way; the woman
whose door to the world is a fascination of balloons; people with autism who
flourish when a music therapist use their natural rhythms as starting point. He is
engaged in explaining what happens when we turn our acquired professional con-
duct upside down and do something different from what we are originally trained
to do. When we take our starting point in things that are already important to the
person with whom we are, regardless that it may be spinning a belt around the arm
or blowing up balloons instead of starting with a decision of the goal and the kind
of normal behaviour that we would like to reach through training and acquirement
of skills. From an esthetical perspective you may say that it is a matter of perfec-
tion of the expression that the other person shows you by seeing it, accepting it as
important as well as sharing and develop the fascination of fellowship. As humans
we have an emotional and experience distance to others, but usually we can break
this barrier by sharing emotions and experiences. This may be difficult to people
with functional impairment to do the same; to experience emotional reactions as
a part of a shared social activity where we partly relieve each other emotionally
and partly share experiences. In case there is no active fellowship, if there is focus
on emotions as splinted actions, emotions will remain un-communicated with the
result of large existential loneliness and frustration.
In his new book Lorentzen (2003) will introduce a new perspective on learn-
ing disability. This means that he will replace the individualistic view on functional
impairment with a relational view. This means that an essential understanding
of intellectual impairment cannot be accepted as the explanation of human be-
haviour, but continently the behaviour is perceived with a reasoned, dyadic and
dialogic perspective. He asks what does it take to redefine deviant behaviour to so-
cial acceptable behaviour and how do we include it in community? This is the very
question that we also focus on in the project “Establishment of shared experience
through improvisation”.
JB[v.20020404] Prn:7/03/2007; 17:09 F: AICR6815.tex / p.8 (423-470)
Lasse, an example
Cathrine Lervig describes her lessons with an eight-year-old boy named Lasse,
who is blind and severely hearing impaired as follows: First she is uncertain of
the quality of the video tape, which she finds “shaken” and unclear. Gradually she
experiences the video in a very different way: “the video record of the lesson is very
special, I will describe it as a piece of art. It is not a film with Lasse and Cathrine.
It is the atmosphere between us. Sometimes we disappear from the screen. But arms,
legs, shoulders and shirts acting in the empty room make it a room with magic and
atmosphere: the atmosphere between us, the room where things are happening”. The
communication between Lasse and Cathrine Lervig is concentrated and through
her analysis she finds points as follow:
Lasse’s interaction / challenges through the process with: From Lasse and I using
our voices in the first lessons: we take turn, we must keep an invisible flow while
the other is on; Till we use the dance more and more in the latest lessons: our
expressions are parallel and we remain in this condition all the time = flow. Lasse
is dancing: he is sitting on his bottom as a tipped V. He keeps the basic rhythm in
body and melody sounds in arms and with hands (sometimes arms and hands have
each their sounds). But the co-ordination is clearly a whole. Just like us dancing:
our feet hit the floor in a basic rhythm, head, arms and hands etc. have other
patterns within the frame of the basic rhythm.
Cathrine Lervig stresses the following facts in the experienced interaction:
– Concentration.
– Lasse listens and acts.
– Lasse is being listened and responded to.
– Lasse expresses his emotions, exchanges emotions and shares emotions with
another person.
– There is a constant flow: maintain close contact with the other, he is dancing,
I am singing.
– Dynamic: Experience and accompanying each other through the emotional
process: experiencing to go with another on a trip to several emotional out-
bursts in “the secure room” of the music.
– Allowing the other to take the lead: to see life from the angle of another human
being; trust another person and follow her in her emotional expressions.
– Take the lead himself; be a part of the decisions made; lead the other through
events which are meaningful from his point of view; having influence on the
course of the emotional events, meaning what we are going through, which
way we are going.
JB[v.20020404] Prn:7/03/2007; 17:09 F: AICR6815.tex / p.9 (470-521)
– Suggest something new, take initiatives, go all out: in the safe room of music,
Lasse may go all out with something; maybe it is understood, held and fol-
lowed up, maybe not. Maybe it is the starting point of something unexpected.
– Choose and challenge: Lasse chooses what he wants to respond to, related to
what I offer him.
– Pauses: Have breaks: Lasse needs breaks: I wake him by touching him with my
hands. He receives these moves.
Lasse’s dance. Cathrine Lervig describes Lasse’s dance as his very own expression.
He has never seen anyone dancing, as he is completely blind. Lasse cannot walk
or crawl. But he can sit down and dance. In his dance he is using many sides of
himself.
– He experiences that his initiatives are responded to meaning that another
person holds him and they create something together.
– Cathrine Lervig writes, that “in the dance Lasse has found his own expres-
sion, an expression able to match my expression and challenge with the same
strength. He wouldn’t be able to use his voice in the same way, since he has a
weaker voice than mine.”
The example illustrates many of the points of this article. Concerning special ped-
agogical efforts the new infant paradigm of teaching children with functional
impairments, means a revolution in regard to taking the starting point in the
relation and the early contact patterns. However, the question is, have we spend
enough time and energy on understanding the musical qualities from which the
mother-child contact arises? If it is a question about creating meaning and through
improvisation open up for each other’s perception of the world, this is not only a
new infant paradigm coming up but also an aesthetical paradigm characterized by
the fact, that the expressions of the Other are taken so seriously that improvisation
and musical elements are given space not only in the establishment of contact but
also as important parts of further development of contact and communication.
Acknowledgment
The project is a co-operation between two research centers: Videnscenter for Børn
og Unge med Multihandicap (VIKOM – Research Centre for Young People and
Children with Multiple Disability) and Videnscenter for døvblindfødte (VCDBF –
Resource Center on Congenital Deafblindness).
JB[v.20020404] Prn:7/03/2007; 17:09 F: AICR6815.tex / p.10 (521-598)
Notes
. See an example of this in the article: Elin Andreasen, Bjarne Øyen: “Etablering av funksjonelle
ferdigheter hos barn med multifunksjonshemning” (Establishment of functionary skill by child
with multiple disabilities). Spesialpedagogikk 8 – 2003:& 28–33 (Norsk Tidsskrift).
. Read the critics of the circumstance in: Carol Potter, Chris Whittaker: Enabling Communica-
tion in Children with Autism. Jessica Kingsley Publishers. London and Philadelphia 2001.
. Since the eighties there is an increased focus on creative and artistic entrance angles on
the area of learning disability, which will give room for personal development through artistic
expression. Examples to be mentioned are the theatre group of day training school of Lim-
fjordsskolen, Karavana, The Art School in Copenhagen, The Art Museum Gaia in Randers and
many others.
. Colwyn Trevarthen (Department of Psychology, The University of Edinburgh): “Musicality
and the intrinsic motive pulse: evidence from human psychobiology and infant communica-
tion.” Musicæ Scientiæ. Rhythm, Musical Narrative, and Origins of Human Communication. The
Journal of the European Society for the Cognitive Sciences of Music. Special Issue 1999–2000.
. Marc Wittmann and Ernst Pöppel (Institute of Medical Psychology, Ludwig-Maximilians-
Universität München, Germany): “Temporal mechanisms of the brain as fundamentals of com-
munication – with special reference to music perception and performance.” Musicæ Scientiæ.
Rhythm, Musical Narrative, and Origins of Human Communication. The Journal of the European
Society for the Cognitive Sciences of Music. Special Issue 1999–2000.
. Stephen N. Malloch (Macarthur Auditory Research Centre Sydney, University of Western
Sydney Macarthur, Australia): “Mothers and infants and communicative musicality.” Musicæ
Scientiæ. Rhythm, Musical Narrative, and Origins of Human Communication. The Journal of the
European Society for the Cognitive Sciences of Music. Special Issue 1999–2000.
. Benjaman Schögler (Department of Psychology, The university of Edinburgh): “Studying
temporal co-ordination in jazz duets.” Musicæ Scientiæ. Rhythm, Musical Narrative, and Origins
of Human Communication. The Journal of the European Society for the Cognitive Sciences of Music.
Special Issue 1999–2000.
. Den Store Danske Encyklopædi, Vol. 20: 502 – with reference to Kant og Baumgarten.
. cf. the chapter “Livet som kunstværk” (Life as art) i Dag Heede: Det tomme menneske (The
empty human being). Introduction to Michel Foucault. Museum Tusculanums Forlag, Køben-
havns Universitet 1992: 148.
References
Bjørkvold, J.-R. (1992). Det musiske menneske (The Muse Within). København: Hans Reitzels
Forlag.
Bråten, S. (1998). Kommunikasjon og samspil – fra fødsel til alderdom (Communication and
Interplay – from Birth to Old Age). Oslo: Tano Aschehoug.
Bråten, S. (2000). Modellmakt og altersentriske spedbarn. Essays on Dialogue in Infant & Adult.
Bergen: Sigma Forlag.
Heede, D. (1992). Det tomme menneske. Introduktion til Michel Foucault (The empty human
being. Introduction to Michel Foucault). Copenhagen: Museum Tusculanums Forlag.
JB[v.20020404] Prn:7/03/2007; 17:09 F: AICR6815.tex / p.11 (598-647)
Kyndrup, M. et al. (2003). Kulturens Fremtid. Æstetik uden grænser (The future of the culture.
Aestethic without borders). Statens Humanistisk Forskningsråd 2003.
Lorentzen, P. (2001). Uvanlige barns språk (Exceptional childrens’ language). Oslo: Universi-
tetsforlaget.
Lorentzen, P. (2003). Fra tilskuer til deltaker. Samhandling og kommunikasjon med voksne
utviklingshemmede (From onlooker to participation. Intercourse and communication with
adult persons with intellectual disability). Oslo: Universitetsforlaget.
Malloch, S. N. (2000). “Mothers and infants and communicative musicality.” Musicæ Scientiæ.
Rhythm, Musical Narrative, and Origins of Human Communication. The Journal of the
European Society for the Cognitive Sciences of Music. Special Issue 1999–2000.
Schögler, B. (2000). “Studying temporal co-ordination in jazz duets.” Musicæ Scientiæ. Rhythm,
Musical Narrative, and Origins of Human Communication. The Journal of the European
Society for the Cognitive Sciences of Music. Special Issue 1999–2000.
Sollied, S., & Kirkebæk, B. (2001). Samspil og samoplevelse (Interplay and intersubjective
experience). Copenhagen: VIKOM 2001.
Stern, D. N. (2004). The Present Moment in Psychotherapy and Everyday Life. New York: Norton.
Trevarthen, C. (2000). “Musicality and the intrinsic motive pulse: Evidence from human
psychobiology and infant communication.” Musicæ Scientiæ. Rhythm, Musical Narrative,
and Origins of Human Communication. The Journal of the European Society for the Cognitive
Sciences of Music. Special Issue 1999–2000.
Wittmann, M., & Pöppel, E. (2000). “Temporal mechanisms of the brain as fundamentals of
communication – with special reference to music perception and performance.” Musicæ
Scientiæ. Rhythm, Musical Narrative, and Origins of Human Communication. The Journal of
the European Society for the Cognitive Sciences of Music. Special Issue 1999–2000.
JB[v.20020404] Prn:7/03/2007; 17:10 F: AICR6816.tex / p.1 (48-139)
chapter
Of all the ways we human beings share company, and communicate being alive,
active and aware in our intricately mobile bodies, singing and dancing, the breath
and activity of music, are the most elemental and persuasive. With them we cel-
ebrate friendship and tell the story of our experiences, hopes and beliefs. There
are messages in the polyrhythmic way our two-legged bodies move with pulse and
accents that can be varied to express the subtleties of will and consciousness to
others, and music seems to be a special manifestation of human skill. We are dif-
ferent from other animals in this, but the foundations for all human cleverness in
moving were laid down in the moving of creatures that evolved long ago. We need
to trace the development and cultivation of human moving by comparison of its
principles with those that guide all animal actions. A beginning can be made by
describing how infants, very lively but naive human beings, move in musical ways.
As soon as they can stand, toddlers dance to the rhythm of music. Newborns
alert to the pulse of a parent’s affectively intoned voice and can respond in syn-
chrony (Malloch 1999). Babies only a few months old alert and turn to the sound
of a song or instrumental music, and then share the tempo and melody, vocal-
izing in harmony, especially on final phrases, swaying the body and beating out
an ‘intrinsic motive pulse’ with arms and legs (Trevarthen 1999; Mazokopaki &
Trevarthen 2007). Sharing body games with song is a favourite pastime of happy
parents with 4- to 6-month-olds all over the world (e.g. Takada 2005).
Now it has been shown that a premature baby, two months short of a full term
gestation, has, not only a coherent body sense, but a precise sense of the rhythm
of ‘talk’ and can exchange little calls with a parent in sensitive improvisation of
syllables in a shared or ‘co-constructed’ phrase of thinking (Figure 1). This previ-
Ben Schögler and Colwyn Trevarthen
JB[v.20020404] Prn:7/03/2007; 17:10
Figure 1. Innate ‘speech’ rhythms: A newborn infant, now 2 months premature, in an ICU in Holland, communicates with her father who is
‘kangarooing’ her under his shirt. When she makes clear calls with her immature vocal system, her father imitates the sounds closely. Both pitch
their sounds a little above Middle C (C4), around E. After the first exchange of one sound each, they generate a 4-second ‘phrase’ of short (c. 0.3
sec.) sounds alternating at a ‘syllable’ frequency, with intervals between 650 and 850 millseconds, i.e. around andante. (See spectrograph on the
lower right). Then a series of single utterances are made. When the father does not respond, the infant makes 3 sounds at phrase length intervals
(4 sec.), the first weak and the others louder, before he replies. The infant has an intrinsic time sense for syllables and phrases. (From a video by
F: AICR6816.tex / p.2 (139-139)
Saskia van Rees (van Rees & De Leeuw 1993). Spectrograph by Stephen Malloch.)
JB[v.20020404] Prn:7/03/2007; 17:10 F: AICR6816.tex / p.3 (139-177)
ously unknown time sense and musical talent of a maximally naive human being
(wrongly conceived by medical and psychological science as at a stage without con-
scious awareness or intersubjective sympathy) give us a new understanding of the
roots of human consciousness (Trevarthen & Reddy 2006). This understanding
recognizes that clever minds live in moving bodies, that emotions are essentially
part of the appreciation of what movements can do, and that thoughts originate
as projects for moving with conscious acceptance of what occurs in perception of
an outside world (Varela et al. 1991; Gallese & Lakoff 2005). It also gives us a new
psychobiology of culture, how we move together to create meaning, not by imi-
tating movements or joint attention to objects, but by sympathy for the motives
and emotions of one another’s actions, by negotiation of roles in intelligent and
inventive acting (Donald 2001; Trevarthen 2004a, b).
In the second year, when language is still rudimentary, a ‘children’s musical
culture’ (Björkvold 1992) flourishes among peers, made by the toddlers as they
invent themes of play. They import or imitate a few ‘standard forms’ of music
from the adult word, but mostly they are inventing and sharing a wide range of
vocal and gestural performance, with a natural and free musicality of breath, voice
and the whole body moving.
Knowing that the mind is ‘embodied’ (Varela et al. 1991), designed to work
in well-timed collaboration with the weight and mobility of all the limbs together,
helps understanding of the wonderful sympathy all animal brains have for move-
ments of other animals – how we, and animals too, are naturally intersubjective,
making social collaboration by sensing in movements both intentions that formu-
late them, and the emotions that modulate and evaluate them. In the human case
there is a new ability to make up rituals and language, for inventing stories and
techniques for acting to change the world – an ability to make culture by ‘mim-
ing’ fantastical projects in the art of communicating (Donald 2001). Even a baby
has special biological functions, anatomical features and physiological motivating
processes of body and brain, which make cooperative communication and cultural
learning a specially human need (Trevarthen 2001a, b, 2004).
mically with integrated purpose – and the fundamental pulse and accelerations of
the movements appeared to match those of spontaneous and intuitive adult ex-
pressions (Trevarthen 1986). In other words, infants and adults are matching or
sympathetic rhythmic performers.
A mother talking with her infant presents a dance of head turns, facial move-
ments and hand gestures, and a singing voice. Infant and mother both exhibit the
polymodal coherence of action in one mind time, as described by the phenome-
nologists (Michotte 1962; Merleau-Ponty 1982). Only later do they learn to attend
with critical focus of attention to ‘seeing’, ‘hearing’ or ‘touching’ with one modality
at a time, using specially limited forms of exploratory moving to ‘fine tune’ skilful
actions, and to learn new ones. From the beginning, the fundamental rhythms of
infant and adult match. By this equality of time sense they can dialogue efficiently,
anticipate one another’s expressions, alternate and synchronize utterances or ges-
tures precisely, and ‘attune’ to one another’s emotions (Stern et al. 1985; Beebe et
al. 1985). The tensions and grace of each gesture can be appreciated between them
in ‘felt immediacy’ (Bråten 1988), because their minds are imagining moving in
time and space by matching or ‘corresponding’ processes.
Thus it was demonstrated by a handful of independent studies around 1970
that the development of human communication of purposes, interests, and feel-
ings, and ultimately the celebration of myths, narratives of purpose and strategies
of ideas as well as the use of language, is founded on and intimate sympathy for
patterns of expressive moving (Bateson1971, 1975; Stern 1971, 1974; Trevarthen
1974, 1979). All parts of the body obeyed the same sources of muscular activa-
tion, what the Russian physiologist Bernstein (1967) had called the ‘Sollwert’ or
command to move, moving to the beat of one ‘ecphorator’ or ‘conductor’.
The acoustic analyses of vocal exchanges in protoconversation and mothers’
songs by Malloch (Malloch et al. 1997; Malloch 1999) have confirmed these ex-
pressive parameters, enriching our appreciation of how the changing pulse and
expressive modulations of a mother’s voice match the rhythm and accelerations
of her infant’s arm movements, and revealing the precision of timing for the
narratives of their vocal interactions and imitations (Figure 2).
While recognizing the conservation of rhythms in human motor activity
through all stages of development, it is important to note that the biological
rhythms of animal action and of animal communication are never metric or con-
stant. Neural ‘clocks’ are not ‘hard wired’ or ‘mechanical’ generators of action. Like
all ‘biological clocks’ they have a preferred periodicity, but, unlike mechanical or
electronic clocks, are adaptable to circumstances of their actions in the body and in
engagement with the world, and consequently variable in their energy and power
(Looby & Loudon 2005). A mother-baby protoconversation is the product of a dy-
namic coordination or negotiation of moves, within the infant, within the mother,
and in the ongoing vital exchange between them. The baby enters the duet with the
JB[v.20020404] Prn:7/03/2007; 17:10 F: AICR6816.tex / p.5 (253-253)
Figure 3. Innate hand gestures to melody of song: A 5-month-old girl, born totally blind,
‘conducts’ the musical rhythms of her mother’s singing of a Swedish nursery song, with
her left hand. A plot of the movements of her left index finger in vertical and horizontal
directions shows that, compared to the pitch plot of her mother’s voice, shows that she is
leading the mother by c. 300 msec. (see events at 4, 16 and 28 sec.). The arrows indicate that
she is synchronising with the mother at other points. She knows the song and can perform
it her way, ‘dancing’ with the mother’s song. (From a video by Gunilla Preisler, Stockholm
University; plot of hand movements by Ben Schögler.)
(i. e. matching pitch and timbre), or by gesturing ‘in time’. The baby is then ap-
parently engaged by the ‘emotional envelope’ of the presentation, or its ‘narrative’
(Stern 1992, 1999; Trevarthen 1987, 1999; Malloch 1999).
JB[v.20020404] Prn:7/03/2007; 17:10 F: AICR6816.tex / p.8 (334-380)
What is innate here is an avidity to learn by moving expressively, and the parent
responds intuitively to teach by moving expressively. By six months simple culture
specific ways of moving in ‘performances’, such as the actions of a hand-clapping
song, are taken up and used or ‘shown off ’ by infants in games with their famil-
iar companions (Trevarthen 2002). These learned behaviours are associated with
strong expressions of shared enjoyment, or ‘pride’, which recall the emotion of
pleasure that is found to be associated with even neonatal imitations. A six-month-
old, now able to sit up and move arms and hands effectively, has limited vocal
capacity compared to a one-year-old, but can call, gurgle, giggle and squeal, and
can assume a special ‘singing’ voice, matching the rhythm of vocal expression with
waving or bouncing gestures (Littleton 2002).
The concept of being ‘moved’ by music must be as old as music itself. The lan-
guage we use to describe the emotional effects of music is full of metaphors for
animal movement, a soaring crescendo, a dancing, or plodding melody, for ex-
ample. Daniel Stern uses the following adverbs to distinguish qualities of ‘time
contours’ or ‘feeling flow patterns’ of ‘vitality’ in subjective experience of social in-
teraction: surging, fading-away, fleeting, explosive, tentative, effortful, accelerating,
decelerating, climaxing, bursting, and drawn out (Stern 1999: 68). These ways of
moving with different profiles of energy or power are the essential aesthetic mes-
sages between musical communicators, or art communicators of any kind (Langer
1953; Dissanayake 1999, 2000).
All the sounds that musicians make in solo performance and in orchestral
concerts are a product of physical movement of human beings, either interacting
with the masses and resonance of an instrument or within the vocal apparatus of
their own body. Music is a product of bodies moving with perceptual control of
the quality or ‘e-motion’ of moving – it carries commands to move in all their vital
quality. That is why it moves us.
Analysis of dynamic emotional exchanges of all human activity, but especially
in the arts of theatre, music and dance, (which Adam Smith (1777/1982) wrote
about as the Imitative Arts) enables researchers to harvest a wealth of information
on the generation of motivated psychological time, thus clarifying the processes
of perception and cognition which depend on the mind’s work to move the body
effectively in engagement with the world. It gives us the key to understanding so-
cial communication in all animal species and humans (Donald 1999; Panksepp &
Bernatzky 2002; Panksepp & Trevarthen 2007). Artists in all their incarnations act
as mediators for emotion and aesthetics, translating narratives of expression and
experience between different modalities of perception.
JB[v.20020404] Prn:7/03/2007; 17:10 F: AICR6816.tex / p.9 (380-431)
rent closure-rate”. This variable is defined as the ‘tau’ of the motion-gap, after the
name for the Greek letter ‘T’ (Lee 1998). The tau function has been demonstrated
to govern the prospective control of a wide range of animal movements (Lee 1998,
2005). This proves that animal brains have evolved capable of anticipating the ex-
perience of a movement to a goal (or the closure of a ‘motion gap’) by comparing
this experience to a function generated in the brain, the tau-guide, which provides
the perceptual system with dynamic temporal information for each movement
about the changing state of the system in relation to an anticipated goal state.
The ‘motion gap’ is defined in independence of either the physical nature of
the movement required, or the perceptual modality that monitors it – it can be the
felt angle of a joint rotation, the swing of a foot to kick a ball, the touch of fingers
grasping an object, a turn of the head in the visual array, a change in the sound of
a voice made by moving the larynx or the jaws, lips and tongue, the sounds echoed
back from the room by walking, or from objects being handled, and so on. Experi-
ments have shown that all ‘motion-gaps’ and the way they change can be described
with high accuracy through the application of tau theory, apparently for any form
of movement to a goal. This is a biological constant for animal movements.
To take a musical example, when a singer moves between two notes a ‘pitch-
gap’ is anticipated between the note the singer is on at first, and the note he or
she is trying to achieve. The hearing of such a musical event has the power to
reach inside our minds and evoke emotions through our experience of the human-
made movement. This power depends on the ability of the musician to engage us
with temporally coherent forms of changing purpose and to express such ‘narra-
tion’ to us in a manner appreciable by us (Trevarthen & Malloch 2001). The study
of musical/creative behaviours thus offers the movement scientist a way to catch
the human agent moving expressively, with intellectual guard down – to see the
mind not as a disembodied, ideal interpreter and thinker, but as a feeling, acting,
impulsive person, spontaneously alive in his or her body.
Without any imitation, instrumental Music can produce very considerable effects;
though its powers over the heart and affections are, no doubt, much inferior to
those of vocal Music, it has however, considerable powers: by the sweetness of its
sounds it awakens agreeably, and calls upon the attention; by their connection and
affinity it naturally detains that attention, which follows easily a series of agree-
able sounds, which have all a certain relation both to a common, fundamental,
or leading note, called the key note; and to a certain succession or combination
of notes, called the song or composition. By means of this relation each foregoing
sound seems to introduce, and as it were prepare the mind for the following: by
its rhythmus, by its time and measure, it disposes that succession of sounds into
a certain arrangement, which renders the whole more easy to be comprehended
and remembered. Time and measure are to instrumental Music what order and
method are to discourse; they break it into proper parts and divisions, by which
we are enabled both to remember better what has gone before, and frequently to
forsee somewhat of what is to come after: we frequently forsee the return of a
period which we know must correspond to another which we remember to have
gone before; and according to the saying of an ancient philosopher and musician,
the enjoyment of Music arises partly from memory and partly from foresight.
(Smith 1777/1982: 203–204)
Smith has identified both the expressive quality and rhythm of musical movement,
and also the prospective control that encompasses the imagining or remembering
of a tune. We tested this conception as follows.
A professional jazz singer was invited to record an acapella version of the song
‘The Beat Goes On’. Her singing was recorded in a traditional studio setting but
with one addition. She was asked to try and move her right hand in a manner that
matched her vocal performance, paying particular attention to her movements
up and down in pitch. Thus, as she moved from a high note to a low note her
hand was to move down, and vice versa. While audio recordings were made of her
singing, her hand movements were also recorded using a Selspot Motion Capture
system. This uses an active light emitting diode (led) marker on the body part to
be tracked, and a special video camera that records the movement. We tracked the
singer’s hand in horizontal (x) and vertical (y) planes at 500 cycles per second. The
set up is shown in Figure 4.
After the singer had performed the song, the recorded sound was processed us-
ing Praat acoustic software (Boersma & Weenink 2000) to extract an accurate pitch
contour. Her gestures of voice (pitch) and hand (movement in x and y planes) as
she sang a phrase of 3.5 seconds are plotted in Figure 5. The song has a repeating
blues structure providing several examples of each distinct pitch movement, which
facilitated analytic comparison.
We search for a coherence in the functions of the nervous information con-
trolling movements of hand and voice that might correspond to the message we
receive from the singer. There are many ‘motion gaps’ being controlled by the brain
JB[v.20020404] Prn:7/03/2007; 17:10 F: AICR6816.tex / p.13 (599-599)
Figure 5. Graph showing an excerpt from the recording of the singer’s voice, with move-
ments in pitch (cross-hatched line) and corresponding horizontal (dotted line) and vertical
(black line) hand movements. This represents the first repetition of the phrase, “Drums
keep pound-ing a rhy-thm to the brai-n”. A graph showing the kappas of the pitch change
and hand movement for repeated performance of the word “brai-n” (circled) is shown in
Figure 6.
JB[v.20020404] Prn:7/03/2007; 17:10 F: AICR6816.tex / p.14 (599-662)
in this behaviour. The two selected for measurement and comparison here are the
‘pitch-gap’ between successive notes and the distance or ‘spatial gap’ that varies
with the movements of the hand.
The musical expression describes some common parameter of intention be-
hind the very different movements of the arm and hand, and of the respiratory
system and larynx, not the excitation of any particular muscle groups in combina-
tion. Tau functions have been identified in the neural activity of the motor cortices
in anticipation of any guided movement (Lee 1998). Its analysis ascertains how any
particular data set matches the hypothesized tau-guide in the brain. A movement
is said to ‘fit’ the tau-coupling model when 95% of the variance in that movement
(equivalent to a probability level of p < 0.05) can be accounted for by the tau-
coupling model. We are asking if the activity of this kind of nervous information
source can be detected and perceived as ‘musical’ in the movements of the singers
vocal system or of her hand. The tau-coupling analyses allow us to measure, not
just the effectiveness of movement, but also different ‘qualitative’ aspects of the
kinematics or control and expression of the ‘motion-gaps’ in question. Two key
components relate to expressive communication in the movements – the qualities
of moving described by the terms Daniel Stern used, as cited above, to describe
different ‘feeling flow contours’. They also help define what Adam Smith referred
to as the ‘sweetness of sound’ in music and its rhythmus.
First, the mean coupling constant, K, describes the dynamic pattern of the
whole movement – in short how the movement caused by changing muscle forces
is ‘coupled’ to the form of action anticipated by nervous activity in the brain. By
sending appropriate tau information to the muscles, the brain ‘intends’ to regu-
late the tau of a motion-gap so that its relation to the tau guide stays constant
at some value K set by the brain. K can be adjusted between movements to vary
their dynamical form or force and power. For example, if the movement acceler-
ated strongly and then followed a longer period of deceleration to arrive gently
and come to rest at its goal state with zero velocity or no impact, then this would
be described by a K changing between 0.0 and 0.5. That is, when the value of K
is between 0 and 0.5, the movement ends with touch contact, as when a person
is reaching carefully for something light and small. When K is between 0.5 and
1.0 the movement ends with hard contact or impact. The mean absolute force and
power involved in moving a part of the body are both raised by increasing K. For
example, perceiving and moving with tau guidance and keeping track of K enables
a musician to play or sing the right note in the right way at the right time (Lee &
Schögler 2007).
The second component of the mathematical account is a moment-to-moment
description of the process of coupling. This transcript of neural control takes the
form of a changing profile of the ratio of the movement tau and the prospective
neural guide tau, giving a resultant description of the process of control as the
JB[v.20020404] Prn:7/03/2007; 17:10 F: AICR6816.tex / p.15 (662-713)
movement unfolds. When this ratio of the tau of the movement to the tau guide
is plotted against time for the duration of a coupled movement a graphical repre-
sentation of the active process of ‘coupling’ is produced in what we have termed
a kappa graph. This transcript displays the adjustments made to the ‘motion-gap
tau’ to maintain proportionality with the ‘guide-tau’ provided neurally. This mea-
sure shows us the ‘flow’ of movements, and consistencies in the ‘way’ these kappa
profiles unfold may provide a glimpse of the underlying expressive ‘image’ or plan,
the quality or ‘tone’ of the gesture the artist is trying to convey through their
movements be they ostenato, vibrato or soaring glissando (Lee & Schögler 2006).
A graph of kappa gives a temporal description of the pattern of control of the
movement over its whole course. These graphs demonstrate a measurable effect of
putting a Sollwert (Bernstein 1967) or ‘motor plan’ (Jeannerod 2006) into action,
and they show systematic variation over different movements in different modali-
ties. We suggest that the mathematical form in a graphical representation of kappa
shows the emotional intention in the nervous plan for action behind the gesture. If
these graphs are the same shape for different types of movements, such as the ges-
tures of hand and voice of our singer, then they go deeper and show us a common
amodal state of emotionality in mind made apparent in both hand and voice, not
dependent on either one medium of changing pitch or spatial orientation – that is,
they convey that which is common to both hand and voice, the singer’s intended
expression.
So, in our study of this the singer’s performance of ‘the beat goes on’, we were
interested in several questions. Can tau analyses be used to accurately describe the
process of control in both vocal and hand movements? Is there coherence between
the tau variables of mean K and kappa for hand and voice? Can this information
communicate to us something about the feelings of the person singing? Coupling
analyses showed that the control of each and every vocal (pitch) and hand (spa-
tial) movements was accurately described by tau functions. However, in addition
to a striking concordance overall between the movements of hand and voice, there
were several instances where the K values did not match. This is an important fea-
ture, demonstrating that the relationship between the central nervous control and
expression of any one behaviour is a dynamic process in an adjustable experience
of activity. The singer had received very little direction regarding her hand gestures
and she had no practice. Her moving was the spontaneous expression of impulses
to move and to feel the movement whilst performing the song. She may have been
uncertain and hesitant in her movements at times, and different points in her ges-
tural narrative have different emotive consequences. To clarify this aspect more
investigation will be required. There were, nevertheless, several instances where
the control of both hand and voice described by the tau coupling analyses were
obviously very close, and we chose these for further attention. At several points
within her performance the way she moved her hand was the same as the way
JB[v.20020404] Prn:7/03/2007; 17:10 F: AICR6816.tex / p.16 (713-747)
Figure 6. Graph showing mean kappas, for hand and voice for 12 repetitions of the down-
ward pitch change, shown in Figure 5 (time is normalized for the different utterances of
the word to facilitate comparison).
she moved her voice. We conclude that the ‘sameness’ would give us information
about how her brain controlled the two activities.
The area within the elliptical line in Figure 5, at the end of the phrase when
she sings the words, “to the brain”, illustrates one such moment of high concor-
dance between vocal and manual gestures. As the singer lifts and drops her voice
we can see that the Y-movement of the hand (a vertical displacement relative to
the camera) anticipates this change by a short interval, and then follows a sim-
ilar time course. When the kappa graphs for both lift and fall of the hand and
pitch change for several such coincident actions of voice and hand in the per-
formance of the song are plotted on the same graph and time is normalized so
their shape can be closely compared, the result is quite remarkable (Figure 6). The
mean kappa graphs, with error bars to indicate the standard deviation of kappa,
for 12 corresponding hand and pitch movements (pitch in black, hand in grey)
show that the temporal pattern of control for both hand and voice are very sim-
ilar indeed. Despite being movements of a very different character made by very
different motor structures, and that take place over different periods of time, they
have similar dynamic form. It can be seen, for example, in Figure 5 that the du-
ration of the downward hand movement is much longer than the corresponding
fall of pitch. The common factor is the singer’s own intended expression evident in
the pattern of control for both hand and voice. This is evidence for a single source
JB[v.20020404] Prn:7/03/2007; 17:10 F: AICR6816.tex / p.17 (747-782)
Figure 7. The movement music cycle: A gesture or feeling is translated from the score to
the mind of a musician, and to the body of a dancer.
for these movements, a single ‘motor image’ or ‘plan’, a measure of what Bernstein
termed the Sollwert (Bernstein 1967). This and other similar experiments have led
to the formulation of a new approach to studying the expressive qualities of com-
municative behaviour, entailing a quest indicated by the simplified Figure 7 and
concerning these processes and relations: There is something measurable in the pat-
tern of flow communicative/expressive behaviour characterized in music and dance
that communicates the underlying emotion or expression. What is this something?
And how is it shared and translated between artists?
In collaboration with Professor David Lee and his team at the Perception in Action
Laboratories at Edinburgh University, we investigate the following theory: the in-
formation for communication between performers in the expressive or ‘imitative’
arts, and for the appreciation of their art by others’, relates to the special dynamic
or ‘kinematic’ properties of movements and sounds, and more specifically to the
tau-coupling information generated in the brain that determines how those kine-
matics are controlled. By means of accurate measurement of the changing form of
expressive actions in different media, perceived in their effects by different modal-
ities, it should be possible to isolate and track those components that relate to
the emotion or expression intended by the performing artist, and to the aesthetic
appreciation of their performances.
The work we report here is but a pilot study, and far from conclusive. However,
it enables us to propose that understanding the expressions of art will require fu-
ture research employing the same degree of precision. The method of tau analysis
affords a way to bring all forms of communicative behaviours in art and tech-
JB[v.20020404] Prn:7/03/2007; 17:10 F: AICR6816.tex / p.18 (782-851)
nique under one form of scrutiny that is given meaning by one theory about their
motives.
The prospect of unlocking the fundamental psychobiological building blocks
that make possible the intuitive intersubjectivity discovered in interactions be-
tween very young infants and their parents – in protoconversations, baby songs
and rhythmic games – is exciting. It must be of significance for understanding
the learning and communal functions of language, and all other forms of culti-
vated rituals of human societies, as Mary Catherine Bateson (1979) predicted. By
augmenting the innovative approach of a detailed acoustic investigation of the
patterns of ‘communicative musicality’ in mother-infant play (Trevarthen & Mal-
loch 2000) with the tau analysis procedures it should be possible to trace with
confidence the communication of shared motives and emotions of human beings
of all ages as they dance between vocal prosody and words, with feeling also made
evident by a smile or a frown, a touch or a gesture. Human conversation is a multi-
talented performance ‘orchestrated’ by an innate sense of the time and energy of
moving generated in the emotional core of the mind.
Acknowledgements
The pilot experiments were carried out, under supervision of Professor David Lee
and Ben Schögler, by undergraduate students at Edinburgh University, R. Berger,
P. Biggs, B. Harvey, J. Scriven, and E. Ward, as research projects for their Honours
Dissertations in Psychology, 2004.
References
Askenfelt, A. (1986). “Measurement of bow motion and bow force in violin playing.” Journal of
the Acoustic Society of America, 80, 50–64.
Bateson, M. C. (1971). “The interpersonal context of infant vocalization.” Quarterly Progress
Report of the Research Laboratory of Electronics, MIT, 100, 170–176.
Bateson, M. C. (1975). “Mother-infant exchanges: The epigenesis of conversational interaction.”
In D. Aaronson & R. W. Rieber (Eds.), Developmental Psycholinguistics and Communication
Disorders. Annals of the New York Academy of Sciences, Vol. 263 (pp. 101–113). New York:
New York Academy of Sciences.
Bateson, M. C. (1979). “The epigenesis of conversational interaction: A personal account of
research development.” In M. Bullowa (Ed.), Before Speech: The Beginning of Human
Communication (pp. 63–77). London: Cambridge University Press.
Beebe, B., Jaffe, J., Feldstein, S., Mays, K., & Alson, D. (1985). “Inter-personal timing: The
application of an adult dialogue model to mother-infant vocal and kinesic interactions.”
In F. M Field & N. Fox (Eds.), Social Perception in Infants (pp. 217–248). Norwood, NJ:
Ablex.
JB[v.20020404] Prn:7/03/2007; 17:10 F: AICR6816.tex / p.19 (851-974)
Stern, D. N. (1974). “Mother and infant at play: The dyadic interaction involving facial, vocal
and gaze behaviours.” In M. Lewis & L.A. Rosenblum (Eds.), The Effect of the Infant on Its
Caregiver (pp. 187–213). New York: Wiley.
Stern, D. N. (1992). “L’enveloppe prénarrative: Vers une unité fondamentale d’expérience
permettant d’explorer la réalité psychique du bébé.” Revue Internationale de Psycho-
pathologie, 6, 13–63.
Stern, D. N. (1999). “Vitality contours: The temporal contour of feelings as a basic unit for
constructing the infant’s social experience.” In P. Rochat (Ed.), Early Social Cognition:
Understanding Others in the First Months of Life (pp. 67–90). Mahwah, NJ: Erlbaum.
Stern, D. N., Hofer, L., Haft, W., & Dore, J. (1985). “Affect attunement: The sharing of feeling
states between mother and infant by means of inter-modal fluency.” In T. M. Field & N. A.
Fox (Eds.), Social Perception in Infants (pp. 249–268). Norwood, NJ: Ablex.
Stevens, C., Malloch, S., McKechnie, S., & Steven, N. (2003). “Choreographic cognition: The
time-course and phenomenology of creating a dance.” Pragmatics and Cognition, 11 (2),
276–326.
Takada, A. (2005). “Mother-infant interactions among the !Xun: Analysis of gymnastic
and breastfeeding behaviors.” In B. S. Hewlett & M. E. Lamb (Eds.), Hunter-Gatherer
Childhoods: Evolutionary, Developmental, and Cultural Perspectives (pp. 289–308). New
Brunswick, NJ: Transaction Publishers.
Thompson, E. (Ed.). (2001). Between Ourselves: Second-Person Issues in the Study of
Consciousness. Charlottesville, VA/Thorverton, UK: Imprint Academic. (Journal of
Consciousness Studies, 8, Numbers 5–7.)
Todd, N. P. (1994). “The kinematics of musical expression.” The Journal of the Acoustic Society of
America, 97, 1940–1949.
Trevarthen, C. (1974). “The psychobiology of speech development.” In E. H. Lenneberg (Ed.),
Language and Brain: Developmental Aspects Neurosciences Research Program Bulletin, 12,
570–585.
Trevarthen, C. (1979). “Communication and cooperation in early infancy. A description of
primary intersubjectivity.” In M. Bullowa (Ed.), Before Speech: The Beginning of Human
Communication (pp. 321–347). London: Cambridge University Press.
Trevarthen, C. (1984). “Emotions in infancy: Regulators of contacts and relationships with
persons.” In K. Scherer & P. Ekman (Eds.), Approaches to Emotion (pp. 129–157). Hillsdale,
NJ: Erlbaum.
Trevarthen, C. (1986). “Development of intersubjective motor control in infants.” In M. G. Wade
& H. T. A. Whiting (Eds.), Motor Development in Children: Aspects of Coordination and
Control (pp. 209–261). Dordrecht: Martinus Nijhof.
Trevarthen, C. (1987). “Sharing makes sense: Intersubjectivity and the making of an infant’s
meaning.” In Language Topics: Essays in Honour of Michael Halliday, Vol. 1 (pp. 177–199).
Amsterdam and Philadelphia: John Benjamins.
Trevarthen, C. (1998). “The concept and foundations of infant intersubjectivity.” In S.
Bråten (Ed.), Intersubjective Communication and Emotion in Early Ontogeny (pp. 15–46).
Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
Trevarthen, C. (2001a). “Intrinsic motives for companionship in understanding: Their origin,
development and significance for infant mental health.” Infant Mental Health Journal, 22
(1–2), 95–131.
JB[v.20020404] Prn:7/03/2007; 17:10 F: AICR6816.tex / p.22 (1194-1243)
chapter
Stein Bråten
University of Oslo
In this volume we have examined the origins and foundations of (pre)verbal in-
tersubjectivity in light of new findings, including the discovery of mirror neurons
and the identification of infant intersubjectivity and other-centred participation.
A number of contributions have highlighted modes of participant perception dur-
ing interaction and laid out its altercentric nature and some of its likely neurosocial
support. As the very reverse of perceiving the other – the model or the patient –
from an ego-centric perspective, altercentric participation entails the empathic ca-
pacity to identify with the other in a virtual participant manner that evokes present
moments of co-enactment or shared experience as if being in the other’s bodily
centre (cf. Bråten 1998, this volume (7); Stern 2000, 2004, this volume (2)). This
basic intersubjective capacity makes inter alia imitation, empathy, and identifi-
cation possible, as expressed by Stern. And what is more, by virtue of empathic
identification it may underlie activation of infant prosociality and even altruistic
behaviours in toddlers (cf. examples in Bråten 1996a, b; Freud & Burlingham 1973;
Whiting & Edwards 1988; Zahn-Waxler et al. 1979). No longer can the theoreti-
cal view be upheld of the egocentric toddler, dominated by the pleasure principle
(Freud 1911), awaiting a long developmental period of de-centration (Piaget 1959)
before becoming social.
In these concluding comments I shall first indicate how the capacity for other-
centred participation enables a general proclivity towards prosocial and even al-
truistic behaviour, and, then, how the altercentric capacity invites in the child as
a subject of care or abuse a mode of imitative learning by empathic identifica-
tion with the caregiver or abuser which may create virtuous and vicious circles of
re-enactment from an implicit participatory memory hidden from consciousness.
JB[v.20020404] Prn:7/03/2007; 17:13 F: AICR6817.tex / p.2 (108-165)
Finally, I shall touch upon questions on how dialogue and other-centred moments
of meeting in psychotherapy may play a role in bringing about change.
Examples of helping and altruistic behaviours afforded by toddlers invite the ques-
tion about the foundations of such prosocial behaviours. In terms of the capacity
for other-centred participation which, while innate, requires to be sensitized by
early experience, two replies are offered, the first about nature, the second about
nurture: first, altercentric capacity enables empathic identification with the pa-
tient’s distress, evoking concern and attempts to relieve the patient of his distress;
second, when subjected to caregiving, altercentricity enables the child to learn to
afford care from virtually participating in the caregiver’s activity, leaving an e-
motional memory that invites circular re-enactment towards others felt to be in
need.
Here is the first of three propositions.
(i) By virtue of the innate capacity for other-centred participation in the patient’s
distress or felt need as if experiencing that from the patient’s centre, there is a
natural proclivity in the child to feel concern and sometimes attempt to help
the patient, perhaps even at own expense, if situational and motoric resources
permit (Bråten 1997).
Even wartime children, deprived of family life, may show themselves capable of
transcending own body-centred position and egoistical needs, as shown in this
episode, reported by Anna Freud:
Rose (19 months) sat at the table and drank her cocoa. Edith (17 months) climbed
up and tried to take the mug from Rose’s mouth. Rose looked at her in surprise,
then turns the mug and holds it for Edith so that she could drink the cocoa.
(Freud & Burlingham 1973: 574)
Rose’s reaction to Edith’s clumsy attempt to get cocoa is most telling, not only be-
cause of her altruistic act, helping Edith to drink cocoa at the cost of stopping her
own drinking, but because of the way in which she reverses the mug in view of
Edith’s bodily position. By turning the mug so that Edith can drink from Edith’s
position, reverse to that of her own, Rose here demonstrates her capacity to tran-
scend her own body-centred perspective. She affords proto-care to Edith by virtue
of other-centred participation, and Rose may have learnt such mirror-reversal with
the mug when she herself has been subjected to feeding from her care-givers.
JB[v.20020404] Prn:7/03/2007; 17:13 F: AICR6817.tex / p.3 (165-212)
Empirical support: Abused toddlers are more likely to become abusive than
other toddlers, and many adult abusers have been childhood victims of abuse
Thus, prior to defence mechanisms setting in, the abused child is not just a victim
of the abuse, but virtually may take a part in the abusive and hurtful event as a
JB[v.20020404] Prn:7/03/2007; 17:13 F: AICR6817.tex / p.4 (212-263)
the re-enactment of abuse in terms of the very same life-giving mechanism that
is operative in children’s proto-care and in their re-enacting the care-giving they
have experienced.
Again, as in the case of circular re-enactment of care, no conceptual or ver-
bal “memory” is required for experiences of abuse in felt immediacy to give rise
to re-enactment. Indeed, men and women who have been subjected to incest
and abuse in their infancy or early childhood may first come to realize that they
may have been victims when a crisis breaks out in adult years. But while the ex-
perience of abuse is not re-presented in virtue of any conceptual memory, the
child is certainly affected in the most profound way. That is why the composite
term e-motional “memory”, or what Fogel (2004) participatory memory, is useful
to denote the affective experience and remembrance of moving with the other’s
motions that afford the infant the feeling of participating in the movement and ac-
companying emotions. Different from higher-order conceptual memory, this kind
of “e-motional memory” will be ineffaceably affected by abusive motions felt to be
co-enacted, and increase the likelihood of circular re-enactment of the previously
felt co-enacted movements later in ontogeny.
Being aware of the way in which the therapist’s potential model power may come
into play, expected by the client to be the source of the only valid replies, and hence
transforming the conversation into a monological conversation, they try to avoid
becoming the “narrative editor” (Anderson 1997: 96).
JB[v.20020404] Prn:7/03/2007; 17:13 F: AICR6817.tex / p.7 (384-423)
Referring to mirror neurons and adaptive oscillators, Stern makes the point that
when people move in mutual attunement and synchrony with each other, they
are participating in an aspect of the other’s experience. “They are partially liv-
ing from the other’s center” (Stern 2004: 81), i.e. entailing mutual other-centred
participation.
The kind of present moments Stern terms ‘moments of meeting’ offers reso-
lution to critical now-moments, and entails, as he puts it in his abstract for the
keynote lecture at the present symposium (this volume (2)):
mutual other-centred participation in which both partners create and undergo
a joint experience. The experience is of short duration: seconds, subjectively a
present moment. The resonant experience enlarges the intersubjective field be-
tween them ... (Stern 2004b: 8)
The threefold meaning of the term “present” gives a clue, perhaps for the
therapist-client relationship: First, they are present to one another, in each other’s
presence; second, they are in one another’s present, partially sharing here and now,
and third, each one is offering herself or himself as a gift, as a present, for such in-
tersubjective sharing which may be communion or communication constituting a
shared and novel intersubjective present. The resolution by ‘moments of meeting’
of what Stern (2004, this volume (2)) terms ‘now-moments’ opens a window to
a qualitative change, holding promise of a novel emerging future within such an
intersubjective present.
Notes
. It need not come to circular re-enactment of abuse, however; several other paths are open
to the victim. One such alternative path is to disengage from the body subjected to abuse, or
to divorce the bodily ego from the virtual alter, each running their separate course. Circular re-
enactment of abuse may be also be prevented if the previous victim’s capacity for altercentric
participation is not “turned off ” in relation to other potential victims, unless pain-seeking has
become a motivating force.
References
Anderson, H. (1997). Conversation, Language, and Possibilities. A Postmodern Approach to
Therapy. New York: Basic Books.
Berk, L. E. (1994). Child Development (3rd ed.). Boston, MA: Allyn and Bacon.
Bråten, S. (1984). “The third position – beyond artificial and autopoietic reduction. Kybernetes,
13, 157–163.
Bråten, S. (1996a). “When toddlers provide care”. Childhood, 3 (4), 449–465.
Bråten, S. (1996b). “Infants demonstrate that caregiving is reciprocal.” Centre for Advanced Study
CAS Newsletter, 2 (November), 2.
Bråten, S. (1997/2000). “What enables infants to give care? Prosociality and learning by
altercentric participation.” Centre for Advanced Study lecture in The Norwegian Academy
of Science and Letters, Oslo March 4 1997. (Printed in S. Bråten: Modellmakt og
altersentriske spedbarn. Essays on Dialogue in Infant & Adult, 231–243. Bergen: Sigma 2000.)
Bråten, S. (1999/2000). “From intersubjective communion in infancy.” The First International
Aarhus Conference on Existential Psychotherapy, Aarhus, Denmark Dec. 3–5 1999.
(Printed in S. Bråten: Modellmakt og altersentriske spedbarn. Essays on Dialogue in Infant
& Adult, 244–260. Bergen: Sigma 2000.)
Bråten, S., & Trevarthen, C. (1994/2000). “Beginnings of cultural learning.” Talk at the ZiF
symposium on The Formative process of society, Bielefeld 17–19 Nov. 1994. (Printed in S.
Bråten Modellmakt og altersentriske spedbarn. Essays on Dialogue in Infant & Adult, 213–218.
Bergen: Sigma 2000.)
Cabassi, A., & Zini, M. T. (2004). L’assistent sociale e lo psicologolo. Rome: Carocci Faber.
Dornes, M. (2002). “Der virtuelle Andere. Aspekte vorsprachlicher Intersubjektivität.” Forum
der Psychoanalyse, 18, 303–331.
JB[v.20020404] Prn:7/03/2007; 17:13 F: AICR6817.tex / p.12 (690-793)
Fogel, A. (2004). “Remembering infancy: Accessing our earliest experiences.” In G. Bremner &
A. Slater (Eds.), Theories of Infant Development (pp. 204–230). Cambridge: Blackwell.
Freud, S. (1911). “Formulations on the two principles of mental functioning.” Yearbook, 3 (1).
In Standard Edition of Freud’s Psychological Writings, 12, 215–226.
Freud, Anna (with Sophie Dann) (1951/1973). “An experiment in group upbringing.” The
Psychoanalytic Study of the Child, 6, 127–168. (Reprinted in The Writings of Anna Freud,
Vol. IV, 163–229. New York: International Universities Press.)
Freud, Anna, & Burlingham, D. (1973). “Infants without families.” In The Writings of Anna
Freud, Vol. III. New York: International Universities Press.
George, C., & Main, M. (1979). “Social interaction of young abused children: Approach,
avoidance and aggression.” Child Development, 50, 306–318.
Harris, P. L. (1989). Children and Emotion. Oxford: Blackwell.
Mead, G. H. (1932). The Philosophy of the Present. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.
Murray, L. (1991). “Intersubjectivity, object relations theory, and empirical evidence from
mother-infant interactions.” Infant Mental Health Journal, 12, 219–232.
Piaget, J. (1959). The Language and Thought of the Child. London: Routledge.
Stern, D. N. (1998). “The process of therapeutic change involving implicit knowledge: Some
implications of developmental observation for adult psychotherapy.” Infant Mental Health
Journal, 19 (2), 300–308.
Stern, D. N. (2000). “Introduction to the paperback edition.” In D. N. Stern (Ed.), The
Interpersonal World of the Infant (pp. xi–xxxix). New York: Basic Books (also London:
Karnac 2003).
Stern, D. N. (2004a). The Present Moment in Psychotherapy and Everyday Life. New York: Norton.
Stern, D. N. (2004b). “Applying developmental and neuroscience findings on other-centred
participation to the process of change in psychotherapy”. Keynote lecture at the Theory
Forum Symposium on Foundations of (pre)verbal intersubjectivity in light of new findings,
The Norwegian Academy of Science and Letters, Oct. 3–5 2004. Abstract in S. Bråten (Ed.),
Theory Forum Symposium Preproceedings, Oslo 2004: 8.
Trevarthen, C. (1979). “Communication and cooperation in early infancy: A description of
primary intersubjectivity.” In M. M. Bullowa (Ed.), Before Speech (pp. 321–347). New York:
Cambridge University Press.
Trevarthen, C., & Hubley, P. (1978). “Secondary intersubjectivity.” In A. Lock (Ed.), Action,
Gesture, and Symbol (pp. 183–229). London: Academic Press.
Vik, K. (2005). Video record of conversation with a mother with postnatal depression. Presented
at a (post)doctoral course at the University of Oslo.
Vik, K., & Bråten, S. (In prep.). Other-centred Moments of Meeting during Video-related
Therapy afforded Mothers with Postnatal Depression. Working paper. Sörlandets Hospital
Trust Research Unit, Kristiansand.
Whiting, B. B., & Edwards, C. P. (1988). Children of Different Worlds. Cambridge, MA: Harvard
University Press.
Winnicot, D. (1986). Home is Where We Start From. Hammondsworth: Penguin.
Zahn-Waxler, C., Radke-Yarrow, M., & King, Y. R. (1979). “Child rearing and children’ prosocial
initiation towards victims in distress.” Child Development, 50, 319–330.
JB[v.20020404] Prn:21/03/2007; 16:03 F: AICR68AI.tex / p.1 (42-184)
Author index
Luckmann, T. , , , Moore, M. K. , , , , Papousek, H. , ,
, , , , , , Papousek, M. , ,
Lyons-Ruth, K. Morales, M. Parnas, J.
Morgan, A. C. , Parsons, T.
Morgan, J. L. Patrick, M. P. H.
M Morosan, D. E. Paus, T.
MacKay, I. Moses, L. J. , Payne, K.
MacLean, P. D. Moss, C. Pearson, D.
Mahler, M. S. , Most, XX Peery, J. C.
Main, M. Möttönen, R. Peg, J. E.
Manthey, S. Mundy, P. Peirce, C. S. ,
Malinowsky, B. Munson, J. Pembrey, M. E.
Malloch, S. N. , , , , Murray, L. , , Perani, D.
, , , , , , Myowa, M. Perrett, D. I. , ,
Myowa-Yamakoshi, G. Perrin, J.
Maratos, O. Perucchini, P.
Marcuse, H. N Peters, K. –
Marino, L. Nadeau, S. E. Petrakos, H.
Markman, E. M. , Nagell, K. , Petrides, M.
Märtha Louise, princess Nagy, E. Petrinovich, L.
Martini, M. Nahum, J. Petty, C. ,
Masserman, J. Nakayama, K. Piaget, J. , , , , ,
Matsuzawa, T. Nehaniv, C. , ,
Mattingly, I. G. Neisser, U. Pickett, E. R.
Maye, J. , , Nelson, K. Pine, F.
Mazokopaki, K. , Neville, H. J. Pinker, S.
Mazziotta, J. C. Newport, E. L. Pires, A.
McCandliss, B. D. Nicely, P. Pisoni, D. B.
McClaskey, C. L. Nishitani, N. , , , Plomin, R.
McClelland, J. L. Nöklestad, A. Plunkett, K.
McRoberts, G. W. , Norris, K. S. Polka, L. ,
McVie, K. Nottebohm, P. Pöppel, E. ,
Mead, G. H. , , , , NRK1 (Norwegian Port, R.
, , , Broadcasting Corporation) Potter, C.
Meador, D. Pourtois, G.
Meltzoff, A. N. , , –, Nusbaum, H. C. Povinelli, D. J.
–, –, , , , , Preisler, G.
, , , , , , O Premack, D.
, , , , , , Ochs, E. Preston, S. D. , , , ,
, , , , , , O’Connell, S. M. Prinz, W. , ,
, , , , Ohta, M. Proust, M. ,
Mendes, I. Oller, D. K.
Mendes, P. Ono, K. R
Menzel, E. Oppenheim, D. Radke-Yarrow, M.
Merleau-Ponty, M. , Oram, M. V. Rall, J. ,
Meyer, J. A. , Osterling, J. Reddy, V. , , , , ,
Miller, P. , ,
Mills, D. L. , P Repacholi, B. M. ,
Michotte, A. Pallier, C. Reich, V.
Mitra, P. P. Pandya, D. N. Reiss, D.
Moll, H. Panksepp, J. , , Reuf, A. M.
Molnár, P. Papastathopoulos, S. , , Richards, B. J.
Moore, C. , , Richards, P. –
JB[v.20020404] Prn:21/03/2007; 16:03 F: AICR68AI.tex / p.5 (637-787)
Subject index
71 Krois, John Michael, Mats Rosengren, Angela Steidele and Dirk Westerkamp (eds.):
Embodiment in Cognition and Culture. Expected September 2007
70 Rakover, Sam S.: To Understand a Cat. Methodology and philosophy. Expected July 2007
69 Kuczynski, John-Michael: Conceptual Atomism and the Computational Theory of Mind. A defense of
content-internalism and semantic externalism. x, 478 pp. + index. Expected June 2007
68 Bråten, Stein (ed.): On Being Moved. From mirror neurons to empathy. 2007. x, 333 pp.
67 Albertazzi, Liliana (ed.): Visual Thought. The depictive space of perception. 2006. xii, 380 pp.
66 Vecchi, Tomaso and Gabriella Bottini (eds.): Imagery and Spatial Cognition. Methods, models and
cognitive assessment. 2006. xiv, 436 pp.
65 Shaumyan, Sebastian: Signs, Mind, and Reality. A theory of language as the folk model of the world.
2006. xxvii, 315 pp.
64 Hurlburt, Russell T. and Christopher L. Heavey: Exploring Inner Experience. The descriptive
experience sampling method. 2006. xii, 276 pp.
63 Bartsch, Renate: Memory and Understanding. Concept formation in Proust’s A la recherche du temps
perdu. 2005. x, 160 pp.
62 De Preester, Helena and Veroniek Knockaert (eds.): Body Image and Body Schema.
Interdisciplinary perspectives on the body. 2005. x, 346 pp.
61 Ellis, Ralph D.: Curious Emotions. Roots of consciousness and personality in motivated action. 2005.
viii, 240 pp.
60 Dietrich, Eric and Valerie Gray Hardcastle: Sisyphus’s Boulder. Consciousness and the limits of
the knowable. 2005. xii, 136 pp.
59 Zahavi, Dan, Thor Grünbaum and Josef Parnas (eds.): The Structure and Development of Self-
Consciousness. Interdisciplinary perspectives. 2004. xiv, 162 pp.
58 Globus, Gordon G., Karl H. Pribram and Giuseppe Vitiello (eds.): Brain and Being. At the
boundary between science, philosophy, language and arts. 2004. xii, 350 pp.
57 Wildgen, Wolfgang: The Evolution of Human Language. Scenarios, principles, and cultural dynamics.
2004. xii, 240 pp.
56 Gennaro, Rocco J. (ed.): Higher-Order Theories of Consciousness. An Anthology. 2004. xii, 371 pp.
55 Peruzzi, Alberto (ed.): Mind and Causality. 2004. xiv, 235 pp.
54 Beauregard, Mario (ed.): Consciousness, Emotional Self-Regulation and the Brain. 2004. xii, 294 pp.
53 Hatwell, Yvette, Arlette Streri and Edouard Gentaz (eds.): Touching for Knowing. Cognitive
psychology of haptic manual perception. 2003. x, 322 pp.
52 Northoff, Georg: Philosophy of the Brain. The brain problem. 2004. x, 433 pp.
51 Droege, Paula: Caging the Beast. A theory of sensory consciousness. 2003. x, 183 pp.
50 Globus, Gordon G.: Quantum Closures and Disclosures. Thinking-together postphenomenology and
quantum brain dynamics. 2003. xxii, 200 pp.
49 Osaka, Naoyuki (ed.): Neural Basis of Consciousness. 2003. viii, 227 pp.
48 Jiménez, Luis (ed.): Attention and Implicit Learning. 2003. x, 385 pp.
47 Cook, Norman D.: Tone of Voice and Mind. The connections between intonation, emotion, cognition and
consciousness. 2002. x, 293 pp.
46 Mateas, Michael and Phoebe Sengers (eds.): Narrative Intelligence. 2003. viii, 342 pp.
45 Dokic, Jérôme and Joëlle Proust (eds.): Simulation and Knowledge of Action. 2002. xxii, 271 pp.
44 Moore, Simon C. and Mike Oaksford (eds.): Emotional Cognition. From brain to behaviour. 2002.
vi, 350 pp.
43 Depraz, Nathalie, Francisco J. Varela and Pierre Vermersch: On Becoming Aware. A pragmatics
of experiencing. 2003. viii, 283 pp.
42 Stamenov, Maxim I. and Vittorio Gallese (eds.): Mirror Neurons and the Evolution of Brain and
Language. 2002. viii, 392 pp.
41 Albertazzi, Liliana (ed.): Unfolding Perceptual Continua. 2002. vi, 296 pp.
40 Mandler, George: Consciousness Recovered. Psychological functions and origins of conscious thought.
2002. xii, 142 pp.
39 Bartsch, Renate: Consciousness Emerging. The dynamics of perception, imagination, action, memory,
thought, and language. 2002. x, 258 pp.
38 Salzarulo, Piero and Gianluca Ficca (eds.): Awakening and Sleep–Wake Cycle Across Development.
2002. vi, 283 pp.
37 Pylkkänen, Paavo and Tere Vadén (eds.): Dimensions of Conscious Experience. 2001. xiv, 209 pp.
36 Perry, Elaine, Heather Ashton and Allan H. Young (eds.): Neurochemistry of Consciousness.
Neurotransmitters in mind. With a foreword by Susan Greenfield. 2002. xii, 344 pp.
35 Mc Kevitt, Paul, Seán Ó Nualláin and Conn Mulvihill (eds.): Language, Vision and Music.
Selected papers from the 8th International Workshop on the Cognitive Science of Natural Language
Processing, Galway, 1999. 2002. xii, 433 pp.
34 Fetzer, James H. (ed.): Consciousness Evolving. 2002. xx, 253 pp.
33 Yasue, Kunio, Mari Jibu and Tarcisio Della Senta (eds.): No Matter, Never Mind. Proceedings of
Toward a Science of Consciousness: Fundamental approaches, Tokyo 1999. 2002. xvi, 391 pp.
32 Vitiello, Giuseppe: My Double Unveiled. The dissipative quantum model of brain. 2001. xvi, 163 pp.
31 Rakover, Sam S. and Baruch Cahlon: Face Recognition. Cognitive and computational processes.
2001. x, 306 pp.
30 Brook, Andrew and Richard C. DeVidi (eds.): Self-Reference and Self-Awareness. 2001. viii, 277 pp.
29 Van Loocke, Philip (ed.): The Physical Nature of Consciousness. 2001. viii, 321 pp.
28 Zachar, Peter: Psychological Concepts and Biological Psychiatry. A philosophical analysis. 2000.
xx, 342 pp.
27 Gillett, Grant R. and John McMillan: Consciousness and Intentionality. 2001. x, 265 pp.
26 Ó Nualláin, Seán (ed.): Spatial Cognition. Foundations and applications. 2000. xvi, 366 pp.
25 Bachmann, Talis: Microgenetic Approach to the Conscious Mind. 2000. xiv, 300 pp.
24 Rovee-Collier, Carolyn, Harlene Hayne and Michael Colombo: The Development of Implicit
and Explicit Memory. 2000. x, 324 pp.
23 Zahavi, Dan (ed.): Exploring the Self. Philosophical and psychopathological perspectives on self-
experience. 2000. viii, 301 pp.
22 Rossetti, Yves and Antti Revonsuo (eds.): Beyond Dissociation. Interaction between dissociated
implicit and explicit processing. 2000. x, 372 pp.
21 Hutto, Daniel D.: Beyond Physicalism. 2000. xvi, 306 pp.
20 Kunzendorf, Robert G. and Benjamin Wallace (eds.): Individual Differences in Conscious
Experience. 2000. xii, 412 pp.
19 Dautenhahn, Kerstin (ed.): Human Cognition and Social Agent Technology. 2000. xxiv, 448 pp.
18 Palmer, Gary B. and Debra J. Occhi (eds.): Languages of Sentiment. Cultural constructions of
emotional substrates. 1999. vi, 272 pp.
17 Hutto, Daniel D.: The Presence of Mind. 1999. xiv, 252 pp.
16 Ellis, Ralph D. and Natika Newton (eds.): The Caldron of Consciousness. Motivation, affect and self-
organization — An anthology. 2000. xxii, 276 pp.
15 Challis, Bradford H. and Boris M. Velichkovsky (eds.): Stratification in Cognition and
Consciousness. 1999. viii, 293 pp.
14 Sheets-Johnstone, Maxine: The Primacy of Movement. 1999. xxxiv, 583 pp.
13 Velmans, Max (ed.): Investigating Phenomenal Consciousness. New methodologies and maps. 2000.
xii, 381 pp.
12 Stamenov, Maxim I. (ed.): Language Structure, Discourse and the Access to Consciousness. 1997.
xii, 364 pp.
11 Pylkkö, Pauli: The Aconceptual Mind. Heideggerian themes in holistic naturalism. 1998. xxvi, 297 pp.
10 Newton, Natika: Foundations of Understanding. 1996. x, 211 pp.
9 Ó Nualláin, Seán, Paul Mc Kevitt and Eoghan Mac Aogáin (eds.): Two Sciences of Mind.
Readings in cognitive science and consciousness. 1997. xii, 490 pp.
8 Grossenbacher, Peter G. (ed.): Finding Consciousness in the Brain. A neurocognitive approach. 2001.
xvi, 326 pp.
7 Mac Cormac, Earl and Maxim I. Stamenov (eds.): Fractals of Brain, Fractals of Mind. In search of a
symmetry bond. 1996. x, 359 pp.
6 Gennaro, Rocco J.: Consciousness and Self-Consciousness. A defense of the higher-order thought theory
of consciousness. 1996. x, 220 pp.
5 Stubenberg, Leopold: Consciousness and Qualia. 1998. x, 368 pp.
4 Hardcastle, Valerie Gray: Locating Consciousness. 1995. xviii, 266 pp.
3 Jibu, Mari and Kunio Yasue: Quantum Brain Dynamics and Consciousness. An introduction. 1995.
xvi, 244 pp.
2 Ellis, Ralph D.: Questioning Consciousness. The interplay of imagery, cognition, and emotion in the
human brain. 1995. viii, 262 pp.
1 Globus, Gordon G.: The Postmodern Brain. 1995. xii, 188 pp.