Donald E. Knuth - Surreal Numbers
Donald E. Knuth - Surreal Numbers
NUMBERS
D. E. KNUTH
This book is to be returned on or before
the last date stamped below.
27. $/tt
H.HQV1994
62577
512.7 KNU
A/C 063577
SURREAL
NUMBERS
Reading, Massachusetts •
Menlo Park, California London • Amsterdam • Don Mills, Ontario •
Sydney
CONTENTS
1 The Rock 1
2 Symbols 8
3 Proofs 14
4 Bad Numbers 19
5 Progress 27
This book has been set in Modern Extended jfl with Albert us chapter
headings. The cover and illustrations were designed by Jill C. Knuth. 6 The Third Day 34
f.O. 7 Discovery 41
63577
8 Addition 48
C- ASS
r/a-? km 7 The Answer 55
10 Theorems 63
</. 23 JAM
N i^A. t« isjH {
1 1 The Proposal 71
/ 12 Disaster 76
13 Recovery 82
Copyright © 1974 by Addison -Wesley Publishing Company, Inc.
Philippines copyright 1974 by Addison-Wesley Publishing Company, Inc. 14 The Universe 89
All rights reserved. No part of this publication may be reproduced, stored 15 Infinity 97
in a retrieval system, or ransmitted,
I in any form or by any means,
electronic, mechanical, photocopying, recording, or otherwise, wit houl he i
prior written permission of the publisher. Printed in the United States of 16 Multiplication 106
America. Published simultaneously in Canada. Library of Congress Catalog
Card Xo. 74-5998.
v / Postscript 113
ISBN 0-201-03812-9
BCDEFGHIJ-AL-79876S
1
THE ROCK
•
""""-"•**-*.
W*v^.,
B. What?
A. I —
mean here we are on the edge of the Indian Ocean, miles
away from civilization. It's been months since wo ran off to
avoid getting swept up in the system, and "to find ourselves."
I'm just wondering if you think we've done it.
B. Actually, Alice. I 've been thinking about the same thing. These B. Hey, what's that big black rock half-buried in the sand over
past months together have been reallygreat—we're com- there ?
pletely free, we know each other, and we feel like real people A. Search me, I've never seen anything like it before. Look,
again instead of like machines. But lately I'm afraid [*ve bean some kind of
it's got graffiti on the back.
missing some ofthfl things we've "escaped" from. You know.
Can you help me dig it out ? It looks like a museum
a hook to read —any
B. Let's see.
I've got this fantastic craving for I nick.
piece. Unnh! Heavy, too. The carving might be some old
even a textbook, even a math textbook. It sounds crazy, hut
Arabian script. . .no, wait, I think it's maybe Hebrew; let's
I've been lying here wishing I had a crossword puzzle to work
turn it around this way.
on.
A. Hebrew ! Are you sure ?
A. Oh, c'mon, not a crossword puzzle; that's what your parents
B. Well. I learned a lot of Hebrew when I was younger, and I
like to do. But I know what you mean, we need some mental .
that the simple, romantic life isn't enough for me. I need Bible. Wasn't he wandering around Arabia for forty years
with his followers before going up to Israel? You don't
something complicated to think about.
suppose ....
A. Well, I'm sorry I'm not complicated enough for you. Why
B. No, no, it goes on much different from the traditional account.
don't we gel up and explore some more of the beach? Maybe
I^et's lug this thing back to our camp, I think I can work
We'll find some pebbles or something that we can use to make
out a translation.
up some kind of a game.
A. Bill, this is wild, just what you needed!
B. (sitting up) Yeah, that's a good idea. But first I think I'll take
a little swim. B. Yeah, I did say I was dying for something to read, didn't I.
5
A. It seems to be broken off at the bottom ; the stone was origin- and said that it shall be a sign to separate positive num-
ally longer. bers from negative numbers. Conway proved that zero
was less than or equal to zero, and he saw that it was
B. A good thing, or we'd never be able to carry it. Of course
good. And the evening and the morning were the day of
it'll be just our luck to find out that the message is getting
zero. On the next day, two more numbers were created,
interesting, right when we come to the broken place.
one with zero as its left set and one with zero as its right
A. Here we are. I'll go pick some dates and fruit for supper set. And Conway called the former number "one," and
while you work out the translation. Too bad languages aren't the latter he called "minus one." And he proved that
my thing, or I'd try to help you. minus one is less than but not equal to zero and zero is
B. Okay, Alice, I've got it. There are a few doubtful places, a A. Are you sure it reads like that?
couple signs I don't recognize; you know, maybe some obso- B. More or less. I dressed it up a bit.
lete word forms. Overall I think I know what it says, though
A. But "Conway". . .that's not a Hebrew name. You've got to
I don't know what it means. Here's a fairly literal translation:
be kidding.
In the beginning, everything was void, and J. H. W. H. B. No, honest. Of course the old Hebrew writing doesn't show any
Conway began to create numbers. Conway said, "Let vowels, so the real name might be Keenawu or something;
there be two rules which bring forth all numbers large maybe related to the Khans ? I guess not. Since I'm translating
and small. This shall be the first rule: Every number into English, I just used an English name. Look, here are the
corresponds to two sets of previously created numbers, shows up on the stone. The
places where it J. H. W. H.
such that no member of the left set is greater than or might also stand for "Jehovah."
equal to any member of the right set. And the second rule
A. No vowels, eh ? So it's real . . . But what do you think it means ?
shall be this: One number is less than or equal to another
B. Your guess is as good as mine. These two crazy rules for
number if and only if no member of the first number's
numbers. Maybe it's some ancient method of arithmetic that's
left set is greater than or equal to the second number, and
been obsolete since the wheel was invented. It might be fun
no member of the second number's right set is less than
to figure them out, tomorrow; but the sun's going down pretty
or equal to the first number." And Conway examined
soon so we'd better eat and turn in.
these two rules he had made, and behold they were very
!
rffr*
j-
A. I think your Conway Stone makes sense after all, Bill. I was
thinking about it during the night.
A. It's not so hard, really; the trouble is that it's all expressed
in words. The same thing can be expressed in symbols and
then you can see what's happening.
9
B. You moan we're actually going to use the New Math to de- A. Good point, but that's the whole beauty of Conway's scheme.
cipher this old stone tablet. Each element of X L and X R must have been created previ-
A. I hate to admit it, but that's what it looks like. Here, the ously, but on the first day of creation there weren't any
first rule says that every number x is really a pair of sets,
previous numbers to work with; so both X, and X R are taken
called the left set x L and the right set xR :
as the empty set!
B. I never thought I'd live to see the day when the empty set
* = (*/.. *«)•
was meaningful. That's really creating something out of
These xL and x K are not just numbers, they're sets of numbers; in the empty set.
and each number in the set is itself" a pair of sets, and so on.
A. So everything gets started all right, and that's thenumber
B. Hold it, your notation mixes me up. I don't know what's a called zero. Using the symbol to stand for the empty set,
set and what's a number. we can write
A. Okay, I'll use capital letters for sets of numbers and small
= (0, 0).
letters for numbers. Conway's first rule is that
B. Incredible.
x = (X L , XR ), where XL J XR .
(1)
A. Now on the second day, it's possible to use in the left or
This means if xL is any number in XL and HzB is any number right sets, so Conway gets two more numbers
in A'„, they must satisfy xL £ x R And
. that means xL is not
- 1 = (0, {0}) and 1 = ({()}, 0).
greater than or equal to xR .
B. (scratching his head) I'm afraid you're still going too fast B. Let me see, does this check out ? For - 1 to be a number, it
for me. Remember, you've already got this thing psyched out, has to be true that no element of the empty set is greater
but I'm still at the beginning. If a number is a pair of sets than or equal to 0. And for 1, it must be that is not greater
of numbers, each of which is a pair of sets of numbers, and than any element of the empty set. Man, that empty set
so on and so on, how does the whole thing get started in the sure gets around! Someday I think I'll write a book called
first place ? Properties of the. Empty Set.
10 11
A. You'd never finish.
These are the symbols I couldn't decipher yesterday, and
If X L or X R is empty, the condition XL £ X R is true no matter your notation makes it all crystal clear ! Those double dots
what is in the other set. This means that infinitely many separate the left set from the right set. You must be on the
numbers are going to be created. right track.
B. Okay, but what about Conway's second rule ? A. Wow, equal signs and everything! That stone-age carver must
sets are nonempty; it's the rule defining less-than-or-cqual. better than mine.
Symbolically, 15. I bet we've underestimated primitive people. They must have
had complex lives and a need for mental gymnastics, just like
x < // means XL £ y and X * )•„. (2) us —at least when they didn't have to fight for food and shel-
ter. We always oversimplify history when we look back.
B. Wait a minute, you're way ahead of me again. Look, X is
L
A. Yes, but otherwise how could we look back?
a set of numbers, and y is a number, which means a pair of
Beta of numbers. What do you mean when you write
X B. I see your point.
L
Z !/? A. Now comes the part of the text I don't understand. On the
A. I mean that every element of X L satisfies x L £ y. In other first day of creation, Conway "proves" that 5 0. Why
words, no element of XL is greater than or equal to y. should he bother to prove that something is less than or equal
B. Oh, I see, and your to itself, since it's obviously equal to itself. And then on the
rule (2) says also that x is not greater than
second day he "proves" that — 1 is not equal to 0; isn't that
or equal to any element of YR . Let me check that with the
text... obvious without proof, since -1 is a different number?
• =<:>
12 13
PROOFS
K. 1 know; but now that I think of it, I wasn't quite sure of that
word I translated "equal to." Maybe it has a weaker meaning,
15
"similar to" or "like." Then Conway's second rule becomes A. Yes, but so far we've been using the empty set in almost every
"One number is less than or like another number if and only argument, so the full implications of the rules aren't clear
if. ." And later on, he proves that Have you
.
zero is less than or like yet. noticed that almost everything we've proved
zero, minus one is less than but not like zero, and so forth. so far can be put into a framework like this: "If X and Y
A. Oh, right, that must be it, he's using the word
are any sets of numbers, then x = (0, X) and y = ( Y, 0) are
in an abstract
technical sense that must be defined by the numbers, and X ^ y."
rules. So of course
he wants to prove that is less than or like 0, in order to B. It's neat the way you've just proved infinitely many things,
see that his definition makes a number "like" itself. by looking at the pattern I used in only a couple of cases. I
B. So does his proof go through By guess that's what they call abstraction, or generalization, or
must show that ? rule (2), he
no element of the empty set is greater than or like 0, and something. But can you also prove that your X is strictly less
that is not greater than or like any element of than y ? This was true in all the simple cases and I bet it's true
the empty
set. .
.Okay, it works, the empty set triumphs again. in general.
B. Well, let's see:- 1 is (0, {0}) and is ({0}, 0), so once again
B. Hmm. You mean (
}', 0) is going to be positive only when )
1
the empty set makes - 1 < 1 by rule (2). On the other hand,
contains some number that is zero or more. I suppose you're
right. But at least we now understand everything that's on
1 < - 1 is the same as saying that £ - and £ 0, ac- 1 1
the stone.
cording to rule (2), but we know that both of these are
false.
Therefore 1 $ - 1, and it must be that - 1 < 1. Conway's A. Everything up to where it's broken off.
16 17
A. I wonder what happened on the third day.
18
BAD NUMBERS
'tn,^^
21
B. Really? I found nineteen; you must have missed two. Here's than or like y, but it shouldn't be necessary to make so many
my list:
tests. If any element of XL
> y, then the largest element of
is
<-••:> 0-> <:•> <:•> <:-•><:-!> B. Yeah, that oughta be right ...
1}, 0) just like I proved it was
I can prove that
less than
1 is less than
the extra
({(), ({1}, 0);
in your list. I don't see that this follows immediately, although it is con-
B. (blinking) So I did. Hinin ... 20 by 20, that's 400 different sistent with everything we know.
cases we'll have to consider in rule (2). A lot of work, and not B. At any rate, it ought to be true, if Conway's numbers arc; to
much fun either. But there's nothing else to do, and 1 know be at all decent. We could go ahead and assume it. but it
it'll bug me until I know the answer. would be neat to show once and for all that it was true, just
A. Maybe we'll think of some way to simplify the job once we by using Conway's rules.
get started. A. Yes, and we'd be able to solve the Third Day puzzle without
B. Yeah, that would be nice . . .
much more work. Let's see, how can it be proved ....
B. Blast these flies! Just when I'm trying to concentrate. Alice,
Well, I've got one result, 1 is less than ({1}, 0). First I had to
prove that £ ({I}, 0).
can you —no, I guess I'll go for a little walk.
22 23
A. No, I seem to be going in circles, and the £ versus < is A. Bill ! You've got it.
x < y, and y <. z, and x $ z. A. No, in each case the new bad numbers are simpler than the
original ones; one of them was created earlier. We can't go
What does rule (2) tell us about "bad numbers" like this?
on and on finding earlier and earlier sets of bad numbers, so
B. It says that
there can't be any bad sets at all
and i, £ Z„> d(x) + d(y) + d(z) = n, then one of your two cases applies
and gives three bad numbers whose day-sum is less than n.
and then also x $ z, which means w hat ! Those, in turn, will produce a set whose day -sum is still less
A. It means one of the two conditions fails. Either there is a and so on; but that's impossible since there are no three num-
bers whose day-sum is less than 3.
number x L in X L for which x L > z. M there is a number zR
24
25
B. Yes, I suppose there will be a next time . . .
B. But does that make your efforts any less creative ? 1 bet every
26
PROGRESS
x £ y and y £ x,
29
A. I suppose we could try the same technique that worked before.
A. But I . . . Okay, you're right, excuse me for going off on such
x and y are bad numbers in
If this sense, then either some a silly tangent. We have x < xLL and xLL < xL so the transi- ,
easy proof.
XL <x and x < Xa . (T2) A. Maybe you can see it, but I don't think it's obvious. At any
rate, let's try to prove
B. That shouldn't be hard to prove. What does xL % x say?
A. Either there is a number xLL in X LL , with xLL > x, or else there
x < x. (T3)
isa number xB in X R with x L > x R But the second case can't
happen, by rule (1).
.
B. I knew we were going to use B. It's curiously like (T2). But uh-oh, here we are in the same
rule (1) sooner or later. But what
can we do with xLL l I don't spot again, trying to show that x < x, is impossible.
like double subscripts.
A. Well, xLL is an element of the left set of a; Since x was A. This time it's all right, Bill. Your argument shows that x ^ x L
t L .
created earlier than x, we can at least assume that x implies xL £ x L which , is impossible by induction.
LL < x L ,
B. I^ead on. place. We've got the "A',. < x" half of (T2) proved, and the
other half must follow by the same argument, interchanging
A. Let's sec, xLL <, xL says that xLLL £ x L and . . .
left and right everywhere.
B. (interrupting) don't want to look at this—your subscripts
I
A. And like we said before, (T2) is enough to prove that all num-
are getting worse.
bers are related; in other words
A. You're a big help.
if a; $ .// then y < x. (T4)
B. Look, I am helping, I'm telling you to keep away from those
hairy subscripts! B. Right. Look, now we don't have to bother saying things so
30
31
I
32
33
THE THIRD DAY
;*&
•i
35
behave like all little
numbers should; they can be arranged
in a from smallest to largest, with every number
line,
x = (X L , XR ) is a number, and we take any other sets of
being numbers Y L and Y R where ,
greater than those to its left and less
than all those on its
right.
YL <x< YR .
B. Now it should be
pretty easy for aa to figure out what
hap-
In other words, enlarging the sets XL and XR , by adding
pened cm the Third Day: those 20 x 20
calculations must be
numbers on the appropriate sides, doesn't really change x.
in.
B. Hmm. it's both < and > 0, so it must be (I'm going to write "x m z," meaning x is like z, I mean
according to
like 0,
rule (3). As I said yesterday, it's effectively equal to 0, so we
x < 2 and 2 ^ a;.)
might as well forget it. That's eight down and welve A. That proves just what we want. For example,
I to go.
A. Let's try to get rid of thus,, ton msm where X, or XR have
more than one element, like I tried to do
yesterday morning.
<-•:> = <•:.><: -•> = <:->
I had an idea during the
night which might work.
Suppose and so on.
36
37
B. So we're left with only two cases: ^«» *\ and S\ |\ . B. (shaking his head) Incredible, Holmes!
A. Actually, (T~) applies to both of these, too, with X = 0! A. Elementary, my dear Watson. One simply uses deduction.
B. Cle-ver. So the Third Day is now completely analyzed: only B. Your subscripts aren't very nice, but I'll ignore it this time.
those seven numbers we listed before are essentially different. What would you do with the number ({a^-j}, fo + i}) if i < }1
A. I wonder if the same thing won't work for the following days, A. (ahrngging her shoulders) I was afraid you'd ask that. I don't
too. Suppose the different numbers at the end of n days are know.
day will be A. Yes, you're right, I hadn't noticed that. But all those ele-
xt
(#,{*»», <W»to». • «**-x). W). ({*«). «)•
B.
ments x,,xt+1
I suppose so . . .
in
it!
interfere.
infinitely many days in one swoop! You'll get ahead of the any of the others! So ({a^-j}, {«/ + i}) = x.
B. Anyway let's try some special eases. Like, what if we had the
number ({a-'i-i}. {*i+i})i 't would have to be equal to one of
the others. B. (smiling) The problem isn't completely solved, yet; we have
A. Sure, it equals x„ because of (T7). Look, each element of to consider numbers like (0,
{% +1}) and ({*,_,}, 0). But in the
X IL is <#(_!, and each clement of X lR is >.r, + 1
. Therefore, lirst case, we get the first -created number of Xlt x2 ., x,, , . .
by (T7), we have and in the second case it's the first-created number of r,,
x(+1 . . . ., xm .
*« = (fa-i) UX iL ,
X IR u {.r
( + 1 }). A. What number wasn't unique? I mean, what
if the first-created
ifmore than one of the x„ ...', Z; were created on that earliest
And again by (T7),
day?
= (Xil VJ fa-i}, U A' 1H B. Whoops. . . No, it's okay, that can't happen, because the proof
({*i-i}. fo+i}) fa +1 } ).
is still valid and it would show that the two numbers are both
By the transitive law. x t
= ({a^-j}, {x, + l }).
like each other, which is impossible.
38 39
A. Neato! You've solved the problem of all the days at once.
B. With your help Lei 'a see, on the fourth day there will be 8
new numbers, then on the fifth day there arc 16 more, and so
on.
A. Yes, after the »th day, exactly 2" - 1 different numbers will
have been created.
B. You know, I don't think that guy Conway was so smart after
40
DISCOVERY
...''
,.- •-"^W
43
B. Well, one of the numbers was bigger than 1. so I suppose
he A. Look, there's a cave over by that cliff. Let's wait out the storm
called it "2." And another was between and 1, so maybe Hey, really pouring!
" |." in there. it's
he called it
part.
Yup, I can make out the words "Conway" and "number,"
A. Oh, I remember was careful to note exactly where
that, I
it so it must be what we're looking for.
was in case we ever wanted to go back.
A. Oh, good, we'll have plenty to work on. We're saved!
B. What would I do Without you? Come on, let's go! But I'm going back
B. The info we need is hero all right. in the
A. Hey wait, don't you think we
should have a little lunch first? cave, it can't keep raining this hard for very long.
44
45
B. True. I've got this mad urge to get up before a class and
A. Exactly. But teachers are so conservative, they'd be afraid
present our results: Theorem, proof, lemma,
remark. I'd make of searing off the "grind" type of students who obediently
it so slick, nobody would be
able to guess how we did it, and
and mechanically do all the homework. Besides, they wouldn't
everyone would be so impressed.
like the extra work of grading the answers to nondirected
A. Or bored.
questions.
B. Yes, there's that. I guess the way to put off all creative aspects until
excitement and the beauty comes The traditional is
almost as much as making my own. ing enough exams in graduate school he's told to do something
So what's the real differ-
ence? original.
15. From now on whenever I read a math book, I'm going B. You always were an optimist. I'm afraid you're painting too
to
try to Ggure out by myself how everything was done, before rosy a picture. But look, the rain has stopped, let's lug this
looking at the solution. Even if [ rock back to camp and see what it says.
don't figure it out, I think
I'll be able to see the beauty
of a proof then.
A. And think we should also try to guess
I
what theorems are
coming up; or at least, to figure out how
and why anybody
would try to prove such theorems in the first
place. We should
imagine ourselves in the discoverer's
place. The creative part
is really more
interesting than the deductive
part. Instead of
concentrating just on finding good answers
to questions, it's
more important to learn bow to find good
questions!
B. You've got something 1hen-. wish our teachers would give us
I
46
47
ft
A. The two pieces fit pretty well, it looks like we've got almost
the whole message. What does it say I
B. This part is a little harder to figure out, there are some ob-
scure words, but I think it goes like this:
each other in this wise : The left set of the sum of two
numbers shall be the sums of all left parts of each number
49
with the other; and in like manner the right set shall be A. What a weird ending. And what do you mean "aleph day"?
from the right parts, each according to his kind." Conway
B. Well, aleph is a Hebrew letter and it's just standing there by
proved that every number plus zero is unchanged, and
itself, look: X. It seems to mean infinity. Let's face it, it's
he saw that addition was good. And the evening and the
heavy stuff' and it's not going to be easy to figure out what
morning were the third day.
iliis means.
And Conway "Let the negative of a number have
said,
A. Can you write it all down while I fix supper? It's too much
as its sets the negatives of the number's opposite sets;
for me to keep in my head, and I can't read it.
and let subtraction be addition of the negative." And it
was Conway proved that subtraction was the inverse
so. B. Okay, that'll help me get it clearer in my own mind too.
And Conway said to the numbers, "Be fruitful and multi- A. It's curious that the four numbers created on the third day
Let part of one number be multiplied by another and
ply.
aren't mentioned. I still wonder what Conway called them.
added to the product of the first number by part of the
other, and let the product of the parts be subtracted. This
B. Maybe if we try the rules for addition and subtraction we
shall be done in could figure out what the numbers are.
all possible ways, yielding a number in
the left set when the parts are of the same
of the product A. Yeah, if we can figure out those rules for addition and sub-
kind, but in the right set when they are of opposite traction. Let's see if we can put the addition rule into symbolic
kinds."
Conway proved that every number times one is unchanged. form, in order to see what it means ... I suppose "its own
And the evening and the morning were the fifth day. kind" must signify that left goes with left, and right with
(3)
And Conway looked over all the rules he had made for
numbers, and saw that they were very, very good. And B. Looks horrible. What does your rule mean?
he commanded them to be for signs, and series, and
quo- A. To get the left set of a: + you take all numbers of the form
y,
tients, and roots.
xL + y, where x L is in XL , and also all numbers y, + x where
Then there sprang up an infinite number less than in- y L is in Y L The right
. set is from the right parts, "in like
finity. And infinities of days brought forth multiple orders manner."
of infinities.
B. I see, a "left part" of # is an clement of XL . Your symbolic
That's the whole bit.
definition certainly seems consistent with the prose one.
50
51
A. And it makes sense too, because each xL + y and x + yL A. Congratulations on coming up with the world's longest proof
ought to lie less than x + y. that 1 + 1 is 2.
B. Okay, I'm willing to try it and see how it works. I see you've B. Have you ever seen a shorter proof?
called it rule (3).
A. Not really. Look, your calculations help me too. I get 1+2
A. Now after the third day, we know that there are seven num- = ({2}, 0), a number that isn't created until the fourth day.
bers, which we might call 0, 1, - 1, a, b, c, and d. B. I suggest we call it "3."
B. No, I have an idea that we can use left-right symmetry and A. Bravo. So rule (3) is working; let's check if b is \ by calculating
call them b + b ...
-a < -1 < -6 < < 6 < 1 < a, B. Hmm, that's odd, it comes out to ({6}, {b + 1}), which hasn't
been created yet.
where
A. And ft + 1 is ({6, 1}, {2}), which is like ({1}, {2}), which is
-x = (-X R , -A",).
(4)
Day I
B. Okay, 1 get ({0 + 1,0+ 1}, 0). And + 1 is ({0 + 0}, 0),
Day i -3 -(/,.|) d 6+1
+ is (0, 0) = 0. Everything fits together, making + 1 1
52 53
A. Oh + b is (b, b + 1), which is formed from rum-
I see, so 6
adjacenl numbers And our theory says it is the earliest-
. . .
A. But the sun is going down. Let's sleep on it, Bill; we've got
lots of time and I'm really drained.
54
THE ANSWER
{ftfa
57
B. (interrupting) Yeah, yesterday we were high on math, but each XL is < some yL by , (T4). Thus XL < y, and similarly, y <
today it's turning sour. I can't get it out of my system, we've XB Soy^zby
. (T7).
got to get more results before I can rest. Where's that pencil now we have
?
It's pretty easy to work out the proof that all
A. Bill, you need some breakfast. There are some apricots and this ammunition to work with.
figs over then*.
A. The nice thing about (T8) is that itmakes the calculation
B. Okay, but I've gotta get right to work. we did last night much easier. Like when we wete calculating
A. Actually I'm curious to see what happens too, but promise b + b = ({&}, {b + 1}), we could have seen immediately that
me one thing. 1 is the first number created between {6} and {b + 1}.
B. What? B. Hey, let me try that on c + c: It's the first number created
A. We'll only work on addition and subtraction today; not multi- between b + c and + c. Well, it must be 6+1,1 mean 1|,
1
so c is f
plication. Wo won't even look at that other part of the tablet
A. That's better. Now I was thinking last night about how you 3
0, I h i, I, #, 2,
solved the problem about all the numbers yesterday morning.
I think it's an important principle that we. ought to write and after five days they will probably be
down as a theorem. I mean:
B. (interrupting)
Given any number y. if x is the first number
created with the property that YL < x and 0,i,i,|, h it. i. l.i U.2,f,3, 4.
(T8)
a: < Y R then , a; = y.
A. Exactly. Can you prove it?
58 59
vinccd we have the right general pattern, but it would be
B. Sounds logical, since adding y should "shift" things over by
nice tohave a proof.
y units. Whoops, no, take x = 1 ; that would say y + 1 is
A. On the fourth day we calculated § by knowing that it was ({y}< 0)> which fails when y is $.
1 + £, not by trying 2 + 2. Maybe adding 1 will do the trick. A. Sorry. In fact, your rule for 1 + x doesn't work when x =
B. Let's see . . . According to the definition, rule either.
(3),
in this case.
B. Let's see. In the first place, addition is obviously what we
A. That's it, Bill! Look at the last eight
numbers on the fifth might call commutative, I mean
day, they are just one greater than the eight numbers on the
fourth day.
x + y = y + x. (T9)
B. A perfect fit. Now all we have to do is prove the pattern for A. True. Now let's prove what Conway claimed, that
the numbers x between and 1 ... but that can always be
done by looking at x + x + = x. (T10)
x, which will be less than 2!
A. Yes, now I'm sure we've got the right pattern. B. The rule says that
B. What a load off my mind. I don't even feel the need to form- x + = (X L + 0, XR + 0).
alize the proof now; 1 know it's right.
XR + is XR ,
since all those numbers were created before x.
'J + * = (V + XL , y + XR ) ?
Q.E.I).
60
61
to, since it really won't make any difference. But actually
doesn't the proof actually show that x + is identically the 10
same pair of sets as x ?
A. Excuse me again. You're right.
B. That's ten theorems. Shall we try for more while we're hot ?
G2
10 THEOREMS
in*
(x + y) + z = x + (y + z). (Til)
65
.
One associative law, coming right up. Can you work out the A. In fact, we might as well prove a stronger statement,
definition ?
B. You're really
then x + w < y + z\
good at these hairy formulas. But how can such
monstrous things be proved equal ?
A. Oh, that follows from (T13), since x + w<y + w = iv+y
A. It's not hard, just using a day-sum argument on (x, y, z) as <z + y = y + z.
we did before. See, (X L + y) + z = XL + (y + z) because H. Okay, that's good, because (T13) is simpler. Well, you're the
(#l- ?/- 2) has a smaller day-sum than (a;, y, z), and we can expert on formulas, what is (T13) equivalent to?
The same for the other
induct on that. five sets, using the
commutative law in some cases. A. Given that XL < y and x < YR , we must prove that X, + z
66
67
B. Hmm. The converse would go through by induction— except A. The same statement also follows immediately from rule (2);
that we might have a case with, say, xL + z < y + z but I mean, y < if and only if Y L < and < y if and only
*,. y. Such cases would be ruled out by (T13), but . . . if < }' B So now what we have to prove is
.
Xr + (-**) = 0?
B. (glowing) Alice, you're a genius! An absolutely gorgeous, tan-
A. Yes, since we can be proving (T15) by induction.
talizing genius!
A. Not so B. Then I've got it! If x L + (-x) were >0, then (-A')„ + xL
fast, we've still got work to do. We had better show-
that would be >0, by definition. But (-.X) R is -(X L ), which con-
tarns -xL , and (-x,) + x L is not >0. Therefore xL + (-x)
x —x= 0. (T15) must be < 0, and the same technique works for the other
cases too.
B. What's that minus sign We
? never wrote down Conway's rule
for subtraction.
A. Bravo! That settles (T15).
B. What next?
A. x ~ y = x + (-y). (5)
A. How about this I
B. 1 notice you put the m in (CIS); okay, it's clear that % + ( -*)
B. Uh oh, it looks hard. How do we show something = any- B. What's that equivalent to ?
way ? ... By (T8), y m if and only if Y L < and < >'„, A. It's a real mess . . . Can't we prove things without going back
since was the first created number of all. to the definitions each time ?
68
B. Aha! Yes, it almost falls out by itself:
11
(X + y) -y = (x + y) + (_ y) by (5)
= X+ (y + (-y)) by (Til)
= x + (y - y) by (5)
=x + by (T12) and (T15)
= X. by (T10)
but I don't think they involve any new ideas; so there's little
point in proving them unless we need 'em.
B. Nineteen theorems, from just a few primitive rules.
70
11 THE PROPOSAL
war AX
B. (lying down beside her) Mostly because of the fresh fish you
caught.
to be some balance.
B. Oh no, don't misunderstand me. These past few days have
B. Well, isn't learning really a process of self-discovery
all
? Don't
shown me that pure mathematics is beautiful it's an art form —
the best teachers help their students to think like poetry or painting or music, and it turns us on. Our natural
on their own ?
A. In a way, yes. Whew, we're getting philosophical.
curiosity has to be satisfied. It would destroy us if we couldn't
have some fun, even in the midst of adversity.
B. I still can't get over how great I fed when I'm doing this crazy
mathematics; A. Bill, it's good to talk with you like this.
it really turns me on right now, bin 1 used to
hate it.
B. I'm enjoying it too. It makes me feel closer to you, and sort
74
75
12 DISASTER
«;-~
B. No!
A. Yes, and i © J
= |. But then I tried (-i) © i, and I was
stopped cold.
A. Yes, the definition of addition isn't legitimate unless we can © ©
prove that L + y < Xr X + y, and X L + y < YR +
B. You mean . . . ? I see, ( - i) © ft
= ({(- 1) 0}, {0 1}),
or, and
which is ({0}, {0}).
> L +x < XR + y, and YL + x < YR + x.
B. These would follow from (T13)
A. And that's not a number. It breaks rule (1).
and (TI4), but ... I see your
point, we proved (TI3) and (T14) assuming that the sum of
B. So your definition of © wasn't legit.
two numbers is a number. How did you ever think of this A. And I realized that you can't just go making arbitrary defi-
problem ? nitions: they have to be proved consistent with the other rules
A. Well, that's kind of interesting. I was wondering what would too. Another problem with © was, for example, that ({ — 1},
happen if we defined addition like this: 0) s Obut({-l},0)©l ft 0©1.
*®y«<x£ e B. Okay, © is out, but I suppose we can fix up the real definition
>'/, A'„ © r fi ).
of +.
I called this © because it wasn't obviously going to come out A. I don't know; what I've just told you is as far as I got. Except
thesame as + But it was pretty easy to see that I thought about pseudo-numbern.
.
O©* = A. Right. And I just noticed that our proof of the transitive law
(Tl) didn't use the £ part of rule (1), so that law holds for
for all x.
pseudo-numbers too.
B. Ouch! Maybe © means multiplication? B. Yes, I remember saying that the full rule (1) wasn't used
A. Then I proved that
© x = for x >
1 1 all 0, and 2 ©x = 2
until (T2). That seems like a long time ago.
for all x > 1, and 3 © x = 3 for x > all 2, and A. Now get ready for a shock. The pseudo-number
. . . . ({1}, {0}) is
B. For <
I see. all and u, m
positive integers m
» is the minimum © neither nor 2: !
78
79
and only if y > l, and it is> a number x if and only if x < 0. A. Good idea . . . Hey, the same proof goes through for all
It's not related at all to any numbers between and 1.
pseudo-numbers: x is always like x.
B. Where's the pencil? 1 want to check that out ... I think
B. This is great but I'm afraid it's taking us away from the main
you're .right. This is fun, we're proving things about quantities problem, whether or not + is well-defined.
that don't even exist.
A. Well, our proofs that x y = y + x, x + = x, and even+
A. Well, do pseudo-numbers exist
any less than Conway's num- the associative law, work for pseudo-numbers as well as num-
bers ? What you mean is, we're
proving things about quantities bers. If the inequality theorems (T13) and (T14) also go
that are purely conceptual,
without real-world counterparts through for pseudo-numbers, then + will be well-defined.
as aids to understanding . . . Remember that V=l was once
B. I see, that's beautiful! So far we've established (Tl), (T3),
thought of as an imaginary number,
and VI wasn't even
('IT)), (TO), (T9), (T10), (Til) for all pseudo-numbers. Let's
thought to be "rational."
look at (T13) again.
B. Conway's rule for adding normal
numbers also gives us a
way to add pseudo-numbers. A. But I'm afraid . . . uh, oh. Bill! We were too gullible yesterday
I wonder what this leads to«
If* = in our acceptance of that day-sum proof for (T13) and (T14);
({!}, {0}), then 1 +x is . . .
({2}, {1}).
it was too good to be true.
A. And x + x is ({1 + *•}, {*}), a secon d-order pseudo-number.
B. What do you mean ?
B. Pure mathematics is a real mind-expander.
A. We were proving that ZL + x < y + z by induction, right?
But did you notice that
({1}, {0}) isn't even < itself? Well, to get this it takes two steps, first ZL + x <, ZL + y
A. I.H s see. * < , ,„ean.s that A', < * < A'*, so this could only and then Z L + y < z + y. Induction gives us the first part
be true if XL < XR .
all right, but the second part involves (2,. z, y), which might
No, wait, we aren't allowed to use "<" have a larger day-sum than (x, y, z).
i„ place of "%*> for
pseudo-numbers, since (T4) isn't true in
general. We have to B. So we really blew it. Conway would be ashamed of us.
go back to the original rule
(2), which says that x < x if and
A. Good thing we didn't see this yesterday, or would have
only if X L i x and x > X So it
R ({1}, {0}) is «s itself after all.
.
80
81
—
13 RECOVERY
i
.
mt
if^" 1
'*•-
HET, •
*-*.:^*J0^^Kw _
L _ .. ;
., /
83
A. (beginning to eat) Well, when m ware going around in circles I(* t ,y), I(*,Y L ), l(XR ,y), I(x,Y B ),
like this before, how did we break out? The main thing was III(X R> X L , y),
to use induction, I mean to show that the
proof in one case IU(x,Xu y), U(y,YR ,x),
depended on the truth in & previous case, which
on a still previous case, and so on, where
depended 111(2/, }',, x), U{x, XR , y),
the chain must Ill(Y R ,YL ,x).
eventually terminate.
B. Like our day-sum argument. For example, we have to prove among other things that
Xi. + y < YR + x. In other words, for and y R all xL in XL
A. Right. The other way we broke
the circle was by proving more in Y R we should have previously established that x L + y
than we first thought we needed. I mean, in order to
keep the < y R + x. Now III(x, x L y) and (T3) show that x +
,
L y
induction going, we had to keep proving several things simul- < x + and U(y, y R x) shows that y + x < y R + x. Right
y, , ?
taneously.
A. It looks good; except I don't see why you included those first
B. Like when you combined (T13) and (T14). Okay, Alice, four, 1(X L y) through I(a;, Y R ). I mean, even if xL + y wasn't
right ,
84
85
come we thought we'd have to prove that tho sum of two
I think it was a good idea to introduce this new notation,
numbers is a number, before proving (T13)?
like I(x, y) and so on, because it makes the patterns become
A. That was before we knew much about pseudo-numbers. clearer. Now all we have to do is find some way to rig up an
It's
strange how a fixed idea will remain as a mental induction hypothesis that goes from these six things to
block!
Remember ? This was the first reason we said it was going to \\(x,y,z).
be hard to prove x + y is a number, because we thought A. But uh-oh. it doesn't work. Look, lV(x, y, z) depends on
(T13)
depended on After learning that pseudo-numbers satisfy
this. IV(2, z L , y), which depends on IV (y R , y, z), which depends on
the transitive laws, we forgot to reconsider the original IV(z, z L y) again; we're in a loop. It's the same stupid prob-
,
source of trouble. lem I noticed before, and now we know it's critical.
B. So at least this big picture method is getting us B. (pounding the dirt) Oh no! Well, there's one more thing
somewhere, . . .
VI(X t *', y, y% ,
86
87
!
Hey, this is actually easier than the other one. the symmetry
is helping. 14
Finally, to prove VI (*, x', we need
y, y'), . . . the suspense is
killing me, I can't think . . .
88
I 14 THE UNIVERSE
.•
k
m
„,.w.
B. You lemma I never look for mistakes. But a thought did strike
me: Here we're supposed to have rules for creating all the
91
!
expecting to see it on the "fourth day." hut the number B. After infinitely many days. I guess (.'on way looked out over
turned out to ho kind of thought, well.
j. |
J a little slow
is all those binary numbers he had created, and . . . Omigosh!
>" arriving, but it will get here sooner or later. Just now it I bet he didn't stop.
struck me that we've analyzed all the numbers, but still
,]
A. You're right I never though* of it before, but the stone does
has never showed. I
92
93
— !
greater than zero and less than all positive real numbers! We
H. (hugging her again) So might
what the Conway Stone means
that's call it e.
94
95
taken X„ = {1, |, J, |, ^ . , .
J.
Also, there are lots of other
crazy numbers in there, like
15
(OMH.li, li.lA,...})
96
15 INFINITY
,..
••
m,
&
^mm
to + 1 - ({a,, 2, 3, 4, 5, . . .
}, 0),
which simplifies to
to + 1 m ({to}, 0).
99
A. That was created on the day after X day.
I guess we can call this 2co, even though we don't have multi-
B. Right, and plication yet, because we'll certainly prove later on that
« + I - ({«}, {« + !})•
will be created on (3X) day, and so on.
A. What about co - 1? B. We still don't know about multiplication, but I'm willing to
bet that co times will turn out to be
B. co — 1! I never thought of subtracting from infinity, because co
all integers, yet less than co. we'd start shouting about who knows the largest number.
1'ivtty soon one of the kids found out from his dad that
A. So that's what the Stone meant about an infinite number less
infinity was the largest number. But I went him one better
than infinity.
by calling out "infinity plus one." Well, the next day we got
Okay, I've got another one for you, what's co + w? up to infinity plus infinity, and soon it was infinity times
B. Easy: infinity.
CO + IT = (CO + I!/, CO + Tl R ).
A. Then what happened?
B. Well, after reaching "infinityfinityfinityfinity . .
." repeated as
This was created on . . . (2X) day ! And so were co + e and long as possible without taking a breath, we sort of gave up
co — e. the contest.
A. Oho! Then there must also be a number 2co. I mean, co + co. A. But there are still a lot more numbers left. Like
B. Yup, "»" = ({«. "2 , CO
3
, CO*,... }, 0).
100
101
B. You mean, there's a/ ", to°> °",
and the limit of this, and so on. in XL . If this assumption is false, then xLL + hasn't been
Why didn't I think of that when I was a kid? proved equal to x lL for some x LL ; or, I guess, some x LR might
be the culprit. Any counterexample would imply an infinite
A. It's a whole new vista . . . But I'm afraid our proofs aren't
sequence of counterexamples.
correct any more, Bill.
A. All we have to do now is show that there is no infinite ancestral
B. What ? Not again. We already fixed them.
sequence of numbers.
Oh-oh, I think I see what you're getting at. The day-sums.
-
Xi, .x 2, x$, a;
A. Right. We can't argue by induction on the day-sums because 4, . . .
B. Maybe our theorems don't even work for the infinite cases. B. That's a nice way to put it.
of "bad numbers." What we had to show was that if a theo- created" which we glossed over in rule (1). Yes, that's it,
rem fails for x, say, then it also fails for some element xL in rule (1) will be on a rigorous footing if we formulate it in this
B. (whistling) I see. For example, in our proof that x + = x, (y, z, x L ) and so on.
we have a: + = (X L + 0, A' R + 0). We want to assume by A. Exactly. But in every case, the induction went back to some
induction that xL + has been proved equal to xL for all xL permutation, of the variables, with at least one of them getting
102 103
an additional L or Ii subscript. Fortunately, this means that B. Let's sec, n + it = (n + Y\ L , n + II R ), which . . . Okay, I see,
there can't be any infinite chain such as there arc infinitely many branches of the calculations but they
all terminate after finitely many steps.
(x, y, z) -> (y, z, x L ) -* (z R . y, x L ) -+ . . .
,
A. The neat thing about the kind of induction we've been using
and so on; if there were, at least one of the variables would is that we never have to prove the "initial case" separately.
quence of ancestors of to, for all n. B. Yeah, I guess, but this is all too deep for me. I'm ready to
B. Right. I've just been thinking about the ancestral sequences tackle multiplication now, aren't you ?
2
of co . They're all finite, of course; but they can be so long, the
liniteness isn't even obvious.
A. This unbounded liniteness means that we can make valid
proofs, for example, that 2 X it m n + ir, but we can't neces-
sarily calculate u + «• in a finite number of steps. Only God
can finish the calculations, but we can finish the proofs.
104 105
MULTIPLICATION
A. Let's see that paper where you wrote down Conway's rule
for multiplication. There must be a way to put it in symbols
. . . Hmm, wc already know what he means by "part of the
same kind."
B. Alice, this is too hard. Let's try to invent our own rule for
107
Why don't we just do like he did for addition. I mean, xy
A. That's it, the product of positive numbers must be positive!
should lie between X,j/ \JxYt and X Ry
Uil'„. At least, it
and
ought to do this
The other three conditions for xy to lie between its left
when negative numbers are excluded.
right sets are essentially saying that
A. But that definition would be identical to addition, so the
product would turn out to be the same as the sum. (*r ~ x)[y R - y) > 0,
(* - xL )(yR - y) > 0,
B. Whoops, so it would ... All right, I'm ready to appreciate
{xR - x)(y - yL ) > 0.
Conway's solution, let's look at that paper.
A. Don't feel bad about it, you've got exactly the right attitude. Okay, the definition looks sensible, although we haven't
Remember what we said about always trying things first ? proved anything.
B. Hah, 1 guess that's one lesson we've learned. B. Before we get carried away trying to prove the main laws
A. The best can make out about multiplication, I want to check out a few simple cases
I is that Conway chooses the left set
of xy to be all numbers of the form just to make sure. Let's see . . .
xy = yx; (T20)
Xi2) + xyL - *dfc or x^ + xyR - x RyR ,
0y = 0; (T21)
iy = y. (T22)
and the right set contains all numbers of the form
You see, the left set gets the "same kinds" and the right set
gets the "opposite kinds" of parts. Does this definition make -(xy) = (-*),/. (T23)
any sense ?
B. Right on. Look, here's a fun one:
B. I.enimc see, it looks weird. Well, xy is supposed to be greater
than its left part, so do we have \x = (l_X L U(Z- U' fi ),
(x - JZL U ) JA' fi ). (T24)
xy > xtf + xyL - x,y L ! A. Hey, I've always wondered what half of infinity was.
- \u>m ({1,2,3,4,...},
(* xL )(y - yL ) > 0.
{(o - 1, cu - 2, w - 3, to - i, ... }).
108
109
! — !
It's interesting to prove that |tu + Jw = o> . . Wow, here's A. Hmm . . . What about division ? ... I bet if x is between
another neat one:
and 1, it'll be possible to prove that
eta a 1,
1
1 -
1 + x
Our infinitesimal number turns out to be the reciprocal of
infinity ({x, X - X2 + X3 X
,
- X2 + x3 - X* + X5 },
{x - X2 X - X2 +
, X3 - X*, . . . }).
A. While you were working that out, I was looking at multipli-
cation in general. It looks a freaky for pseudo-numbers
little
At least, this is got J, for x = i. Perhaps we'll be able
how we
I found a pseudo-number p for which ({1}, Q)p is not like
to show that every nonzero number has a reciprocal, using
({0, 1}, Q)p, even though ({1}, 0) and ({0, 1}, 0) are both equal
some such method.
to 2. In spite of this difficulty, I applied your Big Picture
method and B. Alice! Feast your eyes on this!
I think it is possible to prove
for arbitrary numbers. It will follow that xy is a number B. (glancing at the sunset) There are infinitely many things yet
110 111
POSTSCRIPT
Tho reader may have guessed that this is not a true story. The late Hungarian mathematician Alfred Renyi composed three
However, "J.BL W. H. Conway" does exist -he is I'rol'rssor stimulating "Dialogues on Mathematics," which were published by
John Horton Conway of Cambridge University. The real Holdeii-Day of San Francisco in 1!)67. His first dialogue, set in ancient
Conway has established many remarkable results about t bese
Greece about 440 B.C., features Socrates and gives a beautiful descrip-
rxtraordinal" numh.rs, beaidee wlml has been mentioned tion of the nature of mathemat ics. The second, which supposedly takes
here. For example, every polynomial of odd degree, with place ill 212 u.c, contains Archimedes' equally beautiful discussion of
arbitrarynumbers as coefficients, has a root. Also, every the applications of mathematics, Renyi's third dialogue is about math-
pseudo-number p corresponds to a position in a two-person ematics and science, and we hear Galileo speaking to us from about
game between players Left and Wight, where the four A.D. 1600.
relations have prepared Surreal Numbers as a mathematical dialogue of the
I
1970's, emphasizing the nature of creative mathematical explorations.
p > 0, P < 0, Of course, I wrote this mostly for fun, and I hope that it will transmit
P = 0, P °II
some pleasure to its readers, but I must also admit that I also had a
correspond respectively to the four conditions serious purpose in the back of my mind. Namely, I wanted to provide
some material which would help to overcome one of the most serious
I.'fi wins. Right wins.
shortcomings our present educational system, the lack of training
in
Second player wins, First player wins.
for research u oikhere is comparatively little opportunity for students
: t
112 113
^
ably faithful portrayal of the important principles, techniques, joys,
4. After Chapter 6. When we are developing the theory of Conway's
passions, and philosophy of mathematics, so I wrote the story as I was
numbers, from these few axioms, is it legitimate to be using the
actually doing the research myself (using no outside sources except a
properties we already "know" about numbers, in the proofs?
vague memory of a lunchtime conversation I had had with John
(For example, the use of subscripts like i — 1 and j + 1, and so
Conway almost a year earlier).
I have intended this book primarily for college mathematics
on.) [Warning: This may lead to a discussion about mctamathe-
matics for which the instructor may have to be prepared.]
students at about the sophomore or junior level. Within a traditional
math curriculum it can probably be used best either (a) as supplemen- 5. After Chapter 9. Find a complete formal proof of the general pat-
tary reading material for an "Introduction to Abstract Mathematics" tern after n days. [This makes an instructive exercise in design of
course or a "Mathematical Tx)gic" course; or (b) as the principal text notations. There are many and the students should
possibilities,
in an undergraduate seminar intended to develop the students' strive to find a notation that makes a rigorous proof most under-
abili-
ties for doing independent work. standable, in that it matches Alice and Bill's intuitive informal
Books which arc used in classrooms usually are enhanced by exer- proof.]
cises; so at
the risk of destroying the purity of this "novel" approach, 6. After Chapter 9. fa there a simple formula telling the day on which
I have compiled a few suggestions for supplementary problems. When a given binary number is created ?
m=(f(XL)V{g(x)}J(X R )).
Now develop the theory of Conway's numbers from scratch, using
Prove that/(.r) < J(y) if and only if a: < y. Then in the special case these definitions. [This leads to a good review of the material in
that g(x) is identically 0, evaluate /(a:) for as many numbers as you the first chapters; the arguments have t<> be changed in several
can. [Note: After Chapter 12, this exercise
makes sense also when places. The major hurdle is to prove x < x for all numbers; there
"numbers" are replaced by "pseudo-numbers."] is a fairly short proof, not easy to discover, whieh I prefer not to
3. After Chapter Let x,y be numbers whose
5. left and right parts are reveal here. The students should be encouraged to discover that
"like" but not identical. Formally, let the new < relation is not identical to Conway's, with respect to
pseudo-numbers (although of course it is the same for all numbers).
fi.'- Xl-*Yu Sr- Xk
In the new case, x < x does not always hold; and if
Ul-Y l gR :YB -+Xa
be functions such that/jzj xL ,fR (x R = xR> gL(yL ) m yL gR(yR )
)
* = ({({0}, {0})}, »),
,
114 115
Show how 17. After Chapter Hi. Call x a real number if —n < x < n for some
10. After Chapter 13. to avoid Alice and Bill's circularity
problem another way, by eliminating 111(2, Z L y) and l\l(Z R z, x)
(nongeneralized) integer n, and if
, ,
from the requirements needed to prove II(:e, y, z). In other words, x=({z- l,x- lx- I ...},{x +l,x+ l,x+ {, .. .}).
prove directly that we can't have z + y < zL + y for any 2,,.
Prove that the real numbers are closed under addition, subtrac-
11. After Chapter 14. Determine the "immediate neighborhood" of tion,and multiplication, and that they are isomorphic to real
each real number during the first few days after X day. numbers defined in more traditional ways. [This exercise and those
12. After Chapter 15. Construct the largest infinite numbers you can which follow were suggested by John Conway.]
think of, and also the smallest positive infinitesimals. 18. After Chapter 16. Change rule (1), allowing {X L , XR ) to be a number
13. After Chapter 15. Does it suffice to restrict A',, and X„ to countable only when X £ X R and the following
L condition is satisfied:
sets? [This is difficult but it may lead to an interesting discussion. XL has a greatest element if and only if XH has a
The instructor can prepare himself by boning up on ordinal num- least element.
bers.]
Show thai precisely the real numbers (no more, no less) are created
14. Almost anywhere. What are the properties of the operation de- in these circumstances.
fined by
19. After Chapter 16. Find a pseudo-number p such that p +p = ({0},
xoy = (X L nY L ,X R vY R )1 {0}). [This is surprisingly difficult and it leads to interesting sub-
problems.]
[The class should discover that this is not min(a:, y)\ Many other
20. After Chapter 15 or The pseudo-number ({0}, {({0}, {0})}) is >0
16.
operations are interesting to explore, e.g., when x ° y is defined to
and <x numbers x. It's really infinitesimal! But
for all positive
be
({0}, {({0}, { — 1})}) is smaller yet. And any pseudo-number p >
or (X L i
y uxoY L ,X K uYR ) 21. After Chapter 16. For any number x define
15. After Chapter 16. If X is the set of all numbers, show that (X, 0)
is not equivalent to any number. [There are paradoxes in set (p«* I «*sXjM n = l,2,3,...n.
theory unless care is taken. Strictly speaking, the class of all
numbers isn't a set. Cf. the "set of all sets"' paradoxes.] Prove that m'u" = mz * v .
Hi. After Chapter 16. Call x a generalized integer if 22. After Chapter Explore the properties of the symmetric pseudo-
16.
(
PL P R )eS
, if and only if P L = PR £ 5.
Show that generalized integers are closed under addition, subtrac-
In other words, the elements of S have identical left and right sets,
tion, and multiplication. They include the usual integers », as
as numbers like <u + n, £u>, etc. [This exercise is due
and so do the elements of their left and right parts. Show that S
well to Simon
is closed under addition, subtraction, multiplication. Explore fur-
Norton.]
116 117
ther properties of S (e.g., how many unlike elements of S are as well as on the mathematical content; say 50-50. They must be told
created on each day, and is their arithmetic interesting in any that a math term paper should not read like a typical homework paper.
way?). [This open-ended problem is perhaps the best on this list, The latter is generally a collection of facts in tabular form, without
because there is an extremely rich theory lurking here.] motivation, etc., and the grader is supposed to recognize it as a proof;
I will send hints to the solutions of exercises 9, 19, and 22 to any the former is in prose style like in math textbooks. Another way to
bona fide teachers who request them by writing to me at Stanford provide experience in writing is to have the students take turns pre-
University. paring resumes of what transpires in class; then all the other students
Now I would like to close this postscript with some suggestions willbe able to have a record of the discussions without being distracted
addressed specifically to teachers who will be leading a seminar based by taking notes themselves. In my opinion the two weaknesses in
on this book. (All other people, please stop reading, and close the book our present mat hematics education are the lack of training in creative
at once.) thinking and the lack of practice in technical writing. I hope that
Dear Teacher: Many topics for class discussion are implicit in the the use of t his little book can help make up for both of these deficiencies.
story. The first few chapters will not take much time, but before long Stanford, California D.E.K.
you may well be covering less than one chapter per class hour. It may May 1974
be a good idea for everyone to skim the whole book very quickly at
first, because the developments at the end are what really make he- I
different.) Another ground rule for the students is that they should
check over the mathematical details which arc often only hinted at;
this is the only way they can really learn what is going on in the book.
Preferably they should tackle a problem first themselves before reading
on. When an ellipsis, i.e., " . .
.
also be told that they will be graded on their English expository style
118 119
\
512.
Dm