Bolzano, Cauc y and "New Ana Sis" of Ear Nineteent Century
Bolzano, Cauc y and "New Ana Sis" of Ear Nineteent Century
Summary
Ill t h i s p a p e r 1 I discuss t h e d e v e l o p m e n t Of m a t h e m a t i c a l a n a l y s i s d u r i n g t h e
second a n d t h i r d decades of tile n i n e t e e n t h c e n t u r y ; a n d in p a r t i c u l a r I a s s e r t t h a t
t h e w e l l - k n o w n c o r r e s p o n d e n c e o f : n e w ideas to b e f o u n d in t h e w r i t i n g s of BOLZANO
a n d CAueHY is not a coincidence, b u t t h a t CA~ICH¥, h a d r e a d one p a r t i c u l a r p a p e r of
BOLZANO a n d d r e w o n its r e s u l t s w i t h o u t a c k n o w l e d g e m e n t , T h e reasons for t h i s
c o n j e c t u r e i n v o l v e n o t o n l y t h e t e x t s ill q u e s t i o n b u t also t h e s t a t e of d e v e l o p m e n t
of m a t h e m a t i c a l a n a l y s i s itself, CAUClty b o t h as p e r s o n a l i t y a n d as m a t h e m a t i c i a n ,
a n d t h e rivalries w h i c h were p r e v a l e n t i n P a r i s a t t h a t time.
Contents
t. I n t r o d u c t i o n . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 372
2. T h e C o m m o n I d e a s in BOLZAI~O a n d C,~ucI~,Y . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 373
3. T h e N e w A n a l y s i s . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 378
4. T h e Old A n a l y s i s . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 38t
5. CAUCI~Y'S O r i g i n a l i t y as a M a t h e m a t i c i a n . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 384
6. T h e S t a t e of P a r i s i a n M a t h e m a t i c s . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 387
7. CAtJCHY'S P e r s o n a l i t y . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 393
8. T h e A v a i l a b i l i t y a n d F a m i l i a r i t y of BOLZANO'S W o r k . . . . . . . . . . . 395
9- Tile P e r s o n a l R e l a t i o n s b e t w e e n BOLZANO a n d CAUCHY . . . . . . . . . . 397
10. E p i l o g u e . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 398
I n d e x of N a m e s . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 400
1. I n t r o d u c t i o n
T h e c e n t r a l t h e m e of t h i s p a p e r is a n h i s t o r i c a l c o n j e c t u r e c o n c e r n i n g t h e
d e v e l o p m e n t of m a t h e m a t i c a l a n a l y s i s i n t h e e a r l y n i n e t e e n t h c e n t u r y . I t is
w e l l k n o w n t h a t t h e m a j o r e v e n t w a s t h e p u b l i c a t i o n i n t 8 2 1 of t h e Cours d'Ana-
1 T h i s p a p e r is a revised a n d g r e a t l y e x p a n d e d v e r s i o n of a l e c t u r e e n t i t l e d "Did
C a u c h y r e a d B o l z a n o before w r i t i n g his Cours d'Analyse?" g i v e n a t tile Problem-
geschichte der Mathematik s e m i n a r a t Oberwolfach, W e s t G e r m a n y , o n t h e 26 th No-
v e m b e r , 1969. I wish to t h a n k Professors J. E. HOFMANN a n d C . J . SCRIBA for t h e i r
i n v i t a t i o n t o t h i s seminar.
T h e t e x t d r a w s f r e q u e n t l y o n m y h i s t o r y of The Development o/ the Foundations
o/ Mathematical Analysis /rom Euler to Riemann a n d Joseph Fourier 1768--1830,
w h i c h are b o t h to be p u b l i s h e d b y t h e M.I.T. Press a n d are referred t o ill l a t e r foot-
n o t e s as Foundations a n d Fourier, respectively. Tile l a t t e r w o r k was w r i t t e n w i t h t h e
c o l l a b o r a t i o n of Dr. J. R. R A V E T Z , a n d t h e f o r m e r w i t h t h e help of his d e t a i l e d
criticism: I w i s h to r e c o r d h e r e m y i n d e b t e d n e s s t o his assistance.
]3olzano, Cauchy and New Analysis 373
term "continuous" was usually confined to functions which we now call "dif-
ferentiable". 4 There were efforts to move away from this view, including by
EULER himself; but nobody had come at all close to the formulation of continuity
given b y BOLZANOand CAUCHY:
BOLZANO: "A function /(x) varies according to the law of continuity for all
values of x which lie inside or outside certain limits, is nothing other than this:
if x is any such value, the difference /(x +co)--/(x) can be made smaller than
any given quantity, if one makes w as small as one ever wants to. ''~
CAUCHY: "The function /(x) will remain continuous with respect to x between
the given limits, if between these limits an infinitely small increase of the variable
always produces an infinitely small increase of the function itself".*
One of the most interesting and important features of this formulation of
continuity is that it extends the old formulation beyond that of differentiability,
for it also encompasses functions with corners. I think that BOLZANOwas aware
of the extension in t8t7, for in later manuscripts he studied the distinction
between the new continuity and differentiability to the extent of constructing
a continuous non-differentiable function of the type studied later only by the
school of WEIERSTRASSin the t870's. ~ But CAUC~IYseems to have seen the new
idea only as a reformulation of the old one when he wrote the Cours d'Analyse,
for the examples he gave there of continuous functions were all of standard
a
differentiable algebraic expressions, with the functions x~ for negative a, and x '
regarded as "discontinuous" at x----0 since they then became infinite) In fact,
he explicitly discussed the distinction only in a paper of 1844, and then in a
way which tried to give the impression that he had known it all along:
"In the works of Euler and Lagrange, a function is caned continuous or
discontinuous, according as the diverse values of that function, corresponding
to diverse values of the variable ... are or are not produced by one and the same
equation . . . . Nevertheless the definition that we have just recalled is far from
offering mathematical precision; for the analytical laws to which functions can
be subjected are generally expressed by algebraic or transcendental formulae
[that is, b y the EULERIAN range of algebraic expressions~, and it can happen that
various formulae represent, for certain values of a variable x, the same function:
then, for other values of x, different functions."
He then quoted the example
(20
V ~ -- 2 f x~ / xifx=>0
~. t~fidt=t_xif x < O, (t)
0
EULER'S classic presentation of his theory of functions was given in the opening
sections of both volumes of his Introductio ad analysin in/initorum (2 vols: 1748,
Lausanne) = Opera Omnia, (1) 8 - - 9 .
5 B . B O L Z A N O , Beweis, preface, part IIa.
A.-L. CAUCI~Y,Cours, 34--35 = Oeuvres, (2) 3, 43.
7 See B. BOLZANO, Functionenlehre (ed. K. RYCHLIK), in his Schriflen, 1 (1930,
Prague), esp. pp. 66--70, 88--89.
8 A.-L. CAvcI~Y, Cours, 36--37 = Oeuvres, (2) 3, 44--45.
Bolzano, Cauchy and New Analysis 375
in which the first two forms are " c o n t i n u o u s " in EULER'S sense while the third
is " d i s c o n t i n u o u s " ;
"... b u t the indeterminacy ceases if for Euler's definition we substitute t h a t
which I have given [in the Cours d ' A n a l y s e j - . 9
2.2. Convergence of a Series. A m a j o r innovation of the new analysis was the
s t u d y of the convergence of a series (or of classes of series) as a general problem
separate from and indeed prior to t h a t of its s u m m a t i o n ; b u t it would be wrong
to presume t h a t the problem of convergence h a d previously been ignored or
taken for granted. 1 7 th and t8 *h c e n t u r y mathematicians were perfectly well
aware t h a t a series was to be interpreted as a t e r m - b y - t e r m addition of its
members, and t h a t individual series (usually series of constant terms or certain
power series) could be shown to be convergent, especially if t h e y were associated
with some geometrical limiting procedure such as the approximation to a curve
b y a polygon. B u t this understanding had been endangered during the 18 th
century, especially b y EULER'S great ability to devise complicated new methods
of summation of series. T o d a y we understand t h a t some of these methods reduce
to orthodox smnmation for orthodox convergent series and some do n o t ; b u t
EULER and his contemporaries seemed to have regarded all methods as legiti-
mate, giving " t h e " sum of the series rather than its sum relative to the m e t h o d
of summation involved. This more sophisticated understanding began to develop
only in the t 890's, under the leadership of BOREL: 1° until then, series considered
" d i v e r g e n t " (that is, oscillatory series as well as those with an infinite sum)
had been banished from analysis under the influence of CAUCHY'S work. B u t he
and BOLZANO were not the first to consider the convergence of a series to be an
i m p o r t a n t p r o p e r t y w o r t h y of investigation of its own. GAUSS had even a d v a n c e d
as far as a sophisticated convergence test b y t 8t 211: FOUI~IER h a d already treated
the convergence of particular examples of his series in 1807, in his first paper on
the diffusion of heatl~: LAGRANGE h a d tried to find expressions for the remainder
term of a TAYLOR series, in connection with his long held belief t h a t the series
could serve as the foundation of the calculus; 13 and LACROIX was also aware of
the need for general formulation of convergence. ~4 B o t h BOLZANO and CAOCHY
also stressed t h a t the convergence of a series is to be determined only b y the
t e n d e n c y of the n th partial sums to a limiting value s as n tended to infinity; ~5
9 A.-L. CAuci~¥, "M6moire sur les fonctions continues ou discontinues" C.R.
Acad. Roy. Sci., 18 (t844), 1t6--130 (see pp. t16--117) = Oeuvres, (t) 8, t45--160
(pp. 145--146).
10 For extended discussion, see my Foundations, ch. 4.
11 K. F. Gauss, "Disquisites generales . . . " Comm. Soc. Reg. Sci. Gdltingen Rec.,
2 (18t1--13: publ. 1813), cl. math., 46pp. = Werke, 3, 123--t62: see art. 16. For a
history of convergence tests, see the appendix to my Foundations.
13 j. B. J. FOURIER, " Sur la propagation de la chaleur," MS. 1851, Ecole Nationale
des Ponts el Chaussdes, Paris: see arts. 42--43. The publication of this entire manuscript
constitutes the body of m y Fourier: see there ch. 7 on this point.
13 See especially his Thdorie des/onctions analytiques .... (2nd edition: 1813, Paris)
= Oeuvres, 9: part 1, arts. 35--40.
i~ See especially his Traild du calcul diJ/drentiel et du calcul intdgral (Ist edition:
t 797--t800, Paris), 1, 4--9.
15 B. BoLzAxo, Beweis, art. 5. A.-L. CAIJCHY, Cours, t 2 3 - - t 2 5 = Oeuvres, (2) 3,
114--t15.
376 I. GRATTAN-GUINNESS:
thus this correspondence is not so striking, although the idea was still then v e r y
m u c h a new one. B u t in both works we find a new t y p e of result, not to be found
in any other c o n t e m p o r a r y writing. BOLZANO had defined a class of series:
"... which possess the p r o p e r t y t h a t the variation (increase or decrease) which
their value suffers through a prolongation Eof terms] as far as desired remains
always smaller t h a n a certain value, which again can be t a k e n as small as one
wishes, if one has already prolonged the series sufficiently f a r " , 1~ and then he
proved t h a t for series with this property,
"... there always exists a certain constant value, and certainly only one,
which the terms of this series always approach the more, and towards which t h e y
can come as close as desired, if one prolongs the series sufficiently f a r . " ~ CAUCHY
stated t h a t :
" F o r the series 1u, to be convergent it is yet necessary t h a t for increasing
values of n the different sums
u~ + u ~ + 1 +u~+~
~C . . . . .
Beweis, art. 5.
lS B . BOLZANO,
Beweis, art. 7.
17 t3. BOLZANO,
is A.-L. CAUCHY, Gouts, t24--125 = Oeuvres, (2) 3, 115--116.
19 A.-L. CAOCHY, Cours, 125 =Oeuvres, (2) 3, 115. My italics.
Bolzano, Cauchy and New Analysis 377
only b y WEIERSTRASS and his followers. Is CAUCHY wrote just once on the real
number system: it was in the Cours d'Analyse, where he gave a superficial formal
exposition of the real number system. The initial stimulus for this work was
foundational questions concerning the representation of complex numbers; but
he took the development of the ideas well into BOLZANO'S territory, twice in-
cluding the remark that "when B is an irrational number, one can obtain it b y
rational numbers with values which are brought nearer and nearer to i t " 37 _
merely a remark on a property of the real numbers and not as a definition of the
irrational number in the sense of the later work, as has sometimes been thought.
Once again CAUCHY did not fully appreciate the depth of BOLZANO'S thought;
and yet it is clear from his partial success that he was aware of ]3OLZANO'Sideas,
rather than from his partial failure that he was ignorant of them. The striking
feature of this remark, as with his interpretation of continuity and his only
incomplete use of the upper limit, is that it is there at all, rather than that it appears
in a mutilated form.
dY-=D~ "h~o
dx lim[ /-(x+h)--/(x) ' (2)
we m a y quite easily obtain the value of the derivative involved; but we are left
with the important foundational question of how t h a t value is obtained in light
0
of the fact that the ratio on the right hand side of (2) becomes ~- when h = 0.
The virtue of infinitesimals, quantities which obeyed the law
a +h=a (3)
of addition to the " o r d i n a r y " numbers, was that, being non-zero they avoided
the limiting value and therefore the difficulty of ~-;
0 on the other hand, being
smaller than " a n y assignable q u a n t i t y " (that is, any non-infinitesimal), they
effectively allowed the limit to be taken. This view was of course an inconsistent
one, but I think that it lay basically behind infinitesimalist reasoning and was
the source of its difficulties. The infinitesimal was either zero or non-zero,
according to the needs of the moment: thus it could be added to or withdrawn
from any quantity in an equation, with the presumed certainty of leaving the
mathematical situation described b y that equation undisturbed. We m a y see
this as a double-interpretation for the infinitesimal -- a limit-avoiding inter-
pretation as a non-zero quantity, and what we m a y call b y contrast a "limit-
achieving" interpretation as an essentially zero quantity allowing the limit to
be taken. From this distinction there follows a corresponding double-inter-
29 In the Beweis ]3OLZANOdid not explicitly discuss the possible continua, and
seemed to have allowed the use of infinitesimals; but later in the year he published
another pamphlet, on Die drei Probleme der Recti/ication, der Complanation und die
Cubirung, ohne Betrachtung des unendlich Kleinen . . . . und ohne irgend eine nicht s~reng
erweisliche Voraussetzung gel6st; ... (t817, P r a g u e ) = Schri/ten, 5 (t948, Prague),
67--138.
26*
380 I. GRATTAN-GUINNESS:
dy
pretation of d x ' Let us take a specific example of a derivative, say for the
function
y = xL (3)
whose derivative
dy
dx = 3 x2 (4)
is calculated from
dy
d. =Dr.
lim[ (X+h)8--x3 ] • (5)
k~o t k
When h achieves its limiting value zero (4) gives us the value of the derivative,
dy
and so the denoting symbol ~ is in fact just a symbol and is not to be taken as
an arithmetical ratio " d y + d x " . Thus it is not valid to multiply through (4) by
dx to obtain
dy = 3 x2dx. (6)
(6) follows from (4) b y turning from the limit-achieving interpretation of dd--~-Yxas
a whole symbol to its limit-avoiding interpretation, where it is the r a t i o " d'y +dx".
For if we avoid the limiting value b y the non-zero infinitesimal quantity dx, then
we see from the right hand side of (5) that the situation for the increment dy
(=d(x~)) is given by
dy = 3 x~ dx + q, (7)
a+q=a (8)
o=o, (1o)
The ideas that I have presented here are essentially straightforward, and are
susceptible of considerable extension; but they are independent of the modern
interest in developing a consistent theory of infinitesimals. 8° They do not them-
selves establish a consistent infinitesimalism but at least show that much can
be clarified in terms which could have been understood and developed in the
infinitesimalist period. Yet they were far from the considerations of the time: in
particular, CAUCHY'S treatment of the foundations of the calculus was as in-
coherent and incompetent as any that were ever offered. In his Rdsumd des
le9ons ... sur le calcul in/initdsimal of 1823, the next instalment of his new anal-
ysis after the Cours d'Analyse, he explicitly rejected LAGRANGE'S faith in
TAYLOR'S series, but he replaced it with an extraordinary theory of the derivative
which made simultaneous use of both LAGRANGE'S theory of derived functions
/' ( x ) , / " ( x ) , ... and also of CARNOT'S theory of differentials dx, ddx, ... : infini-
tesimals not only achieved the limit in CAUCHY'S system but they also avoided it,
at times b y non-infinitesimal amounts, changing their role with every appearance
of new and usually unnecessary notation. 31 However, when CAUCHY came to
integration he was wonderfully successful, laying out the whole basic structure
of the theory of the "CAucH¥ integral" (defined in terms of the area as the
limit of a sum) in a masterly display of the power of the new analysis of limit-
avoidance.
This is what the new analysis was: only in limit-avoidance terms can its full
power and subtlety be appreciated, and theorems such as the necessary and
sufficient condition for convergence in the diminishing of ( s ~ + ~ - s,) - - where the
limit s is avoided altogether - - and BOLZANO'S theorem on the existence of upper
limits, can be seen to their best advantage. Yet to understand BOLZANO and
CAUCH¥'S work we must look at the old as well as the new. W h a t sort of analysis
had they replaced ?
tions. The analytical techniques themselves - - which involved not only dif-
ferentiation and integration, but also summation and rearrangement of series
(especially power series), manipulations of algebraic expressions, the taking of
limiting cases (in moving from difference to differential equations for example),
and so on - - were normally used as required without consideration of their
validity. This is not intended as a criticism, but merely a general statement of
the situation: it led to an enormous range of results in pure and applied mathe-
matics which have remained important ever since. Further, there were cases when
questions of rigour and validity did arise, of which the most important was the
problem of the motion of the vibrating string; 32 but ill general the situation at
the beginning of the 19 ~ century was that not only were such considerations
relatively limited but the techniques themselves were susceptible of, and received,
plenty of further development without concern for the rigour involved. This is a
m a t t e r of great importance when considering the " n e w analysis" of BOLZANO
and CAUCHY. Their new foundations, based on limit avoidance, certainly swept
away the old foundations, founded largely on faith in the formal techniques; but
it would be a mistake of posterior wisdom to assume that old foundations had
been in a serious and comprehensive state of decay and were recognised as such
b y those who were using them. Historians of science seem to be only too ready
to make assumptions of this kind when considering "revolutions" in science:
they also tend to identify anticipations of a new system in the old one with that
new system instead of what they probably were, something else in the old system
which was quite different and also interesting. The historiographical point here
is the danger of determinism; that because a body of knowledge developed in a
particular way, then it must be viewed historically as having been capable of
developing only t h a t way, certainly from the intellectual point of view and per-
haps even chronologically. Yet in fact any situation is always open to a variety
of future developments: we must not allow the intermediate historical processes
that actually happened to distort our vision of the situation from which they
started.
I have already claimed that the new analysis replaced an old analysis which
does not seem to have needed such a radical replacement: from the point of view
of the BOLZANo-CAucHY question, it follows that it is all the more surprising that
exactly the same type of replacement began to emerge twice within four years.
But we must consider also the anticipations of the new system ill the old one.
The " n e w analysis" laid great stress on the rigour of processes: did no "old
analyst" t r y to do the same ? Yes, certainly, but not ill any way resembling the
comprehensive and homogeneous character of the new method: they had other
ideas which were quite different and also interesting. EULER tried hard, though
with little practical success, to produce a consistent infinitesimalism in his
"reckoning with zeros", including consideration of different orders of infinitesi-
mal. D'ALEMBERT tended to distrust infinitesimals altogether, while LAGRANGE
tried to avoid all limiting processes b y defining the derivatives of a function in
terms of the coefficients of its expansion as a TAYLol~ series. This was "limit-
avoidance" of a completely different and considerably less successful kind, and
it won few supporters. One of them, however, was ARBOGAST, WhO tried towards
the end of the century to reduce the number of distinctions between types of
function to a group based on analytical rather than algebraic or mechanical
considerations. L'I-IuILIER offered a thoughtful essay on the taking of limits:
I am sure that CAISCHYread it, for he always used the notation " l i m " for a
limiting value which L'HuILIER introduced there. But I doubt if he learnt much
more from it, for the results obtained are severely limited, being concentrated on
the derivative and often providing no more than a re-writing of known ideas.
L'HIJILIEI~ also criticised (with iustice) EULEI~'S use of infinitesimals, and CARNOT
took it further into a profound essay on orders of the infinitely small and the
interpretation of the LEIBNIZIAN notations as infinitesimals. But perhaps the
best example, especially from the point of view of anticipations of BOLZAI~Oand
CAUCHY, iS LACROIX, the principal text-book writer of the day. He was not an
important creative mathematician, but he was capable of some measure of
appreciation of contemporary work and he read exhaustively among the earlier
literature. I referred earlier to his understanding of convergence of series as a
general problem, which he learnt from D'ALEMBERT'S vague warnings against
divergent series in the t760's: he also gave in t806 a formulation of continuity
vaguely similar to that of BOLZANOand CAucI~Y.3~ Thus we m a y say that LACROlX
anticipated them if we wish; yet it would be more misleading than illuminating
to do so, not least to the understanding of LACROIX'S results. For one cannot
find in LACROIX'S writings the general aim that BOLZANO and CAI~CI~Yachieved,
not even in the new editions of his works that continued to appear after CAUCI-IY'S
text-books were published.
What would have happened if CAUCH¥ had not read BOLZANO? Without
doubt, foundational questions would have received discussion, but it seems to
me most unlikely that the radical reform that in fact happened would have taken
place: rather only parts of that theory would probably have emerged, especially
in the convergence of series and the integral as the limit of a sum, while the rest,
apparently sound enough, would have received well-meaning but limited ex-
amination. But in order to put the old and the new analyses into better perspective
we must describe some of the fundamental problems which were current before
BOLZANO'S paper; and at the same time we shall pass on to further aspects of
the CAUCHY-BoLZANOquestion, aspects which involve not only analysis itself
but also the Paris in which CAUCHY was working and the way in which his
mathematical genius was inspired.
~ S. ~'. LACROIX, Traitd dldmentaire du calcul intdgral (2nd edition; 1806, Paris):
see art. 60. The other works to which we referred explicitly were L. F. A. ARBOGAST,
Mdmoire sur la nature des/onctions arbitraires qui ent~ent dam les intdgvales des dquations
aux diHdrentielles partielles (t 791, St. Petersburg) : S. L'HuILIER, Exposilion dldmentaire
des principes des calculs supdrieures (1786, Berlin), esp. chs. I and a I ; and L. N. M.
CARNOT, Re/lexions suv la mdtaphysique du calcul in/initdsimale (1st edition: 1797,
Paris. 2nd edition: 1813, Paris). On EULER'S and LAGRANGE'Sviews on analysis, see
A. P. JUSCI-IKEWITSCI-I, Euler and Lagrange ~ber die Grundlagen der Analysis," Sam-
'"
melband der zu Ehren des 250. Geburtstages Leonhard Eulers (ed. K. SCI-IRODER:1959,
Berlin), 224--244; and on all these and other developments, m y Foundations, chs. 1 and 3.
384 I. GRATTAN-GUINNESS:
f xcosax dx (t4)
• si~b~ t + x~ "
0
a
Put in modern terms, if we regard the integral as a function of ~- then it has a
discontinuity of magnitude ~ at the odd multiple values of its argument. CAVCHY
had b y separate equations evaluated the left- and right-hand limiting values of
a a
the function for ~- < t a n d s - > t" but in the t814 instalment of his book LEGE~-
DI~E had used a power series expansion method on a generalisation of (t4) to
produce in a limiting case the arithmetic mean of CAUCHY'S two evaluations for
a
b - - t , and he could not understand that this new type of algebraic expression
- the integral representation -- could in fact give a discontinuous function.
-
f f o,
Yl J('l
~7-x d x d y - - .
X1
ff Yl
,
-~x d y d x = .
0
f ES(X + p , Y +q) (t5)
- - S ( X + p , Y - - q ) -- S ( X - - p , Y +q) + S ( X - - p , Y - - q ) ] d p ,
os
where ~ has an infinity at the point (X, Y) inside the rectangle bounded by
the sides, x = x1, x = x 2, y = yl and y = Y2.3~ His later fine achievements in the
new analysis with the theory of integration may be traced in large part to the
issues involved in the profound result (15).
In the following year of 18t5 CAVC~IYhad another large paper ready, this
time on the propagation of water-waves. 3s Complex variables were again present,
as they were to be in all of his mathematical output; and integrals were also to
be found, for the prominent new feature here was tile use of integral methods to
solve linear partial differential equations (and thus to use again the integral
representation of a function). The inspiration in this case is not so easy to trace,
as it is impossible to say how much of FOURIER'S then still unpublished work on
heat diffusion he had seen; but he knew of POlSSON'S (lesser) work in the same
field, and doubtless he was aware of some results of LAPLACE which we shall
discuss later. At all events, in 18t 7 his further researches brought him to "Fou-
rier's Integral T h e o r e m " :
oo oo
/(x) =
0 0
in a short paper whose rushed and excited tone suggests that he had really found
the result independently of FOURIER.39 FOURIER acquainted him with his own
prior discovery of the theorem, and then CAUCHY certainly did read his manu-
scripts: not only did he publish an acknowledgement in 1818, 40 but in all his
later work on integral solutions to partial differential equations there was a new
confidence and dexterity, and again -- extensions and generalisations (to multiple
integral solutions, and so on) of what FOURIER had already done. 41
And then we come to t 82t and tile Cours d'Anatyse: large numbers of theorems
on all aspects of real and complex variable function theory, based on the ideas
which we listed in our section 2. From where had the inspiration come this time ?
From within CAucI~= himself ? Perhaps; but it is so utterly untypical of his kind
of achievement whereas under the hypothesis of his prior reading of BOLZANO it
is SO perfect an example of it, that it seems difficult not to accept the latter
possibility. Perhaps I can best illustrate the force of this point b y describing m y
own researches into the development of the foundations of analysis during this
period. I had started naturally enough with CAUCHY'S Cours d'Analyse and his
other contributions to analysis, and in the course of reading other of his writings
his need for an initial external stimulus to his genius had become clear to me.
Thus I wanted to find the source of the new ideas of the Cours d'Analyse, and so
I made a special search of all of CAOCHY'S work written prior to 182t. I found
m a n y important things, especially the 18t 4 integrals paper and the disagreement
over (t4) with LECENDRE, and the affair of 1817 over FOU~IER'S Integral Theo-
rem (16): there was clearly plenty of motivation for CAUCHY to t r y to improve
analytical techniques. But of the new ideas that were to achieve that aim -- of
them, to m y great surprise, I could find nothing. Only later did I follow up m y
knowledge that BOLZANO had done " s o m e t h i n g " in analysis which no-one had
read (or so I thought) ; and I can remember quite clearly the extraordinary effect
of reading BOLZANO'S 18t7 pamphlet and seeing the Cours d'Analyse emerging
from its pages. I then re-read the Cours d'Analyse and found the fine details of
3 . A.-L. CAUCHY, "Sur une loi de r6ciprocit6 qui existe entre certaines fonctions",
Bull. Sci. Soc. Philom. Paris (1817), 121--124 = Oeuvres, (2) 2, 223--227.
~0 A.-L. CAucI~Y, "Second note sur les fonctions r6ciproques", Bull. Sci. Soc.
Philom. Paris (t8t8), 178--181 = Oeuvres, (2) 2, 228--232.
4, For discussion of these developments, see my Fourier, chs. 21 and 22; and
BURKHARDT 3a, chs. 8--11 passim.
Bolzano, Cauchy and New Analysis 387
correspondence; but more than that, I could see CAlsCI~Y'Smind at work in its
own individual way, taking the fragments of BOLZANO'Sthought as he had taken
LEGENDRE'S morsels and FOURIER'S substantial achievements earlier, and pro-
ducing from them whole new systems of mathematical thought.
But if CAUCHYowed so much to BOLZANO,why did he not acknowledge him ?
To answer this question, we move more fully into the social situation of the time:
to Paris, the centre of the mathematical world.
~4 For the references of this manuscript, see 12; and for a detailed analysis of its
contents, see my "Joseph Fourier and the revolution in mathematical physics",
Journ. Inst. Maths. Applics., 5 (t 969), 230--253. Much new information on FOURIER'S
life and Prefectural responsibilities is contained in my Fourier, ch. t.
4~ S. D. POISSON, "M6moire snr les solutions particuli~res des 6quations diff6ren-
tielles et des 6quations aux diff6rences", Journ. Ec. Polyt., call. 13, 6 (1806), 60--116
(pp. 109--t11).
46 S. I). POlSSON, "M6moire sur la propagation de la chaleur darts les corps solides",
Nouv. Bull. Soc. Philom. Paris, 1 (1808), t t 2 - - t t6 ~ FOURIER'SOeuvres, 2, 2t 3--221.
]3olzano, Cauchy and New Analysis 389
had risen to a strong political position, having been appointed sdcretaire perpdtuel
of the Acaddmie des Sciences in 182t; and then there developed the second of
our major controversies, which directly involved CAUCHY'S Cours d'Analyse --
the convergence problem of FOURIER series.
FOURIER series contain many of the problems which we tackle b y means of
the new analysis, but we have not yet described any of FOURIER'S work in that
field. The reason is that, although he understood all the basic analytical problems
-- convergence, the possibility of discontinuous functions, the integral as an
area -- before both BOLZANO and CAUCHY had begun their work, he was not
strongly attracted to pure analysis as a study and so did not develop his own
understanding to the extent of that which he was capable. ~2 Doubtless CAUC~IY
was aware of this fact, for in the Cours d'Analyse he put the following theorem:
P ~
" W h e n the different terms of the series [ ~ u~ are functions of the same
[--r=l J
variable x, continuous with respect to that variable in the vicinity of a particular
value for which the series is convergent, the sum of the series is also a continuous
function of x in the vicinity of that particular value."sa
The theorem is remarkable for its falsehood: it was known in its day to be
false, and indeed CAUCHYknew it was refuted when he put it in his book. But to
find the reasons why it was included, we must examine the type of counter-
examples which were then known. They were in fact FOURIER series:
+~
a, = ~ /(u) cos r u d u , r = 1, 2 . . . . (20)
+=
b,---- I f /(u) s i n r u d u , r = 1, 2 . . . . . (2t)
The trigonometric functions are continuous, and so the series on the fight hand
side of (18) is covered by CAUCHY'S theorem: thus if [(x) is discontinuous, tile
series cannot be convergent to it. But FOURIER had produced several series of
discontinuous functions, and had shown by direct consideration of their n th
partial sums that they were convergent; and since t8t 5 POlSSOX had found that
he had had to abandon his belief in functional and power series solutions in favour
of FOURIER series solutions, and he had found similar examples also. So what was
CAUCHY'S purpose in stating his theorem ? There was of course an intellectual
aspect to it, for CAUCHY did have a proof: suffice it to say for now that the
52 I n t h e 1807 m a n u s c r i p t 1~, see arts. 4 2 - - 4 3 , 6 4 - - 7 4 : i n t h e 1811 p a p e r ~1, see
p a r t 1, 2 6 9 - - 2 7 3 a n d 3 0 4 - - 3 1 6 : i n t h e b o o k 50 ( m o s t l y w r i t t e n b y 1815), see a r t s .
1 7 7 - - I 79 a n d 2 2 2 - - 2 2 9 .
5a A.-L. CAUCHY, Cours, 1 3 1 - - t 3 2 = Oeuvres, (2) 3, 120.
t3olzano, Cauchy and New Analysis 39t
f 1 --
(1__p2)
2p cos (xI(~)
-- ~) +p2 d ~ ; 56 (22)
5~ A.-L. CAUCHY, " N o t e sur les s6ries convergentes ...", C. R. Acad. Roy. Sci.,
36 (1853), 454--459 = Oeuvres, (1) 12, 30--36. For a detailed account of the intro-
duction of modes of convergence, see my Foundations, ch. 6. The relevance of CAUCHY'S
theorem in the Cours is especially connected with one paper important in the develop-
ment of modes of convergence: P . L . SEIDlgL'S "Note tiber eine Eigenschaff der
t~eihen, welche discontinuirlichen Functionen darstellen", Abh. Akad. Wiss. Mi~nich,
7 (t 847--49), m a t h : p h y s . KI., 381--393. This paper (by a pupil of DIRICHLET!) dealt
explicitly with that theorem in the light of discontinuous FOURIER series, and is more
than likely to have been the (unmentioned) inspiration of CAUCHY'S paper of five
years later.
55 A detailed description is given in my Foundations, eh. 5.
5 6 S.-D. PolssoN, "M6moire sur la mani~re d'exprimer les fonctions ..." Journ.
7. Cauchy's Personality
If CAUCHY was one of the greatest mathematicians of his time, he was one
of the most unpleasant personalities of all time: a fanatic for Catholic and Bour-
bonist causes to the point of perversion, he had to prove his superiority at all
times over even the weakest of his contemporaries and to publish a virtually
continuous stream of work. He also wrote articles on education, the rights of the
Catholic and Bourbon causes, and the reform of criminals, to supplement his
mathematical output; but he never helped and even at times hindered his
younger colleagues in their careers and work. A good example of this concerns a
young man who wrote the following of him:
" C a u c h y is a fool, and one can't find any understanding with him, although
he is the mathematician who at this time knows how mathematics should be
treated ... he is extremely catholic and bigoted . . . . "
The writer was ABEL, in a letter sent to his friend HOLMBOE when, like
DIRICHLET, he visited Paris in October, t826. ea Poor ABEL: he cannot have
known how right he was, just as he did not understand the Parisian political
situation. While in Berlin during the previous January, he had written a paper
on convergence tests and their application to the binomial series which made
important use of the new analysis: he had also spotted the weakness in CAUCHY'S
theorem of the Cours d ' A n a l y s e and made the first public mention of the point
in a footnote to the paper. 84 Later in the same letter to HOLMBOE he remarked:
" I have worked out a large paper on a certain class of transcendental functions
to present to the Institut. I am doing it on Monday. I showed it to Cauchy: but
he would hardly glance at it. And I can say without bragging t h a t it is good.
I am very curious to hear the judgement of the I n s t i t u t . . . . " ~
This was the paper which ushered in the transformation of LEGENDRE'S theory
of elliptic integrals into his own theory of elliptic functions; and the story of its
fate is only too characteristic of Parisian science and of CAUCtIY. CAUCIIY and
L E G E N D R E w e r e the examiners: CAUCHY took it and, perhaps because of ABEL'S
footnote against his theorem, ignored it entirely: only after ABEL'S death in
t829 did he fulfil a request to return it to the A c a d d m i e des Sciences. I t was
finally published in 184t, when the manuscript vanished in sensational circum-
stances, to be rediscovered only in the t950's. This story is well-known ;~ however,
there is one aspect of it which has been little remarked upon but which shows
the depths to which CAUCH¥ could sink. When ABEL'S paper was in the press
another Norwegian mathematician presented a paper to the A c a d d m i e des Sciences
on elliptic functions. CAUCHYwas again an examiner, and his report contains the
following words:
" G e o m e t e r s know the beautiful works of Abel and of Mr. Jacobi on the
theory of elliptic transcendentals. One knows that of the important papers ...
one of them in particular was approved b y the Acaddmie in t829, on the report
of a commission of which Mr. Legendre was a part ECAucHYhimself having been
the other!l, then crowned by the Institut in 1830, and that the value of the prize
was remitted to Abel's mother. In fact this illustrious Norwegian, whom a pro-
ject of marriage had determined to undertake a voyage in the depth of winter,
unfortunately fell ill towards the middle of J a n u a r y t829 and, in spite of the
care that had been lavished on him by his fianc6e's family, he died of phthisis
on the 6th April, having been confined to bed for three months . . . .
" B e f o r e completing this report where we have often had to recall the works
of Abel, it appears to us proper to dispel an error which is already quite wide-
spread. I t has been supposed that Abel died in misery, and this supposition has
been the occasion for violent attacks directed against scholars from Sweden and
from other parts of Europe. We would want to believe that the authors of these
attacks will regret that they expressed themselves with such vehemence, when
they read the Preface of the ... Oeuvres d'Abel, recently published in Norway
b y Mr. Holmboe, the teacher and friend of the illustrious geometer. They will
see there with interest the flattering encouragements, the expressions of esteem
and admiration that Abel received from scholars during his life, particularly
from those who occupied themselves at the same time as he with the theory of
elliptic transcendentals . . . . -67
In fact CAUCH¥ must have known that, while preparing his t839 edition of
ABEL'S works, HOLMBOEhad tried without success to obtain the 1826 manuscript
from the Acaddmie des Sciences and that its publication in t84t was due only to
the fact that he had raised the matter to governmental level. Anyone capable of
writing in this manner, knowing the negative role played by himself in the matter
under discussion, would hardly think twice about borrowing from an unknown
paper published in Prague without acknowledgement.
But how unknown was BOLZANO'Spaper ?
e~ A.-L. CAI:CH¥, "Rapport sur un m6moire de M. Broch, relatif ~ une certaine
t 85--21 t : see pp. t 89, 209---210. The first major study was by STOLZ, as " B. Bolzanos
Bedeutung in der Geschichte der Infinitesimalrechnung", Math. Ann., 18 (1881),
255--279 (and corrections in 22 (1883), 5t8--519).
70 See K. SCHWARZ, " Z u r Integration der partiel Differentialgleichung
~u ~2u
ax , + ~ - = 0 " , Journ. rei. ang. Math., 74 (t872), 218--253 (p. 221) = Abhandlungen,
2, t75--210 (p. 178).
~ See his Exercises des Mathdmatiques (4 vols. and I instalment: 1826---30, Paris),
and Exercises d'Analyse et de Physique Mathdmatique (4 vols: 1840---47, Paris). They
appear respectively in his Oeuvres, (2) 6---9; and (2) 11--14.
27*
396 I. GRATTAN-GUINN]~SS:
Kulik deliver to him (1834) an essay filling a single quarto sheet which I had
drafted for Cauchy sometime in French, on the famous mathematical problem
of the rectification of curves, because I rightly feared that he would find the
" P a p e r on the three problems of rectification, planing and cubing" published
in 18t779 too comprehensive and difficult. Early last year, as I was looking
through some issues of Cauchy's writings 8° bound with the usual coloured wrap-
pers, and [turned to I the lists of works announced on the back, I noticed with
astonishment a small note by him on the same subject, that he had published
as a lithograph in Paris in t834 (therefore presumably only after he had read m y
little essay). Naturally I would be very eager to read the note . . . . ,,81
Eventually BOLZANOmanaged to obtain a copy of the paper: in fact it came
through FESL who pointed out to him that it had been written in 1832 rather
than 1834 and so could not be related to his essay, and that it treated the sub-
ject in a quite different way. BOLZANO admitted this in an acknowledgement to
FESL in May, t 844, 82 and it is quite clear that in this case there was not even a
correspondence of ideas; but on the foundations of analysis a very different
situation seems to have applied. One would dearly like to know the content of
their conversations; but if BOLZANO ever wondered even for a moment that
CAUCHY had read his 18t7 paper before writing the tours d'Analyse, I imagine
that he would have been pleased rather than annoyed. For when he wrote that
paper, he had known then that it was a significant work which would probably
not reach the audience that it deserved; and so he had ended its preface with a
plea to the scientific community which I believe CAUCHYaccepted:
"... I must request ... that one does not overlook this particular paper be-
cause of its limited size, but rather examine it with all possible strictness and
make known publicly the results of this examination, in order to explain more
clearly what is perhaps unclear, to revoke what is quite incorrect, but to let
succeed to general acceptance, the sooner the better, what is true and right. ''s8
10. Epilogue
My conjecture has aroused considerable adverse criticism before publication,
and will doubtless receive much more now: thus to minimise the possibility of
misunderstandings of this paper, a few points m a y be worth stressing.
t. Part of m y purpose has been to describe some of the extra-intellectual
aspects of Parisian mathematics; and whether or not m y conjecture is correct
I am firmly convinced that rivalries of the type of which I have given some
examples played an important role in Parisian mathematics, and so I have tried
to bring to the attention of historians of this period the kinds of historical problem
that they will have to face in interpreting its literature. In addition, the theory
of "limit-avoidance" is an historical tool which appears to be some use in one
form or another in investigating the development of analysis and the calculus
in this and other periods.
2. I cannot stress too strongly that in characterising Cauchy's genius as respon-
sive to exterior stimuli I am trying to describe rather than decry the depth and
extent of his originality. Without any question he and GAUSS were the major
mathematicians of the first decades of the nineteenth century: thus his work
has to be given especial attention by historians. It is of course not m y position
that CAUCHY would never give references without intending a double meaning,
but I do think that in his writings, and equally in those o[ his" colleagues", questions
of this type do need to be borne very carefully in mind. With regard to ]3OLZANO'S
pamphlet, it is possible that CAUCHY,the busy and active researchmathematician
and professor at three Paris colleges, simply did not bother to mention it or
even forgot that he had read it (though personally I would not regard this
explanation as sufficient). My case would be much strengthened by documentary
evidence of some kind: CAUCHY did leave a Nachlass containing mathematical
manuscripts and correspondence, for it was used by VALSON when preparing
his excessively admiring biography of CAUCHY,s4 but unfortunately it was kept
in the family and there is reason to think that, like his library, it has now been lost.
3. I remarked that CAUCHY was familiar with European languages: in the
case of German, it is perhaps worth mentioning explicitly (from a number of
examples) that he examined in t817 a manuscript in German sent in to the
Acaddmie des Sciences, s5 and that he reviewed MCBIUS'S Der barycentrische Calcul
in t828. s~ We may also record another "coincidence of ideas" with obscure
German writing strikingly similar to the case of t3OLZANO'S pamphlet. In April
t847, GRASSMANN,then a schoolmaster at Stettin, sent to CAUCHY tWO copies
of his t844 Ausdehnungslehre, but he never received any acknowledgement; how-
ever between late 1847 and t853 CAUCHY published a number of papers on a
theory of "clefs algCbriques" which basically used the same sort of ideas and
even some almost identical notation, s7 I offer no judgement here on the matter:
84 C.-A. VALSON, La vie et les travaux du Baron Cauchy (2 vols.: 1868, Paris):
see esp. vol. 2, viii--x.
s5 See Proc~s-Verbaux des sdances de l'Acaddmie tenues depuis la fondation jusqu'au
mois d'ao~t, 1835 (10 vols: 1910--22, Hendaye), 6, 210. I may remark here that these
volumes are an invaluable source of historical insight into the period 1795--1835,
when the rivalries were at their height. They give the minutes of all the private
meetings of the A caddmie des Sciences, which the participants can hardly have expected
to be published!
s6 A.-L. CAUCHY,Bull. Univ. Sci. Ind. [Ferrusac~, Sci. math. phys. chim., 9 (1828),
77--80. Not in the Oeuvres.
sT For the references and some discussion of the affair, see M. J. CROWE, A history
of vector analysis (1967, Notre Dame and London), 82--85 and 106. CROWE'S last
reference in his 63 is inaccurate and ill fact misleading; it should be "MCmoire sur les
clefs algCbriques", Exercises d'Analyse et de Physique Mathdmatique, 4 (t847, Paris),
356---400 = Oeuvres, (2) 14, 4t7--460.
400 I. GRATTAN-GUINNESS: Bolzano, Cauchy and New Analysis
Index of Names
We list here the names and dates of persons mentioned in the main text.
D'ALEMBERT, JEAN LE ROND (t 7t 7--1783)
AMPERE, ADRIEN MARIE (1775--1836)
ARBOGAST, LOUIS FRANCOIS ANTOINE (1759--1803)
BERNOULLI, DANIEL (1700--t 782)
BESSEL, FRIEDRICHWILHELM (1784--1846)
BLOT, JEAN BAPTISTE (t 774--1862)
DU BOIS REYMOND, PAUL DAVID GUSTAV (t83t--1889)
BOLZANO, BERNARD PLACIDUS JOHANN NEPOMUK (t781--1848)
BOREL, EMILE FELIX EDOUARD JUSTIN (187t--t959)
CANTOR, GEORG FERDINAND LUDWIG PHILIPP (1845--t 918)
CARNOT, LAZARENICOLAS MARGUERITE(1753--t823)
CAUCHY, AUGUSTIN-LouIs (t 789--1857)
CHARLES X, KING (t 757--1836)
DIRICHLET, PETER GUSTAVLEJEUNE- (1805--t859)
EULER, LEONHARD (I707--t 783)
FESL, MICHAEL JOSEPH (1786--1864)
FOURIER, JEAN BAPTISTE JOSEPH (I 768--t830)
GAUSS, KARL FRIEDRICH (1777--t855)
GRASSMANN, HERMANN G/JNTHER (1809---t877)
HANKEL, HERMANN (t839--1873)
HARNACK, CARL GUSTAVAXEL (I 851--1888)
HEINE, EDUARD HEINRICH (I821--I 881)
L'HUILIER, SIMON ANTOINE JEAN (1750--1840)
HOLMBOE, BERNT MICHAEL (1795--1850)
JACOBI, CARL GUSTAV JACOB (t804--1851)
KULIK, JAKOB PHILIPP (1793--1863)
LACROIX, SYLVESTREFRAN9OIS (1765--1843)
LAGRANGE, JOSEPH LOUIS (1736--18t 3)
LAPLACE, PII~RRE SIMON (1749---1827)
LEGENDRE, ADRIEN MARIE (1752--t833)
LEIBNIZ, GOTTFRIED WILHELM (1646--1716)
M6BIUS, AUGUSTFERDINAND (t 790--1868)
MONGE, GASPARD (! 746--1818)
NEWTON, ISAAC (1642--1727)
POISSON, SIMI~ONDENIS (1781--1840)
PR~HONSK~', FRANZ (1788--t859)
RIEMANN, GEORG FRIEDRICH BERNHARD (1826--1866)
SCHWARZ, KARL HERMANN AMANDUS (1843--192t)
STOLZ, OTTO (1842--1905)
TAYLOR, BROOKE (1685--1731)
VALSON, CLAUDEALPHONSE (1826-- ? )
WEIERSTRASS, KARL THEODORWILHELM (t 8t 5--1897)