Analetheism: A Pyrrhic Victory: Bradley Armour-Garb Graham Priest
Analetheism: A Pyrrhic Victory: Bradley Armour-Garb Graham Priest
1. Introduction
In a recent article Jc Beall and David Ripley (2004), bending a term
of Terry Parsons’s (1990), describe a position concerning the paradoxes
of self-reference that they call ‘analetheism’, and claim that it would
appear to be just as good as the dialetheic account advocated by Priest
(1987) – hereafter IC. They say:
As far as we can see, the analetheist achieves whatever expressive
virtues that the dialetheist achieves; and she also partakes of the same
sort of expressive vices as the dialetheist. What could tip the scales
in favour of one position over the other? We do not know. (33)
The present note provides an answer.
IC provides what is, in effect, a three-valued logic in which the middle
value is interpreted as both true and false. And since it is at least true, it
is designated. Analetheism adopts exactly the same logic, but interprets
the middle value as neither true nor false. What distinguishes analetheism
from more simple-minded truth-value gap theories is precisely that it takes
the middle value to be designated. In particular, things with the middle
value are just as assertable as things that are true.1
2. An expressive difficulty
According to dialetheism, paradoxical sentences are both true and false
(i.e. have a true negation). Indeed, some sentences, such as the liar paradox
in the form l: ÿT·lÒ, are both true and not true: T·lÒ& ÿT·lÒ.2 It follows
(by De Morgan laws, which are valid in the logic) that ÿ(T·lÒ ⁄ ÿT·lÒ).
Now, Beall and Ripley say (32):
The intended interpretation of ‘T·lÒ’ (that l is true) renders ‘ÿ(T·lÒ
⁄ ÿT·lÒ)’ as the claim that l is neither true nor not true, certainly
not something the dialetheist wants to say given her aversion to truth-
value gaps.
1
‘Given that some sentences of the form A&ÿA may be designated (and hence
assertable), ...’ (Beall and Ripley 2004: 32).
2
We use T for the truth predicate, and angle brackets as a name-forming device. Beall
and Ripley use l as a name, not a sentence, and so write T l.
Analysis 65.2, April 2005, pp. 167–73. © Bradley Armour-Garb and Graham Priest
168 bradley armour-garb & graham priest
Now, it is not clear why the dialetheist should be averse to the claim in
question. There are no truth-value gaps in the dialetheic semantics; but
neither does this sentence say that l is a gap. This would be expressed by
the sentence ÿ(T·lÒ ⁄ ÿT·lÒ), which is not forthcoming without the
principle that T·lÒ Æ ÿT·lÒ, which IC (4.9) rejects.
So why should it be thought so? The sentence is, after all, true: both
disjuncts are false; so, therefore, is their disjunction. The problem, if there
is one, is in thinking that the sentence means something that it does not,
namely that it rules out l’s being true (and not true). In consistent con-
texts, it does so, but things are not always as they seem in inconsistent
contexts. In a paraconsistent logic, ÿa does not rule out a. In particular,
ÿ(T·lÒ ⁄ ÿT·lÒ) does not rule out T·lÒ.
Any residual discomfort one might experience here can be accounted
for by pointing out some facts about conversational implicature. When
we assert, we are bound by the Gricean conversational maxim to say
everything that is relevant. Thus, simply to assert ÿa, when a and ÿa are
both true, is misleading. A hearer may reasonably draw the conversational
implicature that a is simply false. Better to say a & ÿa. To assert just
ÿ(T·lÒ ⁄ ÿT·lÒ) is misleading in a similar way, since T·lÒ ⁄ ÿT·lÒ is also
true. Better to say ÿ(T·lÒ ⁄ ÿT·lÒ) & (T·lÒ ⁄ ÿT·lÒ).
As Beall and Ripley note, if dialetheism has any problem here, analethe-
ism has a similar problem. An analetheist asserts that ÿ(T·lÒ ⁄ ÿT·lÒ).
By De Morgan’s laws, this is equivalent to T·lÒ & ÿT·lÒ, which appears
to say that l both is and is not true. But the reply is the same: even though
we are dealing with truth-value gaps, contradictions are still acceptable.
In particular, T·lÒ & ÿT·lÒ does not rule out ÿ(T·lÒ v ÿT·lÒ). Similar
points about conversational implicature also apply.
3. The T-schema
Let us now turn to reasons for preferring dialetheism to analetheism. IC
subscribes to the T-schema:
• T·aÒ ´ a
their paper. We will return to this later. For the moment let us just consider
analetheism in the form in which they present it. An evident weakness of
this is just that it does not endorse the T-schema, the ability to do which
is one of the great advantages of dialetheism.
It might be contested that dialetheism suffers from an analogous weak-
ness: it does not accept the contraposed form of the schema. But this
principle is not in the same league. From Aristotle, through Tarski, to
contemporary deflationism about truth, it is the T-schema that is taken
as fundamental to truth, not its contraposed form. To say of what is that
it is, this is the truth.3 The contraposed form does not even say what truth
is; it just comes along for the ride – on the back of contraposition, if that
holds for the biconditional employed in the schema.
This is one weighty consideration.
The first falsity-norm may get its pull from two (mistaken) sources. The
first is from the classical confusion of what is not true with what has a
true negation. The second is from the considerations concerning conver-
sational implicature that we mentioned in §2. If we assert that a has a
true negation, that is, ÿT·aÒ, and so, by implication, ÿa, we may well
conversationally infer that a is true-only, that is that ÿT·aÒ. In this case,
we can then apply the first falsity-norm to infer that one should refrain
from asserting a. But this rests on a conversational implicature, not an
entailment.
Now that we have this straight, we can ask whether a dialetheist does
abandon the falsity norm. The answer is no. A dialetheist (but not an
analetheist) can well subscribe to the claim that if something is untrue it
ought not to be asserted. They can also, as we have just noted, subscribe
to the first-falsity norm, but only as a conversational implicature. It is the
second-falsity norm that is unreservedly correct.
It is worth noting that the second falsity-norm may give rise to dilemmas
on occasions. As we have already observed, paradoxes of self-reference
are true and false (have a true negation); but a few – such as the liar
paradox as formulated in §2 – are stronger: they are true and not true.
For such a paradox, we both ought to assert it, since it is true, and ought
not to assert it, since it is not true. Well, life is like that sometimes: we do
face dilemmas where you are damned if you do and damned if you don’t.7
Actually, dilemmas of this kind seem to occur independent of the falsity-
norm. Consider the sentence ‘It is not the case that this sentence is
assertable’, i.e.:
• a: ÿ·aÒ is assertable.
Suppose that a is false; then a is assertable. But it can’t be assertable if it
is false. So it must be true (assuming the Law of Excluded Middle, which
both the dialetheism and the analetheist endorse). Thus, it is not assert-
able. But we have just established that it is true, so it is. You ought and
ought not to assert a.8
At any rate, the important point in the present context is that a dialethe-
ist can subscribe to the falsity-norm, correctly understood.
6. A Pyrrhic victory
We have now seen that there are a number of reasons to prefer dialetheism
to analetheism. But let us end with a final observation. As Beall and Ripley
7
The possibility of dilemmas concerning legal and moral norms is discussed in IC,
ch. 13. The dilemma concerning the falsity-norm is discussed further in Priest 1993.
8
This is a version of the ‘irrationalist paradox’. For this and other paradoxes of
rationality that have nothing to do with self-reference at all: see Priest 2002.
172 bradley armour-garb & graham priest
note, dialetheism and analetheism are exactly the same, except that where
one says ‘both true and false’ the other says ‘neither’. Is this anything more
than a nominal difference? If the truth-norm obtains, then clearly not.
Since the middle value is designated, things that have this value are true
(as are their negations). So what Beall and Ripley call ‘neither true nor
false’ is simply a species of truth.
If the norm of truth does not hold, this may not be the case. However,
it remains true that analetheists are still prepared to go around asserting
contradictions in the full knowledge that they are contradictions, and with
no caveats. This gives dialetheists pretty much everything they ask for.
Call such things neither true nor false if you like; it doesn’t really matter.
Indeed, it is not really clear what the rationale for, or virtue of, appealing
to truth-value gaps is if you end up asserting contradictions anyway.
(Normally, the whole point of appealing to the notion, in the context of
the paradoxes of self-reference, is to avoid inconsistency.)
The point, we think, is pretty much conceded by Beall and Ripley at
the end of their paper. They point out that an analetheist can, in fact,
subscribe to both the T-schema and its contraposed form (as can the
dialetheist), making a and T·aÒ generally inter-substitutable. And if one
does this there are really no differences of any significance left between
the two views; they are, as Beall and Ripley themselves say, ‘no longer
distinguishable’ (34).
Indeed so. If analetheism has any kind of victory over dialetheism it is
an entirely Pyrrhic one.9
University of Melbourne
Melbourne, Vic. 3010, Australia
and
University of St Andrews
St Andrews KY16 9AL, UK
[email protected]
9
Thanks go to Jc Beall and Dave Ripley for their comments on earlier drafts of the
paper.
analetheism: a pyrrhic victory 173
References
Beall, Jc 2004. True and false – as if. Ch. 12 of G. Priest, Jc Beall and B. Armour-
Garb (eds.), The Law of Non-Contradiction: New Philosophical Essays, Oxford:
Oxford University Press.
Beall, Jc and D. Ripley. 2004. Analetheism and dialetheism. Analysis 64: 30–35.
Brandom, R. 1983. Asserting. Nôus 17: 637–50.
Dummett, M. 1959. Truth. Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society 59: 141–62; repr.
as ch. 1 of M. Dummett, Truth and Other Enigmas. London: Duckworth.
Parsons, T. 1990. True contradictions. Canadian Journal of Philosophy 20: 335–54.
Priest, G. 1987. In Contradiction: a Study of the Transconsistent. The Hague: Martinus
Nijhoff. Second (extended) edition, Oxford: Oxford University Press, forthcoming.
Priest, G. 1993. Can contradictions be true? Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society,
Suppl. Vol. 67: 35–54.
Priest, G. 2001. An Introduction to Non-Classical Logic. Cambridge: Cambridge
University Press.
Priest, G. 2002. Rational dilemmas. Analysis 62: 11–16.
Williamson, T. 1996. Knowing and asserting. Philosophical Review 105: 489–523.