Christopher Pierson, Frank Castles - The Welfare State Reader-Polity Press
Christopher Pierson, Frank Castles - The Welfare State Reader-Polity Press
State Reader
The Welfare
State Reader
Second Edition
Edited by
Christopher Pierson
and Francis G. Castles
polity
Copyright© Editorial matter and organization Christopher Pierson and Francis G.
Castles 2006
Polity Press
65 Bridge Street
Cambridge CB2 lUR, UK.
Polity Press
350 Main Street
Malden, MA 02148, USA
All rights reserved. Except for the quotation of short passages for the purpose of criti-
cism and review, no part of this publication may be reproduced, stored in a retrieval
system, or transmitted, in any form or by any means, electronic, mechanical, photo-
copying, recording or otherwise, without the prior permission of the publisher.
ISBN: 0-7456-3555-5
ISBN: 0-7456-3556-3 (pb)
A catalogue record for this book is available from the British Library.
Acknowledgements Vlll
Editors' Note xu
Editors' Introduction to the Second Edition
'Classical' 15
The Welfare State in Historical Perspective Asa Briggs 16
Citizenship and Social Class T H. Marshall 30
Universalism versus Selection Richard Titmuss 40
Globalization 199
Globalization, Economic Change and the Welfare State: 200
The 'Vexatious Inquisition of Taxation'? Colin Hay
Negative Integration: States and the Loss of Boundary
Control Fritz Scharpf 223
A Race to the Bottom? Francis G. Castles 226
Europeanization 245
Welfare-State Regress in Western Europe: Politics,
Institutions, Globalization, and Europeanization Walter Korpi 246
Deliberative Governance and EU Social Policy Paul Teague 269
The Open Method of Co-ordination and the European
Welfare State Damian Chalmers and Martin Lodge 289
Vll
Index 478
Acknowledgen1ents
Wil Arts and John Gelissen, 'Three Worlds of Welfare Capitalism or More?
A State-of-the-Art Report'. From journal of European Social Policy, 12
(2002), by permission of the authors and Sage Publications.
Francis G. Castles, 'A Race to the Bottom?' From Francis G. Castles, The
Future of the Welfare State, Oxford University Press, 2004, by permission
of the publisher.
Colin Hay, 'Globalization, Economic Change and the Welfare State. The
"Vexatious Inquisition of Taxation?'". From R. Sykes, B. Palier and P.M.
Prior (eds), Globalization and European Welfare States, Palgrave, 2001, by
permission of Palgrave Macmillan.
Mary Mcintosh, 'Feminism and Social Policy'. From Critical Social Policy,
1 (1981 ), ©Journal of Critical Social Policy 1981, by permission of the
author and Sage Publications.
Lawrence M. Mead, 'The New Politics of the New Poverty'. From The
Public Interest, 103 (Spring 1991), by permission of the author.
Charles Murray, 'The Two Wars against Poverty'. From The Public Interest,
69 (Winter 1982), by permission of the author.
James O'Connor, 'The Fiscal Crisis of the State'. From the Introduction to
]. O'Connor, The Fiscal Crisis of the State, Transaction, © 2001, by per-
mission of the publisher.
Philippe van Parijs, 'Basic Income and the Two Dilemmas of the Welfare
State'. From Political Quarterly, 67, 1 (1996), by permission of Blackwell
Publishing Ltd.
Paul Pierson, 'The New Politics of the Welfare State'. From World Politics,
48 (1996), copyright© The Johns Hopkins University Press, by permis-
sion of the publisher.
Acknowledgements Xl
Every effort has been made to trace copyright holders, but if any have been
inadvertently overlooked, the publishers will be pleased to make the nec-
essary arrangements at the first opportunity.
Editors' Note
This second edition of The Welfare State Reader continues our efforts to
produce an introduction to the politics of the welfare state that brings
together enduring themes of the literature with up-to-the-minute accounts
of the challenges confronting contemporary welfare states. The enduring
themes of the literature are ones with a continuing broad resonance across
the social sciences. Questions about how best to minimize poverty and
promote equality, what sorts of policy intervention produce the best
results and the extent to which state intervention for welfare purposes is
compatible with other desired goals of modern societies have been central
preoccupations of the disciplines of social theory and social policy and
have informed a large part of the analytical content of both political science
and sociology throughout these disciplines' existence. They are, moreover,
questions that have become ever more salient and of ever greater practical
policy relevance as the governments of democratic states have responded
to popular demands and to new social and economic problems by extend-
ing the scope of the caring state. Today, the state spends more on welfare
than on all other purposes combined, and long-established programmes
like old age pensions, sickness and unemployment benefits and health care
have been joined by programmes catering to the care needs of dual-earner
families, the residential needs of the frail elderly and income needs of
workers whose skills levels do not produce an adequate return in the
market economy. An understanding of the main approaches taken to ques-
tions relating to the early growth and developmental progress of the
welfare state provides an invaluable point of reference for locating the
issues raised by contemporary struggles over the state's role as an agency
of social amelioration.
While, however, the literature's enduring themes remain hugely relevant
to contemporary concerns, the substance of contemporary debates is
2 Editors' Introduction to the Second Edition
ological and/ or theoretical, like the debates separating left and right on the
appropriate limits to state intervention or the polemics directed by femi-
nist scholars at the patriarchialism of traditional welfare state arrange-
ments. They are also frequently empirical, when, as in debates over the
appropriateness of particular models of the welfare state, the extent of
welfare retrenchment, the effects of Europeanization and the welfare
implications of population ageing, scholars disagree in their analyses and
diagnoses of contemporary issues and future welfare state prospects.
Whether ideological, theoretical or empirical, such debates are inherently
policy relevant because different welfare preferences and diagnoses imply
different ways of conceptualizing and tackling pressing social problems.
That is why issues concerning the welfare state are inherently political and
will always be of passionate concern to scholars and commentators who
care about the future of the communities of which they are members.
Part I
Approaches to Welfare
tutions and of formal and informal labour markets, voluntary and family
care and so on, have generated welfare regimes which can be seen to be very
clearly gendered in their structures and outcomes. At the same time, they
argue that this aspect of gender within the welfare state is effectively con-
cealed, often under the rubric of the universality of citizenship. The two
papers in the Feminism section, Mcintosh's article on 'Feminism and Social
Policy' and Pateman's piece on 'The Patriarchal Welfare State' arc out-
standing examples of this approach.
The First Welfare State?
Thomas Paine
[ ... ]
When, in countries that are called civilized, we see age going to the work-
house and youth to the gallows, something must be wrong in the system
of government. It would seem, by the exterior appearance of such coun-
tries, that all was happiness; but there lies hidden from the eye of common
observation, a mass of wretchedness that has scarcely any other chance
than to expire in poverty or infamy. Its entrance into life is marked with
the presage of its fate; and until this is remedied, it is in vain to punish.
Civil government does not consist in executions; but in making that pro-
vision for the instruction of youth, and the support of age, as to exclude,
as much as possible, profligacy from the one, and despair from the other.
Instead of this, the resources of a country are lavished upon kings, upon
courts, upon hirelings, impostors and prostitutes; and even the poor them-
selves, with all their wants upon them, are compelled to support the fraud
that oppresses them.
Why is it, that scarcely any are executed but the poor? The fact is a proof,
among other things, of a wretchedness in their condition. Bred up without
morals, and cast upon the world without a prospect, they are the exposed
sacrifice of vice and legal barbarity. The millions that are superfluously
wasted upon governments are more than sufficient to reform those evils,
and to benefit the condition of every man in a nation, not included within
the purlieus of a court.
[ ... ]
In the present state of things, a labouring man, with a wife and two or three
children, does not pay less than between seven and eight pounds a year in
10 The First Welfare State?
taxes. He is not sensible of this, because it is disguised to him in the articles
which he buys, and he thinks only of their dearness; but as the taxes take
from him, at least, a fourth part of his yearly earnings, he is copse:quently
disabled from providing for a family, especially, if himself, or any of them,
are afflicted with sickness.
The first step, therefore, of practical relief, would be to abolish the poor
rates entirely, and in lieu thereof, to make a remission of taxes to the poor
of double the amount of the present poor-rates, viz. 4 millions annually out
of the surplus taxes. By this measure, the poor will be benefited 2 millions,
and the housekeepers 2 millions.
[ ... ]
[ ... ]
[I propose] To pay to every such person of the age of fifty years, and until
he shall arrive at the age of sixty, the sum of six pounds per ann. out of the
surplus taxes; and ten pounds per ann. during life after the age of sixty. The
expense of which will be,
Seventy thousand persons at £6 per ann. 420,000
Seventy thousand ditto at £10 per ann. 700,000
£1,120,000
This support, as already remarked, is not of the nature of a charity, but of
a right. Every person in England, male and female, pays on an average in
taxes, two pounds eight shillings and sixpence per ann. from the day of his
(or her) birth; and, if the expense of collection be added, he pays two
pounds eleven shillings and sixpence; consequently, at the end of fifty years
he has paid one hundred and twenty-eight pounds fifteen shillings; and at
sixty, one hundred and fifty-four pounds ten shillings. Converting, there-
fore, his (or her) individual tax into a tontine, the money he shall receive
after fifty years is but little more than the legal interest of the net money
he has paid; the rest is made up from those whose circumstances do not
require them to draw such support, and the capital in both cases defrays
the expenses of government. It is on this ground that I have extended the
probable claims to one third of the number of aged persons in the nation.
Is it then better that the lives of one hundred and forty thousand aged
persons be rendered comfortable, or that a million a year of public money
be expended on any one individual, and him often of the most worthless
or insignificant character?
[ ... ]
After all the above cases are provided for, there will still be a number of
families who, though not properly of the class of poor, yet find it difficult
to give education to their children; and such children, under such a case,
would be in a worse condition than if their parents were actually poor. A
nation under a well-regulated government should permit none to remain
uninstructed. It is monarchical and aristocratical government only that
requires ignorance for its support.
Suppose then four hundred thousand children to be in this condition,
which is a greater number than ought to be supposed, after the provisions
already made, the method will be,
To allow for each of those children ten shillings a year for the
expense of schooling, for six years each, which will give them six
months schooling each year and half a crown a year for paper and spelling
books.
12 The First Welfare State?
There will then remain one hundred and ten thousand pounds.
Notwithstanding the great modes of relief which the best instituted and
best principled government may devise, there will be a number of smaller
cases, which it is good policy as well as beneficence in a nation to con0ider.
Were twenty shilling to be given immediately on the birth of a child, to
every woman who should make the demand, and none will make it whose
circumstances do not require it, it might relieve a great deal of instant
distress.
There are about two hundred thousand births yearly in England, and if
claimed, by one fourth,
[ ... J
First, To erect two or more buildings, or take some already erected,
capable of containing at least six thousand persons, and to have in each of
these places as many kinds of employment as can be contrived, so
that every person who shall come may find something which he or she
can do.
Secondly, To receive all who shall come, without enquiring who or what
they are. The only condition to be, that for so much, or so many hours
work, each person shall receive so many meals of wholesome food, and a
warm lodging, at least as good as a barrack. That a certain portion of what
each person's work shall be worth shall be reserved, and given to him, or
her, on their going away; and that each person shall stay as long, or as short
time, or come as often as he choose, on these conditions.
If each person stayed three months, it would assist by rotation twenty-
four thousand persons annually, though the real number, at all times,
would be but six thousand. By establishing an asylum of this kind, persons
to whom temporary distresses occur would have an opportunity to recruit
themselves and be enabled to look out for better employment.
Allowing that their labour paid but one half the expense of supporting
them, after reserving a portion of their earnings for themselves, the sum of
Thomas Paine 13
forty thousand pounds additional would defray all other charges for even
a greater number than six thousand.
The fund very properly convertible to this purpose, in addition to the
twenty thousand pounds, remaining of the former fund, will be the produce
of the tax upon coals, so iniquitously and wantonly applied to the support
of the Duke of Richmond. It is horrid that any man, more especially at the
price coals now are, should live on the distresses of a community; and any
government permitting such an abuse deserves to be dismissed. This fund
is said to be about twenty thousand pounds per annum.
I shall now conclude this plan with enumerating the several particulars,
and then proceed to other matters.
The enumeration is as follows:
First, Abolition of two million poor-rates.
Secondly, Provision for two hundred and fifty-two thousand poor
families.
Thirdly, Education for one million and thirty thousand children.
Fourthly, Comfortable provision for one hundred and forty thousand
aged persons.
Fifthly, Donation of twenty shillings each for fifty thousand births.
Sixthly, Donation of twenty shillings each for twenty thousand mar-
nages.
Seventhly, Allowance of twenty thousand pounds for the funeral expenses
of persons travelling for work, and dying at a distance from their friends.
Eighthly, Employment, at all times, for the casual poor in the cities of
London and Westminster.
By the operation of this plan, the poor laws, those instruments of civil
torture, will be superseded, and the wasteful expense of litigation pre-
vented. The hearts of the humane will not be shocked by ragged and
hungry children, and persons of seventy and eighty years of age begging
for bread. The dying poor will not be dragged from place to place to
breathe their last, as a reprisal of parish upon parish. Widows will have a
maintenance for their children, and not be carted away, on the death of
their husbands, like culprits and criminals; and children will no longer be
considered as increasing the distresses of their parents. The haunts of the
wretched will be known, because it will be to their advantage; and the
number of petty crimes, the offspring of distress and poverty, will be less-
ened. The poor, as well as the rich, will then be interested in the support of
government, and the cause and apprehension of riots and tumults will
cease.- Ye who sit in ease, and solace yourselves in plenty, and such there
are in Turkey and Russia, as well as in England, and who say to yourselves,
'Are we not well off', have ye thought of these things? When ye do, ye will
cease to speak and feel for yourselves alone.
[ ... ]
14 The First Welfare State?
Note
[ ... J
commodities, land, money and labour. The multiple motives lying behind
the attempt to control these markets require careful and penetrating analy-
sts.
Second, the conception of 'social contingencies' is strongly influenced
by the experience of industrialism. Sickness, old age and death entail hard-
ships in any kind of society. Ancient systems of law and morality include
precepts designed to diminish these hardships, precepts based, for
example, on the obligations of sons to support their parents or on the
claims of charity, obsequium religionis. Unemployment, however, at least
in the form in which it is thought of as a social contingency, is a product of
industrial societies, and it is unemployment more than any other social
contingency which has determined the shape and timing of modern welfare
legislation. Before the advent of mass unemployment, 'unemployability',
the inability of individuals to secure their livelihood by work, was a key
subject in the protracted debates on poor law policy. The existence of
'chronic unemployment', structural or cyclical, has been a powerful spur
from the nineteenth century onwards leading organized labour groups to
pass from concentration on sectional interests to the consideration of
'social rights' of workers as a class; to philanthropic businessmen wishing
to improve the 'efficiency' and strengthen the 'social justice' of the busi-
ness system; and to politicians and governments anxious to avoid what
seemed to be dangerous political consequences of unemployment. The
memories of chronic unemployment in the inter-war years and the dis-
covery of what it was believed were new techniques of controlling it rein-
forced welfare state policies in many countries after the Second World War.
Third, the idea of using organized power (through politics and adminis-
tration) to determine the pattern of welfare services requires careful his-
torical dating. Why not rely for welfare on the family, the church, 'charity',
'self help', 'mutual aid' (guild, trade union, friendly society) or 'fringe ben-
efits' (business itself)? Whole philosophies of welfare have been founded
on each of these ideas or institutions: often the philosophies and the intere-
sts sustaining them have been inimical to the suggestion that the state itself
should intervene. The possibility of using governmental power has been
related in each country to the balance of economic and social forces; esti-
mates of the proper functions and, true or false, of the available resources
of the state; effective techniques of influence and control, resting on
knowledge (including expert knowledge); and, not least, the prevalence (or
absence) of the conviction that societies can be shaped by conscious poli-
cies designed to eliminate 'abuses' which in earlier generations had been
accepted as 'inevitable' features of the human condition.
Not only does the weighting of each of these factors vary from period to
period, but it also varies from place to place. It was Bentham, scarcely dis-
tinguished for his historical sense, who in distinguishing between agenda
(tasks of government) and sponte acta (unplanned decisions of individuals)
18 The Welfare State in Historical Perspective
wrote that 'in England abundance of useful things are done by individuals
which in other countries are done either by government or not at all ...
[while] in Russia, under Peter the Great, the list of sponte acta being a blank,
that of agenda was proportionately abundant.' 1 This contrast was noted by
many other writers later in the nineteenth century, just as an opposite con-
trast between Britain and the United States was often noted after 1945.
If the question of what constitutes welfare involves detailed examination
of the nature and approach to 'social contingencies', the question of why
the state rather than some other agency becomes the main instrument of
welfare involves very detailed examination of a whole range of historical
circumstances. The answer to the question is complicated, moreover, by
differences of attitude in different countries, to the idea of 'the state' itself.
Given these differences, a translation of basic terms into different lan-
guages raises difficulties which politicians and journalists may well have
obscured. For example, is the term Wohlfahrtsstaat the right translation of
welfare state? British and German approaches to 'the state' have been so
different that they have absorbed the intellectual energy of generations of
political scientists. In the nineteenth century there were somewhat similar
difficulties (although on a smaller scale) surrounding the translation of the
British term 'self help'. A French translator of Samuel Smiles's book of that
title (1859) said that the term 'self help' was 'a peu pres intraduisible'.
Fourth, the 'range of agreed social services' set out in the provisional def-
inition of 'welfare state' is a shifting range. Policies, despite the finalism of
much of the post-1945 criticism, are never fixed for all time. What at various
times was considered to be a proper range shifts, as Dicey showed, and con-
sequently must be examined historically. So too must changing areas of
agreement and conflict. Public health was once a highly controversial issue
in European societies: it still is in some other societies. The 'sanitary idea'
was rightly regarded by the pioneers of public health as an idea which had
large and far-reaching chains of consequences. It marked an assault on 'fate'
which would be bound to lead to other assaults. Public health, in the admin-
istrative sphere of drains, sewers and basic 'environmental' services, has been
taken outside the politics of conflict in Britain and other places, but personal
health services remain controversial. There is controversy, very bitter indeed
in the United States, not only about the range of services and who shall enjoy
them but about the means of providing them. The choice of means influ-
ences all welfare state history. Welfare states can and do employ a remark-
able variety of instruments, such as social insurance, direct provision in cash
or in kind, subsidy, partnership with other agencies (including private busi-
ness agencies) and action through local authorities. In health policy alone,
although medical knowledge is the same in all countries of the West and the
same illnesses are likely to be treated in much the same kind of way, there is
a remarkable diversity of procedures and institutions even in countries
which make extensive public provision for personal health services.
Asa Briggs 19
Notes
From C. Schottland, ed., The Welfare State, New York, Harper and Row, 1969,
pp. 29-45.
J. Bentham, Works, ed. J. Bowring, 1843, vol. III, p. 35. Cf. J. M. Keynes's view
of the 'agenda' of the state in The End of Laissez Faire (1926).
2 W. H. Dawson, Bismarck and State Socialism (1890), p. ix.
28 The Welfare State in Historical Perspective
23 PEP, 'free Trade and Security', Planning Quly 1957); 'A Comparative
Analysis of the Cost of Social Security', in International Labour Review
(1953).
24 E. M. Burns, Social Security and Public Policy (1956), p. 274.
25 For the nature of the nineteenth-century pattern, see J. M. Baernreither,
English Associations of WorkingMen (1893 ). For industrial relations, see Clegg
and Flanders, op. cit.
26 R. M. Titmuss, Essays on the Welfare State (1958), pp. 21-2.
27 Ibid., p. 19.
28 See A. Peacock, 'The Welfare Society', Unservile State Papers (1960); R. M.
Titmuss, 'The Irresponsible Society', Fabian Tracts (1960); J. Saville, 'The
Welfare State', The New Reasoner, no. 3 (1957).
Citizenship and Social Class
T. H. Marshall
[ ... J
I propose to divide citizenship into three parts. [ ... ] I shall call these three
parts, or elements, civil, political and social. The civil element is composed
of the rights necessary for individual freedom - liberty of the person,
freedom of speech, thought and faith, the right to own property and to
conclude valid contracts, and the right to justice. The last is of a different
order from the others, because it is the right to defend and assert all one's
rights on terms of equality with others and by due process of law. This
shows us that the institutions most directly associated with civil rights are
the courts of justice. By the political element I mean the right to participate
in the exercise of political power, as a member of a body invested with
political authority or as an elector of the members of such a body. The cor-
responding institutions are parliament and councils of local government.
By the social element I mean the whole range, from the right to a modicum
of economic welfare and security to the right to share to the full in the
social heritage and to live the life of a civilized being according to the stan-
dards prevailing in the society. The institutions most closely connected
with it are the educational system and the social services. [ ... J
By 1832 when political rights made their first infantile attempt to walk,
civil rights had come to man's estate and bore, in most essentials, the
appearance that they have today. 1 'The specific work of the earlier
Hanoverian epoch', writes Trevelyan, 'was the establishment of the rule of
law; and that law, with all its grave faults, was at least a law of freedom.
On that solid foundation all our subsequent reforms were built.' This
eighteenth-century achievement, interrupted by the French Revolution
and completed after it, was in large measure the work of the courts, both
in their daily practice and also in a series of famous cases in some of which
T H. Marshall 31
no interference of the legislature with the freedom of trade, or with the perfect
liberty of every individual to dispose of his time and of his labour in the way
and on the terms which he may judge most conducive to his own interest, can
take place without violating general principles of the first importance to the
prosperity and happiness of the community. 2 [ ••• J
The story of civil rights in their formative period is one of the gradual add-
ition of new rights to a status that already existed and was held to apper-
tain to all adult members of the community- or perhaps one should say to
all male members, since the status of women, or at least of married women,
was in some important respects peculiar. This democratic, or universal,
character of the status arose naturally from the fact that it was essentially
the status of freedom, and in seventeenth-century England all men were
free. Servile status, or villeinage by blood, had lingered on as a patent
anachronism in the days of Elizabeth, but vanished soon afterwards. This
change from servile to free labour has been described by Professor Tawney
as 'a high landmark in the development both of economic and political
society', and as 'the final triumph of the common law' in regions from
which it had been excluded for four centuries. Henceforth the English
peasant 'is a member of a society in which there is, nominally at least, one
32 Citizenship and Social Class
law for all men'. 3 The liberty which his predecessors had won by fleeing
into the free towns had become his by right. In the towns the terms
'freedom' and 'citizenship' were interchangeable. When freegom became
universal, citizenship grew from a local into a national institution.
The story of political rights is different both in time and in character. The
formative period began, as I have said, in the early nineteenth ce~1tury,
when the civil rights attached to the status of freedom had already acquired
sufficient substance to justify us in speaking of a general status of citizen-
ship. And, when it began, it consisted, not in the creation of new rights to
enrich a status already enjoyed by all, but in the granting of old rights to
new sections of the population. [ ... ]
It is clear that, if we maintain that in the nineteenth century citizenship
in the form of civil rights was universal, the political franchise was not one
of the rights of citizenship. It was the privilege of a limited economic class,
whose limits were extended by each successive Reform Act. [ ... ]
It was, as we shall see, appropriate that nineteenth-century capitalist
society should treat political rights as a secondary product of civil rights.
It was equally appropriate that the twentieth century should abandon this
position and attach political rights directly and independently to citizen-
ship as such. This vital change of principle was put into effect when the Act
of 1918, by adopting manhood suffrage, shifted the basis of political rights
from economic substance to personal status. I say 'manhood' deliberately
in order to emphasize the great significance of this reform quite apart from
the second, and no less important, reform introduced at the same time -
namely the enfranchisement of women. [ ... ]
The original source of social rights was membership of local communi-
ties and functional associations. This source was supplemented and pro-
gressively replaced by a Poor Law and a system of wage regulation which
were nationally conceived and locally administered. [ ... ]
As the pattern of the old order dissolved under the blows of a competi-
tive economy, and the plan disintegrated, the Poor Law was left high and
dry as an isolated survival from which the idea of social rights was gradu-
ally drained away. But at the very end of the eighteenth century there
occurred a final struggle between the old and the new, between the planned
(or patterned) society and the competitive economy. And in this battle cit-
izenship was divided against itself; social rights sided with the old and civil
with the new. [ ... ]
In this brief episode of our history we see the Poor Law as the aggres-
sive champion of the social rights of citizenship. In the succeeding phase
we find the attacker driven back far behind his original position. By the Act
of 1834 the Poor Law renounced all claim to trespass on the territory of
the wages system, or to interfere with the forces of the free market. It
offered relief only to those who, through age or sickness, were incapable
of continuing the battle, and to those other weaklings who gave up the
T. H. Marshall 33
struggle, admitted defeat, and cried for mercy. The tentative move towards
the concept of social security was reversed. But more than that, the
minimal social rights that remained were detached from the status of citi-
zenship. The Poor Law treated the claims of the poor, not as an integral
part of the rights of the citizen, but as an alternative to them - as claims
which could be met only if the claimants ceased to be citizens in any true
sense of the word. For paupers forfeited in practice the civil right of per-
sonal liberty, by internment in the workhouse, and they forfeited by law
any political rights they might possess. This disability of defranchisement
remained in being until1918; and the significance of its final removal has,
perhaps, not been fully appreciated. The stigma which clung to poor relief
expressed the deep feelings of a people who understood that those who
accepted relief must cross the road that separated the community of citi-
zens from the outcast company of the destitute.
The Poor Law is not an isolated example of this divorce of social rights
from the status of citizenship. The early Factory Acts show the same ten-
dency. Although in fact they led to an improvement of working conditions
and a reduction of working hours to the benefit of all employed in the indus-
tries to which they applied, they meticulously refrained from giving this
protection directly to the adult male- the citizen par excellence. And they
did so out of respect for his status as a citizen, on the grounds that enforced
protective measures curtailed the civil right to conclude a free contract of
employment. Protection was confined to women and children, and champi-
ons of women's rights were quick to detect the implied insult. Women were
protected because they were not citizens. If they wished to enjoy full and
responsible citizenship, they must forgo protection. By the end of the nine-
teenth century such arguments had become obsolete, and the factory code
had become one of the pillars in the edifice of social rights. [ ... ]
By the end of the nineteenth century elementary education was not only
free, it was compulsory. This signal departure from laissez-faire could, of
course, be justified on the grounds that free choice is a right only for mature
minds, that children are naturally subject to discipline, and that parents
cannot be trusted to do what is in the best interests of their children. But
the principle goes deeper than that. We have here a personal right combined
with a public duty to exercise the right. Is the public duty imposed merely
for the benefit of the individual- because children cannot fully appreciate
their own interests and parents may be unfit to enlighten them? I hardly
think that this can be an adequate explanation. It was increasingly recog-
nized, as the nineteenth century wore on, that political democracy needed
an educated electorate, and that scientific manufacture needed educated
workers and technicians. The duty to improve and civilize oneself is there-
fore a social duty, and not merely a personal one, because the social health
of a society depends upon the civilization of its members. And a commu-
nity that enforces this duty has begun to realize that its culture is an organic
34 Citizenship and Social Class
unity and its civilization a national heritage. It follows that the growth of
public elementary education during the nineteenth century was the first
decisive step on the road to the re-establishment of the sociaJ rights of citi-
zenship in the twentieth. [ ... ]
capitalism. Such a view was encouraged by the fact that one of the main
achievements of political power in the later nineteenth century was the
recognition of the right of collective bargaining. This me,~nt that social
progress was being sought by strengthening civil rights, not by creating
social rights; through the use of contract in the open market, not through
a minimum wage and social security.
But this interpretation underrates the significance of this extension of
civil rights in the economic sphere. For civil rights were in origin intensely
individual, and that is why they harmonized with the individualistic pbase
of capitalism. By the device of incorporation groups were enabled to act
legally as individuals. This important development did not go unchal-
lenged, and limited liability was widely denounced as an infringement of
individual responsibility. But the position of trade unions was even more
anomalous, because they did not seek or obtain incorporation. They can,
therefore, exercise vital civil rights collectively on behalf of their members
without formal collective responsibility, while the individual responsibil-
ity of the workers in relation to contract is largely unenforceable. These
civil rights became, for the workers, an instrument for raising their social
and economic status, that is to say, for establishing the claim that they, as
citizens, were entitled to certain social rights. But the normal method of
establishing social rights is by the exercise of political power, for social
rights imply an absolute right to a certain standard of civilization which is
conditional only on the discharge of the general duties of citizenship. Their
content does not depend on the economic value of the individual claimant.
There is therefore a significant difference between a genuine collective
bargain through which economic forces in a free market seek to achieve
equilibrium and the use of collective civil rights to assert basic claims to the
elements of social justice. Thus the acceptance of collective bargaining was
not simply a natural extension of civil rights; it represented the transfer of
an important process from the political to the civil sphere of citizenship.
But 'transfer' is, perhaps, a misleading term, for at the time when this hap-
pened the workers either did not possess, or had not yet learned to use, the
political right of the franchise. Since then they have obtained and made full
use of that right. Trade unionism has, therefore, created a secondary system
of industrial citizenship parallel with and supplementary to the system of
political citizenship. [ ... ]
A new period opened at the end of the nineteenth century, conveniently
marked by Booth's survey of Life and Labour of the People in London and
the Royal Commission on the Aged Poor. It saw the first big advance in
social rights, and this involved significant changes in the egalitarian princi-
ple as expressed in citizenship. But there were other forces at work as well.
A rise of money incomes unevenly distributed over the social classes
altered the economic distance which separated these classes from one
another, diminishing the gap between skilled and unskilled labour and
T. H. Marshall 37
between skilled labour and non-manual workers, while the steady increase
in small savings blurred the class distinction between the capitalist and the
propertyless proletarian. Secondly, a system of direct taxation, ever more
steeply graduated, compressed the whole scale of disposable incomes.
Thirdly, mass production for the home market and a growing interest on
the part of industry in the needs and tastes of the common people enabled
the less well-to-do to enjoy a material civilization which differed less
markedly in quality from that of the rich than it had ever done before. All
this profoundly altered the setting in which the progress of citizenship
wok place. Social integration spread from the sphere of sentiment and
patriotism into that of material enjoyment. The components of a civilized
and cultured life, formerly the monopoly of the few, were brought pro-
gressively within reach of the many, who were encouraged thereby to
stretch out their hands towards those that still eluded their grasp. The
diminution of inequality strengthened the demand for its abolition, at least
with regard to the essentials of social welfare.
These aspirations have in part been met by incorporating social rights
in the status of citizenship and thus creating a universal right to real
income which is not proportionate to the market value of the claimant. Class-
abatement is still the aim of social rights, but it has acquired a new meaning.
It is no longer merely an attempt to abate the obvious nuisance of destitution
in the lowest ranks of society. It has assumed the guise of action modifying
the whole pattern of social inequality. It is no longer content to raise the
floor-level in the basement of the social edifice, leaving the superstructure as
it was. It has begun to remodel the whole building, and it might even end by
converting a skyscraper into a bungalow. It is therefore important to con-
sider whether any such ultimate aim is implicit in the nature of this develop-
ment, or whether, as I put it at the outset, there are natural limits to the
contemporary drive towards greater social and economic equality. [ ... ]
The degree of equalization achieved [by the modern system of welfare
benefits] depends on four things: whether the benefit is offered to all or
to a limited class; whether it takes the form of money payment or service
rendered; whether the minimum is high or low; and how the money to
pay for the benefit is raised. Cash benefits subject to income limit and
means test had a simple and obvious equalizing effect. They achieved
class-abatement in the early and limited sense of the term. The aim was
to ensure that all citizens should attain at least to the prescribed
minimum, either by their own resources or with assistance if they could
not do it without. The benefit was given only to those who needed it, and
thus inequalities at the bottom of the scale were ironed out. The system
operated in its simplest and most unadulterated form in the case of the
Poor Law and old age pensions. But economic equalization might be
accompanied by psychological class discrimination. The stigma which
attached to the Poor Law made 'pauper' a derogatory term defining
38 Citizenship and Social Class
a class. 'Old age pensioner' may have had a little of the same flavour, but
without the taint of shame. [ ... ]
The extension of the social services is not primarily a me,ans of equaliz-
ing incomes. In some cases it may, in others it may not. The question is rela-
tively unimportant; it belongs to a different department of social policy.
What matters is that there is a general enrichment of the concrete substance
of civilized life, a general reduction of risk and insecurity, an equalization
between the more and the less fortunate at all levels - between the healthy
and the sick, the employed and the unemployed, the old and the active~ the
bachelor and the father of a large family. Equalization is not so much
between classes as between individuals within a population which is now
treated for this purpose as though it were one class. Equality of status is
more important than equality of income. [ ... J
I said earlier that in the twentieth century citizenship and the capitalist
class system have been at war. Perhaps the phrase is rather too strong, but
it is quite clear that the former has imposed modifications on the latter. But
we should not be justified in assuming that, although status is a principle
that conflicts with contract, the stratified status system which is creeping
into citizenship is an alien element in the economic world outside. Social
rights in their modern form imply an invasion of contract by status, the
subordination of market price to social justice, the replacement of the free
bargain by the declaration of rights. But are these principles quite foreign
to the practice of the market today, or are they there already entrenched
within the contract system itself? I think it is clear that they are. [ ... J
I have tried to show how citizenship, and other forces outside it, have
been altering the pattern of social inequality. [ ... J We have to look, here,
for the combined effects of three factors. First, the compression, at both
ends, of the scale of income distribution. Second, the great extension of the
area of common culture and common experience. And third, the enrich-
ment of the universal status of citizenship, combined with the recognition
and stabilization of certain status differences chiefly through the linked
systems of education and occupation. [ ... J
I asked, at the beginning, whether there was any limit to the present
drive towards social equality inherent in the principles governing the
movement. My answer is that the preservation of economic inequal-
ities has been made more difficult by the enrichment of the status of cit-
izenship. There is less room for them, and there is more and more
likelihood of their being challenged. But we are certainly proceeding at
present on the assumption that the hypothesis is valid. And this assump-
tion provides the answer to the second question. We are not aiming at
absolute equality. There are limits inherent in the egalitarian movement.
But the movement is a double one. It operates partly through citizenship
and partly through the economic system. In both cases the aim is to remove
inequalities which cannot be regarded as legitimate, but the standard of
T H. Marshall 39
Notes
Originally delivered in Cambridge as the Marshall Lecture for 1949 and published
in Citizenship and Social Class and Other Essays, ed. T. H. Marshall, Cambridge,
Cambridge University Press, 1950. This version extracted from States and Societies,
ed. D. Held, London, Open University/Martin Robertson, 1983, pp. 249-60.
1 G. M. Trevelyan, English Social History (1942), p. 351.
2 Sidney and Beatrice Webb, History of Trade Unionism (1920), p. 60.
3 R. H. Tawney, The Agrarian Problem in the Sixteenth Century (1916),
PP· 43-4.
4 P. Colquhoun, A Treatise in Indigence (1806), pp. 7-8.
Universalism versus Selection
Richard Titmuss
[ ... ]
In any discussion today of the future of (what is called) 'The Welfare State'
much of the argument revolves around the principles and objectives of uni-
versalist social services and selective social services.
[ ... J
Consider, first, the nature of the broad principles which helped to shape
substantial sections of British welfare legislation in the past, and particu-
larly the principle of universalism embodied in such postwar enactments
as the National Health Service Act, the Education Act of 1944, the
National Insurance Act and the Family Allowances Act.
One fundamental historical reason for the adoption of this princi-
ple was the aim of making services available and accessible to the
whole population in such ways as would not involve users in any humil-
iating loss of status, dignity or self-respect. There should be no sense
of inferiority, pauperism, shame or stigma in the use of a publicly pro-
vided service; no attribution that one was being or becoming a 'public
burden'. Hence the emphasis on the social rights of all citizens to use or
not to use as responsible people the services made available by the com-
munity in respect of certain needs which the private market and the
family were unable or unwilling to provide universally. If these services
were not provided for everybody by everybody they would either not be
available at all, or only for those who could afford them, and for others
Richard Titmuss 41
An Analytical Framework
Whatever the nature of the service, activity or function, and ,whether it be
a service in kind, a collective amenity, or a transfer payment in cash or by
accountancy, we need to consider (and here I itemize in question form for
the sake of brevity) three central issues:
This represents little more than an elementary and partial structural map
which can assist in the understanding of the welfare complex [ ... ].
Needless to say, a more sophisticated (inch to the mile) guide is essential
for anything approaching a thorough analysis of the actual functioning of
welfare benefit systems. I do not, however, propose to refine further this
frame of study now, nor can I analyse by these classifications the several
hundred distinctive and functionally separate services and benefits actually
in operation in Britain [in the 1960s].
Further study would also have to take account of the pattern and oper-
ation of means-tested services. It has been estimated by Mr M. J. Reddin,
my research assistant, that in England and Wales today local authorities are
responsible for administering at least 3,000 means tests, of which about
1,500 are different from each other. 4 This estimate applies only to services
falling within the responsibilities of education, child care, health, housing
and welfare departments. It follows that in these fields alone there exist
some 1,500 different definitions of poverty or financial hardship, ability to
pay and rules for charges, which affect the individual and the family. There
must be substantial numbers of poor families with multiple needs and mul-
tiple handicaps whose perception [ ... ] of the realities of welfare is to see
only a means-testing world. Who helps them, I wonder, to fill out all those
forms?
I mention these social facts, by way of illustration, because they do form
part of the operational complex of welfare in 1967. My main purpose,
however, in presenting this analytical framework was twofold. First, to
underline the difficulties of conceptualizing and categorizing needs,
causes, entitlement or gatekeeper functions, utilization patterns, benefits
and compensations. Second, to suggest that those students of welfare who
are seeing the main problem today in terms of universalism versus selec-
tive services are presenting a naive and oversimplified picture of policy
choices.
Some of the reasons for this simple and superficial view are, I think, due
to the fact that the approach is dominated by the concept or model of
welfare as a 'burden'; as a waste of resources in the provision of benefits
44 Universalism versus Selection
for those who, it is said, do not need them. The general solution is thus
deceptively simple and romantically appealing: abolish all this welfare
complexity and concentrate help on those whose needs are g_reatest.
Quite apart from the theoretical and practical immaturity o{this solu-
tion, which would restrict the public services to a minority in the popula-
tion leaving the majority to buy their own education, social se:curity,
medical care and other services in a supposedly free market, certain other
important questions need to be considered.
As all selective services for this minority would have to apply some t~st
of need-eligibility, on what bases would tests be applied and, even more
crucial, where would the lines be drawn for benefits which function as
compensation for identified disservices, compensation for unidentifiable
disservices, compensation for unmerited handicap, as a form of social pro-
tection, as an investment, or as an increment to personal welfare? Can rules
of entitlement and access be drawn on purely 'ability to pay' criteria
without distinction of cause? And if the causal agents of need cannot be
identified or are so diffuse as to defy the wit of law- as they so often are
[ ... ] -then is not the answer 'no compensation and no redress'? In other
words, the case for concentrated selective services resolves itself into an
argument for allowing the social costs or diswelfares of the economic
system to lie where they fall.
The emphasis [ ... ] on 'welfare' and the 'benefits of welfare' often tends
to obscure the fundamental fact that for many consumers the services used
are not essentially benefits or increments to welfare at all; they represent
partial compensations for disservices, for social costs and social insecuri-
ties which are the product of a rapidly changing industrial-urban society.
They are part of the price we pay to some people for bearing part of the
costs of other people's progress; the obsolescence of skills, redundancies,
premature retirements, accidents, many categories of disease and handicap,
urban blight and slum clearance, smoke pollution, and a hundred-and-one
other socially generated disservices. They are the socially caused diswel-
fares; the losses involved in aggregate welfare gains.
What is also of major importance [ ... ] is that modern society is finding
it increasingly difficult to identify the causal agent or agencies, and thus to
allocate the costs of disservices and charge those who are responsible. It is
not just a question of benefit allocation- of whose 'Welfare State'- but also
of loss allocation - whose 'Diswelfare State'.
If identification of the agents of diswelfare were possible - if we could
legally name and blame the culprits- then, in theory at least, redress could
be obtained through the courts by the method of monetary compensation
for damages. But multiple causality and the diffusion of disservices - the
modern choleras of change - make this solution impossible. We have,
therefore, as societies to make other choices; either to provide social ser-
vices, or to allow the social costs of the system to lie where they fall. The
Richard Titmuss 45
Notes
There is more than one notion associated with the term social justice. In
some connections, for example, justice is thought to have something to do
with equality. Sometimes it seems to relate to need: for example, it can seem
notably unfair if bad fortune prevents someone from having something
they really need, such as medical care, less unfair if it is something they just
happen to want. Yet again, justice relates to such notions as entitlement,
merit and desert. These are not the same as each other. For example, if
someone wins the prize in the lottery, they are entitled to the money, and
it would be unjust to take it away from them, but it has nothing to do with
their merits, and they have done nothing to deserve it. Similarly, if talented
people win prizes in an activity that requires no great practice or effort,
they are entitled to the prize and get it on the strength of their merits (as
opposed, for instance, to someone's getting it because he is the son of the
promoter), but they may well have not done anything much to deserve it.
People who are especially keen on the notion of desert may want there to
be prizes only for effort; or, at least, think that prizes which command
admiration (as the lottery prize does not) should be awarded only for
effort. Humanity has shown so far a steady reluctance to go all the way
with this view.
As well as being complex in this way, people's views about justice are
also indeterminate. This means that it is often unclear what the just
outcome should be - particularly when various considerations of social
justice seem to pull in different directions, as they often do. Most people,
for instance, think that inheritance is at least not intrinsically evil, and that
parents are entitled to leave property to their children. But no one thinks
that one can leave anything one likes to one's children - one's job, for
instance- and almost everyone thinks that it can be just for the state to tax
inheritances in order to deal with social injustice, or simply to help the
common good.
The mere fact that people's ideas about justice are both complex and
indeterminate has an important consequence for democratic politics. There
is more than one step from general ideas to practical recommendations.
There have to be general policies directed to social justice, and these are
going to be at best an interpretation of people's ideas on such matters.
General policies will hope to offer considerations which people can recog-
nize as making sense in the light of their own experience and ideas (this
need not exclude challenging some of those ideas). Specific policies,
however, involve a further step, since they have to express general policies
in a particular administrative form. A given scheme of taxation or social
security is, in that sense, at two removes from the complex and indetermin-
ate ideas that are its moral roots.
This is not to deny that some administrative practices may acquire a
symbolic value of their own. In the 1940s, the death grant was a symbol of
society's commitment to end paupers' funerals and ensure for every family
52 What is Social Justice?
There are important theories of social justice. The most ambitious give a
general account of what social justice is, explain and harmonize the rela-
tions between the different considerations associated with it, do the same
for the relations between justice and other goods, notably liberty, help to
resolve apparent conflicts between different values, and in the light of all
that, even give pointers to practical policies. The most famous such theory
in modern discussion is that of John Rawls, which gives a very rich elabor-
ation to a very simple idea: that the fair division of a cake would be one that
could be agreed on by people who did not know which piece they were
gomg to get.
Rawls invokes an 'Original Position', in which representatives of
various parties to society are behind 'a veil of ignorance' and do not know
what role each party will occupy in the society. They are asked to choose
a general scheme for the ordering of society. The scheme that they would
reasonably choose in these imagined circumstances constitutes, in Rawls's
view, the scheme of a just society.
Rawls's theory, and others with similar aims, contains important
insights, and anyone who is trying to think about these problems should
pay attention to them. But there is an important question- one acknow-
ledged by Rawls himself- of what relation such a theory can have to pol-
itics. Rawls thinks that his theory articulates a widely spread sense of
fairness, but it is certain that the British public would not recognize in such
a theory, or in any other with such ambitions, all its conflicting ideas and
feelings about social justice. Even if the Commission, improbably, all
agreed on Rawls's or some other such theory, we would not be justified in
presenting our conclusions in terms of that theory. The Commission has a
more practical purpose.
Our task is to find compelling ways of making our society more just. We
shall be able to do so only if we think in ways that people can recognize
and respect about such questions as how best to understand merit and
need; how to see the effects of luck in different spheres of life; what is
implied in saying, or denying, that health care is a morally special kind of
good which makes a special kind of demand.
Commission on Social justice 53
The Commission has to guard against ali-or-nothing assumptions. It is
not true that either we have a complete top-down theory, or we are left
only with mere prejudice and subservience to polls. This particularly
applies to conflict. Confronted, as will often be the case, with an apparent
conflict within justice, or between justice and some other value, we may
rend to assume that there are only two possibilities: the conflict is merely
apparent, and we should understand liberty and equality (for instance) in
such a way that they cannot conflict; or it is a real conflict, and then it can
only be left to politics, majorities, subjective taste, or whatever. This will
not do. Reflection may not eliminate all conflicts, but it can help us to
understand them, and then arrive at policy choices.
Unjustified Inequalities
Proponents of equality sometimes seem to imply that all inequalities are
unjust (although they usually hasten to add that they are not in fact arguing
for 'arithmetical equality'). We do not accept this. It seems fair, for
instance, that a medical student should receive a lower income than the
fully qualified doctor; or that experience or outstanding talent should be
rewarded, and so on. Different people may have different views about what
the basis of differential rewards should be; but most people accept, as we
do, that some inequalities are just. There is, however, a question about the
justifiable extent of an inequality, even if we accept that the inequality per
se is not unjust.
Similarly, most people believe that it is fair for people to bequeath their
property as they see fit, even though this means that some will inherit more
than others. Nonetheless, it is also accepted that society may claim a share
of an inheritance through the taxation of wealth or gifts, particularly when
the estate is large. It is, after all, offensive to most ideas of social justice that
a growing number of people own two homes while others have nowhere
to live at all. This does not imply that one person's property should be con-
fiscated to house another; but it does suggest the need for a fundamental
reform of housing policy, an issue the Commission will certainly be
addressing.
But if some inequalities are just, it is obviously the case that not all are
so. It would, for instance, be unjust to allow people to inherit jobs from
their parents: employment should be open to all, on the basis of merit.
Inheritance of a family title offends many people's views about a classless
society, but could not be said to deny somebody else something which they
deserved. But inheritance of a peerage, in the UK, carries with it automatic
entitlement to a seat and vote in the Second Chamber of Parliament: and
that is an inequality of power which seems manifestly unjust.
This is a very strong and surprising claim. Some people might agree that
no one deserves a reward that they get on the basis of some raw advantage,
without any investment of effort. (Of course, given the e:x;isting rules, that
docs not mean that they are not entitled to it, or that it can merely be taken
away from them. It means that it would not necessarily be an injustice to
change the rules.) But those who agree to this are very likely to think that
people who do invest effort deserve its rewards, at least up to a certain
point. But Rawls's argument applies just as much to effort as to raw talent.
First, it is practically impossible to separate the relative contributions of
effort and talent to a particular product. Moreover, the capacity to make
a given degree of effort is itself not equally distributed, and may plausi-
bly be thought to be affected by upbringing, culture and other social
factors. Virtually everything about a person that yields a product is itself
undeserved. So no rewards, in Rawls's view, are, at the most basic level, a
matter of desert.
Few people believe this. If someone has taken a lot of trouble in design-
ing and tending a garden, for instance, they will be proud of it and appro-
priately think of its success as theirs. The same applies to many aspects of
life. This does suggest that there is something wrong with the idea that
basically people never earn anything by their talents or labours- that in the
last analysis all that anyone's work represents is a site at which society has
achieved something. Yet, certainly, one does not 'deserve' the talents of
birth. It must be true, then, that one can deserve the rewards of one's talents
without deserving one's talents. As the American philosopher Robert
Nozick forcefully put it, why docs desert 'have to go all the way down'?
What the various arguments about entitlement and desert suggest seems
to be something close to what many people believe: that there is basic
justice in people having some differential reward for their productive
activities, but that they have no right to any given differential of their
reward over others. It is not simply self-interest, or again scepticism about
government spending programmes (though that is certainly a factor), that
makes people resist the idea that everyone's income is in principle a
resource for redistribution; that idea also goes against their sense of what
is right. They rightly think that redistribution of income is not an aim
in itself.
At the same time, they acknowledge that the needs of the less fortunate
make a claim. Luck is everywhere, and one is entitled to some rewards of
luck, but there are limits to this entitlement when one lives and works with
other people. Even if one is entitled to some rewards from the product of
one's efforts and talents, there is the further point that in a complex enter-
prise such as a company or family, there is rarely a product which is solely
and definitely the product of a given person's efforts and talents.
This is no doubt one reason why people are sceptical about vast rewards
to captains of industry. It is also a question of the relation of one person's
Commission on Socialjustice 59
rivity to that of others. Few people mind that Pavarotti or Lenny Henry
ace paid large sums - there is only one of them, and they are undoubtedly
a~e star of the show. But in some cases, one person's reward can be another
t erson's loss. The Nobel Prize winning economist Professor James Meade
Prgued in a submission to the Commission that 'Keynesian full-
:mploymcnt policy.... collapsed simply and solely because a high level of
money expenditures came to lead not to a high level of output and emplo-
yment but to a high rate of n:~ney wages, costs ~nd prices ... It is very
possible that t~ absorb two m.dho.n extra workers m,to employment would
require a considerable reductiOn m real wage costs.
This raises a crucial point, concerning the power to determine one's own
rewards, and the relationship of that power to questions of justice and
desert. In contrast to a simple focus on the distribution of rewards, this
raises the question of the generation of rewards, the processes whereby
inequalities are generated.
Unequal incomes are inherent in a market economy. Even if everyone
started off with the same allocation of money, differences would
soon emerge. Not all labour commands the same price; not all investments
produce the same return; some people work longer hours, others prefer more
leisure and so on. The resulting inequalities are not necessarily unjust -
although the extent of them may be. In the real world, of course, people start
off with very different personal and financial resources. The problem is
that too many of these inequalities are exacerbated in the UK's system of
market exchange.
But market economics are not all of a piece; different kinds of market
produce different outcomes. For instance, Germany, Japan and Sweden all
have more equal earnings distributions than the UK, where the gap
between the highest and lowest paid is wider today than at any time since
1886. Social justice therefore has a part to play in deciding how a market is
constructed, and not simply with the end result.
Fair Reward
Most people have some idea of a 'fair reward'. For example, it is clear to
the vast majority of people that disadvantage and discrimination on
grounds of sex or race or disability is unjust. However, once one gets
beyond the general idea, there is less agreement on what fair rewards
should be. Even if there were more agreement about this, it is very diffi-
cult, both practically and morally, to impose such notions on a modern
economy. The very idea of a society that can be effectively managed from
the top on the basis of detailed centralized decisions is now discredited.
Moreover, our society does not stand by itself and happily does not have
walls around it, and people can go elsewhere.
60 What is Social justice?
Ideas of social justice in this area are not, however, necessarily tied to the
model of a command economy. It is often clear, at least, that_ given rewards
in a market economy are not fair, because they are not bei,ng determined
by such things as talent, effort and the person's contribution to the enter-
prise, but rather by established power relations. Real life does not conform
to economic models: people are not paid for the 'marginal product' of their
labour. They are paid, among other things, according to social norms. In
one sense, such distortions are the product of the market: they are what we
get if market processes, uncorrected, are allowed to reflect establi~hed
structures and habits of power. Examples of this are the huge salaries and
bonuses distributed to the directors of some large companies. [ ... ] These
salaries and bonuses are often quite unrelated to the performance of the
company concerned, and are sometimes actually inversely correlated with
company performance.
In another sense, unjust inequalities are themselves distortions of the
market: it is not a fair market in talent and effort if it is not talent and effort
that determine the outcome. This is most obviously demonstrated in the
case of inequalities of pay between men and women. Although the 1970
Equal Pay Act eliminated overt pay inequities, it had a limited effect on the
gap between men's and women's pay, which resulted in the main from job
segregation and gender-biased views of what different jobs and different
qualities were worth. Hence the concept of 'equal pay for work of equal
value', which permits comparisons between two very different jobs per-
formed for the same employer. Although designed to eradicate gender as a
consideration in earnings, equal value claims may in practice require a
complete transformation in an organization's pay-setting. Equal pay for
work of equal value, after all, implies unequal pay for work of unequal
value: thus, the basis for differentials has to be made explicit and justified.
Different organizations and people will have different views of what
constitutes a fair basis for differentials: it should not be an aim of govern-
ment to substitute its own view of fair wage settlements. It is, however, a
legitimate aim of policy concerned with social justice to develop social
institutions (of which equal value laws are one example) which will enable
people to express their own ideas of a fair reward.
·ustice, based on a basic belief in the intrinsic worth of every human being,
~cho the deeply held views of many people in this country. They provide
a compelling justification and basis for our work:
[ ... J
Note
From Commission on Social Justice, The Justice Gap, London, Institute for Public
Policy Research, 1993, pp. 4-16.
The Fiscal Crisis of the State
James 0 'Connor
[ ... ]
Our first premise is that the capitalistic state must try to fulfil two basic
and often mutually contradictory functions - accumulation and legit-
imization. [ ... ] This means that the state must try to maintain or create
the conditions in which profitable capital accumulation is possible.
However, the state also must try to maintain or create the conditions for
social harmony. A capitalist state that openly uses its coercive forces to help
one class accumulate capital at the expense of other classes loses its legit-
imacy and hence undermines the basis of its loyalty and support. But a state
that ignores the necessity of assisting the process of capital accumulation
risks drying up the source of its own power, the economy's surplus pro-
duction capacity and the taxes drawn from this surplus (and other forms
of capital). This contradiction explains why President Nixon calls a legis-
lated increase in profit rates a 'job development credit', why the govern-
ment announces that new fiscal policies are aimed at 'stability and growth'
when in fact their purpose is to keep profits high and growing, why the tax
system is nominally progressive and theoretically based on 'ability to pay'
when in fact the system is regressive. The state must involve itself in the
accumulation process, but it must either mystify its policies by calling
them something that they are not, or it must try to conceal them (e.g. by
making them into administrative, not political, issues).
Our second premise is that the fiscal crisis can be understood only in
terms of the basic Marxist economic categories (adapted to the problems
taken up here). State expenditures have a twofold character corresponding
to the capitalist state's two basic functions: social capital and social
expenses. Social capital is expenditures required for profitable private
accumulation; it is indirectly productive (in Marxist terms, social capital
james 0' Connor 63
indirectly expands surplus value). There are two kinds of social capital:
social investment and social consumption (in Marxist terms, social con-
stant capital and social variable capital). [ ... ] Social investment consists
of projects and services that increase the productivity of a given amount of
labour power and, other factors being equal, increase the rate of profit.
A good example is state-financed industrial-development parks. Social
consumption consists of projects and services that lower the reproduction
costs of labour and, other factors being equal, increase the rate of profit.
An example of this is social insurance, which expands the reproductive
powers of the workforce while simultaneously lowering labour costs. The
second category, social expenses, consists of projects and services which are
required to maintain social harmony - to fulfil the state's 'legitimization'
function. They are not even indirectly productive. [ ... ] The best example
is the welfare system, which is designed chiefly to keep social peace among
unemployed workers. (The costs of politically repressed populations in
revolt would also constitute a part of social expenses.)
Because of the dual and contradictory character of the capitalist state,
nearly every state agency is involved in the accumulation and legitimiza-
tion functions, and nearly every state expenditure has this twofold charac-
ter. For example, some education spending constitutes social capital (e.g.
teachers and equipment needed to reproduce and expand workforce tech-
nical and skill levels), whereas other outlays constitute social expenses (e.g.
salaries of campus policemen). To take another example, the main purpose
of some transfer payments (e.g. social insurance) is to reproduce the work-
force, whereas the purpose of others (e.g. income subsidies to the poor) is
to pacify and control the surplus population. The national income
accounts lump the various categories of state spending together. (The state
does not analyse its budget in class terms.) Clearly, the different categories
cannot be separated if each budget item is not examined.
Furthermore, precisely because of the social character of social capital
and social expenses, nearly every state expenditure serves these two (or
more) purposes simultaneously, so that few state outlays can be classified
unambiguously. For example, freeways move workers to and from work
and are therefore items of social consumption, but they also transport
commercial freight and are therefore a form of social investment. And,
when used for either purpose, they may be considered forms of social
capital. However, the Pentagon also needs freeways; therefore they in part
constitute social expenses. Despite this complex social character of state
outlays we can determine the political-economic forces served by any
budgetary decision, and thus the main purpose (or purposes) of each bud-
getary item. [ ... ]
The first basic thesis presented here is that the growth of the state sector
and state spending is functioning increasingly as the basis for the growth
of the monopoly sector and total production. Conversely, it is argued that
64 The Fiscal Crisis of the State
the growth of state spending and state programmes is the result of the
growth of the monopoly industries. In other words, the growth of the state
is both a cause and effect of the expansion of monopoly capital. [ ... ]
More specifically, the socialization of the costs of social investment and
social consumption capital increases over time and increasingly is needed
for profitable accumulation by monopoly capital. The general reason is
that the increase in the social character of production (specialization, div-
ision of labour, interdependency, the growth of new social forms of capital
such as education, etc.) either prohibits or renders unprofitable the private
accumulation of constant and variable capital. The growth of the monop-
oly sector is irrational in the sense that it is accompanied by unemploy-
ment, poverty, economic stagnation and so on. To ensure mass loyalty and
maintain its legitimacy, the state must meet various demands of those who
suffer the 'costs' of economic growth. [ ... ]
It might help to compare our approach with traditional economic
theory. Bourgeois economists have shown that increases in private con-
sumption beget increases in private investment via the accelerator effect. In
turn, increases in private investment beget increases in private consump-
tion via the multiplier effect. Similarly, we argue that greater social invest-
ment and social consumption spending generate greater private investment
and private consumption spending, which in turn generate surplus capital
(surplus productive capacity and a surplus population) and a larger volume
of social expenses. Briefly, the supply of social capital creates the demand
for social expenses. In effect, we work with a model of expanded repro-
duction (or a model of the economy as a whole) which is generalized to
take into account the socialization of constant and variable capital costs
and the costs of social expenses. The impact of the budget depends on the
volume and indirect productivity of social capital and the volume of social
expenses. On the one hand, social capital outlays indirectly increase pro-
ductive capacity and simultaneously increase aggregate demand. On the
other hand, social expense outlays do not increase productive capacity,
although they do expand aggregate demand. Whether the growth of pro-
ductive capacity runs ahead or behind the growth of demand thus depends
on the composition of the state budget. In this way, we can see that the
theory of economic growth depends on class and political analyses of the
determinants of the budget.
This view contrasts sharply with modern conservative thought, which
asserts that the state sector grows at the expense of private industry. We
argue that the growth of the state sector is indispensable to the expansion
of private industry, particularly monopoly industries. Our thesis also con-
trasts sharply with a basic tenet of modern liberal thought- that the expan-
sion of monopoly industries inhibits the growth of the state sector. The fact
of the matter is that the growth of monopoly capital generates increased
expansion of social expenses. In sum, the greater the growth of social
james 0' Connor 65
capital, the greater the growth of the monopoly sector. And the greater the
growth of the monopoly .sector, the greater the state's expenditures on
social expenses of productiOn.
The second basic thesis in this study is that the accumulation of social
capital and social expenses is a contradictory process which creates ten-
dencies toward economic, social and political crises. [ ... ] Two separate
but related lines of analysis are explored.
First, we argue that although the state has socialized more and more
capital costs, the social surplus (including profits) continues to be appro-
priated privately. The socialization of costs and the private appropriation
of profits creates a fiscal crisis, or 'structural gap', between state expendi-
tures and state revenues. The result is a tendency for state expenditures to
increase more rapidly than the means of financing them. While the accu-
mulation of social capital indirectly increases total production and
society's surplus and thus in principle appears to underwrite the expansion
of social expenses, large monopoly-sector corporations and unions
strongly resist the appropriation of this surplus for new social capital or
social expense outlays. [ ... ]
Second, we argue that the fiscal crisis is exacerbated by the private
appropriation of state power for particularistic ends. A host of
'special interests' - corporations, industries, regional and other business
interests - make claims on the budget for various kinds of social invest-
ment. [ ... J(These claims are politically processed in ways that must either
be legitimated or obscured from public view.) Organized labour and
workers generally make various claims for different kinds of social con-
sumption, and the unemployed and poor (together with businessmen in
financial trouble) stake their claims for expanded social expenses. Few if
any claims are co-ordinated by the market. Most are processed by the
political system and are won or lost as a result of political struggle.
Precisely because the accumulation of social capital and social expenses
occurs within a political framework, there is a great deal of waste, duplica-
tion and overlapping of state projects and services. Some claims conflict
and cancel one another out. Others are mutually contradictory in a variety
of ways. The accumulation of social capital and social expenses is a highly
irrational process from the standpoint of administrative coherence, fiscal
stability and potentially profitable private capital accumulation.
Note
From J. O'Connor, The Fiscal Crisis of the State, New York, St Martin's Press,
1973, pp. 6-11.
Sotne Contradictions of the
Modern Welfare State
Claus Offe
The welfare state has served as the major peace formula of advanced capi-
talist democracies for the period following the Second World War. This
peace formula consists, first, in the explicit obligation of the state appar-
atus to provide assistance and support (either in money or in kind) to those
citizens who suffer from specific needs and risks which are characteristic
of the market society; such assistance is provided as legal claims granted to
the citizens. Second, the welfare state is based on the recognition of the
formal role of labour unions both in collective bargaining and the forma-
tion of public policy. Both of these structural components of the welfare
state are considered to limit and mitigate class conflict, to balance the
asymmetrical power relation of labour and capital, and thus to overcome
the condition of disruptive struggle and contradiction that was the most
prominent feature of pre-welfare state, or liberal, capitalism. In sum, the
welfare state has been celebrated throughout the postwar period as the
political solution to societal contradictions.
Until [the 1970s], this seemed to be the converging view of political elites
both in countries in which the welfare state is fully developed (e.g. Great
Britain, Sweden) as well as in those where it is still an incompletely real-
ized model. Political conflict in these latter societies, such as the USA, was
centred not on the basic desirability and functional indispensability, but on
the pace and modalities of the implementation of the welfare state model.
This was true, with very minor exceptions, up to the mid-1970s. From
that point on we see that in many capitalist societies this established peace
formula becomes itself the object of doubts, fundamental critique and
political conflict. It appears that the most widely accepted device of polit-
ical problem-solving has itself become problematic, and that, at any rate,
the unquestioning confidence in the welfare state and its future expansion
has rapidly vanished. It is to these doubts and criticisms that I will direct
Claus Offe 67
my attention in the following remarks. The point to start with is the obser-
vation that the almost universally accepted model for creating a measure of
social peace and harmony in European postwar societies has itself become
the source of new contradictions and political divisions in the 1970s.
Historically, the welfare state has been the combined outcome of a
variety of factors which change in composition from country to country:
Social Democratic reformism, Christian socialism, enlightened conserva-
tive political and economic elites and large industrial unions. They fought
for and conceded comprehensive compulsory insurance schemes, labour
protection legislation, minimum wages, the expansion of health and edu-
cation facilities and state-subsidized housing, as well as the recognition of
unions as the legitimate economic and political representatives of labour.
These continuous developments in Western societies were often dramatic-
ally accelerated in a context of intense social conflict and crisis, particularly
under war and postwar conditions. The accomplishments, which were
won under conditions of war and postwar periods, were regularly main-
tained; added to them were the innovations that could be introduced in
periods of prosperity and growth. In the light of the Keynesian doctrine of
economic policy, the welfare state came to be seen not so much as a burden
imposed upon the economy, but as a built-in economic and political stabi-
lizer which could help to regenerate the forces of economic growth and
prevent the economy from spiralling downward into deep recessions.
Thus, a variety of quite heterogeneous ends (ranging from reactionary pre-
emptive strikes against the working class movement in the case of
Bismarck, to socialist reformism in the case of the Weimar Social
Democrats; from the social-political consolidation of war and defence
economies, to the stabilization of the business cycle) adopted identical
institutional means which today make up the welfare state. It is exactly its
multi-functional character, its ability to serve many conflicting ends and
strategies simultaneously which made the political arrangement of the
welfare state so attractive to a broad alliance of heterogeneous forces. But
it is equally true that the very diversity of the forces that inaugurated and
supported the welfare state could not be accommodated forever within the
institutional framework which today appears to come increasingly under
attack. The machinery of class compromise has itself become the object of
class conflict.
labour more complicated and less predictable. On the other hand, as the
welfare state imposes regulations and rights upon the labour-capital
exchange that goes on in production, while leaving the authority structure
and the property relations of production untouched, it is hardly surprising
to see that the workers are not, as a rule, intrinsically motivated to work as
productively as they possibly can. In other words, the welfare state main-
tains the control of capital over production, and thus the basic source of
industrial and class conflict between labour and capital; but it by no means
establishes anything resembling 'workers control'. At the same time, it
strengthens workers' potential for resistance against capital's control, the
net effect being that an unchanged conflict is fought out with means that
have changed in favour of labour. Exploitative production relations coexist
with expanded possibilities to resist, escape and mitigate exploitation.
While the reason for struggle remained unchanged, the means of struggle
increased for the workers. It is not surprising to see that this condition
undermines the work ethic, or at least requires more costly and less reli-
able strategies to enforce such ethic.
My point so far has been that the two key arguments of the liberal-
conservative analysis are valid to a large extent, contrary to what critics
from the left have often argued. The basic fault in this analysis has less to
do with what it explicitly states than with what it leaves out of its consid-
eration. Every worthwhile political theory has to answer two questions:
first, what is the desirable form of the organization of society and state, and
how can we demonstrate that it is at all workable, i.e. consistent with our
basic normative and factual assumptions about social life? This is the
problem of defining a consistent model or goal of transformation. Second,
how do we get there? This is the problem of identifying the dynamic forces
and strategies that could bring about the transformation.
The conservative analysis of the welfare state fails on both counts. To
start with the latter problem, it is extremely hard today in Western Europe
to conceive of a promising political strategy that would aim at even par-
tially eliminating the established institutional components of the welfare
state, to say nothing about its wholesale abolition. That is to say, the
welfare state has, in a certain sense, become an irreversible structure, the
abolition of which would require nothing less than the abolition of polit-
ical democracy and the unions, as well as fundamental changes in the party
system. A political force that could bring about such dramatic changes is
nowhere visible as a significant factor (right-wing middle-class populist
movements that occasionally spring up in some countries notwithstand-
ing). Moreover, political opinion research has shown that the fiercest advo-
cates of laissez-faire capitalism and economic individualism show marked
differences between their general ideological outlook and their willingness
to have special transfers, subsidies and social security schemes aban-
doned from which they personally derive benefits. Thus, in the absence of
Claus Offe 71
Ian Gough and others before him have argued, that increases in the
::penditures ar~ par_alleled by incre,ases in_ real 'w~lfar~'. ~?~ du~l fallacy,
known in techmcal_ hterature_as the spcndmg scrv1ce c_hche, 1s th1s: first, a
arginal increase m expend1tures must not necessanly correspond to a
marginal increment in the 'output' of the welfare state apparatus; it may
:ell be used up in feeding the bureaucratic machinery itself. Second, even
if the output (say of health services) is increased, a still larger increase in the
level of risks and needs (or a qualitative change of these) may occur on the
part of the clients or recipients of such services, so as to make the net effect
negative.
The bureaucratic and professional form through which the welfare state
dispenses its services is increasingly seen to be a source of its own ineffi-
ciency. Bureaucracies absorb more resources and provide less services
than other democratic and decentralized structures could. The reason why
the bureaucratic form of administering social services is maintained in
spite of its inefficiency and ineffectiveness must therefore have to do with
the social control function exercised by centralized welfare bureaucracies.
This analysis leads to the critique of the repressiveness of the welfare state,
its social control aspect. Such repressiveness, in the view of the critics, is
indicated by the fact that in order to qualify for the benefits and services
of the welfare state, the client must not only prove his or her 'need', but
must also be a 'deserving' client, that is, one who complies to the domin-
ant economic, political and cultural standards and norms of the society.
The heavier the needs, the stricter these requirements tend to be defined.
Only if, for instance, the unemployed are willing to keep themselves avail-
able for any alternative employment (often considerably inferior to the
job they have lost) that is made available to them by employment agen-
cies, are they entitled to unemployment benefits; and the claim for welfare
payments to the poor is everywhere made conditional upon their confor-
mity to standards of behaviour which the better-to-do strata of the popu-
lation are perfectly free to violate. In these and other cases, the welfare
state can be looked upon as an exchange transaction in which material
benefits for the needy are traded for their submissive recognition of the
'moral order' of the society which generates such need. One important
precondition for obtaining the services of the welfare state is the ability of
the individual to comply with the routines and requirements of welfare
bureaucracies and service organizations, an ability which is often inversely
correlated to need itself.
A third major aspect of the socialist critique of the welfare state is its
politico-ideological control function. The welfare state is seen not only as
the source of benefits and services, but at the same time the source of false
conceptions about historical realities which have damaging effects on
working-class consciousness, organization and struggle. The welfare
state creates the false image of two separated spheres of working-class life.
74 Some Contradictions of the Modern Welfare State
On the one side is the sphere of work, the economy, production and
'primary' income distribution. On the other is the sphere of citizenship,
the state, reproduction and 'secondary' distribution. This qivi~ion of the
socio-political world obscures the causal and functional links that exist
between the two, and thus prevents the formation of a political under-
standing of society as a coherent totality to be changed. That is to say, the
structural arrangements of the welfare state tend to make people ignore or
forget that the needs and contingencies which the welfare state responds to
are themselves constituted, directly or indirectly, in the sphere of work
and production. The welfare state itself is materially and institutionally
constrained by the dynamics of the sphere of production, and a reliable
conception of social security does therefore presuppose not only the
expansion of citizen rights, but of workers' rights in the process of
production. Contrary to such insights, which are part of the analytical
starting-points of any conceivable socialist strategy of societal transforma-
tion, the inherent symbolic indoctrination of the welfare state suggests the
ideas of class co-operation, the disjunction of economic and political strug-
gles, and an ill-based confidence in an ever continuing cycle of economic
growth and social security.
What emerges from this discussion of the analysis of the welfare state by
the right and the left are three points on which the liberal conservative and
the socialist critic exhibit somewhat surprising parallels.
First, contrary to the ideological consensus that flourished in some of
the most advanced welfare states throughout the 1950s and 1960s, the
welfare state is no longer believed to be the promising and permanently
valid answer to the problems of the socio-political order of advanced cap-
italist economies. Critics in both camps have become more vociferous and
fundamental in their negative appraisal of welfare state arrangements.
Second, neither of the two approaches to the welfare state could or would
be prepared, in the best interests of their respective clientele, to abandon
the welfare state, as it performs essential and indispensable functions both
for the accumulation process as well as for the social and economic well-
being of the working class. Third, while there is, on the conservative side,
neither a consistent theory nor a realistic strategy about the social order
of a non-welfare state (as I have argued before), it is evident that the situ-
ation is not much better on the left where one could possibly speak of a
consistent theory of socialism, but certainly not of an agreed upon and
realistic strategy for its construction. In the absence of the latter, the
welfare state remains a theoretically contested, though in reality firmly
entrenched fact, of the social order of advanced capitalist societies.
Claus Offe 75
In short, it appears that the welfare state, while being contested both from
the right and the left, will not be easily replaced by a conservative or pro-
gressive alternative.
[ ... J
Note
Walter Korpi argues that most modern social scientific accounts of social
structure and change have relied upon one of three models: a 'pluralist-
industrial' model which emphasizes the emergence in developed industrial
societies of a plurality of competing interests and social groupings whose
relations are mediated through largely consensual societal institutions; a
'Marxist-Leninist' model which insists that Western societies are still
essentially riven by those forms of class struggle originally identified
by Marx and in which the state acts in the interests of capital; and a
neo-corporatist account in which certain (economically defined) interests
have privileged access to the state and in which collective action is negoti-
ated at an elite level between the state and these privileged social
actors. Here he offers his own alternative account of a 'power resources
model'. (Eds)
Power Resources
The stability implied in the pluralist industrial model of society rests on the
assumption that the distribution of power resources between various
groups and collectivities in the capitalist democracies is potentially equal.
Schmitter's assumption of relative stability of nco-corporatist arrange-
ments appears to imply an unequal yet fairly stable distribution of power
resources. The Leninist interpretation of Marx similarly implies an
unequal but stable power distribution in the capitalist democracies. Such
assumptions must be questioned. One way of elucidating the distribution
of power is to analyse what instruments and resources of power different
groups and collectivities in society have at their disposal in the interaction
which takes place between them over long periods of time.
Walter Korpi 77
What, then, are power resources? Power resources are characteristics
which provide actors - individuals or collectivities - with the ability to
punish or reward other actors. These resources can be described in terms
of a variety of dimensions. Power resources can thus vary with regard to
domain, which refers to the number of people who are receptive to the par-
ticular type of rewards and penalties. They can also differ in terms of scope
-the various kinds of situation in which they can be used. A third import-
ant dimension is the degree of scarcity of a power resource of a particular
type. Furthermore, power resources can vary in terms of centrality; i.e.
they can be more or less essential to people in their daily lives. They also
differ with regard to how easily they are convertible into other resources.
The extent to which a power resource can be concentrated is a crucial
dimension. Of relevance are also the costs involved in using a power
resource and in its mobilization, i.e. in making it ready for use. Power
resources can furthermore differ in the extent to which they can be used to
initiate action or are limited to responses to actions by others.
It is important to realize that power resources need not be used or acti-
vated in order to have consequences for the actions of other people. An
actor with the ability to reward or punish need thus not always do so to
influence others. Since every activation of power resources entails costs, it
actually lies in the interests of power holders to increase efficiency in the
deployment of power resources. This can be achieved through what we
may call the investment of power resources. Thus, power resources can be
invested through the creation of structures for decision-making and con-
flict regulation, whereby decisions can be made on a routine basis and in
accordance with given principles. Investments of power resources can be
made in institutions for conflict resolution such as laws, ordinances and
bureaucracies, in technologies, in community and national planning, and
in the dissemination of ideologies.
Some types of power resource can be described as basic in the sense that
they in themselves provide the capacity to reward or to punish other
actors. Through processes of investment, from basic power resources
actors can derive new types of power resource. These derived power
resources, however, ultimately depend on the basic power resources for
their effectiveness. The distinction between basic and derived power
resources is not easy to make but appears fruitful. It indicates, for instance,
that power resources such as ideologies can be seen as ultimately based
on resources which provide the capability to apply positive or negative
sanctions.
Let us now look briefly at the characteristics of some of the more import-
ant basic power resources in Western societies. Among resources familiar
to students of power, means of violence have traditionally been considered
important. In terms of the aforementioned dimensions, means of violence
have a large domain, wide scope and high concentration potential, as well
78 The Power Resources Model
Social Change
In Western societies variations in the difference in power reso_llrces between
labour and business interests, along with their allied groups, can be
expected to have a variety of consequences. This difference can influence:
in the distribution of power resources and are of such a nature that they
significantly affect institutional arrangements and strategies of conflict for
long periods of time. In connection with such settlements. or 'historical
compromises', the patterns and conceptions of 'normal politics' change.
In the capitalist countries, the acceptance of the wage-earners' right
to organize in unions and parties and to participate in political decision-
making via universal and equal suffrage are examples of such historical
settlements. The winning of political democracy was the result of a
decrease in the disadvantage of working-class power resources brought
about through organization and often through alliances with middle-class
groups. It limited the legitimate use of means of repression by the state and
opened up legitimate avenues for the citizens to participate in the decision-
making of state organs. In many Western countries, the historical settle-
ments concerning political democracy came around the First World War.
These institutional changes significantly affected the patterns of interest
conflicts in the years to come.
Societal Bargaining
With the exception of setbacks in countries like Italy, Germany and Spain,
during the inter-war period the strength of the unions and working-class
parties increased in the Western nations. In the period after the Second
World War this trend has by and large continued. Through increasing
levels of organization the wage-earners have considerably strengthened
their bargaining position in the distributive conflicts in the capitalist
democracies. This has affected strategies of conflict and patterns of insti-
tutional arrangements. It is my hypothesis that the tripartite 'nco-
corporatist' institutional arrangements largely reflect the compromises and
settlements generated by the decreasing differences in the distribution of
power resources between wage-earners and representatives of capital and
allied groups in these countries. The decreasing disadvantage in wage-
earner power resources has generated institutional arrangements and prac-
tices in reaching settlements involving major interest groups, which we can
describe as 'societal bargaining'. The notion of bargaining implies that the
outcome of the interaction cannot be predetermined.
The choice of the term 'societal bargaining' to describe arrangements
and practices which others have termed 'corporatism' is made not only to
avoid a word which many have found hard to swallow. In my view, soci-
etal bargaining of the tripartite type that was developed in some countries
of Western Europe during the postwar period clearly differs from trad-
itional corporatist arrangements. It is therefore misleading to regard the
two as more or less functional equivalents in the way several writers on
nco-corporatism have done.
Walter Korpi 83
the Leninist interpretation of Marxism tend to argue that. the major orga-
nized interest groups, which presently are the main actors in these con-
flicts, do not actually represent the interests of the worki,ng .class. Many
writers on nee-corporatism also share such a view. Let us look briefly at
the concepts concerned and the counter-arguments made.
The class concept is of relevance, inter alia, in attempts to explain social
conflict, the distribution of goods and social change. This concept should
therefore sensitize us to the many fissures and rents in the social fabric,
which may become cleavages delineating the bases upon which citi.zens
will organize themselves into collective action in the conflicts of interest in
society. According to my reading of Marx and Weber, the two dominant
figures in the theory of class, they both view the class concept in this per-
spective. Marx no less than Weber recognized a multitude of potential
cleavages on the basis of which citizens can combine themselves for col-
lective action. The two differ, however, in the relative importance which
they ascribe to different types of bases of cleavage.
Marx assumed that, in the long run, the conflicts of interest rooted in the
sphere of production and especially in the economic organization of pro-
duction would come to dominate over the other potential cleavages, such
as those based on market resources and status. Contrary to what is often
assumed, the class theory of Marx is not a one-factor theory. Its basic
hypothesis is instead that, among the multitude of lines of cleavage and
conflicts of interest, the relative importance of those arising from the eco-
nomic organization of production will increase in the long run.
Weber, however, places class, market resources and status on an equal
footing as potential bases for cleavages and assumes that over rime their
importance will tend to oscillate. The class theory of Weber has also often
been misinterpreted, not least by those who regard him as their intellectual
standard-bearer. Weber explicitly argued that power must be seen as the
generic concept of social stratification, the threefold expressions of which
are class, status and party. Yet, pluralist writers have often conceived of
power as a separate 'dimension' of social stratification, parallel to, but not
included in, 'class' and 'status'. In contrast to Weber's stress on power as
the basic independent variable behind social stratification, pluralist writers
have therefore tended to conceive of power as restricted to the realm of the
political order. While Weber saw 'property' and 'the lack of property' as
the basic characteristics of all class situations, the institution of property
has received scant attention in pluralist and functionalist analyses of indus-
trial societies.
[ ... ]
Notes
From W. Korpi, The Democratic Class Struggle, London, Routledge and Kegan
Paul, 1983, pp. 14-25.
F. Parkin, Marxism and Class Theory, New York, Columbia University Press,
1979.
2 A. Lijphart, 'Language, Religion, Class and Party Choice', in R. Rose,
Electoral Participation, Beverly Hills, CA, Sage, 1980.
Responses from the Right
The Meaning of the Welfare
State
Friedrich von Hayek
[ ... ]
developments. Our problem here is not so much the aims as the methods
of government action.
References are often made to those modest and innocent aims of govern-
mental activity to show how unreasonable is any opposition to the welfare
state as such. But, once the rigid position that government should not
concern itself at all with such matters is abandoned - a position which is
defensible but has little to do with freedom- the defenders of liberty com-
monly discover that the programme of the welfare state comprises a great
deal more that is represented as equally legitimate and unobjectionable. If,
for instance, they admit that they have no objection to pure-food laws, this
is taken to imply that they should not object to any government activity
directed toward a desirable end. Those who attempt to delimit the functions
of government in terms of aims rather than methods thus regularly find
themselves in the position of having to oppose state action which appears
to have only desirable consequences or of having to admit that they have no
general rule on which to base their objections to measures which, though
effective for particular purposes, would in their aggregate effect destroy a
free society. Though the position that the state should have nothing to do
with matters not related to the maintenance of law and order may seem
logical so long as we think of the state solely as a coercive apparatus, we
must recognize that, as a service agency, it may assist without harm in the
achievement of desirable aims which perhaps could not be achieved other-
wise. The reason why many of the new welfare activities of government are
a threat to freedom, then, is that, though they are presented as mere service
activities, they really constitute an exercise of the coercive powers of gov-
ernment and rest on its claiming exclusive rights in certain fields.
The current situation has greatly altered the task of the defender of liberty
and made it much more difficult. So long as the danger came from social-
ism of the frankly collectivist kind, it was possible to argue that the tenets
of the socialists were simply false: that socialism would not achieve what
the socialists wanted and that it would produce other consequences which
they would not like. We cannot argue similarly against the welfare state,
for this term does not designate a definite system. What goes under that
name is a conglomerate of so many diverse and even contradictory elem-
ents that, while some of them may make a free society more attractive,
others are incompatible with it or may at least constitute potential threats
to its existence.
We shall see that some of the aims of the welfare state can be realized
without detriment to individual liberty, though not necessarily by the
methods which seem the most obvious and are therefore most popular; that
others can be similarly achieved to a certain extent, though only at a cost
much greater than people imagine or would be willing to bear, or
only slowly and gradually as wealth increases; and that, finally, there are
92 The Meaning of the Welfare State
others - and they are those particularly dear to the hearts of the socialists_
that cannot be realized in a society that wants to preserve personal freedom.
There are all kinds of public amenities which it may be in,,the interest of
all members of the community to provide by common effort, such as parks
and museums, theatres and facilities for sports - though there are strong
reasons why they should be provided by local rather than national author-
ities. There is then the important issue of security, of protection against
risks common to all, where government can often either reduce these risks
or assist people to provide against them. Here, however, an important <;lis-
tinction has to be drawn between two conceptions of security: a limited
security which can be achieved for all and which is, therefore, no privilege,
and absolute security, which in a free society cannot be achieved for all. The
first of these is security against severe physical privation, the assurance of
a given minimum of sustenance for all; and the second is the assurance of
a given standard of life, which is determined by comparing the standard
enjoyed by a person or a group with that of others. The distinction, then,
is that between the security of an equal minimum income for all and the
security of a particular income that a person is thought to deserve. The
latter is closely related to the third main ambition that inspires the welfare
state: the desire to use the powers of government to ensure a more even or
more just distribution of goods. Insofar as this means that the coercive
powers of government are to be used to ensure that particular people get
particular things, it requires a kind of discrimination between, and an
unequal treatment of, different people which is irreconcilable with a free
society. This is the kind of welfare state that aims at 'social justice' and
becomes 'primarily a redistributor of income'. It is bound to lead back to
socialism and its coercive and essentially arbitrary methods.
Though some of the aims of the welfare state can be achieved only by
methods inimical to liberty, all its aims may be pursued by such methods.
The chief danger today is that, once an aim of government is accepted as
legitimate, it is then assumed that even means contrary to the principles of
freedom may be legitimately employed. The unfortunate fact is that, in the
majority of fields, the most effective, certain and speedy way of reaching a
given end will seem to be to direct all available resources towards the now
visible solution. To the ambitious and impatient reformer, filled with indig-
nation at a particular evil, nothing short of the complete abolition of that evil
by the quickest and most direct means will seem adequate. If every person
now suffering from unemployment, ill health or inadequate provision for
[ ... ] old age is at once to be relieved of his [or her] cares, nothing short of
an all-comprehensive and compulsory scheme will suffice. But if, in our
impatience to solve such problems immediately, we give government exclu-
sive and monopolistic powers, we may find that we have been short-sighted.
If the quickest way to a now visible solution becomes the only permissible
Friedrich von Hayek 93
one and all alternative experimentation is precluded, and if what now seems
the best method of satisfying a need is made the sole starting-point for all
future development, we may perhaps reach our present goal sooner, but we
shall probably at the same time prevent the emergence of more effective
alternative solutions. It is often those who are most anxious to use our exist-
ing knowledge and powers to the full that do most to impair the future
growth of knowledge by the methods they use. The controlled single-
channel development towards which impatience and administrative con-
venience have frequently inclined the reformer and which, especially in the
field of social insurance, has become characteristic of the modern welfare
state may well become the chief obstacle to future improvement.
If government wants not merely to facilitate the attainment of certain
standards by the individuals but to make certain that everybody attains
them it can do so only by depriving individuals of any choice in the matter.
Thus the welfare state becomes a household state in which a paternalistic
power controls most of the income of the community and allocates it to
individuals in the forms and quantities which it thinks they need or deserve.
In many fields persuasive arguments based on considerations of effi-
ciency and economy can be advanced in favour of the state's taking sole
charge of a particular service; but when the state does so, the result is
usually not only that those advantages soon prove illusory but that the
character of the services becomes entirely different from that which they
would have had if they had been provided by competing agencies. If,
instead of administering limited resources put under its control for a spe-
cific service, government uses its coercive powers to ensure that men are
given what some expert thinks they need; if people thus can no longer exer-
cise any choice in some of the most important matters of their lives, such
as health, employment, housing and provision for old age, but must accept
the decisions made for them by appointed authority on the basis of its
evaluation of their need; if certain services become the exclusive domain of
the state, and whole professions- be it medicine, education or insurance-
come to exist only as unitary bureaucratic hierarchies, it will no longer be
competitive experimentation but solely the decisions of authority that will
determine what men shall get. 3
The same reasons that generally make the impatient reformer wish to
organize such services in the form of government monopolies lead him also
to believe that the authorities in charge should be given wide discretionary
powers over the individual. If the objective were merely to improve oppor-
tunities for all by supplying certain specific services according to a rule, this
could be attained on essentially business lines. But we could then never be
sure that the results for all individuals would be precisely what we wanted.
If each individual is to be affected in some particular way, nothing short of
the individualizing, paternalistic treatment by a discretionary authority
with powers of discriminating between persons will do.
94 The Meaning of the Welfare State
It is sheer illusion to think that when certain needs of the citizen have
become the exclusive concern of a single bureaucratic machine, democratic
control of that machine can then effectively guard the libc~ty: ofthe citizen.
So far as the preservation of personal liberty is concerned, the division of
labour between a legislature which merely says that this or that should be
done 4 and an administrative apparatus which is given exclusive power to
carry out these instructions is the most dangerous arrangement possible.
All experience confirms what is clear enough from American as
well as from English experience, that the zeal of the administrative agencies to
achieve the immediate ends they see before them leads them to see their func-
tion out of focus and to assume that constitutional limitations and guaranteed
individual rights must give way before their zealous efforts to achieve what
they see as a paramount purpose of government. 5
Notes
name. And the evil would be greater, the more efficiently and scientifically the
administrative machinery was constructed- the more skilful the arrangements
for obtaining the best qualified hands and heads with which to work it.'
4 Cf. T. H. Marshall, Citizenship and Social Class, Cambridge, 1958, p. 59: 'So
we find that legislation ... acquires more and more the character of a declara-
tion of policy that it is hoped to put into effect some day.'
5 Roscoe Pound, 'The Rise of the Service State and its Consequence', in The
Welfare State and the National Welfare, ed. S. Glueck, Cambridge, MA, 1952,
p. 220.
6 P. Wiles, 'Property and Equality', in The Unservile State, ed. G. Watson,
London, 1957, p. 107.
7 See L. von Mises, Human Action, New Haven, 1949, pp. 196ff.
The Two Wars against
Poverty
Charles Murray
[ ... ]
When news reports cite percentages of 'people living in poverty', they are
drawing from the official definition of the 'poverty line' established in 1964
by a task force in the Social Security Administration. The poverty line is,
in effect, set at three times the cost of an adequate diet, and is adjusted for
inflation, a variety of family characteristics and one's location (rural or
non-rural).
This measure has been attacked as niggardly by some and as overly gen-
erous by others. Almost everyone agrees that it fails to capture the import-
ant differences in the quality of life between a family living at the poverty
line in the South Bronx, for example, and a family with the same income
that lives in a less punishing environment. But this measure of poverty has
its merits nonetheless. It is widely known, it takes family size and inflation
into account, and it provides a consistent measure for examining income
over time. I will use it to discuss the history of three different 'types' of
poverty: official poverty, net poverty and latent poverty [ ... ].
The most widely used measure of poverty is the percentage of people with
cash incomes that fall beneath the poverty line before taxes, but after taking
cash income transfers from government into account. We shall call it official
poverty because it is the measure reported by the Bureau of the Census.
Conventional wisdom has it that, at least according to this one measure,
the 1960s and 1970s brought economic progress for the poor. The most
widely shared view of recent events is that the United States entered the
1960s with a large population that had been bypassed during the prosper-
ity of the Eisenhower years. The rich and the middle class gained but the
poor did not. Then, after fits and starts during the Kennedy years, came the
explosion in the number and size of social programmes under Johnson.
Charles Murray 97
Net Poverty
The official poverty statistic is based only on cash income. In-kind assist-
ance- food programmes, housing, medical care- is not included. Yet this
assistance has been the fastest-growing component of the social welfare
budget, rising from $2.2 billion in 1965 to $72.5 billion in 1980. If the dollar
value of these benefits is computed and added to cash income, this new
measure may be called net poverty: the percentage of the population
remaining beneath the poverty level after all resources- cash and in-kind,
earned and unearned- are taken into account. 2
In 1950, in-kind transfers were quite small, so the percentage of official
poor (30 per cent) was nearly identical to the percentage of net poor. This
situation continued into the early 1960s as net poverty decreased at
roughly the same rate as official poverty. By 1968, the gap between official
poverty (12.8 per cent) and net poverty (10.1 per cent) was quite small.
Unlike changes in official poverty, however, large decreases in net
poverty continued into the early 1970s. Then, from 1972 until 1980, the
trendline flattened, just as that for official poverty had a few years earlier.
In 1980, net poverty stood at 6.1 per cent of the population, compared with
6.2 per cent in 1972, despite the fact that expenditures on in-kind assistance
had tripled (in constant dollars) during the 1970s.
The concept of net poverty is ambiguous. Taken by itself, 6.1 per cent
represents a near victory over poverty; it is a very small proportion of the
population. But a citizen who lives in a black or Hispanic ghetto, for
example, may be forgiven for arguing that poverty has not come within 6.1
percentage points of vanishing. We must consider what it really means to
live at or near the poverty level through in-kind support.
It means, to begin with, living in housing projects or other subsidized
housing. Given their cost, most of these units ought to provide decent,
comfortable housing, but in practice public housing is among the most
vandalized, crime-ridden and least livable housing in the country. It means
relying on food stamps. In theory, food stamps can purchase the foods
Charles Murray 99
necessary for a nutritious diet, but in practice they can be misused in other
ways. It also means paying for medical care through Medicaid or Medicare,
which have concrete value only if the recipient is sick.
In short, having the resources for a life that meets basic standards of
decency is not the same as actually living such an existence. Whether this
is the fault of the welfare system or the recipient is not at issue; it is simply
a fact that must be kept in mind when interpreting the small, encouraging
:figure of 6.1 per cent.
But the economic point remains: as of 1980, the many overlapping cash
and in-kind benefit programmes made it possible for almost anyone to
place themselves above the official poverty level. If the ultimate criterion
of social welfare policy is eliminating net poverty, the War on Poverty has
very nearly been won.
Latent Poverty
We are not content to accept endless growth of relief or welfare rolls. We want
to offer the forgotten fifth of our population opportunity and not doles ....
The days of the dole in our country are numbered. 3
poor [was] calculated. 4 But we do know that the number of latent poor (pre-
transfer poor) can be no smaller than the number of post-:-transfer poor;
therefore, since the number of post-transfer poor stood at 30 pzr cent of the
population in 1950, the percentage of latent poor had to have been somewhat
larger (a conservative estimate is 32 per cent). As of 1965, the latent poor
were 21 per cent of the population- a drop of about one-third. Put another
way, dependency decreased during the years 1950-65. Increasing numbers
of people were able to make a living that put them above the poverty level
and progress was being made on the long-range goal of eliminating the dole.
The proportion of latent poor continued to drop through 1968, when the
percentage was calculated at 18.2, but this [ ... ] proved to be the limit of
our success in the war against economic dependence. At some point during
1968-9, progress stopped; the percentage of latent poor then started to grow.
It was 19 per cent by 1972, 21 per cent by 1976, and 22 per cent by 1980. 5
Once again, as in the case of official poverty, the shift in the trendline coin-
cided with the advent of the programmes that were to eliminate poverty.
Again, how could it be that progress against official poverty and net
poverty slowed or stopped when so much more money was being spent
for cash and in-kind transfers? The data on latent poverty provide one of
the most important answers: because latent poverty was increasing, it took
more and more money in transfers just to keep the percentage of post-
transfer poor stable. The social welfare system fell into the classic trap of
having to run faster and faster to stay in the same place. The extremely large
increases in social welfare spending during the 1970s were papering over
the increase in latent poverty.
The three measures of poverty- official poverty, net poverty and latent
poverty- reveal a pattern from 1950 to 1980 that has important implica-
tions for the American welfare state. For example, it explains a major
element in the budget crisis. As of 1980, roughly the same proportion of
people remained above the poverty line through their own earned incomes
as did in the early 1960s. But in the early 1960s, our legislated spending
obligations to those who earned less than that amount were comparatively
small. Whether or not one approves of the spending obligations taken on
since then, they cannot be sustained indefinitely in the face of increasing
latent poverty. Latent poverty must be turned around, or the obligations
must be slashed, or both.
The poverty trendlines [ ... ] are not widely publicized. Because it has not
been recognized that the implementation of the Great Society reforms
coincided with an end to progress in reducing poverty, there has been no
debate over why this should be the case.
Charles Murray 101
The best place to begin the debate is to examine the common view that
the bright hopes of the 1960s dimmed in the 1970s due to a slowdown in
the economy. According to this view, inflation and dislocations brought on
by the Vietnam War, along with the revolution in energy prices, made the
economy go sour. As the expansionist environment of the 1960s vanished,
strategies and programmes of the War on Poverty had to be put aside. It is
aood
b
that the entitlements and income transfer programmes were in place,
runs this line of argument, or else the troubles in the economy would have
been even more devastating on the poor.
What, if anything, do the data suggest about the merits of this economic
explanation? As in the discussion of poverty, I must start with the simplest,
most widely used measure of the state of the economy, growth in the GNP,
and examine its relation to changes in the number of people living in
poverty. The answer - perhaps surprisingly to those who have ridiculed
'trickle-down' as a way to help the poor- is that changes in GNP have a
very strong inverse relation to changes in poverty. As GNP increases,
poverty decreases. (The simple correlation coefficient for the period
1950-80 is - .69 6 .) The effects of economic growth did indeed trickle down
to the lowest economic levels of the society. Economic growth during the
1950s and 1960s was strong, during the 1970s it was weak- and progress
in reducing poverty ceased.
So it can be said that the fortunes of the economy explain recent trends
in poverty. But the flip side of this finding is that social welfare expendi-
tures did not have an effect on poverty. Once the effects of GNP are taken
into account, increases in social welfare spending do not account for reduc-
tions in poverty [since the 1950s}. The same analysis that supports the eco-
nomic explanation for the failure in the 1970s gives scant support to
remedies that would boost social welfare spending [ ... ].
Conservatives generally recognize the role of economic growth in
reducing poverty, but some feel this is not a sufficient explanation for the
failures of the 1970s. It is not just that the social welfare reforms were inef-
fective in reducing poverty, they argue, but that the reforms actually made
matters worse by emasculating the work ethic and creating 'work disin-
centives'. As people became less inclined to take low-paying jobs, hold
onto them, and use them to get out of poverty, they became dependent on
government assistance. The academic treatment of poverty has generally
dismissed this conservative explanation out of hand. It has understandably
been mistaken for curmudgeonly, mean-spirited and occasionally racist
rhetoric. But the trendline for latent poverty - the key indicator of how
people are doing without government help- offers a solid reason for con-
cluding that the Great Society reforms exacerbated many of the conditions
they sought to alleviate.
It is important to emphasize that the trend in latent poverty did not
reverse direction when the economy went bad; it did not even wait until
102 The Two Wars against Poverty
the official poverty and net poverty figures stabilized .. Latent poverty
started to increa~e.while the other two measures of poverty w.ere still going
down. Most stnkmgly, progress on latent poverty stopped IQ 1968 while
the economy was operating at full capacity (unemployment stood at
3.5 per cent in 1968-9, the lowest rate since the Korean War).
The second half of the 1960s was a watershed in other ways as well.
A number of social indicators began showing strange and unanticipated
shifts during those years, and the onset of these changes had no discernible
relation to the health of the economy. Together, the evidence is sufficiently
provocative to make the conservative interpretation worth looking into.
One such indicator is participation in the labour force. By definition, par-
ticipation in the civilian labour force means either being employed or
intending to work, given the opportunity. Among the poor, participation in
the labour force 'should' be very high, approaching 100 per cent, for able-
bodied adults without childcare responsibilities. Conservatives argue that
such participation has dropped because welfare benefits have become more
extensive and more easily available. The statistics on labour-force participa-
tion- a standard measure calculated by the Bureau of Labor Statistics- are
readily available, and they conform quite well to conservative expectations.
Consider the record of two populations of immediate comparative inter-
est: black males, who are disproportionately poor relative to the entire
population, and white males, who are disproportionately well off. In 1948
(comparable data for 1950 are not available), the participation rate for both
groups was 87 per cent. This equivalence- one of the very few social or eco-
nomic measures on which black males could claim parity with whites in the
1950s - continued throughout the decade and into the early 1960s. As late
as 1965, only a percentage point separated the two groups. But by 1968,
a gap of 3.4 percentage points in participation had opened up between black
males and white males. By 1972, the gap was 5.9 percentage points. In 1980,
70.5 per cent of black males participated in the labour force compared with
78.6 of white males; the gap had grown to 8.1 percentage points. To put it
another way, during the period 1954-67, 1.4 black males dropped out of the
labour force for every white male who dropped out; from 1968 to 1980, 3.6
black males dropped out for every white male who did.
The abrupt drop in the labour-force participation of black males cannot
easily be linked to events in the economy at large. One of the most com-
monly cited popular explanations of why poor people drop out of the
labour force is that they become discouraged- there are no jobs, so people
quit looking. But the gap first opened up during the boom years of 1966-8,
when unemployment was at a historic low. The 'discouraged worker'
Charles Murray 103
argument cannot be used to explain the drop-out rate during this period.
Nor can the opposite argument be substituted: black males did not stop
dropping out when the Vietnam boom cooled and unemployment rose.
Whether unemployment was high or low, until 1967 black males behaved
the same as whites; after 1967 they did not.
One may ask whether this is a racial phenomenon; it is nothing of the
kind. Using the 1970 census data, participation for 1970 may be broken
down by both race and economic status, and doing so reveals that the
apparent racial difference is artificial. For males at comparable income
levels, labour-force participation among black males was higher than
among white males. The explanation of the gap is not race, but income.
Starting in 1966, low-income males- white or black- started dropping out
of the labour force. The only reason it looks as though blacks were drop-
ping out at higher rates is that blacks are disproportionately poor. If trend-
lines are examined showing participation rates by income rather than race,
the 1970 census data strongly suggest that middle- and upper-income males
participated in the labour force at virtually unchanged rates since the 1950s,
while the participation rate for low-income males decreased slowly until
1966, and plummeted thereafter.
This phenomenon needs explanation, for it was a fundamental change in
economic behaviour - participation in the labour market itself. Once
explanations based on unemployment fail, and once the racial discrepancy
is shown to be artificial, the conservative hypothesis has considerable
force. Without a doubt, something happened in the mid-1960s that
changed the incentives for low-income workers to stay in the job market.
The Great Society reforms constitute the biggest, most visible, most plaus-
ible candidate.
A Pyrrhic Victory?
The effect of the decline in labour-force participation, and of the breakup
of the husband-wife family, were tragic and severe. In the case of the labour
market, the nature of the effect is obvious: when low-income males drop
out of the labour force and low-income females do not enter it, the size of
the latent poor population will grow. This alone could explain why the
proportion of latent poor increased even as the proportions of official poor
and net poor were still declining.
The effects of family breakup are less obvious, but no less noteworthy.
An analysis by the Bureau of the Census indicates that changes in family
composition accounted for two million additional poor families in the
1970s. 7 For example, the analysis shows that if black family composition
had remained the same as in 1971, the poverty rate for black families would
have been 20 per cent in 1980 instead of 29 per cent. Other findings all lead
to the same conclusion: the changes in family composition that started in
the mid-1960s have raised poverty significantly above the levels that 'would
have' prevailed otherwise. The Bureau's analysis actually understates the
overall effect of the change in family composition on poverty- by 1971, the
baseline for the analysis, much of the deterioration had already occurred.
These are some of the reasons behind the paradox of our failure to make
progress against poverty in the 1970s despite the enormous increases in the
amount of money that the government has spent to do so. There are other
reasons as well- the large proportion of the social welfare budget spent on
people above the poverty level being perhaps the most notable- but the
preceding few will serve to convey a point that is too often missed in the
debates over budget cuts in social welfare programmes. It is genuinely an
open issue - intellectually as well as politically - whether we should be
talking about spending cuts, or whether we should be considering an over-
haul of the entire welfare system as conceived in the Great Society. If the
War on Poverty is construed as having begun in 1950 instead of 1964, it
may fairly be said that we were winning the war until Lyndon Johnson
decided to wage it.
Notes
2 The figures are taken from Timothy M. Smeeding, Measuring the Economic
Welfare of Low-Income Households and the Antipoverty Effectiveness of Cash
and Noncash Transfer Programs, PhD diss., Department .of Economics,
University of Wisconsin-Madison, 1975; Smeeding, 'The Antipoverty
Effectiveness of In-Kind Transfers', Journal of Human Resources, 12, 1977,
pp. 360-78; and Smeeding, 'The Anti-poverty Effect of In-Kind Transfers:
A 'Good Idea Gone Too Far?', Policy Studies journal, 10, 3, 1982 pp. 499-522.
3 Quoted in the New York Times, 21 August 1964, p. 1.
4 The figures for 1965-78 are taken from Sheldon Danziger and Robert
Plotnick, 'The War on Income Poverty: Achievements and Failures', in
Welfare Reform in America, ed. P. Sommers, Hingham, MA, Martinus
Nijhoff, 1982, table 3.1, p. 40.
5 It should be noted that the measure of latent poverty excludes social security
income. Since families headed by persons over the age of sixty-five make up
nearly half of those in latent poverty, the percentages reported here may
somewhat exaggerate the extent of the problem among those able to
work. (Unfortunately, no figures on this point prior to 1976 have been pub-
lished.) But even if it were possible to include social security- or exclude the
elderly- in calculations over this period, this adjustment would not affect the
steep rise in latent poverty we have observed. [ ... ]
6 The variables are the first difference in real GNP per household and the first
difference in percentage of population under the poverty line using the official
measure of poverty.
7 Gordon Green and Edward Wclniak, 'Measuring the Effects of Changing
Family Composition during the 1970s on Black-White Differences in
Income', unpublished manuscript, Bureau of the Census, 1982.
The New- Politics of the New
Poverty
Lawrence M. Mead
Recent disagreements over tax hikes and budget cuts suggest that redis-
tributive conflicts over the economy remain very much with us; economic
inequality has increased, and Kevin Phillips's prediction ,of heightened
conflict between rich and poor received much attention [in 1990].
Nevertheless, in the absence of economic collapse serious class conflict is
unlikely. The politics of conduct, which focuses on dependency and dis-
order, is simply more salient than the politics of class. The problems of
rising crime, welfarism, homelessness and declining schools (and the tax
increases imposed to pay for them) are what chiefly concern most
Americans; they worry far less about the income gap separating them from
their employers. Most Americans doubt government's ability to solve the
new social problems that confront us. Unless government better responds
to them, it will receive no new mandate to tackle the older problem of
unequal fortunes.
The public's focus on dependency and disorder has obviously damaged
the American left, which is more comfortable dealing with issues of eco-
nomic redistribution. The public's conservatism on social (as opposed to
economic) issues largely explains why Republicans have controlled the
White House and the national agenda for most of a generation. Democrats
in presidential politics have paid a high price for their perceived softness
on the question of 'values'. In the 1988 election, Michael Dukakis pro-
posed new benefit programmes of the kind that used to win elections for
Democrats. The Bush campaign easily defeated him by speaking of crime
and Willie Horton.
But despite its electoral advantages, the anti-government right -like the
redistributionist left - is uncomfortable with dependency politics. When
the poor behave badly, bigger government becomes indefensible, because
many of its beneficiaries are 'undeserving'. But smaller government is also
questionable, because many believe that the poor could not cope without
the many benefits and services that they receive. Distrust of the dysfunc-
tional poor defeated the most ambitious plans to expand government
during the Great Society. But concern for these same poor helps explain
why Ronald Reagan was unable significantly to reduce the size of domes-
tic government.
poor are now substantially detached from the economy. Each in its own way,
these strategies provided new chances to poor adults, but neither directly
addressed the puzzling reluctance of the poor to do more to help themselves.
As a result, social policy has been driven away from structural reforms
and towards paternalism. The drift is toward policies that address motiva-
tion by seeking to direct the lives of those dependent on government.
Public institutions are taking over tutelary functions from weakened fam-
ilies. Social-service agencies are raising children, and schools are organiz-
ing the lives of students before and after class as well as during it. Homeless
shelters and the criminal-justice system are managing the disordered
lives of single men. Above all, recent welfare legislation requires rising
numbers of employable recipients to participate in job placement or train-
ing on pain of cuts in their grants. Such measures violate the traditional pre-
scriptions of liberals, who want benefits given without conditions, but also
those of conservatives, who would prefer to see discipline applied by the
private rather than the public sector. But they seem required by the chang-
ing nature of the social problem.
These trends are most advanced in the US, but they are appearing in
Europe as well. An underclass, largely non-white, has grown up in British
cities, while throughout Europe controversy rages over whether immig-
rants from the Third World are corrupting traditional mores. These racial
and ethnic divisions now arouse more passion than the traditional conflicts
of labour and business. The behaviour of 'outsiders' is far more contro-
versial than economic claims. Crime, dependency and a failure to learn the
national language are at issue, not working-class demands for higher wages
and benefits. The West as a whole seems destined for a politics of conduct
rather than class.
than the economic, structure of society is at issue. The focus -is on troubled
individuals or ethnic groups rather than industry, agriculture, or the rela-
tions of labour and management. Social problems are no longe.t seen to stem
directly from injustice, nor are they obviously reformable. So social policy
must focus on motivation and order rather than opportunity or equality.
Affluence helped produce this shift. Before the 1960s, working-class
incomes were still low enough that many people were poor, even though
they worked normal hours. That is much less common today, because the
poverty line is constant in real terms while real wages have risen. The poor,
who used to work more than the better-off, now commonly work less.
Inevitably, the focus of the social agenda has shifted from the low wages
that used to impoverish workers to the dysfunctions that keep the non-
working poor out of the labour force.
In progressive-era politics the issue was government control of the
economy; in dependency politics it is government supervision of behaviour.
Progressive-era politicians disputed how far government should regulate
the free market in the collective interest, how much it should spend on
benefit programmes such as Social Security.
In dependency politics, however, the chief question is how far govern-
ment should control the lives of dysfunctional people in their own inter-
ests. Do we require that people stay in school, obey the law, avoid drugs,
and so on? Above all, do we require adults to work or prepare for work as
a condition of receiving welfare? Proposals to do these things do not much
change what government does for people. Rather, they demand that
dependants do more for themselves in return.
Formerly it was local authorities who grappled with maintaining social
order, while Washington managed the economy. But order issues have
become federal, because national programmes are involved in all the key
areas- welfare, education and criminal justice. It is now the main domestic
challenge of presidents, as of mayors, to reduce crime and dependency and
to raise standards in the schools. Presidents Nixon, Carter and Reagan all
tried to reform welfare, and George Bush aspired to be an 'education pres-
ident'.
The old issues concerned adults; the new issues concern children and
youth. Progressive-era political claims were on behalf of adults, especially
workers. The question was how to reorganize government or the economy
so that adults could have influence and opportunity. In the dependency era,
however, these issues are less salient than people's problems on the road to
adulthood - illegitimacy, educational failure and crime. So dependency
politics focuses heavily on the formative years. Reformism aims to
improve family, neighbourhood and schools rather than the political or
economic structure.
Daniel Patrick Moynihan says that social policy has entered a 'post-
industrial' age. The main challenge is no longer to expand economic
Lawrence M. Mead 113
opportunity but to overcome social weaknesses that stem from the 'post-
marital' family and the inability of many people to get through school.
The inequalities that stem from the workplace are now trivial in comparison
to those stemming from family structure. What matters for success is
less whether your father was rich or poor than whether you knew your
father at all.
A focus on youth is inevitable once the leading social problem changes
from the poverty of workers to dysfunctional poverty. For if the source of
poverty is behaviour rather than lack of opportunity, remedies must focus
on youth, the stage of life at which behaviour is most malleable.
Conversely, reform for adults must be structural because it must take
personality largely as given.
The pressures in progressive-era politics arise from self-seeking beha-
viour; in dependency politics, they arise from passivity. Progressive-era pol-
itics debates the freedom that America allows people to make money and
get ahead on their own. To conservatives, this prerogative is a right that
government may not limit. To the left, it is a licence that government must
restrain in the name of a broader social interest.
The poor and dependent, however, are not exploitative but inert. They
are controversial mostly because they do so little to help themselves, not
because they hurt others in the pursuit of advantage. Even when violent,
they are unable to exert themselves effectively. They are not aggressive so
much as passive aggressive. So in dependency politics, the issue is whether
poor people should have to do more to help themselves. The question is
how passive you can be and still be a citizen in full standing.
Formerly, the right defended property and the established order against
public controls. Now it is the left that defends the status quo, by justify-
ing passivity among the needy, while the right demands greater activity.
Recent measures such as workfare or reformed schools are attempts to
stimulate the poor, not to curb the rich. The point is to set a floor under
self-advancement, not a ceiling above it. The hope is to make the poor more
effectively self-seeking than they are.
Claims in progressive-era politics derived from strength; those in depend-
ency politics arise from weakness. The chief players in the progressive era
were unions, farmers, businesses and other economic interests that
demanded some benefit or protection from government on a basis of desert.
They were economically disadvantaged, but their demands were also made
from a position of strength, because they had economic and political
resources of their own. They could use these resources to get attention from
politicians, but they could also survive on their own if rebuffed.
In dependency politics, the claimants usually have no such strength, as
they lack any regular position in the economy. They are simply needy.
Their main claim is precisely their vulnerability. It is not their own power
that gets attention, but politicians' fear of a backlash from the better-off if
114 The New Politics of the New Poverty
the needy are left unprotected. Economic groups state their claims by
speaking of troubled finances. The very poor state theirs by a disassembly
of the personality- by failing to function in embarrassing w;:1.ys that force
society to take responsibility for them.
In dependency politics, the poor claim a right to support based on the
injuries of the past, not on anything that they contribute now. Wounds are
an asset today, much as a pay cheque was in progressive-era politics. One
claims to be a victim, not a worker. The non-white poor, particularly,
appeal to historic injustices. Even some policies that aid better-functioning
minorities, such as affirmative action, require their beneficiaries to adopt
the identity of victimhood to some extent- to exploit an appeal, as Shelby
Steele says, based on 'suffering' rather than 'achievements'.
Poverty shifts the agenda from equality to citizenship. The question is
no longer what the worst-off members of the community should receive.
Now the question is who should be considered a bona fide member of the
community in the first place. Who has the moral standing to make the
demands for economic redress typically made in the progressive era? When
dependency comes to dominate politics, class-oriented issues of equality
for workers inevitably move off the agenda, while issues of identity and
belonging replace them.
In Europe as well as the US, dependency concerns replaced progressive
ones as motives for the reconsideration of the welfare state that began in
the 1970s and 1980s. At first, the issues were economic, the fear that exces-
sive spending on income and health programmes was overburdening the
economy. Cuts were made to promote economic growth, the step conser-
vatives always recommend in progressive-era politics. [In the 1990s],
however, the greater concern has been declining social cohesion, as evi-
denced by rises in crime, single parenthood and chronic unemployment.
The response, in Britain and Sweden as in the US, has been new steps to
enforce child support and work effort among the dependent. The shift
from the older, redistributive agenda to these new, more behavioural issues
ushers in a new political age.
[ ... ]
effort (though they have not yet reduced dependency). But it is doubtful
that even these programmes can do more than contain the social problem.
Even if they are effective, paternalistic measures raise serious political
objections. The new structures reduce disorder, but at a cost to the auton-
omy of clients. This is particularly true if, as is likely, the chronic poor
require direction on an on-going basis, not just temporarily. That is why,
even now, government prefers to spend money on the dependent rather
than try to tell them how to live. Benefits lack the power of public author-
ity to change behaviour, but they do not violate our notions of a free
society.
A more serious problem stems from our political traditions. Anti-depen-
dency policies - and disputes about them- find no basis in the Western
political tradition, which assumes that the individuals who compose society
are competent to advance their own interests, if not society's. The tradi-
tional Western assumption is that politics arises from conflicting interests,
as individuals and groups seek economic advantage. Government's task is
to resolve these disputes in the general interest. It does not animate society,
but rather responds to energy coming from below.
Historically, Western politics has been class-oriented: aristocratic elites,
then bourgeois elements, then workers without property have advanced
their own conceptions of how government and the economy should be
organized. The dominant principles have become more democratic, then
more collectivist, as government came to represent the mass of the popu-
lace and then to serve its needs. The contending visions may seem radically
opposed, but from today's perspective they were remarkably alike: all
assumed a working population, competent to advance its own interests.
This tradition is inapplicable to the problems posed by today's dysfunc-
tional poor. But policy makers in [the US] and Europe are prone to
respond to these problems by replaying the old scenarios. Today's liberals
see history as a grand progression in which the rights of ordinary people
have been expanded: first civil liberties, then representative government,
then protections against the insecurities of capitalism were attained. Faced
with passive poverty, the left can imagine no response other than provid-
ing some further entitlement, for example government jobs. The idea that
dependants should have to function better seems like an attempt to deny
benefits, and is thus anathema.
Anti-government conservatives, for their part, blame poverty on an
excess of government, just as the left blames it on the lack of government
intervention. They insist that cuts in spending and taxes will somehow lib-
erate the energy of the poor, as they do that of entrepreneurs. The idea that
competence is a prior and different problem, requiring perhaps more gov-
ernment rather than less, is unthinkable.
These liberal and conservative responses are doomed to fail. If the ser-
iously poor had the initiative to respond to new opportunities, they would
116 The New Politics of the New Poverty
not be poor for very long in the first place. The Great Society .and the Reagan
era both failed to solve poverty, because each in a different way offered new
chances to the poor without confronting the motivation pi-o~ble~. Neither
could seriously address competence, because that problem fell outside the
Western assumptions underlying their ideas of social reform.
But despite these conceptual failures, government has begun to do some-
thing about poverty: a new, paternalistic regime for the poor is emerging.
Ronald Reagan's greatest domestic legacy, despite his tax cuts, was not to
reduce government; it was to start changing welfare into workfare. But ~he
new regime is accepted grudgingly, if at all. Politicians argue heatedly
about the issues of responsibility and competence that it raises, but they
seldom do so honestly. They mention the 'underclass' and the need for dis-
cipline, but they still talk as if they were offering the poor only 'freedom'
or 'opportunity'.
We need a new political language that considers more candidly the ques-
tions of human nature that now underlie politics. The political contestants
need to defend their positions on a philosophic level, rather than hide
behind outmoded theories. Liberals need to show why poor people are
blameless, therefore still deserving; conservatives need to show how the
poor are competent and why they need to be held accountable, in spite of
dysfunction. From such premises they could then erect consistent doc-
trines of social policy, comparable to the competing theories of economic
management that framed the leading issues in the progressive era.
If anyone is writing this theory, it is not philosophers like John Rawls and
his critics (who assume a rational economic psychology and thus remain
wedded to the competence assumption) but social-policy experts who
grapple concretely with poverty. They know too much of the hard evidence
about barriers to pretend that nothing has changed. To explain poverty and
justify any policy toward it, experts need a psychological doctrine that
explains how personal degradation occurs in an affluent and open society.
Differing visions of human nature are what really divide Charles
Murray, William Julius Wilson, myself and others. For Murray, poor adults
are short-sighted calculators who are tempted into dysfunction by the dis-
incentives of welfare. For Wilson, they are driven into disorder by a chan-
ging economy that denies them jobs that could support a family. My own
view, articulated in Beyond Entitlement: The Social Obligations of
Citizenship [1986], is that they are depressed but dutiful, willing to observe
mainstream norms like work if only government will enforce them. But
none of us has defended these premises in enough depth, or linked them
clearly enough to our prescriptions.
Armed with theories like this, the political process might face more
squarely the issues raised by dependency politics. It is more important that
the positions be candid than that they agree. Progress requires that the fears
of both sides be more fully aired, not that one side wins. The debate might
Lawrence M. Mead 117
Note
From The Public Interest, 103,1991, pp. 3-20; fuller version in Lawrence M. Mead,
The New Politics of Poverty, New York, Basic Books, 1992.
Feminism
Feminism and Social Pol~cy
Mary Mclntosh
During the 1970s, feminists developed a critique of the welfare system that
was both sophisticated and damning. It began in a fragmentary way in the
early seventies with specific protests about issues like the 'cohabitation
rule' and the 'tax credit' proposals. There was a growing awareness that
women figure prominently among the clients of social workers, the
inmates of geriatric and psychiatric hospitals, the claimants of supplemen-
tary benefits- despite the fact that married and cohabiting women are not
eligible for many benefits. There was resentment about the degrading way
that women are treated when they need state benefits and state services.
The first responses were articulated most clearly by libertarian feminists,
who could express vividly what women know of the conditions under
which welfare is granted. They know the queues and the forms, the defer-
ence, the anger, the degradation, the sense of invisibility and the loss of
autonomy. They see the mean, withholding face of the state and can readily
take up the negative cry of 'smash the state!' But the cohabitation campaign
also raised deeper issues. It was not just that the 'SS' were 'sex snoopers'
who prevented women claimants from drawing their benefit if they were
suspected of living with a man. They also tried to force women into pros-
titutional dependence on the men they slept with. This raised the whole
question of women's dependence on men and the fact that women were
second-class citizens. The Women's Family Allowance Campaign against
the Tory government's 1972 tax-credit proposals focused on the same
problems. The family allowance paid directly to a mother was preferable
to the same, or even a greater, amount paid in tax credits through a father's
pay packet. The model of the couple as a financial unit bore little relation
to reality as many women experienced it. In the end, after we had defeated
this aspect of the tax-credit scheme, the trade unions' reluctance to accept
the loss of the child tax allowance that accompanied the improved child
Mary Mcintosh 121
benefit only verified what we already knew: that money in a husband's pay
packet was not equivalent to a direct payment to his wife.
With all their problems, then, the state and the employer can be fought col-
lectively and unlike modern marriage they are not intrinsically patriarchal.
And whenever feminists have formulated the demand for the socialization
of housework and of personal care, it has been state provision rather than
private commercial provision that they have had in mind.
Mary Mcintosh 123
Feminists in [England] have never been for very long attracted to purely
nti-statist positions. Such utopian individualism (or even small-scale col-
~ectivism) is a possible dream for men who can envisage a world of self-
supporting able-bodied people. But women are usually concerned with
how the other three-quarters live. They have argued for new forms of
interdependence based in the community and not in the family, and these
necessarily involve the state at one level or another.
There have been some interesting debates in the women's movement
about the development and provision of feminist services. The question
has been: should we provide these ourselves or should we demand state
provision and then fight about the form that provision should take?
Nurseries, playgroups, health care, advice on contraception and abortion,
refuges for battered women, rape crisis centres, legal and welfare rights
advice- all clearly fall within the ambit of things that we expect to be pro-
vided by state agencies. Yet these are either not available or, when they
are, are inadequate and unfeminist in their approach. Setting up services
like this is a way both of meeting women's needs and also of developing
public awareness of the effects of women's oppression, and providing a
base for feminist analysis and agitation around the issue (Flaskas and
Hounslow, 1980). In Australia and in the United States there has been a
great proliferation of feminist health and welfare services and the results
have sometimes been disappointing in that the energies of the women
involved have been used up in providing a good service so that the more
forward-looking political tasks have been neglected. In England, with the
notable exception of the network of Women's Aid refuges for battered
women, the tendency has been to set up very few feminist agencies but to
concentrate on campaigning for state provision. The more developed
social and health services in England have made this a more promising
direction to work in. It also seems to me to be the right approach, since
it can lead to more long-term and more universal provision than any vol-
untary efforts are likely to do. The character of such campaigns is also dif-
ferent and in some ways more outgoing politically. Instead of the
independent and sometimes rather inward-looking group work involved
in establishing and running a feminist service, there is the need to make
alliances and work in the existing political arena. The struggle to develop
the present services in a feminist direction involves work in the unions
and professional bodies of the service workers as well as organizing
among clients and users.
Making claims on the state thus involves fruitful political work and agi-
tation at many levels and is far from being confined to the politics of
Westminster. So in this respect, as in some others, women have been at
the forefront of the rethinking of the rather facile radical libertarianism
of the 1960s and early 1970s. (The other thing that feminists questioned
was the general assumption that decriminalization, decarceration and
124 Feminism and Social Policy
(1) The first is that although the dominant factor affecting state policies
will always be the long-term interests of the ruling class and although the
central interests of the working class and the capitalist class are antagonis-
tic, it is not necessarily the case that their interests will be opposed on every
single issue of social policy. The most fundamental reason for this is that,
despite the fact that the wage relation is an antagonistic one, workers' and
capitalists' interests coincide in requiring the satisfaction of the workers'
basic needs, whether through the wage or by other means. The capitalist
requires the reproduction of labour power; the worker requires food and
clothing. Of course, they will differ widely over what sort of needs should
be met and under what conditions: over what constitutes 'adequate' repro-
duction of labour power; and this is where struggles over social policy
come in. The history of the growth of the welfare state and the growth of
collective consumption (Grevet, 1976; Castells, 1978) in general in capital-
ist societies is thus neither a history of cherries snatched from the greedy
hands of capitalists by a militant working class, nor is it a history of a crafty
capitalist plot to control and enfeeble the workers in the interests of guar-
anteeing the reproduction of labour power and of the relations of produc-
tion. It is both. The gains and losses have to be figured partly in terms of
some felicific calculus and partly in political terms: are we better placed for
the next battle? Has morale improved?
Mary Mcintosh 125
(Z) The second key point is that we need to keep in mind the limits that
reset on social policy by the capital-labour contradiction. In particular,
~e need to recognize that the wage system is fundamental to capitalist pro-
duction and that the primary means of the reproduction of labour power
will be the wage. Social security provisions and collective consumption
will be designed in such a way as to minimize their interference with the
labour market and with the existence of a proletariat obliged to sell its
labour power in order to survive.
This means that demands for a 'guaranteed minimum income' have no
connection with social policy in capitalist society. The 'guaranteed
minimum income' is a demand adopted by the Claimants' Union as a
radical solution to their degrading experiences at the hands of the social
security officials. They see the problems of the means test, the search for
a 'liable relative', and the obligation to sign on for employment as ways
in which the working class are harassed and controlled. So they demand
their abolition, the right of everyone to a guaranteed income regardless
of whether or not they are willing to look for waged work. As a
Claimants' Union representative argued in one of the workshops at the
'Crisis in the Welfare State' conference [1980]: 'People who don't have
jobs need an income as much as those who do; it is hard work just staying
alive in capitalist society.' The demand is thus very different from a
demand for a minimum wage coupled with improved social security ben-
efits at the same level. It is a demand that the need to sell one's labour
power in order to survive should be abolished. So it is nothing less than
a demand that socialism be introduced: but a demand ostensibly made of
the capitalist state and a demand that socialism should enter through the
back door, the relations of distribution; rather than the front door, the
relations of production. It is thus, as its proponents are well aware, an
unrealizable demand under capitalism, since it negates the wage relation
which lies at the heart of capitalism. Any of their supporters who join the
ranks because they think they might actually gain the demand have been
sadly deceived. But the existence of such demands can have the depress-
ing effect of making all real current struggles over policy look paltry and
reformist by comparison.
Feminists have been very aware of this problem in relation to the
demand for 'wages for housework', rejected by the women's liberation
movement in England in 1972, but still having a small, vocal following.
Effectively this is a demand that women should have a guaranteed
minimum income, since the idea that there should be any check on whether
they actually do any housework is rejected. It is thus a demand that all
women should be lifted out of the proletariat and put on a pension. It, too,
can be dispiriting if it has the effect of making current struggles over
matters like invalid care allowances or the infamous 'Housewife's
Non-Contributory Disability Allowance' seem trivial and reformist.
126 Feminism and Social Policy
The argument against the older equalitarianism took the form of a rejec-
tion of male definitions of women's work as inferior and a plea for a new
dignity and new measures of protection. In some respects it was more pro-
gressive than equalitarianism: it sought to change the world, not merely to
Mary Mcintosh 127
give women access to the better places in it. But in the end it was less radical
because the changes it sought were too shallow. They were designed to ease
the suffering where the shoe pinches rather than build a new shoe on a
better last. For modern feminists it is easy to see why Rathbone's moun-
tainous ideal of Family Endowment brought forth the rather ridiculous
mouse of Child Benefit and why women's dependence is still a key issue
wday. As Hilary Land put it: 'Eleanor Rathbone laid much emphasis on
the unequal economic relationship between husband and wife but had far
less to say about the division of responsibilities for child care and house-
work' (Land, 1980). A deeper analysis would have led her to see the two as
inseparable within any wage-based economy. The problem as it was posed
then is that of the impossibility either of the equalitarian ideal- which asks
for equal treatment for unequal people- or of the 'new feminist' ideal -
which asks for women to be treated as different but equal.
It is interesting to ask whether the difference between these two strat-
egies has been transcended by the more recent feminism of the women's
liberation movement. Certainly it is not the basis for the main divisions
within the movement at present. And the modern movement is character-
ized much more by methods that have nothing to do with legal changes or
state policies and so may appear to sidestep the problems of equalitarian-
ism: cultural politics, the politics of lifestyle and changing household rela-
tionships, self-help and self-defence, support for victims of rape and
violence, forming international links and (perhaps most distinctively)
developing theoretical analyses of women's oppression.
Yet in many fields of work, the choice between those two strategies
remains and continues to pose thorny problems. These tend to be the
modern versions of the very issues of law and social policy that exercised
our feminist grandmothers. The issue of protective legislation, restricting
the hours and conditions of women's work in factories, is a conspicuous
example. Feminists have been divided over it ever since it was first intro-
duced during the nineteenth century. At that time equalitarianism was the
dominant approach and such feminists as took an interest in the question
opposed the legislation on the grounds that it infringed women's liberty and
put them at a disadvantage in the labour market - a view which I think is
justified by the historical evidence (Barrett and Mcintosh, 1980; but for the
opposite view, see Hutchins and Harrison, 1911; Humphries, 1977, 1981).
Later the 'new feminists' attacked this stance and argued that women's
functions of home-making and child-rearing could not be carried out prop-
erly if they were forced to work long hours and at night outside the home.
This is not, of course, a defence that appeals to women's liberationists today.
However, the situation today is not at all comparable to that in the past.
For one thing, we have formulated the goal of transforming the processes
of home-making and child-rearing, so that if these are to be done privately
we want men's factory hours to be limited as well. For another, while the
128 Feminism and Social Policy
CBI wants protective legislation ended, the TUC wants it continued and
extended to cover men and to cover workers everywhere, not just in
factory production. So when the Equal Opportunities Comll)ission (1979)
[ ... ] recommended abolishing the legislation it was siding with the bosses
as well as taking an unhistorical perspective and thinking in terms of imme-
diate equality of treatment (for the unequal) rather than of working to
eliminate the underlying inequality.
However, it should be noted that the position that women's liber-
ationists usually adopt on this issue depends upon trusting the TUC., If
they are not genuine in their commitment to extend protection to men- or
if they have no hope of carrying it through- our position becomes one that
simply accepts the present role of women and seeks to protect us from
some of its worst penalties. I shall come back later to the questions of polit-
ical practice that this raises. I want first to say something about strategy in
relation to one particular feminist campaign, that for 'disaggregation'. I
focus on this campaign because it raises important problems and also
because I happen to have been involved in it, rather than because I believe
it to be any more or less important than other campaigns. It is obviously
just one part of a wider struggle.
Socialist feminists in the women's liberation movement have transcended
the old divide in the sense that they have questioned not only masculinity
and femininity, not only man's place and woman's place, but also the very
existence of social division and difference based on sex. We have firmly
located the origin and support for this division in the family. This does not
mean that we locate it in individual kin-based households, but in the insti-
tution of the family, with its ideology, its imperatives and its constraints,
which spread far beyond households themselves and both cause and enable
the organization of everything else to be marked by gender division.
Women's liberation depends upon the radical transformation of that family.
However, although there is much disagreement about the relation of that
family system to capitalism, most socialist feminists agree on two things:
that the specific character of women's oppression at present is related to the
articulation between the family system and the wage system; and that we
should start working now towards the transformation of the family system
and that it will not automatically arrive along with socialism. Indeed, I
would add that the family system is changing and is under great strain at
present (and not only because of the resurgence of feminism), so that it is
incumbent on us to play a part in determining what form that change takes.
On the whole we choose to campaign for those things that we know will
both help the immediate problems of many women and also help to open up
possibilities for further and more far-reaching change. The demand for 'dis-
aggregation' in social security, income tax, student grants and so on is a
good example. The aggregation of the married couple into a tax unit
and into a means-testable unit - however it may be dressed up in unisex
Mary M clntosh 129
welfare', 'women and crime', or whatever. This is done with a modest, 'I
am only a man; I can't speak for women'. But I sometimes wonder what
they think the other eighteen lectures in their course ar:- apout: men?
neuters? a gender-free society? The welfare system as it stands (or totters)
is utterly dependent upon a specific construction of gender. The
Department of Health and Social Security is well aware of that and it is
time that critics of social policy were as well.
Note
This extract, from Critical Social Policy, 1, 1981, pp. 32-42, is based on the author's
paper given at the Critical Social Policy Conference, 'Crisis in the Welfare State',
November 1980.
References
Abbott, Elizabeth and Bompas, Katherine (1943) The Woman Citizen and Social
Security: A Criticism of the Proposals Made in the Beveridge Reports as they
Affect Women, London, Mrs Bompas.
Allen, Sandra et al. (eds) (1974) Conditions of Illusion, Leeds, Feminist Books.
Barrett, Michele and Mcintosh, Mary (1980) 'The Family Wage', Capital and
Class, no. 11.
Bennett, Fran et al. (1980) 'The Limitations of the Demand for Independence',
Politics and Power, no. 1.
Bottomley, Anne et al. (1981) The Cohabitation Handbook: A Woman's Guide to
the Law, London, Pluto Press.
Castells, Manuel (1978) 'Collective Consumption and Urban Contradictions in
Advanced Capitalism', reprinted in Castells, City, Class and Power, London,
Macmillan.
Charlton, Valerie (1974) 'The Patter of Tiny Contradictions', Red Rag, no. 5,
reprinted in Allen et al.
Equal Opportunities Commission (1979) Health and Safety Legislation: Should
we Distinguish between Men and Women? London, HMSO.
Flaskas, Carmel and Hounslow, Betty (1980) 'Government Intervention and
Right-Wing Attacks on Feminist Services', Scarlet Woman (Australia) no. 11.
Gieve, Katherine et al. (1974) 'The Independence Demand', in Allen et al.
Grevet, Patrice (1976) Besoins populaires et financement public, Paris, Editions
Sociales.
Hamill, Lynn (1978) 'Wives as Sole and Joint Breadwinners', paper presented to
the Social Science Research Council, Social Security Research Workshop.
Humphries, Jane (1977) 'Class Struggle and the Persistence of the Working-Class
Family', Cambridge journal of Economics, vol. 1, no. 3, pp. 241-58.
Humphries, Jane (1981) 'Protective Legislation, the Capitalist State and Working-
Class Men: 1842 Mines Regulation Act', Feminist Review, no. 7.
Hutchins, B. L. and Harrison, A. (1911) A History of Factory Legislation, London,
P. S. King and Son, 2nd edn.
Land, Hilary (1976) 'Women: Supporters or Supported?', in Diana Barker and
Sheila Allen, Sexual Divisions and Society: Process and Change, London,
Tavistock.
Mary Mcintosh 133
L nd Hilary (1977) 'Social Security and the Division of Unpaid Work in the
aH~me and Paid Employment in the Labour Market', in Department of Health
and Social Security, Social Security Research Seminar, London, HMSO,
43-61.
L:n~·, Hilary (1980) 'The Family Wage', Feminist Review, no. 6.
Law Commission (1980) Family Law: The Financial Consequences of Divorce:
The Basic Policy: A Discussion Paper, Law Com. no. 103, London, HMSO,
Cmnd. 8041.
Lewis, Jane (1973) 'Eleanor Rathbone and the New Feminism during the 1920s',
mimeograph.
Lister, Ruth and Wilson, Leo (1976) The Unequal Breadwinner, London,
National Council for Civil Liberties.
Mitchell, Juliet (1974) Psychoanalysis and Feminism, London, Allen Lane.
Pierce, Sylvie (1979) 'Ideologies of Female Independence in the Welfare State:
Women's Response to the Beveridge Report', paper given at British Sociological
Association Annual Conference.
Rathbone, Eleanor F. (1929) Milestones: Presidential Addresses at the Annual
Council Meetings of NUSEC, London.
Streather,Jane and Weir, Stuart (1974) Social Insecurity: Single Mothers on Social
Security, Child Poverty Action Group, Poverty Pamphlet no. 16.
Wilson, Elizabeth (1974) 'Women and the Welfare State', Red Rag, no. 2.
The Patriarchal Welfare State
Carole Pa ternan
[ ... ]
Theoretically and historically, the central criterion for citizenship has been
'independence', and the elements encompassed under the heading of inde-
pendence have been based on masculine attributes and abilities. Men, but
not women, have been seen as possessing the capacities required of 'indi-
viduals', 'workers' and 'citizens'. As a corollary, the meaning of 'depend-
ence' is associated with all that is womanly - and women's citizenship in
the welfare state is full of paradoxes and contradictions. [ ... ] Three elem-
ents of 'independence' are particularly important for present purpqses, all
related to the masculine capacity for self-protection: the capacity to bear
arms, the capacity to own property and the capacity for self-government.
First, women are held to lack the capacity for self-protection; they have
been 'unilaterally disarmed' .1 The protection of women is undertaken by
men, but physical safety is a fundamental aspect of women's welfare that has
been sadly neglected in the welfare state. From the nineteenth century, fem-
inists (including J. S. Mill) have drawn attention to the impunity with which
husbands could use physical force against their wives, 2 but women/wives
still find it hard to obtain proper social and legal protection against violence
from their male 'protectors'. Defence of the state (or the ability to protect
your protection, as Hobbes put it), the ultimate test of citizenship, is also a
masculine prerogative. The anti-suffragists in both America and Britain
made a great deal of the alleged inability and unwillingness of women to use
armed force, and the issue of women and combat duties in the military forces
of the warfare state was also prominent in the [ ... ] campaign [of the 1980s]
against the Equal Rights Amendment in the United States. Although women
are now admitted into the armed forces and so into training useful for later
civilian employment, they are prohibited from combat duties in Britain,
Carole Pateman 135
Australia and the United States. Moreover, past exclusion of women from
the warfare state has meant that welfare provision for veterans has also ben-
efited men. In Australia and the United States, because of their special 'con-
tribution' as citizens, veterans have had their own, separately administered
welfare state, which has ranged from preference in university education (the
GI bills in the United States) to their own medical benefits and hospital ser-
vices, and (in Australia) preferential employment in the public service.
In the 'democratic' welfare state, however, employment rather than mili-
tary service is the key to citizenship. The masculine 'protective' capacity
now enters into citizenship primarily through the second and third dimen-
sions of independence. Men, but not women, have also been seen as prop-
erty owners. Only some men own material property, but as 'individuals',
all men own (and can protect) the property they possess in their persons.
Their status as 'workers' depends on their capacity to contract out the
property they own in their labour power. Women are still not fully recog-
nized socially as such property owners. To be sure, our position has
improved dramatically from the mid-nineteenth century when women as
wives had a very 'peculiar' position as the legal property of their husbands,
and feminists compared wives to slaves. But today, a wife's person is still
the property of her husband in one vital respect. Despite recent legal
reform, in Britain and in some of the states of the United States and
Australia, rape is still deemed legally impossible within marriage, and thus
a wife's consent has no meaning. Yet women are now formally citizens in
states held to be based on the necessary consent of self-governing individu-
als. The profound contradiction about women's consent is rarely if ever
noticed and so is not seen as related to a sexually divided citizenship or as
detracting from the claim of the welfare state to be democratic.
The third dimension of 'independence' is self-government. Men have
been constituted as the beings who can govern (or protect) themselves, and
if a man can govern himself, then he also has the requisite capacity to govern
others. Only a few men govern others in public life- but all men govern in
private as husbands and heads of households. As the governor of a family,
a man is also a 'breadwinner'. He has the capacity to sell his labour power
as a worker, or to buy labour power with his capital, and provide for his
wife and family. His wife is thus 'protected'. The category of 'breadwinner'
presupposes that wives are constituted as economic dependants or 'house-
wives', which places them in a subordinate position. The dichotomy bread-
winner/housewife, and the masculine meaning of independence, were
established in Britain by the middle of the nineteenth century; in the earlier
period of capitalist development, women (and children) were wage-labour-
ers. A 'worker' became a man who has an economically dependent wife to
take care of his daily needs and look after his home and children. Moreover,
'class', too, is constructed as a patriarchal category. 'The working class' is
the class of working men, who are also full citizens in the welfare state.
136 The Patriarchal Welfare State
state and the social wage, the wage is usually treated as a return for the sale
of individuals' labour power. However, once the opposition breadwinner/
housewife was consolidated, a 'wage' had to provide subsistel)ce for several
people. The struggle between capital and labour and the controversy about
the welfare state have been about the family wage. A 'living wage' has been
defined as what is required for a worker as breadwinner to suppon a wife
and family, rather than what is needed to support himself; the wage is not
what is sufficient to reproduce the worker's own labour power, but what
is sufficient, in combination with the unpaid work of the housewife,, to
reproduce the labour power of the present and future labour force.
[ ... ]
[went] hand-in-hand with praise for loving care within families, that is,
with an attempt to obtain ever more unpaid welfare from (house) wives.
The Invalid Care Allowance in Britain has been a particularly blatant
example of the way in which the welfare state ensures that wives provide
private welfare. The allowance was introduced in 1975 - when the Sex
Discrimination Act was also passed - and it was paid to men or to single
women who relinquished paid employment to look after a sick, disabled
or elderly person (not necessarily a relative). Married women (or those
cohabiting) were ineligible for the allowance.
The evidence indicates that it is likely to be married women who provide
such care. In 1976 in Britain it was estimated that two million women were
caring for adult relatives, and one survey in the north of England found
that there were more people caring for adult relatives than mothers looking
after children under sixteen. 8 A corollary of the assumption that women,
but not men, care for others is that women must also care for themselves.
Investigations show that women living by themselves in Britain have to be
more infirm than men to obtain the services of home helps, and a study of
an old people's home found that frail, elderly women admitted with their
husbands faced hostility from the staff because they had failed in their job. 9
Again, women's citizenship is full of contradictions and paradoxes.
Women must provide welfare, and care for themselves, and so must be
assumed to have the capacities necessary for these tasks. Yet the develop-
ment of the welfare state has also presupposed that women necessarily are
in need of protection by and are dependent on men.
The welfare state has reinforced women's identity as men's dependants
both directly and indirectly, and so confirmed rather than ameliorated our
social exile. For example, in Britain and Australia the cohabitation rule
explicitly expresses the presumption that women necessarily must be eco-
nomically dependent on men if they live with them as sexual partners. If
cohabitation is ruled to take place, the woman loses her entitlement to
welfare benefits. The consequence of the cohabitation rule is not only sexu-
ally divided control of citizens, but an exacerbation of the poverty and other
problems that the welfare state is designed to alleviate. In Britain today
when a man lives in, a woman's independence- her own name on the weekly
giro [welfare cheque] is automatically surrendered. The men become the
claimants and the women their dependents. They lose control over both the
revenue and the expenditure, often with catastrophic results: rent not paid,
fuel bills missed, arrears mounting. 10
taxation system has always treated a wife's income as her husband's for tax-
ation purposes. It is only relatively recently that it ceased to be the husband's
prerogative to correspond with the Inland Revenue about h_is wife's earn-
ings, or that he ceased to receive rebates due on her tax payments. Married
men can still claim a tax allowance, based on the assumption that they
support a dependent wife. Women's dependence is also enforced through the
extremely limited public provision of childcare facilities in Australia, Britain
and the United States, which creates a severe obstacle to women's full par-
ticipation in the employment society. In all three countries, unlike
Scandinavia, childcare outside the home is a very controversial issue.
Welfare-state legislation has also been framed on the assumption that
women make their 'contribution' by providing private welfare, and, from
the beginning, women were denied full citizenship in the welfare state. In
America 'originally the purpose of ADC (now AFDC) was to keep
mothers out of the paid labor force. . . . In contrast, the Social Security
retirement program was consciously structured to respond to the needs of
white male workers.>~ I In Britain the first national insurance, or contribu-
tory, scheme was set up in 1911, and one of its chief architects wrote later
that women should have been completely excluded because 'they want
insurance for others, not themselves'. Two years before the scheme was
introduced, William Beveridge, the father of the contemporary British
welfare state, stated in a book on unemployment that the 'ideal [social] unit
is the household of man, wife and children maintained by the earnings of
the first alone. . .. Reasonable security of employment for the bread-
winner is the basis of all private duties and all sound social action.' 12 Nor
had Beveridge changed his mind on this matter by the Second World War;
his report, Social Insurance and Allied Services, appeared in 1942 and laid
a major part of the foundation for the great reforms of the 1940s. In a
passage now (in)famous among feminists, Beveridge wrote that 'the great
majority of married women must be regarded as occupied on work which
is vital though unpaid, without which their husbands could not do their
paid work and without which the nation could not continue.' 13 In the
National Insurance Act of 1946 wives were separated from their husbands
for insurance purposes. (The significance of this procedure, along with
Beveridge's statement, clearly was lost on T. H. Marshall when he was
writing his essay on citizenship and the welfare state.) Under the act,
married women paid lesser contributions for reduced benefits, but they
could also opt out of the scheme, and so from sickness, unemployment and
maternity benefits, and they also lost entitlement to an old age pension in
their own right, being eligible only as their husband's dependant. By the
time the legislation was amended in 1975, about three-quarters of married
women workers had opted out. 14
A different standard for men and women has also been applied in the
operation of the insurance scheme. In 1911 some married women were
Carole Pateman 141
insured in their own right. The scheme provided benefits in case of 'incap-
acity to work', but, given that wives had already been identified as 'incap-
acitated' for the 'work' in question, for paid employment, problems over
the criteria for entitlement to sickness benefits were almost inevitable. In
1913 an inquiry was held to discover why married women were claiming
benefits at a much greater rate than expected. One obvious reason was that
the health of many working-class women was extremely poor. The extent
of their ill health was revealed in 1915 when letters written by working
women in 1913-14 to the Women's Cooperative Guild were published.
The national insurance scheme meant that for the first time women could
afford to take time off work when ill- but from which 'work'? Could they
take time off from housework? What were the implications for the embry-
onic welfare state if they ceased to provide free welfare? From 1913 a dual
standard of eligibility for benefits was established. 15 For men the criterion
was fitness for work. But the committee of inquiry decided that, if a
woman could do her housework, she was not ill. So the criterion for eligi-
bility for women was also fitness for work- but unpaid work in the private
home, not paid work in the public market that was the basis for the con-
tributory scheme under which the women were insured! This criterion for
women was still being laid down in instructions issued by the Department
of Health and Social Security in the 1970s. 16 The dual standard was further
reinforced in 1975 when a non-contributory invalidity pension was intro-
duced for those incapable of work but not qualified for the contributory
scheme. Men and single women were entitled to the pension if they could
not engage in paid employment; the criterion for married women was
ability to perform 'normal household duties'Y
Wollstonecraft's Dilemma
So far, I have looked at the patriarchal structure of the welfare state, but
this is only part of the picture; the development of the welfare state has also
brought challenges to patriarchal power and helped provide a basis for
women's autonomous citizenship. Women have seen the welfare state as
one of their major means of support. Well before women won formal citi-
zenship, they campaigned for the state to make provision for welfare, espe-
cially for the welfare of women and their children; and women's
organizations and women activists have continued their political activities
around welfare issues, not least in opposition to their status as 'depend-
ants'. In 1953 the British feminist Vera Brittain wrote of the welfare state
established through the legislation of the 1940s that 'in it women have
become ends in themselves and not merely means to the ends of men', and
their 'unique value as women was recognised'. 18 In hindsight, Brittain was
clearly overoptimistic in her assessment, but perhaps the opportunity now
142 The Patriarchal Welfare State
life. From at least the 1790s they have also struggled with the task of trying
to become citizens within an ideal and practice that have gained universal
meaning through their exclusion. Women's response has been complex.
On the one hand, they have demanded that the ideal of citizenship be
extended to them, and the liberal-feminist agenda for a 'gender-neutral'
social world is the logical conclusion of one form of this demand. On the
other hand, women have also insisted, often simultaneously, as did Mary
Wollstonecraft, that as women they have specific capacities, talents, needs
and concerns, so that the expression of their citizenship will be differenti-
ated from that of men. Their unpaid work providing welfare could be
seen, as Wollstonecraft saw women's tasks as mothers, as women's work as
citizens, just as their husbands' paid work is central to men's citizenship.
The patriarchal understanding of citizenship means that the two
demands are incompatible because it allows two alternatives only: either
women become (like) men, and so full citizens; or they continue at
women's work, which is of no value for citizenship. Moreover, within a
patriarchal welfare state neither demand can be met. To demand that citi-
zenship, as it now exists, should be fully extended to women accepts the
patriarchal meaning of 'citizen', which is constructed from men's attrib-
utes, capacities and activities. Women cannot be full citizens in the
present meaning of the term; at best, citizenship can be extended to
women only as lesser men. At the same time, within the patriarchal
welfare state, to demand proper social recognition and support for
women's responsibilities is to condemn women to less than full citizen-
ship and to continued incorporation into public life as 'women', that is,
as members of another sphere who cannot, therefore, earn the respect of
fellow (male) citizens.
The example of child endowments on family allowances in Australia and
Britain is instructive as a practical illustration of Wollstonecraft's dilemma.
It reveals the great difficulties in trying to implement a policy that both aids
women in their work and challenges patriarchal power while enhancing
women's citizenship. In both countries there was opposition from the right
and from laissez-faire economists on the ground that family allowances
would undermine the father's obligation to support his children and
undermine his 'incentive' to sell his labour power in the market. The femi-
nist advocates of family allowances in the 1920s, most notably Eleanor
Rathbone in Britain, saw the alleviation of poverty in families where the
breadwinner's wage was inadequate to meet the family's basic needs as only
one argument for this form of state provision. They were also greatly con-
cerned with the questions of the wife's economic dependence and equal
pay for men and women workers. If the upkeep of children (or a substan-
tial contribution toward it) was met by the state outside of wage bargain-
ing in the market, then there was no reason why men and women doing
the same work should not receive the same pay. Rathbone wrote in 1924
144 The Patriarchal Welfare State
that 'nothing can justify the subordination of one group of producers- the
mothers - to the rest and their deprivation of a share of their own in the
wealth of a community'. 19 She argued that family allowances WO\lld, 'once
and for all, cut away the maintenance of children and the reproduction of
the race from the question of wages'. 20
But not all the advocates of child endowment were feminists- so that the
policy could very easily be divorced from the public issue of wages
and dependence and be seen only as a return for and recognition of
women's private contributions. Supporters included the eugenicists and
pronatalists, and family allowances appealed to capital and the state as a
means of keeping wages down. Family allowances had many opponents in
the British union movement, fearful that the consequence, were the
measure introduced, would be to undermine the power of unions in wage
bargaining. The opponents included women trade unionists who were sus-
picious of a policy that could be used to try to persuade women to leave
paid employment. Some unionists also argued that social services, such as
housing, education and health, should be developed first, and the TUC
adopted this view in 1930. But were the men concerned, too, with
their private, patriarchal privileges? Rathbone claimed that 'the leaders
of working men are themselves subsconsciously biased by prejudice of
sex .... Are they not influenced by a secret reluctance to see their wives and
children recognised as separate personalities ?' 21
By 1941 the supporters of family allowances in the union movement had
won the day, and family allowances were introduced in 1946 as part of the
government's wartime plans for postwar reconstruction. The legislation
proposed that the allowance would be paid to the father as 'normal, house-
hold head', but after lobbying by women's organizations, this was over-
turned in a free vote, and the allowance was paid directly to mothers. In
Australia the union movement accepted child endowment in the 1920s
(child endowment was introduced in New South Wales in 1927, and at the
federal level in 1941 ). But union support there was based on wider redis-
tributive policies, and the endowment was seen as a supplement to, not a
way of breaking down, the family wage. 22 In the 1970s, in both countries,
women's organizations again had to defend family allowances and the
principle of redistribution from 'the wallet to the purse'.
The hope of Eleanor Rathbone and other feminists that family
allowances would form part of a democratic restructuring of the wage
system was not realized. Nevertheless, family allowances are paid to
women as a benefit in their own right; in that sense they are an important
(albeit financially very small) mark of recognition of married women as
independent members of the welfare state. Yet the allowance is paid to
women as mothers, and the key question is thus whether the payment to a
mother- a private person- negates her standing as an independent citizen
of the welfare state. More generally, the question is whether there can be a
Carole Pateman 145
welfare policy that gives substantial assistance to women in their daily lives
and helps create the conditions for a genuine democracy in which women
are autonomous citizens, in which we can act as women and not as 'woman'
(protected/dependent/subordinate) constructed as the opposite to all that
is meant by 'man'. That is to say, a resolution of Wollstonecraft's dilemma
is necessary and, perhaps, possible.
The structure of the welfare state presupposes that women are men's
dependants, but the benefits help to make it possible for women to be eco-
nomically independent of men. In the countries with which I am con-
cerned, women reliant on state benefits live poorly, but it is no longer so
essential as it once was to marry or to cohabit with a man. A considerable
moral panic has developed in recent years around 'welfare mothers', a
panic that obscures significant features of their position, not least the
extent to which the social basis for the ideal of breadwinner/ dependant has
crumbled. Large numbers of young working-class women have little or no
hope of finding employment (or of finding a young man who is employed).
But there is a source of social identity available to them that is out of the
reach of their male counterparts. The socially secure and acknowledged
identity for women is still that of a mother, and for many young women,
motherhood, supported by state benefits, provides 'an alternative to
aimless adolescence on the dole' and 'gives the appearance of self-
determination'. The price of independence and 'a rebellious motherhood
that is not an uncritical retreat into femininity' 23 is high, however; the
welfare state provides a minimal income and perhaps housing (often sub-
standard), but childcare services and other support are lacking, so that the
young women are often isolated, with no way out of their social exile.
Moreover, even if welfare state policies in Britain, Australia and the United
States were reformed so that generous benefits, adequate housing, health
care, child care and other services were available to mothers, reliance on the
state could reinforce women's lesser citizenship in a new way.
Some feminists have enthusiastically endorsed the welfare state as 'the
main recourse of women' and as the generator of 'political resources which,
it seems fair to say, are mainly women's resources'. 24 They can point, in
Australia for example, to 'the creation over the decade [1975-85] of a range
of women's policy machinery and government subsidized women's services
(delivered by women for women) which is unrivalled elsewhere.' 25
However, the enthusiasm is met with the rejoinder from other feminists that
for women to look to the welfare state is merely to exchange dependence on
individual men for dependence on the state. The power and capriciousness
of husbands is being replaced by the arbitrariness, bureaucracy and power
of the state, the very state that has upheld patriarchal power. The objection
is cogent: to make women directly dependent on the state will not in itself
do anything to challenge patriarchal power relations. The direct dependence
of male workers on the welfare state and their indirect dependence when
146 The Patriarchal Welfare State
their standard of living is derived from the vast system of state regulation of
and subsidy to capitalism - and in Australia a national arbitration court _
have done little to undermine class power. However, the o~je<:;tion also
misses an important point. There is one crucial difference between the con-
struction of women as men's dependants and dependence on the welfare
state. In the former case, each woman lives with the man on whose btnevo-
lence she depends; each woman is (in J. S. Mill's extraordinarily apt phrase)
in a 'chronic state of bribery and intimidation combined'. 26 In the welfare
state, each woman receives what is hers by right, and she can, potentially,
combine with other citizens to enforce her rightful claim. The state has enor-
mous powers of intimidation, but political action takes place collectively in
the public terrain and not behind the closed door of the home, where each
woman has to rely on her own strength and resources.
Another new factor is that women are now involved in the welfare state
on a large scale as employees, so that new possibilities for political action
by women also exist. Women have been criticizing the welfare state in
recent years not just as academics, as activists, or as beneficiaries and users
of welfare services, but as the people on whom the daily operation of the
welfare state to a large extent depends. The criticisms range from its patri-
archal structure (and, on occasions, especially in health care, misogynist
practices), to its bureaucratic and undemocratic policy-making processes
and administration, to social work practices and education policy. Small
beginnings have been made on changing the welfare state from within; for
example, women have succeeded in establishing Well Women Clinics
within the NHS in Britain and special units to deal with rape victims in
public hospitals in Australia. Furthermore, the potential is now there for
united action by women employees, women claimants and women citizens
already politically active in the welfare state - not just to protect services
against government cuts and efforts at 'privatization' (which has absorbed
much energy recently), but to transform the welfare state. Still, it is hard to
see how women alone could succeed in the attempt. One necessary condi-
tion for the creation of a genuine democracy in which the welfare of all citi-
zens is served is an alliance between a labour movement that acknowledges
the problem of patriarchal power and an autonomous women's movement
that recognizes the problem of class power. Whether such an alliance can
be forged is an open question.
Despite the debates and the rethinking brought about by mass
unemployment and attack on the union movement and welfare state by the
Reagan and Thatcher governments, there are many barriers to be overcome.
In Britain and Australia, with stronger welfare states, the women's move-
ment has had a much closer relationship with working-class movements
than in the United States, where the individualism of the predominant
liberal feminism is an inhibiting factor, and where only about 17 per cent of
the workforce is now unionized. The major locus of criticism of authori-
Carole Pateman 147
Notes
Every theoretical paradigm must somehow define the welfare state. How
do we know when and if a welfare state responds functionally to the needs
of industrialism, or to capitalist reproduction and legitimacy? And how do
we identify a welfare state that corresponds to the demands that a mobil-
ized working class might have? We cannot test contending arguments
unless we have a commonly shared conception of the phenomenon to be
explained.
A remarkable attribute of the entire literature is its lack of much genuine
interest in the welfare state as such. Welfare state studies have been motiv-
ated by theoretical concerns with other phenomena, such as power, indus-
trialization or capitalist contradictions; the welfare state itself has generally
received scant conceptual attention. If welfare states differ, how do they
differ? And when, indeed, is a state a welfare state? This turns attention
straight back to the original question: what is the welfare state?
A common textbook definition is that it involves state responsibility for
securing some basic modicum of welfare for its citizens. Such a definition
skirts the issue of whether social policies are emancipatory or not; whether
they help system legitimation or not; whether they contradict or aid the
market process; and what, indeed, is meant by 'basic'? Would it not be
more appropriate to require of a welfare state that it satisfies more than our
basic or minimal welfare needs?
The first generation of comparative studies started with this type of con-
ceptualization. They assumed, without much reflection, that the level of
social expenditure adequately reflects a state's commitment to welfare. The
theoretical intent was not really to arrive at an understanding of the welfare
state, but rather to test the validity of contending theoretical models in
G0sta Esping-Andersen 161
Few can disagree with T. H. Marshall's (1950) proposition that social citi-
zenship constitutes the core idea of a welfare state. But the concept must
be fleshed out. Above all, it must involve the granting of social rights. If
Gc-'JSta Esping-Andersen 163
social rights are given the legal and practical status of property rights, if
they are inviolable, and if they are granted on the basis of citizenship rather
than performance, they will entail a de-commodification of the status of
individuals vis-a-vis the market. But the concept of social citizenship also
involves social stratification: one's status as a citizen will compete with, or
even replace, one's class position.
The welfare state cannot be understood just in terms of the rights it
grants. We must also take into account how state activities are interlocked
with the market's and the family's role in social provision. These arc the
three main principles that need to be fleshed out prior to any theoretical
specification of the welfare· state.
Conclusion
Note
From The Three Worlds of Welfare Capitalism, Cambridge, Polity Press, 1990,
pp. 18-34.
References
[ ... J
. . . or More?
Leibfried (1992) Anglo-Saxon (Residual): Right to income transfers; welfare state as compensator of last Poverty, social insurance
resort and tight enforcer of work in the market place and poverty policy
2 Bismarck (Institutional): Right to social security; welfare state as compensator of first
resort and employer of last resort
3 Scandinavian (Modern): Right to work for everyone; universalism; welfare state as
employer of first resort and compensator of last resort
4 Latin Rim (Rudimentary): Right to work and welfare proclaimed; welfare state as a semi-
institutionalized promise
Castles & Mitchell (1993) Liberal: Low social spending and no adoption of equalizing instruments in social policy Welfare expenditure
2 Conservative: High social expenditures, but little adoption of equalizing instruments Benefit equality
in social policy
3 Non-Right Hegemony: High social expenditure and use of highly equalizing instruments Taxes
in social policy
4 Radical: Achievement of equality in pre-tax, pre-transfer income (adoption of equalizing
instruments in social policy), but little social spending
Siaroff (1994) Protestant Liberal: Minimal family welfare, yet relatively egalitarian gender situation in the • Family welfare
labour market; family benefits are paid to the mother, but are rather inadequate orientation
2 Advanced Christian-Democratic: No strong incentives for women to work, but strong • Female. work desirability
incentives to stay at home
3 Protestant Social-Democratic: True work-welfare choice for women; family benefits are Extent of family benefits
high and always paid to the mother; importance of Protestantism being paid to women
4 Late Female Mobilization: Absence of Protestantism; family benefits are usually paid to the
father; universal female suffrage is relatively new
Ferrera ( 1996) Anglo-Saxon: Fairly high welfare state cover; social assistance with a means test; mixed Rules of access
system of financing; highly integrated organizational framework entirely managed by a (eligibility)
public administration
2 Bismarck: strong link between work position (and/or family state) and social entitlements; Benefit formulae
benefits proportional to income; financing through contributions; reasonably substantial
social assistance benefits; insurance schemes mainly governed by unions and employer
organizations
3 Scandinavian: social protection as a citizenship right; universal coverage; relatively generous • Financing regulations
fixed benefits for various social risks; financing mainly through fiscal revenues; strong
organizational integration
4 Southern: fragmented system of income guarantees linked to work position; generous • Organizational-
benefits without articulated net of minimum social protection; health care as a right of managerial arrangements
citizenship; particularism in payments of cash benefits and financing; financing through
contributions and fiscal revenues
Bonoli (1997) British: Low percentage of social expenditure financed through contributions Bismarck and Beveridge
(Beveridge); low social expenditure as a percentage of GDP model
2 Continental: High percentage of social expenditure financed through contributions
(Bismarck); high social expenditure as a percentage of GDP
3 Nordic: Low percentage of social expenditure financed through contributions (Beveridge); • Quantity of welfare state
high social expenditure as a percentage of GDP expenditure
4 Southern: High percentage of social expenditure financed through contributions (Bismarck);
low social expenditure as a percentage of GDP
(continued)
Table 1 (continued)
Types of welfare states and their characteristics Indicators/dimensions
Korpi & Palme (1998) Basic Security: Entitlements based on citizenship or contributions; application of the flat-
rate benefit principle
2 Corporatist: Entitlements based on occupational category and labour force participation; • Bases of entitlement
use of the earnings-related benefit principle
3 Encompassing: Entitlement based on citizenship and labour force participation; use of the • Benefit principle
flat-rate and earnings-related benefit principle
4 Targeted: Eligibility based on proved need; use of the minimum benefit principle • Governance of social
msurance programme
5 Voluntary State Subsidized: Eligibility based on membership or contributions; application
of the flat-rate or earnings-related principle
Wil Arts and john Gelissen 181
The Mediterranean
The Antipodes
Esping-Andersen discusses the Antipodean countries (i.e. Australia and
New Zealand) as representatives of the liberal welfare state regime. This is
Wil Arts and john Gelissen 183
for the definitions of interests and identities among citizens. They can
thereby be expected to influence coalition formation, which is significant
for income redistribution and poverty. As the basis of their,.classification
Korpi and Palme take the institutional structures of two social pro~
grammes- old age pensions and sickness cash benefits- which they con-
sider to lie at the heart of the welfare state. The institutional structures of
the two programmes are classified according to three aspects: the bases of
entitlements, the principles applied to determine benefit levels (to what
extent social insurance should replace lost income), and the governance of
a social insurance programme (whether or not representatives of employ-
ers and employees participate in the governing of a programme). Based on
these three aspects, they discriminate among five different ideal-types of
institutional structures: the targeted (empirically exemplified by the
Australian case), voluntary state subsidized, corporatist, basic security and
encompassing model. In table 1, these ideal-types and their most impor-
tant features are delineated. Again, the Esping-Andersen model stands.
However, a number of countries arc no longer considered to belong to a
subcategory of his three prototypes, but to a new prototype.
With respect to another issue, social care, Daly and Lewis (2000, p. 289)
argue that different styles of social policy have incorporated the key
element of social care differently. They identify certain tendencies con-
cerning care in specific welfare states. For example, the Scandinavian coun-
tries form a distinct group in that they have strongly institutionalized care
for both the elderly and children. In the Mediterranean welfare states, care
tends to be privatized to the family, whereas in Germany it is seen as most
appropriately a function of voluntary service providers. In France, a strong
distinction is made between care for children and for the elderly, with a
strong collective sector in the former and little voluntary involvement.
Another form is found in the Beveridge-oriented welfare states - Great
Britain and Ireland - where a strong distinction is also made between
caring for children and caring for (elderly) adults. In the former - as
opposed to the latter -little collectivization has taken place. Although they
do not really classify welfare states into actual clusters, Daly and Lewis
make a strong case for using social care as a critical dimension for analysing
variations.
As far as the gender gap in earnings is concerned, Gornick and ] acobs
(1998) found that Esping-Andersen's regime-types do capture important
distinctions among contemporary welfare states. Their results showed that
the size of the public sector, the extent of the public-sector earnings
premium and the impact of the public sector on gender differentials in
wages all varied more across regimes than within them. In this way, they
showed the fruitfulness of emphasizing the gender perspective in Esping-
Andersen's classification of welfare states. Moreover, Trifiletti (1999)
incorporated a gender perspective into Esping-Andersen's classification
by showing that a systematic relationship exists between the level of
decommodification and whether the state treats women as wives and
mothers or as workers. The latter is also an important dimension identified
by Lewis (1989).
Finally, Siaroff (1994) also argues that the existing literature does not pay
enough attention to how gender inequality is embedded in social policy
and welfare states. In order to arrive at a more gender-sensitive typology
of welfare state regimes, he examines a variety of indicators of gender
equality and inequality in work and welfare. He compares the
work-welfare choice of men and women (i.e. whether to partake in the
welfare state or to engage in paid labour) across countries. This allows him
to distinguish among a Protestant Social-Democratic, a Protestant Liberal,
an Advanced Christian-Democratic and a Late Female Mobilization
welfare state regime. Although the labels suggest otherwise, this typology
also shows a strong overlap with the Esping-Andersenian classification.
Only the latter type- the Late Female Mobilization welfare state regime-
is an addition, which resembles the previously distinguished
Mediterranean type of welfare states.
186 Three Worlds of Welfare Capitalism or More?
ented; the Basic Security type. However, most authors place the Netherlands
in the second category of Corporatist/Continental/Conservative welfare
states. This is also the choice of Visser and Hemerijck (1997), perhaps the
foremost specialists on the Dutch welfare state. Curiously enough, this is
done using Esping-Andersen's work as a constant, positive reference. If we
have another look at Esping-Andersen's work, this is not as surprising as one
would expect. It is true that the Netherlands is rated relatively high on social-
democratic characteristics, but not exceptionally low on liberal and conser-
vative characteristics. Recently, Esping-Andersen has called the Netherlands
the 'Dutch enigma' because of its Janus-faced welfare regime (1999, p. 88).
The Netherlands is indeed more a hybrid case than a prototype of a specific
ideal-type. If one attaches more importance to certain attributes than to
others- and adds other characteristics or substitutes previous ones- then it
is easy to arrive at different classifications.
Esping-Andersen claims that if we rate real welfare states along the dimen-
sions of degree of decommodification and the modes of stratification, three
qualitatively different clusters will appear. Alongside the more fundamen-
tal criticism of his three-way classification - that Esping-Andersen
employs faulty criteria to demarcate a regime - the empirical fit of his
three-way classification has also been questioned. Several authors have
tested the goodness-of-fit of the three-way regime typology. In the fol-
lowing, we discuss their findings, which are presented in table 3.
In an effort to evaluate the possible extent to which quantitative tech-
niques - OLS regression and cluster analysis - suggest the same conclu-
sions as alternative qualitative approaches - such as 'BOOLEAN'
comparative analysis- Kangas (1994) found some support for the existence
of Esping-Andersen's different welfare state regimes. Specifically, cluster
analyses of data on characteristics of health insurance schemes in OECD
countries in 1950 and 1985 corroborated his conjectures. However, the
results also showed the existence of two subgroups within the group of
liberal welfare states, which largely accorded with the classification of
Castles and Mitchell (1993).
Ragin (1994) also tested Esping-Andersen's claim of a three-world clas-
sification. By applying a combination of cluster analysis and 'BOOLEAN'
comparative analysis to characteristics of pension systems, he determined
which, if any, of Esping-Andersen's three worlds of welfare capitalism each
country fitted best. His cluster analysis suggested the existence of a social-
democratic cluster, a corporatist cluster and, finally, a rather large 'spare'
cluster, which accommodates cases that do not conform to Esping-
Andersen's three worlds. On the basis of his findings, Ragin concludes that
Table 2 Classification of countries according to seven typologies
Type
I II III IV v
Esping-Andersen Liberal Conservative Social-Democratic
(Decommodification) • Australia • Italy • Austria
Canada • Japan • Belgium
• United States • France • Netherlands
• New Zealand • Germany • Denmark
• Ireland • Finland • Norway
• United Kingdom • Switzerland • Sweden
Leibfried Anglo-Saxon Bismarck Scandinavian Latin Rim
• United States • Germany • Sweden • S.Illin
• Australia Austria • Norway • Portugal
• New Zealand • Finland • Greece
United Kingdom • Denmark • Italy
• France
Castles & Mitchell Liberal Conservative Non-Right Radical
Hegemony
• Ireland • West-Germany • Belgium • Australia
• Japan • Italy • Denmark • New Zealand
• Switzerland • Netherlands • Norway • United
• United States • Sweden Kingdom
Siaroff Protestant Liberal Advanced Christian- Protestant Social- Late Female
Democratic Democratic Mobilization
• Australia • Austria • Denmark • Greece
•
•
Canada
New Zealand
• Belgium
• France
• Finland
·~ .
•. Ireland
~
United Kingdom West-Germany Sweden Japan
United States Luxembourg Portugal
• Netherlands • Spain
• Switzerland
Ferrera (Europe only) Anglo-Saxon Bismarckian Scandinavian Southern
• United Kingdom
• Ireland
• Germanv
• France
• Belgium
• Sweden
• Denmark
•
.
• Italy
Spain
• Portugal
~
• Netherlands • Finland • Greece
• Luxembourg
• Austria
• Switzerland
Bonoli (Europe only) British Continental Nordic Southern
• United Kingdom • Netherlands • Sweden • Italy
• Ireland • France • Finland • Switzerland
• Belgium • Norway Spain
• Germany • Denmark Greece
• Luxembourg • Portugal
Korpi & Palme Basic Security Corporatist Encompassing Targeted
• Canada • Austria • Finland • Australia
• Denmark • Belgium • Norway
• Netherlands • France • Sweden
• New Zealand • Germany
Switzerland • Italy
Ireland • Japan
• United Kingdom
• United States
to make up his mind once and for all. Initially, Esping-Andersen (1997)
reacted, for example, positively to Castles and Mitchell's proposal to add a
fourth type - a radical welfare state regime - to his typology.. He recog-
nized that the residual character and the matter of a means test are just one
side of the coin of the Antipodean welfare states. However, he felt that a
powerfully institutionalized collection of welfare guarantees, which
operate through the market itself, could not be neglected. Later on,
however, he argued that the passage of time is pushing Australia, Great
Britain and New Zealand towards what appears to be prototypical liberal-
ism (Esping-Andersen, 1999). At first he also partially supported the
proposal to add a separate Mediterranean type to his typology (Esping-
Andersen, 1996, p. 66; 1997, p. 171). He acknowledged the- sometimes
generous- benefits which are guaranteed by certain arrangements, the near
absence of social services and, especially, the Catholic imprint and high
level of familialism. From the feminist critics he learned not so much the
overarching salience of gender as the analytical power that a re-examina-
tion of the family can yield. Recently he argued that the acid test of a dis-
tinct Mediterranean model depends on whether families are the relevant
focus of social aid, and whether families will fail just as markets and states
can fail (Esping-Andersen, 1999, p. 90).
All in all, Esping-Andersen is very reluctant to add more regime-clusters
to his original three. Against the benefits of greater refinement, more
nuance and more precision, he weighs the argument of analytical parsi-
mony, stressing that 'the peculiarities of these cases are variations within a
distinct overall logic, not a wholly different logic per se (Esping-Andersen,
1999, p. 90).
The answer to the question of whether Esping-Andersen's three-type or
a derivative or alternative four-, or five-type typology is preferable
depends, however, not only on parsimony and verisimilitude. It also
depends on whether these typologies lead to a theoretically more satisfy-
ing and empirically more fruitful comparative analysis of welfare state
regimes. As far as theory construction is concerned, Baldwin (1996, p. 29)
has argued that when asking about typologies, whether of welfare states or
anything else, we must ask not just what but also why. Esping-Andersen's
tentative answer to the question of why three different welfare state regime
types emerged has been sketched earlier on in this paper. Different
welfare regimes are shaped by different class coalitions within a context of
inherited institutions. This answer is embedded in a power-resources
mobilization paradigm. The tentative answer to the question of why
regime shifts are scarce is that a national state cannot easily escape its his-
torical inheritance. Institutional inertia is one factor why different welfare
state regime types persist, and path dependency is another (Kohl, 2000,
p. 125; Kuhnle and Alestalo, 2000, p. 9). Korpi and Palme- and some fem-
inist authors- work in the same power-resources mobilization tradition as
Wil Arts and john Gelissen 193
:Notes
References
Introduction
That the conventional wisdom on the subject is indeed correct, that the
welfare state represents a drain on competitiveness in an era of global-
ization and the competition state (Cerny, 1990, 1997), but that the insti-
tutional and cultural architecture of the welfare state has become so
entrenched and embedded as to make its reform and retrenchment an
iterative and incremental yet cumulative process down which we are
now only slowly embarking (Pierson, 1994, 1996 ).
2 That the conventional wisdom is simply inaccurate and that far from
representing a drain on competitiveness, the welfare state (at least in
certain institutional and cultural environments) retains and acquires yet
further positive externalities (Barr, 1998; Esping-Andersen, 1994;
Finegold and Soskice, 1988; Garrett, 1998; Gough, 1996; Pfaller et al.,
1991; cf. Polanyi, 1944).
3 That the aggregate empirical evidence in fact masks the actual degree of
retrenchment and that once we control for demographic and other
'welfare inflationary' pressures, observed welfare expenditure is in fact
substantially below that we would anticipate (Esping-Andersen, 1996a,
1996b; Rhodes, 1996, 1997).
4 That, once again, the aggregate evidence masks the degree of real
retrenchment since the market-conforming nature of that process has
served to increase welfare pressures by effectively trading inflation for
unemployment. Consequently, although aggregate spending has
proved 'sticky', once we control for increased welfare demand we
observe both a narrowing of the scope of social provision and retrench-
ment in terms of the value of benefits to claimants (Ferrera, 1998;
Martin, 1997; Rhodes, 1997).
202 Globalization, Economic Change and the Welfare State
The argument proceeds in four sections. In the first of these I assess the scale
of welfare retrenchment in contemporary Europe before moving, in the
second, to assess and evaluate the orthodox view in the light of such evi-
dence. In the third section, I attempt to draw up a more balanced assessment
of the positive and negative externalities of the welfare state in the competi-
tive environment of the contemporary global political economy. I conclude
by considering the prospects for the welfare state in an era of putative globa-
lization. In particular, I focus on the consequences for the form and function
of the welfare state of the stark choice currently facing European economies
between cost competitive and quality competitive strategies.
DK Ga F IRE NL sw UK EU15
1970 36.1 32.4 33.9 30.1 28.3 36.2 36.8 31.9 31.4
1975 42.4 43.1 35.4 38.8 34.7 45.4 44.6 37.6 35.4
1980 50.8 42.7 42.8 41.4 37.9 51.1 56.8 40.2 41.8
1985 55.2 43.4 49.4 47.4 45.3 53.5 61.1 41.8 45.8
1990 55.5 42.0 46.5 38.5 48.6 51.5 58.4 36.6 44.4b
1995 58.2 46.3 51.0 37.4 49.2 49.0 64.7 41.0 47.6b
Log openness
[(exports+ imports)/GDP]
E0 - E 1 expected correlation
0 0 - 0 1 observed correlation (Cameron, 1978; Rodrik, 1996, 1997)
and duties of claimants, we would expect far more than a merely secular
tendency for social expenditure to rise (Esping-Andersen, 1996c; Ferrera,
1998; Hagen, 1992; Jordan, 1998; Ormerod, 1998; Rhodes, 1997; Stephens,
1996; Stephens, Huber and Ray, 1999). The difference between expected
welfare expenditure (assuming consistent income replacement ratios and
eligibility criteria) and that observed provides a rough index of the extent
of effective welfare retrenchment (see figure 1).
A further indication of the degree of welfare retrenchment is provided by
income replacement ratios. These express the value of welfare entitlements
(such as unemployment, sickness and disability benefits) as a percentage of
the average net (post-tax) working wage. Throughout the advanced cap-
italist economies they display a common and marked downward trajectory
from a range of start dates (earlier in the liberal countries, later in the social
democratic countries) and a variety of initial levels (lower in the liberal
regimes, higher in the social democratic regimes) (see, for instance, Clark,
1999; Esping-Andersen, 1996c; Hagen, 1992; Stephens et al., 1999).
6:'
a(j
.......
0
~
0.0
~
:..a~
C1)
0...
V)
(;j Oo
"(J
0
trJ
Time
0 0
- E 1 expected
0 0
- 0 1 observed
population ageing does not automatically imply crisis ... the cost of ageing
depends on long-run productivity growth. The OECD estimates that real
earnings growth at an annual average rate of 0.5-1.2 per cent (depending on
nation) will suffice to finance the additional pension expenditures. (1996a, p. 7)
208 Globalization, Economic Change and the Welfare State
the earnings performance of many nations in the past decade suggests that
such levels of growth may not be so easily attainable. In the United States, for
example, real manufacturing earnings declined by an annual average of 0.2 per
cent during the 1980s. In Europe, where labour shedding has been much more
dramatic, productivity and thus wages have grown at higher rates (1.7 per cent
in France, 0.9 per cent in Italy, and 2.4 per cent in Germany). (1996a, p. 28 n6)
That capital invests where it can secure the greatest net return on that
investment and is possessed of perfect information of the means by
which to maximise this utility.
2 That capital enjoys perfect mobility and that the cost of exit is zero.
3 That capital will invariably secure the greatest return on its investment
through minimizing its labour costs by seeking out a captive supply of
cheap labour in flexible and deregulated labour markets and by reloc-
ating its productive activities in economies with the lowest rates of cor-
porate taxation.
This third assumption leads fairly directly to a fourth and final assumption:
4 That the welfare state (and the taxation receipts out of which it is
funded) represent nothing other than lost capital to mobile asset-
holders and have no positive (or even potentially positive) externalities
for the competitiveness and productivity of the national economy.
this suggests that the orthodox account that presents welfare expenditure
simply as a drain on competitiveness is a gross and distorting simplifica-
tion of a far more complex and contingent reality.
Given the now pervasive orthodoxy, we might expect to find little in the
way of hypothesized competitive-enhancing externalities associated with
inclusive social provision. Yet what is most striking given the ascendancy
of the conventional wisdom is the sheer range and diversity of factors, even
in quite mainstream economic analysis, pointing to the potential contribu-
tion of the welfare state to competitiveness in export markets. These are
presented schematically in table 3 (for a fuller discussion, see Hay, 1999b ).
(6) Reduced costs of ill health Poor health, arising from under-insurance
or non-insurance in a privately financed system, is likely to disrupt pro-
duction whilst imposing punitive healthcare costs (however funded).
Consequently, health- as a public good- is best provided by the state and
is most efficient when it contains a significant preventative component.
Moreover, a redistributive welfare state contributes significantly to a soft-
ening of social stratification (itself closely correlated to poor health)
(Wilkinson, 1996 ). An inclusive state-funded national health service may,
then, both decrease the volume of healthcare demand (through preventa-
tive medicine) while minimizing the cost of satisfying that demand.
(7) Welfare enhances flexibility via greater trust and reduced transaction
costs Inclusive welfare states, particularly where associated with encom-
passing labour-market institutions, encourage relations of cooperation and
trust. Significantly, this facilitates internal flexibility - in which workers
adapt themselves and their working practices to new demands and new
technology - as opposed to external flexibility (i.e. recourse to the labour
market). This fosters cooperative relations between managers and labour,
with consequent reductions in the rate of labour turnover. This, in turn, is
rewarded by higher levels of investment in human capital as workers are
less likely to depart with their newly acquired skills (skills acquired at the
company's expense) to the competition.
Conclusion
markets and a cheap and voluminous supply of docile (for .which read de-
unionized and/or demoralized) labour. The welfare state in such a scenario
is likely to represent little more than an expensive indulgenc/=- though the
social and economic cost of its retrenchment (in terms of the criminaliza-
tion and marginalization of an underclass) should not be underestimated.
Whether out-and-out cost competitiveness represents a viable competitive
strategy for any contemporary European economy is debatable. What it
does suggest, however, is the stark choice that European economies now
face and the significance of that choice for the continued viability of ,the
welfare state. Yet one thing should perhaps be made clear. Europe's most
open economies (Britain excepted) have, throughout the postwar period,
always sought competitiveness on the basis of quality not cost. They have
thus sought to promote internal flexibility within the firm rather than
external flexibility in the labour-market, permanent innovation in produc-
tion as opposed to productivity gains on the basis of hire-and-fire and the
elimination of supply-side rigidities, high and stable levels of both human
and physical capital formation, and inclusive and encompassing labour-
market institutions. Within such a model, far from representing a supply-
side rigidity, the welfare state is not only a competitive advantage it is a
competitive necessity.
Notes
From R. Sykes, B. Palier and P.M. Prior (eds), Globalization and European Welfare
States, London, Palgrave, 2001, pp. 38-58.
The author would like to acknowledge the support of the ESRC for research
on 'Globalization, European Integration and the European Social Model'
(L213252043), research which concentrates on globalization, European integration
and welfare/labour market reform in Denmark, Germany, France, Hungary,
Ireland, Italy, the Netherlands, Sweden and the UK. I would also like to express
gratitude to Pete Alcock, Robert Sykes, Matthew Watson and Daniel Wincott for
comments on an earlier version of this chapter.
This burden is, however, unevenly distributed and has been responded to dif-
ferently in different national contexts. For a more extended discussion see Hay
(1999b ).
2 In the US, for instance, occupationally insured workers are frequently reluc-
tant to move job because of the risk to their eligibility for medical benefits in
a context where private provision is likely to prove punitively expensive.
References
Ashton, D. and Green, F. (1996) Education, Training and the Global Economy,
London, Edward Elgar.
Barr, N. (1998) The Economics of the Welfare State, 3rd edn, Oxford, Oxford
University Press.
Boix, C. (1998) Political Parties, Growth and Equality: Conservative and Social
Democratic Economic Strategies in the World Economy, Cambridge, Cambridge
University Press.
Bosworth, D., Dawkins, P. and Stromback, T. (1996) The Economics of the Labour
Market, Harlow, Longman.
Bowles, S. and Gin tis, H. (1994) 'Efficient Redistribution in a Globally
Competitive Economy', paper presented to the Colloquium on Social Justice
and Economic Constraints, Universite Catholique de Louvain, 3 June.
Cameron, D. R. (1978) 'The Expansion of the Public Economy: A Comparative
Analysis', American Political Science Review, 72, 4, pp. 1243-61.
Cerny, P. G. (1990) The Changing Architecture of Politics, London, Sage.
Cerny, P. G. (1997) 'Paradoxes of the Competition State: The Dynamics of Political
Globalisation', Government and Opposition, 49, 4, pp. 595-625.
Clark, G. L. (1999) 'The Retreat of the State and the Rise of Pension Fund
Capitalism', in R. Martin (ed.), Money and the Space Economy, New York,
Wiley.
Esping-Andersen, G. (1990) The Three Worlds of Welfare Capitalism, Cambridge,
Polity.
Esping-Andersen, G. (1994) 'The Welfare State and the Economy', inN. J. Smelser
and R. Swedberg (eds), The Handbook of Economic Sociology, Princeton,
Princeton University Press.
Esping-Andersen, G. (1996a) 'After the Golden Age? Welfare State Dilemmas in a
Global Economy', in G. Esping-Andersen (ed.), Welfare States in Transition:
National Adaptations in Global Economies, London, Sage.
Esping-Andersen, G. (1996b) 'Positive-Sum Solutions in a World ofTrade-Offs?',
in G. Esping-Andersen (ed.), Welfare States in Transition: National Adaptations
in Global Economies, London, Sage.
Esping-Andersen, G. (1996c) 'Welfare States without Work: The Impasse of
Labour Shedding and Familialism in Continental European Social Policy', in G.
Esping-Andersen (ed.), Welfare States in Transition: National Adaptations in
Global Economies, London, Sage.
Esping-Andersen, G. (1999) Social Foundations of Postindustrial Economies,
London, Sage.
European Commission (1996) European Economy, no. 62, Brussels, Directorate-
General for Economic and Financial Affairs.
Ferrera, M. (1998) 'The Four "Social Europes": Between Universalism and
Selectivity', in M. Rhodes and Y. Meny (eds), The Future of the European
Welfare State: A New Social Contract? Basingstoke, Macmillan.
Fine, Ben (1998) 'The Triumph of Economics: or, "Rationality" Can be Dangerous
to your Reasoning', in J. G. Collier and D. Miller (eds), Virtualism: A New
Political Economy, Oxford, Berg.
Finegold, D. and Soskice, D. (1988) 'The Failure of Training in Britain: Analysis
and Prescription', Oxford Review of Economic Policy, 4, 3, pp. 21-53.
Fisher, I. (1930) The Theory of Interest, Basingstoke, Macmillan.
Fisher, I. (1935) The Clash of Progress and Security, Basingstoke, Macmillan.
Garrett, G. (1998) Partisan Politics in the Global Economy, Cambridge, Cambridge
University Press.
Gilder, G. (1981) Welfare and Poverty, New York, Basic Books.
220 Globalization, Economic Change and the Welfare State
[ ... ]
In the history of capitalism, the decades following the Second World War
were unusual in the degree to which the boundaries of the territorial state
had become coextensive with the boundaries of markets for capital, ser-
vices, goods and labour. These boundaries were by no means imperme-
able, but transactions across them were nevertheless under the effective
control of national governments. As a consequence, capital owners were
generally restricted to investment opportunities within the national
economy, and firms were mainly challenged by domestic competitors.
International trade grew slowly, and since governments controlled
imports and exchange rates, international competitiveness was not much
of a problem. While these conditions lasted, government interest rate
policy controlled the rate of return on financial investments. If interest
rates were lowered, job-creating real investments would become rela-
tively more attractive, and vice versa. Thus, Keynesian macroeconomic
management could smooth the business cycle and prevent demand-
deficient unemployment, while union wage policy, where it could be
employed for macro-economic purposes, was able to control the rate of
inflation. At the same time, government regulation and union collective
bargaining controlled the conditions of production. But since all effective
competitors could be, and were, required to produce under the same
regimes, the costs of regulation could be passed on to consumers. Hence
the rate of return on investment was not necessarily affected by high
levels of regulation and union power; capitalist accumulation was as
224 Negative Integration
[ ... ]
Note
From G. Marks et al., eds, Governance in the E U, London, Sage, 1996, pp. 16-17.
A Race to the Bottotn?
Francis G. Castles
theories exaggerate the extent of the threat resulting from changes in the
international economy. Frequently, they neglect consumption consider-
ations in the determination of locational advantage (i.e. being close to one's
market may be as important as minimizing production costs) and offer an
exaggerated picture of the likely consequences of capital flight (by the mid-
t990s, corporate taxes amounted to somewhat less than 10 per cent of total
taxation in OECD countries - see Ganghof, 2000). Second, there are
reasons for supposing that the consequences of globalization may be quite
different from those presupposed by such accounts. Indeed, rival accounts
suggest that exposure to the world economy may actually serve as an
incentive for governments to intervene to maintain or even improve regu-
latory standards in the hope of thereby mitigating some of the adverse con-
sequences of international economic vulnerability (see Cameron, 1978;
Ruggie, 1982; Katzenstein, 1985; Rodrik, 1997).
Globalization accounts may also be unrealistic in other ways. A third
reason that social expenditures may not have declined as much as predicted
is that the extent of change in the international economy in recent years is
rather less than is sometimes implied in the crisis literature. In the 1990s,
the average level of imports plus exports as a percentage of GDP in OECD
countries was only around 5 per cent higher than in the 1980s. Admittedly,
over the same period, the average level of foreign direct investment had
more than doubled, but this was from a very low base. At the same time,
overseas investment flows in OECD countries during the 1980s and 1990s
averaged less than 3 per cent of GDP, a figure hardly indicative of over-
whelming capital mobility among nations. Finally, these accounts appear
totally to misjudge the dynamics of social expenditure change. The impli-
cation of the 'race to the bottom' analysis is that countries can rapidly
adjust their social expenditure levels in a downward direction, but the pre-
vailing imagery of the policy change literature is of a trajectory of social
policy reform strongly shaped by an inertia and irreversibility stemming
from a logic of 'increasing returns' and 'path dependent' institutional
development (see Pierson, 2000). In Karl Hinrichs's beautiful simile, social
security systems are like 'elephants on the move' (Hinrichs, 2001). When
they are young, they may stampede ahead, but when they are mature they
generally move forward rather slowly. Irrespective of age, turning them
around involves much energy and no little persuasive power.
In this chapter, we are looking for signs that such a turnaround has
occurred during the course of the past two decades. We assess the extent to
which this may have occurred by examining trajectories of social expend-
iture measured in a variety of ways. Our premise is that, a few minor excep-
tions apart, it simply does not make sense to talk of a 'race to the bottom'
in social provision that is not manifested in social expenditure terms. That
is because, in most advanced welfare states, the vast bulk of provision takes
the form of income-maintenance schemes and social services funded from
228 A Race to the Bottom?
a Because data for 1960 and for 1980 and onwards come from different sources,
the figures for change 1960-80 are, at best, approximations.
Sources: Data for 1960 from OECD, 1994. In the cases of Denmark, Belgium and
Spain, the 1960 figures are the sum of social security transfers plus health spending
(data from Castles, 1998). Data from 1980 onwards from OECD, 2001c. Missing
data in 1980 for occupational injury spending for Australia and for other
contingencies for Denmark, Greece and Italy. 1980 unemployment cash benefits for
Austria, France and Ireland interpolated from OECD, 1985. 1998 UK total
expenditure reduced by 3.3 per cent of GDP to take account of a definitional change
relating to old age cash benefits. All calculated figures subject to rounding errors.
230 A Race to the Bottom?
to classify in family of nations terms and data for them are presented sep-
arately. In tables 1 to 4, we separately present family of nations means and
overall means for all twenty-one cases. This serves as a simple device for
assessing the extent of differences among groupings of nations. An overall
measure of the similarity of cases is given by the coefficient of variation,
which is provided for all measures of expenditure levels, but not for
changes over time. Lower values of the coefficient imply a reduction in the
overall variation of cases and a consistent downward trend in values sug-
gests a move towards greater convergence in spending patterns.
Looking initially at family of nations patterns in respect of levels of
aggregate spending, we note changes in the groupings featuring as welfare
state leaders and laggards. Table 1 shows that, in 1960, continental Western
Europe was the area making much the greatest welfare effort, with little to
choose between the English-speaking and Scandinavian countries in the
middle of the distribution, and with Southern Europe, Italy excepted, in the
rearguard. By 1980, however, this clear hierarchy of spending had collapsed
into two broader groupings, with the Scandinavian and continental Western
European countries spending around a quarter of GDP for social policy
purposes and the English-speaking and Southern European countries
around 15 per cent. Finally, during the course of the period that concerns
us here, hierarchy was restored, but along lines rather different from those
of the early postwar era. By 1998, the Scandinavian countries had become
outright welfare state leaders, with average spending levels of just below
30 per cent of GDP. The countries of continental Western Europe followed
close behind, with Southern Europe now somewhat ahead of an English-
speaking rearguard. Changes in the welfare state ranking of individual
countries were no less dramatic than those of country groupings, with
Switzerland moving from the position of being OECD's second lowest
spender in 1960 to its third highest in 1998, and with Ireland moving from
a position above the OECD mean in 1980 to the third lowest level of spend-
ing in 1998. The diversity of expenditure patterns demonstrated in table 1,
and the relatively tight bunching of nations sharing close historical, cultural
and linguistic affinities, does not seem readily compatible with hypotheses
of the kind offered by the crisis literature, suggesting that welfare states
everywhere were responding to the same powerful external forces.
Turning now to patterns of expenditure growth, the initial point to note
is the substantial contrast between periods. The 1960 to 1980 period was
one of consistent and strong social expenditure growth. All the OECD
member countries featuring in table 1 experienced increases in spending
measured as a percentage of GDP, with Denmark and Sweden leading the
way with increases in spending of 18.5 and 18.2 per cent of GDP respect-
ively. For OECD countries in general, expenditure grew by 9 per cent of
GDP, which meant a virtual doubling in size of the average OECD welfare
state in just two decades. The 1980 to 1998 period was, in comparison, an
Francis G. Castles 231
era of more inconsistent and much reduced spending growth. In the earlier
period, there were eight countries which increased their spending by more
than 10 per cent of GDP; in the later period, there were just two,
Switzerland and Portugal, both of them catching up from the rear of the
distribution. In the earlier period, the smallest increase in spending was
Australia's 3.9 per cent of GDP; in the later period, there were no fewer
than nine countries with expenditure growth of less than 3.9 per cent.
Finally, in the second period, the average rate of expenditure growth was
more than halved, dropping from nine to four percentage points of GDP.
Whether as a consequence of globalization or some other concatenation of
forces, there can be no question at all that the pace of welfare state growth
had slowed dramatically after 1980.
However, it declined on nothing like the scale hypothesized by the crisis
literature. Three sets of figures in table 1 make this abundantly plain. A
'race to the bottom' implies an across-the-board contraction in social
spending. However, as the final column of table 1 shows, there were, in
fact, only two countries- Ireland and the Netherlands- that experienced
any overall cutback in aggregate social expenditure during these years. The
second relevant figure is the average 4 per cent increase in spending as a
percentage of GDP between 1980 and 1998. Translated into a percentage
rise in spending, this means that the average OECD country increased its
welfare effort by slightly more than 20 per cent- from 18.7 to 22.7 per cent
of GDP- in precisely that period in which the prevailing crisis accounts
suggest that expenditure should have been dropping like a stone. The
salience of this finding is highlighted by a third set of figures, the consist-
ent downward trend in the coefficients of variation appearing in the final
row of table 1, demonstrating a growing similarity of social expenditure
levels over a period of almost four decades. The 'race to the bottom' argu-
ment implies a sharp break in trend, with a general movement towards
higher expenditures in the early postwar years replaced, more recently, by
a process of downwards convergence. What table 1 demonstrates is that,
throughout the postwar period, increased similarity has been conjoint with
increased spending.
We now turn to corresponding patterns of overall public expenditure
development. Table 2 presents data on total outlays of general government
as a percentage of GDP from OECD Economic Outlook (various years)
for the same time points and periods as table 1. Table 2, in most respects,
tells much the same story as table 1. Total expenditure magnitudes are, of
course, much greater than for social spending, with mean levels of total
expenditure starting out at a level three times greater than social expend-
iture and ending up at a level somewhat less than twice as high. By 1998,
the OECD mean for total outlays was 43 per cent of GDP, with a high of
55.5 per cent of GDP in Sweden and a low of 30.5 per cent of GDP in the
United States. However, despite differences in magnitudes, family of
Table 2 Total outlays of general government as a percentage of GDP in
twenty-one OECD countries, 1960, 1980, 1998 and change over time
nations patterns were similar, with the single exception that the countries
of Southern Europe remained well below the level of public spending of
the English-speaking countries in 1980. By 1998, the hierarchy of families
of nations in respect of social spending is almost exactly replicated for total
outlays. Also, as in the case of aggregate social expenditure, there was a
very substantial contrast in growth trajectories in the two periods. In the
1960s and 1970s, average total outlays growth of 15 per cent of GDP was
about 60 per cent greater than social expenditure growth in the same
period. However, in the period from 1980 to 1998, overall total outlays in
the OECD were effectively becalmed, ending up only 0.7 of a percentage
point of GDP higher at the end of the period than at its beginning.
This is where the one really significant contrast between total outlays
and aggregate social expenditure trends is to be found. Only two out of
twenty-one countries experienced social expenditure cutbacks between
1980 and 1998, but no less than eight of the nineteen countries for which
we have total outlays data experienced overall public expenditure cuts in
the same period. It is also possible to surmise the expenditure trajectories
of countries for which data are missing. Given the very substantial expan-
sion of Swiss social spending in this period shown in table 1 and docu-
mented in a number of studies (see Lane, 1999; Kriesi, 1999; Armingeon,
2001), it seems reasonable to assume that total outlays in Switzerland
increased markedly between 1980 and 1998. By the same token, the rela-
tively small increase in New Zealand's social expenditure shown in table 1,
combined with a public sector which, by all accounts, was cut to ribbons
in this period (see Kelsey, 1993; Boston and Uhr, 1996; Stephens, 1999),
seems likely to have contributed to an overall decline in total outlays in the
period after 1980. Given the probability of diverse spending trends in these
two countries, it may be concluded that there was some degree of expend-
iture reduction in nearly half the countries of the OECD. There was also
extreme diversity in spending trajectories. Belgium, Ireland and the
Netherlands all experienced expenditure cutbacks in excess of 10 per cent
of GDP. The public sectors of Finland, Greece and Portugal, on the other
hand, grew by similar amounts.
This discrepancy between trends in aggregate social spending and in
total public expenditure is extremely interesting. The items of spending
included in total outlays which are not also included under the social
expenditure head are general public services, public order and safety,
defence, education, housing and community services, economic affairs,
recreation and culture and a residual other category which includes debt
interest payments (see United Nations, 1999). Reading tables 2 and 1 in
conjunction suggests that, over the past two decades, these non-social
components of public spending have, in aggregate, been subject to greater
attrition and downward pressure than has aggregate social spending.
Whether these cutbacks are of sufficient magnitude to suggest a possible
234 A Race to the Bottom?
the high priority they attached to spending of this nature. In 1960, the gap
in salience between the top and bottom family groups - continental
Western Europe and the English-speaking nations - was 11.6 percentage
points. In 1998, the gap between top and bottom - Scandinavia and
Southern Europe- was just 6.1 percentage points. Summary statistics tell
the same story, with a strongly declining coefficient of variation over time.
Francis G. Castles 237
The next important point to note is that this process of convergence had
occurred as a consequence of more and more countries becoming welfare
states according to Therborn's criterion. In 1960, Germany was the only
OECD country to devote more resources to welfare than to other pur-
poses. In 1980, Denmark had replaced Germany as the OECD's only
welfare state. By 1998, however, fourteen of the twenty countries featur-
ing in table 3 were welfare states by this criterion and Switzerland, the
country for which data are missing, would also undoubtedly qualify if the
data were available. Finally, and most significantly, this mass shift across
the threshold of welfare statehood occurred, not in the golden years
between 1960 and 1980, but in the supposedly crisis-ridden years after
1980. In 1980, the average level of welfare salience was 43.5 per cent; by
1998, it was 52.4 per cent. By one reckoning, the OECD area had itself
become a giant welfare state, in so far as it was constituted largely by
nations spending more on welfare than for all other purposes. By another,
there was still some way to go, given that two of the countries yet to
become welfare states according to this criterion were the OECD's most
populous nations, the United States and Japan.
This analysis has important implications. Over the past two decades,
most OECD countries have committed themselves to social policy as their
first priority and table 3 provides absolutely no sign that this is a trajectory
of change which has exhausted its potential. As we have seen, part of what
happened in the 1980s and 1990s was an increase in real spending on
welfare, but just as important was a decline in non-social spending.
Admittedly, as already noted, the barriers between the categories of spend-
ing are far from watertight, but, accepting the distinction as given, what
appears to have been happening is that, in a period in which overall expen-
diture increases have been constrained, policy-makers have been privileg-
ing welfare priorities at the margin. This is not what the 'race to the
bottom' theorists would have us believe, but clearly finding out why this
kind of trade-off is occurring is vital for an understanding of contempo-
rary welfare state dynamics.
A possible explanation that might simultaneously account for a general-
ized malaise about the future of the welfare state and for an enhanced pri-
ority for welfare over other purposes would be if demands or needs for
welfare had been increasing over time. This is, in essence, the basis of the
account offered in Paul Pierson's book The New Politics of the Welfare
State (2001 ). The argument is that expenditure retrenchment is a difficult
project for modern governments because they are expected to tackle a wide
range of problems from deindustrialization to population ageing and to
provide a whole range of new services from drug rehabilitation to services
enabling women to combine labour force participation and maternity.
Under these circumstances, it is easy to see why commentators interpret
what is happening in terms of increased pressure on the welfare state or
238 A Race to the Bottom?
even of crisis. If governments feel that there are economic and/or political
constraints on higher taxing and spending, and if, at the same time, there is
an increased demand for welfare services, one of two things,.ml1st happen:
either other expenditure must be cut or existing standards of provision
must decline.
We have already seen that there has been some decline in non-social
expenditure. In what follows, we discuss briefly what has been happening
to standards of welfare provision. Although the 'race to the bottom' argu-
ment is essentially a hypothesis about the likely future trajectory of welfare
spending, an analogous argument is sometimes encountered about effects
on welfare standards. Indeed, for many left-of-centre commentators that
is the main concern. Their worry is that capital will press governments to
reduce existing standards in order for business to compete in an era of
global competition. The arguments are familiar. Enterprises are not com-
petitive when employers must pay huge social security contributions,
when generous sickness benefits create mass absenteeism and when unem-
ployment benefits are so high that they diminish the incentive to work.
Reducing standards of protection- 'social dumping'- can be presented as
the only way for a country to attract new capital or to retain the capital it
already has. In effect, this argument concedes that globalization is not the
sole factor determining expenditure growth, with increased welfare
demand and welfare dependency countering the 'race to the bottom'. The
impact of globalization under these circumstances is not to reduce aggre-
gate welfare spending, but rather to reduce individual welfare generosity.
Table 4 provides an admittedly simplistic measuring rod for assessing
how well contemporary welfare states have been coping with the increased
demands made of them. The two categories of increased welfare need most
generally noted in the literature are the impact of population ageing and
increasing levels of unemployment. The latter has been highlighted by
many commentators as a snare and delusion for those measuring
welfare states in purely monetary terms, since increased spending on this
count is simply seen as a measure of the welfare state's incapacity to control
unemployment (see Esping-Andersen, 1990; Mishra, 1990; Clayton and
Pontusson, 1998). All that we do in table 4 is to divide the aggregates of
expenditure appearing in table 1 by the percentage of the dependent popu-
lation, that is, the population aged 65 and over plus the percentage of the
civilian population registered as unemployed. The resulting ratio gives a
crude measure of welfare generosity, theoretically to be interpreted as the
percentage of GDP received in welfare spending for every 1 per cent of the
population in need.
There are two obvious deficiencies with this measure. First, it presents
an average figure for each country, when we know that benefits to differ-
ent sections of the population in need in a given country often vary quite
markedly. In some countries, and particularly in Southern Europe (see
Francis G. Castles 239
Notes and sources: Welfare state generosity ratio calculated by dividing social
expenditure data from table 1 by the sum of the percentage of the population
aged 65 years and over and the percentage of the civilian population unemployed.
Data on both aged population and unemployment from OECD, 2001 b. All
calculated figures subject to rounding errors.
Conclusion
Note
from Francis G. Castles, The Future of the Welfare State, Oxford, Oxford
University Press, 2004, pp. 21-46.
References
Introduction
Once upon a time- not that long ago- there was consensus in Western
Europe that the welfare states' full employment and expanding social-
citizenship rights inaugurated after the end of World War II had come to
stay. This reshaping of the welfare state had emerged in the context of the
sea change in power relations, when for the first time in history left parties
had come to be either dominant parties in governments or the major oppo-
sition parties. In its 1945 election manifesto the British Labour Party made
'jobs for all' and 'social insurance against the rainy day' its primary polit-
ical objectives and outlined 'the means needed to realise them' (Craig, 1975,
pp. 124-5, 130). Labour's unexpectedly great victory set the tone and
impressed a lesson that was widely accepted in Europe. Scholars, polit-
icians, and the public came to see the continued existence of such welfare
states as ensured by a supportive electorate. In the 1950s this mood was
summed up by a leading British Labour politician: 'Any Government
which tampered seriously with the full employment welfare state would
meet with a sharp reversal at the polls' (Crosland, 1956, p. 28). In the mid-
1970s, however, this stability began to evaporate. Before the end of the
century Western scholars had shifted their focus from the study of welfare-
state expansion to analyses of its regress, welfare-state retrenchment. In the
1990s the study of retrenchment became a growth industry with an out-
pouring of articles and books.
In scholarly debates on welfare-state retrenchment, one key issue has
concerned the extent of retrenchment. On this question the dominant view
has been that in Western Europe no sweeping or radical retrenchment has
occurred, a view that has recently been questioned. Other central questions
have concerned the causes of retrenchment. Here the debate has been
Walter Korpi 247
In the study of retrenchment the dependent variable, the welfare state, has
typically been defined in terms of social transfers and/ or social services.
Although these two areas, of course, are central, in analyses of retrench-
ment it is necessary to have a theoretically based definition of the depend-
ent variable. In the power-resources approach scholars view postwar
changes in welfare states to a significant extent as reflecting power contests
among major interest groups related to the relative role of markets and
democratic politics in distributive processes. These conflicts also define
and change institutions that set frames for continued distributive conflicts.
Such an approach indicates that, although transfers and services are
important, here at least one more area must be considered, namely that of
unemployment.
In the power-resources perspective unemployment appears as a central
variable because for categories of citizens with labour power as their main
basic power resource, the efficacy of this resource in distributive conflict
and bargaining is to a major extent determined by the demand for labour
and by the level of unemployment. In this perspective the maintenance of
low levels of unemployment empowers citizens and is an essential preven-
tive part of the welfare state (for example, see Korpi, 1983, p. 188).
However, the right to employment is very difficult to establish as a claim
right. Yet, in almost all countries of Western Europe in the years after the
end of World War II, full employment became what can be called a social
protoright in the sense that it was widely expected by citizens and that irre-
spective of partisan composition most European governments acted so as
to maintain full employment
As Blanchflower and Oswald (1994) have shown, the level of unem-
ployment has a clear relevance to wage levels. In local labour markets and
industries with high unemployment, wages tend to be lower than where
unemployment is low. This empirical fact indicates that the level of unem-
ployment is likely to be both a main bone of contention between employ-
ers and employees and a major factor determining outcomes of the
positive-sum distributive conflict between them concerning the distribu-
tion of firm revenues. The state of the labour market and changes in levels
of unemployment must therefore be seen as essential welfare-state indica-
tors and cannot be overlooked in analyses of welfare-state retrenchment.
As in earlier analyses of welfare-state expansion, in the study of
retrenchment the typical dependent variable has been welfare-state effort,
defined as the size of government social expenditures in relation to the
gross domestic product. With basic data available in publications by the
International Labour Organization (ILO) and the Organization for
Economic Cooperation and Development (OECD), this indicator has
been widely used. Unfortunately, however, the well-known problems
250 Welfare-State Regress in Western Europe
In the United States the postwar social contract did not include full
employment in the European sense. From 1955 to 1973 US unemployment
levels averaged 4.9 per cent (figure 1). In the same period six r:ore countries
of the European Economic Community - Belgium, Denmark, France
Germany, Netherlands, and the United Kingdom- had less than half of th;
US unemployment level, 2.1 per cent. But after the oil shocks in 1'i73 and
1979, the average unemployment level in these countries quadrupled and
was 8.2 per cent during 1982-2000, while changes in the United States were
modest. In fact, after World War II and until the end of the century, US
unemployment rates have shown essentially trendless fluctuation. In stark
contrast Western Europe experienced first the arrival of full employment
and thereafter the return of mass unemployment.
Clearly a number of factors were of relevance to the return of mass
unemployment to Europe. 2 However, conflicts of interest between major
interest groups are likely to have been of significance there. Long-lasting
full employment in Europe came to have consequences unwanted by
important interest groups. Thus business interests saw with increasing
alarm the rising levels of labour-force involvement in industrial conflict as
well as the falling share of profits and increasing share of wages in the
domestic product. Yet the fear of voter reactions pressed governments of
11
10
9
---..
~ 8
H
C1! 7
1-.
6
=
v
E
>. 5
0
0.. 4
E United States
v
c::
:::> 3
2
0
1./") 0 1./") 0 1./") 0 1./") 0 1./") 0
1./")
0'
~
0'
-
~
0' "'
0'
"'
0'
Year
00
0'
00
0'
0'
0'
0'
0'
0
0
(".1
all political shades to give top priority to full employment in the trade-off
between inflation and employment (OECD, 1970). As argued by Rehn
(1987), many European governments are likely to have used the window
0 f opportunity created by the oil shocks of 1973 and 1979 to allow levels
of unemployment to escalate. In the 1990s US unemployment rates
decreased more than the European average.
Within the European perspective, full employment was thus a constitu-
tive part of the welfare state. When judged in relation to the reality prior
to 1973, the return of mass unemployment must be seen as a major
retrenchment, the eradication of one of the cornerstones of Western
European welfare states. However, this radical change has occurred
outside the focus of the new-politics approach and has therefore not been
conceived as a case of retrenchment.
pension systems the working generation is paying the pensions for retirees
and cannot easily accept also contributing to their own future pensions in a
funded system. Mature pay-as-you-go pension systems are therefore diffi-
cult to change into funded programmes. It is important that we can explain
differences in the extent of path dependency in terms of specific mechanisms
that generate more or less resistance to cuts. Often, however, the concept of
path dependency is used to label absence of change rather than to explain
resistance to change.
As noted above, in the new-politics perspective it is widely assumed that
resistance to welfare-state cuts comes primarily from categories of benefit
recipients, such as retirees, the unemployed, the handicapped, and health-
care consumers. Although such categories are relevant and retirees in par-
ticular constitute a significant part of the electorate in most countries, other
benefit recipients, for example the unemployed, have traditionally been
very difficult to mobilize. It can be argued that of greater relevance here is
the much larger constituency of risk-averse citizens, who benefit from
insurance in terms of the reduction of risks they are likely to face during
the life course. However, in Western societies risk-averse citizens are inter-
nally differentiated by a number of potential and partly cross-cutting lines
of cleavage, such as occupation, status, income, education, ethnicity, reli-
gion, and region. These cleavages also differentiate citizens in terms of life-
time risk as well as in terms of the resources they control to handle these
risks. Given these circumstances, reflecting theory formation within the
'new institutionalism', it can be argued that major welfare-state institu-
tions are likely to be of relevance for the formation of values, attitudes, and
interests among citizens in ways that are of relevance for patterns of col-
lective action. This is because welfare-state institutions tend to create tem-
plates that emphasize some of the lines of cleavage discussed above while
downplaying others. The institutional contexts generated by welfare states
are therefore likely to affect citizens' coalition formation in terms of the
extent of support and resistance that government efforts to cut back social
rights are likely to face (Korpi and Palme, 1998; Korpi, 2001). The institu-
tional organization of risk-averse citizens, rather than the number of
benefit recipients, is likely to be of main relevance for the degree of path
dependency in welfare-state programmes.
To account for differences among countries in terms of welfare-state
development, it is fruitful to relate changes in social rights to a welfare-state
typology based on the nature of the institutional structures of the main
social-insurance programmes in a country (Korpi and Palme, 1998; Korpi,
2001 ). 4 This typology differentiates social-insurance institutions by using
three criteria: basis for claiming benefits, principles for setting benefit
levels, and forms of governance of insurance programmes. On the bases of
these criteria, it is possible to identify five different types of institutional
structures, which historically have existed in Western welfare states. These
256 Welfare-State Regress in Western Europe
clearly in the lead with average net replacement rates that were reduced by
almost half. Ireland followed with cutbacks amounting to one-third of
peak rates. Denmark had cutb~cks of the order of one-fifth of pe~k rates,
while lower rates were found m the Netherlands. Among the bas1c secu-
rity countries Switzerland had no major cutbacks. 6 Among the state cor-
poratist countries cuts were, on average, lowest. Thus whereas in Austria,
france, Germany, and Italy unemployment insurance programmes had
seen significant cuts, sickness and work-accident programmes had largely
been spared. An exception here was Belgium, where net benefits decreased
markedly in sickness insurance. In the encompassing category, cuts were
on the average lower than in countries with basic-security programmes,
but both Sweden and Finland had made some important cuts, primarily
during the early 1990s when their unemployment levels exploded. Norway
with its oil economy largely escaped cuts.
With reliable and comparable empirical data reflecting the character of
social rights in a large number of countries over a longer period, we get a
perspective on the extent of retrenchment in social-insurance programmes
that is quite different from the ones based on expenditure data and quali-
tative case studies. In at least a handful of European countries, major
retrenchment in social-insurance rights now appears. There is no general
path dependency; instead the different types of welfare-state institutions in
combination with factors such as constitutional veto points appear to play
significant roles in terms of path dependency and resistance to cuts.
In the 1990s globalization became a term on everybody's lips and was used
to suggest a variety of international challenges facing nation-states and their
welfare-state arrangements in particular. 7 Initially threats from globaliza-
tion against welfare states were often seen as severe, but gradually views
have been shifting. For example, although Mishra (1999) saw globalization
as avery serious threat to the foundations of welfare states, such views have
been questioned by others (e.g., Boyer and Drache, 1996; Garrett, 1998).
Many scholars have come to see the effects of globalization as conditional
on national institutions and political interventions (Esping-Andersen, 1996;
Palier and Sykes; 2001; Swank, 2001). In the processes of globalization
international organizations have played significant roles (Deacon et al.,
1997). As noted above, Pierson largely dismisses globalization as a source
for fundamental welfare-state change. In discussions of the effects of efforts
260 Welfare-State Regress in Western Europe
towards economic and political integration within the EU we also find con-
siderable debates (Leibfried and Pierson, 1995; Rhodes, 1996, 2002).
In analysing the role of international political and economic changes for
national policy-making, distinguishing between different policy sectors in
welfare states is fruitful. One important distinction is found between pol-
icies to maintain full employment and social insurance and social services.
National policies to maintain full employment are likely to be much more
sensitive to, and dependent on, international developments than social-
insurance and social-service programmes are. Of relevance here is that,
with the exception of the largest economies, most Western countries are
markedly export dependent. As Fligstein and Merand (2002) noted, trade
growth has been especially pronounced within the E.U. When countries in
economic crises decrease their imports, export possibilities in other coun-
tries decline and their unemployment problems mount, thereby likely
creating a situation that pressures governments to make cuts in social-
insurance and social-service programmes. In Europe full employment after
the end of World War II was conditioned by Bretton-Woods institutions,
giving national governments influence over cross-border capital flows
while liberalizing cross-border trade. With the dismantling of cross-border
capital controls and increasing economic integration within Europe, if
unemployment is allowed to rise in some countries, maintaining full
employment becomes very difficult, especially for smaller countries.
A large-scale experiment on the role of economic interdependence and
political factors contributing to the rise of unemployment took place in
Europe after the two oil shocks in 1973 and 1979. As discussed above,
while levels of unemployment increased dramatically in the EEC coun-
tries, the EFTA countries (Austria, Finland, Norway, Sweden, and
Switzerland), where social democrats had long participated in govern-
ments, attempted via various means to avoid the return of mass unem-
ployment. For almost two decades, the EFTA countries were relatively
successful in these attempts, but in the early 1990s, especially in Finland
and Sweden, unemployment levels converged to the high European
average (Korpi, 2002).
Many economists have argued that globalization has interacted with
technological developments to increase levels of unemployment in the eco-
nomically advanced countries. The assumption here is that technological
developments in these economies have escalated educational job require-
ments to levels where the less educated no longer are qualified. At the same
time less-qualified production is moved to low-wage countries. In
advanced economies job demands are thus assumed to have outrun the edu-
cational qualifications of significant sectors of the labour force. Such inter-
pretations are often supported by the observation that levels of
unemployment tend to be especially high among workers with low educa-
tional qualifications, a correlation interpreted in causal terms. However,
Walter Korpi 261
Discussion
The dramatic changes taking place in the economies of the Western coun-
tries during the past three decades have generated a number of important
and informative books and articles on the consequences of these changes
for welfare states. A review of the rapidly expanding research on welfare-
state retrenchment points to the importance of clarifying the nature of the
dependent variable, the welfare state. A definition focusing on social
expenditures for transfers and services easily invites scholars to consider
explanations in terms of general forces related to structural economic
change. In the early decades after the end of World War II, scholars widely
interpreted welfare-state expansion as a result of the development of indus-
trialism generating universally shared needs for a well-trained and inter-
nally differentiated labour force (Kerr et al., 1964). Three decades later,
analysts have explained welfare-state retrenchment in terms of postindus-
trialism, which via demographic and economic changes generates perma-
nent austerity and thereby drives retrenchment. Although it is obvious that
both industrialism and postindustrialism significantly change the contexts
and conditions for policy-making, the question is to what extent these
changes basically alter the nature of distributive conflict in Western soci-
eties. In the power-resources approach, viewing welfare states largely as
outcomes of distributive conflicts between major interest groups differ-
ently endowed in terms of assets to be used in markets and in collective
action via politics, conflicts concerning the determination of demand for
labour and levels of unemployment emerge as key issues. Government
budgetary pressures, the central causal factor driving retrenchment in the
new-politics perspective, is to a major extent correlated with the rise in
unemployment levels.
The widely shared view that welfare-state regress in Western Europe has
been relatively limited partly reflects the fact that many scholars on
welfare-state retrenchment have overlooked the return of mass unem-
ployment, a central feature of Western European retrenchment.
Furthermore, the widespread reliance on expenditure data has tended to
blur the contours of retrenchment. Although the many case studies of a
single or a few countries have given very valuable clues to the processes of
retrenchment, such information has been difficult to forge into a larger
picture of the extent and causes of retrenchment. In this context data on
changes in social rights in social-insurance programmes provide a comple-
ment to earlier studies, offering limited sets of well-defined comparative
Walter Korpi 263
measures for a large number of countries and a relatively long time period.
Analyses based on such data question earlier interpretations of the extent
and causes of retrenchment. Thus since 1975 in a handful of European
countries citizenship rights in three main social-insurance programmes
have changed in ways that must be described as major retrenchment.
Differences in outcomes between earlier analyses and those based on social
citizenship rights are especially stark when it comes to Britain, a crucial test
case in the discussion on the extent and causes of retrenchment. In the
debates on the role of class-related political parties in welfare-state regress,
analyses based on social-rights data clearly support the hypothesis of a
continued role of partisan politics in the retrenchment phase.
In discussions on the role of globalization and on European integration
for welfare-state regress, conflicting hypotheses have been advanced. Here,
however, considering different aspects of welfare states and their interac-
tions is necessary. It can be argued that a major part of the effects of globali-
zation and transnational integration on welfare-state retrenchment has
been focused on full employment, one of the cornerstones of the postwar
European welfare state, the undercutting of which in turn may have effects
on social insurance and services. The liberalization of cross-border capital
movements has to a significant extent turned the tables to the disadvantage
of governments attempting to safeguard full employment. Within the EU,
developments limiting the economic policy choices of governments in
member countries are also likely to have been significant. In the power-
resources perspective, the return of mass unemployment and attempts
to make cuts in social-citizenship rights appear as a reworking of the
implicit social contract established in Western Europe after the end of
World War II.
Notes
References
Introduction
The two main paradigms for analysing European integration have long
been intergovernmentalism and nco-functionalism. The former suggests
that the Member States control the decision-making process inside the EU
and ensure that national sovereignty is as far as possible protected. From
this point of view, European integration entails not the creation of a super-
state but fostering mutually advantageous political and economic cooper-
ation in a manner that respects national sovereignty. N eo-functionalism
normally assumes the opposite, addressing the conditions under which
people might shift their loyalty and commitment from national to EU
level (Haas, 1958). In explaining just how such a transfer could occur,
much use is made of the concept of spillover, a process whereby integra-
tion in one functional area obliges closer cooperation between Member
States in others.
Although both views still have their robust advocates (Moravcsik, 1999;
Str0by Jensen, 2000), it is now widely accepted that neither is able to capture
the full complexities of European integration. The new consensus is that
while the EU has traits of intergovernmentalism and nco-functionalism, it
fully reflects neither one nor the other. It is a political entity that defies such
established analytical categories. Multi-level governance is the term now
most frequently used to describe its political formation. From this perspec-
tive, the EU is not like the traditional nation-state with a tight fit between
citizenship, political representation and policy-making. Nor is it a fully
fledged supranational body with the capacity to 'steer' the European
economy and polity. Rather it is a multi-layered amalgam of national gov-
ernments and EU institutions, policy networks, independent agencies and
interest groups, creating a patchwork governance regime.
270 Deliberative Governance and E U Social Policy
The purpose of this article is threefold. The first is to suggest that the
consequence of this patchwork form of governance has been to create a
dilemma with regard to the institutional organization of econom.ic citizen-
ship- the bundle of rights and procedures used to incorporate people into
the world of work- in Europe. On the one hand, EU social policy has been
strong enough to create a wedge between economic citizenship and the
nation-state- the notion of 'national' industrial relations systems has been
destabilized. On the other hand, the institutional system of the EU is too
weak to sustain a fully formed model of economic citizenship. Our second
aim is to deepen insight into the origins of this dilemma by outlining the
institutional dynamics and tensions of key parts of the EU social policy
regime. Finally, we argue that EU social policy actors faced with the above
dilemma are now designing a new approach, termed deliberative gover-
nance, which seeks a more comfortable accommodation of the 'national'
and 'European' in the sphere of economic citizenship. It is uncertain
whether this new regime can be made fully sustainable.
combines social rules with open markets and which is worth protecting.
The prolonged and acrimonious battles in the European Council over par-
ticular pieces of labour law cannot be dismissed as relatively minor politi-
cal squabbles. On the whole, they reflect a genuine and continued
commitment on the part of large sections of the administrative and politi-
cal elites in Europe to developing some type of 'third way' capitalism. It is
this commitment that explains why most Member States have shied away
from the American 'deregulated' labour market model. At the same time,
the interpretative framework for Social Europe recognizes that the institu-
tional and political diversity of the Member States places enormous con-
straints on the adoption of policies to harmonize or centralize employment
regulation on an EU basis. Most serious advocates of EU social policy rec-
ognize that such a regime will founder if it is not sensitive to the wide vari-
ations in national institutional circumstances inside the EU.
Second, the emerging body of European labour law has opened up a reg-
ulatory arena for labour market affairs at EU level. Clearly some employ-
ment Directives have had a greater impact on domestic employment
systems than others. Those on health and safety have probably had the
biggest impact, followed by legislation on equality. A distinctive feature of
the EU regulatory arena is that while it does not lay down 'tablets of stone'
for national labour law regimes, it has nevertheless created important
frameworks for the development of domestic employment rules. For
example, Marginson (2000) shows that although the European Works
Council Directive is weak in several important respects it has opened the
door to the Europeanization of national systems of corporate governance.
Third, EU social policy has caused an increase in extra-national forms of
policy collaboration and social mobilization. The Amsterdam Treaty made
the benchmarking of employment and social policies across the EU a legal
obligation. As a result, an essential dimension of national employment policy
formation from now on will be lesson-drawing across the Member States.
The aim is a convergence in the goals of employment policy in the context of
national institutional diversity. A similar but more amorphous process is
emerging in relation to the actions of civil associations in the labour market.
Trade unions when setting bargaining demands have one eye on domestic
circumstances and another on European developments. Equal opportunities
groups across the EU are linking up to find the best way to advance the main-
streaming of gender measures in public administration and enterprise prac-
tice. Thus a dense web of social and policy connections has emerged as a
result of the European integration process, fusing together national admin-
istrative and social structures. A loose association, yet to be fully under-
stood, is unfolding between social learning and liberalization inside the EU:
a political marketplace has emerged alongside the economic one.
But it is important to recognize that the relationship between the insti-
tutional architecture of EU social policy and the European market is far
272 Deliberative Governance and E U Social Policy
Weiler (1999) has argued that the judicial system of the EU, particularly the
workings of the ECJ, has been the key engine behind its political develop-
ment, even maintaining that it has been responsible for the transformation
of Europe. This overstates the role of the EU judicial system in deepening
institutional and economic ties between the Member States; nevertheless it
has played an influential role across a wide range of policy areas, not least
in the labour market sphere. The EU judicial system has advanced inter-
vention in national employment systems in two important ways. One is by
Paul Teague 273
law so that the various tiers of governance with a judicial capacity to inter-
vene in labour market affairs better complement one another.-
Formidable obstacles stand in the way of such a constitutional.ization of
EU social policy. Although the application of national constitutions may
vary, the presumption is that each shares the characteristics of promoting
equal access and that the law is interpreted and enforced within a common
framework of understanding. But are these three attributes- access, inter-
pretation and enforcement - sufficiently developed in the EU judicial
system to support a fully fledged EU social policy constitution? For a stan,
sharply contrasting systems of labour market regulation exist across the
Member States. It is common to classify national legal regimes into three
categories: Roman-Germanic; Anglo-Saxon; and Nordic (Barnard et al.,
1995). In the first, the state has a central and active role in the organization
of the labour market; for instance in almost every case there is a law that
'extends' collective agreements to all workers in the relevant sector. In con-
trast, the Anglo-Saxon system is marked by the relative absence of state
intervention in employment relations; for example, the law does not extend
the coverage of collective agreements to non-unionized workplaces. The
Nordic system lies somewhere between the other two regimes, with com-
prehensive regulation based on voluntary agreement between strong col-
lective organizations, within the framework of a highly developed welfare
state. These national distinctions make it difficult to create a common
European framework for the interpretation and enforcement of labour
market rules.
Other differences reinforce these core distinctions in national law
systems. Thus whereas Germany and the Netherlands use company-based
works councils to reinforce employment rights, in France this function is
largely the responsibility of government labour inspectorates. In some
countries, ordinary courts resolve employment disputes whereas in others
it is the responsibility of specially constituted labour or industrial tri-
bunals; more generally, the frameworks of penalties and compensation
used to encourage compliance with employment laws differ considerably
across the Member States. The use of public agencies to promote and
enforce employment legislation, as with equal opportunities or health and
safety, is yet another arena of unevenness. All these differences in national
labour law traditions and practices make it improbable that an EU social
constitution could be enacted.
Consider the issue of subsidiarity. Included in the Amsterdam Treaty is
a detailed catalogue of procedures to operationalize subsidiarity as a leg-
islative and policy-making instrument. The Commission now has to show
that the Union has the competence to act on a particular matter, explain
why EU intervention is preferable to national action in solving the
problem, and ensure that the envisaged action is proportional or commen-
surate to the problem that is being addressed. It is hard to interpret these
Paul Teague 275
1997). The Commission has made energetic efforts to. overcome these
hurdles; during the Delors years in particular, it encouraged and cajoled the
social partners to enter into meaningful exchanges (Ross,_.1995). The first
moves came with the Val Duchesse talks which started an open-ended dia-
logue between the social partners. Both sides (for different reasons) were
wary of the initiative, but by assuaging anxieties, resolving disputes and
providing administrative back-up, the Commission successfully addressed
their concerns. As a result of this brokerage role, more cooperative and
purposeful relationships now prevail between the social partners.
As guardian of the Union's legal base, the Commission has the author-
ity to bring cases against Member States considered to be in breach of EU
law. Over the years, it has not shunned this responsibility in the social
policy field, having made complaints at the ECJ against every Member
State for failure to implement properly some piece of EU employment law;
the majority of these cases have related to equal opportunities. While
action of this kind shows that the Commission is more than willing to fulfil
its role as guardian, it also serves to highlight its limited resources to
monitor and enforce EU regulation. The Commission is a relatively small
bureaucracy unable to police properly the legal relationships between the
EU and Member States, that are riven with complexity and lack of trans-
parency (Bercusson, 1996 ).
The Commission's use of its 'representative function' on labour market
matters is relatively undocumented. It has the greatest ability to act
autonomously in the area of external trade relationships, as Member States
forfeit the right to negotiate their own international trade deals on joining
the EU. In the 1970s and 1980s, the Commission used this authority to
introduce standards of human rights practices into trading agreements
with non-Member States. For instance the Lome Convention, which gave
countries in Africa and the Caribbean preferential access to the European
market, committed these countries to enacting a range social and human
rights rules. More recently, the Commission has used this representative
function to enter the hot debate about connecting international labour
standards to world trade agreements. For example, it has supported
enabling the World Trade Organization (WTO) to raise concerns about
social standards as part of the regulation of the global trading regime. In
the future this external dimension of EU social policy is likely to increase
in importance as economic liberalization grows apace and other parts of
the world form regional economic blocs to strengthen their status and bar-
gaining position in the international trading system.
Characterizing the overall role of the Commission in EU social policy is
a matter of some dispute, in line with a wider disagreement about its polit-
ical status in the integration process. Pollack (1997) argues that the
Commission has used the various functions delegated to it by the Member
States to carve out a role as a supranational policy entrepreneur with the
Paul Teague 277
The European Council, Court of Justice and Commission are the institu-
tional bulwarks of the EU, yet the dynamics of its social policy cannot be
explained by the activities of these organizations alone. Other factors have
278 Deliberative Governance and E U Social Policy
dynamics are evident not only inside the 'vertical' institutions of the ED· a
unprecedented level of 'horizontal' communication and exchange' ~ 0
employment-related matters occurs across the Member _.Stc:~,tes (Teague
1999b). Much of this activity seeks to make national industrial relation~
systems consistent with deeper political and economic integration inside
the EU. Monetary union is a striking example of this process. Now that the
introduction of the single currency has begun, trade unions are eager to
develop greater coordination of wage determination so that trade unions
from one Member State do not seek to undercut collective agreements that
prevail in other parts of the EU. For the most part, these moves towards
Europe-wide coordination have not involved formalized and hierarchical
institutional rules or the introduction of American-style pattern bargain-
ing. Instead, coordination is decentralized and horizontal. The motivation
is simply to make national collective bargaining institutions compatible
with monetary integration so that trade unions do not lose influence in
Euroland. In choosing the decentralized route to coordination rather than
any other alternative, the trade unions do not appear to have engaged in any
profound strategic evaluation: it is as if the national trade unions converged
on the decentralized option simultaneously. This can be seen as an instance
where the socialization mechanisms of European integration create 'focal
points' around which actors almost spontaneously converge. Thus trade
unions are increasingly engaging in cross-national learning to weave a
European component into their national employment relations strategies.
The general implication is that the socialization influences associated
with European integration are finally altering the behaviour of industrial
relations actors across the EU: the web of vertical and horizontal employ-
ment relations networks spanning the Member States is more dense
and meaningful than ever before. In less tangible terms, the interpretative
or cognitive frameworks of the separate national employment relations are
now much closer to each other. Thus the socialization dynamic to Euro-
pean integration is breaching the sovereignty/supranational dichotomy
that has consistently held back deeper forms of policy coordination across
the Member States (Taylor, 1996). A common understanding appears to
have emerged across the Member States that the important game in town
is to invent structures and arrangements that marry established systems of
national governance with overarching (but not monolithic) EU regulatory
frameworks. This new permissive environment holds out the promise for
richer forms of pan-European collaboration on employment relations
matters.
However, the argument that socialization dynamics associated with
European integration are encouraging cross-jurisdictional learning rests
on a fairly distinctive theoretical perspective of how labour markets work.
The point of departure of this account is that most market situations
exhibit limited information and high transaction costs and that such imper-
Paul Teague 283
Conclusions
The foregoing analysis suggests that the EU lacks the institutional capac-
ity to replicate existing national social systems. It has only sparse compe-
tencies in areas such as fiscal redistribution, health and education, social
benefits, pensions and even central matters relating to the employment
relationship such as pay and industrial action. Because of these limited
competencies, talk of the EU building a Social Europe that effectively
replaces national social systems is fatuous: the institutional design of the
EU always closed off this possibility. At the same time, those accounts that
dismiss Social Europe as a sideshow to the market-making activities of
European integration are either too negative or assess EU social policy
against unrealistic or inappropriate benchmarks. The EU has had an
impact on national labour regimes which may be fragmented and contested
but which nonetheless cannot be discounted. Overall, EU social policy has
evolved in a manner that has raised the prospect of a pan-European form
of economic citizenship but at the same time has neither the institutional
strength nor political legitimacy to deliver on this promise.
In a sense, European integration has created an acute political dilemma
for labour market governance inside the EU. On the one hand, as a result
of the deepening institutional and market interdependencies, it is hard to
see how purely national social systems in Europe can be economically or
institutionally efficient; on the other, the political and institutional foun-
dations are not in place for a fully integrated European model of economic
citizenship. It is unlikely that this dilemma will be addressed by a big polit-
ical 'fix', such as the adoption of a European social constitution or a major
transfer of powers relating to redistribution and regulation from the
national to the European level. Neither the Member States nor the
Commission would support this; instead they have adopted a pragmatic
approach to EU social policy in the face of this political dilemma. Social
284 Deliberative Governance and E U Social Policy
policy has been advanced on a piecemeal basis so that it does not fall foul
of the ever-present political and institutional constraints.
An unintended consequence of this pragmatic approach,, is. that the
design features of what has been termed deliberative governance are
beginning to come into view (Sand, 1998). First, the EU centre, which is
made up of the core decision-making organs and the panoply of sur-
rounding committees and interest groups, has a powerful agenda-setting
capacity. Commission social policy proposals may go through several
burials and resurrections but they tend never to disappear. Directives
passed in the 1990s, for instance on European Works Councils and part-
time employment, have their origins in proposals first made by the
Commission at the start of the 1980s. Through this agenda-setting capac-
ity, the EU is becoming an important 'framing' institution for European
employment relations.
Second, a problem-solving style of policy-making is taking root. This
has a number of interrelated dimensions. One is that discussions between
the social partners at the European-level involve deliberation (preference-
changing behaviour) and planning rather than the straightforward bar-
gaining which is more characteristic of interactions between employers
and trade unions at national level. A distinctive feature of this deliberative
process is reasoned argument in which the social partners find ways to
advance certain matters relating to the organization of the labour market,
even in the absence of an agreed view on how to solve the particular matter
in hand. Deliberation thus enables a procedural consensus to be reached
even when there is disagreement about the substantive issues. A further
benefit of a deliberative process is that it gives rise to credible commitments
through which social partners gain an assurance about each other's behav-
iour. Where credible commitments prevail, opportunistic behaviour is less
likely and trust relations come to the fore. Thus in regard to the European
social dialogue the vision is of the various participants seeking to advance
their own interests by promoting a common agenda that incorporates the
interests and views of others.
Another dimension to problem-solving is the devising of policy packages
that are not heavily prescriptive but open-ended and flexible. In the situa-
tion where there is such diversity in national labour market institutions it
would simply entail policy failure to attempt to over-harmonize employ-
ment rules and regulations. Traditional command-and-control type regula-
tions are also unlikely to succeed as the EU lacks the capacity to monitor
and enforce such one-size-fits-all policies. Thus a major component of
problem-solving in the social policy arena is to accommodate the political
demand for a common or converging industrial relations agenda with the
hard reality of wide variation in national labour market institutions. In this
context, respecting national autonomy through the use of subsidiarity pro-
cedures is not a pretext for pushing 'minimalist' social policies but the only
Paul Teague 285
Note
References
Barnard, C., Clark, J. and Lewis, R. (1995) 'The Exercise of Individual Rights in
the Member States of the European Union', Department of Employment
Research Strategy Paper 0863924492, Sheffield.
Bercusson, B. (1996) European Labour Law, London, Butterworths.
Bercusson, B., Deakin, S., Koistinen, P., Kravaritou, Y., Muckeberger, U., Supiot,
A. and Veneziani, B. (1996) A Manifesto for Social Europe? Brussels: ETUI.
Biagi, M. (1998) 'The Implementation of the Amsterdam Treaty with Regard to
Employment: Co-ordination or Convergence?', International journal of
Comparative Labour Law and Industrial Relations, 14, 4, pp. 325-6.
Carter, C. and Scott, A. (1998) 'Legitimacy and Governance beyond the European
Nation State: Conceptualising Governance in the European Union', European
Law journal, 4, 4, pp. 429-45.
Paul Teague 287
Introduction
5. The Union has today set itself a new strategic goal for the next decade: to
become the most competitive and dynamic knowledge-based economy in the
world, capable of sustainable economic growth with more and better jobs and
greater social cohesion. 1
290 The Open Method of Co-ordination
Four key policies were to be central to this vision, which, if s.uccessful, was
to deliver 20 million jobs by 2010.
• Better policies for the information society and research and develop-
ment (R&D).
• Stepping up the process of structural reform for competitiveness and
innovation.
• Completion of the internal market .
• 'Modernization' of the European social model.
• Applying an appropriate macroeconomic policy mix .
• An employment policy with a goal of full employment in a society
which is more adapted to the personal choices of men and women.
• A Sustainable Development Strategy. 2
sistency, entailed that national policies were to enhance each other's effec-
tiveness. Finally, national government performance was to converge.
Open Method Co-ordination was to provide an institutional frame-
work for securing these values. It was to draw upon the methodologies
that had first been applied to the European Employment Pact: co-ordina-
tion of economic policy and improvement of the interaction between
wage developments and monetary, budget and fiscal policy; improvement
of labour market efficiency; and structural reform of the goods, services
and capital markets. In addition, the method was to be extended to a
number of other fields - the information society, research policy, enter-
prise, education and vocational training, combating social exclusion,
immigration policy, and sustainable development. 4 The institutional
frameworks that were to govern these areas were to be marked by the fol-
lowing features:
The fixing of pan-Union guidelines Guidelines and targets will be set for
each policy sector in which OMC is applied with specific timetables to be set
for achieving the goals which they set in the short, medium and long terms.
• delivery of the Lisbon goals depended upon a 3 per cent growth rate,
which has proved problematic in the economic climate since
September 11th;
• it is early days for most areas of OMC; the Commission was still in the
process of formulating draft guidelines;
• progress in some areas, notably structural reform of capital markets -
the so-called Cardiff Process- was being held back by a failure to agree
legislation at the EC level.
build on these. Thus the SDS is really a redescription of the Sixth Actio
Plan, in that it does not carry any of the features that distinguish OM~
from it, notably feedback and review of national policies. ,.
The fourth category contains the OMCs against poverty and social
exclusion and those on pensions. A series of objectives have been set.These
are, however, very broad. They include facilitating participation in
employment and access to all resources; preventing the risks of exclusion·
helping the most vulnerable; and mobilizing the relevant bodies. Whil;
indicators have been established, no quantitative targets or benchmarks are
set. Instead, there is merely a requirement that Member States develop
national action plans in these areas. 8
Fifthly, there are a number of areas which are subject to wide-scale bench-
marking. These include e-learning, investment in education, early school-
leavers, graduates in mathematics, science and technology, upper secondary
education attainment and participation in lifelong learning. In such cases,
there is no strategy as such. Rather international excellence and the average
of the three cbest performing' states are set as a standard of excellence. 9
Finally, there is one other area, immigration, 10 where proposals for
OMC have been made, but there has been little further development.
[ ... ]
Notes
From a paper for the ESRC Centre for Analysis of Risk and Regulation, London
School of Economics and Political Science, 2003.
Presidency Conclusions (Lisbon European Council), Council of the
European Union, SN 100/00,23-24 Mar. 2000 (emphasis added).
2 This Strategy was introduced not at Lisbon but at the Goteborg European
Council, 15 June 2001.
3 At www.europa.eu.int/comm/lisbon_strategy/index_en.html (accessed 16
June 2003).
4 This was added by the Goteborg European Council, 15 June 2001.
5 Conclusions of the Presidency of the European Council, 15 and 16 Mar. 2002;
para. 39.
6 For the latest, see Decision 2002/549/EC on the broad guidelines of the eco-
nomic policies of the Member States and the Community, OJ 2002, L 182/1.
7 Regulation 1466/97, OJ 1997, L 209/1.
8 The most recent outlines are contained in a Communication from the Social
Protection Committee to the Committee of Permanent Representatives
296 The Open Method of Co-ordination
(COREPER) on 25 Nov. 2002, Doc 14164/02, Rev 1. EC Commission, 'Joint
Report from the Council and the Commission on Adequate and Sustainable
Pensions', 17 Dec. 2002.
9 For analysis of these see EC Commission, 'European Beilchmarks in
Education and Training', COM (2002) 629 final.
10 EC Commission, 'Proposal for Open Method Co-ordination on
Immigration', COM (2001) 387.
References
The population of the whole world is getting older and the whole world,
sooner or later, will have to manage the consequences. This is happening
because birth rates have declined, or are declining, almost everywhere, and
additionally because older people are surviving to enjoy longer lives. In
most richer countries, birth and death rates started to decline in the nine-
teenth century or earlier. In the case of Japan, this transition has been par-
ticularly rapid and did not begin until the twentieth century. In the poorer
countries of the world, rapid declines in birth and death rates have only
emerged in the last few decades and in a few the process has not begun. But
most demographers believe that eventually the whole world will have few
children, but long lives.
When death rates first fell, population started to grow fast. The world
increased from 2 to 6 billion people in 100 years, and in the process acquired
a newly youthful population with its attendant burdens of dependency.
Now as populations mature, we are leaving that behind, the rich countries
much sooner than the poor ones. We exchange youthful dependants for
elderly ones. If the decline in family size halted so that women continued
to have about two children on average (which most women say they want)
then with current death rates the proportion of persons aged 65 and over in
richer countries would eventually remain constant at about 20 per cent of
the total (with 19 per cent aged 15 and under) compared with about 15 per
cent at present. Such a population would eventually remain constant in size.
With fertility at no more than the 'replacement' rate of just over two
children, population, and the size of the workforce, will eventually cease
to grow and would remain constant in size except for the contri-
bution from continued decline in death rates. With fertility below this
David Coleman 299
channels of support will also be different. Families, which .made and still
make the greatest provision for children, will see the burden of transfers
eased except in those richer countries where family support i:s traditionally
more important for the elderly, notably southern Europe and Japan. A higher
proportion of transfers to the elderly will pass through the state. Those pop-
ulations which also have a tradition of family care for the elderly wiil suffer
most unless they can change their system (Ermisch and Ogawa, 1994).
rates cannot have a further enhancing effect once they have reached their
maximum level, beyond say 2020.
The most effective measures would relate to retirement age. ~!hile formal
retirement age is 65 in most EU states, actual retirement age is about 58 or
59. Preservation of today's actual support ratio would require the actual
retirement age to rise by between five and six years, to between 65 and 66.
On that basis, managing the additional costs of elderly dependency simply
requires people to stop work when they are 'expected' to, at some time in
the future. For the UK itself, the scenarios indicate that an annual increase
in work productivity rising to 0.8 per cent by 2025 would be needed to cover
additional costs of pensions transfers, in the absence of any other measures.
The incorporation of all dependency (all those not working of all ages,
including children) into the equation further ameliorates the expectation of
future dependency and future costs. All these measures together could
restore the future position to about the current level in most European
countries at least up to 2020, according to an analysis published in the
Economic Survey of the United Nations Economic Commission for
Europe in 1999 (UNECE, 1999).
Demographic Measures
play only a modest role. Some studies have found evidence only for a weak
effect of welfare and fiscal changes on family size and the pattern of family
formation (Gauthier and Hatzius, 1997). Others report somev,rhat stronger
effects. In the early 1980s French pronatalist measures were estimated to
add about 0.3 to the average family size. The Swedish case in particular is
claimed to be an example of precise, if temporary, response of marriage and
birth rates and intervals to changes in relative financial advantage, includ-
ing the fertility downturn following more recent welfare retrenchment and
raised unemployment (Hoem, 2000). It is noteworthy that the only devel-
oped countries in the world with relatively high birth rates are those which·
also have high levels of childbearing outside marriage.
Family subsidies of various kinds, state child care, preferential access to
housing in the absence of an open housing market and other measures in
the former Communist countries of Eastern Europe attempted simultane-
ously to promote female workforce participation and the birth rate.
Although these policies are often dismissed as having had no more than a
transient effect, they appear to have maintained fertility there at close to
replacement level until their withdrawal during the post-1990 transition
period (UNECE, 1999b ). However, these policies operated in a system of
universally early marriage, limited access to modern contraception and few
social outlets as alternatives to family life.
Elsewhere in the industrial world, there may be tenacious cultural imped-
iments to the development of higher birth rates. Theories of 'gender equity'
suggest that very low birth rates arise from unbalanced equality for women
(McDonald, 2000). If law, state subsidies and cultural preferences allow
women some freedom to engage in work and higher education, but still load
them unfairly with expectations to care for children, older relatives and the
house by themselves, their time and energies will be so squeezed that child-
bearing will be very delayed and minimized. Paradoxically, this is likely to
happen in societies with a traditional 'familist' culture which considers the
care of the elderly to be a family matter, resists state interference and con-
signs women to unequal domestic roles in which men play little part. The
low level of fertility in the familist southern European countries, and in
Japan, seems unlikely to be reversed without a broader shift in personal and
political culture, as well as fiscal measures to support the family and help
women to combine work and child care. Societies with high gender inequal-
ity will continue to suffer lower birth rates.
Conclusion
In conclusion, a substantial level of population ageing is here to stay. The
'easy' option of encouraging more immigration to address population
ageing is demographically ineffective. It would be a short-term measure
which enables hard but necessary decisions to be evaded and would bring
serious cultural, social and political difficulties and economic costs.
Excessive population ageing can be avoided if excessively low birth rates
are avoided. Prudent administrative measures, of the kind noted above,
should go hand in hand with policies to make the workplace and the tax
and welfare systems more favourable to women, so they can fulfil ambi-
tions, consistently stated in surveys, to have more than one child. But in
some low-fertility countries, cultural changes in gender equity in the
home, difficult for government to influence, will be essential. In differ-
ent ways, the US and the Scandinavian countries have shown the way,
not for the sake of demographic engineering but to promote equity.
Look after women's interests, it may be said, and population will look
after itself.
Note
References
What Friedmann and Havighurst were referring to was the fact that retire-
ment is a product of the industrial revolution. Older people before that his-
toric economic event were not 'retired' people, and there was no retirement
role. A big part of the dramatic growth in economic productivity arising
from the industrial revolution was a change in the terms of employment-
resulting in increased leisure. This increase was particularly marked during
a period towards the end of life that became known as 'retirement'.
However, not all workers retired. A few avoided this new opportunity
to leave the labour force. Writing about the retirement decision in his book
Chronicles of Wasted Time, Malcolm Muggeridge (1973) observes: 'Few
men of action have been able to make a graceful exit at the appropriate
time.' While retirement has been avoided over the years by 'men of action'
(a few statespeople and many self-employed farmers and professionals),
that is not the interesting part of this historic transformation. Of more
importance is the fact that most people do not avoid retirement, do not
want to, and in fact retire as soon as it is economically feasible. Any list of
the most significant developments of the twentieth century should include
the dramatic decline in male older worker participation rates over that
century and the sharp rise in leisure that went with it.
310 The Evolving Concept of 'Retirement'
in the years 2030-50 than it was during the 1950-70 period - assuming a
relatively high rate of economic growth. 1
Bow many years will the future aged be able to spend in retirement? The
answer depends fundamentally on the growth of economic output relative
to the size of the labour force. The potential impact of demographic ageing
on growth has been a major issue for decades in the debate about the roles
of public and private pensions. Economists today are virtually unanimous
in stressing the need to increase national saving in order to promote eco-
nomic growth. This emphasis on saving results in part from a long tradi-
tion in economics. Both traditional neoclassical growth theory and more
recent growth theory give major attention to the role of saving. Economist
Robert A. Blecker (1997) points out: 'Since the late 1970s, mainstream
macroeconomics has been dominated by a conservative policy consensus,
which emphasizes raising national saving rates and avoiding government
intervention in financial or labor markets.' But there is a growing literature
(discussed in Barr, 2000; Schulz, 1999) that questions this emphasis, espe-
cially in connection with pension policy. Recent research suggests that
increasing private saving, other factors unchanged, does little to raise
private investment. In fact, econometric analysis by Gordon (1995)
strongly supports the view of some economists that investment generates
saving, not v1ce versa.
Moreover, there is not just one factor (saving) or two (saving and
investment) that are the key determinants of economic growth. While
saving and investment are necessary, they are not sufficient to ensure the
rate of growth will be adequate to achieve any specified set of goals. There
are many other factors that are important- probably more so. These would
include the rate of technological change, the willingness of producers to
take risks, management organizational and human resource skills, the
extent of entrepreneurial drive, and the quality of education and training
given to young and old entrants into the labour force.
Therefore, we are left with two conclusions: first, that economic growth
is the product of many factors- not just saving and investment in physical
capital; and, second, that economic growth is the key to leisure and the
primary determinant of potential future leisure.
[ ... ]
[W]ith the approaching retirement of the 'baby boomers' and the conse-
quent demographic ageing, there arise new concerns about retirement
policy. As William Jackson (1998) points out: 'A new policy question has
312 The Evolving Concept of 'Retirement'
If health care expenditures for the elderly continue to grow rapidly ... and if
the ability to finance these expenditures by transfers from the young reaches
its limit, the only alternative is for the elderly to pick up a large share of the
bill. If these payments must come from incomes that grow at only a modest
pace, the elderly will become increasingly 'health care poor' .... To prevent
more and more elderly becoming 'health care poor', they must have addi-
tional personal income. They need more income from savings (including pen-
sions and investments) and from earnings, which means they will have to
work more both before and after age 65.
But is this feasible based on what we know about past practice and current
attitudes? Employers may not need, or be inclined to hire, older workers.
Moreover, older people may not want the new jobs, even if they are
offered. Without dramatic changes in the ability of countries to moderate
business cycles and keep unemployment low over the long run, there may
be little change in current provisions that encourage retirement and 'early
retirement'. I think that, as in the past, we can expect employers, unions,
politicians, and workers themselves to continue supporting mechanisms
that encourage older workers to retire at increasingly early ages during
periods when unemployment is high.
The issue is further complicated by attitudes of older workers towards
work and training. As they grow older, most workers become very choosy
James H. Schulz 313
abilities die hard. Many older workers and most employers truly believe
that productivity almost always declines with age and, as the old saying
goes, 'old dogs cannot learn new tricks'. Moreover, work ,.environments
may remain very rigid with regard to making adjustments to job require-
ments and remuneration patterns -making it nearly impossible to easily
match older workers with existing employment opportunities.
Clearly, there is a need for major changes in employer and union atti-
tudes/practices regarding the training and employment of individuals over
the life cycle. As the rate at which young people enter the labour force
slows in coming years, businesses will be forced to rethink how they will
get the labour necessary for producing their products and services.
However, the outcome of that rethinking is not as predictable as some
writers suggest. Firms can respond to demographic changes in the avail-
ability of labour in a number of ways; recruiting and hiring different
types of workers (such as older workers) is only one of many ways.
Alternatively, firms can invest in more physical capital that reduces labour
needs; or encourage liberalization of immigration policies favouring
applicants with needed skills; or encourage more women with children to
stay in the labour force by, for example, offering daycare facilities; or shift
production processes to developing countries with large labour surpluses
and cheap wages.
As a consequence, the new demographic profile evolving in industrialized
countries does not necessarily mean there will be serious labour shortages in
the future. Nor does it mean that all older workers will find that it is much
easier to obtain suitable re-employment after losing or shifting jobs.
Hopefully, however, the new demographics do provide an opportunity to
devise and promote better policies and programmes for a more efficient use
of potential labour force participants. Raising the size and productivity of
the labour force through human resource policies is a major alternative to
current calls by some for cutbacks in retirement benefits for the old.
Thus, the biggest 'retirement issue' of the new century is likely to be
whether both workers and employers see the need and are willing to
modify the retirement 'right'. Will it be changed to include what each group
sees as viable work options in later life to complement the retirement life
everyone now expects and almost all enjoy?
Productive Ageing
In recent years, a number of gerontologists have sought to promote an ana-
lytical framework that emphasizes the fact that almost all individuals are
engaged in productive activities throughout most of their lives, including
the retirement period. 2 The concept of 'productive ageing' has developed
in part as a reaction to the limited view of work as defined by economists
James H. Schulz 315
and the resulting structure of the national income and product accounts
which measure the aggregate economic output of the nation. Given present
practices, many of the activities and contributions made after (and some
before) retirement are not counted in official statistical reckonings of
national economic activity.
The productive ageing framework accepts the economic paradigm that
focuses on activities that have 'value'. But it seeks to expand the definition
of economically valuable activities beyond those whose value is determined
by economic markets. Herzog and Morgan (1992), for example, argue that
government 'social reporting efforts aimed at monitoring productivity and
how it might change as a function of the age of the person are biased by the
way productivity is operationalized in most available social statistics'.
In general, the proposed approach to deal with these limitations is to
include both traditional market and non-market economic activities that
result in the production of goods and services. Bass, Caro and Chen (1993),
in the introduction to their edited book on productive ageing, expand this
view by adding to their definition of productive ageing activities that
develop the capacity to produce goods and services.
But as Bass, Caro and Chen point out, even with this change, most def-
initions of productive ageing would exclude 'many important and con-
structive activities undertaken by the elderly. They exclude, for example,
such activities as reflection, worshiping, meditation, reminiscing, reading
for pleasure, carrying on correspondence, visiting with family and friends,
traveling, and so forth'. Given these exclusions, and others, not everyone
agrees with an approach that focuses a discussion of roles in later life
almost solely on older persons' economic activities and potential.
A different approach is one that seeks to escape from the economic para-
digm and looks at the later years of life in primarily non-economic terms.
Philosopher Harry Moody (1993) strongly criticizes the productive ageing
concept. He argues that:
By insisting on the productivity of the old, we put the last stage of life at the
same level as the other stages. This transposition implicitly sets up a kind of
competition or struggle (who can be the most productive?) which the old are
doomed to lose as frailty increases. By celebrating efficiency, productivity or
power, we subordinate any more claim for the last stage of life in favor of
values that ultimately depreciate with meaning of old age.
We are now ready to draw from the above discussion some of the proba-
ble characteristics of retirement in future years. As the World Health
Organization has recently stated in a discussion paper for the Second UN
World Assembly on Ageing:
It is time for a new paradigm, one that views older people as active partici-
pants in an age-integrated society and as active contributors ... [The paradigm
should challenge] the traditional view that learning is the business of children
and youth, work is the business of midlife, and retirement is the business of
old age. (WHO, n.d.)
Attitudes towards retirement in the future are likely to move sharply away
from the simplistic view of all work before retirement and no work after.
Some of the resulting changes we can expect to see arc as follows.
50
Q.)
OJ)
40
('$
~
Q.)
u 30
1.<
Q.)
0...
20
10
0
Age 55-59 Age 60-64 Age 65-69 Age 70+
60
50
Q.) 40
OJ)
('$
~
Q.)
u 30
1.<
Q.)
0-.
20
10
0
Age 55-59 Age 60-64 Age 65-69 Age 70+
since 1993, French employees have been entitled to take phased early retire-
ment between the ages of 55 and 65. Early retirement schemes with the princi-
pal aim of creating jobs were introduced on an experimental basis in France in
1996, covering both the public and private sectors (House of Commons, 1999).
sures to work 'to survive', we can expect to see a growth in volunteer work
and community and family assistance and involvement, and a rising concern
about the environment and the quality of life. Older people in the coming
decades will not just sit in their rocking chairs and watch television. They
will continue to be active but with a new combination of leisure and work
activities- new forms of what might be called 'citizen participation'.
30
25
...
V)
Q)
...0
....!<::
20
~
.........
0 15
J= 10
~
5
0
1950 1960 1970 1980 1990 2000
robotics -are seen as creating a surplus of workers. Many people argue that
nations should recognize the reality of 'surplus labour' and spread the avail~
able work around, creating shorter work weeks and earJier retirement.
Given the seemingly unlimited desire of people for old and new products
and services, economists argue that this view is erroneous - that scarce
resources (including labour) will never be sufficient to keep up with
growing demand. But the idea of labour surplus as a result of technological
revolutions remains strong among many non-economists. In such a world
of labour surplus, there would seem to be no need for workers to be
retrained, especially as they get older- and also given that there often seems
to be no shortage of workers when unemployment is high.
Second, even if a need for labour develops, the view is often that older
workers are not as likely to be suitable for the new jobs. This is because it
is believed that work performance declines with age. However, this view is
not so much the result of research and fact as it is of prejudice and igno~
ranee. To the extent that there has been research, it in large part contradicts
the prevailing views of employers. Regarding performance, Sterns and
McDaniel (1994) point out that
an extensive body of research indicates that age and job performance are by
no means highly correlated. If performance does anything with age, it
improves slightly, but the relationship is very weak. This is true regardless of
whether performance is measured by supervisory ratings or through other
more objective productivity measurements.
The biggest pressure is likely to come from workers themselves. Over the
past couple of decades, job insecurity has risen dramatically among workers
at later ages (when job security has traditionally been the highest) and among
white-collar workers (again, where job security has historically been rela-
tively high). Many workers have been unable or unwilling to retire as a result
of 'downsizing', mergers, employment shifts triggered by global competi-
tion, and other results of the new world economic situation. They have had
to take what have come to be called 'bridge jobs'- transitional jobs between
their prior 'regular' jobs and retirement. Often these jobs are less desirable,
given the barriers to 'regular' employment for workers at older ages.
If this bridging phenomenon continues, we can expect workers, and
perhaps their unions, to pressure governments and employers to provide
retraining. Many governments currently give huge tax subsidies to encour-
age people to save for retirement and to retire early but give very little in
the way of incentives for them to seek out the education and training they
need to work longer. Likewise, every country spends huge sums of money
on its educational institutions, but those expenditures are almost exclu-
sively for younger people. We can expect to see that imbalance in govern-
ment resources changed as older workers demand better job opportunities
when forced to leave regular employment before retirement.
Notes
From International Social Security Review, 55, 1, 2002, pp. 85-105.
The basic projections were carried out using a real growth rate of 3.0 per cent.
Sensitivity testing was then carried out using lower and higher rates, demon-
James H. Schulz 323
strating that the burden is very sensitive to the growth rate but not as sensitive
to assumptions with regard to either population growth or labour force par-
ticipation rates.
2 This section is based on material appearing in Schulz (2001).
References
Schulz, J. (1990) 'What can Japan Teach us about an Aging US Work Force)'
Challenge (Nov.-Dec.). . ·'
Schulz, J. (1999) 'Saving, Growth, and Social Security: Fighting our Children over
Shares of the Future Economic Pie?', in R. Butler, L. Grossman ;{nd M. Oberlink
(eds), Life in an Older America, New York, Century Foundation Press.
Schulz, J. (2001) 'Productive Aging - An Economist's View', in N. Morrow-
Howell, J. Hinterlong and M. Sherraden (eds), Productive Aging: Concepts and
Challenges, Baltimore, Johns Hopkins University Press.
Schulz,]., Borowski, A. and Crown, W. (1991) Economics of Population Aging: The
'Graying' of Australia, Japan, and the United States, Westport, CT, Auburn
House.
Siegenthaler, J. and Brenner, A. (2000) 'Flexible Work Schedules, Older Workers,
and Retirement', journal of Aging and Social Policy, 12, 1.
Sterns, H. and McDaniel, M. (1994) 'Job Performance and the Older Worker', in
S. Rix (ed.), Older Workers: How do they Measure Up? Washington DC, Public
Policy Institute, American Association of Retired Persons.
WHO (n.d.) 'Health and Ageing: A Discussion Paper' (1st version), World Health
Organization, Department of Health Promotion, Geneva.
The Global Retiretnent Crisis
Richard]ackson
[ ... J
'Demography is destiny,' demographer Richard Easterlin famously
observed. When it comes to public budgets, it certainly is. Rising longevity
and falling fertility translate directly into a lower ratio of taxpaying
workers to retired beneficiaries, and this in turn translates into a higher
cost rate for retirement programmes.
[ ... J
[In 2001] the European Commission (EC) and the OECD published long-
term projections of the impact of global aging on public budgets.
According to these 'official' numbers, spending on public pensions in the
typical developed country will grow by 4.4 per cent of GDP by 2050, or
from 8.8 to 13.2 per cent of GDP. This represents a 50 per cent increase-
and it may be a serious underestimate.
The official projections, in fact, rest on a remarkably optimistic set of
assumptions about future economic and demographic developments. They
assume that unemployment rates in most countries will fall, that labour
force participation rates will rise, and that fertility will rebound back
towards the replacement level. All of these developments increase the pro-
jected size of the workforce and tax base, and hence decrease the projected
pension cost rate. The projections also assume that the historical rate of
improvement in longevity will slow. Although this is bad news for people
personally, it is good news for government budgets.
[ ... ]
326 The Global Retirement Crisis
To assess the potential magnitude of the ageing challenge> the Center for
Strategic and International Studies' Global Aging Initiative has developed
an alternative projection (see CSIS, 2002). The CSIS projectipn ?egins with
the official projections, but adjusts key assumptions to more closely reflect
historical trends. It assumes that unemployment will continue at its 1990s
level, that women's work patterns will not change (except to aaow for
cohort effects), that fertility will remain constant, and that longevity will
grow at its historical pace.
Pension spending under the CSIS 'historical trends' projection grow~ by
7.0 per cent of GDP between now and 2050 in the typical developed
country, or from 8.8 to 15.8 per cent of GDP (figure 1). This is nearly 3 per-
centage points more than under the official projections - and it is just the
average. In some countries, the difference is much more dramatic. In Italy,
CSIS projects that pension spending will grow by 4.2 per cent of GDP
(rather than 0.3 per cent); in Japan, by 9.6 per cent (rather than 6.3 per cent);
and in Spain by 15.8 per cent (rather than 7.9 per cent).
16 15.8%
13.2%
12
~
a(j
'-+-<
0
Q)
M 8
~
EQ)
u
I-<
Q)
~
4 8.8o/o 8.8% 8.8%
?fl
-=T
~
20
?fl
Ui
0
0
a'
00
lo 2ooo • 2o5o I r--.:
16
~
Q
0 12
'-1-<
0
Q)
OJ:)
(";$
c;
Q) 8
u
1-<
Q)
~
0
UK us Canada Japan Italy Germany France
Figure 2 Behind the averages: the size of the projected pension burden varies
greatly among the developed countries (spending on public pensions, as a
percentage of GDP; developed country (unweighted) average for 2000 and
official and CSIS projections for 2050)
Source: ECIOECD, 2001, and CSIS, 2002.
328 The Global Retirement Crisis
the developed countries, each elder on average consumes three to five times
more health care than a younger adult. Moreover, the older. elders are, the
more costly their care becomes. In the United States, the ov;,era_ll per capita
ratio of public health care spending on the 'old old' aged 85 and over to
spending on the 'young old' aged 65 to 74 is roughly 3 to 1; for nursing
home care, the ratio is roughly 20 to 1.
What makes these differentials so ominous is that it is precisely the pop-
ulation of old old that will be growing the fastest. The UN projects that
the number of elderly aged 65 to 74 in the developed world will grow by
roughly 50 per cent between now and 2050, while the number aged 85 and
over will grow by nearly 300 per cent (figure 3). Today, just one out of ten
elders in the developed world is 85 or older. By mid-century, the 'ageing of
the aged' will push this share up to one out of five.
These demographic multipliers threaten to interact explosively with the
rising trend in healthcare costs. Due mostly to the introduction and diffu-
sion of new technologies, per capita public healthcare spending in the
developed countries has grown 1.2 percentage points faster than per capita
GDP over the past thirty years. The official projections assume that in the
future per capita spending will grow no faster than per capita GDP. Even
so, the EC and OECD project that public health benefits for the elderly
will grow by an average of 2.5 per cent of GDP over the next fifty years,
or from 2.1 per cent of GDP today to 4.6 per cent by 2050.
300
273%
c:
.2 250
~
""3
0...
0
0...
200
.::
v
bJ)
c: 150
~
...c:u
vbJ)
~ 100
=
v
u
1-.
v 50
0...
0
Age 65-74 Age 75-84 Age 85 & over
Figure 3 The 'old old' will be the fastest growing age group (percentage change
in the elderly population of the developed world from 2000 to 2050, by elderly
age group: UN projection)
Source: UN, 2001.
Richard Jackson 329
24 23.4%
20
17.8%
16
0...
Q 7.0%
0
._
0
<1.1
OJ) 12
ro
=
<1.1
u
~
<1.1
0...
8
In the United States, according to the Urban Institute, the typical single
male retiring in 1960 earned a return of 11.0 per cent on his Social Security
payroll taxes; the typical single male retiring in 1980 earned a return of
4.2 per cent (Steuerle and Bakija, 1994). The same worker retiring today can
expect a return of just 1.6 per cent. By the time today's college graduates
retire, the return will be 1.1 per cent- one-third what they could earn by
investing their payroll taxes in risk-free Treasury bonds (figure 5).
For a long time, the advantages of universal pay-as-you-go pensions-
social solidarity, poverty relief, and 'windfall returns'- seemed to outweigh
Richard Jackson 331
20
18
~ 16
~
e 14
~ 12
0
~
r: 10
-;;;
;:l
c::
c::
<II
~ 6
r:
~"'
2
Note
Short extract from chapter 1, 'Behind the Projections', of The Global Retirement
Crisis, Washington, DC, Center for Strategic and International Studies, 2002.
References
CSIS (2002) The Global Retirement Crisis, Washington, DC, Center for Strategic
and International Studies.
EC/OECD (2001) 'Budgetary Challenges Posed by Ageing Populations: The
Impact of Public Spending on Pensions, Health and Long-Term Care for the
Elderly', Economic Policy Committee, EC; and 'Fiscal Implications of Ageing:
Projections of Age-Related Spending', Economics Department Working Papers
no. 305, OECD.
Employee Benefit Research Institute (2000) The 2000 Retirement Confidence
Survey, Washington, DC, Employee Benefit Research Institute.
Steuerle, C. E. and Bakija, J. M. (1994) Retooling Social Security for the Twenty-
First Century, Washington, DC, Urban Institute.
Technical Review Panel (2000) Review of Assumptions and Methods of the
Medicare Trustees' Financial Projections, Washington, DC, Technical Review
Panel on the Medicare Trustees' Reports.
UN (2001) World Population Prospects: The 2000 Revision, New York, United
Nations.
Vanston, N. (2000) 'Maintaining Prosperity', Washington Quarterly (Summer).
Gender Equity in Theories of
Fertility Transition
Peter McDonald
Mason has employed the concept of the gender system, which she defines
as 'the socially constructed expectations for male and female behaviour
that are found (in variable form) in every known human society. A gender
system's expectations prescribe a division of labour and responsibilities
between women and men and grant different rights and obligations to
334 Gender Equity in Theories of Fertility Transition
'A mother with a train of children after her is one of the most admirable and
lovely Sights in the visible Creation of God,' declared Benjamin Colman as he
introduced the text of his sermon 'Fruitful Mothers in Israel' to his
Boston congregation. In 1715 the Old Testament injunction 'Be fruitful and
multiply', which Colman proceeded to discuss, was familiar to his listeners,
and his interpretation of the text was representative of American thought on
the purpose of marriage and on women's ordained part as childbearer.
(Scholten 1985, p. 8)
Individual-oriented
. s
. d instituuon
'\y-onente
fatn 1
Time
individual voting rights, not family voting rights. However, the progress to
this situation has passed through a period in which rights and freedoms
were extended to individual men, but not to individual women. Effectively,
prior to the twentieth century, men exercised the democratic rights of
women. Women were educated to the level that would fit them to be suit-
able wives to the husbands whom they were expected to marry. Education
for women was not directed towards future employment in the paid labour
force. By the late nineteenth century, a woman was expected to eschew
paid employment unless she was single or could not rely upon the earnings
of her husband. 6 Thus, individual-oriented institutions were male institu-
tions and, as such, they promoted and protected the male-breadwinner
model of the family. A relatively high level of gender equity was a charac-
teristic of women in their family role only.
Women in the West have gradually gained rights also within individual-
oriented institutions. The early successes were in the domains of property
rights and voting rights. Rights in education grew gradually over a long
period of time to the point of broad equality with men today. Rights of
women in market employment have risen dramatically in the past few
decades. Generally women's remuneration now tends to be guided by the
principle of equal pay for equal work and, at least at the non-managerial
level, women are now able to compete equitably with men in the labour
market. Cumulatively, these changes represent radical or revolutionary
change.
Peter McDonald 343
At the same time, progress towards gender equity within the family and
hence in family-oriented institutions has continued to advance very slowly.
While, as argued in the previous section, the change within the family has
been sufficient to allow women to have extensive control over their fertil-
ity, it has not provided other forms of equity within the family. Full gender
equity would be achieved only if gender were not a determinant of which
member of the couple undertook the three forms of family work: income
generation, caring and nurturing, and household maintenance. In mar-
riages, women remain the predominant providers of care and continue to
carry most of the burden of household maintenance. Gender stratification
continues to prevail within the contemporary Western family. The same is
true in the East Asian developed economies that also now experience low
fertility.
Conclusion
The apparent contradiction stated at the beginning of this article has been
addressed through distinguishing two broad forms of gender equity: gender
equity in family-oriented institutions and gender equity in individual-
oriented institutions. I have argued that the fertility transition from high to
344 Gender Equity in Theories of Fertility Transition
low levels has been associated mainly with improving gender equity within
family-oriented social institutions, indeed almost exclusively within the
family itself. The fall in fertility is associated with women acquiring rights
within the family that enable them to reduce the number of their births to
more desirable levels. However, change in the institution of the family pro-
ceeds slowly because the family system is strongly linked to conservative
institutions such as religion. The link is the reification of family as defined
by an idealized family morality.
During the twentieth century, a revolution took place in levels of gender
equity in individual-oriented institutions in advanced countries. Starting
from a point where women had a subordinate status in individual institu-
tions such as formal education and market employment, the century ended
with very high levels of gender equity prevailing in these institutions. High
levels of equity enjoyed by women as individuals in combination with con-
tinuing low levels of equity for women in their roles as wives or mothers
mean that many women will end up bearing fewer children than they
aspired to when they were younger. The outcome for the society is a very
low fertility rate.
The achievement of gender equity in individual-oriented institutions
will not be reversed. But in a context of persistent relatively low gender
equity in family-oriented institutions, high gender equity in individual-
oriented institutions results in very low fertility. The idea is conceptual-
ized in figure 1. Very low fertility rates will persist unless gender equity
within family-oriented institutions rises to much higher levels than prevail
today. In a context of high gender equity in individual-oriented institu-
tions, higher gender equity in family-oriented institutions will tend to
raise fertility.
Notes
References
income from the welfare state.' 7 With these massive programmes have
come dense interest-group networks and strong popular attachments to
particular policies, which present considerable obstacles to re{Drm. To take
one prominent example, by the late 1980s the American Association of
Retired People (AARP) had a membership of 28 million and a staff of 1,300
(including a legislative staff of more than 100). 8 The maturation of the
welfare state fundamentally transforms the nature of interest-group pol-
itics. In short, the emergence of powerful groups surrounding social pro-
grammes may make the welfare state less dependent on the political parties,
social movements, and labour organizations that expanded social pro-
grammes in the first place. Nor is the context altered simply because
welfare states create their own constituencies. The structures of social pro-
grammes may also have implications for the decision rules governing
policy change (for example, whether national officials need the acquies-
cence of local ones) and for how visible cutbacks will be. 'Policy feedback'
from earlier rounds of welfare state development is likely to be a prom-
inent feature of retrenchment politics. 9
In short, the shift in goals and context creates a new politics. This new
politics, marked by pressures to avoid blame for unpopular policies, dic-
tates new political strategies. 10 Retrenchment advocates will try to play off
one group of beneficiaries against another and develop reforms that com-
pensate politically crucial groups for lost benefits. Those favouring cut-
backs will attempt to lower the visibility of reforms, either by making the
effects of policies more difficult to detect or by making it hard for voters
to trace responsibility for these effects back to particular policy makers. 11
Wherever possible, policy makers will seek broad consensus on reform in
order to spread the blame. Whether these efforts succeed may depend very
much on the structure of policies already in place.
[ ... ]
a 1989.
aProjection.
Source: OECD, Economic Outlook (December 1993), table A23.
a 1989.
1979 1990 1979-90 1979 1990 1979-90 1979 1990 1979-90 1979 1989 1979-89
Total 44.9 43.2 -1.7 49.9 45.8 -4.1 63.2 61.4 -1.8 33.2 36.9 +3.6
Public goodsb 9.5 9.7 +0.1 10.0 9.2 -0.8 10.5 8.8 -1.7 8.2 9.3 +1.1
Merit goods 13.6 12.2 -1.4 12.3 10.9 -1.4 15.9 13.4 -2.6 6.1 6.0 -0.1
Education 5.5 5.0 -0.5 5.2 4.2 -1.0 6.6 5.6 -1.0 4.7 4.7 -0.0
Healthc 4.8 5.1 +0.3 6.3 6.0 -0.3 8.1 6.9 -1.1 0.9 0.9 -0.0
Housing and other 3.4 2.1 -1.2 0.8 0.7 -0.1 1.2 0.8 -0.4 0.5 0.4 -0.1
Income trans. 12.5 13.4 +0.9 20.2 18.5 -1.7 24.6 26.8 +2.2 11.2 11.9 +0.7
Pensions 6.7 6.5 -0.2 12.7 11.2 -1.5 11.0 11.5 +0.4 6.9 7.0 +0.1
Sickness 0.4 0.3 -0.1 0.8 0.7 -0.1 3.4 4.5 +1.2 0.1 0.2 +0.1
Family allowance 1.7 1.6 -0.0 1.2 0.8 -0.4 1.6 1.3 -0.3 0.4 0.4 -0.0
Unemployment 0.7 0.6 -0.1 0.9 1.3 +0.4 0.4 0.5 +0.1 0.4 0.3 -0.1
Other income
supports 0.1 0.8 +0.7 1.3 1.6 +0.3 0.1 0.2 +0.1 0.0 0.0 0.0
Admin. and other
spending 1.4 1.6 +0.3 2.6 2.4 -0.2 4.9 5.2 +0.3 0.6 0.6 -0.0
Add. transfer 1.4 1.8 +0.5 0.5 0.4 -0.1 3.2 3.7 +0.6 2.7 3.5 +0.8
a Numbers may not sum to total due to rounding.
b Defence and other public services.
c For the US, social security related to health spending is included under 'Additional transfers' below.
[ ... ]
Notes
Introduction
these countries are more difficult to change than others. As far as France is
concerned, Giuliano Bonoli and myself have shown that some of the pecu-
liar_ities of the French social policy-making sys_tem help tc. ex;plain why
maJor retrenchm~nt has not occurred. I~ pa_rucular, these are a highly
popular but particularly fragmented soc1al msurance system which is
largely financed by social contributions; numerous divided trade unions
who are particularly eager on keeping their position in the system becaus~
of their weakness in industrial relations; and a central state which is rela-
tively weak in this field and thus obliged to negotiate with the other social
protection actors (Bonoli and Palier, 1998, 2000).
There might therefore have to be a twofold agenda in comparative welfare
state research. On the one hand, we should be able to identify more changes
than are usually recognized. On the other, we should be able to understand
why continental welfare states are more resistant to change, or at least change
differently, than other welfare states. For this, I suggest that we need to draw
on and combine public policy analysis and the role of welfare institutions in
order to develop and arrive at a more adequate framework of analysis.
With reference to my previous work (Bonoli and Palier, 1998, 2000;
Palier, 2000, 2001) and in line with that of others (for instance, Visser and
Hemerijck, 1997), I would argue that current research on welfare state
changes should go beyond the notion of retrenchment so as to be able to
embrace the different kinds of developments which have occurred. Recent
European welfare states changes should be analysed by differentiating
between both different periods of time and different types of changes
introduced by governments. Some reforms may prove to enforce conti-
nuity, some others may prove to introduce a new logic in the welfare
system. In contrast to the general notion of retrenchment, reforms do not
always imply less welfare state. Inspired by general public policy analysis,
in this chapter a specific analytic framework is proposed which empha-
sizes the role of welfare institutions, and distinguishes three types of
changes. This framework has been influenced by some dissatisfaction with
current research on welfare state changes and in particular with four
aspects: the notion of retrenchment, the concept of path dependency,
institutionalist approaches of reform, and the analysis of change. Taking
each of these four issues in turn, I will conclude with putting forward a
proposal for an analytic framework to study recent (and future) social
policy changes.
Beyond Retrenchment
there are three paths for welfare state changes. Scharpf and Schmidt (2000)
convincingly show that the three worlds do not have the same kind of vul-
nerabilities in the face of the new global and European environment.
Examining the implementation of several policies, Pierson proposes that in
each world a specific type of reform is predominantly pursued: commodifi-
cation in the liberal welfare states, cutbacks in the Nordic countries and
recalibration of the Continental systems (Pierson, 2001 b).
Very convincingly these analyses provide us with a much better under-
standing of what is going on than others which simply focus on curtail-
ments. They demonstrate that there are (broadly three) different ways of
reforming welfare states and that differences between the welfare regimes
explain difference in reforms implemented. However, they still frame their
approach in terms of retrenchment or adaptation, as if there has been,
within a single country, only one single trend of reform over the last
twenty-five years. Clearly, as Visser and Hemerijck (1997) claimed for the
Netherlands, there is a need to differentiate between different kinds of
reforms within the same country (or welfare regime). Governments have
not always implemented the same recipes. They did not display the same
behaviour in the late 1970s as during the 1980s or during the 1990s. There
is a need for an analytical framework for studying reforms which allows
differentiation between countries, but, in accordance with the type or
period of reform, also within countries.
Usually, recent comparative studies have concluded that reforms had a
limited impact on the structure of the different welfare states, not threaten-
ing but preserving the very nature of each system. In fact, reforms are seen
as merely reinforcing the logic of each welfare system. Due to the different
processes of marketization of their social policies, liberal welfare states have
become even more residual and liberal. The social democratic welfare states,
thanks to an egalitarian distribution of cuts (around 10 per cent across all
benefits) and a rediscovery of the workline, have returned to their traditional
road to welfare (Kuhnle, 2000a). Also most of the continental welfare states
have remained the same, not only because reforms have reinforced their
characteristics but also because of an apparent inability to implement any
substantial reform (giving rise to terms such as 'eurosclerosis or 'frozen
Fordism'). In short, it seems that fundamental structures of welfare states
have remained to a large extent unaltered. The (neo-institutionalist) path
dependence approach often leads to the conclusion of prevailing continuity.
or against welfare reforms. In part they also determine who is and who is
not participating in the political game which leads to reforms. Depending
on how these different variables are set, different patterns of support and
opposition can be encountered. In general, one may expect these variables
to influence the politics of social programmes in the following ways.
Mode of access As it delimits the beneficiaries and thus the likely sup-
porters of a scheme, this factor is crucial for shaping the politics of a given
social programme. The mode of access also relates to the objectives of a
programme, i.e. income maintenance, poverty alleviation or equality. As a
result, support for a scheme might come from groups with an ideological
orientation congenial to one of these objectives. Generally, left-wing
parties have tended towards equality, Christian-Democrats have sup-
ported income maintenance and liberal parties have been keener to allevi-
ate poverty (Esping-Andersen, 1990, p. 53).
Financing mechanisms While related to the two previous factors, this vari-
able has some significance in its own right. If the mode of access delineates
the beneficiaries of a programme, the financing mechanism determines who
is paying for it. The political support for a financing mechanism is likely to
be stronger if those who pay for a programme are also those who receive the
benefit. The looser the link between benefit and payment, the less legitimate
the financing mechanism becomes. As a result, there is a crucial difference
between tax- and contribution-financed schemes in their ability to attract
public support. Whereas taxation goes to the state, social contributions are
perceived as a 'deferred wage' which will return to the insured person at
366 Beyond Retrenchment
Actors who manage the system This dimension determines the account-
ability and legitimacy of different actors. The more the state controls a
system and its generosity, the more the political class is likely to be held
responsible for any changes. When benefits are increased, the government is
credited; when benefits are reduced, it will be blamed (Pierson, 1996). When
management is shared with trade unions and employers, responsibility tends
to be diluted, thus diminishing the state capacity to control the development
of the social protection system, and particularly levels of expenditure. This
variable also determines the range of actors which are regarded as legitim-
ately participating in welfare reform debates. In a state controlled system the
debate is confined to political parties. When the management is handed to
the social partners, their participation in the debate is legitimized. In the
latter case also trade unions are seen as important actors in social policy-
making, and widely regarded as defending the current system against
retrenching governments. This institutional setting gives rise to tensions
over controlling social security between governments on the one hand -
often regardless of political persuasion - and trade unions on the other.
Union involvement in the management of social security grants unions a
de facto veto power against welfare state reforms (Bonoli and Palier, 1996).
used to attain those goals, and the precise settings of these instruments ... '.
According to this approach, it is possible to recast our understanding of
welfare regimes in terms of public policies. The instrume9-ts .of social
policy are mainly the four institutional variables mentioned above (the
mode of access, the benefit structure, financing mechanisms and manage-
ment arrangements).
The 'overarching goals' can be related to the three different political logics
which are associated with three welfare state regimes (Esping-Andersen,
1990): the centrality of the market in the allocation of resources and resid-
ual state intervention in the liberal regime; the centrality of equality, citi-
zenship and 'harmonization' of the population in the social-democratic
welfare regime; and the centrality of work, status and occupational identity
in conservative-corporatist social insurance systems.
If the above regimes are interpreted as ideal-types rather than precise
descriptions of specific realities, three major combinations of these prin-
ciples, logics and institutional instruments can be derived from the classic
typology. These three combinations can be seen as three different reper-
toires of social policies which are more or less salient in any one specific
social protection system. [ ... ]
While these kinds of categories cannot pretend to describe the reality of
any specific social protection system either in its entirety or in detail
(because no social protection system would be this consistent, and all
combine different logics and instruments to some extent), they are never-
theless useful for the comparative analysis of a specific programme. Each
social protection programme is close to one of three goals and presents a spe-
cific setting of the four institutional dimensions. Therefore, these categories
represent indicators against which changes can be located. In identifying the
specific characteristics of a programme (i.e. its goal and the specific combi-
nation of the four institutional variables) before and after a reform, objec-
tive criteria for assessing changes will have been established. For example,
did the reform only lower benefit levels, or did it introduce new modes of
access or new rules of calculation- or did the reform set new goals? In other
words, it is possible to assess whether a reform did change one or several of
the institutional dimensions, and whether it implied a change in the goals.
We can identify three distinct kinds of changes in policy ... First, [a change
of] the levels (or settings) of the basic instruments. We can call the process
Bruno Palier 369
whereby instrument settings are changed in the light of experience and new
knowledge, while the overall goals and instruments of policy remain the same,
a process of first order change in policy ... When the instruments of policy
as well as their settings are altered in response to past experience even though
the overall goals of policy remain the same, [changes] might be said to reflect
a process of second order change ... Simultaneous changes in all three com-
ponents of policy: the instrument settings, the instruments themselves, and
the hierarchy of goals behind policy ... occur rarely, but when they do occur
as a result of reflection on past experience, we can describe them as instances
of third order change. (Hall, 1993, pp. 278-9)
Conclusion
apparently remaine? all but untouc~ed ~n terms of their own logic and
main features. The lmk, often seen as mev1table, between path dependency
and continuity needs to be questioned. [ ... ] Explaining continuities
usually relies on references to the impact of institutions. However, while
institutions shape the particular context in which problems, interests and
solution are framed, apart from the role played by political institutions,
those of the welfare state created by social policy legacies (both as inde-
pendent and dependent variables) need to be acknowledged more.
Emphasizing continuity rarely takes account of public policies, which can
have an important impact on welfare state structures. Finally, there is a
need for a better differentiation between types of reforms: some reinforce
rhe pattern of a particular system, others introduce structural change. In
order to identify the different kinds of reforms, one has to assess whether
they merely imply a change in the settings of given instruments, a change
of instruments, or a change in both the instruments and in the goals.
With these analytical tools, we will be able to identify more adequately
social policy changes which occurred in the recent past and will continue
to occur. The analytical framework put forward here confirms that
Continental welfare states are more difficult to reform than others.
Reference to the impact of welfare states' institutions help us to understand
why this is the case. For example, contributory benefits enjoy a particu-
larly high level of legitimacy and are therefore difficult to cut back radi-
cally. Transfers are 'paid' for by social contributions, workers assume that
they have 'bought' social rights, and benefits are usually generous. In this
sense their loss would be more significant than the reduction of a benefit
which is already at a low level. Finally, insurance-based transfers are well
defended by organized interests, and in particular by trade unions of dif-
ferent branches corresponding to the different professional schemes.
However, this framework of analysis also helps us to realize that
structural, paradigmatic changes have occurred, and particularly in
Bismarckian countries. In order to cope with structural problems (regard-
ing benefit financing, entitlements and capacities for change), these coun-
tries have created new benefit programmes according to new logics
(means-tested benefits, privately funded schemes in pension and health
systems), they have developed new modes of financing, partly replacing
social contributions, and are implementing new management arrange-
ments (privatization of some administrative tasks, empowerment of the
state at the expense of the social partners). These changes are the result of
a process of policy learning. They have been (or will be) implemented very
gradually. Probably because of their marginal scope and because of the fact
that they do not directly affect the level of expenditure, few analyses have
concentrated on them compared with the more common analyses of
welfare state change (and especially of Continental welfare systems)
which tend to emphasize path dependency and continuity. However, the
372 Beyond Retrenchment
Notes
From Jochen Clasen (ed.), What Future for Social Security? Debates and Reforms
in National and Cross-National Perspective, The Hague, Kluwer Law
International, 2003, pp. 105-20. Earlier versions of this chapter were presented at
the University of Stirling, the University of Tokyo, the Max Planck Institut in
Cologne and to Fellows at Harvard University, Center for European Studies.
The author wishes to thank all the commentators from earlier presentations of this
paper, and particularly Olli Kangas, Mari Miura, Fritz Scharpf, Peter Hall and
Rosemary Taylor for their very useful comments.
'The 1980s were not a time of simple retrenchment. Under the condition
where neither federal nor state government was obliged to pay the welfare bill,
the door was open for increased benefits or expanded entitlements' (Manow
and Seils, 2000, p. 279).
2 An increasing number of scholars are using this framework of analysis for
understanding social policy reforms (see for instance Visser and Hemerijck
(1997) or Hinrichs (2000)).
3 Myles and Quadagno (1997) illustrate this. Within pension systems, a tran-
sition from a defined benefit to a defined contribution scheme implies a
change in the mode of pension benefit from deferred wages to savings, for
instance.
4 The social insurance system came to be accused of partly causing some eco-
nomic, social and political problems through three broad mechanisms: the
weight of social contributions preventing job creation; the contributory
nature of most social benefits reinforcing social exclusion; and the joint man-
agement of the system by social partners engendering irresponsibility and a
management crisis of the system.
References
Bichot, Jacques (1997) Les Politiques sociales en France au 20eme siecle, Paris,
Armand Colin.
Bonoli, Giuliano (2000) The Politics of Pension Reform: Institutions and Policy
Change in Western Europe, Cambridge, Cambridge University Press.
Bonoli, Giuliano (2001) 'Political Institutions, Veto Points, and the Process of
Welfare State Adaptation', in P. Pierson (ed.), The New Politics of the Welfare
State, Oxford, Oxford University Press, pp. 314-37.
Bonoli, Giuliano and Palier, Bruno (1996) 'Reclaiming Welfare: The Politics of
Social Protection Reform in France', in M. Rhodes (ed.), Southern European
Welfare States, London, Frank Cass, pp. 240-59.
Bonoli, Giuliano and Palier, Bruno (1998) 'Changing the Politics of Social
Programmes: Innovative Change in British and French Welfare Reforms',
journal of European Social Policy, 8, 4, pp. 317-30.
Bruno Palier 373
Bonoli, Giuliano and Palier, Bruno (2000) 'How Do Welfare States Change?
Institutions and their Impact on the Politics of Welfare State Reform', European
Review, 8, 2, pp. 333-52.
Esping-Andersen, G0sta (1990) The Three Worlds of Welfare Capitalism,
Cambridge, Polity.
Esping-Andersen, G0sta (ed.) (1996) Welfare States in Transition: National
Adaptations in Global Economies, London, Sage.
Ferrera, Maurizio (1996) 'Modeles de solidarite, divergences, convergences.
Perspectives pour l'Europe', Swiss Political Science Review, 2, 1, pp. 55-72.
Ferrera, Maurizio and Rhodes, Martin (eds) (2000) Recasting European Welfare
States, Special Issue of West European Politics, 23, 2.
Gaxie, Daniel et al. (1990), Le 'Social' transfigure, Paris, PUF.
George, Vic and Taylor-Gooby, Peter (eds) (1996) European Welfare Policy:
Squaring the Welfare Circle, London, Macmillan.
Hall, Peter (1993) 'Policy Paradigm, Social Learning and the State, the Case of
Economic Policy in Britain', Comparative Politics, April, pp. 275-96.
Hinrichs, Karl (2000) 'Ageing and Public Pension Reforms in Western Europe and
North America: Patterns and Politics', paper presented at the conference What
Future for Social Security? Cross-National and Multidisciplinary Perspectives,
organized in Stirling by J ochen Clasen, 15-17 June.
Huber, Evelyne and Stephens, John D. (2001) Political Choice in Global Markets:
Development and Crisis of Advanced Welfare States, Chicago, University of
Chicago Press.
Join-Lambert, Marie-Therese (1997) Politiques sociales, 2nd edn, Paris, Dalloz.
Kuhnle, Stein (2000a) 'The Scandinavian Welfare State in the 1990's: Challenged but
Viable', in M. Ferrera and M. Rhodes (eds), Recasting European Welfare States,
Special Issue of 23, 2, West European Politics, pp. 209-28.
Kuhnle, S. (ed.) (2000b) Survival of the European Welfare State, London,
Routledge.
Leibfried, Stephan (1993) 'Toward a European Welfare State?', in Catherine Jones
(ed.), New Perspectives on the Welfare State in Europe, London, Routledge,
pp. 133-56.
Leibfried, Stephan (ed.) (2000) 'Welfare State Futures', European Review, 8, 2.
Levy, Jonah (1999) 'Vice into Virtue? Progressive Politics of Welfare Reform in
Continental Europe', Politics and Society, 27, pp. 239-73.
Levy, Jonah (2000) 'France: Directing Adjustment?', in F. W. Scharpf and V. A.
Schmidt (eds), From Vulnerability to Competitiveness, Oxford, Oxford
University Press, vol. 2, pp. 308-50.
Manow, Philip and Seils, Eric (2000) 'Adjusting Badly: The German Welfare State,
Structural Change and the Open Economy', in F. W. Scharpf and V. A. Schmidt
(eds), From Vulnerability to Competitiveness, Oxford, Oxford University Press,
vol. 2, pp. 264-307.
Myles, John and Pierson, Paul (2001) 'The Comparative Political Economy of
Pension Reform', in P. Pierson (ed.), The New Politics of The Welfare State,
Oxford, Oxford University Press.
Myles, John and Quadagno, Jill (1997) 'Recent Trends in Public Pension Reform:
A Comparative View', in K. Banting and R. Boadway (eds), Reform of
Retirement Income Policy: International and Canadian Perspectives, Kingston,
Ontario, Queen's University, School of Policy Studies, pp. 247-72.
Palier, Bruno (2000) '"Defrosting" the French Welfare State', in M. Ferrera and
M. Rhodes (eds), Recasting European Welfare States, special issue of West
European Politics, 23, 2, p. 113-36.
374 Beyond Retrenchment
Palier, Bruno (2001) 'Reshaping the Social Policy Making Framework: France from
the 1980's to 2000', in P. Taylor-Gooby (ed.), Welfare States under Pressure,
London, Sage.
Pierson, Paul (1994) Dismantling the Welfare State? Reagan, Thatcher and the
Politics of Retrenchment, Cambridge, Cambridge University Press.
Pierson, Paul (1996) 'The New Politics of the Welfare State', World Politics, 48, 1,
pp. 143-79.
Pierson, Paul (1998) 'Irresistible Forces, Immovable Objects: Post-industrial
Welfare States Confront Permanent Austerity', Journal of European Public
Policy, 5, 4.
Pierson, P. (ed.) (2001a) The New Politics of the Welfare State, Oxford, Oxford
University Press.
Pierson, P. (2001 b) 'Coping with Permanent Austerity: Welfare State Restructuring
in Affluent Democracies', in P. Pierson (ed.), The New Politics of the Welfare
State, Oxford, Oxford University Press.
Ross, Fiona (2000) 'Interests and Choice in the "Not Quite So New" Politics of
Welfare', West European Politics, 23, 2, pp. 11-34.
Scharpf, Fritz W. and Schmidt, Vivien A. (eds) (2000) From Vulnerability to
Competiveness: Welfare and Work in the Open Economy, 2 vols, Oxford, Oxford
University Press.
Visser,Jelle and Hemerijck, Anton (1997) 'A Dutch Miracle':]ob Growth, Welfare
Reform and Corporatism in the Netherlands, Amsterdam, Amsterdam
University Press.
Part III
The Futures of Welfare
Part III on the futures of welfare is comparatively short and is more specu-
lative than those that have gone before. In it, we bring together a number
of authors thinking about the 'coming' welfare state. We begin with a short
selection from the work of Anthony Giddens. As director of the London
School of Economics and thinker-in-residence to Britain's New Labour
government especially during its agenda-setting first term, Giddens's
thinking on welfare was extraordinarily influential. Drawing on his wider
articulation of a 'Third Way', Giddens here discusses the ways in which
welfare institutions might be remade in a radically changed social and eco-
nomic environment to underpin a new form of 'positive welfare' within an
'active welfare state' built on the shifting terrain of the new context set by
'reflexive modernity'. This is followed by a much longer piece in which
Giuliano Bonoli considers the emergence of 'new social risks' and consid-
ers their impact on the emergence of a 'politics of the new social policies'.
The 'new' social risks- reconciling work and family life, coping with single
parenthood, dealing with obsolescent skills in mid-career, working outside
the formal economy (and its world of welfare)- pose new challenges for
both citizens and policy-makers. Bonoli considers the ways in which these
issues may be addressed. Finally in this first of the concluding sections, we
include Nick Ellison's discussion of welfare theory 'beyond universalism
and particularism'. Universality - of provision and of citizenship - has
traditionally been seen by its architects (or perhaps, social democratic the-
orists of the welfare state) as one of the key virtues of the modern welfare
state. And yet in recent years these claims to universalism have been
increasingly challenged by those who have seen the logic of universalism
as repressing 'difference' and speaking of and to a privileged majority.
Ellison attempts to think his way around the dualism of 'universalism
versus difference', favouring decentralized and 'deliberative' conceptions
376 The Futures of Welfare
of the politics of the social and a greater role for the 'politics- of presence',
as ways of recasting a social politics that can embrace the virtues of both
difference and universality.
The final section contains three more programmatic papers. In 'A
Welfare State for the Twenty-First Century', G0sta Esping-Andersen pre-
sents his blueprint for a new welfare regime which is up to all of the chal-
lenges (social, economic and political) that social policy at the start of the
new millennium must meet. His emphasis is on the requirements of a
'social investment state', with a special focus on children and families, life-
time learning, lifelong outcomes and 'life chance guarantees rather than
here-and-now equality of all'. Ruth Lister sounds a cautionary note about
the parameters and policy implications of the 'social investment state'
favoured both by Esping-Andersen and the social policy-makers of New
Labour. She is especially concerned that the focus has come to rely so
heavily on the iconic status of children as 'citizen-workers of the future' to
the neglect of issues of equality and 'child-citizens' in the here and now. In
a final, very short but incisive contribution, Philippe van Parijs sketches his
ingenious plan to respond to the current crisis of welfare ('the first mar-
riage of justice and efficiency') by jettisoning most of the existing appara-
tus of the (income transfer) welfare state in favour of a guaranteed Basic
Income for every citizen. Even for those who doubt the political practicab-
ility of Van Parijs's solution, it is a fascinating and challenging proposal
which has provoked a wide-ranging and ongoing debate.
A New World of Welfare
Positive Welfare
Anthony Giddens
[ ... ]
Positive Welfare
No issue has polarized left and right more profoundly in recent years
than the welfare state, extolled on the one side and excoriated on the
other. What became 'the welfare state' (a term not in widespread use until
the 1960s and one William Beveridge, the architect of the British welfare
state, thoroughly disliked) has in fact a chequered history. Its origins were
far removed from the ideals of the left- indeed it was created partly to
dispel the socialist menace. The ruling groups who set up the social insur-
ance system in imperial Germany in the late nineteenth century despised
laissez-faire economics as much as they did socialism. Yet Bismarck's
model was copied by many countries. Beveridge visited Germany in 1907
in order to study the model. 1 The welfare state as it exists today in
Europe was produced in and by war, as were so many aspects of national
citizenship.
The system Bismarck created in Germany is usually taken as the classic
form of the welfare state. Yet the welfare state in Germany has always had
a complex network of third sector groups and associations that the author-
ities have depended on for putting welfare policies into practice. The aim
is to help these to attain their social objectives. In areas such as child care,
third sector groups have almost a monopoly on provision. The non-profit
sector in Germany expanded rather than shrank as the welfare state grew.
Welfare states vary in the degree to which they incorporate or rely upon
the third sector. In Holland, for instance, non-profit organizations are the
main delivery system for social services, while in Sweden hardly any are
Anthony Giddens 379
used. In Belgium and Austria, as in Germany, about half the social services
are provided by non-profit groups.
The Dutch political scientist Kees van Kersbergen argues that 'one of the
major insights of the contemporary debate [about the welfare state] is that
to equate social democracy and the welfare state may have been a mistake?
He examines in detail the influence of Christian democracy upon the devel-
opment of continental welfare systems and the social market. The Christian
democratic parties descend from the Catholic parties that were important
between the wars in Germany, Holland, Austria and to a lesser degree
France and Italy. The Catholic unionists saw socialism as the enemy and
sought to outflank it on its own ground by stressing co-determination and
class reconciliation. Ronald Reagan's view, expressed in 1981, that 'we have
let government take away those things that were once ours to do voluntar-
ily' finds a much earlier echo in Europe in the Catholic tradition. Church,
family and friends are the main sources of social solidarity. The state should
step in only when those institutions don't fully live up to their obligations.
Recognizing the problematic history of the welfare state, third way poli-
tics should accept some of the criticisms the right makes of that state. It is
essentially undemocratic, depending as it does upon a top-down distribu-
tion of benefits. Its motive force is protection and care, but it does not give
enough space to personal liberty. Some forms of welfare institution are
bureaucratic, alienating and inefficient, and welfare benefits can create per-
verse consequences that undermine what they were designed to achieve.
However, third way politics sees these problems not as a signal to disman-
tle the welfare state, but as part of the reason to reconstruct it.
The difficulties of the welfare state are only partly financial. In most
Western societies, proportional expenditure on welfare systems has
remained quite stable (since the late 1980s]. In the UK, the share of GDP
spent on the welfare state increased steadily for most of the century up to
the late 1970s. Since then it has stabilized, 3 although the gross figures
conceal changes in the distribution of spending and the sources of revenue.
The resilience of welfare budgets in the UK is all the more remarkable
given the determination of Margaret Thatcher's governments to cut them.
Expenditure on education as a percentage of GDP fell between 1975 and
1995 from 6.7 per cent to 5.2 per cent. Spending on the health service,
however, rose over this period. In 1975 it was equivalent to 3.8 per cent of
GDP. By 1995 it had risen to 5.7 per cent (a lower percentage than in most
other industrial countries). Public housing experienced the greatest cut,
declining from 4.2 per cent of GDP in 1975 to 2.1 per cent twenty years
later. As happened elsewhere, spending on social security increased most.
In 1973-4 it made up 8.2 per cent of GDP. This reached 11.4 per cent by
1995-6. Expenditure on social security went up by more than 100 per cent
in real terms over the period. The main factors underlying the increase
were high unemployment, a growth in the numbers of in-work poor, and
380 Positive Welfare
systems, for example, have met with concerted resistance. We should have
our pensions because we are 'old' (at age sixty or sixty-five), we have paid
our dues (even if they don't cover the costs), other people before have had
them, everyone looks forward to retirement and so forth. Yet such institu-
tional stasis is in and of itself a reflection of the need for reform, for the
welfare state needs to be as dynamic and responsive to wider social trends
as any other sector of government.
Welfare reform isn't easy to achieve, precisely because of the entrenched
interests that welfare systems create. Yet the outline of a radical project for
the welfare state can be sketched out quite readily.
The welfare state, as indicated earlier, is a pooling of risk rather than
resources. What has shaped the solidarity of social policy is that 'otherwise
privileged groups discovered that they shared a common interest in reallo-
cating risk with the disadvantaged'. 5 However, the welfare state isn't geared
up to cover new-style risks such as those concerning technological change,
social exclusion or the accelerating proportion of one-parent households.
These mismatches are of two kinds: where risks covered don't fit with
needs, and where the wrong groups are protected.
Welfare reform should recognize the points about risk made earlier in
the discussion: effective risk management (individual or collective) doesn't
just mean minimizing or protecting against risks; it also means harnessing
the positive or energetic side of risk and providing resources for risk
taking. Active risk taking is recognized as inherent in entrepreneurial activ-
ity, but the same applies to the labour force. Deciding to go to work and
give up benefits, or taking a job in a particular industry, are risk-infused
activities- but such risk taking is often beneficial both to the individual and
to the wider society.
When Beveridge wrote his Report on Social Insurance and Allied
Services, in 1942, he famously declared war on Want, Disease, Ignorance,
Squalor and Idleness. In other words, his focus was almost entirely nega-
tive. We should speak today of positive welfare, to which individuals them-
selves and other agencies besides government contribute - and which is
functional for wealth creation. Welfare is not in essence an economic
concept, but a psychic one, concerning as it does well-being. Economic
benefits or advantages are therefore virtually never enough on their own
to create it. Not only is welfare generated by many contexts and influences
other than the welfare state, but welfare institutions must be concerned
with fostering psychological as well as economic benefits. Quite mundane
examples can be given: counselling, for example, might sometimes be more
helpful than direct economic support.
Although these propositions may sound remote from the down-to-
earth concerns of welfare systems, there isn't a single area of welfare reform
to which they aren't relevant or which they don't help illuminate. The
guideline is investment in human capital wherever possible, rather than the
382 Positive Welfare
Since the institutions and services ordinarily grouped together under the
rubric of the welfare state are so many, I shall limit myself here to com-
ments on social security. What would the social investment state aim for in
terms of its social security systems? Let us take two basic areas: provision
for old age and unemployment.
As regards old age, a radical perspective would suggest breaking out of
the confines within which debate about pension payments is ordinarily
carried on. Most industrial societies have ageing populations, and this is a
big problem, it is said, because of the pensions time bomb. The pension
commitments of some countries, such as Italy, Germany or Japan, are way
beyond what can be afforded, even allowing for reasonable economic
growth. If other societies, such as Britain, have to some extent avoided this
difficulty, it is because they have actively reduced their state pension com-
mitments- in Britain, for example, by indexing pensions to average prices
rather than average earnings.
An adequate level of state-provided pension is a necessity. There is good
reason also to support schemes of compulsory saving. In the UK the effect
of relating pension increases to prices rather than earnings, without other
statutory provisions, is likely to leave many retirees impoverished. A man
who is fifty in 1998 and leaves the labour market aged sixty-five will receive
a government pension amounting to only 10 per cent of average male earn-
ings. Many people don't have either occupational or private pensions. 6
Other countries have come up with more effective strategies. A number of
examples of combined public/private sector funding of pensions exist,
some of which are capable of generalization. The Finnish system,
for example, combines a state-guaranteed basic minimum income and
earnings-related pension with regulated private sector provision.
The interest of the pensions issue, however, stretches more broadly than
the questions of who should pay, at what level and by what means.
Anthony Giddens 383
It should go along with rethinking what old age is and how changes in the
wider society affect the position of older people. Positive welfare applies
as much in this context as in any other: it isn't enough to think only in
terms of economic benefits. Old age is a new-style risk masquerading as an
old-style one. Ageing used to be more passive than it is now: the ageing
body was simply something that had to be accepted. In the more active,
reflexive society, ageing has become much more of an open process, on a
physical as well as a psychic level. Becoming older presents at least as many
opportu~ities as problems, both for individuals and for the wider social
commumty.
The concept of a pension that begins at retirement age, and the label
'pensioner', were inventions of the welfare state. But not only do these not
conform to the new realities of ageing, they are as clear a case of welfare
dependency as one can find. They suggest incapacity, and it is not surpris-
ing that for many people retirement leads to a loss of self-esteem. When
retirement first fixed 'old age' at sixty or sixty-five, the situation of older
people was very different from what it is now. In 1900, average life
expectancy for a male aged twenty in England was only sixty-two.
We should move towards abolishing the fixed age of retirement, and we
should regard older people as a resource rather than a problem. The cat-
egory of pensioner will then cease to exist, because it is detachable from
pensions as such: it makes no sense to lock up pension funds against reach-
ing 'pensionable age'. People should be able to use such funds as they wish
-not only to leave the labour force at any age, but to finance education, or
reduced working hours, when bringing up young children. 7 Abolishing
statutory retirement would probably be neutral in respect of labour market
implications, given that individuals could give up work earlier as well as
stay in work longer. These provisions won't as such help pay for pensions
where a country has overstretched its future commitments, and this per-
spective is agnostic about what balance should be aimed for between public
and private funding. Yet it does suggest there is scope for innovative think-
ing around the pensions issue.
A society that separates older people from the majority in a retirement
ghetto cannot be called inclusive. The precept of philosophic conservatism
applies here as elsewhere: old age shouldn't be seen as a time of rights
without responsibilities. Burke famously observed that 'society is a part-
nership not only between those who are living, but between those who are
living, those who are dead and those who are to be born'. 8 Such a partner-
ship is presumed, in a relatively mundane context, by the very idea of col-
lective pensions, which act as a conduit between generations. But an
intergenerational contract plainly needs to be deeper than this. The young
should be willing to look to the old for models, and older people should
see themselves as in the service of future generations. 9 Are such goals real-
istic in a society that has retreated from deference, and where age no longer
384 Positive Welfare
appears to bring wisdom? Several factors suggest they may be. Being 'old'
lasts longer than it used to do. There are far more old people in the popu~
~ation and he.nce the old are more soc~ally visible. Final:ly, their growing
mvolvement m wo~k and the commumty should act to lmk them directly
to younger generatwns.
The position of the frail elderly, people who need continuous care, raises
more difficult questions. There are twenty times more people over eighty~
five in the UK today than there were in 1900. Many of the 'young old' may
be in quite a different situation from that of those in the same age group a
couple of generations ago. It is a different matter for the 'old old', some of
whom fare badly. 10 The question of what collective resources should be
made available to the frail elderly is not just one of rationing. There are
issues to be confronted here, including ethical questions of a quite funda~
mental sort, that go well beyond the scope of this discussion.
What of unemployment? Does the goal of full employment mean any-
thing any more? Is there a straight trade-off, as the neo-liberals say,
between employment and deregulated labour markets- contrasting the US
'jobs miracle' with Eurosclerosis? We should note first of all that no simple
comparison between the 'US' and the 'European model' is possible. As
economist Stephen Nickell has shown, labour markets in Europe show
great diversity. Over the period from 1983 to 1996, there were large vari-
ations in unemployment rates in OECD Europe, ranging from 1.8 per cent
in Switzerland to over 20 per cent in Spain. Of OECD countries, 30 per
cent over these years had average unemployment rates lower than the US.
Those with the lowest rates are not noted for having the most deregulated
labour markets (Austria, Portugal, Norway). Labour market rigidities like
strict employment legislation don't strongly influence unemployment.
High unemployment is linked to generous benefits that run on indefinitely
and to poor educational standards at the lower end of the labour market-
the phenomenon of exclusion. 11
The position of the third way should be that sweeping deregulation is
not the answer. Welfare expenditure should remain at European rather
than US levels, but be switched as far as possible towards human capital
investment. Benefit systems should be reformed where they induce moral
hazard, and a more active risk-taking attitude encouraged, wherever pos-
sible through incentives, but where necessary by legal obligations.
It is worth perhaps at this stage commenting briefly on the 'Dutch
model', sometimes pointed to as a successful adaptation of social democ-
racy to new social and economic conditions. In an agreement concluded at
Wassenaar some sixteen years ago, the country's unions agreed to wage
moderation in exchange for a gradual reduction in working hours. As a
result, labour costs have fallen by over 30 per cent [since 1988], while the
economy has thrived. This has been achieved with an unemployment rate
below 6 per cent in 1997.
Anthony Giddens 385
Looked at more closely, however, the Dutch model is less impressive, at
least in terms of job creation and welfare reform. Substantial numbers who
would in other countries count as unemployed are living on disability
bene:6t- the country in fact has more people registered as un:6t for work
than it has of:6cially unemployed. At 51 per cent, the proportion of the
population aged between :fifteen and sixty-four in full-time work is below
what it was in 1970, when it was nearly 60 per cent and well short of the
European average of 67 per cent. Of jobs created [since 1988], 90 per cent
are part-time. Holland spends the highest proportion of its income on
social security of any European country, and its welfare system is under
considerable strain. 12
Strategies for job creation and the future of work need to be based upon
an orientation to the new economic exigencies. Companies and consumers
are increasingly operating on a world scale in terms of the standards
demanded for goods and services. Consumers shop on a world level, in the
sense that distribution is global and therefore 'the best' no longer has any
generic connection with where goods and services are produced. Pressures
to meet these standards will also apply more and more to labour forces. In
some contexts such pressures are likely to deepen processes of social exclu-
sion. The differentiation will be not only between manual and knowledge
workers, or between high skills and low skills, but between those who are
local in outlook and those who are more cosmopolitan.
Investment in human resources is proving to be the main source of lever-
age which firms have in key economic sectors. One study in the US com-
pared 700 large companies across different industries. The results showed
that even a marginal difference in an index of investment in people
increased shareholder returns by $41,000. 13 The business analyst Rosa beth
Moss Kanter identi:6es :five main areas where government policy can assist
job creation. There should be support for entrepreneurial initiatives con-
cerned with small business startups and technological innovation. Many
countries, particularly in Europe, still place too much reliance upon estab-
lished economic institutions, including the public sector, to produce
employment. In a world 'where customers can literally shop for workers',
without the new ideas guaranteed by entrepreneurship there is an absence
of competition. Entrepreneurship is a direct source of jobs. It also drives
technological development, and gives people opportunities for self-
employment in times of transition. Government policy can provide direct
support for entrepreneurship, through helping create venture capital, but
also through restructuring welfare systems to give security when entre-
preneurial ventures go wrong - for example, by giving people the option
to be taxed on a two- or three-year cycle rather than only annually.
Governments need to emphasize lifelong education, developing educa-
tion programmes that start from an individual's early years and continue
on even late in life. Although training in speci:6c skills may be necessary
386 Positive Welfare
Notes
From The Third Way, Cambridge, Polity Press, 1998, pp. 111-28.
1 Nicholas Timmins, The Five Giants, London, Fontana, 1996, p. 12.
2 Kees van Kersbergen, Social Capitalism, London, Routledge, 1995, p. 7.
3 Howard Glennerster and John Hills, The State of Welfare, Oxford, Oxford
University Press, 2nd edition, 1998.
4 Assar Lindbeck, 'The End of the Middle Way?', American Economic Review,
vol. 85, 1995.
388 Positive Welfare
[ ... J
Single Parenthood
As in the case of children, during the trente glorieuses care for frail elderly or
disabled people was mostly provided by non-employed women on an
unpaid, informal basis. Again, with the change in women's patterns of labour
market participation, this task needs to be externalized too. The inability to
do so (because of lack of services) may also result in important welfare losses.
It is tempting to see parallels between the groups that today are exposed to
NSR and industrial workers whose lives were also shattered by social and
economic change centuries ago. In so far as industrial workers are con-
cerned, increased exposure to market risks resulted in what has probably
been one of the most sustained and successful instances of political mobil-
ization in modern Western history: the creation of labour movements and
social democratic parties. These were able to bring workers' concerns to
the centre of the political arena and to force through the adoption of labour
392 The Politics of the New Social Policies
Participation
The key socio-demographic characteristics of NSR groups outlined above
are the fact of being young, of possessing low skills and of being a woman.
Two of these factors are also the main predictors of voting turnout across
Western democracies, and are associated with lower participation. Age is a
particularly strong predictor of political participation. Using survey data
for seventeen countries, Norris finds that age is by far the best predictor of
voting turnout at the micro-level. On average, turnout for the under-25s is
just 55 per cent whereas it reaches 88 per cent for the late middle-aged voters
(Norris, 2002). It is not entirely clear if the impact of age on turnout reflects
a cohort or a life-cycle effect, however. With regard to the US, Putnam pro-
vides evidence that political participation of younger generations does not
increase as they become older, suggesting that the link between age and
turnout reflects a cohort effect (Putnam, 2000). However, other studies
reviewed by Norris support the view that in Western Europe the age gap in
voting turnout has remained more or less constant over the last thirty years,
suggesting instead a life-cycle effect. From the point of view of this article,
however, it is not essential to establish whether it is cohort or position in
the life-cycle that determines participation. What matters is that those who
today have to confront NSRs are less likely to participate in elections.
After age (and together with income), education is the second best pre-
dictor of voting turnout, though its impact varies across countries.
Education does not successfully predict political participation in most
Western European countries, but does so in the US and in Eastern Europe.
Finally, gender used to be a powerful predictor of voting turnout, men
being more likely to participate in elections than women, but in recent
years this is no longer the case (Norris, 2002).
With the exception of women, NSR groups clearly suffer from a partici-
pation gap with regard to the rest of society. It is true that education is
Giuliano Bonoli 393
Representation
1990 2001
France 57
Germany 54
Italy 52
Switzerland 51
UK 51
Sweden 49
Finland 47
Denmark 47
predominance of older men among their members and leadership (table 3).
There are, however, important country variations. In the Nordic countries
and in the UK women are more likely to be union members than male
workers. In addition, in these countries the age gap in union membership is
virtually non-existent, with similar density rates for younger and older
employees. In continental European countries, by contrast, there is a clear
gender and age gap in unionization rates. It is here that the bias towards
higher density among older male workers is stronger. The picture emerging
from tables 1, 2 and 3 is one that can be described in terms of underrepre-
sentation of NSR groups in key democratic institutions. Governments, par-
liaments and trade unions are mostly composed of late-middle-aged men.
There are some clear country variations, which, interestingly, go in the same
Table 3 Net union density for different social groups, 1996
Men Women Younger workers Older workers
(up to 34) (55 and older)
direction. In each of the three tables the presence of NSR groups in key rep-
resentative outfits is stronger in the Nordic countries, and to a lesser extent
in the UK. Their parliaments are younger and more feminiz.ed, and their
labour movements are more feminized and younger than those found in
other Western European countries.
But presence is not a sufficient condition for effective interest represen-
tation. What matters is how elected NSR groups vote in their parliaments
and the positions they defend. The question of whether members of a given
social group tend to represent their fellow members when elected to. a
position of power is one that, in relation to women, has intrigued feminist
political science for several decades.
There is a large corpus of literature on the voting behaviour of women
MPs, on their political attitudes, and on their political activities in general.
Overall, the message that one gets from this literature is that the presence
of women in Parliament matters for decisions on issues that are of parti-
cular concern to women, such as childcare policy or equal opportunities
(Norris and Lovenduski, 1989, 2003; Tramblay, 1998; Sawer, 2000). If we
can rely on several studies on the behaviour of women acting as elected
officials, we know much less about other social groups likely to be more
strongly exposed to NSR, such as the young or the low-skilled. One study
of British parliamentary candidates' attitudes found that support for
gender equality measures was stronger among younger women (Norris
and Lovenduski, 2003 ), suggesting that age might have an impact on issues
that are of relevance to the lives of NSR groups. But we certainly need
more empirical research on this issue if it is to be settled satisfactorily.
The available evidence suggests that, when elected, individuals belong-
ing to NSR-exposed groups are likely to be more sensitive to the needs and
demands of this social group than other elected officials, and that this trend
may be on the increase. This finding goes in the direction of more political
influence for NSR groups, as in spite of the lack of dedicated representa-
tive outfits, they seem capable of making themselves heard through the
existing channels. However, the evidence reviewed is sketchy, and should
be weighed against the presence gap outlined above before concluding that
NSR groups have real opportunities to influence policy-making in parlia-
ments and in labour market institutions.
Preferences
The third condition that needs to be fulfilled for NSR groups to be able to
influence policy to their advantage is some degree of distinctiveness and
homogeneity of their political preferences. Do NSR groups tend to express
political preferences that are different from those of other voters? Are these
shared by all NSR-exposed individuals? The last two decades have seen
Giuliano Bonoli 397
to work for those groups of the population who have traditionally been
excluded from paid employment, especially women. One of the conse-
quences of better NSR coverage is to increase labour supply. In the current
context of population ageing and, in some countries, population decline
combined with difficulties in integrating immigrant populations, an
increase in domestic labour supply is likely to be welcomed by business.
The new social policies discussed here distinguish themselves from the
traditional ones also in terms of cost. Generally speaking, to provide a
service to a section of the population only, say working parents, is less
costly than to set up a universal pension scheme. A quick comparison of
expenditure figures in social programmes covering old and new risks shows
very clearly that the latter come much cheaper. The biggest spenders on
family services and on active labour market policies have outlays on these
programmes not exceeding 2 per cent of GDP, whereas typical figures for
programmes like health care and pensions are in the region of 10 per cent of
GDP. The comparatively low cost of providing coverage of NSRs may
reduce the opposition against it from those who have to foot the bill.
These key features of NSR coverage policies open up a set of new oppor-
tunities for policy-making that have been exploited, especially in contin-
ental European countries. By understanding the mechanisms that are
behind policy decisions in this broad field, we may be better able to
account for developments in countries where the political mobilization
and representation of NSR groups are particularly weak, and which lack a
tradition of social intervention in this area of policy, or where political
institutions do not allow the unilateral imposition of government policy.
Modernizing Compromises
years following the birth of a child, contributions are credited to his or her
pension account on the basis of previous earnings. If he or she stops
working completely, then the contribution credit will be based on 75 per
cent of the average wage. The Swedish reform combined overall retrench-
ment in pensions with the introduction of one of the most generous
systems of contribution credits for carers. Swedish contribution credits,
unlike those in most other countries, apply not only to the state pension,
but also to private individual retirement accounts. In this way, the reform
package was able to attract the support of a sufficient number of political
actors to guarantee its adoption.
Modernizing compromises seem a promising avenue to achieve
advances in the coverage of NSRs. Supporters of welfare retrenchment and
of increased coverage for NSRs usually belong to different political camps,
and if they do join forces on a single reform initiative, they are likely to
form an extremely strong coalition in the political arena. This mechanism
is more likely to exist in countries where political institutions, because of
their fragmentation, encourage the formation of large coalitions around
given policy proposals. Here the incentive for political actors to compro-
mise is strongest (the alternative being stalemate). Paradoxically, one may
thus expect countries with fragmented political institutions to move faster
in the development of policies that cover NSRs.
Some of the key features of NSR coverage policies make them particularly
attractive to employers. As seen above, these policies do not provide
decommodification, they are generally not as costly as the more traditional
forms of social intervention, and they have a clearly favourable impact on
labour supply. This is the case especially of child care and other policies
aimed at making it easier for families to reconcile work and family life. As
a result of their introduction, one can expect the labour supply of women
to increase significantly (Daly, 2000). Active labour market policies
(ALMPs) can have a similar impact, by encouraging the transition from
non-employment to employment of individuals belonging to various
groups of non-working people, most notably youth and long-term unem-
ployed people, older working-age persons, and some disabled people.
ALMPs have a positive impact on labour supply not only in quantitative
but also in qualitative terms, and can contribute to matching labour supply
and demand.
These sorts of policies would obviously present a clear interest for
employers under any set of circumstances, but the ongoing process of
population ageing makes them essential measures. In virtually all industrial
countries, all other things being equal, population ageing will lead to a
402 The Politics of the New Social Policies
stantial electoral losses. In many cases, the strategy of focusing social policy
on NSR groups has failed to gain the social democrats new votes. This may
be explained with reference to the overall low levels of poli-tical participa-
tion of NSR groups. The fact that in the 1970s, contrary to the 1990s, polit-
ical parties found child care to be a vote winner (for instance in France and
Sweden) may reflect changes in political attitudes but also in the age com-
position of electorates. The proportion of the population aged 65 or more
in France and Sweden in the 1970s was between 13 and 14 per cent. In con-
trast, in the late 1990s, in Italy and Germany, two countries where third
way social democratic parties have suffered major electoral losses, the same
figure is between 16 and 19 per cent. While the difference (between three
and six percentage points) may not look dramatic, one needs to take into
account that because of the participation gap between different age groups,
it underestimates the increase in the political influence of older voters.
Conclusion
suggests that this part of the process of welfare state adaptation will be char-
acterized by mechanisms of political exchange, compromise and cross-class
alliances. As the political weakness of NSR groups makes unilateral impo-
sition of policy impossible, the only path to effective reform is to strike
compromises and form alliances with other political forces. Ironically, these
deals are most likely with those political actors that have been most inimi-
cal to the welfare state: retrenchers and employers. Alliances between NSR
groups and the former can be made on the basis of what has been referred
to above as a modernizing compromise, or the combination within a single
piece of legislation of cuts in provision with improvements in the coverage
0 £ NSRs. Employers may also be interested in joining forces with NSR
groups, especially when protection against NSRs means easier labour
market participation. From the employers' point of view this means
increased labour supply and a more efficient labour market, a goal for which
it may be worth investing some public money.
Notes
From Policy and Politics, 33, 3, 2005, pp. 431-49. Earlier versions of this article have
been presented at the Nordic Social Policy Research Meeting, Helsinki, 22-24 Aug.
2002; at the American Political Science Association annual meeting, Boston, 29
Aug.-1 Sept. 2002; at the annual meeting of the Swiss Political Science Association,
Fribourg, 9 Nov. 2003; and at the conference on The Politics of New Social Risks,
Lugano, 25-27 Sept. 2003. It is based on research financed by the Swiss Office for
Education and Science (grant 00.0438) in the context of the EU Framework
5 project WRAMSOC.
The author would like to thank Karen Anderson, Klaus Armingeon, Maurizio
Ferrera, Silja Hausermann, Peter Taylor-Gooby and Martin Rein for their comments.
As a matter of fact there is a fairly strong and statistically significant correla-
tion among OECD countries between the size of the gender gap in voting and
the female employment rate (r = 0,534, sig. 0.049, two-tailed).
2 This loss should, however, be compensated by the income stream resulting
from newly introduced individual private pensions, although this will depend
to a significant extent on the returns on the invested capital, and is as a result
unpredictable.
References
Bonoli, G. (2001) 'Political Institutions, Veto Points, and the Process of Welfare
State Adaptation', in P. Pierson (ed.), The New Politics of th~ Welfare State
Oxford, Oxford University Press, pp. 238-64. " '
Bonoli, G. (2003) 'Two Worlds of Pension Reform in Western Europe'
Comparative Politics, 35, 4, pp. 399-416. '
Bonoli, G. (2004a) 'Generational Conflicts over Resource Allocation: Evidence
from Referendum Voting on Social Policy Issues in Switzerland', paper pre-
sented at the conference on Erosion or Transformation of the Welfare State)
University of Fribourg, Switzerland, 15-16 Oct. .,
Bonoli, G. (2004b) 'Social Democratic Party Policies in Europe: Towards A Third
Way?', in G. Powell (ed.), Social Democratic Party Policies in Contemporary
Europe, London, Routledge, pp. 197-213.
Castles, F. G. (1982) The Impact of Parties: Politics and Policies in Democratic
Capitalist States, London/Beverly Hills, CA: Sage Publications.
Daly, M. (2000) 'A Fine Balance: Women's Labor Market Participation in
International Comparison', in F. V. Schmidt (ed.), Welfare and Work in the Open
Economy, Oxford, Oxford University Press, vol. 2, pp. 467-510.
Ebbinghaus, B. (2003) 'Trade Union Movements in Post-industrial Welfare States',
paper presented at the conference on The Political Regulation of New Social
Risks', Lugano, 23-25 Sept.
Esping-Andersen, G. (1985) Politics against Markets: The Social Democratic Road
to Power, Princeton, Princeton University Press.
Esping-Andersen, G. (1999a) Social Foundations of Post-industrial Economies,
Oxford, Oxford University Press.
Esping-Andersen, G. (1999b) 'Politics without Class? Post-industrial Cleavages in
Europe and America', in H. Kitschelt, P. Lange, G. Marks and J. D. Stephens
(eds), Continuity and Change in Contemporary Capitalism, Cambridge,
Cambridge University Press, pp. 293-316.
Hemerijck, A. (2002) 'The Self-Transformation of the European Social Model(s)',
in G. Esping-Andersen (ed.), Why we Need a New Welfare State, Oxford,
Oxford University Press, pp. 173-214.
Inglehart, R. and Norris, P. (2003) Rising Tide: Gender Equality and Cultural
Change, Cambridge, Cambridge University Press.
Iversen, T. and Wren, A. (1998) 'Equality, Employment, and Budgetary Restraint:
The Trilemma of the Service Economy', World Politics, 50, pp. 507-46.
Jenson, J. (2002) 'From Ford to Lego: Redesigning Welfare Regimes', paper pre-
sented at the American Political Science Association annual meeting, Boston,
31 Aug.-3 Sept.
Korpi, W. (1983) The Democratic Class Struggle, London, Routledge and Kegan
Paul.
Levy, J. (1999) 'Vice into Virtue? Progressive Politics and Welfare Reform in
Continental Europe', Politics and Society, 27, 2, pp. 239-73.
Morgan, K. (2001) 'Conservative Parties and Working Women in France', paper
presented at the American Political Science Association annual meeting, San
Francisco, 30 Aug.-2 Sept.
Naumann, I. (2001) 'The Politics of Child Care: Swedish Women's Mobilization
for Public Child Care in the 1960s and 1970s', ECSR Summer School on Family,
Gender and Social Stratification, Stockholm, 23-25 Aug.
Norris, P. (2002) Democratic Phoenix: Reinventing Political Activism, Cambridge,
Cambridge University Press.
Norris, P. and Lovenduski, J. (1989) 'Women Candidates for Parliament:
Transforming the Agenda?', British journal of Political Science, 19, 1, pp. 106-15.
Giuliano Bonoli 407
Norris, P. and Lovenduski, J. (2003) 'Westminster Women: The Politics of
Presence', Political Studies, 51, 1, pp. 84-102.
pierson, P. (1998) 'Irresistible Forces, Immovable Objects: Post-industrial Welfare
States Confront Permanent Austerity', journal of European Public Policy, 5, 4,
PP· 539-60.
putnam, R. D. (2000) Bowling Alone: The Collapse and Revival of American
Community, New York, Simon and Schuster.
Sawer, M. (2000) 'Parliamentary Representation of Women: From Discourses of
Justice to Strategies of Accountability', International Political Science Review,
21, 4, pp. 361-80.
Siaroff, A. (2000) 'Women's Representation in Legislatures and Cabinets m
Industrial Democracies', International Political Science Review, 21, 4,
pp. 197-215.
Stephens, J. ( 1979) The Transition from Capitalism to Socialism, Urbana, Illinois
University Press.
Taylor-Gooby, P. (2004) 'New Risks and Social Change', in P. Taylor-Gooby (ed.),
New Risks, New Welfare? Oxford, Oxford University Press, pp. 1-27.
Tramblay, M. (1998) 'Do Women MPs Substantively Represent Women? A Study
of Legislative Behaviour in Canada's 35th Parliament', Canadian journal of
Political Science, 31, 3, pp. 435-65.
Beyond Universalism and
Particularism: Rethinking
Contemporary Welfare
Theory
Nick Ellison
the recognition of duties at the personal level, duties which usually far exceed
those required from universal principles like human rights or altruism, is fun-
damental to much moral conduct ... I suspect that we would feel that there
was something morally wrong with someone whose commitment for the
Third World was so great that he or she subordinated all responsibility to
family, friends and community to it.
particularism' (see Jones, 1990) which takes seriously the need to empower
disadvantaged groups but which, in adjudicating amongstdifferent inter-
ests, would also take cognizance of the relative weight of advantage and
disadvantage, especially where this affects freedom and choice over avail-
able resources. Spieker (1996, p. 231) contends that
their dissatisfaction with what they regard as the false divide between uni-
versalist and 'postmodern' /particularist perspectives. In their opinion:
These difficulties suggest not only that Thompson and .Hoggett have
failed to resolve the universalist-particularist dichotomy as successfully as
might initially have appeared, but that the attempt to discover <!- means of
reconciling these opposing perspectives might in fact be misguided. For it
seems that efforts to prescribe formulae for integrating universalist and
particularist values will always be vulnerable to inherent centrifugal
impulses, both at the level of theory, where the epistemological status of
proposed distributional principles is open to challenge from either view-
point, and at the level of practice, where specific patterns of resource allo-
cation are likely to be contested on the grounds that they favour one or
other set of interests.
The remainder of this article argues that it is possible to move beyond
the constraints imposed by the universalist-particularist paradigm
without entirely losing our sense of the importance of having universal
allocatory principles for social provision but that, in order to do so, uni-
versalist ambitions must be reduced in favour of a greater recognition of
the claims of specific interests. We need to advance on two fronts.
Theoretically, it is important to strip away the conceptual dualism that
characterized the above discussion. While there is a need to retain a sense
of principled allocation which continues to address issues of 'fairness' and
'justice' there is no reason why this should depend too heavily on univer-
salist prescriptions. Indeed, it will be argued below that the only 'univer-
sal' elements needed to underpin claims to particular patterns of
distribution are those procedural requirements, agreed by all participants
in the public sphere, which underpin agreed norms of communicative
behaviour. With these elements in place, outcomes could be elaborated
according to decentralized, essentially pragmatic, processes of 'delibera-
tion' as parties to particular debates negotiate on the strength of their
claims.
Certain aspects of 'deliberative democracy' are explored below but
before moving on to consider this issue it is important to see how a greater
appreciation of postmodern ideas can sharpen our understanding of the
contemporary social and political context that deliberative theories will
need to address. In an increasingly complex and fragmented social world,
claims to resources become intimately connected to perceptions of iden-
tity and difference, and these in turn are accompanied by dilemmas of
social inclusion and exclusion which threaten efforts to mount coherent
demands because they introduce a genuine ambivalence about the nature
of social belonging into distributional debates. Postmodern thinking can
help to illuminate our perceptions of the difficult, ambiguous nature of
identity and difference in contemporary societies. In so doing, and
even where their logic is not accepted entirely, postmodern insights can
enhance our appreciation of the forms that deliberative institutions will
need to take if they are to facilitate agreement about the (particularist)
Nick Ellison 417
a place called home, a place free of power, conflict and struggle, a place - an
identity, a form of life, a group vision - unmarked or unriven by difference
and untouched by the power brought to bear upon it by the identities that
strive to ground themselves in its place.
The prospect, then, is one of permanent struggle, both within and among
different identities, to achieve transitory forms of belonging, permanently
threatened by disruption, as these fragile constructions fracture under both
internal and external pressures.
Construing this postmodernist identity politics in the social and polit-
ical language of fairness and social justice is clearly an ambitious task, but
one which postmodern radical democrats like Chantal Mouffe are cur-
rently attempting. In Mouffe's (1996, p. 24) words, 'a radical pluralist
418 Beyond Universalism and Particularism
Space does not permit a full discussion of the various possible approaches
to deliberative democracy (see, for example, Cohen, 1989; Fishkin, 1991;
Rawls, 1993; Young, 1993; Habermas, 1995). For present purposes, it is
important to develop a deliberative account that can speak to the fragmen-
tary, complex social politics which informs contemporary debates about
social policy, so the ideas of theorists such as Rawls and Habermas, both
of whom perceive deliberation in overly formal and rationalistic terms
(Bohman, 1996, pp. 44-5), will not be drawn upon here.
To accomplish this task we need to be aware of the significance of 'infor-
mal' sites of social and political interaction as 'transformative spaces' in
which the clash of competing interests can lead to potentially new and
unheralded outcomes. As Anne Phillips has written, 'the common core
that characterises theories of deliberative or communicative or discursive
democracy is that political engagement can change initial statements of
preference or interest'. Indeed, the point 'that deliberative democracy
insists on ... is the capacity for formulating new positions in the course of
discussion with others' (Phillips, 1995, p. 149). There is a flexible quality
to this conception which is further developed by Bohman (1996, p. 57)
who argues that deliberation should be based upon 'dialogue' rather than
more formal or regulative types of discourse which may require 'specific
epistemic expertise', hence:
dialogue is the mere give and take of reasons. It does not necessarily aim to
produce well-justified claims; rather it aims to produce claims that are wide
enough in scope and sufficiently justified to be accountable to an indefinite
public space of fellow citizens.
producing proposals for, say, teaching and learning needs (including special
needs), buildings and equipment, educational opportunities and access,
and so on. Taken as a whole, however, the community's task would be to
decide policy priorities, reaching internal agreement about necessary
goods and services, and the resources required to deliver them, before
channelling its demands for resources through the relevant local authority
department.
How this process might work in practice needs further elaboration on
at least two counts. First, how is the membership of a social policy com-
munity to be decided? Second, how is competition for inevitably limited
resources among policy communities within local authority areas and,
more generally, among local authorities themselves to be managed?
Membership
Because policy community members will not simply debate choices pre-
sented to them but actively develop policy alternatives in ways which evoke
Barber's (1984, p. 200) conception of 'strong democracy', it is vital that all
those who wish to be involved 'feel able to contribute to ongoing debates'.
As suggested, membership of social policy communities would be likely to
reflect a functional mix with individuals desiring different levels of involve-
ment according to the (changing) depth of interest and the nature of the
issues involved. The main concern is how this complex membership can be
honed into a reasonably sophisticated policy-making body. Here it is helpful
to invert Stewart's (1996, p. 31) point that participatory democratic
processes can actively strengthen representative democracy for, conversely,
there is every reason to believe that particular forms of decentralized repre-
sentation can enhance the wider deliberative process. If, for example, indi-
viduals were to be elected by standing policy community 'fora' (formally
constituted bodies but open to all those able to demonstrate a direct inter-
est) to develop proposals for the community's consideration, these policy-
making committees could be placed under a duty both to disseminate
detailed information about their proposals and to invite counter-proposals.
Naturally, these would need to be debated and ultimately endorsed by the
full forum, with opportunities being provided for the expression of dissent-
ing views and recommendations for possible alternatives, but this prefigura-
tion of forum discussions would help to develop fairly sophisticated
knowledge of relevant issues, so ensuring a high standard of deliberation.
Of course, some of the difficulties commonly associated with delibera-
tive democracy (see Johnson, 1998)- monopoly of discussion by power-
ful interests, the undue influence of those who speak last - could well
emerge if the above model, or something like it, was operationalized. These
are complex issues, to be sure, and satisfactory solutions cannot be fully
426 Beyond Universalism and Particularism
Functional departments
Responsibilities: advising social policy communities on
substantive policy issues and resourcing
Enforced
standards of
procedural and advisers and
social justice elected
forum reps
Conclusion
Note
References
[ ... ]
These challenges to social protection are not equally severe across all
European welfare systems. We must avoid two errors. One is to ignore the
great diversity of European welfare systems. A second is to remain too nar-
rowly preoccupied with just the welfare state. Society's total welfare
package combines inputs from the welfare state proper, markets (and espe-
cially labour markets), and families. Many view the welfare state as over-
burdened, inefficient, threatened or, simply, malfunctioning. Some
advocate that it be radically slimmed, others that it be strengthened, and
still others that it be overhauled. Whatever opinions are put forth, there is
an implicit view of what, alternatively, ought to be the role of markets and
families. Those who advocate 'decentralization' basically suggest a greater
responsibility to families and the 'local community'; those who champion
privatization assign welfare to the cash-nexus but, in practice, the result
would also be a greater burden on many families. To capture the interplay
of state, family, and market, it is useful to cast our analysis in terms of
welfare regimes.
Turn the clock back to the postwar decades, and we would identify two
distinct European welfare regimes. The Nordic-cum-British was largely
general revenue financed, stressing universal, flat-rate benefits. The other,
prevalent in Continental Europe, emphasized contribution financed and
employment-based social insurance. As social protection systems evolved
and matured by the 1970s, differences emerged much more clearly. The
Nordic countries branched out into a unique model, first by adding an ear-
nings-related component to flat-rate 'citizens' benefits and, secondly, by
shifting the emphasis from income transfers towards servicing families,
stressing employment-activating policies and, above all, women's integra-
tion in the labour market. The Nordic model may be famous for its gen-
erosity and universalism, but what really stands out is its employment-bias
G0sta Esping-Andersen 437
of their lives. Until the 1970s, the norm was stable, male breadwinner-
based families. With few interruptions, the male could count on secure
employment, steady real earnings growth, and long careers" followed by
a few years in retirement after age 65. Women would typically cease to
work at first birth, and were thus the main societal provider of social care
for children and the frail elderly. Unemployment and poverty were limited
among prime-age households, and the main social risks were concentrated
at the two 'passive' tail-ends of the life cycle: in large child families, and
among the aged. Hence, besides health care, European welfare states came
to prioritize income maintenance and, par excellence, pensions.
The problem behind the new risk configuration is that it stems primar-
ily from weakened families and poorly functioning labour markets. As a
consequence, the welfare state is burdened with responsibilities for which
it was not designed. A well-functioning welfare state for the future must,
accordingly, be recalibrated so that labour markets and families function
more optimally.
Family Risks
Families today have far fewer children, yet child poverty is rising. Ongoing
changes in labour markets and families affect young households most
severely. The reasons are well-documented: Firstly, unemployment and
insecurity are concentrated among youth and the low-educated (males in
particular). The incidence of 'no-work households' is sometimes alarm-
ingly high, and this is one symptom of an emerging new polarization:
Homogamy means that unemployment, precariousness, and poverty
'comes in couples'. Youth often face serious delays in 'getting started', in
making a smooth transition from school to careers, or in forming inde-
pendent families; southern European youth can often anticipate three
years' unemployment and this, obviously, is one cause of falling birth rates.
The consequences of youth precariousness vary nonetheless depending on
social policy approach. The unemployed- particularly youth- face severe
revenue problems in many EU countries. Southern Europe's 'familialism'
implies that most unemployment is absorbed by parents, but this is not the
case in northern Europe. Where, as in Denmark, unemployed youth are
typically entitled to social benefits, poverty is modest; where, as elsewhere,
they rely primarily on assistance, poverty is widespread.
The new risks are also a function of the rise of 'non-standard' households.
[ ... ] Two types have, in particular, become prominent: the 'no work-
income' and the single parent household. Both run high risks of income
poverty. No-work households are generally transfer dependent, often
relying on social assistance. Except in Scandinavia, child poverty is alarm-
ingly high in lone parent families. Yet, across all kinds of child families- in
G0sta Esping-Andersen 439
that the rising welfare of retirees occurs at the expense .of youth and
children, at least in countries (like the U.S. or Italy) where improvements
in aged welfare have not been accompanied by an upgrading qf family poli-
cies. Also, it is clear that income distribution trends in most countries
favour the aged. The median retired household can usually count on a dis-
posable income of at least 80 per cent of the national median. 3
Certainly there remain pockets of poverty among the aged, typically
concentrated among widows and persons with problematic contribution
histories. Old-age poverty tends to be higher in countries which, until
recently, had large rural populations (Greece, Italy, and Spain, for
example). It is also well known that retirement income declines somewhat
with age. Nonetheless, all indications are that the large mass of pensioners
in most countries have sufficient (and sometimes perhaps 'excess')
incomes, especially in light of reduced consumption and household capital
expenditures, and because an often very large proportion (the EU average
is 75 per cent) of the elderly own their home outright. What is more, in
many countries retirees enjoy preferential tax treatment and are generally
exempt from social contributions.
The economic well-being of today's elderly is the result of a unique com-
bination of factors that produced high retirement income and lifetime asset
accumulation. 4 [ ••. ] The average household at age 65 possesses wealth
that equals 4-5 times its annual income stream. And, although we have
only scattered nation-specific evidence, there are indications of pension
overprovision in some countries. My own analyses of Italian family expen-
diture data indicate a 30 percentage point excess of income over expendi-
ture in the average retiree household. A recent study by Kohli on
intra-family money streams indicates a huge dominance of transfers from
the aged (70+) to their children and grandchildren: 24 per cent of income
is transferred to their children; almost 15 per cent to their grandchildren. 5
Such downward intra-family redistribution surely varies by income
decile and by nation. Moreover, excess revenues reflect not just pension
generosity but also home ownership, private assets, and lower consump-
tion needs. Still, where it exists the redistributive effect must be considered
perverse if the welfare of youth is becoming a function of the riches of their
retired forebears. Indeed, it is doubly perverse in the sense that pay-as-
you-go pensions are financed by the working age population. The welfare
state was presumably built in order to even the playing field, but here is a
case where it helps re-establish inherited privilege.
Any debate on reforming pensions must consider the life course speci-
ficities of past, current and especially future retiring cohorts. If current
retirement cohorts are generally well-off it is because they are the main
beneficiaries of Golden Age capitalism. Firstly, most of their careers
spanned decades of strong productivity and earnings growth with low
unemployment among prime-age males. Secondly, with the regulation of
Gosta Esping-Andersen 441
run if, as is very possible, future retirees will look more like their
forebears in the 1940s or 1960s. If, now, pensioner households have too
much income, it would be a more equitable, and certainly more prudent
policy to simply tax away the excess. 8 If, then, a major reduction of publi~
pensions is a suboptimal long-run strategy, our attention must shift to an
alternative policy. As virtually all agree, the key to long-term sustainabil-
ity lies in population growth and, more realistically, in raising participa-
tion rates. 9
[ ... J
[ ... ]
[ ... ]
[ ... ]
The issue before us has to do with the long term, with the kind of society
that our children will live in. And if this means redefining welfare prior-
ities, we cannot escape the need for some common, basic criterion of what
is desirable, given known constraints. What are the common goals to be
reached? What do we seek to accomplish? What are the first principles that
G('JSta Esping-Andersen 445
[ ... ]
446 A Welfare State for the Twenty-First Century
This will, in the most general terms, imply a greater emphasis on pro-
tecting young households, and a stronger emphasis on servicing families.
accelerated. If not, we are left with a mix of continued early retirement, pos-
sibly retraining, or downward wage adjustments (or re-employment). The
social partners are clearly unwilling to accept across-the-bo;::rd .deregulation
of job security and wages, but it might be an efficiency gain to prolong the
employability of older workers by subsidizing part of their wage bill. This
is especially the case if, as often occurs, retired workers return to work in the
undeclared shadow economy. Just as in the case of youth workers, very high
fixed labour costs help price them out of the market.
A lifelong learning strategy can be effective when the basic cognitive
skills are already present, and this means that we need to make sure that
coming generations have the resources required to benefit from invest-
ments in training and education across their lifetime. In many EU coun-
tries, the existing generational gap is enormous and it is, therefore,
imperative that this is not reproduced in the future.
Equitable retirement
derived from the husband. And the dual-earner family is the single best
strategy to minimize child poverty. Two earners are moreover an effective
household buffer in the eventuality of employment interruptions. It
follows that a knowledge-society strategy premised on investments in edu-
cation must be coupled to a recast family policy, the cornerstones of which
must be guarantees against child poverty. Such guarantees must centre on
affordable child and aged care, on adequate child benefits, and on maternity
and parental leave arrangements that minimize mothers' employment dis-
ruption and maximize their incentive to have children. In the long xun,
therefore, the most persuasive 'win-win' strategy is to redirect resources to
child families if our goal is to sustain our long-term welfare obligations
towards the aged while effectively combating social exclusion.
Whether the externalization of family care is placed in the market or
directly furnished by public agencies is unimportant, as long as standards
and affordability are guaranteed. [ ... ] There [is] a strong case for priori-
tizing high standard childcare services to the weakest families since optimal
quality care may offset inequalities that stem from uneven social capital
within families.
[ ... ]
G0sta Esping-Andersen 453
Notes
Extract from 'Ageing Societies, Knowledge Based Economies, and the Sustainability
of European Welfare States', report prepared for the Portuguese Presidency of the
European Union, Spring 2000; reprinted in this version in Anthony Giddens (ed.),
The Global Third Way Debate, Cambridge, Polity, 2001, pp. 134-56.
1 Social transfers account for only a third of working single mothers' total
income in Scandinavia.
2 My own estimates suggest that due to high fixed labour costs and wage com-
pression, full-time, full-year day care in countries such as Germany or Italy
costs about half of what an average full-time employed mother can expect to
earn. A significant reduction of relative servicing costs can only realistically
occur on the backdrop of a radical deregulation of wages and reduction of
fixed labour costs.
3 We usually define the poverty line as less than 50 per cent of median (adjusted)
disposable income.
4 Public transfers account for the lion's share of total disposable income in coun-
tries like France, Germany and Sweden (70-90 per cent), but far less in others
(such as the UK or the USA, where private pension plans and accumulated
savings play an important role). Earnings (often undeclared) can play an
important role in pensioner income packages. This may be especially pro-
nounced in cases, such as Italy, where early retirement is prevalent and where
there exist strong incentives to supply and demand workers who do not incur
fixed labour costs. Pension schemes are, in some cases, clearly subsidizing the
informal economy.
5 In some countries, young families' access to housing depends heavily on inter-
generational capital transfers of this kind. M. Kohli: 'Private and Public
Transfers between Generations', European Societies, 1, 1999, pp. 81-104.
6 To illustrate the point, workers at age (ca) 60 earn 100 per cent of average wage
in Denmark and the UK, a full140 per cent in France, but only 80 per cent in
the USA:
Source: OECD.
7 The OECD estimates that workers with less than secondary education can
expect five to seven years of unemployment over their lifetime in the UK,
Finland and Spain, and between three and five years in Ireland, Germany,
Sweden, France, Belgium, Denmark, and Canada.
8 The same argument holds for privatizing pensions. Just like public insurance
schemes, private plans work well for workers with long stable and well-paid
careers. Coverage is low among employees in atypical (such as part-time or
temporary) employment, and traditional employer occupational pension plans
are eroding as a result of the decline of large firms. Encouraging private pensions
454 A Welfare State for the Twenty-First Century
for the top half of the labour market and limiting public pension commitments
to the bottom half of the population is certainly one possible long-term scen-
ario. I assume, however, that such a scenario is not on the political agenda in the
large majority of EU countries. Targeting public pensions only t() the poor
would reduce the public expenditure burden dramatically, but to put it bluntly:
why should we construct inequalities in the future when it is not necessary?
Privatization will never qualify as a Paretian welfare improvement. As far as
taxing retirement income is concerned, one should clearly avoid too much tax-
ation since this may produce negative savings incentives among pre-retirement
workers. If there is inequity in the distribution of resources between the aged
and the young, a system of taxing excess incomes among the aged would be
acceptable (and more incentive-neutral) if it were earmarked to cover other risks
among the elderly (such as disabilities and intensive care needs).
9 Forecast simulations suggest that a move to strictly targeted public pensions
(covering the bottom third only) would bring most countries' pension
finances into balance by 2050.
10 In the Nordic countries, up to a third of total employment is in the public
sector, fuelled by social service growth. There, as across the European
continent, private consumer services are generally 'priced out of the market'-
indeed, they have been declining over the past decades.
11 Individual countries, like Denmark, have experimented with alternative sub-
sidization schemes to induce more consumption of service labour. Often such
subsidies are an attempt to avoid lower-end services ending up in the black
economy.
12 And, that such deregulation would almost surely have adverse consequences
across the entire labour market, not to mention that it would by necessity
imply a major roll-back of existing welfare guarantees.
13 Hence, women's average weekly hours of unpaid domestic labour is almost
twice as high in Spain as in Denmark.
14 Contemporary national accounts systems are unable to distinguish between
social expenditures that play an 'investment role' and those that do not.
Parallel to the distinction between capital and consumption accounts, some
social expenditures arguably enhance a nation's capital stock and reap a divi-
dend. The actual task is daunting and full of ambiguities, but this is also the
case in conventional national economic accounts (should a tank or a jeep for
the military be classified as investment or consumption?).
15 Whether such an income guarantee be designed around the Anglo-Saxon
formula of work-conditional income supplements or along more traditional
social assistance lines is left open.
16 It is very important to distinguish this 'life chances' guarantee from conven-
tional 'guaranteed citizen income' plans that many advocate. Above all, the life
chances guarantee is meant to be premised on work and not, like the latter, on
the assumption that there will not be sufficient work available. Indeed, the
main principle here is to reward the incentive to work. This is not the place to
discuss the practical design of such life chance guarantees. Clearly, active train-
ing and learning policies will come to play a core role. One might consider a
variant of the American 'earned income credit' subsidy, or similar 'negative
income tax' models, as a means to guarantee welfare for those who end up
trapped in inferior employment.
Investing in the Citizen-
Workers of the Future:
Transformations in
Citizenship and the State
under Ne-w Labour
Ruth Lister
Introduction
there is no unconditional right to benefit ... It's not only possible, but
entirely desirable that we should look at making sure the social security
456 Investing in the Citizen- Workers of the Future
system and the benefits system are matched by responsibility .... It is right
that we should ask ourselves if there is a role for the benefits system as part of
the wider system in asserting the values we hold and asserting ~he kind of
behaviour that we want to see. (Address to the Parliamentary Press ·Gallery,
reported in the Independent, 16 May 2002)
'Citizenship for the twenty-first century' is how Tony Blair (2002b) has
described New Labour's governance model of partnership between the
individual and the state. This model of governance represents a further
development of the managerial state inherited from the Conservatives
(Clarke and Newman, 1997; Clarke et al., 2000; Lister, 2002). With part-
nership 'out goes the Big State. In comes the Enabling State' (Blair, 2002b,
2002c). The enabling state is a leaner state, in which brokerage and regu-
lating, as well as enabling, are emphasized over providing (Miliband,
1999). Partnership, while not a novel idea, is, in its multifarious guises and
new suits of clothing, the linchpin of New Labour's modernizing govern-
ance agenda (Newman, 2001). 3 Although frequently associated in the
governance literature with the 'hollowing out' of the state, Janet Newman
suggests an alternative interpretation of partnerships:
that they can be viewed as a further dispersal and penetration of state power.
The spread of an official and legitimated discourse of partnership has the
capacity to draw local stakeholders, from community groups to business
organisations, into a more direct relationship with government and involve
them in supporting and carrying out the government's agenda ... Labour's
emphasis on holistic and joined-up government, and its use of partnerships as
a means of delivering public policy, can be viewed as enhancing the state's
capacity to secure political objectives by sharing power with a range of actors,
drawing them into the policy process. (Newman, 2001, p. 125)
in each area of service delivery ... we are tying new resources to reform and
results, and developing a modern way for efficient public services, which
includes setting demanding national targets; monitoring performance by
independent and open audit and inspection; giving front-line staff the power
and flexibility to deliver; extending choice; rewarding success; and turning
around failing services. (Brown, 2002b, col. 22)
Children
For the Commission on Social Justice (CSJ), families and children were
critical to the strengthening of both social and human capital. 'Children are
100 per cent of the nation's future' it declared, and it argued that 'the best
indicator of the capacity of our economy tomorrow is the quality of our
children today' (1994, p. 311). A similar message emerges from Esping-
Andersen's sketch of a 'new welfare architecture', in which he emphasizes
that 'a social investment strategy directed at children must be a centrepiece
of any policy for social inclusion' (Esping-Andersen et al., 2002, p. 30).
Children emerged as key figures in New Labour's nascent social invest-
ment state early in 1999. In his Beveridge Lecture, the Prime Minister
pledged the government to eradicate child poverty in two decades, explain-
ing that 'we have made children our top priority because, as the Chancellor
memorably said in his Budget, "they are 20 per cent of the population but
they are [echoing the CSJ] 100 per cent of the future"' (Blair, 1999, p. 16).
Around the same time, the Treasury published a document, Tackling
Poverty and Extending Opportunity, which emphasized the impact of
poverty on children's life chances and opportunities (HM Treasury, 1999).
Ruth Lister 459
Although the pledge to end child poverty was made by Blair, much of
the policy impetus on children has come from the Treasury, which under
Brown has become a key actor in the development of social policy (Deakin
and Parry, 2000). Brown has described child poverty as 'a scar on Britain's
soul', arguing that 'we must give all our children the opportunity to achieve
their hopes and fulfil their potential. By investing in them, we are invest-
ing in our future' (Brown, 1999, p. 8). He has developed these themes in a
series of speeches, together with the argument that 'tackling child poverty
is the best anti-drugs, anti-crime, anti-deprivation policy for our country'
(Brown, 2000a). In his foreword to the pre-2002 Budget report, he states
that 'our children are our future and the most important investment that
we can make as a nation is in developing the potential of all our country's
children' (Brown, 2001, p. iv). While this report does acknowledge that
'action to abolish child poverty must improve the current quality of chil-
dren's lives as well as investing to enable children to reach their full poten-
tial as adults' (HM Treasury, 2001, p. 5, emphasis added), the point is not
developed. 6 Brown went on to present his 2002 Budget as:
assistance rates for children so that by October 2002 the real value of assist-
ance for under-11-year-old children had virtually doubled. This improve-
ment deviates from the third way in welfare as initially articuL0ted by New
Labour: improvements in out-of-work benefits were dismissed as 'depend-
ency'- inducing 'cash handouts' to be rejected in favour of 'a modern form
of welfare that believes in empowerment not dependency' (DSS, 1998,
p. 19). It has therefore not been trumpeted as loudly as other policy devel-
opments, so much so that many people are still unaware of it. It is an example
of a wider phenomenon: 'redistribution by stealth'. Redistribution of
resources, as opposed to redistribution of opportunities, does not fit the
New Labour template. When pressed on the issue, Brown has therefore
described it as redistribution based on 'people exercising responsibilities' to
work and bring up children in contrast to old forms of redistribution based
on 'something for nothing' (Today Programme, BBC Radio 4, 29 Mar. 1999).
More consistent with the New Labour template has been the piloting
and planned introduction of means-tested educational maintenance
allowances to encourage young people from low-income families to stay
on at school and a commitment to an experiment in 'asset-based welfare'
with a universal 'child trust fund' under which every new-born child
would be given a modest capital sum, accessible only when they reach 18
(Kelly and Le Grand, 2001). Indeed, assets-based welfare has itself been
characterized as representing a transition to a social investment state
(Sherraden, 2002). The New Labour template also informs a series of
service-based initiatives. Of particular significance is Sure Start, which was
inspired by the American Head Start programme (see HM Treasury, 2001).
Sure Start is to be combined with early years education and child care
within a single interdepartmental unit with an integrated budget. A further
injection of funds into the national childcare strategy is promised, in the
face of evidence that the policy is flagging. This will involve the creation of
children's centres and of an additional250,000 childcare places by 2005-6
(Strategy Unit, 2002).
For all its weaknesses, the national childcare strategy represents a break-
through in British social policy. It represents the first time that government
has accepted that child care is a public as well as a private responsibility.
Birte Siim has argued that 'from the point of view of social policies towards
women and children, Britain ... represents an exception to the rule of
European social policies', particularly in the area of childcare services
(Siim, 2000, p. 92). This, she suggests, reflects the dominant liberal philos-
ophy of the separation of public and private spheres and (partial) non-
intervention in the latter (see also Lewis, 1998; O'Connor et al., 1999).
This philosophy has framed general policy towards children other than
those deemed at risk of abuse or neglect. Despite the introduction of family
allowances and their extension and replacement by child benefit, children
have been the subject of public neglect. The UK has been described as
Ruth Lister 461
'a serious contender for the title of worst place in Europe to be a child'
(Micklewright and Stewart, 2000, p. 23 ). Arguably, this reflects not only
the liberal strand in the dominant social welfare philosophy but also
ambivalence in British attitudes towards children (Lister, 2000b ). A ten-
dency to sentimentalize and idealize children has existed alongside a reluc-
tance to accommodate their presence in the adult world and an element of
hostility and fear, as reflected in the recent demonization of 'feral chil-
dren'.9 In addition, during the Thatcher years there was an increasingly
strongly expressed view that having children is 'essentially a private
matter', akin to other expensive consumer goods (Beenstock, 1984, cited in
J. Brown, 1988). Such claims tap deep-rooted attitudes put most crudely in
the (male) expression- 'why should I pay for another man's pleasure?'
This sentiment underlies some of the hostility that has always existed
towards family allowances/child benefit and the fact that child poverty
has not been a popular cause in the UK. Keith Banting's analysis, for
instance, suggests that, although family poverty became an important
issue for the 1964-70 Wilson Labour government (partly thanks to pres-
sure from the newly formed Child Poverty Action Group), it was a key
concern for neither organized labour nor the wider electorate (Banting,
1979). As the former Conservative Chancellor observes, approvingly, in
his memoirs, 'the moral sense of the nation' is more sympathetic to pen-
sioner than child poverty (Lawson, 1992, p. 595). Such attitudes may help
to explain signs of disappointment among some government ministers
that 'the pledge to end child poverty has not generated the expected polit-
ical returns', particularly in the 'Labour heartlands' (Barnes, 2000, p. 1).
One consequence has been the bizarre spectacle of the Chancellor calling
for an 'alliance for children' to put the kind of pressure on him that Jubilee
2000 did with regard to debt eradication in the South. He envisaged 'a
movement based on faith in the future, a crusade for nothing less than the
kind of society our children will inherit' (Brown, 2000b ). In response, the
End Child Poverty Campaign has been set up by a number of children's
charities.
Prout does not reject the discourse of investment in children but warns that,
'on its own a focus on futurity is unbalanced and needs to be accompanied
by a concern for the present well-being of children, for their participation
in social life and for their opportunities for human self-realisation' (2000,
p. 306). As the Children's Forum declared in their official statement to the
UN General Assembly, 'you call us the future, but we are also the present'
(cited in Stasiulis, 2002, p. 508).
This assertion of their agency as children is supported by a study of
childhood poverty from within the new paradigm of childhood. Its author,
Tess Ridge, criticizes the focus 'on children as "adults to be", as future
investments, rather than as children with their own voices and agency, their
own experiences and concerns' (Ridge, 2002b, p. 12; 2002a; see also Roche,
1999). Goals and targets are future-oriented rather than focused 'on the
quality of children's lives- goals of achieving childhoods that are, as far as
possible, happy, healthy and fulfilled' (Piachaud, 2001, p. 453; see also
Thomas and Hocking, 2003). Likewise, in the target-filled world of the
managerial state, education is reduced to a utilitarian achievement-oriented
measurement culture of tests and exams, with little attention paid to the
actual educational experience.
The state is, however, not monolithic and there are spaces within it where
children are valued as 'beings' and not just 'becomings'. For instance,
Fawcett et al. (forthcoming) suggest that, on the ground, programmes such
as Sure Start do often engage with 'quality of life issues in the here-and-now
as well as investing in the future'. Of particular significance is the Children
and Young People's Unit (CYPU) established by the government in 2000
within the Department for Education and Skills. In 2001 it published a con-
sultation document, Building a Strategy for Children and Young People.
This set out a vision and set of principles that pays attention to the present
as well as the future and that treats children and young people as social
actors whose views should be taken into account. An imaginative consulta-
tion process was designed to maximize children and young people's own
participation. The Unit has also published a guidance document on children
and young people's participation in decisions that affect their lives at every
level from their own lives to national policy-making.
'Promoting citizenship and social inclusion' is one of the arguments put
in favour of such an approach (CYPU, 2001, p. 6). This conjures up what
Daiva Stasiulis calls the 'imaginary of the child citizen as an active partici-
pant in governance', personified in and promoted by an emergent inter-
national children's movement (2002, p. 509; see also Roche, 1999). 13 This
imaginary does not, however, have very deep roots in government think-
ing about children and children's rights, as codified in the UN Convention
on the Rights of the Child.
Children's right to express their views and have them taken seriously in
all matters affecting them is enshrined in Article 12 of the Convention on
464 Investing in the Citizen-Workers of the Future
the Rights of the Child. Gerison Lansdown (2002) has argued .that 'it is far
from adequately implemented in respect of children in the UK'.. Her view
and that of many children's rights activists is that the appointment of a
Children's Rights Commissioner is crucial to the protection and promo-
tion of the human rights of children (Children's Rights Alliance for
England, 2002; Willow, 2002). 14 Hitherto, the government has resisted
such calls for an English Commissioner, despite acceptance in the devolved
administrations and many other countries and a commitment in Labour's
1992 Election Manifesto (subsequently dropped by Blair) (Lansdown)
2002). This was the subject of criticism in the second UK report of the UN
Committee on the Rights of the Child, which highlighted the extent to
which the government's approach to children's rights has been piecemeal
and partial (CRC, 2002). A particular focus of criticism in the report is the
'unequal enjoyment of economic, social, cultural, civil and political rights'
by vulnerable groups of children including asylum and refugee children
(CRC, 2002, para. 22). There has, for instance, been a reluctance to extend
to the children of asylum-seekers the welfare and educational rights
enjoyed by other children (Maternity Alliance, 2002; Sale, 2002; see also
Stasiulis, 2002).
More generally, New Labour has been more willing to countenance
rights for children who do not live with their parents than to intervene in
the private sphere of the family of those who do. This is most notable in
the refusal to remove parents' right to hit their children, again strongly
criticized by the UN Committee as constituting 'a serious violation of the
dignity of the child' (CRC, 2002, para. 35). As Fawcett et al. (forthcom-
ing) observe, the government thereby 'allies itself with older discourses
around "children as property" and sets itself firmly against moves to
democratize the family more fully, a rather curious positioning in view of
its much-vaunted claims to be "modern" and its assumptions about
gender equality'.
Jenson and Saint-Martin (2001) warn that neglect of gender equality
issues may be one consequence of the future-oriented social investment
state. There is a danger that children's poverty is divorced from that of
their mothers and more generally that 'questions of gender power ... are
more and more difficult to raise, as adults are left to take responsibility
for their own lives' Genson, 2001, p. 125). In Canada, the discourse of
child poverty has dominated policy-making on poverty for longer.
A Status of Canada Women report argues that the discourse has served
to make the structural causes of poverty less visible; to encourage a
response motivated by pity for the helpless child; and to displace
women's issues generally and women's poverty specifically (Wiegers,
2002; Stasiulis, 2002).
A focus on children and social investment does not, however, neces-
sarily have to mean the displacement of gender issues. Esping-Andersen,
Ruth Lister 465
for instance, makes the somewhat instrumentalist case for treating the
development of 'women-friendly' policies as themselves 'a social invest-
ment'. He justifies this position on the grounds that 'in many countries
women constitute a massive untapped labour reserve that can help
narrow future age dependency rates and reduce associated financial pres-
sures' and that 'female employment is one of the most effective means
of combating social exclusion and poverty' (Esping-Andersen et al.,
2002, p. 94 ).
It would be wrong to say that New Labour has ignored the issue of
gender equality but the consensus is that it has accorded it relatively low
priority, despite the establishment of a Women and Equality Unit and a
number of specific policies that will improve women's lives. New Labour's
avoidance of a systematic gendered analysis and strategy is not, however,
simply a function of its child-oriented priorities. It also reflects its associ-
ation of feminism with 'yesterday's politics' (Coote, 2002, p. 3) and a
related reluctance to acknowledge structural inequalities and conflicts of
interest in a concern to promote consensus and cohesion (Franklin, 2000a,
2000b; McRobbie, 2000; Coote, 2001). That said, a focus on the child is one
way of side-stepping social divisions, even though these frame and shape
children's opportunities and adult outcomes: 'because the figure of the
child is unified, homogeneous, undifferentiated, there is little talk about
race, ethnicity, gender, class and disability. Children become a single, essen-
tialized category' (Dobrowolsky, 2002, p. 67).
Conclusion
The design of the new welfare architecture in the UK involves the chan-
ging construction of both citizenship and the state. With regard to citizen-
ship, in return for the promise of investment in economic opportunity by
the state, increased emphasis is being placed on the responsibilities of citi-
zens, most notably: to equip themselves to respond to the challenges of
economic globalization through improved employability; to support
themselves through paid work; to invest in their own pensions; and to
ensure the responsible behaviour of their children.
The changing construction of the state has been analysed here from the
perspective of both governance and its role. In terms of governance, the
emergent state can be characterized as 'the enabling, managerial, partner-
ship state', a partial inheritance from the previous Conservative govern-
ment. In terms of role, the notion of 'the social investment state' captures
its essence, both analytically and normatively. While there are some differ-
ences of detail and emphasis in the various formulations of the social
investment state, broadly its key features are as set out in box 1.
466 Investing in the Citizen- Workers of the Future
with citizenship responsibility and the obligations associated with the paid
work ethic needs to be analysed in its own right as well as simply as an
expression of the social investment state. Indeed, it helps us to understand
better the true complexion of the model-citizen in that state. Likewise, shifts
in governance, characterized here as the emergence of the 'managerial, part-
nership state', cannot simply be subsumed under the rubric of social invest-
ment, even if they are associated with it in practice. Second, the state is not
a monolith and it is dangerous to assume 'unity or integration' or to flatten
out complexity (Pringle and Watson, 1992, p. 63; Clarke, 2000). New
Labour itself has been described as 'essentially ambiguous and Janus-faced',
reflecting the 'often contradictory and conflicting traditions of social
democracy, social conservatism, Thatcherism and pragmatism' upon which
it draws (Smith, 2001, p. 267; Lister, 2001 ). Such ambiguities mean that there
are spaces, such as around childhood and poverty, that civil society actors
can exploit to argue for a more genuinely child-focused and also more egal-
itarian approach. Thus, from both a normative and analytic perspective, even
if we are witnessing a genuine paradigm shift, analysts and activists need to
remain alert to complexities and possible inconsistencies within the specific
policy configurations to be found in emergent social investment states.
Notes
This paper was first given at the American Political Science Association annual
meeting in 2002 and then published in this revised form in Social Policy and
Administration, 37, 5, 2003, pp. 427-43. It engages with the work of a team of polit-
ical scientists led by Jane Jenson of Montreal University.
A revised version of the report has been published as Esping-Andersen et al.,
2002. See also 'A Welfare State for the Twenty-First Century' in this volume.
2 Interestingly, Amitai Etzioni has dismissed this formulation as a 'grave moral
error' on the grounds that 'basic individual rights are inalienable, just as one's
social obligations cannot be denied': the relationship between the two is com-
plementary not conditional (2000, p. 29). For a more detailed exposition of the
construction of citizenship under New Labour see, for instance, Dwyer, 1998,
2000; Lister, 1998; Heron and Dwyer, 1999; Rose, 1999.
3 In New Zealand also, partnerships have been identified as a key element in 'a
post-welfarist, post-neoliberal form of social governance' (Lamer and Craig,
2002, p. 4).
4 Under the Tories, managerialism cast welfare subjects as customers and con-
sumers rather than citizens (Clarke, 1997, 1998; Hughes and Lewis, 1998).
New Labour has attempted to marry the two in the person of 'the demanding,
sceptical, citizen-consumer' who expects improved standards from public ser-
vices in line with those in the private sector (DSS, 1998, p. 16). There is the
same emphasis on individual customer service and user- rather than provider-
led welfare as under the Conservatives (a model which was not necessarily
realized in practice and which had more purchase in some arms of the
welfare state than others). At the same time, though, there is something of a
more collective and democratic approach: examples include the introduction
of citizens' juries and various fora for 'listening to' particular groups such as
468 Investing in the Citizen- Workers of the Future
References
Anderson, B. (2002) 'The Time for Sentimentalism is Over: Let Us Tame these Feral
Children', Independent, 29 Apr.
Ruth Lister 469
Banting, K. (1979) Poverty, Politics and Policy, Basingstoke, Macmillan.
Barnes, M. (2000) 'Editorial: Keeping up the Pressure', Poverty, 106, p. 1.
Bashevkin, S. (2000) Road-testing the Third Way: Welfare Reform in Canada,
Britain and the United States, Jerusalem, Hebrew University of Jerusalem.
Beck, W., van der Maesen, L., and Walker, A. (eds) (1997) The Social Quality of
Europe, The Hague, Kluwer Law International.
Beenstock, M. (1984) 'Rationalising Child Benefit', paper given at Policy Studies
Institute seminar, London, June, cited in]. Brown, Child Benefit, London, Child
Poverty Action Group, 1988.
Blair, T. (1998a) The Third Way: New Politics for the New Century, London,
Fabian Society.
Blair, T. (1998b) 'The Government's Strategy', in The Government's Annual Report
97/98, London, Stationery Office.
Blair, T. (1999) Beveridge Lecture, Toynbee Hall, London, 18 Mar., reproduced in
R. Walker (ed.), Ending Child Poverty, Bristol, Policy Press.
Blair, T. (2002a) 'New Labour and Community', Renewal, 10, 2, pp. 9-14.
Blair, T. (2002b) Speech to Labour Party Conference, Blackpool, 1 Oct. at
www.labour.org/uk/ tbconfspeech/.
Blair, T. (2002c) 'My Vision for Britain', Observer, 10 Nov.
Blair, T. and Schroder, G. (1999) 'Europe: The Third Way/Die Neue Mitte', repro-
duced in The Spokesman, 66, pp. 27-37.
Brown, G. (1999) 'A Scar on the Nation's Soul', Poverty, 104.
Brown, G. (2000a) Speech to the Children and Young Person's Unit conference,
Islington, London, 15 Nov.
Brown, G. (2000b) Speech to the CPAG Child Poverty conference, Our Children
are our Future, London, 15 May.
Brown, G. (2001) 'Foreword', in HM Treasury, Tackling Child Poverty, at www.
hm-treasury.gov.uk.
Brown, G. (2002a) Budget Statement, House of Commons Hansard, 17 Apr.
Brown, G. (2002b) Spending Review, House of Commons Hansard, 15 July.
Brown, J. (1988) Child Benefit: Investing in the Future, London, Child Poverty
Action Group.
Children's Rights Alliance for England (2002) Report to the Pre-sessional Working
Group of the Committee on the Rights of the Child, London: CRAE, at
www.crights.org.uk.
Clarke, J. (1997) 'Capturing the Customer', Self, Agency and Society, 1, 1,
pp. 55-73.
Clarke, J. (1998) 'Consumerism', in G. Hughes (ed.), Imagining Welfare Futures,
London, Routledge.
Clarke,]. (1999) 'Coming to Terms with Culture', in H. Dean and R. Woods (eds),
Social Policy Review 11, Luton, Social Policy Association.
Clarke, J. (2000) 'Governing Welfare Systems: Subjects and States', paper presented
at the Social Policy Association annual conference, Roehampton.
Clarke, J. and Hoggett, P. (1999) 'Regressive Modernisation? The Changing
Patterns of Social Services Delivery in the United Kingdom', in H. Wollmann
and E. Schroter (eds), Comparing Public Sector Reform in Britain and Germany,
Aldershot, Ashgate.
Clarke, J. and Newman, J. (1997) The Managerial State, London, Sage.
Clarke, J., Gewirtz, S. and McLaughlin, E. (cds) (2000) New Managerialism, New
Welfare? London, Sage.
Commission on Social Justice (1994) Social justice: Strategies for National
Renewal, London, Vintage.
470 Investing in the Citizen-Workers of the Future
Forge a New Welfare Deal between the Individual and the State', Social Policy
and Administration, 33, 1, pp. 91-104.
HM Treasury (1998) Modern Public Services for Britain: Investing in Reform
(Pocket Guide), London, HM Treasury.
HM Treasury (1999) Tackling Poverty and Extending Opportunity, London, HM
Treasury.
HM Treasury (2001) Tackling Child Poverty: Giving Every Child the Best Possible
Start in Life, London, HM Treasury, at www.hm-treasury.gov.uk.
HM Treasury (2002a) Budget Report, London, HM Treasury.
HM Treasury (2002b) Pre-Budget Report, London, HM Treasury.
Holden, C. (1999) 'Globalization, Social Exclusion and Labour's New Work
Ethic', Critical Social Policy, 19, 4, pp. 529-38.
Hughes, G. and Lewis, G. (1998) Unsettling Welfare, London, Routledge.
Jenson, J. (2001) 'Rethinking Equality and Equity: Canadian Children and the
Social Union', in E. Broadbent (ed.), Democratic Equality, What Went Wrong?
Toronto, University of Toronto Press.
Jenson, J. and Saint-Martin, D. (2001) 'Changing Citizenship Regimes: Social
Policy Strategies in the Investment State', paper prepared for workshop on
Fostering Social Cohesion: A Comparison of New Political Strategies,
Universite de Montreal, 21-22 June.
Jenson, J. and Saint-Martin, D. (2002) 'Building Blocks for a New Welfare
Architecture: From Ford to LEGO', paper prepared for the American Political
Science Association annual conference, Boston, 29 Aug.-1 Sep.
Jessop, B. (1994) 'The Transition to Post-Fordism and the Schumpeterian Workfare
State', in R. Burrows and B. Loader (eds), Towards a Post-Fordist Welfare State?
London, Routledge.
Jessop, B. (2000) 'From the KWNS to the SWPR', in G. Lewis, S. Gewirtz and
J. Clarke (eds), Rethinking Social Policy, London, Sage.
Kelly, G. and LeGrand, J. (2001) 'Assets for the People', Prospect, Dec.
Lansdown, G. (2002) 'Children's Rights Commissioners for the UK',
in B. Franklin (ed.), The New Handbook of Children's Rights, London,
Routledge.
Lamer, W. and Craig, D. (2002) 'After Neoliberalism? Local partnerships and
Social Governance in Aotearoa New Zealand', paper presented at the American
Political Science Association annual meeting, Boston, 28 Aug.-1 Sep.
Lawson, N. (1992) The View from No. 11, London, Bantam Press.
Levitas, R. (2000) 'Community, Utopia and New Labour', Local Economy, 15, 3,
pp. 188-97.
Lewis, J. (ed.) (1998) Gender, Social Care and Welfare State Restructuring in
Europe, Aldershot, Ashgate.
Lister, R. (1998) 'Vocabularies of Citizenship and Gender: The UK', Critical Social
Policy, 18, 3, pp. 309-31.
Lister, R. (2000a) 'To RIO via the Third Way: Labour's "Welfare" Reform Agenda',
Renewal, 8, 4, pp. 9-20.
Lister, R. (2000b) 'The Politics of Child Poverty in Britain from 1965 to 1990',
Revue Franraise de Civilisation Britannique, 11, 1, pp. 67-80.
Lister, R. (2001) 'New Labour: A Study in Ambiguity from a Position of
Ambivalence', Critical Social Policy, 21, 4, pp. 425-47.
Lister, R. (2002) 'Towards a New Welfare Settlement?', in C. Hay (ed.), British
Politics Today, Cambridge, Polity.
McRobbie, A. (2000) 'Feminism and the Third Way', Feminist Review, 64,
pp. 97-112.
472 Investing in the Citizen- Workers of the Future
Maternity Alliance (2002) 'A Crying Shame: Pregnant Asylum Seekers and their
Babies in Detention', briefing paper, London, Maternity Alliance ..
Micklewright,]. and Stewart, K. (2000) 'Child Well-Being and Socia~ Cohension',
New Economy, 7, 1, pp. 18-23. · ·
Miliband, D. (1999) 'This is the Modern World', Fabian Review, 111, 4, pp. 11-13.
Mulgan, G. (1998) 'Social Exclusion: Joined Up Solutions to Joined Up Problems',
in C. Oppenheim (ed.), An Inclusive Society: Strategies for Tackling Poverty,
London, Institute for Public Policy Research.
Newman,]. (1998) 'Managerialism and Social Welfare', in G. Hughes and G. Lewis
(eds.), Unsettling Welfare London, Routledge.
Newman, J. (2001) Modernising Governance, London, Sage.
O'Connor, J. S., Orloff, A. S. and Shaver, S. (1999), States, Markets, Families:
Gender, Liberalism and Social Policy in Australia, Canada, Great Britain and the
United States, Cambridge, Cambridge University Press.
Piachaud, D. (2001) 'Child Poverty, Opportunities and Quality of Life', Political
Quarterly, 72, 4, pp. 446-53.
Polakow, V. (1993) Lives on the Edge: Single Mothers and their Children in the
Other America, Chicago, University of Chicago Press.
Powell, M. (ed.) (1999) New Labour, New Welfare State? Bristol, Policy Press.
Pringle, R. and Watson, S. (1992) '"Women's Interests" and the Post-structuralist
State', in M. Barrett and A. Phillips (eds), Destabilizing Theory: Contemporary
Feminist Debates, Cambridge, Polity.
Prout, A. (2000) 'Children's Participation: Control and Self-Realisation in British
Late Modernity', Children and Society, 14, pp. 304-15.
Ridge, T. (2002a) Childhood Poverty and Social Exclusion: From a Child's
Perspective, Bristol, Policy Press.
Ridge, T. (2002b) 'Listening to Children: Their Contribution to Anti-poverty
Policies', Po·verty, 111, pp. 10-13.
Roche, J. (1999) 'Children: Rights, Participation and Citizenship', Childhood, 6, 4,
pp. 475-93.
Rose, N. (1999) 'Inventiveness in Politics', Economy and Society, 28, 3, pp. 467-93.
Sale, A. U. (2002) 'News analysis', Community Care, 20-26 June, p. 20.
Schram, S. F. (1995) Words of Welfare: The Poverty of Social Science and the Social
Science of Poverty, Minneapolis, University of Minnesota Press.
Sherraden, M. (2002) 'from a Social Welfare State to a Social Investment State', in
C. Kober and W. Paxton (eds), Asset-based Welfare and Poverty, London,
National Children's Bureau.
Siim, B. (2000) Gender and Citizenship: Politics and Agency in France, Britain and
Denmark, Cambridge, Cambridge University Press.
Smith, M. J. (2001) 'Conclusion: The Complexity of New Labour', inS. Ludlam
and M.]. Smith (eds), New Labour in Government, Basingstoke, Macmillan.
Social Exclusion Unit (2001) A New Commitment to Neighbourhood Renewal,
London, Cabinet Office.
Stasiulis, D. (2002) 'The Active Child Citizen: Lesson from Canadian Policy and
the Children's Movement', Citizenship Studies, 6, 4, pp. 507-38.
Strategy Unit (2002) Delivering for Children and Families, London, Cabinet
Office.
Thomas, G. and Hocking, G. (2003) Other People's Children, London, Demos.
Titmuss, R. M. (1974) Social Policy, London, Allen and Unwin.
Wiegers, W. (2002) The Framing of Poverty as 'Child Poverty' and its Implications
for Women, Ottawa, Status of Women Canada.
Willow, C. (2002) 'Lagging Behind?', Community Care, 12-18 Sept., p. 30.
Basic Incotne and the Two
Diletnmas of the Welfare State
Philippe van Parijs
Can we avoid a social tragedy? Can we help entering the next century with
our welfare states in disarray, with labour's hard-won conquests under
deadly threat, and with a growing minority of citizens losing all hope of ever
getting a decent job and securing a decent standard of living throughout their
existence? I believe we can, but also that it won't be easy. We shall badly need
intelligence and will, to come to terms with two central dilemmas.
viding the administrative security which will enable many people to take
the risk of accepting a job or creating their own. Thirdly, basic income can
be viewed as a soft strategy for job-sharing, by providing all with a small
unconditional sabbatical pay, and thereby making it more affordable for
many either to relinquish their job temporarily in order to get a break, go
self-employed or retrain, or to work durably on a more part-time basis.
The combined effect of these three processes should lead to a far more
flexible working of the labour market, with significantly more stepping-
stone, training-intensive, often part-time jobs. Such jobs must be paid little
because they represent a risky investment on the part of the employer in a
free human being who could leave at any time; and they could acceptably
be paid little because the pay would supplement an income to which the
workers are unconditionally entitled and which therefore enables them to
filter out the jobs that are not sufficiently attractive in themselves or in
terms of the prospects they offer.
Of course, the size of this effect will be very sensitive to the level of the
basic income and to the package of labour-market and tax-and-benefit
institutional adjustments that will need to accompany its introduction. But
if embedded in an appropriate package, even a modest basic income could
put a halt to the growing dualization and demoralization of our socio-
economic system. Under present conditions, the indignation of the jobless
who arc morally and legally expected to keep looking for what many know
they will never find is matched by the outrage of those who subsidize with
their social security contributions the idleness of people who are overtly
transgressing the rules of the game. Once it stops being Utopian to believe
that all those who wish to work can find a job which earns them (when
added to the unconditional part of their income) enough to live on, the
conditions attached to supplementary entitlements- typically, unemploy-
ment benefits restricted to active job-seekers- can more realistically and
more legitimately be expected to be enforced. The introduction of an
unconditional basic income would thereby also make it possible to reha-
bilitate the social insurance aspect of our welfare systems. Consequently,
whereas a well-intentioned gradual increase in the real level of the safety
net could rightly be feared further to disturb the working of the labour
market, a well-embedded gradual lifting of the floor can be expected to
address both the poverty and the unemployment problem.
Notes