Analysis of Human Act
Analysis of Human Act
3.0 Objectives
3.1 Introduction
3.2 Understanding of Human Act
3.3 The Constituent Elements of Human Act
3.4 Impediments for Human Act
3.5 Factors Determining the Morality of Human Acts
3.6 Determinism and Indeterminism
3.7 Let Us Sum Up
3.8 Key Words
3.9 Further Readings and References
3.10 Answers to Check Your Progress
3.0 OBJECTIVES
• Secondly, this unit highlights the obstacles that could possibly obstruct the performance
of a human act.
• Thirdly, it is very important to analyse the factors that generally influence the morality of
human action.
3.1 INTRODUCTION
Humans are said to be evaluative in nature. Whenever a person does something we find others
analysing his/her behaviour and commenting that it was good, bad or at times indifferent. Ethics
is said to be a philosophical treatise which studies human behaviour and tries to determine
whether the act performed was morally right or wrong. It cannot content itself with simply
registering facts; it attempts to reflect on the meaningfulness or meaninglessness of such facts,
establish or reject them on a rational basis, understand their implications, draw relevant
consequences and, above all, intuit their ultimate cause. There is a continuous effort made for
studying our own moral beliefs and our moral conduct and striving to ensure that we, and the
institutions we help to shape, live up to standards that are reasonable and morally based. This
contributes towards establishing sound moral foundation on which people build their lives.
Hence one can reasonably aver that Ethics represents a broad framework for determining a core
value system one uses for our day to day existential situation.
1
The above discussion raises an essential question: How we judge certain actions as good or right
whereas others are regarded as bad or wrong? Any attempt to provide an adequate answer to this
query brings us to the analysis of a basic question: What is human action?
Scholastic philosophy outlines a distinction between Actus Hominis and Actus Humanus i.e.
‘Acts of Man/Human’ and ‘Human Acts’ respectively. Not every act that a human being does is
a typically human act. Human activities, like the circulation of blood, heart beat, over which
normal people in general have no control are not classified as human acts. Such acts which are
beyond the control of humans and those which they share in common with animals are called as
‘Acts of humans’. Acts of humans, then, are involuntary and therefore, not morally responsible
for them.
On the other hand a ‘Human Act’ is one which proceeds from knowledge and from consent of
free will. Or in other words it is an act which emanates from the will with a knowledge of the
end or goal to which the act leads. The Human act is to be distinguished from acts of humans
which are performed without intervention of intellect and free will. An act is termed as
distinctively a human act which is voluntary in character, that is, the human person under
consideration could have done it differently if s/he had so willed or chosen. It is an act which is
in some way under the control or direction of the will, which is proper to humans. Such an act is
performed by a person deliberately and intentionally in order to realize some foreseen end/s.
Thus one can rightly assert that a voluntary act proceeds from the will with the apprehension of
the end sought, or, in other words, is put forth by the will solicited by the goodness of the object
as presented to it by the intellect. Such acts, moreover, proceed from the will's own
determination, without necessitation, intrinsic or extrinsic.
Constituent elements of the human act refer to the inner causes or the constituting elements
which generate a human person to undertake a certain act. The understanding of the human act
indicates that there are two essential elements which constitute a human act: The Intellectual
Element and The Volitive Element.
Knowledge is one of the important qualities which distinguish humans from other sentient
beings. Absolute truth in all situations and matters might be beyond human capabilities. But we
humans can attain truth and that not all truths are relative are undeniable facts, as Epistemology
will have established. The denial of such assertions only results in re-asserting them, by the very
act itself. Universal scepticism and absolute relativism are found to be self-contradictory and as
such are philosophically untenable doctrines.
The faculty of willing can make a choice for something and seek it only when it is first known.
This act of knowing is undertaken by the faculty of the intellect. The human act is voluntary
when its different elements and its implications are sufficiently known by the agent or the doer
2
prior to the operation of the will. This process of knowing entails certain important conditions:
(i) adequate knowledge of the aspired object, (ii) attention to the action by which the particular
object is to be pursued and (iii) judgement on the value of the act.
The fulfilment of the above elements is found to be essential, for, human person cannot
consciously and freely will something without having proper knowledge about what the object
one is concerned with and therefore conscious of the act one is to perform in order to achieve the
desired aim. It is also required that one evaluates the action undertaken in its concrete nature as a
desirable good or an undesirable evil. Such an appraisal includes judgement on the moral or
ethical value of the act.
Furthermore, the goodness or the badness of a particular human act is judged only under those of
its aspects which are sufficiently known. For instance a person who robs and kills a person not
knowing him to be his brother, he is guilty of criminal injury but not culpable of offence of
fratricide.
However, from the above discussion one should not presuppose that we have full knowledge of
the act and its implications every time we undertake a human act. There is still room left for
mistakes. What we affirm here is that with right effort the person can have sufficient knowledge
of the object and its other considerations which are essential for the making of a human act.
Another important characteristic which sets apart the human person from animals is that of
voluntariness or what we commonly designate as free will. It is the task of the intellect to
conceptualize the good, to propose it to the will as something desirable, and to judge the
suitability of the means in its attainment. This awareness which is based on certain amount of
reflection is very important in the analysis of the human act. It can occur in varying degrees
depending on which, they can affect the morality of the act. However, just this awareness is
insufficient for the production of the human act. It is required that the presented good is willed
freely by the person. The volitive dimension points that the will can freely make a choice of the
concrete object in which the good is sought. Thus when we hold a person morally responsible for
his/her action, we assume that the act was done freely, knowing and willingly. The idea of
responsibility would seem then to connote and presuppose that of free will.
If a human person for some valid reason is not free to choose what he/she would like according
to his/her insight and will, but has to act against one’s will, his/her action is not free and
consequently such an act cannot be designated as a human act. For instance a mentally disturbed
person feels compelled to do something again and again but he/she is conscious of the object one
is concerned with and also the end of the action with which the object is pursued, yet such an act
will not be voluntary because its execution is done with psychic compulsion and not with free
will. So an act to be a free act and consequently a human act, it is to be done without any internal
or external compulsion. The degree of compulsion determines to a large extent the voluntariness
of the action and consequently the culpability of the person. For instance a high degree of
compulsion may almost render the act involuntary and subsequently reduce the degree of
culpability.
3
One must note that anything that is an object of the will, we call the thing willed. But not
everything that is willed is necessarily an effect of the will; for e.g. the setting of a house on fire
which is not caused, but desired by someone, is something willed but is not the effect of the will.
Thus when what is willed is both the object and the effect of the will, we call it voluntary.
One can conclude the discussion on the two constitutive elements of the human act: intellectual
and volitive, by affirming the essential union of the knowledge and will in the generation of the
human act.
Very often a voluntary act, performed by an agent knowingly and freely in order to realize some
foreseen end, is not a spontaneous reaction. It involves a dynamic process. Voluntary action has
its advent in the mind. It begins with a feeling of want or a craving or a desire which is either real
or ideal. Such an impulse, though to a certain extent painful, is mixed with pleasure which arises
from the anticipation of satisfaction of this craving by the attainment of the desired object. The
person also has awareness of the means that are required to attain the proper object. In a simple
action, where there is no conflict of motives, the choice is easily made and the desired action is
performed. However, in our daily course of living many of our actions are of a complex nature
which often involves a conflict of motives thereby causing difficulty in the matter of choice that
eventually delays decision and the performance of the act. Hence, when the self is confronted
with divergent and competing motives the mind experiences a challenge generated by conflict of
motives. In order to tackle this, the mind deliberates on the merits and demerits of the different
courses of action that are available. After weighing the advantages and disadvantages the mind
chooses a particular motive and a particular action to achieve the end. This act of selection of one
motive to the exclusion of others results in decision. The decided motive is subjectively
evaluated as the strongest motive among the others. The decision phase is often converted
immediately into action and the decision is actualised. However at times the decision might be
postponed for a future fulfilment in which case there is scope for resolution. Resolution refers to
the capacity of remaining committed to the decided motive. The state of decision or resolution
gives way to the actual performance of a bodily action which is technically designated as a
human act. The undertaking of the external bodily action produces changes in the external world,
certain of these are foreseen consequences whereas many others are unforeseen consequences.
b) Check your answers with those provided at the end of the unit
1) What is human action? Explain the relationship between the intellectual element and the
volitve element in the performance of human action.
4
…………………………………………………………………………………..
…………………………………………………………………………………..
…………………………………………………………………………………..
………………………………………………………………………………….
…………………………………………………………………………………..
………………………………………………………………………………….
…………………………………………………………………………………..
…………………………………………………………………………………..
………………………………………………………………………………….
In the process of performing a human act the individual might encounter certain obstacles which
though may not nullify the human act and make it involuntary but they may reduce the
imputability or culpability of the individual, thereby making him less responsible for the
particular act. In this section, we shall elaborate some of the main impediments which might
affect either the intellectual or the volitive constituent (or both together) of the human action.
Ignorance: This to a great extent affects the intellectual dimension of the human act. It is
elucidated as lack of adequate knowledge in an individual with regard to the nature or moral
quality of an act one is performing or proposes to perform. Ignorance is mainly of two
categories: Invincible ignorance and Vincible ignorance. The former is explained as that
ignorance which cannot be dispelled by reasonable diligence a prudent individual would be
expected to exercise in a given situation. Such ignorance almost renders the act performed as
involuntary and consequently the individual may not be imputable for the act for what is
unknown cannot be the object of volition. On the other hand, Vincible ignorance is that which
could be eliminated by the application of reasonable diligence. Here the agent has not put in
enough effort to gain the required knowledge and as such the concerned person is culpable or
imputable for the act performed under such type of ignorance. However the degree of
imputability depends on the extent of the individual’s cupable negligence.
Habit: Habit is an acquired tendency for doing something as a result of repeated practice. It may
be voluntary or involuntary, depending on whether it was imbibed with consent of a person or
without. Habits usually do not render an act non-human, because though they exert certain
5
coercion they can be overcome by a committed effort. As such imputability of acts from habit
increases or decreases depending upon the effort exerted.
Fear: It is defined as the shrinking back of the mind on account of an impending evil considered
to be difficult to avoid or even impossible at times. Fear may be grave or mild according to
whether it is caused by a grave evil whose avoidance is rather difficult if not impossible, or only
by a mild evil which can be easily avoided. Fear is characterised as highly grave when it
exercises great deterrence on an average person for e.g. fear of killing. Fear is relatively grave
when the threatened evil is generally considered as objectively slight but it scares a particular
person subjectively depending on the person’s emotional disposition. Fear hampers the use of
reason and as such destroys voluntariness. Fear in general does not fully destroy the
voluntariness of action but merely reduces its gradation and as such usually lessens its
culpability. Only in extreme cases when the highly grave fear totally impairs the two constitutive
elements the act done out of fear may be regarded as involuntary.
Analyzing the morality of the human act is said to be a complex enterprise since it is affected by
so many conditions which are within and without. Most of the moralists agree that to judge the
goodness or badness of any particular human act, three elements must be weighed from which
every act derives its morality. They are: the Object of the act, the Circumstances surrounding
the act, and the End or Intention that the one performing the act has in mind.
6
the agent performs a particular act. It is the effect that the agent subjectively wills in his/her
action. At times it can so happen that the intention of the agent coincides with the object of the
human act, for e.g. offering a glass of water to a thirsty person to quench thirst. However at other
times both of them might be different. For e.g. a captured spy may commit suicide in order to
safeguard the secrets of the country. A human act to be morally good the agent or doer must have
a good intention—he must want to accomplish something that is good in one way or another.
The end too can affect the morality of the human act just as circumstances do. A good intention
can make better an act which is good in its object, for e.g. helping a poor person to start a small
business with the intention of making him independent. Also the end can worsen a act which is
already evil in its object, for e.g. killing the father, who is the only breadwinner in the family, so
that his children might be on the street. To a great extent many of the actions that we do which
otherwise might be indifferent morally in themselves, but they receive their moral quality from
the intention behind them.
According to the moralists a human act is said to be morally good when it is good in its object,
circumstances and also in the intention, for it is believed that an action is good when each of
these three factors is conformed to order (Bonum ex integra causa). If even one of these
determinants is contrary to order, the action will be bad, at least in part (Malum ex quocumque
defectu).
The question of free will or human freedom in the matter of making a moral choice, has been an
issue which is discussed and deliberated by philosophers down the centuries. And the complexity
of problem makes it rather difficult to take a stand in the category of ‘Either Or.’ The problem is
formulated thus: Determinism versus Indeterminism. Immanuel Kant has given a sound
articulation to this issue in his, Critique of Practical Reason. He states thus: The concept of
freedom is the stone of stumbling for all empiricists, but at the same time the key to the loftiest
practical principles for critical moralists, who perceive by its means that they must necessarily
proceed by a rational method.
Determinism
Determinism is a theory which explains that all human action is conditioned entirely by
preceding events, and not by the faculty of the Will. In philosophy, the theory is based on the
metaphysical principle that an uncaused event is rather impossible. The success of scientists in
discovering causes of certain behaviour and in some cases effecting its control tends to support
this doctrine. The deterministic view seems to be very much at home with the scientific temper
because the subject matter of any science rests on the principle of causality which asserts that
every event has a cause and the aim of science is to find a causal explanation for anything that
happens within the domain of that science. Accordingly one can enumerate different categories
of determinism based on a particular science. We have the theory of Physical determinism
stating that human interaction can be reduced to relationships between biological, chemical, or
physical entities. This has its origin in the Atomism of Democritus. Theological determinism is
the theory, which posits that there is God, omnipotent and omniscient, who is determining all
7
that humans will do, either by knowing their actions in advance or by decreeing their actions in
advance. German philosopher Leibniz with his theory of monads advocated a form of theological
determinism. He averred that the monads (the simple, indivisible elements) seek their own
perfection through a ‘preestablished harmony’ instituted by God ‘the Prime Monad’.
Psychological determinism posits that we all possess certain mental qualities which govern our
life. Freud, with his psychoanalytic theory, expressed a form of psychological determinism that
all we do is due to mental factors some of which we are conscious but most of them are beyond
our conscious states. Biological determinism is the idea that all behaviour, belief, and desire are
fixed by our genetic endowment.
In summary we can say that in general, determinism is a doctrine which in some way holds the
stance that there is no such thing as free choice for any choice that we make is already
conditioned by a set of causes or is settled prior to our act of choosing. As such, the person
cannot be held morally accountable or responsible for his/her act.
Indeterminism
Indeterminism is a theory, though not denying the influence of behavioural patterns and certain
extrinsic forces on human actions, insists on the reality of free will or the capacity of the humans
to make a free choice. This view asserts that humans are an exception to the rigid determinism
that occurs in nature. Indeterminists accept the principle of causality but aver that human free
will or human choices are not totally bound by the causal law. Some of the proponents of this
view try to seek support for their claim by appealing to the Physicist Werner Heisenberg’s
‘Principle of Indeterminacy’ which shows that randomness in the universe is compatible with
science. He questions whether it is possible to determine an objective framework through which
one can distinguish cause from effect. But one must also note that according to some other
thinkers Heisenberg’s principle has little to do with choice or free will. Attempts have been also
made to use the indeterminism of the latest theory of quantum mechanics, which postulates
irreducible physical indeterminacy, to buttress the claim that human actions to a great extent are
grounded in free will.
Efforts have been made to reconcile free will with determinism by introducing the theory of soft
determinism. This doctrine posits humans are free from external coercion and as such are
indetermined but they cannot make a free choice against their individual characters. In other
words it asserts that a person is free physically but psychologically he/she is determined.
However this reconciliatory tone too has been questioned: if a person is internally or
psychologically determined can we really hold that the person is free?
Another theory, which so to say strives to provide a mediating proposal to the problem of
determinism and free will, is that of self-determinism. It accepts the causality principle and
affirms that nothing can happen without a cause. Hence our so called free acts are also caused
but they are caused by the very person as a self-governing or free agent, so that agent could have
acted otherwise and freely choose not to do so. Self-determinist believes that though humans are
strongly influenced by the motives and as such are called to deliberate between them, still they
are not necessitated by them either way, they can make their own choices.
8
In concluding this section on determinism and indeterminism one has to note that the position or
the view one holds will obviously affect one’s interpretation of moral responsibility or
accountability.
Human action is explained as an act which proceeds from prior knowledge and free will. It
differs from ‘acts of humans’ which result without the intervention of intellect and free will and
as such normally they are beyond human control. From the understanding of human action we
deduce the two constituent principles viz, volitive and intellectual which are essential in its
constitution. The human action is not a spontaneous reaction but rather a gradual process
beginning in the mind and ending by producing certain external consequences. In this process it
encounters certain obstacles which obstruct the imputablility of the agent performing the act. The
morality of the human action depends on three main determinants: object, circumstances and
intention. The theories of determinism and indeterminism are closely related to the analysis of
human action.
Preestablished Harmony: It is a term from art which is used by Leibniz. It refers to the order in
the monads that is installed by God in advance in such a way that each subsequent state is a
consequence of the preceding one.
Universal Skepticism: It is elucidated as the philosophical doctrine which doubts that we can
have any certitude in knowledge
9
3.9 FURTHER READINGS AND REFERENCES
Billington, Ray. Living Philosophy: An Introduction to Moral Thought (3rd ed.). London:
Routledge, 2003.
Composta, Dario. Moral Philosophy and Social Ethics. Bangalore: TPI, 2000.
Frankena, William. Ethics (2nd ed.). New Jersey: Prentice Hall Inc., 1973.
Gonsalves, Milton A. Fagothey’s Right and Reason (7th ed.). London: The C. V. Mosby
Company, 1981.
Johnson, Oliver A. Ethics: Selection from Classical and Contemporary Writers (3rd ed.). New
York: Holt, Rhinehart and Winston, Inc., 1974.
Kadankavil, Thomas. Ethical World: A Study on the Ethical Thought in the East and the West.
Bangalore: Dharmaram Publications, 1995.
Kane, Robert. The Significance of Free Will. New York: Oxford University Press, 1996.
Sinha, Jadunath. A Manual of Ethics. Calcutta: New Central Book Agency, 1986.
Taylor, Paul W. Problems of Moral Philosophy: An Introduction to Ethics (2nd ed.). California:
Dickenson Publishing Company, Inc., 1972.
Williams, Clifford. Free Will and Determinism: A Dialogue. Indianapolis: Hackett Publishing
Co., 1980.
1. Human act is elucidated as that act which an agent performs with knowledge and free will. It
is an act which results from the integration of reason and will and so is not determined. The act is
within the control of the agent and therefore it is distinguished from ‘acts of humans’ over which
the agent has no power, for e.g. digestion.
The intellectual and the volitive elements functions in co-operation in the production of human
action. The faculty of willing can make a choice freely for a particular alternative only when the
10
intellect provides adequate knowledge of the aspired object, indicates the action by which the
object is to be pursued and also provides some sort of judgement on the value of the act.
Therefore when we hold a person accountable or responsible for a specific action we presume
that the concerned act was performed knowingly, willingly and freely. Any sort of compulsion
reduces the voluntariness of the action and its eventual culpability. At times if the degree of
coercion is extremely high then it can even render an act involuntary.
1. Moralists have outlined three main factors which, to a great extent, define the morality of a
human act. These determinants include: the Object of the act, the Circumstances surrounding
the act, and the End or Intention that the one performing the act has in mind. Object refers to
the effect that an action primarily and directly causes. This is considered as the primary
factor for moral judgement. Circumstances include all the particulars, surrounding the human
action, which have somehow the capacity to affect its morality. The end or intention refers to
the reason or the purpose for which the agent chooses to perform a particular action. So while
judging the morality of a particular action all these three factors are to be evaluated not in
isolation but in an integral framework.
2. A voluntary human action is believed to be performed by an agent with prior knowledge and
free will. Is human will really free? This is a question that is deliberated by the ethical
thinkers for a long time without arriving at an exhaustive solution which is agreed by all
without any reservation. The determinists, basing themselves on the metaphysical principle
that uncaused event is impossible, appear to be convinced that human action is wholly
controlled by preceding events. Their stand is rather strengthened by the scientific temper
which is primarily based on the principle of causality which leaves no room for any chance
or ‘free’ happening. On the other hand indeterminists, without denying the principle of
causality, aver that humans are specifically blessed with the capacity of free will and that
their choices are not totally bound by the causal law. Self determinism seems to be a midway
path between the two extremes. It affirms that nothing happens without a cause. Even our so
called free acts are caused by the very person as a self-governing or free agent who chooses
to act in that particular way.
11