A. J. Ayer
A. J. Ayer
s ^
OSWALD HANFLING
Ayer
THE
GREAT
PHILOSOPHERS
Consulting Editors
Ray Monk and Frederic Raphael
Oswald Hanfling
A.J. AVER
PHCENIX
A PHOENIX PAPERBACK
8
is meaning?' The criterion is, however, dedudhle from the
principle. If meaning is identified with method of verifica-
tion, then it follows that if there is no method of
verification - if the statement is not verifiable - then it
must be devoid of meaning. There is, however, no
entailment in the other direction, so that one may put
forward the criterion without commitment to the princ-
iple. This was the case with Ayer, though his terminology
is not always consistent (he sometimes referred to his
criterion as 'the principle of verification'). The verification
principle, as advocated by members of the Vienna Circle,
calls for separate discussion, but this will not be our
concern.
The first question that may occur to one on reading the
above passage from Ayer is why, or whether, one should
accept his criterion. That there is a connection between
meaning and verification would hardly be doubted. A
good way of finding out what, if anything, a person
means by a given statement is, indeed, to ask what 'would
lead him ... to accept [it] as being true, or reject it as being
false'. And if the answer is 'Nothing', then we might
perhaps conclude that, as far as he is concerned, the
statement is meaningless. But is this necessarily so? One
of those who refused to accept the criterion was Father
Copleston, who held certain religious beliefs that would
hot satisfy it. In a debate broadcast in 1949, Ayer tried
to persuade Copleston of the error of his position.
He invented the word 'drogulus' for this purpose.
10
reference to the arguments in which it was embedded; but
perhaps it would not seem meaningless to someone who
had read those arguments - even if it failed to satisfy
Ayer's criterion.
In 1946 there appeared a second edition of Ayer's book,
with a substantial introduction in which he modified
several of its main tenets. In the following extract he
conceded that metaphysics cannot be disposed of as easily
as he had thought; butfirsthe addressed the fundamental
question about the status of his criterion: what reason is
there for accepting it? Is it true to what we actually mean
by 'meaning'?
11
but as a definition, it is not supposed to be entirely
arbitrary. It is indeed open to anyone to adopt a
different criterion of meaning and so to produce an
alternative definition which may very well correspond
to one of the ways in which the word 'meaning' is
commonly used. And if a statement satisfied such a
criterion, there is, no doubt, some proper use of the
word 'understanding' in which it would be capable of
being understood. Nevertheless, I think that, unless it
satisfied the principle of verification, it would not be
capable of being understood in the sense in which
either scientific hypotheses or common-sense state-
ments are habitually understood. I confess, however,
that it now seems to me unlikely that any metaphysi-
dan would yield to a claim of this kind; and although I
should still defend the use of the criterion of verifiability
as a methodological principle, I realize that for the
effective elimination of metaphysics it needs to be
supported by detailed analyses of particular meta-
physical arguments. <LTL 20-1)
12
terion is put forward as a methodological principle, for
such a principle cannot be described (any more than a
suggestion or a proposal) as true or false; and neither,
therefore, can it be subject to the test of verifiability.
But this still leaves the question: should we accept
Ayer's proposal? Is his 'methodological principle' a good
one - one that we ought to endorse? Ayer tells us that he
would still 'defend the use of the criterion', but he does
not say what the defence would be. Perhaps it can be
argued, in favour of the criterion, that it is useful to
distinguish the two kinds of statement on the lines
suggested, even if the description of one of them as
'meaningless' is withdrawn. But how exactly is the
criterion to be formulated and applied? This question is
not as straightforward as it may seem.
13
This is SO; according to Ayer, because of a discrepancy
between the scope of such propositions and the observa-
tions on which they are based. The number of observa-
tions is, necessarily, finite; but the statements in question
are not restricted to afinitenumber of instances. ('All men
are mortal' does not refer only to people observed so far.)
Whether it follows that such statements 'cannot be
established with certainty' is debatable, but Ayer, like
many others, took it to be so. But then, if to verify is to
'establish with certainty', it will follow that these state-
ments, not being verifiable, must be declared 'not literally
significant', along with those of metaphysics.
To acconmiodate such statements, Ayer introduced a
distinction between 'strong' and 'weak' verification. 'A
proposition is ... verifiable in the strong sense of the term,
if, and only if, its truth could be conclusively established
... But it is verifiable in the weak sense if it is possible for
experience to render it probable' (LTL 50). He would settle
for verification in the weak sense. 'It is only if a negative
answer must be given' to the question of weak verification
'that we conclude that the statement under consideration
is nonsensical' (LTL 52). To make his position clear, he
introduced the term 'experiential proposition'.
14
propositions can be deduced from it in conjunction
with certain other premises without being deducible
from those other premises alone. (LTL 52)
15
There are other difficulties, however. Having introduced
the requirement of 'weak' verifiability, Ayer commented
that it 'seems liberal enough' (LTL 52) to accommodate
laws of nature; but in his new introduction he had to
concede (in view of an objection from Isaiah Berlin) that
'in fact it is far too liberal, since it allows meaning to any
statement whatsoever' (LTL 15). To illustrate this point he
invented a clearly nonsensical statement.
16
VERIFICATION AND ANALYSIS
17
quences, then to assert the existence of a god' will mean
no more than that - though, as he went on to observe, 'no
religious man would admit that this was all he intended
to assert' (LTL 152). Again,
18
material thing] is always equivalent to saying something
about [sense-contents] (LTL 185).
What did Ayer mean by 'sense-contents'? In LTL, he
gave little attention to this question. He introduced the
term by reference to the 'ideas' of Locke and Berkeley; but
since their use of this term is notoriously obscure and
controversial, it hardly throws light on the difficulty.
What is clear is that the term in question is to stand for
something with which an observer is more directly related
than he is with ordinary objects, so that his knowledge of
the latter is either inferential (he infers that there is a table
before him from the occurrence of suitable sense-con-
tents) or - as in the passage quoted above - it is a matter of
'logical construction' (to say that there is a table before
him is to say that sense-contents X, Y and Z are occurring
or will occur). But Ayer did not explain what kinds of
occurrences or entities X, Y and Z would be.
In later writings he was more sensitive to the need for
explaining and justifying his talk of sense-contents or
sense-data. In The Problem of Knowledge he devoted a
section to what he called 'the legitimacy of sense-data' (PK
105), in which he examined arguments for and against
introducing such terminology, concluding that 'the argu-
ment from illusion' provides the strongest reason in
favour of it. This argument proceeds from the premise
that things sometimes seem to be otherwise than they
really are (there seems to be an oasis before me, but it is
only a mirage). It is then pointed out that the experience
of seeing (say) a mirage is just like the experience of seeing
19
the real thing; and from this it is concluded that 'when-
ever anyone perceives, or thinks that he perceives, a
physical object, it must then seem to him that he perceives
something or other' (PK 104). The final step is tp 'pass
from "it seems to me that I perceive x" to "I perceive a
seeming-;^", with the implication that there is a seeming-;i^
which I perceive' (PK 105). It turns out, then, that the
direct objects of perception - which in LTL he had called
'sense-contents' - are the 'seeming'-objects to which the
argument from illusion appears to lead.
One difficulty of this line of argument may be men-
tioned here. The claim that 'whenever anyone perceives
... a physical object, it must then seem to him that he
perceives something or other' would not normally be
recognized. On the contrary, 'it seems to him that he
perceives a chair' would be held to imply that he does not
really perceive a chair. Some argument is needed to
defend Ayer's reversal of the logic of these expressions as
normally understood.
Let us turn to another aspect of the programme of LTL.
The task that Ayer set himself was to show that all
genuine statements could be analysed into statements
about sense-contents. Whatever could not be so analysed
must be consigned to some other category than that of
genuine statement. (This, it turned out, was what the
criterion of verifiability really amounted to.) 'Our
remarks', he wrote, 'apply to all empirical propositions
without exception, whether they are singular, or particu-
lar, or universal. Every [such] proposition is a rule for the
20
anticipation of future experience [of sense-contents]' (LTL
134).
But why 'a riile for the anticipation', etc.? This brings us
to phenomenalism - the view that apparently categorical
statements about material things ('Here is a table', 'The
table is white', etc.) are to be analysed in hypothetical
terms ('If anyone looks this way, he will experience sense-
contents X, Y and Z'; or 'If anyone were to look this way,
he would', etc.). It is in this sense that the analysis into
sense-contents must be understood: otherwise, it appears,
it might have the absurd consequence of consigning
ordinary ideas about tables and chairs to the class of
metaphysical 'nonsense'. We normally think of such
objects as enduring at times when they are not imder
observation, but this belief cannot be tested by observa-
tion. It is here that phenomenalism, with its use of
hypothetical statements, must come to the rescue.
21
the allegations of 'metaphysics', is the advantage of
representing the meaning of our statements in this way?
According to Ayer, it 'serves to increase our understanding
of the sentences in which we refer to material things' (LTL
91). He conceded that 'there is of course a sense in which
we already understand such sentences ... as "This is a
table", or "Pennies are round"', but, he argued, we
22
His argument in the following extract is not the 'argu-
ment from illusion'; it is an argument about the various
and complex implications of such statements as 'Here is a
table'.
23
more than one observer and it has to be capable of
existing unperceived. In addition, it has to occupy a
position or series of positions in three-dimensional
space and to endure throughout a period of time ...
Neither is it only a question of the validity of these
general assumptions. Our perceptual judgements are
seldom indefinite, in the sense that we claim only to
perceive a physical object of some sort or other. In the
normal way, we identify it as a thing of some specific
kind, and this brings in further assumptions, as, for
example, that the object is solid, or flexible, or that it is
not hollow. These further assumptions may relate to
the purposes which the object serves, as when we
identify something as a pen-knife, or a telephone: they
may relate to its physical constitution, as in the
identification of an object as an orange or an apple,
which denies its being made of wax. They may
presume on the deliverances of other senses, as when
our descriptions of an object which we believe our-
selves to be seeing or touching carries implications
about the way in which it tastes or sounds or smells.
But now can it seriously be maintained that all this
can fall within the content of a single act of percep-
tion? Can my present view of the table, considered
purely in itself as a fleeting visual experience, conceiv-
ably guarantee that I am seeing something that is also
tangible, or visible to other observers? Can it guarantee
even that I am seeing something which exists at any
other time than this, let alone something that is made
of such and such materials, or endowed with such and
24
such causal properties, or serving such and such a
purpose? I think it evident that it cannot. But if these
conclusions are not logically guaranteed by the con-
tent of my present visual experience, one is surely
entitled to say that they go beyond it, and just this is
what I take to be meant by saying that my judgement
that this is a table embodies an inference. It embodies
an inference, not in the sense that it results from any
conscious process of reasoning, but just in the sense
that it affirms more than can logically be entailed by
any strict account of the experience on which it is
based. What I mean here by a strict account Is one that
is tailored to the experience, in that it describes the
quality of what is sensibly presented/ without carrying
any further implications of any sort. In the normal way,
we do not formulate such propositions because we are
interested not in the data as such, but in the interpreta-
tions which we have learned to put upon them. I
cannot, however, see any logical reason why they
should not be formulable.
If I am right on this point, the naive realists are
wrong in so far as they deny that our ordinary
judgements of perception are susceptible of analysis, or
deny that they embody inferences which can be made
explicit. (CQ 79-81)
25
those judgements 'are susceptible of analysis'? Are we to
suppose that 'Here is a table' can be translated into a set of
statements about the occurrence of sense-contents (or
'percepts') of the kind mentioned? If this is what he
thought in LTL, it was no longer so now.
26
be at all plausible, it has to draw on possible as well as
actual percepts, with the result that most of the
propositions which render its account of the world will
take the form of unfulfilled conditionals. They will state
that if such and such conditions, which are not in fact
realized, were to be so, then such and such percepts
would occur. But apart from the obvious difficulty of
giving a sufficient description of the conditions in
purely sensory terms, I no longer think that such
conditional statements are suitable to play this part.
(CQ 106-7)
27
STATEMENTS ABOUT THE PAST
28
physical sense of the terai' (LTL 135). But what makes the
analysis objectionable, and indeed highly paradoxical, is
not that the past is 'somehow objectively there': it is that
it makes no allowance for the distinction between reality
and report: between 'Caesar crossed the Rubicon' and
'Such and such history books say that Caesar crossed the
Rubicon'.
'I do not see', he argued, 'how else our "knowledge of
the past" is to be analysed.' Here, as elsewhere, the
requirement of analysis is more stringent than the original
criterion of verifiability. Asked how I would verify the
statement about Caesar, or what empirical observation
would 'lead me to accept it as being true', I could certainly
answer by reference to a reputable history book, and in
that way establish the credentials of the statement as
meaningful in accordance with the original criterion. But,
as we saw, that criterion had, in the face of certain
difficulties, to give way to the requirement of analysis,
which in its turn produced difficulties including that
about the past.
Here again Ayer showed himself more sensitive in the
second edition. He no longer thought that statements
about the past were really about experiences that would or
might be had in the future, though he still maintained
that such statements could 'be analysed in phenomenal
terms'. The analysis, as now conceived, would be in terms
of sense-contents that the speaker would have experi-
enced if he had been present. A difficulty about this
analysis was, he conceded, that 'these conditions never
can be fulfilled; for they require of the observer that he
29
should occupy a temporal position that ex hypothesi he
does not' (LTL 25). He did not, however, regard this
difficulty as serious, since, he claimed, we could suppose
that the observer occupied a different temporal position
just as we can suppose that he occupies 'a different spatial
position'. But is this true? 1 can suppose that 1 were now in
Cambridge and not in Oxford, but can I suppose that I
was present when Caesar crossed the Rubicon? Could
someone who was present then have been meV
Forty-odd years later Ayer was still trying to analyse
statements about the past on the lines of LTL. Having
reviewed a number of alternatives, he confessed that he
found the position in which he found himself 'counterin-
tuitive'. In the following passage he deals first with
historical statements and then with personal memories
about the recent past.
30
that he will remember ('have a memory') of the leaves
rustling. But it is quite likely that he will not. We all make
thousands of more or less trivial observations that pass
from our minds quite soon. In that case, must we say that
they did not take place - or that it is meaningless to
suppose that some did?
On the other hand, suppose that Ayer does remember
what happened the day before. In that case 'Ayer remem-
bers that the leaves rustled' will be true. But is this a
statement about a present or future experience? This is
what Ayer must hold, in accordance with the phenomen-
alist analysis. (That is why he speaks, rather oddly, of
'having such and such a memory' rather than of remem-
bering.) In LTL he had claimed that to say of a person that
he remembers 'is to say merely that some of [his] sense-
experiences . . . contain memory images which cor-
respond to the sense-contents which have previously
occurred in the sense-history' of that person (LTL 166).
But one may remember that the leaves rustled without
having such images; and conversely, one may have such
images without remembering that the leaves rustled: one
may be imagining this as opposed to remembering it. (A
similar problem was raised, but not solved, by David
Hume in the eighteenth century.) An alternative view of
memory is that when we say 'Ayer remembers that the
leaves rustled' we are not speaking of the present occur-
rence of images (or anything else); we are saying, rather,
that (a) Ayer knows that the leaves rustled, and (b) he
knows this because he heard them rustling at the time.
31
MYSELF AND OTHERS
32
logically obliged to be a solipsist - that is, to hold that
no other people besides himself exist, or at any rate
that there is no good reason to suppose [this]... For it
follows from his prennises, so it will be argued, that the
sense-experiences of another person cannot possibly
form part of his own experience. (LTL 169)
33
He hastened to asstire the reader that his analysis did not
fail to do justice to the reality of other people.
34
contents do occur In his sense-history gives him a good
reason for believing that there are other conscious
beings besides himself. And thus we see that the
philosophical problem of 'our knowledge of other
people' is not the insoluble, and, indeed, fictitious,
problem of establishing by argument the existence
of entities which are altogether unobservable, but
is simply the problem of indicating the way In which
a certain type of hypothesis is empirically verified.
(LTL 171-2)
35
the statements which I make about my feelings cannot
have the same meaning for any other person as they
have for me. [And therefore] if someone asks me
whether I am in pain and I answer that I am, my reply,
as / understand it, is not an answer to his question. For I
am reporting the occurrence of a certain feeling;
whereas, so far as he was concerned, his question
could only have been a question about my physical
condition. So also, if he says that my reply is false, he is
not strictly contradicting me: for ail that he can be
denying is that I exhibited the proper signs of pain, and
this is not what I asserted. (PK 214-15)
36
which account for the same behaviour in terms of
different mental states rather than hypotheses which
deny to others any mental life at all. (CQ 134)
37
beyond the bounds of meaningful discourse as he himself
had defined it.
38
Bretons are Europeans, I am not describing any nnatter
of fact. But I am showing that in the statement that all
Bretons are Frechmen, and all Frenchmen Europeans,
the further statement that all Bretons are Europeans is
implicitly contained. And I am thereby indicating the
convention which governs our usage of the words 'if
and 'all'.
We see, then, that there is a sense in which analytic
propositions do give us new knowledge. They call
attention to linguistic usages, of which we might
otherwise not be conscious, and they reveal unsus-
pected implications in our assertions and beliefs.
But we can see also that there is a sense in which they
may be said to add nothing to our knowledge. For they
tell us only what we may be said to know already.
(LTL106)
39
since the words are, indeed, synonymous. But can the
same be said about mathematical equations? 7 + 5' and
'12' are mathematically equivalent, but they cannot
properly be described as 'synonymous'. Douze is synonym-
ous with 'twelve', '7 + 5' is not. If '7 + 5 = 12' adds nothing
to our knowledge, it is not because the expressions are
synonymous, but because we are most unlikely to be
ignorant of the truth of this statement. But how would
this apply to less obvious mathematical truths? According
to Ayer, his treatment of '7 + 5 = 12' would also hold good
for such statements as '91 x 79 = 7189', even though here
we have to 'resort to calculation ... to assure ourselves that
[these expressions] are s)monymous' (LTL 114).
In the case of such statements as this, however, it
cannot even be claimed that they 'add nothing to our
knowledge' (let alone that the expressions in them 'are
synonymous'). While anyone acquainted with the mean-
ings of 'oculist' and 'eye-doctor' must be aware that an
oculist is an eye-doctor, it is quite possible for someone
acquainted with the meanings of '91', 'x', '79', etc. to be
ignorant of the product of these numbers. He may then
learn what the answer is (thus 'adding to his knowledge'),
either by being informed of it or by working it out for
himself.
Ayer was not unaware of this difficulty. He would need,
he said, to 'explain how a proposition which is empty of
all factual content can be true and useful and surprising'
(LTL 97). He thought he could do so as follows.
40
depends, like their usefulness, on the limitations of our
reason. A being whose intellect was infinitely powerful
would take no interest in logic and mathematics. For
he would be able to see at a glance everything that his
definitions implied, and, accordingly, could never learn
anything from logical inference which he was not fully
conscious of already. But our intellects are not of this
order. It is only a minute proportion of the conse-
quences of our definitions that we are able to detect
at a glance. Even so simple a tautology as '91 x 79 =
7189' is beyond the scope of our immediate apprehen-
sion. (LTL 114)
41
This conversation, held in 1968, was recalled by Quesada
when writing his contribution to The Philosophy of A.J.
Ayer in the late 1980s. Responding to that contribution,
Ayer confessed: '1 have not yet wholly freed myself from
[my] perplexity' on this subject." Nevertheless, having
added some fresh arguments, he concluded: 'I adhere to
the line that I took in Language, Truth and Logic all those
years ago.'^^ 'A fairly competent mathematician', he
observed, 'can tell at a glance that 37 + 37 = 74. He has to
use pen and paper to discover that 37 x 37 = 1369.'^^ Yet,
he argued, 'since multiplication is definable in terms of
addition, it is absurd to put these propositions into
separate categories'.
But from the point of view of the programme of LTL,
there is good reason for putting them into separate
categories. The essential question there, as we saw, is
whether mathematical statements can be informative -
whether they have 'factual content' or merely 'tell us what
we already know'. According to the empiricism of Ayer
and others, only empirical statements can be informative.
But the informative capacity of '37 x 37 = 1369' is not put
into doubt by the claim that multiplication is definable in
terms of addition. (It may be worth pointing out that
addition itself can be informative: this is so where the
sums to be added are large or many.)
A relevant distinction can be made by reference to
knowledge of meanings. Let us take '2 + 2 = 4' as an
example. Anyone who understands the meaning of this
sentence must recognize that what it says is true. But this
is not so when we turn to '37 x 37 = 1369': in thi§ case
42
knowledge of meaning does not entail knowledge that
the statement is true, and that is why the statement
can be informative. It is true that there is a way of arriving
at this information which is different from that of
arriving at empirical information, but this difference is not
captured by Ayer's account. (I have preferred '2 + 2 = 4' to
Ayer's '37 + 37 = 74', because recognition of the latter
may depend, as he puts it, on being 'a fairly competent
mathematician'.)
43
someone, 'You acted wrongly in stealing that money/1
am not stating anything more than if I had simply said,
'You stole that money/ In adding that this action is
wrong I am not making any further statement about it.
I am simply evincing my moral disapproval of it It is as
if I had said, 'You stole that money/ in a peculiar tone
of horror, or written it with the addition of some
special exclamation marks. The tone, or the exclama-
tion marks, adds nothing to the literal meaning of the
sentence. It merely serves to show that the expression
of it is attended by certain feelings in the speaker.
If now I generalize my previous statement and say,
'Stealing money is wrong,' I produce a sentence which
has no factual meaning - that is, expresses no
proposition which can be either true or false. It is as if I
had written 'Stealing money!!' - where the shape and
thickness of the exclamation marks show, by a suitable
convention, that a special sort of moral disapproval is
the feeling which is being expressed. It is clear that
there is nothing said here which can be true or false.
(LTL142)
44
there is no reason why both these statements should
not be true. (LTL 146)
45
was something to be done in moral philosophy, but it was
not much.
46
I ought to have done something else'. And in a court of
law it may be important to establish whether the defend-
ant knew he was doing wrong.
In this matter, as in others, Ayer was more sensitive in
later writings to the dangers of departing from the
ordinary uses of words. 'Certainly', he admitted in an
essay of 1949,
47
not what it really is, or 'really' is what it really is not,
that we do not, for example, 'really' see chairs and
tables, whereas there is a perfectly good and familiar
sense in which we really do ... it should not always be
assumed that he is merely making a mistake. Very often
what he is doing, although he may not know it, is to
recommend a new way of speaking, not just for
amusement, but because he thinks that the old, the
socially correct, way of speaking is logically misleading,
or that his own proposal brings out certain points more
clearly. Thus, in the present instance, it is no doubt
correct to say that the moralist does make statements,
and, what is more, statements of fact, statements of
ethical fact ... But when one considers how these
ethical statements are actually used, it may be found
that they function so very differently from other, types
of statement that it is advisable to put them into a
separate category altogether; either to say that they
are not to be counted as statements at all, or, if this
proves inconvenient, at least to say that they do not
express propositions, and consequently that there are
no ethical facts ... It is merely a matter of laying down
a usage of the words 'propositions' and 'fact', accord-
ing to which only propositions express facts and ethical
statements fall outside the class of propositions. This
may seem to be an arbitrary procedure, but I hope to
show that there are good reasons for adopting it. And
once these reasons are admitted the purely verbal
point is not of any great importance. If someone still
wishes to say that ethical statements are statements of
48
fact, only it is a queer sort of fact, he is welcome to do
so. So long as he accepts our grounds for saying that
they are not statements of fact, it is simply a question
of how widely or loosely we want to use the word
'fact'. My own view is that it is preferable so to use it as
to exclude ethical judgements, but it must not be
inferred from this that I am treating them with
disrespect. The only relevant consideration is that of
clarity. (MJ 232-3)
49
and 'know' are improper, would be beneficial. (The
question is similar to that which arose about accepting the
criterion of verifiability as a 'methodological principle'.)
The implication at the end of the passage is that the
new way of speaking would have the advantage of clarity;
but is this really so? What is impprtant is to bring
out the differences between moral and empirical
statements (which Ayer proceeded to do by means of
a detailed example). Thus one might draw attention to
the difference between 'How do you know?' in the cases
of 'He took the money' and 'He acted wrongly'. But it
is not clear what could be achieved by introducing a
new way of talking which, in any case, could not displace
the existing one.
50
CONCLUSION
51
ABBREVIATIONS
used to refer to works by Ayer
52
NOTES
3. Ibid., p. 7.
8. Ibid., p. 598.
9. Ibid., p. 467.
53
C:oN.sui;nN(; KUITORS:
R A Y M O N K A N D FRK.DERK: R A P I I A E I
Cover painting":
Swinging by VVassiiy
Kandin.sky, courtesy of the
T i t e Gallery