Dharmakirti:refutation of Theism PDF
Dharmakirti:refutation of Theism PDF
Your use of the JSTOR archive indicates your acceptance of the Terms & Conditions of Use, available at .
http://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsp
JSTOR is a not-for-profit service that helps scholars, researchers, and students discover, use, and build upon a wide range of
content in a trusted digital archive. We use information technology and tools to increase productivity and facilitate new forms
of scholarship. For more information about JSTOR, please contact [email protected].
University of Hawai'i Press is collaborating with JSTOR to digitize, preserve and extend access to Philosophy
East and West.
http://www.jstor.org
Roger Jackson Dharmakirti's refutation of theism
I. INTRODUCTION
Indian civilization, no less than that of the West, is haunted by the concept of
God, and Indian philosophical writing, no less than the works of Aquinas,
Descartes, Kant, or Hume, has as one of its important concerns the existence or
nonexistence of an omniscient, eternal, independent, benevolent being who
creates and/or designs the cosmos. Despite Lin Yutang's description of India as a
nation "intoxicated with God," 1 Indian skepticism about such a being goes back
very far indeed,2 and explicit arguments against theism find an important place in
the writings of Buddhism, Jainism, and Mimamsa (as they must have in the lost
writings of Carvaka), while God's importance or even existence for early Sam-
khya, Nyaya, and Vaisesika is at best moot.3 Indeed, the only Indian philosoph-
ical systems that are explicitly theistic are Vedanta, Yoga, and later, Nyaya-
Vaisesika. It undoubtedly is due to the overwhelming preference for Vedanta
among modern exponents of Indian philosophy that Indian tradition so often is
presented through theistically-shaded lenses, and it is not incorrect to assert that,
in general, Indian civilization has become more theistic during the same period in
which the West has become less so. Still, this should not blind us to the fact that as
recently as five hundred years ago thinkers like the Jaina Gunaratna were
adducing sharp and original arguments against theistic assertions, and that even
today the unanimity of Indian belief in God may not be as thoroughgoing as
most swamis and scholars would have us believe.4
As might be expected, arguments for the existence or nonexistence of the being
variously called purusa, brahman,paramatman, or isvara, or by the name of one
or another sectarian deity, increased in sophistication as methods of philosoph-
ical discussion grew more complex and precise. Sometime around the middle of
the first millennium A.D. a philosophical watershed was reached wherein the
various Indian schools arrived at least at a broad consensus on the criteria for
valid and invalid formal inferences, anumdna, and proper and improper argu-
mentative modes, tarka. In principle, at least, this permitted intersystemic debate
on the basis of commonly accepted "logical" canons, and thus prompted the
hope that arguments on fundamental philosophical issues might indeed be
capable of resolution. In general, before the development of these canons, Indian
philosophical arguments that were not simply dogmatic were analogical or
dialectical in form; arguments after the canons were developed still employed
illustrative analogies and dialectical dilemmas, but within the much more care-
fully articulated framework of what is sometimes called the Indian "syllogism."
Among those contributing greatly to the development of generally acceptable
II. PHILOSOPHICALTHEISMBEFOREDHARMAKIRTI
Indian speculation about the cosmos, of course, goes back as far as the later
sections of the .Rgveda,where the first cause is said to be, for example, visvakar-
man ("the all-maker"),10 or purusa ("the person"),11 or prajdpati ("the lord of
creatures"),12or tadekam ("the one").13 The divine power, or supreme purusa,
first is referred to as isvara ("the lord") in the Atharvaveda,14while the Brah-
manas and Aranyakas continue Vedic speculations regarding prajapati and
visvakarmanand introduce the concepts of brahmanand brahmd. 5 In most of
these accounts, the discussion of the first cause is couched in mythological
narrative; little real attempt is made to justify the concepts philosophically,
though lurking in the background are unstated assumptions about limiting
principles and simplicity of explanation. Discussions of the first cause in the
various Upanisads focus on the concept of brahman(also referredto as atman or
paramdtman),whose reality as the source and (most often) the substance of the
cosmos is inferredusually through a reductive process that moves from change to
permanence, multiplicity to unity, complexity to simplicity, materiality to spiri-
tuality, and grossness to subtlety.16The earlier, more "monistic" Upanisads tend
to regard brahmanas an impersonal principle that simply becomes the cosmos
(while at the same time remaining in some way transcendent to it); in later
Upanisads, such as the Svetdsvatara, brahmanis personalized-at least to the
point where it has a creative aspect that is responsible for originating the cosmos
and that can be addressed as "lord" (Isa, isvara), or "deity" (deva),17or even as
Rudra. The Svetdsvatara actually lists non-Vedic explanations of the cosmos,
such as svabhdva(nature), kala (time), niyata (fate), yadrccha (chance), and so
forth, but it rejects them out of hand, simply asserting that brahman,rather than
any of these, is the true explanatory principle.18 The BhagavadgTtdfurther
personalizes the first cause by identifying its ultimate nature with the divine
person of Visnu,19 but, again, the fact is asserted rather than argued, and the
appeal is aimed more at the imagination and emotions than at rationality.
It is only with the development of the classical darsanasin the last centuries B.C.
or the first centuries A.D. that theism, widespread as it had become religiously,
began to receive philosophicaljustification. If we take the term "theism" in the
broad sense in which I am using it-comprising any theory that attributes the
creation and/or ordering of the cosmos to one source, whether personal or
impersonal-then there are three darsanas that can be said to be "theistic":
Vedanta, Yoga, and Nyaya.
The Brahmasutrasof Badarayana did not receive their most important advaita
commentaries until Gaudapada and Safikara, both of whom probably postdate
Dharmakirti,20but the sutras themselves have as one of their central concerns to
establish that brahmanis the source and substance of the cosmos.21 Brahmanis
asserted to be that on which the world is dependent,22 the material cause of all
318 Jackson
Prasatapada (sixth century) advanced the discussion still further in his Padarth-
adharmasamgrahaby arguing that tsvara is necessary as the conscious impeller
of the unseen (adrsta) force that regulates karman, and as that which impels
atoms to movement and combination at the end of the universe's dormancy
(pralaya).32
The last important pre-Dharmakirti Naiyayika (although by now it is possible
to speak of Nyaya-Vaisesika) was Uddyotakara, who probably flourished in the
period between Dignaga and Dharmakirti (late sixth or early seventh century). In
his Nyayavdrttika, he goes beyond arguing for Tsvaraon grounds peculiar to
Nyaya-Vaisesika and seeks to establish his existence on more general grounds.
Isvara, Uddyotakara asserts, is the instrumental cause (nimittakdrana)of things,
because he assists beings in reaping the fruits of their actions. ITvarafurther is
necessary as an adjunct to material results, because all results must be preceded
by conscious action, as a hatchet requires a wielder in order to function, or the
flow of milk to a calf requires the cow's intention. Further, although Tsvarais a
permanent, unaltering entity, he can cause impermanent entities, because we see
that, for example, spun yarn, though unmoving, is the cause of a movable
garment. Isvara is not the creator of the eternal atoms that comprise the material
world; his "creation," therefore, is neither ex nihilo nor out of himself. Rather, he
fashions the preexistent "material" into a cosmos in response to the necessary
fruition of the dharma and adharma of beings. Finally, tsvara's power and
consciousness are eternal, omnipresent, and unlimited, for events throughout the
entire extent of space and time require a conscious agent as their instrumental
cause; since that cause, Tsvara,can effect all results, his power is unlimited,
and since he is conscious effector of all results, he must, by definition, be
omniscient.33
III. PRE-DHARMAKIRTIBUDDHIST ATTACKSON THEISM
will mention only the Yogacdrabhumiof Asafiga, which argues that (a) if isvara
has a reason for creation, then that reason is the real cause, whereas if he has
none, then he cannot be motivated to become a cause; (b) if isvarais immanent in
the cosmos, then he cannot stand outside as its creator, whereas if he is not
immanent in it, then he has no relation to it, and so cannot create it; (c) if isvara
creates intending some purpose, then it must be admitted that there is a purpose
he has not yet fulfilled; and (d) if creation depends on Tsvara'swill alone, then
everything must arise simultaneously, while if it depends on an isvara who is
assisted, then he is not the unique cause.51
One final pre-Dharmakirti text worthy of brief mention is the Tarkajvaldof
Bhavaviveka, or Bhavya (sixth century), whose discussion of isvara52 shows at
least a rudimentaryawareness of attempts to prove isvarainferentiallyand of the
pitfalls entailed by those attempts. Bhavaviveka recites a number of the standard
refutations, noting that the multiple events we observe in the world cannot be
asserted to arise from a unique cause, but rathermust be explained as proceeding
from a multiplicity of karmic conditions, and that isvaracannot be held to be any
more real than a sky-flower or a barren woman's son. He does note that one
possible argument for Tsvarais the syllogism, "The eye and so forth exist as
accompanied (that is, caused) by a maker, because they are arrangedlike a pot."
To this Bhavaviveka's response is that the syllogism is invalid because it proves
what is already proven for the Buddhist, namely, that events have causes-for
the Buddhist, however, the causes are multiple (karman, the elements, parents,
and so forth), not a single arranger. A second syllogism, namely, "Isvara is the
maker of the eye and so forth because he is permanent, unique and unproduced,"
is rejected as unproved (asiddha) because of the absence of any corroborative
example of such an entity. Finally, the syllogism, "(The eye and so forth have)
isvara (as a maker preceding them) because (they are shaped), just as a pot has a
potter as its maker," is rejected on the grounds that a potter is (a) embodied and
(b) impermanent, neither of which is applicable to Tsvara.53
IV. DHARMAKIRTI'S CRITIQUE OF THEISM: CONTEXT
arguments, the most important of which revolve around (a) defining authorita-
tiveness and giving negative and positive examples of beings who embody it, (b)
proving that positive mental qualities such as benevolence can be developed
infinitely, through demonstrating that the mind-body relation is an interactionist
dualism that permits the existence of past and future lives, and (c) showing that
the Four Noble Truths taught by the Buddha are in fact true, and, especially, that
acceptance or rejection of a self (atman) is the key to samsdraand nirvana.As the
nineteenth-century Tibetan commentator Mi pham notes, the proof of past and
future lives paves the way for proving that the Buddha has the causes for being
regarded as authoritative, while the proof that the Four Noble Truths are true
shows us the reason why he is authoritative.56
It is in the first general division of the chapter, that which defines and exem-
plifies authoritativeness, that the rejection of Tsvarais to be found. After defining
pramdna (authoritativeness) in the first six verses57 as uncontradicted, fresh
cognition, Dharmakirti asserts in verse 7 that the Buddha fulfills this definition.
Before demonstrating generally (as he will in verses 29-33) that the Buddha is
authoritative because he knows what is to be rejectedand what accepted (heyopa-
deya) by those intent on liberation, Dharmakirti provides a "nonaccordant
example" for his definition of authoritativeness. This, of course, is Tsvara,whose
authoritativeness, creatorship, and existence are rejected in verses 8-28. The
argument can be broken down into three general sections: (1) verses 8-9 reject
isvara'sauthoritativeness; (2) verses 10-20 are a refutation of a theistic syllogism
purporting to prove that worldly effects must have a conscious cause, and that
cause is Tsvara;and (3) verses 21-28 question the possibility that isvara could be
a causal agent, through a comparison between the characteristics attributed to
Tsvaraand the reality of the causal process. We will consider each of these
arguments in turn, relying primarily upon Dharmakirti's own words. Where
necessary, we will turn for interpretive help to one of the greatest of Tibetan
Pramanavarttika commentators, rGyal tshab dar ma rin chen (1364-1432),58
and, on occasion, to Dharmakirti's own disciple, Devendrabuddhi (or -mati).59
V. DHARMAKIRTI'SREJECTIONOF ISVARA'S AUTHORITATIVENESS
(8-9a:)
There is no permanent authoritative (being),
Because authoritativeness cognizes (functioning) entities;
Because, since objects of knowledge are impermanent,
That (which cognizes them) is unstable;
Because that which is generated consecutively
Cannot be accepted as generated from a permanent (cause);
(And because) it is unsuitable that (a permanent cause) depend on conditions.60
324 Jackson
Note that the explicit object of refutation here is simply a permanent authorita-
tive cognition, which could define not only isvara, but such other non-Buddhist
concepts as dtman,purusa, and so forth. In fact, the term Isvaradoes not appear
until verse 28. Still, isvarais probably the primaryobject of refutation throughout
this discussion, for (a) isvara is the only "permanent authority" mentioned
anywhere in the verses, (b) isvara is clearly indicated as the object of refutation
by Dharmakirti's commentators, and (c) isvara had been singled out by pre-
Dharmakirti Nyaya-Vaisesikas as a permanent being who was the creator of all
effects, hence, by definition, authoritative regarding all effects (omnisicient).
Taking isvaraas the permanent authoritative being who is being rejected,then,
we see that Dharmakirti's argument is as follows. That which any authoritative
cognition cognizes are the functioning entities (vastu) that are what is "real" in
the world. Functioning entities are known to be impermanent, that is, to exist
only momentarily. Any entity, therefore, actually is a succession of momentary
events, each following the other with inconceivable rapidity, and constituting a
"thing" only insofar as there is a certain similarity from one moment to the next.
Since it is objects that (conventionally, at least) generate cognitions, a cognition
of an object only can arise where an object exists. If an object exists only for a
moment, its cognition must be similarly momentary, generated successively.
Indeed, a permanent authority said to cognize all entities only could cognize them
simultaneously, for it does not change from one moment to the next. This would
mean that all objects in fact exist simultaneously, which manifestly is not so. If
it is maintained that isvara himself remains permanent, but that his cognitions
are impermanent in accordance with the succession of objects, then at least
two consequences ensue: (a) tsvara is being qualified with contradictory prop-
erties (permanence and impermanence) and (b) he is being accepted as depen-
dent on conditions (the succession of objects), which a permanent being cannot
be.61
It ought to be noted, before we continue, that Dharmakirti's argument here
presupposes the validity of the Buddhist doctrine of momentariness, whereby
"existence" only is predicated of efficient(arthakriya)entities, and efficiencyonly
can be predicated of momentary entities-since an entity that is not inherently
and instantly destructible cannot be destroyed, hence is immutable, and what is
immutable cannot interact with what is successive, as entities manifestly are.
Buddhist arguments for momentariness were highly controversial,62being open
to criticism for (a) vitiating causality by denying continuity and (b) begging the
question by defining existence in such a way (as a particulartype of efficacity)that
only momentary entities could fulfill the definition. It is not my intention to enter
into these fundamental arguments here, but simply to point out that the debate
between Dharmakirti and his opponents is not necessarily self-contained, but
constantly opens out onto the broader metaphysical issues dividing them (and
these issues, in turn, are inextricably intertwined with questions of the religious
psychologies of different traditions63).
325
(9b:)
Because (a permanent cognizer) has not been helped in any way,
There cannot be an impermanent authoritative (being).64
(10a:)
(Because of) intermittence, particular shape,
Efficiency, etc., (a creator exists).68
The unnamed opponent here may be the Nyaya-Vaisesika, for, to our knowl-
edge, of all the Hindu theistic schools, only the Nyaya-Vaisesika had, by
Dharmakirti's time, sought to justify the creatorship of isvara through formal
inference. Furthermore, the syllogism here phrased in rather skeletal form by
Dharmakirti bears a close similarity to the argumentsprofferedby Uddyotakara,
who insisted that worldly results required a conscious motivator, like a hatchet,
whose fashioning and use both point to the intervention of a conscious agent.69
The syllogism also recalls Bhavaviveka's unnamed opponent, who argued that
all results require a creator because they have a specific arrangement, like a pot,
whose arrangement informs us of the existence of a potter.70
Commentarial glosses on Dharmakirti's presentation of the theistic syllogism
make it clear that, in fact, threedifferent reasons are being offered as probative of
326 Jackson
a creator. rGyal tshab, thus, restates the syllogism more fully as follows:
"Worldly environs, bodies and enjoyments are preceded by the mind of a maker,
(a) because they act intermittently, like a hatchet, (b) because they have a
particular shape, like a pot and (c) because they are efficient (in fulfilling beings'
aims), like a battle-axe." From these and other such statements, it is proven that
(abodes, bodies and possessions) have a maker whose mind has preceded them,
and also that that (maker) is Tsvara.7'
The argument from intermittence makes the claim that because entities some-
times function and sometimes do not, their existence must be due to action by a
conscious agent. The argument from particularshape makes the claim that, quite
simply, design implies a designer, and there is a design to entities, so there must be
a designer. The argument from efficiency makes the claim that the observed
efficiency of entities requires that they be preceded by an efficient maker who
foresaw the purposes they could fulfill. Dharmakirti does not turn to the argu-
ments from intermittenceand efficiencyuntil later in his discussion, where he will
reject them as part of his refutation of the causal agency attributed to Tsvara.He
will address himself first and in most detail to the argument from particular
shape.
Dharmakirti's first move in refuting the syllogism, however, is to state gener-
ally the problems it entails:
(1Ob:)
(Here,) either (a) the assertion is already proven, or (b) the example is uncertain,
Or (c) the statement issues in doubt.72
According to rGyal tshab, (a) the assertion is already proven because the
syllogism simply states that "environs, bodies and enjoyments are preceded by
the mind of a maker," and this general concomitance will be accepted by the
Buddhist, too, since, according to the Buddhist, environs, bodies, and enjoy-
ments are preceded by mental karman,hence by "the mind of a maker." One of
the requisites for posing a formal inference is that it seek to prove something not
proven before, so the theistic syllogism is, in its general form, redundant. Fur-
thermore, if isvara in particular is posited as the conscious creator, then (b) the
example is uncertain, because all three examples-the hatchet, the pot, and the
battle-axe-are impermanent entities, which must, therefore, be made or em-
ployed by impermanent beings, whereas the entity to whose existence they are
supposed to point, Tsvara,is permanent. The examples, thus, may be probative of
impermanentcauses, but not of a permanentone. Finally, (c) the statement issues
in doubt, because even if environs, bodies, and enjoyments are preceded by a
maker, there is no guarantee that that maker is TIvara,for Isvarais simply one
possible explanation for the way things are-and not a very promising one, given
that, for example, the entities whose explanation is sought are impermanent and
intermittent, while Tsvarais permanent, and so cannot be intermittent.73
Dharmaklrti now turns to an analysis of the argument from particular shape,
327
that is, that environs, bodies, and enjoyments have preceding them the mind of a
maker (Tsvara),because they have particular shape, like a pot, or a mansion:
(11:)
(If) shape, etc., are proved such as to be
Positively and negatively related to a designer,
An inference from that (shape to that designer)
Is reasonable.74
Much of the force of this statement is derived by implication. According to rGyal
tshab, the main point is this: if, and only if, environs, bodies, and enjoyments are
shaped just as a pot is, can we infer that they are preceded by a single conscious
designer, as a pot is. "Shaped as a pot is" can have two different meanings here:
the arrangement of the material of the pot, and the process whereby that
arrangementwas achieved. By either interpretation, "particularshape" is found
to be a reason that is unproven in the subject ("environs, bodies, and enjoy-
ments"). First of all, it is perfectly self-evident that environs, bodies, and enjoy-
ments do not have the same shape as a pot (or a mansion), and so we cannot
necessarily infer that they have a maker in the same way that a pot does, for it is
entirely possible that different particular types of shapes may have different
particular types of causes generating them. Indeed, a Buddhist will argue that
such things as environs, bodies, and enjoyments actually have preceding them a
multiplicity of mental karmans,not a single creator-designer. Secondly, the mere
fact that a particular shape, a pot, arises from a single conscious designer does
not mean that different shapes or different types of shapes need necessarily arise
in the same way; again, the Buddhist will posit mental karmansas the cause and
will claim that, although consciousness may be involved in producing karmic
effects, conscious design is not. Thus, unless the theist wants to claim, absurdly,
that all entities are shaped just as a pot is, he cannot make inferences about them
that are based on the particular circumstances of the pot.75
Dharmakirti turns now from an examination of "particularshape" to "shape
in general," to see whether it may be probative:
(12:)
(A quality) is proven in an entity by a particular (reason),
(But that) a term similar (to the reason is probative) because of its (alleged) non-
difference (from the reason)
Cannot reasonably be inferred;
(That would be) like (inferring) fire from a grey substance.76
Here, the theist's problem is that if he tries to claim the term "shape" in general
(rather than the particular shape of, for example, a pot) as probative, he has
provided a reason that is too general, and thus unproven in the subject. Granted,
we legitimately apply the term "shaped" to environs, bodies, and enjoyments,
but whereas we are able to infer that a pot or a mansion has preceding it the mind
of some person, because we have observed positive and negative concomitance
328 Jackson
between these objects and a maker, we have not observed such concomitance in
the case of, for example, the particularrealms into which we are born, the bodies
we have, and the environment that we share, with its mountains, seas, and
forests. Thus, a particular designer is proven in the cases of some particular
shapes, but one cannot generalize from this that any object to which the word
"shaped" applies necessarily must have a similar designer, for the sources of the
shapes of differing shaped objects may very well differ. Thus, just as the term
"grey substance" (of which smoke is only one type) is too general to be the basis
of a legitimate inference of the presence of fire in a particular place, so the term
"shape" alone is too general to be the basis of a legitimate inference that all
shaped objects must arise in the same way that some shaped objects do.77
Dharmakirti draws out the extreme consequences entailed by the probative
value of "shape" by pointing out that:
(13:)
If that is not the case, then a potter
May be proven to have made an ant-hill,
Because it has some (similarity) to the shape
Of clay in a pot, etc.78
The example is an interesting one, because it can be read as refuting the probative
value of either a particular shape or the general term "shape," the particular
aspects of shape analyzed in the two preceding verses. First, an anthill-at least
of the Indian variety-has the same shape as a pot. We ought, therefore, to
conclude on the basis of this similarity that it was made by a potter, whereas we
know quite well that it was made by ants. Thus, a similarity in shape does not
imply a necessary similarity in origin. Second, even if an anthill were not shaped
like a pot, the general fact that it is "shaped" has no probative value for the
theistic syllogism. Indeed, if anything, the anthill is a counter-example to the pot,
since it is an instance of a shaped object, yet it is one that we know by observation
to be positively and negatively concomitant with causes that are (a) multiple
rather than single and (b) very possibly unconscious rather than conscious.79 In
short, then, the term "shape" cannot be probative, because specific inquiries into
its meaning and relevance show that a particular shape (for example, a pot)
cannot be probative because not all objects have that particular shape, while
shape in general cannot be probative because different shapes may arise under
different circumstances, as an anthill arises in a different manner from a pot.
In the next six verses (numbers 14-20) Dharmakirti digresses in a direction
that is more of logical than theological interest, and I will pass over this dis-
cussion relatively quickly. Against an opponent's suggestion that the analysis to
which he has subjected the reason in the theistic syllogism is an instance of
karyasama, an overly specific refutation that can rebound upon or have "equal
results" for the refuter, Dharmakirti points out that karyasamaoccurs only when
a legitimate general reason is illegitimately undermined by an overly specific
329
analysis of its details,80 as when the generally valid inference "A conch-sound is a
result, because it arises from effort" is undermined by posing a sophistic dilemma
whereby a sound cannot arise before the effort or as a result of a new, unpre-
cedented effort.81 The refutation of the theistic reason, on the other hand, has
rested on the principle that a reason may be probative of a predicate for a
particular class of objects, but that a term lexically similar but semantically
different from that reason cannot thus be probative; one cannot, for instance,
maintain that words have horns simply because there exists a term, gotva, that
denotes both "cowness" and "wordness" 82-any more than one can maintain
that environs, bodies, and enjoyments are preceded by the mind of a creator,
tivara, simply because they have "shape." 83Dharmakirti drives home the conse-
quences of the theistic syllogism by pointing out that if words alone were
probative, then simply by uttering a word one ought to attain its object, and all
goals would be achieved, and all syllogisms proved, simply through the manipu-
lation of words-which, in fact, arise not from the existence of their referents,
but simply from a speaker's or writer's desire to express them.84
This same type of refutation, Dharmakirti adds, can be applied to the syllo-
gisms of other schools. For instance, the Samkhya assertion, "Buddhiis nonsen-
tient, because it is impermanent," is refuted on the grounds that the Samkhya is
using a reason, impermanence, that he himself cannot really accept, since imper-
manence only is admitted of momentary entities, which buddhi and the other
evolutes ofprakrti are not. The Jaina assertion, "A tree is sentient, because it dies
when its bark is stripped," is refuted on the grounds that the definition of death
being applied by the Jaina is too broad to be admissible by his opponents, and
thus cannot be adduced.85 In both cases, words ("impermanence," "death") are
used improperly, and so the syllogism is vitiated.
In the next three verses (and a supplemental verse found in Tibetan but not
Sanskrit), Dharmakirti goes on to draw from these considerations some general
conclusions about logical reasons. In the first place, the validity of a reason
depends on whether it is generally relevant to the subject and positively and
negatively concomitant with the predicate. If the reason is generally correct, then
it cannot be undermined by overly specific critiques, as, for instance, the fact that
"sound is impermanent because it is a product" cannot be refuted by attempting
to show that sound's relationship to space is unaccounted for.86 Further, even if
a particular term is unproven, if the meaning of the term is proven then the
syllogism is valid, as, for instance, the Buddhist syllogism "Atoms are imperma-
nent because they have aspects (murti)" will be accepted for discussion by a
Vaisesika, who does not admit the wording of the reason "have aspects," but can
supply from his own system a term with equivalent meaning, "is tangible."87
Conversely, even if a word is unmistaken, if the meaning is inappropriate, then
the term cannot be probative, for entities are proven from other entities, not from
words.88 The Tibetan version here adds an example illustrating this last point:
one cannot argue that either (a) "A colored cow is a cow because it is a 'goer
330 Jackson
In the final eight verses of his discussion, Dharmakirti directly attacks the idea
that isvara can be considered a causal entity, exposing the logical difficulties
involved in the theistic belief in a permanent creator-God. In the course of his
analysis, he refutes the two other reasons that formed part of the theistic
syllogism, that is, the argument from intermittence and the argument from
efficiency.He does not refute them in as much detail as he did the argument from
specific shape, but they are central to his concerns. We will signal those passages
in which they are addressed, since the refutation of the arguments from inter-
mittence and efficiencywill complete the refutation of the theistic syllogism posed
in verse 10.
Dharmakirti first attempts to show that the argument from intermittence
entails a logical contradiction:
(21:)
How, if an entity is a cause,
(But is said) sometimes to be
A non-cause, can one assert in any way
That a cause is a non-cause? One cannot so assert.90
The argument from intermittencestates that the fact that entities sometimes arise
and sometimes do not, that is, are occasional or intermittent in nature, requires
the postulation of a conscious being that serves as their cause at those times when
they arise, and that that being is isvara. Dharmakirti points out, however, that a
being that serves as the cause of intermittententities must, by definition, be a
noncause, too, since (a) an intermittent entity has times of nonproduction, when
its eventual cause is actually its noncause, and (b) at the time when the cause is
generating the intermittent entity, there still are other intermittent entities that it
is not generating, so it serves as the noncause of some entities at the same time as
it serves as the cause of others. (a) Successive causality and noncausality poses a
problem because the causal entity posited by the theist, Isvara,is permanent. He
cannot, therefore, change from moment to moment, and if he is asserted to be
causal, then he must always be causal, and can never become noncausal, for that
would entail a change in nature, an impossibility for a permanent entity. (b)
Simultaneous causality and noncausality poses a problem, because isvara is a
single entity, yet is being furnished with contradictory qualities at one and the
same time. Contradictory properties cannot be predicated of a single, partless
331
entity at one and the same time, and if these properties are reaffirmed,then Tsvara
cannot be single, but must be multiple.91 Isvara cannot, thus, be a creator of
intermittent entities.92
Dharmakirti next turns to a series of problems that revolve around the theistic
contention that Tsvarais the actual empowering cause that gives to the causes we
observe the ability-or efficiency-whereby they yield their results. The first
dilemma entailed by this is that:
(22:)
(If Tsvarais an unseen cause, then) when Caitra is healed
By connection with a weapon or medicine,
Why could not an unconnected post,
Although not cognized, be the cause (of healing)?93
Dharmakirti's attack here is directed at the postulation of an extra causal entity
in situations where we already can provide an adequate account of the causal
process. For instance, it is to Dharmaklrti a well-attested fact that a knife wound
can be healed by medicine or by the knife itself, the latter being an instance of
what Nagatomi calls "homeopathic magic." 94 If we are to posit a further unseen
cause behind the observed causes, then why not claim that an unseen, irrelevant
post be involved in the process?95One invisible entity, Dharmakirti implies, is
really no more absurd than another, and the postulation of any such entity tends
to make a mockery of our attempts to understand causality, for the implication is
that anything may be posited as the cause of any result.
Dharmakirti presses the attack, pointing out further problems in the concept
of Tsvara:
(23:)
One whose nature does not vary
Is unsuitable as a creator;
Since a permanent (entity) never is absent,
Even if it has the ability (to be a cause), it is difficult to see.96
The first half of the verse is, in a sense, a reiteration of a fundamental and
recurring argument, namely, that a permanent entity cannot be posited as the
cause of impermanent entities, since (a) the entity is asserted sometimes to be a
noncause, and its nature cannot change, so it cannot become a cause;97 (b)
causality is a process that involves intermittence, and a permanent entity cannot
be intermittent, since intermittence involves a change in nature; and (c) if a
permanent cause is posited, then causality cannot be an intermittent process, but
must occur all at once, since a permanent cause could not alter so as to produce
entities in a second moment. The second half of the verse raises still another basic
objection, namely, that if isvara is the unseen cause of every result, then he must
be ubiquitous and can never be absent. A cause, however, is defined as that in the
absence of which a result does not arise, so an entity that never is absent cannot
meaningfully be described as a cause. Indeed, whether Tsvarais only intermit-
332 Jackson
tently present (as argued earlier) or ubiquitous (as his nature would seem to
dictate) seems to have little actual bearing on our analyses of causality, which, in
fact, turn on the presence or absence of certain observablefactors. One may, if
one wishes, posit an extra entity such as isvara as the cause behind observable
causes, but positive and negative concomitance can only be observed with regard
to the observed causes. Since observedpositive and negative concomitance is an
adequate basis for the explication of any causal situation, the extra "behind-the-
scenes" cause (whether principal or assistant) must be either redundant or
impotent.98
There is a furtherconsequence of the postulation of an invisible cause-behind-
the-scenes, namely:
(24:)
When some (cause) exists, some (result) comes to be;
If some cause other than that
Is supposed, then there will be no end
To the causes of any result.99
Once again, then, the postulation of an unseen cause destabilizes our notion of
causality, for the admission of unseen and unseeable causes opens the door to an
infinity of such causes, which is tantamount to causal chaos. Here, it ought
perhaps to be added in all fairness that the Buddhist notion of karman can be
subjected to the same general critique as isvara. Karman is certainly neither
permanent nor ubiquitous in the way that isvara is, but it is an unseen causal
factor that is operative in virtually every situation in which sentient beings are
involved. In those instances where other causes can be adduced, karman is
superfluous, unless we insist that there be a moral explanation for everything;
while in those instances where we do not have adequate explanations, karman
serves somewhat the way the "God of the gaps" does in Western theology, that is,
as a stop-gap explanation where observable concomitances have not yet been
established. Karman, like isvara, explains so much that it threatens to explain
nothing at all.
In the final four verses of the section, Dharmakirti responds to some possible
objections to his arguments, thereby clarifying his notion of the causal process
and tsvara'sunsuitability for participation in it. The first objection, as supplied
by rGyal tshab, claims that, "... according to you, when soil, etc., do not
generate a sprout, they cannot change their nature, so there will be no generation
of a sprout." 101In other words, if entities cannot change their nature from that
of noncause to cause, then soil, moisture, sunlight, and the seed itself, which are
333
not at this moment generating a sprout, will never be able to. Dharmakirti's
response is that:
(25:)
In the generation of a sprout, the soil and other (conditions)
Do change their nature
And become causes, for when we see that (cultivation)
Is done well, (the harvest) is excellent.102
The implicit point here is that it is only a permanent entity, such as isvara, that
cannot become a cause once it has been a noncause; such causal conditions as
soil, moisture, sunlight, and the seed are all impermanent, momentary entities, so
there is no contradiction in asserting that at one moment they are noncauses and
at another moment they are causes. Indeed, such must be the case, for we observe
that soil and the other conditions do serve as noncauses at one time (early in the
season) and as causes at another, later time (harvest).103Conversely, it might be
added, the fact that it clearly is the case that entities can change from noncauses
into causes is a further demonstration of their necessary impermanence, since a
permanent entity could not thus change.
Dharmakirti next entertains and answers a related objection:
(26:)
If you say, "Just as object and organ,
Meeting without alteration, cause cognition,
So, too, (Isvarais a cause without alteration,)" it is not so.
Because there is alteration (of organ and object) from when (they have not
met).104
The objector here evidently is a Nyaya-Vaisesika, for the account of cognition
being offered derives from the Nydyasutra,l05 where it is said that cognition
results from the contact between an organ and an object. The claim is made that
just as organ and object do not perceptibly change from one moment to the next,
and yet in the first moment there is no cognition while in the second there is, so
isvara, although he does not change, can be a noncause one moment and-our
nonperception notwithstanding-a cause the next. The Buddhist has two pos-
sible responses, one doctrinal, the other logical. The doctrinal is that the Nyaya-
Vaisesika account of the cognitive process is incorrect, and that there is a third
factor that determines a cognition, namely, a previous cognition, whose presence
or absence and particular qualities must be posited to explain the evident fact
that-even if organ and object are admitted not to vary-cognitions do vary.106
Alternatively, if the opponent be taken as accepting the Buddhist postulation of
threeconditions for cognition, then the logical objection can be made that, at the
very least, the organ must vary, for otherwise we could not explain the relative
clarity or dullness of cognitions.107
A further logical objection, of course, is simply that the postulation of an
entity's noncausality at one time and causality at another requiresthat there be
334 Jackson
(27:)
(Factors) that are individually powerless (as causes),
If they do not change their nature,
Will be powerless even when they meet.
Thus, alteration is proved.108
In the instance of the organ, object, and cognition, the three factors are con-
sidered individuallyunable but collectively able to generate a cognition. Dhar-
makirti's point, however, is that regardless of whether they are functioning
individually or collectively, the three factors cannot be causally potent if it is not
admitted that their nature changes-for the simple reason that previously they
have been a noncause, and in order to be efficacious, they must change in nature
so as to become a cause. Thus, according to rGyal tshab:
... it is proven that the three conditions have different natures when they have
met and when they have not met, because we see the differencethat they generate
or do not generate sense-cognition when they have met or have not met.109
(28:)
Thus, those (factors) that are individually powerless
(But bring about) the existence of the quality (of the result) when they have met
Are causes; [svara, etc.,
Are not (causes), because they do not alter.110
Causality, then, is a process entailing not only the presence or absence of certain
factors (whereby, as we saw, s'varacould not be considered a cause), but also the
alteration of those factors in such a way that they change from being noncauses
to being causes. Thus, the generation of a sprout requires (a) the presence of
certain factors that might not be present, that is, the seeds, soil, moisture,
sunlight, and so forth, and (b) the alteration of the nature of each of these so that
their individual causal nonefficacity becomes their collective efficacity. Similarly,
a sense-cognition requires (a) the object, organ, and preceding cognition and (b)
an alteration of each of these such that individual nonefficacity can become
collective efficacity. Now, this alteration is not some superadded process beyond
the meeting of the conditions, but it must be specified as part of the causal
process, for without such specification, one might overlook the ontological
difference that is entailed by causality. Difference, in turn, requires imperma-
nence, for entities are known sometimes to be causes and sometimes to be
noncauses of particular events, but it is contradictory that they be both at the
335
same time, while a permanententity, like isvara, cannot alter its nature, and so it
must always be a noncause or always a cause. If it is always a noncause, then the
discussion is academic; if it is always a cause, then it must be ubiquitous, and it
cannot be accepted as a cause, because its presence or absence cannot be
observed to make a difference in the generation of a result.
Before leaving Dharmakirti, we ought to note that he adduces one additional
argument against 7svara,later in the Pramdnasiddhichapter, when he insists
(following the line of reasoning of such predecessors as Vasubandhu111) that the
cause of the various sufferings experienced by beings cannot be a unique cause,
because the variety among results permits us only to infer a variety of causes, and
because, as has been demonstrated, a permanent cause cannot be proven to
exist.112 rGyal tshab, finally, adds his own version of the argument from evil, at
the end of his discussion of the vital and trivial characteristicsof omniscience that
may be attributed to "authoritative" beings: "If someone who can make any-
thing because of his knowledge of the sciences is omniscient, then he also has
made the sufferings of the lower realms...." With this in mind, rGyal tshab
concludes, we should turn not to such a being, but to "someone who, having
accomplished the elimination of every last fetter, is omniscient regarding how all
objects really exist." 113 The latter sort of being is one who truly is authoritative
for those intent on liberation, and is, of course, exemplified by the Buddha, who
has not made the world, but knows it, and knows the way out of it.
VIII. THE THEIST-ATHEISTDEBATEAFTERDHARMAKIRTI
Dharmakirti's attack on theism was a stinging one, but it did not end the debate
between theists and atheists any more than did Hume's critique in the West.
Indeed, as noted earlier, Dharmakirti's discussions had the salutary effect of
raising the discussion to a new level of sophistication, and in the centuries
following him the issue was joined not only by Nyaya-Vaisesikas responding to
his attacks, but by still other Buddhists, as well as by Mimamsakas and Jainas.
These debates have been covered well elsewhere,114and we have neither the need
nor the space to outline them in detail. We will, however, survey them briefly.
The Nyaya-Vaisesika response to Dharmakirti's critique was far from
immediate. Indeed, it was nearly three centuries after Dharmakirti, in the
Nyayamafijarl of Jayanta Bhatta, that a counterattack finally was mounted. In
the meantime, further critiques of theism had been forthcoming, not only from
Buddhists, but from Mlmamsakas and Jainas, as well. The first important post-
Dharmakirti Buddhist attack on theism is that of Santideva (eighth century),
who criticizes a number of non-Buddhist views of causality in the ninth chapter
of his Bodhicaryivatara. Among these is the Naiyayika claim that isvara, a
divine, pure, permanent, single creator, is the source of everything. But, notes
Santideva, if tsvara is identified with the elements that are accepted as the
material causes of material things, there is a contradiction, because these ele-
ments are neither pure nor permanent nor single. On the other hand, if he is said
336 Jackson
All these points are well taken, but they do not totally undermine the com-
parison. To begin with, the "languages" of Indian and Western philosophy are
different, but that does not mean that there is not a fair degree of translatability
across traditions: the inductive and deductive processes generally accepted to be
the basis of sound reasoning are found in both, as are many of the same notions
of the types of flaws that may vitiate arguments. Secondly, even if there are
differences between isvara and God, they are not so great as to obviate all
comparison between their roles and the arguments for their existence. The
argument from design, after all, simply attempts to show generally that the order
we perceive in the cosmos presupposes a single conscious designer and/or sus-
tainer of that order. It really is a secondary matter (pace Kant) whether the being
responsible for the cosmic order creates ex nihilo or arranges preexistent raw
material; in either case, it is not mode of ordering that is at issue, but the existence
of a single eternal being who is the conscious agent of that ordering.
Thus, I think it is fair to call the Nyaya-Vaisesika syllogism rejected by
Dharmakirti an "Indian argument from design," just as I think it is relativelyfair
to call s'vara"God." Therefore, I think that the sorts of arguments proffered by
Dharmakirti and his opponents can be of interest to Western theologians. The
precise ways in which the Indian arguments overlap or deviate from the Western
ones must be the topic of another study, as must detailed considerations of
whether the Indian tradition has arguments that could serve either theists or
antitheists in the West.132 Hume, Kant, and others have given fairly thorough
treatment to the problem of conscious agency, and it is my suspicion that it is on
the permanence-impermanenceissue that the Indian tradition may have the most
to contribute. The Buddhist critique of a God believed to be immutable seems to
me an acute one, and the price of accepting God's mutability a high one, that is,
his susceptibility to conditions, hence loss of omnipotence. There are, of course,
currents in modern Christianity, represented by, for example, Hartshorne, or
Kazantzakis (in his The Saviors of God), that do not require the omnipotence of
God, and admit his dependence on his creatures for the fulfillment of his ends.
These would escape the objections raised against a permanent, independent God,
though whether they could evade criticisms aimed at the concept of divine
teleology (especially those regardingthe admissibility of extraneous causes), I am
not so certain. It also is my suspicion, alas, that cross-cultural debates may in the
end be no more conclusive than intra-cultural ones have been, and that the
arguments, if examined carefully enough, will be seen to rest on prephilosophical
choices and assumptions that cannot really be questioned, and yet which vitiate
the certainty to which philosophers forever aspire.
This final note of uncertainty can, if we permit it, grow into a more general
uncertainty about the "order" we perceive and discover in the cosmos, an order,
incidentally, that was assumed by both theists and atheists in India, their only
disagreement being over how to account for it. Is it not, in fact, possible that this
order simply is not there, that it actually is conceived and invented rather than
342 Jackson
NOTES
1. Lin Yutang, ed., The Wisdom of Chinaand India (New York: Modern Library, 1942), p. 11.
2. Compare such "skeptical" Vedic passages as Rg (Rgveda) II, 12, 5; IV, 18, 12; and VIII, 100,
3; and their discussion in Depibrasad Chattopadhyaya, Indian Atheism (Calcutta: Manisha, 1969),
pp. 32-43. Chattopadhyaya's book, while occasionally straining for evidence that one or another
ambiguous passage is atheistic, presents overall a compelling picture of the pervasiveness of atheism
in Indian philosophical (if not religious) thought-especially early in the tradition.
3. Compare Chattopadhyaya, Indian Atheism, chaps. 9 and 16.
4. Compare, for example, ibid., chap. 14; and Narendranath Bhattacharyya, Jain Philosophy:
Historical Outline (New Delhi: Munshiram Manoharlal, 1976), pp. 93-108.
5. Compare, for example, Nagin J. Shah, Akalahka's Criticismof DharmakTrti'sPhilosophy:A
Study, L. D. Series no. 11 (Ahmedabad: L. D. Institute of Indology, 1967);and D. N. Shastri, Critique
of Indian Realism: A Study of the Conflict Between the Nyaya-Vaisesika and the BuddhistDignaga
School (Agra: Agra University, 1964).
6. The Tibetans attribute seven works to him: Pramanavarttika(hereaftercited as PV), Pramd-
n.aviniscaya,Nydyabindu,Hetubindu,SambandhaparTkisd, Samtdndntarasiddhiand Vadanydya.Only
the PVand Nyayabinduare completely extant in Sanskrit;the others exist in Tibetan translation. For
a list of editions and translations, compare A. K. Warder, Indian Buddhism,2d ed. (Delhi: Motilal
Banarsidass, 1980), pp. 539-540.
343
Miyasaka does not, so the Shastri number is found by adding 2 to the Miyasaka number. Compare
previous note 7, for references.
58. rGyal tshab rje, Rnam-Agrel-Thar-Lam-Gsal-Byed(hereafter cited as GT) (Sarnath: Tibetan
Monastery, 1974), vol. 1, pp. 238-248. The section on 'svarais, according to rGyal tshab (p. 239),
part of Dharmakirti's attempt to show the meaning of the word "became" (bhuta) authoritative: a
permanent entity like Tsvaraalways has been authoritative, and so cannot "become" so.
59. The PVpanjikd,or -vrtti (hereaftercited as PVV) is extant only in Tibetan: PTT no. 5717(b),
vol. 130; and sDe dge no. 4217, found at, for example, TheNyingma Edition of the sDe-dge bka'-'gyur
andbsTan-'gyur(Oakland, California: Dharma Press, 1981), vol. 94, fols. 732-746, pp. 184- 188. The
section on Tsvarais at the end of chapter 11 and the beginning of chap. 12.
60. nityam pramanam naivdsti pramdnydd vastusangateh / jneydnityatayd tasyd adhrauvyat
kramajanmanah// nitydd utpattivislesddapeksaya ayogatah / (tshad ma rtag pa nyid yod min / dngos
yod rtogspa tshadphyirdang / shes bya mi rtagpa nyidkyis / de ni mi brtannyidphyir ro / rimbzhinskye
ba can dag ni // rtag las skye ba mi 'thadphyir / Itos pa mi rungpa yi phyir /).
61. GT, pp. 239-240; Jackson, Is EnlightenmentPossible? pp. 564-566.
62. Compare, for example, Shah, chap. 2; and D. N. Shastri, passim.
63. Compare the concluding section for remarks on this issue.
64. kathancinnopakdryatvddanitye'py apramdn.ata-// (rnam 'gasphan gdags bya min phyir / mi
rtag na yang tshad med nyid //).
65. Prajiakaragupta, Pramdnavdrttika-bha.syaor Vdrttikalahkdra of Prajntikaragupta, ed.
Rahula Sankrityayana (Patna: Kashi Prasad Jayaswal Research Institute, 1953), p. 34.
66. GT, p. 240; Jackson, Enlightenment,p. 566.
67. PVV, Nyingma sDe-dGe, vol. 94, fols. 733-734, p. 185.
68. sthitva pravrttisamsthdnavisesdrthakriyddisu / sdod 'jugdbyibs kyi khyadpar dang / don byed
pa la sogs pa dag /). Cf Tattvasam.graha(TS) 46 (for full references, compare note 117 following).
69. Preceding, p. 6. Prof. Karl Potter has disagreed with me that the syllogism being refuted is
Nyaya-Vaisesika, noting (a) that no such exact syllogism is found in Nyaya-Vaigesika works and (b)
that no later Nyaya-Vaisesika works specifically defended the tradition against Dharmakirti's
attacks. Prof. Potter has suggested that Dharmakirti's opponent may, in fact, be a lost Sam.khya
work. This may well be, but it must be argued from silence, and it seems to me that (a) while the
syllogism refuted by Dharmakirti is not precisely like those found in Nyaya-Vai§esika works, there is
a significant overlap and (b) later Nyaya-Vai§esika works may not have specifically addressed
Dharmakirti's objections because by the time they were written, Dharmakirti's arguments perhaps
had been overshadowed by those of Santaraksita, Kamala§ila and Jiama§ri. Prof. Potter also has
pointed out-and in this I quite agree with him-that Dharmaklrti's opponent may be unidentifiable
for the simple reason that DharmakTrtihas distorted the theistic position in recasting it for discussion.
Thus, the Nyaya-Vai§esikas may have been the intended target, but not recognized for their own
position as restated by Dharmakirti. Alternatively, Dharmakirti may be combining the ideas of more
than one theistic school into the syllogism.
70. Preceding, p. 10.
71. GT, p. 241; Jackson, Enlightenment, p. 567. This does not depart substantially from the
interpretation of Devendrabuddhi, who differs only in describing that which must be created as
bodies, environs, and products, and cites as an example of "particular shape" not a pot, but a
mansion, PVV, fol. 734, p. 185.
72. istasiddhirasiddhirvi drstdntesam. ayo 'thavi // ('dodpa grubpa 'amdpe ma grub/ yang na the
tshom za ba yin //).
73. GT, p. 241; Jackson, Enlightenment,pp. 567-568.
74. siddham.yddrg adhisthdtrbhdvdbhdvdnuvrttimat / sam.nivesaditadyuktam tasmddyad anumTy-
ate// (byin rlabsyod med rjes jug can / dbyibssogs ci 'drarabgrubpa / de las rjessu dpoggang yin / de ni
rigs pa nyid yin no //).
75. GT, pp. 241-242; Jackson, Enlightenment,p. 569; compare TS 63.
76. vastubhede prasiddhasya sabdasiamnyid abhedinah / na yuktdnumitih pdn.dudravyddivad
dhutWsane// (tha dadngos la rabgrubpa / sgra mtshungstha dadmedpa'iphyir / rjes dpog rigspa ma yin
te / skye bo'i rdzas las me bzhin no //).
77. GT, p. 242; Jackson, Enlightenment,p. 570.
346 Jackson
akdranam// (ji Itardngos de rhyuyinpa / de lta de nyidgang gi tshe / rgyumingang gis de ni rgyur/ 'dod
la rgyu ma yin mi 'dod//).
91. GT, p. 247; Jackson, Enlightenment,pp. 578-579.
92. Compare preceding, p. 16, alternative (c).
93. sdstrausadhdbhisambandhdc caitrasya vranarohane/ asambaddhasyakim sthdnohkdranatvam
na kalpyate // (mtshon dang sman sogs 'brelba las / nag pa'i rma dang 'drubsyin na / 'brelmed sdong
dum ci yi phyir / rgyu nyid du ni rtog mi byed //).
94. Nagatomi, A Study of DharmakTrti'sPramdnavdrttika,p. 33.
95. GT, p. 247; Jackson, Enlightenment,p. 579. rGyal tshab probably was unfamiliar with the
instance of "homeopathic magic" cited by Dharmakirti, and glosses the verse as having the weapon
inflict the wound and the medicine heal it. Devendrabuddhi (fol. 742, lines 6-7) supports the reading
we have given. Incidentally, an instance of homeopathic magic is cited in Dante's Inferno (XXXI,
4-6), where the poet recalls the lance of Achilles and his father, which could both wound and heal.
96. svabhdvabhedanavind vydpdro 'pi na yujyate / nityasydvyatirekitvdtsdmarthyan ca duran-
vayam// (rang bzhinkhyadpar medpar ni / byedpar yang ni mi rungngo / rtag la Idogpa medpa'i phyir /
nus pa nyid kyang rtog par dka' //).
97. GT, p. 247; Jackson, Enlightenment,p. 579.
98. Ibid.
99. yesu satsu bhavaty eva yat tebhyo 'nyasyakalpane / taddhetutvenasarvatrahetunamanavasth-
itih // (gang dag yod na gang 'gyurnyid / de dag las gzhan de yi rgyu / rtog pa yin na thamscad la / rgyu
rnams thugpa med par 'gyur //).
100. GT, pp. 247-248; Jackson, Enlightenment,pp. 579-580.
101. GT, p. 248; Jackson, Enlightenment,p. 580.
102. svabhavaparindmenahetur ahkurajanmani/ bhuimyddistasya sam.skdretadvisesasya darsandt
// (myugu skyed la sa la sogs / rang bzhinyongs su gyur nas ni / rgyu yin de legs byas pa na / de yi khyad
par mthongphyir ro //).
103. GT, p. 248; Jackson, Enlightenment,p. 580.
104. yathd visesena vind visayendriyasam.hatih/ buddherhetus tathedamcen na tatrdpi visesatah //
(gal teji Itaryul dbangpo / tshogspa khyadmed blo rgyuyin / de Itar 'diyin zhe na min / de las khyadpar
yodphyir ro //).
105. NS,I, 1,4.
106. This is the import of Devendrabuddhi's reading at PVV, fol. 745, line 2, p. 188.
107. GT, p. 248; Jackson, Enlightenment,p. 580.
108. prtak prtag asaktdndam svabhdvdtisaye'sati / samhatdvapy asdmarthyam.sydt siddho 'tisayas
tatah // (so so so sor nus med rnams/ rang bzhinkhyadpar medpas na / tshogs kyang nuspa med 'gyur
bas / de phyir khyad par grubpa yin //).
109. GT, p. 248; Jackson, Enlightenment,pp. 580-581. Emphasis mine.
110. tasmdtprtag asaktesu yesu sam.bhdvyategunah / samhatauhetuta tesdm.nesvardderabhedatah
// (dephyir so sor gang nus med / tshogs na yon tan srid 'gyurba / de dag rgyuyin dbangphyugsogs / ma
yin khyadpar med phyir ro //).
111. Compare preceding, p. 9.
112. Verse 183; GT, p. 219; Jackson, Enlightenment, pp. 713-714. The verse is found in the
discussion of the aspect of origination (samudaya) of the truth of origination.
113. GT, p. 251; Jackson, Enlightenment,p. 586.
114. Compare, for example, the writings of Chattopadhyaya, N. Bhattacharyya, and Potter
mentioned in this article (preceding, notes 2, 4, and 29).
115. Bodhicaryavatara IX, 118-123. It ought to be noted that Santideva is misrepresenting the
Nyaya-Vaisesika view, whereby 7~varais not the creator of the paddrthas, but their arranger.
116. Ibid., IX, 124-125.
117. Tsvarais rejected at TS 46-93, purusa at TS 153-170. Compare Ganganatha Jha, trans., The
Tattvasamgraha of Sdntaraksita with the Commentary of Kamalahsla(Baroda: Oriental Institute,
1937), vol. 1, pp. 68-101, 132-139.
118. TS 47-48 and 56-60; Jha, Tattvasamgraha,pp. 69-71 and 75-79.
119. TS 85; Jha, Tattvasamgraha,p. 92.
348 Jackson