Reinhart Koselleck - Critique and Crisis - Enlightenment and The Pathogenesis of Modern Society (Studies in Contemporary German Social Thought) (1998, The MIT Press) PDF
We take content rights seriously. If you suspect this is your content, claim it here.
Available Formats
Download as PDF or read online on Scribd
0 ratings0% found this document useful (0 votes)
78 views107 pages
Reinhart Koselleck - Critique and Crisis - Enlightenment and The Pathogenesis of Modern Society (Studies in Contemporary German Social Thought) (1998, The MIT Press) PDF
We take content rights seriously. If you suspect this is your content, claim it here.
Available Formats
Download as PDF or read online on Scribd
You are on page 1/ 107
Studies in Contemporary German Social Thought
Thomas McCarthy, General Editor
Todor W. Adorn, Assit Epitemology: A Metcrtiqne
“Theodor W. Adowno, Prime "
KarhOuo Ape, Undersmingand Explanation t Tancendenal: Pragmatic
Ponpecace
Richard J. Berscin et Habermas ad Modernity
inst Bish, Nea Laon Panay Diy
Ernst ich Fe rape of Hope
Est Bch The Urpin Bsn of Arend Later: Sted Bway
Tian Blumer. The Gent of te Copemuan World
Hin Blumen. The Leginay of he ser Age
Fans Hlumenber. Work ow Mah
elt Dubie, Thor ond Poi Sade onthe Dec lopment of Crical
Tico
John Forester editor, ie Theory and Pale Life
David Fess Papmonts of Mody Theo of Mader h the Nor of
Somat, Rrciter on Besponm
Hans-Georg Gadaner Phlvphad Aprensehps
Hans-Georg Galimer, Reso nthe ge of Sten
Jurgen Haberman, The Piosophl Dison of Maman Tecve Eecares
"teen Haber Pisopi-otta hls
Sirgen Habermas nots Obearons oh "Pe Spal hction ofthe Age’
Mane fone Mud Contemporary Resocminatio of te Fought
Reinhart ovals Citigu and Cp Eugcument avd the Pathogen of
Sto Sty
Reinhart Kose, Fates Pa On the Sent of Herc Tine
Hove Marans Hegel's Onelgy tnd the Theory of Hoarty
Clio Ge Conran of te Wel suse
Chas Oe, Doargnied Captain: Contenporay Troon: of Work ad
ence, Action, ant Fenders Tes: Toward « Tovlogy
Ie Fonh Relat Esa othe Philosophy of
abe
Ae Schmit, Hoy and Seca tm Esa om Hepa: Mast and
Siac Theone of History
Dennis Sch The Uagy ofthe rte Hegel Mrideger ad the
tener 9f Phicwphy
car Schmit, The Cra of Parhameary Deora
‘Lari Sonny Poles! Romane
a Thea Fo Chapter a the Concept of Sovereign
The Ober Sade th Sua! Once) of Fase
Heseguy See, nd Baber
Gay Sith ediog, On Wales npn Ciel Eye and Restle
Tint Toundha, el Concionsne dS Decrmiation
Mink Warns isce soe Poll Thaaghe
lav Pour,
Joachim Rin, Hegel an
Cael Seis, Poi
‘Michael Theuanisen,
Critique and Crisis
Enlightenment and the Pathogenesis of
Modern Society
REINHART KOSELLECK
‘The MIT Press
Cantbridge, MassachusettsFirst MIT Pees «
This Engh transition @) 1988 Recg Publisters Lid
ie, Eine Studi er Pato
der bingetichen Wele by
Verlag Kael Alber Gi, Preibung/Murich, West German
989 Verlag Kal Alber Crib Hl
Originally published as Ki»
I sighs ese
No part this book maybe roredaced in an form or by Contents
permission in writing fom the pubs
Livy of Congres Cxalogingin-Pulcon Dat
Kosei, Rear Foreword Victor Gonrevitch
Paahayencts of Modern Sectey Preface to the English Edition
Cais in contenparary German i Hough Introduction
Fat of ek cd Ri
Bioguh Part |The Political Structure of Absolutism as the
Incades index
1 Policlscence—History, 2, Enlightenment.
3, Divine ght of kings. History—Phiknophy
Precondi
mn of Enlightenment
1, The Absolutist State, Raison d’Ftat and the
Tiles Me Series,
JAS Koss 1988 320.09 159 Emergence of the Apolitical Sphere (Barclay,
ISUN'O 262 11127 & ’Aubigne)
2. Hobbesian Rationality and the Origins of
Prins in Gres Britain Enlightenment
3. The Exclusion of Natural Law Morality from
International Polities and the Concept of War
between States as a Precondition of Moral Progress
Part IL The Self-Image of the Enlightenment Thinkers
as a Response to their Situation within the
Absolutist State
4. Locke’s Law of Private Censure and its Significance
for the Emergence of the Bourgeoisie
5. The Creation of Indirect Countervailing Powers and
the Arcanum of Politics
6. The Proliferation of Indirect Power and the Schism of
Morals and Politics
41
fa
767. The Political Function of the Lodges and the Plans of
the Illuminati
8. The Process of Criticism (Schiller, Simon, Bayle,
Voltaire, Diderot and the Encyclopédie, Kant)
Part III Cris
9. ‘The Philosophy of Progress and its Prognosis of
Revolution
and Philosophy of History
10. The Recognition of the Crisis and the Emergence of a
Moral Totalism as a Response to Political Absolutism
(Turgor)
11. Crisis, Consciousness and Historical Construstion
(Rousseau, Diderot, Raynal, Paine)
Excursus
graphy
Indexes
36
98
Foreword
Professor Koselleck’s learned and influential study remains as ab-
sorbing today as it was when first published, nearly thirty years ago,
under the title Kritik und Krise. is good to have it available at last.
in English
In Professor Koselleck’s view the modern understanding of poli-
tics, and hence modern political practice, has become dangerously
depoliticised. The basic differences between the political realm
proper and other public but non-political realms, have become
blurred. At the same time visions of eventually escaping the hard
constraints of politics distort the real altern
Professor Koselleck traces this malady — to use his own metaphor —
to the changing status of political authority in the age of Absolutism
and Enlightenment, the period that stretches from the Peace of
Utrecht to the waning years of the ancien régime, from the major
writings of Hobbes 10 those of Rousseau and Raynal. His thesis,
reduced to a formula, is that during that period the widening
breach, in fact and in theory, between State and society, and
between politics and ethics, inevitably led to the challenge — the
critique — and the eventual subversion — the crisis — of the
political by the social, cultural and moral realms
The specifically modern order which was established by the
middle of the seventeenth century redistributed the public space
into two sharply separate domains: that of politcal authority proper,
the prince or State; and the striedly subordinate domain of the sub-
jects, the domain which at about that time came to be known as
society. In Professor Koselleck’s view this ordering of sovereign
and subject is given its clearest theoretical formulation by Hobbes.
ives here and nowvill Foreword
Hobbes fully recognised that such an ordering entails the strict
subordination of the claims of individual morality to the require-
ments of political necessity. He argues for it none the less, on the
grounds that ‘the state of man can never be without some incom-
modity or other’, and that the ordering of sovereign and subjects
which he proposes makes for fewer incommodities than does any
other. For it at least permits subjects to lead secure, commodious,
and hence decent and just lives.
Yet when and wherever men are denied an active share in the
‘exercise of political authority, when and wherever they are subjects
without being citizens, they inevitably endow other concerns and
pursuits — economic, cultural, moral — with an independent, and
hence rival, authority. The absolutisms of seventeenth and eight-
centh-century continental Burope are in large measure themselves
responsible for the criticism and the challenges to which they finally
succumbed. Professor Koselleck makes the point in the fascinating,
chapters in which he traces the gradual transformation of such free,
voluntary associations as the Masonic lodges and the Republic of
Letters from enclaves of internal exile into centres of moral auth-
rity, and eventually into surrogates and even models for political
society. In the process, existing political societies came to be judged
by standards which take litle or no account of the constraints
which political men must inevitably take into account, standards
which for all politcal intents and purposes are therefore Utopian.
But Utopia is not, properly speaking, a politica. alternative at all
In Professor Koselleck’s view, political Utopianism is as much a
contradiction in terms as is, for example, dogmatic scepticism. In
theoretical terms, it draws from all those political constraints which,
in practice, it challenges and subverts. And in so far as it either fails
or refuses to take cognisance of its self-evident political role, he
regards it as an outright hypocrisy as well. He does not ever
consider the possibility of a politically self-conscious and respon-
sible Utopia.
‘The study concludes with some particularly incisive analyses of
how Enlightenment Utopianism becomes rationalised, radicalised
and transmuted into the new philosophy of history. The philo-
sopher of history or, more precisely, the philosopher of historical
progress, by stationing himself in the hoped-for future, typically
looks back upon the conflicts and the suffering caused by the clash
between intransigently held norms and political realities as if these
Foreword ix
conflicts had been happily resolved, and therefore had been jus-
tified. He confidently expects that, to paraphrase a remark of
Hegel’s, the wounds inflicted by history invariably heal without
leaving sears. By thus justifying confrontation, conflict and crisis,
the philosophy of history abets them and so contributes further to
that depoliticisation which Professor Koselleck sees as pethaps the
most distinctive feature of the Enlightenment.
By contrast, he himself adopts the stance by which he believes
that political matters are most accurately perceived as the viewpoint
of the citizen or of the statesmen on the spor. By studying the
doctrines of the philosophers and the opinions of representative
‘men or groups as they appear to a political agent rather than to a
detached chronicler, he calls attention to a great deal that otherwise
goes unnoticed. ‘This political perspective on the history of ideas
also makes for much that is fresh, original and absorbing in his
book. Admittedly a number of his judgements are impassioned;
political judgements are apt to be so. It is, indeed, altogether
striking how engaged much of the most valuable recent Enlighten-
ment scholarship continues to be. Although Professor Koselleck
himself refrains from pointing to possible morals, he clearly recog-
nises that his critical history of criticism and of what he regards as
its hypoerisies, from the mid-seventeenth to the late-cighteenth
century, also serves as a critique of the critical theories of the
mid-nineteenth and, especially, of the mid-twentieth century.
‘The reader of Critique and Crisis is left with the distinct impression
that ic is the political teaching of Hobbes that captures what Profes-
sor Koselleck regards as the essential features of political life
Clearly, he does not wish to restore any particular doctrine of
Hobbes's, so much as to restore the characteristically Hobbesian
awareness that there is no escaping the constraints of political life,
and that itis not possible to reduce some measure of contingency,
conflict and compulsion to the status of differences of opinion or to
resolve them by discussion and peaceful competition. He certainly
shares the conviction, so forcibly articulated by Hobbes, that the
only alternative to politics that takes these constraints into account
is the war of all against all. He is, of course, also aware of the
fact that the great and very real evils of civil strife can be exagger-
ated, and that such exaggerations ean serve as a screen behind which
far greater evils are introduced into the civil order. It would seem
that he wants to warn against both of these extremes when heapprovingly alludes co
"Nowadays, fate is politics”
Foreword
joleon’s remark t0 the ag
ing Goethe:
Vietor Goureviteh
Preface to the English Edition
This study is a product of the early postwar period. It represented
an attempt to examine che historical preconditions of German
National Socialism, whose loss of reality and Utopian self-
exaltation had resulted in hitherto unprecedented crimes. There was
also the context of the cold war, Here, too, I was trying to enquire
into ity Utopian roots which, it seemed, prevented the two super~
powers from simply recognising each other as opponents. Instead
they blocked one another and thereby destroyed the opportunity
for a peace which each superpower self-confidently proclaimed to
be capable of establishing single-handedly. It was in the Enlighten
ment, to which both liberal-democratic America and socialist Russia
rightly retraced themselves, that I began to look for the common,
roots of their claim to exclusiveness with its moral and philosophi-
cal legitimations,
My starting-point was therefore to explain the Utopian ideas of
the twentieth century by looking at their origins in the eighteenth,
My original intention was to test my arguments by reference to
Kane’ critiques whose politial function during the age of Absolucism
1 was planning to investigate. But, as tends to happen to German
scholars, I never got beyond the preliminaries. The analysis of the
concepts of ‘critique’ and ‘crisis’ became an end in itself and the
basis of a new hypothesis. This hypothesis argues that che Enlight-
enment itself became Utopian and even hypocritical because — as
far as continental Europe was concerned — it saw itself excluded
from political power-sharing. The steucture of Absolutism, which
wwas rooted in the dichotomy between sovereign and subject, be-
tween public policy and private morality, prevented the Enlighten-
ment and the emancipation movement produced by it from seeing
12 Preface to the English Edition
itself as a political phenomenon. Instead the Enlightenment deve-
loped patterns of thought and behaviour which, a the latest from
1789 onwards, foundered on the rocks of the concrete political
challenges that arose. The Enlightenment succumbed to a Utopian
image which, while deceptively: propelling it, helped to produce
contradictions which could not be resolved in practice and prepared
the way for the Terror and for dictatorship. Here was an ideal-type
framework which time and again made its reappearance in the
subsequent history of the modern world
Given that this book raised a question which was topical not only
from an historical, but also from a political point of view, its impact
went beyond the debate originally generated in Germany. Transla-
tions into Spanish, Italian and French appeared in 1965, 1972 and
1979 respectively. It appears to be more than a coincidence that all
three were continental European languages. If nothing else, their
societies had at least one thing in common with Central Europe:
they had all been ruled by Absolutist regimes, whatever the political
differences between these regimes may have been. Accordingly it
‘was only in these countries that there emerged a type of Enlighten-
mene which, while trying to evade censorship and other chicancries,
was directed against the Absolutist claims of the sovereign ruler.
Whoever refused to follow che majority, who adapted and subjected.
themselves to their ruler, invented way’ of camouflage and mystifi
cation as well as other indirectly operative modes of behaviour
which ultimately began to pervade the ideas of the Enlightenment
themselves. It is true that arguments about rationality and natural
justice subjected the Absolutise State to fresh pressure to legitimate
itself and to respond to change. But, none the ess, such arguments.
remained confined to the corridors outside the chambers of actual
political decision-making. As a result there emerged, by way of
compensation, a progressive philosophy of history which promised
victory to the intellectual elive, but one gained without struggle and
civil war
Since 1688 at the latest Britain, by contrast, underwent a different
development. She never experienced the tension between State and
society which so shaped the nations of the European continent.
Both spheres remained sufficiently interlinked through Parliament
and the judicial constitution to appreciate that all moral questions
represented at the same time political problems. The Utopian ideas
of the continental Enlightenment therefore never gained a foothold
Preface to the English Edition 3
across the Channel. There it was the Scottish moral philosophers
with their sober theories rooted in social history who set the tone
and who began to respond to the economic lead gained by Britain,
Ac first the Scots moved in the wake of Britain's progress which was
soon also to affect the whole of the European continent. This was an
important point to which my book gives no more than marginal
attention.
Against the background of these considerations, it may be appro-
priate to add a few further remarks, now that this translation into
English has become available. During the past two decades many
and methodologically very sophisticated studies have appeared in
the fields of intellectual as well as social history. It would be
impossible to list chem here. This research on Hobbes, Locke,
Diderot, Rousseau and Raynal has become so intensified that my
contribution to an interpretation of their writings may seem rather
peripheral, Similarly, the social history of Freemasonry and of the
Mluminati, research on the Republic of Letters and its networks of
communication, on literary societies, academies and libraries, on
reading habits, in short on the mentalités of divergent social groups
in different European countries, has expanded our knowledge so
much that my study will not teach the reader anything new.
However, what I hope will be of value to the interested reader
of this book is its theoretical framework. This framework provides
a larger, ideal-typically constructed context into which detailed
events and findings can be put. Thus this book tries to interpret the
origins of Absolutism as an outgrowth of religious wars. As a next
step, it attempts to explain the genesis of the modern Utopia from
the context of the political interaction in which the men of the
Enlightenment found themselves vis-a-vis the system of Absolut-
ism, It is in this way that two major themes of the early modern
period have been connected, with the aim of deducing therefrom the
evolution of a long-term process which went beyond what the
contemporaries had intended. As a result I hope to highlight more
persistent structures of the modern age which may be seen as
elements of historical anthropology: the sense that we are being
sucked into an open and unknown future, the pace of which has
kept us in a constant state of breathlessness ever since the dissolu-
tion of the traditional standische societies; and the pressure on our
post-theological age to justify politics and morals without us being
able to reconcile the two. These were the challenges which the4 Preface to the English Edition
Enlightenment faced, and they produced mentalities, attitudes and
behavioural patterns which have survived the special circumstances
of their birth. Putin a nutshell this book attempts to offer a genetic
theory of the modern world which may help us co explain individ-
ual historical phenomena, If this assumption is correct, my central
hypothesis will also serve to provoke criticism. After all, itis not
merely historical problems that are being raised here, but questions
which are challenging us to this day to search for an answer.
RK.
Biclefeld, September 1987
Introduction
In the fires of a evolution, when hatreds prevail and the
sovereign power is spit, itis difficult to write history
Rivarol
From an historical point of view the present tension between ewo
superpowers, the USA and the USSR, is a result of European
history. Europe's history has broadened; it has become world
history and will run its course as that, having allowed the whole
world to drift into a state of permanent crisis, As bourgeois society
was the first to cover the globe, the present crisis stems from a
mainly Utopian self-conception on the part of the philosophers of
history — Utopian because modern man is destined to be at home
everywhere and nowhere. History has overflowed the banks of
tradition and inundated all boundaries. The technology of com-
‘munications on the infinite surface of the globe has made all powers
omnipresent, subjecting all to each and each to all. At the same time,
wwe have seen the opening up of interplanetary space, although the
result may well be to blow up mankind as well in a sell-initiated
process of self-destruction.
Unified, the ewo phenomena are historically one. ‘They constitute
the political crisis which — if it really is a crisis — presses for a
decision, and they are the philosophies of history that correspond to
the crisis and in whose name we seek to anticipate the decisi
influence it, steer it, or, as catastrophically, to prevent it.
common root lies in the eighteenth century, and this indicates the
direction of questions determined by the situation of today
The eighteenth century witnessed the unfolding of bourgeois
5
heir6 Introduction
society, which saw itself as the new world, laying intellectual claim
to the whole world and simultancously denying the old. It grew out
of the territories of the European states and, in dissolving this link,
developed a progressive philosophy in line with the process. The
subject of that philosophy was all mankind, to be unified from its
European centre and led peacefully towards a better future. Today
its field of action, a single global world, is claimed in the name of
analogous philosophies of history, but now by two powers at once.
‘To speak in historico-philosophical terms, today's world unity
turns out — and it is this which makes its fictitious character
apparent — to be a politically dichotomous unity. One half, sworn
to progress like the other, lives by that other’s imagined reaction.
‘The two halves block each other's way, but it is this very fact chat
gives them identity. They mutually segregate each other in order to
feign a non-existent unity. Their testimony is therefore one of terror
and fear. The world’s Utopian unity reproduces its own fission,
In the eighteenth century, Utopian planning for the future had a
specifically temporal historic function. As the European bour-
sgeoisie externally encompassed the whole world and in so doing
postulated one mankind, it set out inwardly, in the name of the
same argumentation, to shatter the Absolutist order. Philosophers
of history prepared and made available the coreepts by which the
rise and the role of the bourgeoisie of that time were justified. The
eighteenth century can be seen as the antechamber to our present
epoch, one whose tensions have been increasingly exacerbated since
the French Revolution, as the revolutionary process spread exten-
sively around the globe and intensively to all mankind. This book
seeks to illuminate that antechamber. The link aerween the origins
‘of the modern philosophy of history and the start of the crisis
‘which, initially in Europe, has been determining political events
ever since 1789, will come within our purview.
This is how the mode of enquiry was narrowed and rendered
historically precise: we shall not question the contents of past
philosophies of history nor their Utopian goals, nor will their
‘ideological structure be measured, for example, by the economic
rise of the bourgeoisie in those times, Instead, and in order to
illuminate its original link with the beginning o* the political crisis,
we shall try to understand the philosophical sense of history by
studying the political situation of the bourgeoisie in the Absolutist
‘State. The philosophies of history chemselves will be left aside, save
Introduction 7
for exemplary exceptions; our investigation will focus on the politi-
cal function which bourgeois thought and endeavour served in the
framework of Absolutism. To elaborate the political significance of,
the Enlightenment, we shall have to look at the structure of the
“Absolutise State, for this Stare was the first victim of the great
Revolution; its disappearance was what enabled a Utopian mod- »
cemnism to unfold. A primary understanding, of Absolutism requires
us to look back farther, to the seventeenth century in which the
sovereign princely State was perfected. The point of this retrospec-
sion is not to construe causalities; suggesting these could only take
us back to prehistoric times and Co the problems of any beginning.
— in short, to the questions af a philosophy of history that goes
beyond ideology, that resorts to historic reality in order to lay the
ground for an historical science which excludes precisely the pseudo-
explanations of a regressus in infinitum. Such an historical regressus
would be nothing but progress in reverse, the very thing we are
obliged to question.
‘Our analyses will concentrate on the present that has passed, not
‘on its past. The earlier past will be considered only in so far as it
contains conditions relevant to our questions about the eighteenth
century. Our theme is the genesis of Utopianism from an historically
deveimined functional context, the context of the eighteenth cen-
tury. We thus have recourse to political history as far as necessary t0
establish the value of civic consciousness in the Absolutist system.
This simultaneously allows us to view the reverse of our investiga
sion: the nascent political erisis. Iris only as a reaction to Absolutist
policies that — intentionally or not — Enlighteners’ historico-
philosophical self-consciousness makes political sense. The State, as
it was, demanded a response, and the response was discovered.
Derivations from the history of ideas were deliberately waived. The
heritage of ideas, already all but completely at the Enlighteners’
disposal, was not accepted until a specific situation arose, and not
until — this was the novelty — che situation was interpreted in
terms of the philosophy of history. In narrowing our enquiry to
historic situations we do not, of course, mean to present the people
of those days with a moral indictment, to find them more or less
guilty. This is self-prohibiting, for man as an historic creature is
always responsible, for what he willed as well as for what he did not
will, and more often, perhaps, for the latter than for the former.
‘The method used is thus a combination of analyses from the8 Introduction
history of ideas and analyses of sociological conditions. We emulate
thought movements, but only far enough for their political accent to
come into view, and we clarify the situations in which the thoughts
were conceived and to which they reacted, but only far enough to
‘extract what was politically manifest in the ideas. We do not show
cither the political course of events as such or the ideas’ declension
as mere ideas, ‘The general conditions from which the Enlighten
ment arose and to which it reacted did not change during the
eighteenth century. Only particular circumstances changed, though
in a manner that brought the Absolutise system's basic difficulties
into so much sharper relief. The French State, above al, lost power
and prestige; with increasing bourgeois affluence it ran up more and
more debts, ceased to score visible successes, lost wars and colonies,
until at last che Enlightenment spread to the State's representatives
themselves. The Enlightenment became ‘a proper ally’
As for the political premises as such, there ean be no doubs that
the State’s own structure remained unchanged. The sovereiga de-
cision continued to lie in the monarch’s hands; he chose between
war and peace, dismissed Parliament at his pleasure, maintained the
standards of his court regardless of all liabilities, until finally the
more stubbornly Louis XVI insisted upon his sovereignty the less
he found himself able to struggle through to effective decisions. The
State had changed; it had become corrupt, but only because it
remained Absolutist. The Absolutist system, he situation from
which the bourgeois Enlightenment took its departure, remained in
force until the outbreak of the Revolution. It constitutes the one
constant element of our enquiry, the yardstick which, through a
variety of examples, enables us to take successive measurements of
she Enlightenment’s political development. The Enlightenment ac~
quired a gravity of its own, which came at last to be one of its
political conditions. Absolutism necessitated the genesis of the
. Enlightenment, and the Enlightenment conditioned the genesis of
the French Revolution. It is around these ewo theses that the action
of this book takes place
Sources will be cited only from the period before 1789. No
testimonials will be adduced to make personal statements about the
authors. Singular events and specific writings are always referred to
bbut are never the issue, The theme remains the unity of the Enlight-
enment as it happened in the Absolutist State, Each action and each
act of thought should direct us towards this event. For our enquiry,
Introduction 9
all authors remain substitutes. All citations and occurrences could
casily be exchanged for others without disturbing the course of the
investigation, The notes often contain parallel quotations even
though cumulative documentation does not enhance the thesis
itself. Great thinkers and anonymous pamphleteers are equally
given the floor; it is precisely what they have in common that
indicates the unity of the Enlightenment’s occurrence, in. which
anonymity and political import generally coincide. Only a few
documents bear the stamp of personality clearly enough — in the
cases of Hobbes or Diderot, for instance — to remain unique in the
overall flow of events; but even their uniqueness serves to bring out
the typical once it is moved into focus.
‘The heuristic comprehension, meant to clarify the link between
the Utopian philosophy of history and the revolution unleashed
since 1789, lies in the presupposed connection of critique and crisis
This grasp will prove itself. The fact that the eighteenth century
failed to note any connection between the critique it practised and
the looming crisis — no literal proof of an awareness of the link
could be found — this very fact led to our thesis: that the eritical
process of enlightenment conjured up the crisis in the same measure
in which the political significance of that crisis remained hidden
from ie. The crisis was as much exacerbated as it was obfuscated in
the philosophy of history. Never politically grasped, it remained
concealed in historico-philosophical images of the future which
caused the day’s events to pale — events that became so much less
inhibited in heading for an unexpected decision. The basis of this
dialectic was the specific manner of critique which the eighteenth
century favoured and from which it derived its name. The role of
the rising bourgeoisie was determined by the critical practice of the
bourgeois intelligentisia and coalesced in the new world
‘The entire period under discussion presents the picture of a
uniquely powerful process. In the eighteenth century, history as a
whole was unwittingly transformed into a sort of legal process. This
occurrence, which inaugurates the Modern age, is identical with the
genesis of the philosophy of history. ‘In critique, history wens
automatically into a philosophy of history’ (Ferdinand Cheistian
Baur). The tribunal of reason, with whose natural members the
rising elite confidently ranked itself, involved all spheres of activity
in varying stages of its development. Theology, at, history, the law,
the State and politics, eventually reason itself — sooner or later all10 Introduction
were called upon to answer for themselves. In these proceedings the
bourgeois spirit functioned simultaneously as prosecutor, as the
court of last resort, and — due co be of crucial importance to the
Philosophy of history — as a party. From the outset, progress
always sided with the bourgeois judges. Nothing and nobody could
evade the new jurisdiction, and whatever failed in the bourgeois
critics’ judgement was turned over to moral censors who diserimi-
nated against the convicted and thus helped to carry out the sen-
tence. ‘He who does not recognise this / is to be viewed with
contempt.”
In the rigorous process of critique — a process of social ferment
at the same time — the bourgeois philosophy of history came into
being. All regions touched by criticism contributed to furthering,
the rise of that philosophy. To begin with, the contrast of ancients
and moderns was articulated within the republic of scholars by art
and literary critics developing an understanding of time that sun-
dered future and past. A central target of the citical offensive, the
Christian religion in its manifold divisions, prepared the chars
‘matic-historical heritage that was subsumed into the future-orien~
tated world-view, in the most varied ways. We know the process of
secularisation, which transposed eschatology into a history of prog
ress, But likewise, consciously and deliberately, che elements of
divine judgement and the Last Day were applied to history itself,
above all in the exacerbated critical situation.
The critical ferment altered the nature of political events. Subjec~
tive self-righteousness ceased reckoning with given values. Every~
thing that was historically given, indeed history itself, was transformed
into a process — the outcome of which, of course, remained open as
long as the categories of private judgement could never catch up
with events they had helped co bring about. Eventually, to reach
them after all the divine, heretofore impervious plan of salvation
was itself transformed: it, too, became enlightened. Tt was trans-
formed into the morally just and rational planning of the future by
the new elite. Since misconceiving the indigenous side of the criti-
ised realms in both religion and polities was a peculiarity of
rational critique, it had to look for an escape hatch, the pledge of a
tomorrow in whose name today could in good conscience be
allowed to perish. To justify itself at all, the critique of the eight
eenth century had to become Utopian. Its ultimate object, the
Absolutist State, helped in its way to establish the Utopian view of
Introduction u
history upheld by the bourgeoisie.
In the political order which it restored by pacifying the areas
devastated by religious wars, the state created the premise for the
unfolding of a moral world. However, just as soon as their religious
bonds are outgrown, the politically powerless individuals will clash
with the State: even though morally emancipating them, the State
will deny them responsibility by restricting them to a private
sphere. Inevitably, citizens will come into conifict with a State that
subordinates morality: to polities, adopts a purely formal under-
standing of the political realm and thus reckons without develop-
ments peculiar to the emancipation of its subjects. For their goal
will be to perfect themselves morally to an extent that will permit
them to know, and let every man know for himself, what is good
and what is evil. Each one thus becomes a judge who knows, on
grounds of his enlightenment, that he is authorised to try whatever
heteronomous definitions concradict his moral autonomy. Once
implemented by the State the separation of morality and polities
hhence turns against the State itself: itis forced into standing a moral
trial for having achieved something, ic. to have created a space in
which it was possible (for the individual) to survive
In the course of unfolding the Cartesian cogito ergo sum as the
self-guarantee of a man who has dropped out of the veligious bouids,
eschatology recoils into Uropianism. Planning history comes to be
just as important as mastering nature. ‘The misconception that
history is open to planning is furthered by the technicise State
because its political value cannot be made comprehensible to its
subject. Politically powerless as a subject of his sovereign lord, the
citizen conceived himself as moral, felt that the existing rule was
overpowering, and condemned it proportionally as immoral since
hhe could no longer perceive what is evident in the horizon of human
finiteness. ‘The dichotomy of morality and politics made morality's
alienation from political reality inevitable. The expression of this
inevitability is that morality skips the political aporia. Unable to
integrate politics, moral man stands in a void and must make a
virtue of necessity. A stranger to reality, he views the political
domain as a heteronomous definition that can only stand in his way
In consequence, this morality makes men think that in so far as they
attain the heights of their destiny they can completely eliminate the
political aporia. That politics is fate, that it is fate not in the sense of
blind fatality, this is what the enlighteners fail to understand. Their2 Introduction
attempts to allow the philosophy of history ro negate historical
factuality, to ‘repress’ the political realm, are Utopian in origin and
character. The crisis caused by moraliy's proceeding against history
will be a permanent crisis as long as history is aienaced in terms of
its philosophy
‘That crisis and the philosophy of history are mutually dependent
and entwined — that ultimately’ one must indeed go so far as to call
them identical — this must, when our enquiry has reached its goal,
have become visible a several points in the course of the eighteenth
century. Its Utopianism arose from an irtelation to polities that was
caused by history, but which was then solidified by a philosophy of
history. The critical crossfire not only ground up topical polities;
politics itself, as a constant task of human existence, dissolved in the
same process into Utopian constructs of the future. The political
edifice of the Absolutist State and the unfolding of Utopianism
reveal one complex occurrence around which the political crisis of
our time begins
The Political Structure of Absolutism as the
Precondition of EnlightenmentCHAPTER |
The Absolutist State, Raison d'Etat and the
Emergence of the Apolitical Sphere (Barclay,
D'Aubigné)
‘Two epochal events mark the beginning and the end of classical
Absolutism. Its point of departure was the religious civil war. The
modern State had laboriously fought its way out of the religious
disorders; not until these had been overcome did it achieve its full
form and delineation. A second civil war — the French Revolution
— brought the Absolutist State ro an abrupt end.
The effective context of both these chains of events touched
Europe as a whole, but
by the fact that on this island the two happened, as it were, to
coincide. Here, the nascent Absolutist State had already been und
mined by religious warfare; the struggle for the faith already
tokened the bourgeois revolution. On the Continent, on the other
hand, as far as one can trace the evolution of the Absolutist State
there, it remained the time-bound outcome of the post-Reformation
disorders. It was in the locally differing solutions of sectarian
conflicts, and in chronologically distinct phases, that the moderna
State power was established. Its policies were the theme of the
seventeenth century; their paths outlined the history of Absolutism.
The following period, though marked by the same State form, bore
another name: ‘the Enlightenment’. It was from Absolutism that the
Enlightenment evolved — initially as its inner consequence, later a5
its dialectical counterpart and antagonist, destined to lead the Ab-
solutist State to its demise
Just as the Enlightenmene’s political point of departure lay within
igland’s exceptional position is elucidated
156 The Political Structure of Absolmism
the Absolutise system, so that of Absolutism hy in the religious
‘wars, An inner connection links the formal completion of Absolut-
ism with its end, a connection that becomes visible in the role which
the Enlightenment was able to play within the confines of the
Absolutist State, The Enlightenment reached its zenith in France,
the very country in which the Absolutist system had for the frst
time, and most decisively, overcome the internal religious conflict.
‘The abuse of power by Louis XIV accelerated che process, in the
course of which the subject discovered himself as a citizen. In
France this same citizen would one day storm the Bastille. The
political structure of the Absolutist State, initially an answer to
religious strife, was no longer understood as such by the Enlighten-
ment that followed.
The first task of our enquiry is to focus on that connection, to
clarify the initial situation of the modern State as far as may’ be
necessary in order to perceive the point of the Enlightenment’s
political attack on that State. The methodological limitation which
this places on any analysis of the politcal structure of Absolutism
— beyond any social or economic questions — is objectively
justified. The princely State, supported by the military and the
bureaucracy, developed a supra-religious, rationalistc field of ac~
tion which, unlike its other aspects, was defined by the policies of
the State. Socially, the monarchies remained entirely bound by
traditional feudal stratification, so much so that in most instances
they sought to preserve that stratification. Politically, however, the
monarchs strove to eliminate or neutralise all institutions with an
independent base. Mercantilism, 100, was an economic system
subject to political planning and State guidance; similarly, religious
and ecclesiastical questions were treated with an eye to their useful-
ness to the State, whether within the framework of an established
Church or under toleration with a purpose. The -ealm of a political
system covering all of Europe constituted the constellation from
which the Enlightenment started out,
‘This realm found its theoretical expression in the doctrine of
raison d'état, What was made room for here was an area where
politics could unfold regardless of moral considerations. ‘Dans les
‘monarchies, la politique fai fare les grandes choses avec le moins de
vertu qu'elle peut.” When Montesquieu made that statement in
1 Montesquieu, Esprit des Loss, A, chap. 8
The Absolutist State "7
1748, to characterise the politics of his own day, his formula —
apart from its polemical content — had already ceased to be intel-
ligible to the Enlighteners. The historical evidence of the formula
was derived from the period of religious wars. In the sixteenth
century the traditional order had disintegeated. As a result of the
split in ecclesiastical unity, the entire sovial order became unhinged.
(Old ties and loyalties were dissolved. High treason and the struggle
for the common good became interchangeable concepts, depending,
fon the point of view of the ascendant faction. The general anarchy
led to duels, violence and murder, while the pluralisation of the
Ecclesia sancta fermented corruption in whatever else remained
swhole: families, estaces, countries, nations. Thus, from the second
half of the sixteenth century onwards, a problem developed with a
virulence which overreached the resources of the traditional order:
the need to find a solution to the intolerant, fiercely embactled and,
mutually persecuting Churches or religion-bound fractions of the
old estates, a solution that would circumvent, settle, or smother the
conflict, How to make peace? On the greater part of the Continent
this epoch-making question found its historic answer in the Ab-
solutis State, And indeed, the State could not be constituted as such
until it had found its specific answer to religious civil warfare. What
was this answer? What did it mean to the monarch? And to the
subject?
While the religious parties drew their energies from sources
outside the domains of princely power, the princes could not prevail
over them unless they challenged the primacy of religion. It was the
only way for rulers to subordinate the various protagonists to the
authority of the State. Cuius regio eins religio was already a conse-
quence of the fact that even if princes were committed to a particu-
lar faith, as rulers they placed themselves above the religious patties.
‘The absolute ruler recognised no other authority over himself than
God, whose atcributes in the political and historic field he appro-
priated: ‘Majestas vero nec a majore potestate nec legibus ullis nec
tempore definitur’.*
In his Argenis, a roman a clef published in 1621, John Barclay
supplied a vindication of absolute monarchy that was widely knowa
at the time and translated into almost all European languages. The
2. Bodin, De rep, libri sex, a quoted by Friedrich Meinsche in Die Fee der
Seaesrsan’ od W" Hofer, Munchy 195, p72,18 The Political Structure of Absolution
author, a humanist learned in the law, had shared the fate of many
of his contemporaries; he was the son of a refugee family whose
carly impressions had been formed by the confrontations with the
League and the trauma of the Gunpowder Plot. Alluding to
occurrences of that sort, he confronted the monarch with a chal
lenging alternative: ‘Either give the people back their freedom or
assure the domestic eranquillty for whose sake they relinquished that
freedom’.* What appears from such passages is the historical mission
accorded the monarchy of those days, the mission that was pro.
claimed as justified® by the great majority of Richelieu's generation
— against the League, the Fronde, or the monarchomachists
Drawing further on the doctrine of the sovereign contract, Barclay
tended towards the Absolutist State, depriving the embattled parties
of their rights and transferring those rights — along with all re-
sponsibility — to the sovereign alone. Argenis was part of Riche-
lieu's constant reading matter; its train of argument, commonplace
at the time, recurs in his political testament.” Forbearance, it pro-
claimed, was more dangerous than stringency, more than cruclty
even, for the consequences of clemency were bloodier and more
devastating than those of instant severity. A monarch who tolerated
opposition did indeed relieve himself of responsibility, but he also
shouldered the guilt deriving from any unrest that emer ged fom his
tolerance.’ His postulated monopoly on peace-making enforced the
monarch’s absolute responsibility, the time-bound expression of
which was the notion of his sole responsibility to God
In his novel, Barclay also showed the direction the King would
have to take in order to pacify the country. Bither he must subjugate
all or no one would be subjugated.* The sovercign’s absolute
responsibility required and presupposed his absolute domination of
all subjects. Only if all subjects were equally under che rulers thumb,
could he assume sole responsibilty for peace and onder. Thus, a deep
1 Gt: Richard Barnet, Barcly’ in Dictionary of National Biography, Oxford
1921-2,
4. John Barlay (Lsmnis BarcleiArgens, Editio V, Franlun, 1626): "Aviles in
libeiatem reste, aut domesticam prkers quleten, proptes iam Rhee oe
guerunt
5. Ch the contemporaries listed by G, Hanotaus, Histoire da Cardinal de Riche.
fen Soles Bar SS el
6, Cle rgent il, chape 4 and 6: and Casdinal de Richelieu, Testament politique
cd, Louis Andre, Pais, 1047, Par I, chap. 5, Sand Por Me chags Peed ee
il surmpsetne
Toa. 2s.
The Absolutist State 9
breach was lai in the subjects’ position. Previously they had their
places in a manifold, if loose, structure of responsibilities: as mem-
bers of a Church, as dependent vassals, in the framework of their
own political institutions or of the feudal order of estates. But the
more the sense of this pluralistic world was reversed into the
senselessness of civil warfare, the more the subjects faced a similarly
cogent alternative as that facing the King himself: ‘Know then that
almost all men have been reduced to this point: to be on bad terms
Sites with thei coscence or withthe course of che century’?
midst the toing and froing of persecutors and persecuted, of
cts ad encase saris snore a sob is
faith but he who sought peace for its own sake. These were the
theses which Agrippe d’Aubigné, the life-long frondeur, the ostra-
cised and rigorous batter for the faith, put into the mouth of his
apostate comrade-in-arms, the palitician de Sancy.”® Conscience and
the needs of the situation are reconcilable no longer hence —
dAubigné’s politician continues — there must be a clean break
between the internal and the external. A prudent man withdraws into
the secret chambers of his heart, where he remains his own judge, but
external actions are to be submitted co the ruler’s judgement’and
jurisdiction, ‘The voice of conscience must never emerge: outwardly it
has to be put to slee
tthy; those who are dead wanted to let their conscience live, and twas
their conscience that killed them." An ironical inversion burdened
conscience with the guilt of its own ruin. The lines separating murder,
manslaughter, and execution were still fluid and indefinite, but in the
politician’s mind any violent death in a war of religion was tantamount
to suicide, He who submits to the sovereign lives by the sovereign; he
who does not submit is destroyed, but the guil is his own, To survive,
the subject must submerge his conscience.
Conscience, the intrinsic relationship between responsibility
PAubigne, La confession du Sieur de Suncy, ed. Reaume et Caussade, Pari, 1997
B69,
De Sane sion of she Haley famiy of juss, had converted in 1897 and
tecome Sopeinicndcnc ot Hinances incwhich po fe ould induce al opportuni
smone bin former so-chgonns tose the Edit of Nantes (ore Av Carn
Agrppe dt: Aubrgné ete Ba Protest sols. Pans 1938 Th 35
Tact Stour de Sucys‘La ran ose aces ean Gu Sone moes ont20 The Political Structure of Absolutism
and guilt, was forced open. Both elements found a novel co-
ordination in the persons of ruler and subject. In che subjects’
domain the ruler was freed from all guilt, but he accumulated all
responsibility. The subject, on the other hand, was relieved of all
political responsibility but threatened, in exchenge, with a wwofold
guilt: externally when acting counter to his sovereign’s interest —
something the sovereign had the sole right to determine — and
inwardly by sceking refuge in anonymity. This fission within the
horizon of religious civil warfare paved the way for the ‘innocence
of power’. The prince alone could claim that innocence, but to
ain it he had to remain aware of the augmented responsibility
it entailed. Then, and only then, was he in possession of the
authority thae guaranteed his power. He came to feel a compulsion
to act which continually conjured up new decisions, including
decisions involving the use of forees the consequences of inaction
‘could be as serious as those of its opposite, che over-utilisation of
power. One tisk matched and constantly challenged the other.
Indeed, the danger of falling from one extre
the very source of the evidence of sovereign decisions.
‘To meet his all-encompassing responsiblity, the prince had to
seek the measure of his actions in their calculable effect on everyone
else, The compulsion to act thus provoked a need for heightened
foresight. A rational calculation of all possible consequences came
to be the first political commandment." However, in order to keep
the consequences of his actions (which, once committed, were not
humanly alterable) under his own control as long as possible, the
prince was driven further to augment his power, which in turn
increased the sources of danger, the risks of abusing or failing to use
the accumulated power, that i, of relinquishing its innocence. Louis
XIV would succumb to this logic of absolute responsibility, yet
obedience to its laws became the art of politics, The scope of the
innocence of power remained narrowly citcumscribed by the
guidelines of a sharpened morality of action. These made up the
political rules, rules which to the powerless subject could not but
remain essentially alien
Both politicians and teachers of the secular ethic agreed on this.
Not until the cighteeath century were they to divide into two
into the other was
12, CF, Richeiew's Testament patie, Uh chap. 42°. idest plus imporane de
privenis Iavenir que le presen ‘fll yood police was ov antcipate
Existather than have thers surpese you
The Absolutist State a
hostilé camps: in the seventeenth they still made common cause
against the theologians. Spinoza continued co maintain that only
theologians believed that statesmen were bound by the same rules
of piety as were private individuals." The exclusion of ‘morality’
from polities was not directed against a secular ethic, but against a
religious one with political
‘The doctrine of raison d
sicuation that it did not even confine itself to monarchival Absolut-
ism, On the Continent the doctrine filtered into a tradition of
enhanced royalty, but it gained just as much ground in countries
with a parliamentary — that is, republican — constitution. Every
power which in those days Sought to equip itself with authority and
4 generally binding nature required this exclusion of the private
conscience in which the bonds of religion or of feudal loyalty were
anchored. Thus the English Parliament in 1649, when ie wished to
strip Charles | of his prerogatives, hastily embraced the argument
that every conscience, even the King's, must bow to the interest of
the State. Parliament claimed coral sovereignty, to the extent af
forcing the King to act against his good conscience."
Even Spinoza in Holland, far from advocating monarchical Ab~
solutism, deemed it perfectly reasonable to look on every good deed
as sinful if it harmed the State — just as, conversely. sins became
pious works if they served the common weal."
Paradigmatic for the modern Scare theory's genesis from the
situation of religious civil warfare is Hobbes, whom Spinoza cited.
Hobbes lends himself especially well to a description of this
genesis because he had already dispensed with such traditional
arguments as the God-King analogy. On the contrary, countering
these with the guiding principles of a scientific method, as Dilthey
pur it" he wanted to bring the phenomena in all their naked reality
13, Spinoes, Tracatas Palins pars 2
4 Clendon isthe apgmnets a which Charles had 1 bow 4 st Tega
Parhument™s proceslings saint Sirabord. That here was 2 private and» pu
‘blige hin odo shadahich wae againe his peat asctence wa mat Tithe
Ainevay obliged an conscience to contornyhumsell an hs own undersanding, 10
thalsce an conscience of his pariament’ "Which war a doce aeely
‘esofed beter diinen and of rest ane them tor the pursuing the furuee
ouasele, Clarendon adds in rerespect(Clagendom, Phe Hitury of the Rebelo
Jind isa Wars on Bland, 6 sols, Oxford, 1888 821 and 3884
is. Spinart, Tastatr Throlgaco-Paacas chap. 19; camcsrning the connection
with rls stl arte ef chap. Ue and Evice WV)
1h. Ch Dishes, Genammalee Schriften een, uuttgare snd Giingen, 1987, Hy
(Suny Series in the Thought and Legacy of Leo Strauss) Corine Pelluchon, Robert Howse - Leo Strauss and the Crisis of Rationalism_ Another Reason, Another Enlightenment-State University of New York Pr